fbpx
Wikipedia

Arthur Schopenhauer

Arthur Schopenhauer (/ˈʃpənhaʊər/ SHOH-pən-how-ər,[18] German: [ˈaɐtʊɐ ˈʃoːpm̩haʊɐ] (listen); 22 February 1788 – 21 September 1860) was a German philosopher. He is best known for his 1818 work The World as Will and Representation (expanded in 1844), which characterizes the phenomenal world as the product of a blind noumenal will.[19] Building on the transcendental idealism of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), Schopenhauer developed an atheistic metaphysical and ethical system that rejected the contemporaneous ideas of German idealism.[6][7] He was among the first thinkers in Western philosophy to share and affirm significant tenets of Indian philosophy, such as asceticism, denial of the self, and the notion of the world-as-appearance.[20] His work has been described as an exemplary manifestation of philosophical pessimism.[21]

Arthur Schopenhauer
Schopenhauer in 1859
Born(1788-02-22)22 February 1788
Died21 September 1860(1860-09-21) (aged 72)
NationalityGerman
Education
Relatives
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
InstitutionsUniversity of Berlin
Main interests
Metaphysics, aesthetics, ethics, morality, psychology
Notable ideas
Anthropic principle[4][5]
Eternal justice
Fourfold root of the principle of sufficient reason
Hedgehog's dilemma
Philosophical pessimism
Principium individuationis
Will as thing in itself
Criticism of religion
Criticism of German idealism[6][7]
Schopenhauerian aesthetics
Wooden iron
Influences
Signature

Though his work failed to garner substantial attention during his lifetime, Schopenhauer had a posthumous impact across various disciplines, including philosophy, literature, and science. His writing on aesthetics, morality, and psychology have influenced many thinkers and artists. Those who have cited his influence include philosophers Emil Cioran, Friedrich Nietzsche[22] and Ludwig Wittgenstein;[23] scientists Erwin Schrödinger and Albert Einstein;[24] psychoanalysts Sigmund Freud[25] and Carl Jung; writers Leo Tolstoy,[26] Herman Melville,[27] Thomas Mann, Hermann Hesse,[28] Machado de Assis,[29] Jorge Luis Borges, Marcel Proust[30] and Samuel Beckett;[31] and composers Richard Wagner,[30] Johannes Brahms,[30] Arnold Schoenberg[30][32] and Gustav Mahler.[30]

Life

Early life

 
Schopenhauer's birthplace house, ul. Św. Ducha (formerly Heiligegeistgasse)

Arthur Schopenhauer was born on 22 February 1788, in Danzig (then part of the Polish–Lithuanian Commonwealth; present-day Gdańsk, Poland) on Heiligegeistgasse (present day Św. Ducha 47), the son of Johanna Schopenhauer (née Trosiener; 1766–1838) and Heinrich Floris Schopenhauer (1747–1805),[33] both descendants of wealthy German patrician families. While they came from a Protestant background, neither of them were very religious;[34]: 79 [35] both supported the French Revolution,[34]: 13  were republicans, cosmopolitans and Anglophiles.[34]: 9  When Danzig became part of Prussia in 1793, Heinrich moved to Hamburg—a free city with a republican constitution. His firm continued trading in Danzig where most of their extended families remained. Adele, Arthur's only sibling, was born on 12 July 1797.

In 1797, Arthur was sent to Le Havre to live with the family of his father's business associate, Grégoire de Blésimaire. He seemed to enjoy his two-year stay there, learning to speak French and fostering a life-long friendship with Jean Anthime Grégoire de Blésimaire.[34]: 18  As early as 1799, Arthur started playing the flute.[34]: 30 

In 1803, he accompanied his parents on a European tour of Holland, Britain, France, Switzerland, Austria and Prussia. Viewed as primarily a pleasure tour, Heinrich used the opportunity to visit some of his business associates abroad.

Heinrich offered Arthur a choice: he could stay at home and start preparations for university, or he could travel with them and continue his merchant education. Arthur chose to travel with them. He deeply regretted his choice later because the merchant training was very tedious. He spent twelve weeks of the tour attending school in Wimbledon, where he was disillusioned by strict and intellectually shallow Anglican religiosity. He continued to sharply criticize Anglican religiosity later in life despite his general Anglophilia.[34]: 56  He was also under pressure from his father, who became very critical of his educational results.

In 1805, Heinrich drowned in a canal near their home in Hamburg. Although it was possible that his death was accidental, his wife and son believed that it was suicide. He was prone to anxiety and depression; each becoming more pronounced later in his life.[36] Heinrich had become so fussy, even his wife started to doubt his mental health.[34]: 43  "There was, in the father's life, some dark and vague source of fear which later made him hurl himself to his death from the attic of his house in Hamburg."[34]: 88 

Arthur showed similar moodiness during his youth and often acknowledged that he inherited it from his father. There were other instances of serious mental health history on his father's side of the family.[34]: 4  Despite his hardship, Schopenhauer liked his father and later referred to him in a positive light.[34]: 90  Heinrich Schopenhauer left the family with a significant inheritance that was split in three among Johanna and the children. Arthur Schopenhauer was entitled to control of his part when he reached the age of majority. He invested it conservatively in government bonds and earned annual interest that was more than double the salary of a university professor.[34]: 136  After quitting his merchant apprenticeship, with some encouragement from his mother, he dedicated himself to studies at the Ernestine Gymnasium, Gotha, in Saxe-Gotha-Altenburg. While there, he also enjoyed social life among the local nobility, spending large amounts of money, which deeply concerned his frugal mother.[34]: 128  He left the Gymnasium after writing a satirical poem about one of the schoolmasters. Although Arthur claimed that he left voluntarily, his mother's letter indicates that he may have been expelled.[34]: 129 

 
Schopenhauer in his youth

Arthur spent two years as a merchant in honor of his dead father. During this time, he had doubts about being able to start a new life as a scholar.[34]: 120  Most of his prior education was as a practical merchant and he had trouble learning Latin; a prerequisite for an academic career.[34]: 117 

His mother moved away, with her daughter Adele, to Weimar—then the centre of German literature—to enjoy social life among writers and artists. Arthur and his mother did not part on good terms. In one letter, she wrote: "You are unbearable and burdensome, and very hard to live with; all your good qualities are overshadowed by your conceit, and made useless to the world simply because you cannot restrain your propensity to pick holes in other people."[37] His mother, Johanna, was generally described as vivacious and sociable.[34]: 9  She died 24 years later. Some of Arthur's negative opinions about women may be rooted in his troubled relationship with his mother.[38]

Arthur moved to Hamburg to live with his friend Jean Anthime, who was also studying to become a merchant.

Education

He moved to Weimar but did not live with his mother, who even tried to discourage him from coming by explaining that they would not get along very well.[34]: 131  Their relationship deteriorated even further due to their temperamental differences. He accused his mother of being financially irresponsible, flirtatious and seeking to remarry, which he considered an insult to his father's memory.[34]: 116,131  His mother, while professing her love to him, criticized him sharply for being moody, tactless, and argumentative, and urged him to improve his behavior so that he would not alienate people.[34]: 129  Arthur concentrated on his studies, which were now going very well, and he also enjoyed the usual social life such as balls, parties and theater. By that time Johanna's famous salon was well established among local intellectuals and dignitaries, the most celebrated of them being Goethe. Arthur attended her parties, usually when he knew that Goethe would be there—although the famous writer and statesman seemed not even to notice the young and unknown student. It is possible that Goethe kept a distance because Johanna warned him about her son's depressive and combative nature, or because Goethe was then on bad terms with Arthur's language instructor and roommate, Franz Passow.[34]: 134  Schopenhauer was also captivated by the beautiful Karoline Jagemann, mistress of Karl August, Grand Duke of Saxe-Weimar-Eisenach, and he wrote to her his only known love poem.[34]: 135  Despite his later celebration of asceticism and negative views of sexuality, Schopenhauer occasionally had sexual affairs—usually with women of lower social status, such as servants, actresses, and sometimes even paid prostitutes.[34]: 21  In a letter to his friend Anthime he claims that such affairs continued even in his mature age and admits that he had two out-of-wedlock daughters (born in 1819 and 1836), both of whom died in infancy.[34]: 25  In their youthful correspondence Arthur and Anthime were somewhat boastful and competitive about their sexual exploits—but Schopenhauer seemed aware that women usually did not find him very charming or physically attractive, and his desires often remained unfulfilled.[34]: 22 

He left Weimar to become a student at the University of Göttingen in 1809. There are no written reasons about why Schopenhauer chose that university instead of the then more famous University of Jena, but Göttingen was known as more modern and scientifically oriented, with less attention given to theology.[34]: 140  Law or medicine were usual choices for young men of Schopenhauer's status who also needed career and income; he chose medicine due to his scientific interests. Among his notable professors were Bernhard Friedrich Thibaut, Arnold Hermann Ludwig Heeren, Johann Friedrich Blumenbach, Friedrich Stromeyer, Heinrich Adolf Schrader, Johann Tobias Mayer and Konrad Johann Martin Langenbeck.[34]: 141–144  He studied metaphysics, psychology and logic under Gottlob Ernst Schulze, the author of Aenesidemus, who made a strong impression and advised him to concentrate on Plato and Immanuel Kant.[34]: 144  He decided to switch from medicine to philosophy around 1810–11 and he left Göttingen, which did not have a strong philosophy program: besides Schulze, the only other philosophy professor was Friedrich Bouterwek, whom Schopenhauer disliked.[34]: 150  He did not regret his medicinal and scientific studies; he claimed that they were necessary for a philosopher, and even in Berlin he attended more lectures in sciences than in philosophy.[34]: 170  During his days at Göttingen, he spent considerable time studying, but also continued his flute playing and social life. His friends included Friedrich Gotthilf Osann, Karl Witte, Christian Charles Josias von Bunsen, and William Backhouse Astor Sr.[34]: 151 

He arrived at the newly founded University of Berlin for the winter semester of 1811–12. At the same time, his mother had just begun her literary career; she published her first book in 1810, a biography of her friend Karl Ludwig Fernow, which was a critical success. Arthur attended lectures by the prominent post-Kantian philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte, but quickly found many points of disagreement with his Wissenschaftslehre; he also found Fichte's lectures tedious and hard to understand.[34]: 159  He later mentioned Fichte only in critical, negative terms[34]: 159 —seeing his philosophy as a lower-quality version of Kant's and considering it useful only because Fichte's poor arguments unintentionally highlighted some failings of Kantianism.[34]: 165–169  He also attended the lectures of the famous Protestant theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher, whom he also quickly came to dislike.[34]: 174  His notes and comments on Schleiermacher's lectures show that Schopenhauer was becoming very critical of religion and moving towards atheism.[34]: 175  He learned by self-directed reading; besides Plato, Kant and Fichte he also read the works of Schelling, Fries, Jacobi, Bacon, Locke, and much current scientific literature.[34]: 170  He attended philological courses by August Böckh and Friedrich August Wolf and continued his naturalistic interests with courses by Martin Heinrich Klaproth, Paul Erman, Johann Elert Bode, Ernst Gottfried Fischer, Johann Horkel, Friedrich Christian Rosenthal and Hinrich Lichtenstein (Lichtenstein was also a friend whom he met at one of his mother's parties in Weimar).[34]: 171–174 

Early work

Schopenhauer left Berlin in a rush in 1813, fearing that the city could be attacked and that he could be pressed into military service as Prussia had just joined the war against France.[34]: 179  He returned to Weimar but left after less than a month, disgusted by the fact that his mother was now living with her supposed lover, Georg Friedrich Konrad Ludwig Müller von Gerstenbergk (1778–1838), a civil servant twelve years younger than her; he considered the relationship an act of infidelity to his father's memory.[34]: 188  He settled for a while in Rudolstadt, hoping that no army would pass through the small town. He spent his time in solitude, hiking in the mountains and the Thuringian forest and writing his dissertation, On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. He completed his dissertation at about the same time as the French army was defeated at the Battle of Leipzig. He became irritated by the arrival of soldiers in the town and accepted his mother's invitation to visit her in Weimar. She tried to convince him that her relationship with Gerstenbergk was platonic and that she had no intention of remarrying.[34]: 230  But Schopenhauer remained suspicious and often came in conflict with Gerstenbergk because he considered him untalented, pretentious, and nationalistic.[34]: 231  His mother had just published her second book, Reminiscences of a Journey in the Years 1803, 1804, and 1805, a description of their family tour of Europe, which quickly became a hit. She found his dissertation incomprehensible and said it was unlikely that anyone would ever buy a copy. In a fit of temper Arthur told her that people would read his work long after the "rubbish" she wrote was totally forgotten.[39][40] In fact, although they considered her novels of dubious quality, the Brockhaus publishing firm held her in high esteem because they consistently sold well. Hans Brockhaus (1888–1965) later claimed that his predecessors "saw nothing in this manuscript, but wanted to please one of our best-selling authors by publishing her son's work. We published more and more of her son Arthur's work and today nobody remembers Johanna, but her son's works are in steady demand and contribute to Brockhaus' reputation."[41] He kept large portraits of the pair in his office in Leipzig for the edification of his new editors.[41]

Also contrary to his mother's prediction, Schopenhauer's dissertation made an impression on Goethe, to whom he sent it as a gift.[34]: 241  Although it is doubtful that Goethe agreed with Schopenhauer's philosophical positions, he was impressed by his intellect and extensive scientific education.[34]: 243  Their subsequent meetings and correspondence were a great honor to a young philosopher, who was finally acknowledged by his intellectual hero. They mostly discussed Goethe's newly published (and somewhat lukewarmly received) work on color theory. Schopenhauer soon started writing his own treatise on the subject, On Vision and Colors, which in many points differed from his teacher's. Although they remained polite towards each other, their growing theoretical disagreements—and especially Schopenhauer's extreme self-confidence and tactless criticisms—soon made Goethe become distant again and after 1816 their correspondence became less frequent.[34]: 247–265  Schopenhauer later admitted that he was greatly hurt by this rejection, but he continued to praise Goethe, and considered his color theory a great introduction to his own.[34]: 252,256,265 

Another important experience during his stay in Weimar was his acquaintance with Friedrich Majer[42]—a historian of religion, orientalist and disciple of Herder—who introduced him to Eastern philosophy[43][34]: 266  (see also Indology). Schopenhauer was immediately impressed by the Upanishads (he called them "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed that they contained superhuman concepts) and the Buddha,[43] and put them on a par with Plato and Kant.[34]: 268,272  He continued his studies by reading the Bhagavad Gita, an amateurish German journal Asiatisches Magazin and Asiatick Researches by the Asiatic Society.[34]: 267,272  Schopenhauer held a profound respect for Indian philosophy;[44] although he loved Hindu texts, he never revered a Buddhist text but regarded Buddhism as the most distinguished religion.[45][34]: 272  His studies on Hindu and Buddhist texts were constrained by the lack of adequate literature,[46] and the latter were mostly restricted to Theravada Buddhism. He also claimed that he formulated most of his ideas independently,[43] and only later realized the similarities with Buddhism.[34]: 274–276 

Schopenhauer read the Latin translation and praised the Upanishads in his main work, The World as Will and Representation (1819), as well as in his Parerga and Paralipomena (1851), and commented,

In the whole world there is no study so beneficial and so elevating as that of the Upanishads. It has been the solace of my life, it will be the solace of my death.[47]

 
Schopenhauer in 1815. Portrait by Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl.

As the relationship with his mother fell to a new low, in May 1814 he left Weimar and moved to Dresden.[34]: 265  He continued his philosophical studies, enjoyed the cultural life, socialized with intellectuals and engaged in sexual affairs.[34]: 284  His friends in Dresden were Johann Gottlob von Quandt, Friedrich Laun, Karl Christian Friedrich Krause and Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl, a young painter who made a romanticized portrait of him in which he improved some of Schopenhauer's unattractive physical features.[34]: 278,283  His criticisms of local artists occasionally caused public quarrels when he ran into them in public.[34]: 282  Schopenhauer's main occupation during his stay in Dresden was his seminal philosophical work, The World as Will and Representation, which he started writing in 1814 and finished in 1818.[48] He was recommended to the publisher Friedrich Arnold Brockhaus by Baron Ferdinand von Biedenfeld, an acquaintance of his mother.[34]: 285  Although Brockhaus accepted his manuscript, Schopenhauer made a poor impression because of his quarrelsome and fussy attitude, as well as very poor sales of the book after it was published in December 1818.[34]: 285–289 

In September 1818, while waiting for his book to be published and conveniently escaping an affair with a maid that caused an unwanted pregnancy,[34]: 342  Schopenhauer left Dresden for a year-long vacation in Italy.[34]: 346  He visited Venice, Bologna, Florence, Naples and Milan, travelling alone or accompanied by mostly English tourists he met.[34]: 350  He spent the winter months in Rome, where he accidentally met his acquaintance Karl Witte and engaged in numerous quarrels with German tourists in the Caffè Greco, among them Johann Friedrich Böhmer, who also mentioned his insulting remarks and unpleasant character.[34]: 348–349  He enjoyed art, architecture, and ancient ruins, attended plays and operas, and continued his philosophical contemplation and love affairs.[34]: 346–350  One of his affairs supposedly became serious, and for a while he contemplated marriage to a rich Italian noblewoman—but, despite his mentioning this several times, no details are known and it may have been Schopenhauer exaggerating.[49][34]: 345  He corresponded regularly with his sister Adele and became close to her as her relationship with Johanna and Gerstenbergk also deteriorated.[34]: 344  She informed him about their financial troubles as the banking house of A. L. Muhl in Danzig—in which her mother invested their whole savings and Arthur a third of his—was near bankruptcy.[34]: 351  Arthur offered to share his assets, but his mother refused and became further enraged by his insulting comments.[34]: 352  The women managed to receive only thirty percent of their savings while Arthur, using his business knowledge, took a suspicious and aggressive stance towards the banker and eventually received his part in full.[34]: 354–356  The affair additionally worsened the relationships among all three members of the Schopenhauer family.[34]: 352,354 

He shortened his stay in Italy because of the trouble with Muhl and returned to Dresden.[34]: 356  Disturbed by the financial risk and the lack of responses to his book he decided to take an academic position since it provided him with both income and an opportunity to promote his views.[34]: 358  He contacted his friends at universities in Heidelberg, Göttingen and Berlin and found Berlin most attractive.[34]: 358–362  He scheduled his lectures to coincide with those of the famous philosopher G. W. F. Hegel, whom Schopenhauer described as a "clumsy charlatan".[50] He was especially appalled by Hegel's supposedly poor knowledge of natural sciences and tried to engage him in a quarrel about it already at his test lecture in March 1820.[34]: 363  Hegel was also facing political suspicions at the time, when many progressive professors were fired, while Schopenhauer carefully mentioned in his application that he had no interest in politics.[34]: 362  Despite their differences and the arrogant request to schedule lectures at the same time as his own, Hegel still voted to accept Schopenhauer to the university.[34]: 365  Only five students turned up to Schopenhauer's lectures, and he dropped out of academia. A late essay, "On University Philosophy", expressed his resentment towards the work conducted in academies.

Later life

 
Sculpture of Arthur Schopenhauer by Giennadij Jerszow

After his tenure in academia, he continued to travel extensively, visiting Leipzig, Nuremberg, Stuttgart, Schaffhausen, Vevey, Milan and spending eight months in Florence.[34]: 411  Before he left for his three-year travel, Schopenhauer had an incident with his Berlin neighbor, 47-year-old seamstress Caroline Louise Marquet. The details of the August 1821 incident are unknown. He claimed that he had just pushed her from his entrance after she had rudely refused to leave, and that she had purposely fallen to the ground so that she could sue him. She claimed that he had attacked her so violently that she had become paralyzed on her right side and unable to work. She immediately sued him, and the process lasted until May 1827, when a court found Schopenhauer guilty and forced him to pay her an annual pension until her death in 1842.[34]: 408–411 

Schopenhauer enjoyed Italy, where he studied art and socialized with Italian and English nobles.[34]: 411–414  It was his last visit to the country. He left for Munich and stayed there for a year, mostly recuperating from various health issues, some of them possibly caused by venereal diseases (the treatment his doctor used suggests syphilis).[34]: 415  He contacted publishers, offering to translate Hume into German and Kant into English, but his proposals were declined.[34]: 417,422  Returning to Berlin, he began to study Spanish so he could read some of his favorite authors in their original language. He liked Pedro Calderón de la Barca, Lope de Vega, Miguel de Cervantes, and especially Baltasar Gracián.[34]: 420  He also made failed attempts to publish his translations of their works. A few attempts to revive his lectures—again scheduled at the same time as Hegel's—also failed, as did his inquiries about relocating to other universities.[34]: 429–432 

During his Berlin years, Schopenhauer occasionally mentioned his desire to marry and have a family.[34]: 404,432  For a while he was unsuccessfully courting 17-year-old Flora Weiss, who was 22 years younger than himself.[34]: 433  His unpublished writings from that time show that he was already very critical of monogamy but still not advocating polygyny—instead musing about a polyamorous relationship that he called "tetragamy".[34]: 404–408  He had an on-and-off relationship with a young dancer, Caroline Richter (she also used the surname Medon after one of her ex-lovers).[34]: 403  They met when he was 33 and she was 19 and working at the Berlin Opera. She had already had numerous lovers and a son out of wedlock, and later gave birth to another son, this time to an unnamed foreign diplomat (she soon had another pregnancy but the child was stillborn).[34]: 403–404  As Schopenhauer was preparing to escape from Berlin in 1831, due to a cholera epidemic, he offered to take her with him on the condition that she left her young son behind.[34]: 404  She refused and he went alone; in his will he left her a significant sum of money, but insisted that it should not be spent in any way on her second son.[34]: 404 

Schopenhauer claimed that, in his last year in Berlin, he had a prophetic dream that urged him to escape from the city.[34]: 436  As he arrived in his new home in Frankfurt, he supposedly had another supernatural experience, an apparition of his dead father and his mother, who was still alive.[34]: 436  This experience led him to spend some time investigating paranormal phenomena and magic. He was quite critical of the available studies and claimed that they were mostly ignorant or fraudulent, but he did believe that there are authentic cases of such phenomena and tried to explain them through his metaphysics as manifestations of the will.[34]: 437–452 

Upon his arrival in Frankfurt, he experienced a period of depression and declining health.[34]: 454  He renewed his correspondence with his mother, and she seemed concerned that he might commit suicide like his father.[34]: 454–457  By now Johanna and Adele were living very modestly. Johanna's writing did not bring her much income, and her popularity was waning.[34]: 458  Their correspondence remained reserved, and Arthur seemed undisturbed by her death in 1838.[34]: 460  His relationship with his sister grew closer and he corresponded with her until she died in 1849.[34]: 463 

In July 1832, Schopenhauer left Frankfurt for Mannheim but returned in July 1833 to remain there for the rest of his life, except for a few short journeys.[34]: 464  He lived alone except for a succession of pet poodles named Atman and Butz. In 1836, he published On the Will in Nature. In 1836, he sent his essay "On the Freedom of the Will" to the contest of the Royal Norwegian Society of Sciences and won the prize for the following year. He sent another essay, "On the Basis of Morality", to the Royal Danish Society for Scientific Studies, but did not win the prize despite being the only contestant. The Society was appalled that several distinguished contemporary philosophers were mentioned in a very offensive manner, and claimed that the essay missed the point of the set topic and that the arguments were inadequate.[34]: 483  Schopenhauer, who had been very confident that he would win, was enraged by this rejection. He published both essays as The Two Basic Problems of Ethics. The first edition, published in 1841, again failed to draw attention to his philosophy. In the preface to the second edition, in 1860, he was still pouring insults on the Royal Danish Society.[34]: 484  Two years later, after some negotiations, he managed to convince his publisher, Brockhaus, to print the second, updated edition of The World as Will and Representation. That book was again mostly ignored and the few reviews were mixed or negative.

Schopenhauer began to attract some followers, mostly outside academia, among practical professionals (several of them were lawyers) who pursued private philosophical studies. He jokingly referred to them as "evangelists" and "apostles".[34]: 504  One of the most active early followers was Julius Frauenstädt, who wrote numerous articles promoting Schopenhauer's philosophy. He was also instrumental in finding another publisher after Brockhaus declined to publish Parerga and Paralipomena, believing that it would be another failure.[34]: 506  Though Schopenhauer later stopped corresponding with him, claiming that he did not adhere closely enough to his ideas, Frauenstädt continued to promote Schopenhauer's work.[34]: 507–508  They renewed their communication in 1859 and Schopenhauer named him heir for his literary estate.[34]: 508  Frauenstädt also became the editor of the first collected works of Schopenhauer.[34]: 506 

In 1848, Schopenhauer witnessed violent upheaval in Frankfurt after General Hans Adolf Erdmann von Auerswald and Prince Felix Lichnowsky were murdered. He became worried for his own safety and property.[34]: 514  Even earlier in life he had had such worries and kept a sword and loaded pistols near his bed to defend himself from thieves.[34]: 465  He gave a friendly welcome to Austrian soldiers who wanted to shoot revolutionaries from his window and as they were leaving he gave one of the officers his opera glasses to help him monitor rebels.[34]: 514  The rebellion passed without any loss to Schopenhauer and he later praised Alfred I, Prince of Windisch-Grätz for restoring order.[34]: 515  He even modified his will, leaving a large part of his property to a Prussian fund that helped soldiers who became invalids while fighting rebellion in 1848 or the families of soldiers who died in battle.[34]: 517  As Young Hegelians were advocating change and progress, Schopenhauer claimed that misery is natural for humans and that, even if some utopian society were established, people would still fight each other out of boredom, or would starve due to overpopulation.[34]: 515 

 
1855 painting of Schopenhauer by Jules Lunteschütz

In 1851, Schopenhauer published Parerga and Paralipomena, which contains essays that are supplementary to his main work. It was his first successful, widely read book, partly due to the work of his disciples who wrote praising reviews.[34]: 524  The essays that proved most popular were the ones that actually did not contain the basic philosophical ideas of his system.[34]: 539  Many academic philosophers considered him a great stylist and cultural critic but did not take his philosophy seriously.[34]: 539  His early critics liked to point out similarities of his ideas to those Fichte and Schelling,[34]: 381–386  or to claim that there were numerous contradictions in his philosophy.[34]: 381–386,537  Both criticisms enraged Schopenhauer. He was becoming less interested in intellectual fights, but encouraged his disciples to do so.[34]: 525  His private notes and correspondence show that he acknowledged some of the criticisms regarding contradictions, inconsistencies, and vagueness in his philosophy, but claimed that he was not concerned about harmony and agreement in his propositions[34]: 394  and that some of his ideas should not be taken literally but instead as metaphors.[34]: 510 

Academic philosophers were also starting to notice his work. In 1856, the University of Leipzig sponsored an essay contest about Schopenhauer's philosophy, which was won by Rudolf Seydel's very critical essay.[34]: 536  Schopenhauer's friend Jules Lunteschütz made the first of his four portraits of him—which Schopenhauer did not particularly like—which was soon sold to a wealthy landowner, Carl Ferdinand Wiesike, who built a house to display it. Schopenhauer seemed flattered and amused by this, and would claim that it was his first chapel.[34]: 540  As his fame increased, copies of paintings and photographs of him were being sold and admirers were visiting the places where he had lived and written his works. People visited Frankfurt's Englischer Hof to observe him dining. Admirers gave him gifts and asked for autographs.[34]: 541  He complained that he still felt isolated due to his not very social nature and the fact that many of his good friends had already died from old age.[34]: 542 

 
Grave at the Hauptfriedhof in Frankfurt

He remained healthy in his own old age, which he attributed to regular walks no matter the weather and always getting enough sleep.[34]: 544–545  He had a great appetite and could read without glasses, but his hearing had been declining since his youth and he developed problems with rheumatism.[34]: 545  He remained active and lucid, continued his reading, writing and correspondence until his death.[34]: 545  The numerous notes that he made during these years, amongst others on aging, were published posthumously under the title Senilia. In the spring of 1860 his health began to decline, and he experienced shortness of breath and heart palpitations; in September he suffered inflammation of the lungs and, although he was starting to recover, he remained very weak.[34]: 546  The last friend to visit him was Wilhelm Gwinner; according to him, Schopenhauer was concerned that he would not be able to finish his planned additions to Parerga and Paralipomena but was at peace with dying.[34]: 546–547  He died of pulmonary-respiratory failure[51] on 21 September 1860 while sitting at home on his couch. He died at the age of 72 and had a funeral conducted by a Lutheran minister.[52][53]

Philosophy

The world as representation

Schopenhauer saw his philosophy as an extension of Kant's, and used the results of Kantian epistemological investigation (transcendental idealism) as starting point for his own. Kant had argued that the empirical world is merely a complex of appearances whose existence and connection occur only in our mental representations.[54] Schopenhauer did not deny that the external world existed empirically but followed Kant in claiming that our knowledge and experience of the world is always indirect.[55] Schopenhauer reiterates this in the first sentence of his main work: "The world is my representation (Die Welt ist meine Vorstellung)". Everything that there is for cognition (the entire world) exists simply as an object in relation to a subject—a 'representation' to a subject. Everything that belongs to the world is, therefore, 'subject-dependent'. In Book One of The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer considers the world from this angle—that is, insofar as it is representation.

Theory of perception

In November 1813 Goethe invited Schopenhauer to help him on his Theory of Colours. Although Schopenhauer considered colour theory a minor matter,[56] he accepted the invitation out of admiration for Goethe. Nevertheless, these investigations led him to his most important discovery in epistemology: finding a demonstration for the a priori nature of causality.

Kant openly admitted that it was Hume's skeptical assault on causality that motivated the critical investigations in Critique of Pure Reason and gave an elaborate proof to show that causality is a priori. After G. E. Schulze had made it plausible that Kant had not disproven Hume's skepticism, it was up to those loyal to Kant's project to prove this important matter.

The difference between the approaches of Kant and Schopenhauer was this: Kant simply declared that the empirical content of perception is "given" to us from outside, an expression with which Schopenhauer often expressed his dissatisfaction.[57] He, on the other hand, was occupied with the questions: how do we get this empirical content of perception; how is it possible to comprehend subjective sensations "limited to my skin" as the objective perception of things that lie "outside" of me?[58]

The sensations in the hand of a man born blind, on feeling an object of cubic shape, are quite uniform and the same on all sides and in every direction: the edges, it is true, press upon a smaller portion of his hand, still nothing at all like a cube is contained in these sensations. His Understanding draws the immediate and intuitive conclusion from the resistance felt, that this resistance must have a cause, which then presents itself through that conclusion as a hard body; and through the movements of his arms in feeling the object, while the hand's sensation remains unaltered, he constructs the cubic shape in Space. If the representation of a cause and of Space, together with their laws, had not already existed within him, the image of a cube could never have proceeded from those successive sensations in his hand.[59]

Causality is therefore not an empirical concept drawn from objective perceptions, as Hume had maintained; instead, as Kant had said, objective perception presupposes knowledge of causality.[60]

By this intellectual operation, comprehending every effect in our sensory organs as having an external cause, the external world arises. With vision, finding the cause is essentially simplified due to light acting in straight lines. We are seldom conscious of the process that interprets the double sensation in both eyes as coming from one object, that inverts the impressions on the retinas, and that uses the change in the apparent position of an object relative to more distant objects provided by binocular vision to perceive depth and distance.

Schopenhauer stresses the importance of the intellectual nature of perception; the senses furnish the raw material by which the intellect produces the world as representation. He set out his theory of perception for the first time in On Vision and Colors,[61] and, in the subsequent editions of Fourfold Root, an extensive exposition is given in § 21.

The world as will

In Book Two of The World as Will and Representation, Schopenhauer considers what the world is beyond the aspect of it that appears to us—that is, the aspect of the world beyond representation, the world considered "in-itself" or "noumena", its inner essence. The very being in-itself of all things, Schopenhauer argues, is will (Wille). The empirical world that appears to us as representation has plurality and is ordered in a spatio-temporal framework. The world as thing in-itself must exist outside the subjective forms of space and time. Although the world manifests itself to our experience as a multiplicity of objects (the "objectivation" of the will), each element of this multiplicity has the same blind essence striving towards existence and life. Human rationality is merely a secondary phenomenon that does not distinguish humanity from the rest of nature at the fundamental, essential level. The advanced cognitive abilities of human beings, Schopenhauer argues, serve the ends of willing—an illogical, directionless, ceaseless striving that condemns the human individual to a life of suffering unredeemed by any final purpose. Schopenhauer's philosophy of the will as the essential reality behind the world as representation is often called metaphysical voluntarism.[3]

For Schopenhauer, understanding the world as will leads to ethical concerns (see the ethics section below for further detail), which he explores in the Fourth Book of The World as Will and Representation and again in his two prize essays on ethics, On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality. No individual human actions are free, Schopenhauer argues, because they are events in the world of appearance and thus are subject to the principle of sufficient reason: a person's actions are a necessary consequence of motives and the given character of the individual human. Necessity extends to the actions of human beings just as it does to every other appearance, and thus we cannot speak of freedom of individual willing. Albert Einstein quoted the Schopenhauerian idea that "a man can do as he will, but not will as he will."[62] Yet the will as thing in-itself is free, as it exists beyond the realm of representation and thus is not constrained by any of the forms of necessity that are part of the principle of sufficient reason.

According to Schopenhauer, salvation from our miserable existence can come through the will's being "tranquillized" by the metaphysical insight that reveals individuality to be merely an illusion. The saint or 'great soul' intuitively "recognizes the whole, comprehends its essence, and finds that it is constantly passing away, caught up in vain strivings, inner conflict, and perpetual suffering".[63] The negation of the will, in other words, stems from the insight that the world in-itself (free from the forms of space and time) is one. Ascetic practices, Schopenhauer remarks, are used to aid the will's "self-abolition", which brings about a blissful, redemptive "will-less" state of emptiness that is free from striving or suffering.

Art and aesthetics

 
In his main work, Schopenhauer praised the Dutch Golden Age artists, who "directed such purely objective perception to the most insignificant objects, and set up a lasting monument of their objectivity and spiritual peace in paintings of still life. The aesthetic beholder does not contemplate this without emotion."[64]

For Schopenhauer, human "willing"—desiring, craving, etc.—is at the root of suffering. A temporary way to escape this pain is through aesthetic contemplation. Here one moves away from ordinary cognizance of individual things to cognizance of eternal Platonic Ideas—in other words, cognizance that is free from the service of will. In aesthetic contemplation, one no longer perceives an object of perception as something from which one is separated; rather "it is as if the object alone existed without anyone perceiving it, and one can thus no longer separate the perceiver from the perception, but the two have become one, the entirety of consciousness entirely filled and occupied by a single perceptual image".[65] Subject and object are no longer distinguishable, and the Idea comes to the fore.

From this aesthetic immersion, one is no longer an individual who suffers as a result of servitude to one's individual will but, rather, becomes a "pure, will-less, painless, timeless, subject of cognition". The pure, will-less subject of cognition is cognizant only of Ideas, not individual things: this is a kind of cognition that is unconcerned with relations between objects according to the Principle of Sufficient Reason (time, space, cause and effect) and instead involves complete absorption in the object.

Art is the practical consequence of this brief aesthetic contemplation, since it attempts to depict the essence/pure Ideas of the world. Music, for Schopenhauer, is the purest form of art because it is the one that depicts the will itself without it appearing as subject to the Principle of Sufficient Reason, therefore as an individual object. According to Daniel Albright, "Schopenhauer thought that music was the only art that did not merely copy ideas, but actually embodied the will itself".[66] He deemed music a timeless, universal language comprehended everywhere, that can imbue global enthusiasm, if in possession of a significant melody.[67]

Mathematics

Schopenhauer's realist views on mathematics are evident in his criticism of contemporaneous attempts to prove the parallel postulate in Euclidean geometry. Writing shortly before the discovery of hyperbolic geometry demonstrated the logical independence of the axiom—and long before the general theory of relativity revealed that it does not necessarily express a property of physical space—Schopenhauer criticized mathematicians for trying to use indirect concepts to prove what he held was directly evident from intuitive perception.

The Euclidean method of demonstration has brought forth from its own womb its most striking parody and caricature in the famous controversy over the theory of parallels, and in the attempts, repeated every year, to prove the eleventh axiom (also known as the fifth postulate). The axiom asserts, and that indeed through the indirect criterion of a third intersecting line, that two lines inclined to each other (for this is the precise meaning of "less than two right angles"), if produced far enough, must meet. Now this truth is supposed to be too complicated to pass as self-evident, and therefore needs a proof; but no such proof can be produced, just because there is nothing more immediate.[68]

Throughout his writings,[69] Schopenhauer criticized the logical derivation of philosophies and mathematics from mere concepts, instead of from intuitive perceptions.

In fact, it seems to me that the logical method is in this way reduced to an absurdity. But it is precisely through the controversies over this, together with the futile attempts to demonstrate the directly certain as merely indirectly certain, that the independence and clearness of intuitive evidence appear in contrast with the uselessness and difficulty of logical proof, a contrast as instructive as it is amusing. The direct certainty will not be admitted here, just because it is no merely logical certainty following from the concept, and thus resting solely on the relation of predicate to subject, according to the principle of contradiction. But that eleventh axiom regarding parallel lines is a synthetic proposition a priori, and as such has the guarantee of pure, not empirical, perception; this perception is just as immediate and certain as is the principle of contradiction itself, from which all proofs originally derive their certainty. At bottom this holds good of every geometrical theorem ...

Although Schopenhauer could see no justification for trying to prove Euclid's parallel postulate, he did see a reason for examining another of Euclid's axioms.[70]

It surprises me that the eighth axiom,[71] "Figures that coincide with one another are equal to one another", is not rather attacked. For "coinciding with one another" is either a mere tautology, or something quite empirical, belonging not to pure intuition or perception, but to external sensuous experience. Thus it presupposes mobility of the figures, but matter alone is movable in space. Consequently, this reference to coincidence with one another forsakes pure space, the sole element of geometry, in order to pass over to the material and empirical.[68]

This follows Kant's reasoning.[72]

Ethics

Schopenhauer asserts that the task of ethics is not to prescribe moral actions that ought to be done, but to investigate moral actions. As such, he states that philosophy is always theoretical: its task to explain what is given.[73]

According to Kant's transcendental idealism, space and time are forms of our sensibility in which phenomena appear in multiplicity. Reality in itself is free from multiplicity, not in the sense that an object is one, but that it is outside the possibility of multiplicity. Two individuals, though they appear distinct, are in-themselves not distinct.[74]

Appearances are entirely subordinated to the principle of sufficient reason. The egoistic individual who focuses his aims on his own interests has to deal with empirical laws as well as he can.

What is relevant for ethics are individuals who can act against their own self-interest. If we take a man who suffers when he sees his fellow men living in poverty and consequently uses a significant part of his income to support their needs instead of his own pleasures, then the simplest way to describe this is that he makes less distinction between himself and others than is usually made.[75]

Regarding how things appear to us, the egoist asserts a gap between two individuals, but the altruist experiences the sufferings of others as his own. In the same way a compassionate man cannot hurt animals, though they appear as distinct from himself.

What motivates the altruist is compassion. The suffering of others is for him not a cold matter to which he is indifferent, but he feels connectiveness to all beings. Compassion is thus the basis of morality.[76]

Eternal justice

Schopenhauer calls the principle through which multiplicity appears the principium individuationis. When we behold nature we see that it is a cruel battle for existence. Individual manifestations of the will can maintain themselves only at the expense of others—the will, as the only thing that exists, has no other option but to devour itself to experience pleasure. This is a fundamental characteristic of the will, and cannot be circumvented.[77]

Unlike temporal or human justice, which requires time to repay an evil deed and "has its seat in the state, as requiting and punishing",[78] eternal justice "rules not the state but the world, is not dependent upon human institutions, is not subject to chance and deception, is not uncertain, wavering, and erring, but infallible, fixed, and sure".[78] Eternal justice is not retributive, because retribution requires time. There are no delays or reprieves. Instead, punishment is tied to the offence, "to the point where the two become one. ... Tormenter and tormented are one. The [Tormenter] errs in that he believes he is not a partaker in the suffering; the [tormented], in that he believes he is not a partaker in the guilt."[78]

Suffering is the moral outcome of our attachment to pleasure. Schopenhauer deemed that this truth was expressed by the Christian dogma of original sin and, in Eastern religions, by the dogma of rebirth.

Quietism

He who sees through the principium individuationis and comprehends suffering in general as his own will see suffering everywhere and, instead of fighting for the happiness of his individual manifestation, will abhor life itself since he knows that it is inseparably connected with suffering. For him, a happy individual life in a world of suffering is like a beggar who dreams one night that he is a king.[79]

Those who have experienced this intuitive knowledge cannot affirm life, but exhibit asceticism and quietism, meaning that they are no longer sensitive to motives, are not concerned about their individual welfare, and accept without resistance the evil that others inflict on them. They welcome poverty and neither seek nor flee death.[79] Schopenhauer referred to asceticism as the denial of the will to live.

Human life is a ceaseless struggle for satisfaction and, instead of continuing their struggle, ascetics break it. It does not matter if these ascetics adhere to the dogmata of Christianity or to Dharmic religions, since their way of living is the result of intuitive knowledge.

The Christian mystic and the teacher of the Vedanta philosophy agree in this respect also, they both regard all outward works and religious exercises as superfluous for him who has attained to perfection. So much agreement in the case of such different ages and nations is a practical proof that what is expressed here is not, as optimistic dullness likes to assert, an eccentricity and perversity of the mind, but an essential side of human nature, which only appears so rarely because of its excellence.[79]

Psychology

Philosophers have not traditionally been impressed by the necessity of sex, but Schopenhauer addressed sex and related concepts forthrightly:

... one ought rather to be surprised that a thing [sex] which plays throughout so important a part in human life has hitherto practically been disregarded by philosophers altogether, and lies before us as raw and untreated material.[80]

He named a force within man that he felt took invariable precedence over reason: the Will to Live or Will to Life (Wille zum Leben), defined as an inherent drive within human beings, and all creatures, to stay alive; a force that inveigles[81] us into reproducing.

Schopenhauer refused to conceive of love as either trifling or accidental, but rather understood it as an immensely powerful force that lay unseen within man's psyche, guaranteeing the quality of the human race:

The ultimate aim of all love affairs ... is more important than all other aims in man's life; and therefore it is quite worthy of the profound seriousness with which everyone pursues it. What is decided by it is nothing less than the composition of the next generation ...[82]

It has often been argued that Schopenhauer's thoughts on sexuality foreshadowed the theory of evolution, a claim met with satisfaction by Darwin as he included a quotation from Schopenhauer in his Descent of Man.[83] This has also been noted about Freud's concepts of the libido and the unconscious mind, and evolutionary psychology in general.[84]

Political and social thought

Politics

 
Bust in Frankfurt

Schopenhauer's politics were an echo of his system of ethics, which he elucidated in detail in his Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik (the two essays On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality).

In occasional political comments in his Parerga and Paralipomena and Manuscript Remains, Schopenhauer described himself as a proponent of limited government. Schopenhauer shared the view of Thomas Hobbes on the necessity of the state and state action to check the innate destructive tendencies of our species. He also defended the independence of the legislative, judicial and executive branches of power, and a monarch as an impartial element able to practise justice (in a practical and everyday sense, not a cosmological one).[85]

He declared that monarchy is "natural to man in almost the same way as it is to bees and ants, to cranes in flight, to wandering elephants, to wolves in a pack in search of prey, and to other animals".[86] Intellect in monarchies, he writes, always has "much better chances against stupidity, its implacable and ever-present foe, than it has in republics; but this is a great advantage."[86] On the other hand, Schopenhauer disparaged republicanism as being "as unnatural to man as it is unfavorable to higher intellectual life and thus to the arts and sciences".[87]

By his own admission, Schopenhauer did not give much thought to politics, and several times he wrote proudly of how little attention he paid "to political affairs of [his] day". In a life that spanned several revolutions in French and German government, and a few continent-shaking wars, he maintained his position of "minding not the times but the eternities". He wrote many disparaging remarks about Germany and the Germans. A typical example is: "For a German it is even good to have somewhat lengthy words in his mouth, for he thinks slowly, and they give him time to reflect."[88]

Punishment

The State, Schopenhauer claimed, punishes criminals to prevent future crimes. It places "beside every possible motive for committing a wrong a more powerful motive for leaving it undone, in the inescapable punishment. Accordingly, the criminal code is as complete a register as possible of counter-motives to all criminal actions that can possibly be imagined ..."[89] He claimed that this doctrine was not original to him but had appeared in the writings of Plato,[90] Seneca, Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Anselm Feuerbach.

Races and religions

Schopenhauer attributed civilizational primacy to the northern "white races" due to their sensitivity and creativity (except for the ancient Egyptians and Hindus, whom he saw as equal):

The highest civilization and culture, apart from the ancient Hindus and Egyptians, are found exclusively among the white races; and even with many dark peoples, the ruling caste or race is fairer in colour than the rest and has, therefore, evidently immigrated, for example, the Brahmans, the Incas, and the rulers of the South Sea Islands. All this is due to the fact that necessity is the mother of invention because those tribes that emigrated early to the north, and there gradually became white, had to develop all their intellectual powers and invent and perfect all the arts in their struggle with need, want and misery, which in their many forms were brought about by the climate. This they had to do in order to make up for the parsimony of nature and out of it all came their high civilization.[91]

Schopenhauer was fervently opposed to slavery. Speaking of the treatment of slaves in the slave-holding states of the United States, he condemned "those devils in human form, those bigoted, church-going, strict sabbath-observing scoundrels, especially the Anglican parsons among them" for how they "treat their innocent black brothers who through violence and injustice have fallen into their devil's claws". The slave-holding states of North America, Schopenhauer writes, are a "disgrace to the whole of humanity".[92]

In his Metaphysics of Sexual Love, Schopenhauer wrote:

Further, the consideration as to the complexion is very decided. Blondes prefer dark persons, or brunettes; but the latter seldom prefer the former. The reason is, that fair hair and blue eyes are in themselves a variation from the type, almost an abnormity, analogous to white mice, or at least to grey horses. In no part of the world, not even in the vicinity of the pole, are they indigenous, except in Europe, and are clearly of Scandinavian origin. I may here express my opinion in passing that the white colour of the skin is not natural to man, but that by nature he has a black or brown skin, like our forefathers the Hindus; that consequently a white man has never originally sprung from the womb of nature, and that thus there is no such thing as a white race, much as this is talked of, but every white man is a faded or bleached one. Forced into the strange world, where he only exists like an exotic plant, and like this requires in winter the hothouse, in the course of thousands of years man became white. The gipsies, an Indian race which immigrated only about four centuries ago, show the transition from the complexion of the Hindu to our own. Therefore in sexual love nature strives to return to dark hair and brown eyes as the primitive type; but the white colour of the skin has become a second nature, though not so that the brown of the Hindu repels us. Finally, each one also seeks in the particular parts of the body the corrective of his own defects and aberrations, and does so the more decidedly the more important the part is.[93]

Schopenhauer also maintained a marked metaphysical and political anti-Judaism. He argued that Christianity constituted a revolt against what he styled the materialistic basis of Judaism, exhibiting an Indian-influenced ethics reflecting the Aryan-Vedic theme of spiritual self-conquest. He saw this as opposed to the ignorant drive toward earthly utopianism and superficiality of a worldly "Jewish" spirit:

[Judaism] is, therefore, the crudest and poorest of all religions and consists merely in an absurd and revolting theism. It amounts to this that the κύριος ['Lord'], who has created the world, desires to be worshipped and adored; and so above all he is jealous, is envious of his colleagues, of all the other gods; if sacrifices are made to them he is furious and his Jews have a bad time ... It is most deplorable that this religion has become the basis of the prevailing religion of Europe; for it is a religion without any metaphysical tendency. While all other religions endeavor to explain to the people by symbols the metaphysical significance of life, the religion of the Jews is entirely immanent and furnishes nothing but a mere war-cry in the struggle with other nations.[94]

Women

In his 1851 essay "On Women", Schopenhauer expressed opposition to what he called "Teutonico-Christian stupidity" of "reflexive, unexamined reverence for the female (abgeschmackten Weiberveneration)".[95] He wrote: "Women are directly fitted for acting as the nurses and teachers of our early childhood by the fact that they are themselves childish, frivolous and short-sighted." He opined that women are deficient in artistic faculties and sense of justice, and expressed his opposition to monogamy.[96] He claimed that "woman is by nature meant to obey". The essay does give some compliments: "women are decidedly more sober in their judgment than [men] are", and are more sympathetic to the suffering of others.

Schopenhauer's writings influenced many, from Friedrich Nietzsche to nineteenth-century feminists.[97] His biological analysis of the difference between the sexes, and their separate roles in the struggle for survival and reproduction, anticipates some of the claims that were later ventured by sociobiologists and evolutionary psychologists.[98]

When the elderly Schopenhauer sat for a sculpture portrait by the Prussian sculptor Elisabet Ney in 1859, he was much impressed by the young woman's wit and independence, as well as by her skill as a visual artist.[99] After his time with Ney, he told Richard Wagner's friend Malwida von Meysenbug: "I have not yet spoken my last word about women. I believe that if a woman succeeds in withdrawing from the mass, or rather raising herself above the mass, she grows ceaselessly and more than a man."[100]

Pederasty

In the third, expanded edition of The World as Will and Representation (1859), Schopenhauer added an appendix to his chapter on the Metaphysics of Sexual Love. He wrote that pederasty has the benefit of preventing ill-begotten children. Concerning this, he stated that "the vice we are considering appears to work directly against the aims and ends of nature, and that in a matter that is all important and of the greatest concern to her it must in fact serve these very aims, although only indirectly, as a means for preventing greater evils".[101] Schopenhauer ends the appendix with the statement that "by expounding these paradoxical ideas, I wanted to grant to the professors of philosophy a small favour. I have done so by giving them the opportunity of slandering me by saying that I defend and commend pederasty."[102]

Heredity and eugenics

 
Schopenhauer at age 58 on 16 May 1846

Schopenhauer viewed personality and intellect as inherited. He quotes Horace's saying, "From the brave and good are the brave descended" (Odes, iv, 4, 29) and Shakespeare's line from Cymbeline, "Cowards father cowards, and base things sire base" (IV, 2) to reinforce his hereditarian argument.[103] Mechanistically, Schopenhauer believed that a person inherits his intellect through his mother, and personal character through the father.[104] This belief in heritability of traits informed Schopenhauer's view of love—placing it at the highest level of importance. For Schopenhauer the "final aim of all love intrigues, be they comic or tragic, is really of more importance than all other ends in human life. What it all turns upon is nothing less than the composition of the next generation. ... It is not the weal or woe of any one individual, but that of the human race to come, which is here at stake." This view of the importance for the species of whom we choose to love was reflected in his views on eugenics or good breeding. Here Schopenhauer wrote:

With our knowledge of the complete unalterability both of character and of mental faculties, we are led to the view that a real and thorough improvement of the human race might be reached not so much from outside as from within, not so much by theory and instruction as rather by the path of generation. Plato had something of the kind in mind when, in the fifth book of his Republic, he explained his plan for increasing and improving his warrior caste. If we could castrate all scoundrels and stick all stupid geese in a convent, and give men of noble character a whole harem, and procure men, and indeed thorough men, for all girls of intellect and understanding, then a generation would soon arise which would produce a better age than that of Pericles.[105]

In another context, Schopenhauer reiterated his eugenic thesis: "If you want Utopian plans, I would say: the only solution to the problem is the despotism of the wise and noble members of a genuine aristocracy, a genuine nobility, achieved by mating the most magnanimous men with the cleverest and most gifted women. This proposal constitutes my Utopia and my Platonic Republic."[106] Analysts (e.g., Keith Ansell-Pearson) have suggested that Schopenhauer's anti-egalitarianist sentiment and his support for eugenics influenced the neo-aristocratic philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, who initially considered Schopenhauer his mentor.[107]

Animal welfare

As a consequence of his monistic philosophy, Schopenhauer was very concerned about animal welfare.[108][109] For him, all individual animals, including humans, are essentially phenomenal manifestations of the one underlying Will. For him the word "will" designates force, power, impulse, energy, and desire; it is the closest word we have that can signify both the essence of all external things and our own direct, inner experience. Since every living thing possesses will, humans and animals are fundamentally the same and can recognize themselves in each other.[110] For this reason, he claimed that a good person would have sympathy for animals, who are our fellow sufferers.

Compassion for animals is intimately associated with goodness of character, and it may be confidently asserted that he who is cruel to living creatures cannot be a good man.

Nothing leads more definitely to a recognition of the identity of the essential nature in animal and human phenomena than a study of zoology and anatomy.

— On the Basis of Morality, chapter 8[111]

The assumption that animals are without rights and the illusion that our treatment of them has no moral significance is a positively outrageous example of Western crudity and barbarity. Universal compassion is the only guarantee of morality.

— On the Basis of Morality, chapter 8[112]

In 1841, he praised the establishment in London of the Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals, and in Philadelphia of the Animals' Friends Society. Schopenhauer went so far as to protest using the pronoun "it" in reference to animals because that led to treatment of them as though they were inanimate things.[113] To reinforce his points, Schopenhauer referred to anecdotal reports of the look in the eyes of a monkey who had been shot[114] and also the grief of a baby elephant whose mother had been killed by a hunter.[115]

Schopenhauer was very attached to his succession of pet poodles. He criticized Spinoza's[116] belief that animals are a mere means for the satisfaction of humans.[117][118]

Intellectual interests and affinities

Indology

 
Photo of Schopenhauer, 1852

Schopenhauer read the Latin translation of the ancient Hindu texts, the Upanishads, translated by French writer Anquetil du Perron[119] from the Persian translation of Prince Dara Shukoh entitled Sirre-Akbar ("The Great Secret"). He was so impressed by its philosophy that he called it "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed it contained superhuman concepts. Schopenhauer considered India as "the land of the most ancient and most pristine wisdom, the place from which Europeans could trace their descent and the tradition by which they had been influenced in so many decisive ways",[119] and regarded the Upanishads as "the most profitable and elevating reading which [...] is possible in the world. It has been the solace of my life, and will be the solace of my death."[119]

Schopenhauer was first introduced to Anquetil du Perron's translation by Friedrich Majer in 1814.[119] They met during the winter of 1813–1814 in Weimar at the home of Schopenhauer's mother, according to the biographer Safranski. Majer was a follower of Herder, and an early Indologist. Schopenhauer did not begin serious study of the Indic texts until the summer of 1814. Safranski maintains that, between 1815 and 1817, Schopenhauer had another important cross-pollination with Indian thought in Dresden. This was through his neighbor of two years, Karl Christian Friedrich Krause. Krause was then a minor and rather unorthodox philosopher who attempted to mix his own ideas with ancient Indian wisdom. Krause had also mastered Sanskrit, unlike Schopenhauer, and they developed a professional relationship. It was from Krause that Schopenhauer learned meditation and received the closest thing to expert advice concerning Indian thought.[120]

The view of things [...] that all plurality is only apparent, that in the endless series of individuals, passing simultaneously and successively into and out of life, generation after generation, age after age, there is but one and the same entity really existing, which is present and identical in all alike;—this theory, I say, was of course known long before Kant; indeed, it may be carried back to the remotest antiquity. It is the alpha and omega of the oldest book in the world, the sacred Vedas, whose dogmatic part, or rather esoteric teaching, is found in the Upanishads. There, in almost every page this profound doctrine lies enshrined; with tireless repetition, in countless adaptations, by many varied parables and similes it is expounded and inculcated.

— On the Basis of Morality, chapter 4[121]

The book Oupnekhat (Upanishad) always lay open on his table, and he invariably studied it before going to bed. He called the opening up of Sanskrit literature "the greatest gift of our century", and predicted that the philosophy and knowledge of the Upanishads would become the cherished faith of the West.[122] Most noticeable, in the case of Schopenhauer's work, was the significance of the Chandogya Upanishad, whose Mahāvākya, Tat Tvam Asi, is mentioned throughout The World as Will and Representation.[123]

Buddhism

Schopenhauer noted a correspondence between his doctrines and the Four Noble Truths of Buddhism.[124] Similarities centered on the principles that life involves suffering, that suffering is caused by desire (taṇhā), and that the extinction of desire leads to liberation. Thus three of the four "truths of the Buddha" correspond to Schopenhauer's doctrine of the will.[125] In Buddhism, while greed and lust are always unskillful, desire is ethically variable – it can be skillful, unskillful, or neutral.[126]

For Schopenhauer, will had ontological primacy over the intellect; desire is prior to thought. Schopenhauer felt this was similar to notions of puruṣārtha or goals of life in Vedānta Hinduism.

In Schopenhauer's philosophy, denial of the will is attained by:

  • personal experience of an extremely great suffering that leads to loss of the will to live; or
  • knowledge of the essential nature of life in the world through observation of the suffering of other people.

Buddhist nirvāṇa is not equivalent to the condition that Schopenhauer described as denial of the will. Nirvāṇa is not the extinguishing of the person as some Western scholars have thought, but only the "extinguishing" (the literal meaning of nirvana) of the flames of greed, hatred, and delusion that assail a person's character.[127] Schopenhauer made the following statement in his discussion of religions:[128]

If I wished to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth, I should have to concede to Buddhism pre-eminence over the others. In any case, it must be a pleasure to me to see my doctrine in such close agreement with a religion that the majority of men on earth hold as their own, for this numbers far more followers than any other. And this agreement must be yet the more pleasing to me, inasmuch as in my philosophizing I have certainly not been under its influence [emphasis added]. For up till 1818, when my work appeared, there was to be found in Europe only a very few accounts of Buddhism.[129]

Buddhist philosopher Keiji Nishitani sought to distance Buddhism from Schopenhauer.[130] While Schopenhauer's philosophy may sound rather mystical in such a summary, his methodology was resolutely empirical, rather than speculative or transcendental:

Philosophy ... is a science, and as such has no articles of faith; accordingly, in it nothing can be assumed as existing except what is either positively given empirically, or demonstrated through indubitable conclusions.[131]

Also note:

This actual world of what is knowable, in which we are and which is in us, remains both the material and the limit of our consideration.[132]

The argument that Buddhism affected Schopenhauer's philosophy more than any other Dharmic faith loses credence since he did not begin a serious study of Buddhism until after the publication of The World as Will and Representation in 1818.[133] Scholars have started to revise earlier views about Schopenhauer's discovery of Buddhism. Proof of early interest and influence appears in Schopenhauer's 1815–16 notes (transcribed and translated by Urs App) about Buddhism. They are included in a recent case study that traces Schopenhauer's interest in Buddhism and documents its influence.[134] Other scholarly work questions how similar Schopenhauer's philosophy actually is to Buddhism.[135]

Magic and occultism

Some traditions in Western esotericism and parapsychology interested Schopenhauer and influenced his philosophical theories. He praised animal magnetism as evidence for the reality of magic in his On the Will in Nature, and went so far as to accept the division of magic into left-hand and right-hand magic, although he doubted the existence of demons.[136]

Schopenhauer grounded magic in the Will and claimed all forms of magical transformation depended on the human Will, not on ritual. This theory notably parallels Aleister Crowley's system of magic and its emphasis on human will.[136] Given the importance of the Will to Schopenhauer's overarching system, this amounts to "suggesting his whole philosophical system had magical powers."[137] Schopenhauer rejected the theory of disenchantment and claimed philosophy should synthesize itself with magic, which he believed amount to "practical metaphysics."[138]

Neoplatonism, including the traditions of Plotinus and to a lesser extent Marsilio Ficino, has also been cited as an influence on Schopenhauer.[139]

Interests

Schopenhauer had a wide range of interests, from science and opera to occultism and literature.

In his student years, Schopenhauer went more often to lectures in the sciences than philosophy. He kept a strong interest as his personal library contained near to 200 books of scientific literature at his death, and his works refer to scientific titles not found in the library.[34]: 170 

Many evenings were spent in the theatre, opera and ballet; Schopenhauer especially liked the operas of Mozart, Rossini and Bellini.[140] Schopenhauer considered music the highest art, and played the flute during his whole life.[34]: 30 

As a polyglot, he knew German, Italian, Spanish, French, English, Latin and ancient Greek, and was an avid reader of poetry and literature. He particularly revered Goethe, Petrarch, Calderón and Shakespeare.

If Goethe had not been sent into the world simultaneously with Kant in order to counterbalance him, so to speak, in the spirit of the age, the latter would have been haunted like a nightmare many an aspiring mind and would have oppressed it with great affliction. But now the two have an infinitely wholesome effect from opposite directions and will probably raise the German spirit to a height surpassing even that of antiquity.[34]: 240 

In philosophy, his most important influences were, according to himself, Kant, Plato and the Upanishads. Concerning the Upanishads and Vedas, he writes in The World as Will and Representation:

If the reader has also received the benefit of the Vedas, the access to which by means of the Upanishads is in my eyes the greatest privilege which this still young century (1818) may claim before all previous centuries, if then the reader, I say, has received his initiation in primeval Indian wisdom, and received it with an open heart, he will be prepared in the very best way for hearing what I have to tell him. It will not sound to him strange, as to many others, much less disagreeable; for I might, if it did not sound conceited, contend that every one of the detached statements which constitute the Upanishads, may be deduced as a necessary result from the fundamental thoughts which I have to enunciate, though those deductions themselves are by no means to be found there.[141]

Thoughts on other philosophers

Giordano Bruno and Spinoza

Schopenhauer saw Bruno and Spinoza as philosophers not bound to their age or nation. "Both were fulfilled by the thought, that as manifold the appearances of the world may be, it is still one being, that appears in all of them. ... Consequently, there is no place for God as creator of the world in their philosophy, but God is the world itself."[142][143]

Schopenhauer expressed regret that Spinoza stuck for the presentation of his philosophy with the concepts of scholasticism and Cartesian philosophy, and tried to use geometrical proofs that do not hold because of vague and overly broad definitions. Bruno on the other hand, who knew much about nature and ancient literature, presented his ideas with Italian vividness, and is amongst philosophers the only one who comes near Plato's poetic and dramatic power of exposition.[142][143]

Schopenhauer noted that their philosophies do not provide any ethics, and it is therefore very remarkable that Spinoza called his main work Ethics. In fact, it could be considered complete from the standpoint of life-affirmation, if one completely ignores morality and self-denial.[144] It is yet even more remarkable that Schopenhauer mentions Spinoza as an example of the denial of the will, if one uses the French biography by Jean Maximilien Lucas[145] as the key to Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione.[146]

Immanuel Kant

 
Schopenhauer's philosophy took Kant's work as its foundation. While he praised Kant's greatness, he nonetheless included a highly detailed criticism of Kantian philosophy as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation.

The importance of Kant for Schopenhauer, in philosophy as well as on a personal level, cannot be overstated. Kant's philosophy was the foundation of Schopenhauer's, and he had high praise for the Transcendental Aesthetic section of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Schopenhauer maintained that Kant stands in the same relation to philosophers such as Berkeley and Plato, as Copernicus to Hicetas, Philolaus, and Aristarchus: Kant succeeded in demonstrating what previous philosophers merely asserted.

Schopenhauer writes about Kant's influence on his work in the preface to the second edition of The World as Will and Representation:

I have already explained in the preface to the first edition, that my philosophy is founded on that of Kant, and therefore presupposes a thorough knowledge of it. I repeat this here. For Kant's teaching produces in the mind of everyone who has comprehended it a fundamental change which is so great that it may be regarded as an intellectual new-birth. It alone is able really to remove the inborn realism which proceeds from the original character of the intellect, which neither Berkeley nor Malebranche succeed in doing, for they remain too much in the universal, while Kant goes into the particular, and indeed in a way that is quite unexampled both before and after him, and which has quite a peculiar, and, we might say, immediate effect upon the mind in consequence of which it undergoes a complete undeception, and forthwith looks at all things in another light. Only in this way can any one become susceptible to the more positive expositions which I have to give. On the other hand, he who has not mastered the Kantian philosophy, whatever else he may have studied, is, as it were, in a state of innocence; that is to say, he remains in the grasp of that natural and childish realism in which we are all born, and which fits us for everything possible, with the single exception of philosophy.[147]

In his study room, one bust was of Buddha, the other was of Kant.[148] The bond which Schopenhauer felt with the philosopher of Königsberg is demonstrated in an unfinished poem he dedicated to Kant (included in volume 2 of the Parerga):

With my eyes I followed thee into the blue sky,
And there thy flight dissolved from view.
Alone I stayed in the crowd below,
Thy word and thy book my only solace.—
Through the strains of thy inspiring words
I sought to dispel the dreary solitude.
Strangers on all sides surround me.
The world is desolate and life interminable.[149]

Schopenhauer dedicated one fifth of his main work, The World as Will and Representation, to a detailed criticism of the Kantian philosophy.

Schopenhauer praised Kant for his distinction between appearance and the thing-in-itself, whereas the general consensus in German idealism was that this was the weakest spot of Kant's theory,[61] since, according to Kant, causality can find application on objects of experience only, and consequently, things-in-themselves cannot be the cause of appearances. The inadmissibility of this reasoning was also acknowledged by Schopenhauer. He insisted that this was a true conclusion, drawn from false premises.[150]

Post-Kantian school

The leading figures of post-Kantian philosophyJohann Gottlieb Fichte, F. W. J. Schelling and G. W. F. Hegel—were not respected by Schopenhauer. He argued that they were not philosophers at all, for they lacked "the first requirement of a philosopher, namely a seriousness and honesty of inquiry."[151] Rather, they were merely sophists who, excelling in the art of beguiling the public, pursued their own selfish interests (such as professional advancement within the university system). Diatribes against the vacuity, dishonesty, pomposity, and self-interest of these contemporaries are to be found throughout Schopenhauer's published writings. The following passage is an example:

All this explains the painful impression with which we are seized when, after studying genuine thinkers, we come to the writings of Fichte and Schelling, or even to the presumptuously scribbled nonsense of Hegel, produced as it was with a boundless, though justified, confidence in German stupidity. With those genuine thinkers one always found an honest investigation of truth and just as honest an attempt to communicate their ideas to others. Therefore whoever reads Kant, Locke, Hume, Malebranche, Spinoza, and Descartes feels elevated and agreeably impressed. This is produced through communion with a noble mind which has and awakens ideas and which thinks and sets one thinking. The reverse of all this takes place when we read the above-mentioned three German sophists. An unbiased reader, opening one of their books and then asking himself whether this is the tone of a thinker wanting to instruct or that of a charlatan wanting to impress, cannot be five minutes in any doubt; here everything breathes so much of dishonesty.[152]

Schopenhauer deemed Schelling the most talented of the three and wrote that he would recommend his "elucidatory paraphrase of the highly important doctrine of Kant" concerning the intelligible character, if he had been honest enough to admit he was parroting Kant, instead of hiding this relation in a cunning manner.[153]

Schopenhauer reserved his most unqualified damning condemnation for Hegel, whom he considered less worthy than Fichte or Schelling. Whereas Fichte was merely a windbag (Windbeutel), Hegel was a "commonplace, inane, loathsome, repulsive, and ignorant charlatan."[154] The philosophers Karl Popper and Mario Bunge agreed with this distinction.[155][156] Hegel, Schopenhauer wrote in the preface to his Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, not only "performed no service to philosophy, but he has had a detrimental influence on philosophy, and thereby on German literature in general, really a downright stupefying, or we could even say a pestilential influence, which it is therefore the duty of everyone capable of thinking for himself and judging for himself to counteract in the most express terms at every opportunity."[157]

Schopenhauer's split with Friedrich Nietzsche

The early relationship between Schopenhauer and Friedrich Nietzsche were marked by a close and scholarly connection but later Nietzsche abandoned his former enthusiasm for Schopenhauer's philosophy because he came to conceive of Schopenhauer's advocacy of quietism as "symptomatic of decadence". Later Nietzsche realised the ardent anti-semitism by Schopenhauer and his early friend Richard Wagner. Both Schopenhauer and Wagner accused Nietzsche of "Judeophilia", and pandering to Jewish interests, a standpoint Nietzsche could not accept logically and historically. While both philosophers did not discredit each other's work, the questions of anti-Judaism and differing methodologies regarding ethics and asceticism, were the major reasons why Nietzsche distanced himself from Schopenhauer (and Wagner) in his later years.[158][159]

Influence and legacy

Schopenhauer remained the most influential German philosopher until the First World War.[160] His philosophy was a starting point for a new generation of philosophers including Julius Bahnsen, Paul Deussen, Lazar von Hellenbach, Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann, Ernst Otto Lindner, Philipp Mainländer, Friedrich Nietzsche, Olga Plümacher and Agnes Taubert. His legacy shaped the intellectual debate, and forced movements that were utterly opposed to him, neo-Kantianism and positivism, to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly.[160] The French writer Maupassant commented that "to-day even those who execrate him seem to carry in their own souls particles of his thought".[161] Other philosophers of the 19th century who cited his influence include Hans Vaihinger, Volkelt, Solovyov and Weininger.

Schopenhauer was well read by physicists, most notably Einstein, Schrödinger, Wolfgang Pauli,[162] and Majorana.[14] Einstein described Schopenhauer's thoughts as a "continual consolation" and called him a genius.[163] In his Berlin study three figures hung on the wall: Faraday, Maxwell, Schopenhauer.[164] Konrad Wachsmann recalled: "He often sat with one of the well-worn Schopenhauer volumes, and as he sat there, he seemed so pleased, as if he were engaged with a serene and cheerful work."[165]

When Erwin Schrödinger discovered Schopenhauer ("the greatest savant of the West") he considered switching his study of physics to philosophy.[166] He maintained the idealistic views during the rest of his life.[167] Wolfgang Pauli accepted the main tenet of Schopenhauer's metaphysics, that the thing-in-itself is will.[168]

But most of all Schopenhauer is famous for his influence on artists. Richard Wagner became one of the earliest and most famous adherents of the Schopenhauerian philosophy.[169] The admiration was not mutual, and Schopenhauer proclaimed: "I remain faithful to Rossini and Mozart!"[170] So he has been nicknamed "the artist's philosopher".[1] See also Influence of Schopenhauer on Tristan und Isolde.

 
Schopenhauer depicted on a 500 million Danzig papiermark note (1923)

Under the influence of Schopenhauer, Leo Tolstoy became convinced that the truth of all religions lies in self-renunciation. When he read Schopenhauer's philosophy, Tolstoy exclaimed "at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. ... It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection."[171] He said that what he has written in War and Peace is also said by Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Representation.[172]

Jorge Luis Borges remarked that the reason he had never attempted to write a systematic account of his world view, despite his penchant for philosophy and metaphysics in particular, was because Schopenhauer had already written it for him.[173]

Other figures in literature who were strongly influenced by Schopenhauer were Thomas Mann, Thomas Hardy, Afanasy Fet, J.-K. Huysmans and George Santayana.[174] In Herman Melville's final years, while he wrote Billy Budd, he read Schopenhauer's essays and marked them heavily. Scholar Brian Yothers notes that Melville "marked numerous misanthropic and even suicidal remarks, suggesting an attraction to the most extreme sorts of solitude, but he also made note of Schopenhauer's reflection on the moral ambiguities of genius."[175] Schopenhauer's attraction to and discussions of both Eastern and Western religions in conjunction with each other made an impression on Melville in his final years.

Sergei Prokofiev, although initially reluctant to engage with works noted for their pessimism, became fascinated with Schopenhauer after reading Aphorisms on the Wisdom of Life in Parerga and Paralipomena. "With his truths Schopenhauer gave me a spiritual world and an awareness of happiness."[176]

Friedrich Nietzsche owed the awakening of his philosophical interest to reading The World as Will and Representation and admitted that he was one of the few philosophers that he respected, dedicating to him his essay "Schopenhauer als Erzieher",[177] one of his Untimely Meditations.

 
Commemorative stamp of the Deutsche Bundespost

Early in his career, Ludwig Wittgenstein adopted Schopenhauer's epistemological idealism, and some traits of Schopenhauer's influence (particularly Schopenhauerian transcendentalism) can be observed in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.[178][179] Later on, Wittgenstein rejected epistemological transcendental idealism for Gottlob Frege's conceptual realism. In later years, Wittgenstein became highly dismissive of Schopenhauer, describing him as an ultimately shallow thinker.[23][180] His friend Bertrand Russell had a low opinion on the philosopher, and even came to attack him in his History of Western Philosophy for hypocritically praising asceticism yet not acting upon it.[181]

Opposite to Russell on the foundations of mathematics, the Dutch mathematician L. E. J. Brouwer incorporated Kant's and Schopenhauer's ideas in the philosophical school of intuitionism, where mathematics is considered as a purely mental activity instead of an analytic activity wherein objective properties of reality are revealed. Brouwer was also influenced by Schopenhauer's metaphysics, and wrote an essay on mysticism.

Schopenhauer's philosophy has made its way into a novel, The Schopenhauer Cure, by American existential psychiatrist and emeritus professor of psychiatry Irvin Yalom.

Schopenhauer's philosophy, and the discussions on philosophical pessimism it has engendered, has been the focus of contemporary thinkers such as David Benatar, Thomas Ligotti, and Eugene Thacker. Their work also served as an inspiration for the popular HBO TV series True Detective as well as Life Is Beautiful.[182] In this regard, Schopenhauer is sometimes considered the founding father of today's antinatalism.[183]

Selected bibliography

  • On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde), 1813
  • On Vision and Colors (Ueber das Sehn und die Farben), 1816 ISBN 978-0-85496-988-3
  • Theory of Colors (Theoria colorum physiologica), 1830.
  • The World as Will and Representation (alternatively translated in English as The World as Will and Idea; original German is Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung): vol. 1, 1818–1819, vol. 2, 1844
  • The Art of Being Right (Eristische Dialektik: Die Kunst, Recht zu Behalten), 1831
  • On the Will in Nature (Ueber den Willen in der Natur), 1836 ISBN 978-0-85496-999-9
  • On the Freedom of the Will (Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens), 1839 ISBN 978-0-631-14552-3
  • On the Basis of Morality (Ueber die Grundlage der Moral), 1840
  • The Two Basic Problems of Ethics: On the Freedom of the Will, On the Basis of Morality (Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik: Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens, Ueber das Fundament der Moral), 1841.
  • Parerga and Paralipomena (2 vols., 1851) – Reprint: (Oxford: Clarendon Press) (2 vols., 1974) (English translation by E. F. J. Payne[184])
  • An Enquiry concerning Ghost-seeing, and what is connected therewith (Versuch über das Geistersehn und was damit zusammenhangt), 1851
  • Arthur Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Volume II, Berg Publishers Ltd., ISBN 978-0-85496-539-7

Online

  • Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at Project Gutenberg
  • The Art of Controversy (Die Kunst, Recht zu behalten). (bilingual) [The Art of Being Right]
  • Studies in Pessimism – audiobook from LibriVox
  • The World as Will and Idea at Internet Archive:
    • Volume I
    • Volume II
    • Volume III
  • On the fourfold root of the principle of sufficient reason and On the will in nature. Two essays:
    • Internet Archive. Translated by Mrs. Karl Hillebrand (1903).
    • Cornell University Library Historical Monographs Collection. Reprinted by Cornell University Library Digital Collections
  • in

See also

References

  1. ^ a b "Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)".
  2. ^ Frederick C. Beiser reviews the commonly held position that Schopenhauer was a transcendental idealist and he rejects it: "Though it is deeply heretical from the standpoint of transcendental idealism, Schopenhauer's objective standpoint involves a form of transcendental realism, i.e. the assumption of the independent reality of the world of experience." (Beiser 2016, p. 40)
  3. ^ a b Voluntarism (philosophy) – Britannica.com
  4. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer, Arthur Schopenhauer: The World as Will and Presentation, Volume 1, Routledge, 2016, p. 211: "the world [is a] mere presentation, object for a subject ..."
  5. ^ Lennart Svensson, Borderline: A Traditionalist Outlook for Modern Man, Numen Books, 2015, p. 71: "[Schopenhauer] said that 'the world is our conception'. A world without a perceiver would in that case be an impossibility. But we can—he said—gain knowledge about Essential Reality for looking into ourselves, by introspection. ... This is one of many examples of the anthropic principle. The world is there for the sake of man."
  6. ^ a b The World as Will and Representation, vol. 3, Ch. 50.
  7. ^ a b Dale Jacquette, ed. (2007). Schopenhauer, Philosophy and the Arts. Cambridge University Press. p. 162. ISBN 978-0-521-04406-6. For Kant, the mathematical sublime, as seen for example in the starry heavens, suggests to imagination the infinite, which in turn leads by subtle turns of contemplation to the concept of God. Schopenhauer's atheism will have none of this, and he rightly observes that despite adopting Kant's distinction between the dynamical and mathematical sublime, his theory of the sublime, making reference to the struggles and sufferings of struggles and sufferings of Will, is unlike Kant's.
  8. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, Book 4. For the philosopher, these accounts of the lives of holy, self-denying men, badly as they are generally written, and mixed as they are with superstition and nonsense, are, because of the significance of the material, immeasurably more instructive and important than even Plutarch and Livy. ... But the spirit of this development of Christianity is certainly nowhere so fully and powerfully expressed as in the writings of the German mystics, in the works of Meister Eckhard, and in that justly famous book Die Deutsche Theologie.
  9. ^ Howard, Don A. (December 2005), "Albert Einstein as a Philosopher of Science" (PDF), Physics Today, 58 (12): 34–40, Bibcode:2005PhT....58l..34H, doi:10.1063/1.2169442, archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022, retrieved 8 March 2015 – via University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, author's personal webpage, From Schopenhauer he had learned to regard the independence of spatially separated systems as, virtually, a necessary a priori assumption ... Einstein regarded his separation principle, descended from Schopenhauer's principium individuationis, as virtually an axiom for any future fundamental physics. ... Schopenhauer stressed the essential structuring role of space and time in individuating physical systems and their evolving states. This view implies that difference of location suffices to make two systems different in the sense that each has its own real physical state, independent of the state of the other. For Schopenhauer, the mutual independence of spatially separated systems was a necessary a priori truth.
  10. ^ Frederick C. Beiser, "After Hegel: German Philosophy, 1840–1900." Princeton University Press. 2014. p. 49: "Dilthey's conception of a worldview, as he finally formulated it in Das Wesen der Philosophie, shows a large debt to Schopenhauer. Like his great forebear, Dilthey believed that philosophy had first and foremost an ethical function, that its main purpose was to address 'the puzzle of the world'."
  11. ^ "John Gray: Forget everything you know – Profiles, People". The Independent. London. 3 September 2002. from the original on 9 April 2010. Retrieved 12 March 2010.
  12. ^ Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin (1973). Wittgenstein's Vienna. New York: Simon and Schuster. p. 74. Kraus himself was no philosopher, even less a scientist. If Kraus's views have a philosophical ancestry, this comes most assuredly from Schopenhauer; for alone among the great philosophers, Schopenhauer was a kindred spirit, a man of philosophical profundity, with a strange talent for polemic and aphorism, a literary as weIl as philosophical genius. Schopenhauer, indeed, was the only philosopher who at all appealed to Kraus.
  13. ^ Kerr, R. B. (1932). "Anthony M. Ludovici The prophet of anti-feminism". www.anthonymludovici.com. Retrieved 5 May 2019.
  14. ^ a b Bassani, Giuseppe-Franco (15 December 2006). Società Italiana di Fisica (ed.). Ettore Majorana: Scientific Papers. Springer. p. xl. ISBN 978-3-540-48091-4. His interest in philosophy, which had always been great, increased and prompted him to reflect deeply on the works of various philosophers, in particular Schopenhauer.
  15. ^ Magee, Bryan (1997). Confessions of a Philosopher., Ch. 16
  16. ^ B.F. McGuinness. Moritz Schlick. pp. 336–37. Once again, one has to understand Schlick's world conception, which he took over from Schopenhauer's world as representation and as will. … "To will something"—and here Schlick is heavily influenced by Schopenhauer
  17. ^ Maertz, Gregory (1994). "Elective Affinities: Tolstoy and Schopenhauer". Wiener Slavistisches Jahrbuch. Harrassowitz Verlag. 40: 53–62. ISSN 0084-0041. JSTOR 24748326.
  18. ^ Wells, John C. (2008), Longman Pronunciation Dictionary (3rd ed.), Longman, ISBN 978-1-4058-8118-0
  19. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer (2004). Essays and Aphorisms. Penguin Classics. p. 23. ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4.
    • The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary. 'Schopenhauer': Oxford University Press. 1991. p. 1298. ISBN 978-0-19-861248-3.
  20. ^ See the book-length study about oriental influences on the genesis of Schopenhauer's philosophy by Urs App: Schopenhauer's Compass. An Introduction to Schopenhauer's Philosophy and its Origins. Wil: UniversityMedia, 2014 (ISBN 978-3-906000-03-9)
    • Hergenhahn, B. R. (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology (6th ed.). Cengage Learning. p. 216. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8. Although Schopenhauer was an atheist, he realized that his philosophy of denial had been part of several great religions; for example, Christianity, Hinduism, and Buddhism.
  21. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer (2004). Essays and Aphorisms. Penguin Classics. pp. 22–36. ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4. …but there has been none who tried with so great a show of learning to demonstrate that the pessimistic outlook is justified, that life itself is really bad. It is to this end that Schopenhauer's metaphysic of will and idea exists.
    • Studies in Pessimism – audiobook from LibriVox.
    • David A. Leeming; Kathryn Madden; Stanton Marlan, eds. (2009). Encyclopedia of Psychology and Religion, Volume 2. Springer. p. 824. ISBN 978-0-387-71801-9. A more accurate statement might be that for a German—rather than a French or British writer of that time—Schopenhauer was an honest and open atheist.
  22. ^ Addressed in: Cate, Curtis. Friedrich Nietzsche. Chapter 7.
  23. ^ a b Culture & Value, p. 24, 1933–34
  24. ^ Albert Einstein in Mein Glaubensbekenntnis (August 1932): "I do not believe in free will. Schopenhauer's words: 'Man can do what he wants, but he cannot will what he wants,[Der Mensch kann wohl tun, was er will, aber er kann nicht wollen, was er will]' accompany me in all situations throughout my life and reconcile me with the actions of others, even if they are rather painful to me. This awareness of the lack of free will keeps me from taking myself and my fellow men too seriously as acting and deciding individuals, and from losing my temper." Schopenhauer's clearer, actual words were: "You can do what you will, but in any given moment of your life you can will only one definite thing and absolutely nothing other than that one thing." [Du kannst tun was du willst: aber du kannst in jedem gegebenen Augenblick deines Lebens nur ein Bestimmtes wollen und schlechterdings nichts anderes als dieses eine.] On the Freedom of the Will, Ch. II.
  25. ^ Magee, Bryan. The Philosophy of Schopenhauer. ISBN 978-0-19-823722-8.
  26. ^ Maertz, Gregory (1994). "Elective Affinities: Tolstoy and Schopenhauer". Wiener Slavistisches Jahrbuch. Harrassowitz Verlag. 40: 53–62. ISSN 0084-0041. JSTOR 24748326.
  27. ^ Melville, Herman. "Melville's Marginalia". Melville's Marginalia Online. Retrieved 1 September 2020.
  28. ^ Punsly, Kathryn (2012). The Influence of Nietzsche and Schopenhauer on Hermann Hesse. CMC Senior Theses. Paper 347. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1353&context=cmc_theses Retrieved on 19 March 2021.
  29. ^ Wicks, Robert (2011). Schopenhauer's The world as will and representation : a reader's guide. London: Continuum. ISBN 978-0-8264-3181-3. OCLC 721337622.
  30. ^ a b c d e Shapshay, Sandra, "Schopenhauer's Aesthetics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/schopenhauer-aesthetics Retrieved on 19 March 2021.
  31. ^ Wicks, Robert (2018). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  32. ^ "Schönberg's Library – Alphabetical List". www.schoenberg.at. Retrieved 19 March 2021.
  33. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur; Günter Zöller; Eric F. J. Payne (1999). Chronology. Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will. Cambridge University Press. p. xxx. ISBN 978-0-521-57766-3.
  34. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao ap aq ar as at au av aw ax ay az ba bb bc bd be bf bg bh bi bj bk bl bm bn bo bp bq br bs bt bu bv bw bx by bz ca cb cc cd ce cf cg ch ci cj ck cl cm cn co cp cq cr cs ct cu cv cw cx cy cz da db dc dd de df dg dh di dj dk dl dm dn do dp dq dr ds dt du dv dw dx dy Cartwright, David E. (2010). Schopenhauer: A Biography. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82598-6.
  35. ^ Bullock, A.B. (1920). The Supreme Human Tragedy: And Other Essays. C.W. Daniel. p. 53. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  36. ^ Safranski (1990), pg. 12
  37. ^ Wallace, W. (2003). Life of Arthur Schopenhauer. Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific. p. 59. ISBN 978-1-4102-0641-1.
  38. ^ Durant, Will, The Story of Philosophy, Garden City Publishing Co., Inc., New York, p. 350
  39. ^ . Germanic American Institute. Archived from the original on 11 June 2010. Retrieved 12 March 2010.
  40. ^ "Full text of "Selected Essays Of Schopenhauer"". Retrieved 12 March 2010.
  41. ^ a b Fredriksson, Einar H. (2001), "The Dutch Publishing Scene: Elsevier and North-Holland", A Century of Science Publishing: A Collection of Essays, Amsterdam: IOS Press, pp. 61–76, ISBN 978-4-274-90424-0
  42. ^ Willson, A. Leslie (1961). "Friedrich Majer: Romantic Indologist". Texas Studies in Literature and Language. 3 (1): 40–49. ISSN 0040-4691. JSTOR 40753707.
  43. ^ a b c Clarke 1997, pp. 67–68.
  44. ^ Clarke 1997, pp. 67–69.
  45. ^ Clarke 1997, pp. 273.
  46. ^ Clarke 1997, p. 69.
  47. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (22 April 2019). The world as will and idea. ISBN 978-1-950330-23-2. OCLC 1229105608.
  48. ^ Although the first volume was published by December 1818, it was printed with a title page erroneously giving the year as 1819 (see Braunschweig, Yael (2013), "Schopenhauer and Rossinian Universiality: On the Italianate in Schopenhauer's Metaphysics of Music", The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 297, n. 7, ISBN 978-0-521-76805-4).
  49. ^ Safranski, Rüdiger (1991) Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy. Harvard University Press. p. 244
  50. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. Author's preface to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of sufficient reason", p. 1 (On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason on Wikisource.)
  51. ^ Dale Jacquette, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Routledge, 2015: "Biographical sketch".
  52. ^ Schopenhauer: his life and philosophy by H. Zimmern – 1932 – G. Allen & Unwin.
  53. ^ Lewis, Peter (15 February 2013). Arthur Schopenhauer, 2013. Reaktion Books. ISBN 978-1-78023-069-6.
  54. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Translated by Paul Carus. § 52c.
  55. ^ See the quotation of Schopenhauer in Storm, Jason Josephson (2021). Metamodernism: The Future of Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 36–37. ISBN 978-0-226-78665-0.
  56. ^ Letter to Goethe on 23 January 1816: "Ich weiß, daß durch mich die Wahrheit geredet hat, – in dieser kleinen Sache, wie dereinst in größern."
  57. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1. Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. But the whole teaching of Kant contains really nothing more about this than the oft-repeated meaningless expression: 'The empirical element in perception is given from without.' ... always through the same meaningless metaphorical expression: 'The empirical perception is given us.'
  58. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. § 21. For sensation is and remains a process within the organism and is limited, as such, to the region within the skin; it cannot therefore contain any thing which lies beyond that region, or, in other words, anything that is outside us. ... It is only when the Understanding begins to apply its sole form, the causal law, that a powerful transformation takes place, by which subjective sensation becomes objective perception.
  59. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. § 21.
  60. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 4. The contrary doctrine that the law of causality results from experience, which was the scepticism of Hume, is first refuted by this. For the independence of the knowledge of causality of all experience,—that is, its a priori character—can only be deduced from the dependence of all experience upon it; and this deduction can only be accomplished by proving, in the manner here indicated, and explained in the passages referred to above, that the knowledge of causality is included in perception in general, to which all experience belongs, and therefore in respect of experience is completely a priori, does not presuppose it, but is presupposed by it as a condition.
  61. ^ a b David E. Cartwright; Edward E. Erdmann. Introduction to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason". Cambridge University Press. pp. xvi–xvii. He had also rehearsed for the first time his physiological arguments for the intellectual nature of intuition [Anschauung, objective perception] in his "On Vision and Colours", and he had discussed how his philosophy was corroborated by the sciences in "On Will in Nature". ... Like the German Idealists, Schopenhauer was convinced that Kant's great unknown, the thing in itself, is the weak point of the critical philosophy.
  62. ^ Einstein, Albert (1935). The World as I See It, p. 14. Snowball Publishing. ISBN 1-4948-7706-6.
  63. ^ The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, §68
  64. ^ The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, §38
  65. ^ The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1, §34
  66. ^ Daniel Albright, Modernism and Music, 2004, p. 39, footnote 34
  67. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (1970). Essays and Aphorisms. 10: Penguin Classics. p. 162. ISBN 978-0-14-044227-4.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  68. ^ a b The World as Will and Representation, vol. 2, ch. 13
  69. ^ "I wanted in this way to stress and demonstrate the great difference, indeed opposition, between knowledge of perception and abstract or reflected knowledge. Hitherto this difference has received too little attention, and its establishment is a fundamental feature of my philosophy ..." – The World as Will and Representation., vol. 2, ch. 7, p. 88 (trans. Payne)
  70. ^ This comment by Schopenhauer was called "an acute observation" by Sir Thomas L. Heath. In his translation of The Elements, vol. 1, Book I, "Note on Common Notion 4", Heath made this judgment and also noted that Schopenhauer's remark "was a criticism in advance of Helmholtz' theory". Helmholtz had "maintained that geometry requires us to assume the actual existence of rigid bodies and their free mobility in space" and is therefore "dependent on mechanics".
  71. ^ What Schopenhauer calls the eighth axiom is Euclid's Common Notion 4.
  72. ^ "Motion of an object in space does not belong in a pure science, and consequently not in geometry. For the fact that something is movable cannot be cognized a priori, but can be cognized only through experience." (Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, B 155, Note)
  73. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 53.
  74. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 23.
  75. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 66.
  76. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Basis of Morality. § 19.
  77. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. Parerga and Paralipomena. Vol. 2, § 173.
  78. ^ a b c The World as Will and Idea Vol. 1 § 63
  79. ^ a b c Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, § 68.
  80. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation: Supplements to the Fourth Book
  81. ^ The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary. Schopenhauer: Oxford University Press. 1991. p. 1298. ISBN 978-0-19-861248-3.
  82. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur, The World as Will and Representation, Supplements to the Fourth Book
  83. ^ Darwin, Charles. The Descent of Man. p. 586.
  84. ^ "Nearly a century before Freud ... in Schopenhauer there is, for the first time, an explicit philosophy of the unconscious and of the body." Safranski p. 345.
  85. ^ The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Ch. 47
  86. ^ a b Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 254).
  87. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 255).
  88. ^ The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Ch. 12
  89. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, § 62.
  90. ^ "... he who attempts to punish in accordance with reason does not retaliate on account of the past wrong (for he could not undo something which has been done) but for the future, so that neither the wrongdoer himself, nor others who see him being punished, will do wrong again." Plato, "Protagoras", 324 B. Plato wrote that punishment should "be an example to other men not to offend". Plato, "Laws", Book IX, 863.
  91. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Philosophy and Natural Science," §92, trans. Payne (p. 158-159).
  92. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, "On Ethics," §114, trans. Payne (p. 212).
  93. ^ "The Metaphysics of Sexual Love - the Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia".
  94. ^ "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", Parerga and Paralipomena, Volume I, trans. Payne (p. 126).
  95. ^ "Arthur Schopenhauer: Ueber die Weiber". aboq.org.
  96. ^ Rodgers (environmentalist) and Thompson in Philosophers Behaving Badly call Schopenhauer "a misogynist without rival in ... Western philosophy".
  97. ^ Feminism and the Limits of Equality PA Cain – Ga. L. Rev., 1989
  98. ^ Julian Young (23 June 2005). Schopenhauer. Psychology Press. p. 242. ISBN 978-0-415-33346-7.
  99. ^ Long, Sandra Salser (Spring 1984). "Arthur Schopenhauer and Elisabet Ney". Southwest Review. 69 (2): 130–47. JSTOR 43469632.
  100. ^ Safranski (1990), Chapter 24. p. 348.
  101. ^ Schopenhauer 1969, p. 566
  102. ^ Schopenhauer 1969, p. 567
  103. ^ Payne, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. II, p. 519
  104. ^ On the Suffering of the World (1970), p. 35. Penguin Books – Great Ideas.
  105. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (1969). E. F. J. Payne (ed.). The World as Will and Representation. Vol. II. New York: Dover Publications. p. 527. ISBN 978-0-486-21762-8.
  106. ^ Essays and Aphorisms, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Middlesex: London, 1970, p. 154
  107. ^ Nietzsche and Modern German Thought by K. Ansell-Pearson – 1991 – Psychology Press.
  108. ^ Christina Gerhardt, "Thinking With: Animals in Schopenhauer, Horkheimer and Adorno." Critical Theory and Animals. Ed. John Sanbonmatsu. Lanham: Rowland, 2011. 137–157.
  109. ^ Stephen Puryear, "Schopenhauer on the Rights of Animals." European Journal of Philosophy 25/2 (2017):250-269.
  110. ^ "Unlike the intellect, it [the Will] does not depend on the perfection of the organism, but is essentially the same in all animals as what is known to us so intimately. Accordingly, the animal has all the emotions of humans, such as joy, grief, fear, anger, love, hatred, strong desire, envy, and so on. The great difference between human and animal rests solely on the intellect's degrees of perfection. On the Will in Nature, "Physiology and Pathology".
  111. ^ Quoted in Schopenhauer, Arthur (1994). Philosophical Writings. London: Continuum. p. 233. ISBN 978-0-8264-0729-0.
  112. ^ Quoted in Ryder, Richard (2000). Animal Revolution: Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism. Oxford: Berg Publishers. p. 57. ISBN 978-1-85973-330-1.
  113. ^ "... in English all animals are of the neuter gender and so are represented by the pronoun 'it,' just as if they were inanimate things. The effect of this artifice is quite revolting, especially in the case of primates, such as dogs, monkeys, and the like...." On the Basis of Morality, § 19.
  114. ^ "I recall having read of an Englishman who, while hunting in India, had shot a monkey; he could not forget the look which the dying animal gave him, and since then had never again fired at monkeys." On the Basis of Morality, § 19.
  115. ^ "[Sir William Harris] describes how he shot his first elephant, a female. The next morning he went to look for the dead animal; all the other elephants had fled from the neighborhood except a young one, who had spent the night with its dead mother. Forgetting all fear, he came toward the sportsmen with the clearest and liveliest evidence of inconsolable grief, and put his tiny trunk round them in order to appeal to them for help. Harris says he was then filled with real remorse for what he had done, and felt as if he had committed a murder." On the basis of morality, § 19.
  116. ^ "His contempt for animals, who, as mere things for our use, are declared by him to be without rights, ... in conjunction with Pantheism, is at the same time absurd and abominable." The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Chapter 50.
  117. ^ Spinoza, Ethics, Pt. IV, Prop. XXXVII, Note I.: "Still I do not deny that beasts feel: what I deny is, that we may not consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in a way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours ..." This is the exact opposite of Schopenhauer's doctrine. Also, Ethics, Appendix, 26, "whatsoever there be in nature beside man, a regard for our advantage does not call on us to preserve, but to preserve or destroy according to its various capacities, and to adapt to our use as best we may."
  118. ^ "Such are the matters which I engage to prove in Prop. xviii of this Part, whereby it is plain that the law against the slaughtering of animals is founded rather on vain superstition and womanish pity than on sound reason. The rational quest of what is useful to us further teaches us the necessity of associating ourselves with our fellow-men, but not with beasts, or things, whose nature is different from our own; we have the same rights in respect to them as they have in respect to us. Nay, as everyone's right is defined by his virtue, or power, men have far greater rights over beasts than beasts have over men. Still I affirm that beasts feel. But I also affirm that we may consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in the way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours, and their emotions are naturally different from human emotions." Ethics, Part 4, Prop. 37, Note 1.
  119. ^ a b c d Clarke 1997, p. 68.
  120. ^ Christopher McCoy, 3–4
  121. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (1840). "Part IV". On the Basis of Morality. Translated by Bullock, Arthur Brodrick. London: Swan Sonnenschein (published 1908). pp. 269–271 – via Internet Archive.
  122. ^ Dutt, Purohit Bhagavan. . Archived from the original on 2 August 2010. Retrieved 9 May 2009.
  123. ^ Christopher McCoy, 54–56
  124. ^ Abelson, Peter (April 1993). Schopenhauer and Buddhism 28 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Philosophy East and West Volume 43, Number 2, pp. 255–278. University of Hawaii Press. Retrieved on: 12 April 2008.
  125. ^ Janaway, Christopher, Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy, pp. 28 ff.
  126. ^ David Burton, "Buddhism, Knowledge and Liberation: A Philosophical Study." Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2004, p. 22.
  127. ^ John J. Holder, Early Buddhist Discourses. Hackett Publishing Company, 2006, p. xx.
  128. ^ "Schopenhauer is often said to be the first modern Western philosopher to attempt integration of his work with Eastern ways of thinking. That he was the first is true, but the claim that he was influenced by Indian thought needs qualification. There is a remarkable correspondence in broad terms between some central Schopenhauerian doctrines and Buddhism: notably in the views that empirical existence is suffering, that suffering originates in desires, and that salvation can be attained by the extinction of desires. These three 'truths of the Buddha' are mirrored closely in the essential structure of the doctrine of the will." (On this, see Dorothea W. Dauer, Schopenhauer as Transmitter of Buddhist Ideas. Note also the discussion by Bryan Magee, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, pp. 14–15, 316–321). Janaway, Christopher, Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy, p. 28 f.
  129. ^ The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2, Ch. 17
  130. ^ Artistic detachment in Japan and the West: psychic distance in comparative aesthetics by S. Odin – 2001 – University of Hawaii Press.
  131. ^ Parerga & Paralipomena, vol. I, p. 106., trans. E.F.J. Payne.
  132. ^ World as Will and Representation, vol. I, p. 273, trans. E.F.J. Payne.
  133. ^ Christopher McCoy, 3
  134. ^ App, Urs Arthur Schopenhauer and China. Sino-Platonic Papers Nr. 200 (April 2010) (PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.; Schopenhauer's early notes on Buddhism reproduced in Appendix). This study provides an overview of the actual discovery of Buddhism by Schopenhauer.
  135. ^ Hutton, Kenneth Compassion in Schopenhauer and Śāntideva. Journal of Buddhist Ethics Vol. 21 (2014)
  136. ^ a b Josephson-Storm, Jason (2017). The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 187–188. ISBN 978-0-226-40336-6.
  137. ^ Quote from Josephson-Storm (2017), p. 188.
  138. ^ Josephson-Storm (2017), pp. 188–189.
  139. ^ Anderson, Mark (2009). "Experimental Subversions of Modernity". Pure: Modernity, Philosophy, and the One. Sophia Perennis. ISBN 978-1-59731-094-9.
  140. ^ Carnegy, Patrick. Wagner and the Art of the Theatre. p. 51.
  141. ^ The World as Will and Representation Preface to the first edition, p. xiii
  142. ^ a b Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. Note 5.
  143. ^ a b "Handschriftlicher, Nachlass, Vorlesungen und Abhandlungen". Gutenberg Spiegel.
  144. ^ Abschnitt: Handschriftlicher Nachlaß. § 588. Es kann daher eine vollkommen wahre Philosophie geben, die ganz von der Verneinung des Lebens abstrahirt, diese ganz ignorirt.
  145. ^ "Vie de Spinoza - Wikisource". fr.wikisource.org.
  146. ^ The World as Will and Representation. § 68. We might to a certain extent regard the well-known French biography of Spinoza as a case in point, if we used as a key to it that noble introduction to his very insufficient essay, "De Emendatione Intellects", a passage which I can also recommend as the most effectual means I know of stilling the storm of the passions.
  147. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer. World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1, Preface of the Second Edition.
  148. ^ Jerauld McGill, Vivian (1931). Schopenhauer. Pessimist and Pagan. p. 320.
  149. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical Essays, Volume 2, trans. Payne, p. 655–656.
  150. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. Vol. 1 Criticism of the Kantian philosophy. Translated by J. Kemp. With the proof of the thing in itself it has happened to Kant precisely as with that of the a priori nature of the law of causality. Both doctrines are true, but their proof is false. They thus belong to the class of true conclusions from false premises.
  151. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 21.
  152. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 23.
  153. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Freedom of the Will. p. 82.
  154. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", Sec. 13, trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 96.
  155. ^ Popper, Karl (1946). "The Open Society and Her Enemies". Nature. 157 (3987): 52. Bibcode:1946Natur.157..387R. doi:10.1038/157387a0. S2CID 4074331.
  156. ^ Bunge, Mario (2020). "Mario Bunge nos dijo: "Se puede ignorar la filosofía, pero no evitarla"". Filosofía&Co.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: uses authors parameter (link)
  157. ^ The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, Preface to the First Edition, trans. Christopher Janaway (Cambridge, 2009), p. 15.
  158. ^ "The Rise and Fall of Nietzschean Anti-Semitism" Chapter ! Princeton University Press. Accessed 10 April 2023.
  159. ^ Conway D. "Nietzsche's Revaluation of Schopenhauer as Educator" Boston University Press. Accessed 10 April 2023.
  160. ^ a b Beiser, Frederick C. (2008). Weltschmerz, Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860–1900. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 14–16. ISBN 978-0-19-876871-5. Arthur Schopenhauer was the most famous and influential philosopher in Germany from 1860 until the First World War. ... Schopenhauer had a profound influence on two intellectual movements of the late 19th century that were utterly opposed to him: neo-Kantianism and positivism. He forced these movements to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly. ... Schopenhauer set the agenda for his age.
  161. ^ Beside Schopenhauer's Corpse
  162. ^ Howard, Don (1997). A Peek behind the Veil of Maya: Einstein, Schopenhauer, and the Historical Background of the Conception of Space as a Ground for the Individuation of Physical Systems. University of Pittsburgh Press. Pauli greatly admired Schopenhauer. ... Pauli wrote sympathetically about extrasensory perception, noting approvingly that "even such a thoroughly critical philosopher as Schopenhauer not only regarded parapsychological effects going far beyond what is secured by scientific evidence as possible, but even considered them as a support for his philosophy".
  163. ^ Isaacson, Walter (2007). Einstein: His Life and Universe. New York: Simon & Schuster. p. 367. ISBN 978-0-7432-6474-7.
  164. ^ Howard (1997). p. 87
  165. ^ Howard (1997). p. 92
  166. ^ Halpern, Paul (2015). Einstein's Dice and Schrödinger's Cat: How Two Great Minds Battled Quantum Randomness to Create a Unified Theory of Physics. p. 189. ISBN 978-0-465-04065-0.
  167. ^ Howard (1997). p. 132
  168. ^ Raymond B. Marcin. "Schopenhauers Metaphysics and Contemporary Quantum Theory". David Lindorff referred to Schopenhauer as Pauli's "favorite philosopher", and Pauli himself often expressed his agreement with the main tenet of Schopenhauer's philosophy. … Suzanne Gieser cited a 1952 letter from Pauli to Carl Jung, in which Pauli indicated that, while he accepted Schopenhauer's main tenet that the thing-in-itself of all reality is will.
  169. ^ See e.g. Magee (2000) 276–278.
  170. ^ Nicholas Mathew, Benjamin Walton. The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism. p. 296.
  171. ^ Tolstoy's letter to Afanasy Fet on 30 August 1869. "Do you know what this summer has meant for me? Constant raptures over Schopenhauer and a whole series of spiritual delights as I've never experienced before. I have brought all of his works and read him over and over, Kant too by the way. Assuredly no student has ever learned and discovered so much in one semester as I have during this summer. I do not know if I shall ever change my opinion, but at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. You say he is so-so, he has written a few things on philosophy? What is so-so? It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection. I have started to translate him. Won't you help me? Indeed, I cannot understand how his name can be unknown. The only explanation for this can only be the one he so often repeats, that is, that there is scarcely anyone but idiots in the world."
  172. ^ Thompson, Caleb (2009). "Quietism from the Side of Happiness: Tolstoy, Schopenhauer, War and Peace". Common Knowledge. 15 (3): 395–411. doi:10.1215/0961754X-2009-020.
  173. ^ Magee 1997, p. 413.
  174. ^ Caleb Flamm, Matthew (2002). "Santayana and Schopenhauer". Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 38 (3): 413–431. JSTOR 40320900. A thinker of whom it is well known that Santayana had an early, deep admiration, namely, Schopenhauer
  175. ^ Yothers, Brian (2015). Sacred Uncertainty: Religious Difference and The Shape of Melville's Career. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-8101-3071-5.
  176. ^ Morrison, Simon (2008). Sergey Prokofiev and His World. Princeton University Press. pp. 19, 20. ISBN 978-0-691-13895-4.
  177. ^ Schopenhauer as Educator
  178. ^ Glock, Hans-Johann (2017). A Companion to Wittgenstein. Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell. p. 60.
  179. ^ Glock, Hans-Johann (2000). The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. p. 424.
  180. ^ Malcolm, Norman. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Oxford University Press, 1958, p. 6
  181. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1946). History of Western Philosophy. Start of 2nd paragraph: George Allen and Unwin LTD. p. 786.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  182. ^ "Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of 'True Detective'". The Wall Street Journal. 12 February 2014.
  183. ^ M.Morioka What Is Antinatalism? and Other Essays, pp.8-12.
  184. ^ Eric Francis Jules Payne (17 February 1895 – 12 January 1983)

Sources

  • Albright, Daniel (2004) Modernism and Music: An Anthology of Sources. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-01267-4
  • Beiser, Frederick C., Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016).
  • Cartwright, David E. (2010). Schopenhauer: A Biography. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82598-6.
  • Clarke, John James (1997). Oriental Enlightenment: The Encounter Between Asian and Western Thought. Abingdon, Oxfordshire: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-13376-0.
  • Hannan, Barbara, The Riddle of the World: A Reconsideration of Schopenhauer's Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
  • Magee, Bryan, Confessions of a Philosopher, Random House, 1998, ISBN 978-0-375-50028-2. Chapters 20, 21.
  • Safranski, Rüdiger (1990) Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy. Harvard University Press, ISBN 978-0-674-79275-3; orig. German Schopenhauer und Die wilden Jahre der Philosophie, Carl Hanser Verlag (1987)
  • Thomas Mann editor, The Living Thoughts of Schopenhauer, Longmans Green & Co., 1939

Further reading

Biographies

  • Frederick Copleston, Arthur Schopenhauer, philosopher of pessimism (Burns, Oates & Washbourne, 1946)
  • O. F. Damm, Arthur Schopenhauer – eine Biographie (Reclam, 1912)
  • Kuno Fischer, Arthur Schopenhauer (Heidelberg: Winter, 1893); revised as Schopenhauers Leben, Werke und Lehre (Heidelberg: Winter, 1898).
  • Eduard Grisebach, Schopenhauer – Geschichte seines Lebens (Berlin: Hofmann, 1876).
  • D. W. Hamlyn, Schopenhauer, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (1980, 1985)
  • Heinrich Hasse, Schopenhauer. (Reinhardt, 1926)
  • Arthur Hübscher, Arthur Schopenhauer – Ein Lebensbild (Leipzig: Brockhaus, 1938).
  • Thomas Mann, Schopenhauer (Bermann-Fischer, 1938)
  • Matthews, Jack, Schopenhauer's Will: Das Testament, Nine Point Publishing, 2015. ISBN 978-0-9858278-8-5. A recent creative biography by philosophical novelist Jack Matthews.
  • Rüdiger Safranski, Schopenhauer und die wilden Jahre der Philosophie – Eine Biographie, hard cover Carl Hanser Verlag, München 1987, ISBN 978-3-446-14490-3, pocket edition Fischer: ISBN 978-3-596-14299-6.
  • Rüdiger Safranski, Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy, trans. Ewald Osers (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989)
  • Walther Schneider, Schopenhauer – Eine Biographie (Vienna: Bermann-Fischer, 1937).
  • William Wallace, Life of Arthur Schopenhauer (London: Scott, 1890; repr., St. Clair Shores, Mich.: Scholarly Press, 1970)
  • Helen Zimmern, Arthur Schopenhauer: His Life and His Philosophy (London: Longmans, Green & Co, 1876)

Other books

  • App, Urs. Arthur Schopenhauer and China. Sino-Platonic Papers Nr. 200 (April 2010) (PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.). Contains extensive appendixes with transcriptions and English translations of Schopenhauer's early notes about Buddhism and Indian philosophy.
  • --------, Schopenhauers Kompass. Die Geburt einer Philosophie. UniversityMedia, Rorschach/ Kyoto 2011, ISBN 978-3-906000-02-2
  • Atwell, John. Schopenhauer on the Character of the World, The Metaphysics of Will.
  • --------, Schopenhauer, The Human Character.
  • Edwards, Anthony. An Evolutionary Epistemological Critique of Schopenhauer's Metaphysics. 123 Books, 2011.
  • Copleston, Frederick, Schopenhauer: Philosopher of Pessimism, 1946 (reprinted London: Search Press, 1975).
  • Gardiner, Patrick, 1963. Schopenhauer. Penguin Books.
  • --------, Schopenhauer: A Very Short introduction.
  • Janaway, Christopher, 2003. Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-825003-6
  • Magee, Bryan, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Oxford University Press (1988, reprint 1997). ISBN 978-0-19-823722-8
  • Neymeyr, Barbara, 1996 (reprint 2011): Ästhetische Autonomie als Abnormität. Kritische Analysen zu Schopenhauers Ästhetik im Horizont seiner Willensmetaphysik. (= Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie. Band 42). Walter de Gruyter, Berlin / New York 1996, ISBN 3-11-015229-0. (reprint 2011, De Gruyter Berlin / Boston).
  • Mannion, Gerard, "Schopenhauer, Religion and Morality – The Humble Path to Ethics", Ashgate Press, New Critical Thinking in Philosophy Series, 2003, 314pp.
  • Trottier, Danick. L’influence de la philosophie schopenhauerienne dans la vie et l’oeuvre de Richard Wagner; et, Qu’est-ce qui séduit, obsède, magnétise le philosophe dans l’art des sons? deux études en esthétique musicale, Université du Québec à Montréal, Département de musique, 2000.
  • Zimmern, Helen, Arthur Schopenhauer, his Life and Philosophy, London, Longman, and Co., 1876.
  • Kastrup, Bernardo. Decoding Schopenhauer‘s Metaphysics - The key to understanding how it solves the hard problem of consciousness and the paradoxes of quantum mechanics. Winchester/Washington, iff Books, 2020.
  • de Botton, Alain: The Consolations of Philosophy. Hamish Hamilton, London 2000, ISBN 0-14-027661-0 (Chapter: Consolation for a Broken Heart).

Fiction

  • Poschenrieder, Christoph: Die Welt ist im Kopf. Diogenes, Zürich 2010, ISBN 978-3-257-06741-5 (The novel accompanies Schopenhauer on a trip to Italy).
  • Yalom, Irvin D.: The Schopenhauer Cure. HarperCollins, New York City 2005, ISBN 978-0-06-093810-9 (The novel switches between the current events happening around a therapy group and the psychobiography of Arthur Schopenhauer).
  • Kortmann, Christian: Happy Hour Schopenhauer. Roman einer Bibliotherapie. Turia + Kant, Wien + Berlin 2022, ISBN 978-3-98514-030-5 (In the novel, Schopenhauer lives in the 21st century and comments on current events in original quotations).
  • J. T. Frederick: In Arthur's Nature. Theorism Press 2020, ISBN 978-0-6451802-0-6 (Schopenhauer faces punishment for alleged assault and battery.)

Articles

  • Abelson, Peter (1993). . Philosophy East and West. 43 (2): 255–78. doi:10.2307/1399616. JSTOR 1399616. Archived from the original on 28 June 2011. Retrieved 25 October 2007.
  • Jiménez, Camilo, 2006, "," Avinus Magazin (in German).
  • Luchte, James, 2009, "The Body of Sublime Knowledge: The Aesthetic Phenomenology of Arthur Schopenhauer," Heythrop Journal, Volume 50, Number 2, pp. 228–242.
  • Mazard, Eisel, 2005, "Schopenhauer and the Empirical Critique of Idealism in the History of Ideas." On Schopenhauer's (debated) place in the history of European philosophy and his relation to his predecessors.
  • Sangharakshita, 2004, ""
  • Young, Christopher; Brook, Andrew (1994). "Schopenhauer and Freud". International Journal of Psychoanalysis. 75: 101–18. PMID 8005756.
  • Oxenford's "Iconoclasm in German Philosophy," (See p. 388)
  • Thacker, Eugene, 2020. "A Philosophy in Ruins, An Unquiet Void." Introduction to Arthur Schopenhauer, On the Suffering of the World. Repeater Books. ISBN 978-1-913462-03-1

External links

arthur, schopenhauer, schopenhauer, redirects, here, other, uses, schopenhauer, disambiguation, aʊər, shoh, pən, german, ˈaɐtʊɐ, ˈʃoːpm, haʊɐ, listen, february, 1788, september, 1860, german, philosopher, best, known, 1818, work, world, will, representation, e. Schopenhauer redirects here For other uses see Schopenhauer disambiguation Arthur Schopenhauer ˈ ʃ oʊ p en h aʊer SHOH pen how er 18 German ˈaɐtʊɐ ˈʃoːpm haʊɐ listen 22 February 1788 21 September 1860 was a German philosopher He is best known for his 1818 work The World as Will and Representation expanded in 1844 which characterizes the phenomenal world as the product of a blind noumenal will 19 Building on the transcendental idealism of Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 Schopenhauer developed an atheistic metaphysical and ethical system that rejected the contemporaneous ideas of German idealism 6 7 He was among the first thinkers in Western philosophy to share and affirm significant tenets of Indian philosophy such as asceticism denial of the self and the notion of the world as appearance 20 His work has been described as an exemplary manifestation of philosophical pessimism 21 Arthur SchopenhauerSchopenhauer in 1859Born 1788 02 22 22 February 1788Danzig Gdansk Crown of the Kingdom of Poland Polish Lithuanian CommonwealthDied21 September 1860 1860 09 21 aged 72 Frankfurt German ConfederationNationalityGermanEducationIllustrious Gymnasium University of Gottingen University of Jena PhD 1813 RelativesJohanna Schopenhauer mother Adele Schopenhauer sister Era19th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolContinental philosophy Post Kantian philosophy Transcendental idealism disputed 1 2 Metaphysical voluntarism 3 Philosophical pessimismInstitutionsUniversity of BerlinMain interestsMetaphysics aesthetics ethics morality psychologyNotable ideasAnthropic principle 4 5 Eternal justiceFourfold root of the principle of sufficient reasonHedgehog s dilemmaPhilosophical pessimismPrincipium individuationisWill as thing in itselfCriticism of religionCriticism of German idealism 6 7 Schopenhauerian aestheticsWooden ironInfluences TheravadaHinduism Upanishads AristotleDescartesBerkeleyHumeGibbonVoltaireGracianRousseauKantSpinozaLockeKrauseGoetheGerman mysticism 8 PlatoSchulzeInfluenced AnjosAssisBahnsenBeckettBergsonBorgesBrahmsBrouwerCampbellDarwinEinstein 9 FetCioranDilthey 10 FreudGray 11 HardyHartmannHesseHorkheimerHuysmansJungKraus 12 Ludovici 13 LigottiMahlerMainlanderMajorana 14 MannMarxMaupassantMichelstaedterNietzscheProustRankReveRilkeRyle 15 SantayanaSchlick 16 ShawSchoenbergSchrodingerSolovyovSpenglerTolstoy 17 VaihingerVolkeltWagnerWeiningerWittgensteinZapffeZolaSignatureThough his work failed to garner substantial attention during his lifetime Schopenhauer had a posthumous impact across various disciplines including philosophy literature and science His writing on aesthetics morality and psychology have influenced many thinkers and artists Those who have cited his influence include philosophers Emil Cioran Friedrich Nietzsche 22 and Ludwig Wittgenstein 23 scientists Erwin Schrodinger and Albert Einstein 24 psychoanalysts Sigmund Freud 25 and Carl Jung writers Leo Tolstoy 26 Herman Melville 27 Thomas Mann Hermann Hesse 28 Machado de Assis 29 Jorge Luis Borges Marcel Proust 30 and Samuel Beckett 31 and composers Richard Wagner 30 Johannes Brahms 30 Arnold Schoenberg 30 32 and Gustav Mahler 30 Contents 1 Life 1 1 Early life 1 2 Education 1 3 Early work 1 4 Later life 2 Philosophy 2 1 The world as representation 2 2 Theory of perception 2 3 The world as will 2 4 Art and aesthetics 2 5 Mathematics 2 6 Ethics 2 6 1 Eternal justice 2 6 2 Quietism 2 7 Psychology 2 8 Political and social thought 2 8 1 Politics 2 8 2 Punishment 2 8 3 Races and religions 2 8 4 Women 2 8 5 Pederasty 2 8 6 Heredity and eugenics 2 8 7 Animal welfare 2 9 Intellectual interests and affinities 2 9 1 Indology 2 9 2 Buddhism 2 9 3 Magic and occultism 3 Interests 4 Thoughts on other philosophers 4 1 Giordano Bruno and Spinoza 4 2 Immanuel Kant 4 3 Post Kantian school 4 4 Schopenhauer s split with Friedrich Nietzsche 5 Influence and legacy 6 Selected bibliography 6 1 Online 7 See also 8 References 8 1 Sources 9 Further reading 9 1 Biographies 9 2 Other books 9 3 Fiction 9 4 Articles 10 External linksLife EditEarly life Edit Schopenhauer s birthplace house ul Sw Ducha formerly Heiligegeistgasse Arthur Schopenhauer was born on 22 February 1788 in Danzig then part of the Polish Lithuanian Commonwealth present day Gdansk Poland on Heiligegeistgasse present day Sw Ducha 47 the son of Johanna Schopenhauer nee Trosiener 1766 1838 and Heinrich Floris Schopenhauer 1747 1805 33 both descendants of wealthy German patrician families While they came from a Protestant background neither of them were very religious 34 79 35 both supported the French Revolution 34 13 were republicans cosmopolitans and Anglophiles 34 9 When Danzig became part of Prussia in 1793 Heinrich moved to Hamburg a free city with a republican constitution His firm continued trading in Danzig where most of their extended families remained Adele Arthur s only sibling was born on 12 July 1797 In 1797 Arthur was sent to Le Havre to live with the family of his father s business associate Gregoire de Blesimaire He seemed to enjoy his two year stay there learning to speak French and fostering a life long friendship with Jean Anthime Gregoire de Blesimaire 34 18 As early as 1799 Arthur started playing the flute 34 30 In 1803 he accompanied his parents on a European tour of Holland Britain France Switzerland Austria and Prussia Viewed as primarily a pleasure tour Heinrich used the opportunity to visit some of his business associates abroad Heinrich offered Arthur a choice he could stay at home and start preparations for university or he could travel with them and continue his merchant education Arthur chose to travel with them He deeply regretted his choice later because the merchant training was very tedious He spent twelve weeks of the tour attending school in Wimbledon where he was disillusioned by strict and intellectually shallow Anglican religiosity He continued to sharply criticize Anglican religiosity later in life despite his general Anglophilia 34 56 He was also under pressure from his father who became very critical of his educational results In 1805 Heinrich drowned in a canal near their home in Hamburg Although it was possible that his death was accidental his wife and son believed that it was suicide He was prone to anxiety and depression each becoming more pronounced later in his life 36 Heinrich had become so fussy even his wife started to doubt his mental health 34 43 There was in the father s life some dark and vague source of fear which later made him hurl himself to his death from the attic of his house in Hamburg 34 88 Arthur showed similar moodiness during his youth and often acknowledged that he inherited it from his father There were other instances of serious mental health history on his father s side of the family 34 4 Despite his hardship Schopenhauer liked his father and later referred to him in a positive light 34 90 Heinrich Schopenhauer left the family with a significant inheritance that was split in three among Johanna and the children Arthur Schopenhauer was entitled to control of his part when he reached the age of majority He invested it conservatively in government bonds and earned annual interest that was more than double the salary of a university professor 34 136 After quitting his merchant apprenticeship with some encouragement from his mother he dedicated himself to studies at the Ernestine Gymnasium Gotha in Saxe Gotha Altenburg While there he also enjoyed social life among the local nobility spending large amounts of money which deeply concerned his frugal mother 34 128 He left the Gymnasium after writing a satirical poem about one of the schoolmasters Although Arthur claimed that he left voluntarily his mother s letter indicates that he may have been expelled 34 129 Schopenhauer in his youth Arthur spent two years as a merchant in honor of his dead father During this time he had doubts about being able to start a new life as a scholar 34 120 Most of his prior education was as a practical merchant and he had trouble learning Latin a prerequisite for an academic career 34 117 His mother moved away with her daughter Adele to Weimar then the centre of German literature to enjoy social life among writers and artists Arthur and his mother did not part on good terms In one letter she wrote You are unbearable and burdensome and very hard to live with all your good qualities are overshadowed by your conceit and made useless to the world simply because you cannot restrain your propensity to pick holes in other people 37 His mother Johanna was generally described as vivacious and sociable 34 9 She died 24 years later Some of Arthur s negative opinions about women may be rooted in his troubled relationship with his mother 38 Arthur moved to Hamburg to live with his friend Jean Anthime who was also studying to become a merchant Education Edit He moved to Weimar but did not live with his mother who even tried to discourage him from coming by explaining that they would not get along very well 34 131 Their relationship deteriorated even further due to their temperamental differences He accused his mother of being financially irresponsible flirtatious and seeking to remarry which he considered an insult to his father s memory 34 116 131 His mother while professing her love to him criticized him sharply for being moody tactless and argumentative and urged him to improve his behavior so that he would not alienate people 34 129 Arthur concentrated on his studies which were now going very well and he also enjoyed the usual social life such as balls parties and theater By that time Johanna s famous salon was well established among local intellectuals and dignitaries the most celebrated of them being Goethe Arthur attended her parties usually when he knew that Goethe would be there although the famous writer and statesman seemed not even to notice the young and unknown student It is possible that Goethe kept a distance because Johanna warned him about her son s depressive and combative nature or because Goethe was then on bad terms with Arthur s language instructor and roommate Franz Passow 34 134 Schopenhauer was also captivated by the beautiful Karoline Jagemann mistress of Karl August Grand Duke of Saxe Weimar Eisenach and he wrote to her his only known love poem 34 135 Despite his later celebration of asceticism and negative views of sexuality Schopenhauer occasionally had sexual affairs usually with women of lower social status such as servants actresses and sometimes even paid prostitutes 34 21 In a letter to his friend Anthime he claims that such affairs continued even in his mature age and admits that he had two out of wedlock daughters born in 1819 and 1836 both of whom died in infancy 34 25 In their youthful correspondence Arthur and Anthime were somewhat boastful and competitive about their sexual exploits but Schopenhauer seemed aware that women usually did not find him very charming or physically attractive and his desires often remained unfulfilled 34 22 He left Weimar to become a student at the University of Gottingen in 1809 There are no written reasons about why Schopenhauer chose that university instead of the then more famous University of Jena but Gottingen was known as more modern and scientifically oriented with less attention given to theology 34 140 Law or medicine were usual choices for young men of Schopenhauer s status who also needed career and income he chose medicine due to his scientific interests Among his notable professors were Bernhard Friedrich Thibaut Arnold Hermann Ludwig Heeren Johann Friedrich Blumenbach Friedrich Stromeyer Heinrich Adolf Schrader Johann Tobias Mayer and Konrad Johann Martin Langenbeck 34 141 144 He studied metaphysics psychology and logic under Gottlob Ernst Schulze the author of Aenesidemus who made a strong impression and advised him to concentrate on Plato and Immanuel Kant 34 144 He decided to switch from medicine to philosophy around 1810 11 and he left Gottingen which did not have a strong philosophy program besides Schulze the only other philosophy professor was Friedrich Bouterwek whom Schopenhauer disliked 34 150 He did not regret his medicinal and scientific studies he claimed that they were necessary for a philosopher and even in Berlin he attended more lectures in sciences than in philosophy 34 170 During his days at Gottingen he spent considerable time studying but also continued his flute playing and social life His friends included Friedrich Gotthilf Osann Karl Witte Christian Charles Josias von Bunsen and William Backhouse Astor Sr 34 151 He arrived at the newly founded University of Berlin for the winter semester of 1811 12 At the same time his mother had just begun her literary career she published her first book in 1810 a biography of her friend Karl Ludwig Fernow which was a critical success Arthur attended lectures by the prominent post Kantian philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte but quickly found many points of disagreement with his Wissenschaftslehre he also found Fichte s lectures tedious and hard to understand 34 159 He later mentioned Fichte only in critical negative terms 34 159 seeing his philosophy as a lower quality version of Kant s and considering it useful only because Fichte s poor arguments unintentionally highlighted some failings of Kantianism 34 165 169 He also attended the lectures of the famous Protestant theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher whom he also quickly came to dislike 34 174 His notes and comments on Schleiermacher s lectures show that Schopenhauer was becoming very critical of religion and moving towards atheism 34 175 He learned by self directed reading besides Plato Kant and Fichte he also read the works of Schelling Fries Jacobi Bacon Locke and much current scientific literature 34 170 He attended philological courses by August Bockh and Friedrich August Wolf and continued his naturalistic interests with courses by Martin Heinrich Klaproth Paul Erman Johann Elert Bode Ernst Gottfried Fischer Johann Horkel Friedrich Christian Rosenthal and Hinrich Lichtenstein Lichtenstein was also a friend whom he met at one of his mother s parties in Weimar 34 171 174 Early work Edit Schopenhauer left Berlin in a rush in 1813 fearing that the city could be attacked and that he could be pressed into military service as Prussia had just joined the war against France 34 179 He returned to Weimar but left after less than a month disgusted by the fact that his mother was now living with her supposed lover Georg Friedrich Konrad Ludwig Muller von Gerstenbergk 1778 1838 a civil servant twelve years younger than her he considered the relationship an act of infidelity to his father s memory 34 188 He settled for a while in Rudolstadt hoping that no army would pass through the small town He spent his time in solitude hiking in the mountains and the Thuringian forest and writing his dissertation On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason He completed his dissertation at about the same time as the French army was defeated at the Battle of Leipzig He became irritated by the arrival of soldiers in the town and accepted his mother s invitation to visit her in Weimar She tried to convince him that her relationship with Gerstenbergk was platonic and that she had no intention of remarrying 34 230 But Schopenhauer remained suspicious and often came in conflict with Gerstenbergk because he considered him untalented pretentious and nationalistic 34 231 His mother had just published her second book Reminiscences of a Journey in the Years 1803 1804 and 1805 a description of their family tour of Europe which quickly became a hit She found his dissertation incomprehensible and said it was unlikely that anyone would ever buy a copy In a fit of temper Arthur told her that people would read his work long after the rubbish she wrote was totally forgotten 39 40 In fact although they considered her novels of dubious quality the Brockhaus publishing firm held her in high esteem because they consistently sold well Hans Brockhaus 1888 1965 later claimed that his predecessors saw nothing in this manuscript but wanted to please one of our best selling authors by publishing her son s work We published more and more of her son Arthur s work and today nobody remembers Johanna but her son s works are in steady demand and contribute to Brockhaus reputation 41 He kept large portraits of the pair in his office in Leipzig for the edification of his new editors 41 Also contrary to his mother s prediction Schopenhauer s dissertation made an impression on Goethe to whom he sent it as a gift 34 241 Although it is doubtful that Goethe agreed with Schopenhauer s philosophical positions he was impressed by his intellect and extensive scientific education 34 243 Their subsequent meetings and correspondence were a great honor to a young philosopher who was finally acknowledged by his intellectual hero They mostly discussed Goethe s newly published and somewhat lukewarmly received work on color theory Schopenhauer soon started writing his own treatise on the subject On Vision and Colors which in many points differed from his teacher s Although they remained polite towards each other their growing theoretical disagreements and especially Schopenhauer s extreme self confidence and tactless criticisms soon made Goethe become distant again and after 1816 their correspondence became less frequent 34 247 265 Schopenhauer later admitted that he was greatly hurt by this rejection but he continued to praise Goethe and considered his color theory a great introduction to his own 34 252 256 265 Another important experience during his stay in Weimar was his acquaintance with Friedrich Majer 42 a historian of religion orientalist and disciple of Herder who introduced him to Eastern philosophy 43 34 266 see also Indology Schopenhauer was immediately impressed by the Upanishads he called them the production of the highest human wisdom and believed that they contained superhuman concepts and the Buddha 43 and put them on a par with Plato and Kant 34 268 272 He continued his studies by reading the Bhagavad Gita an amateurish German journal Asiatisches Magazin and Asiatick Researches by the Asiatic Society 34 267 272 Schopenhauer held a profound respect for Indian philosophy 44 although he loved Hindu texts he never revered a Buddhist text but regarded Buddhism as the most distinguished religion 45 34 272 His studies on Hindu and Buddhist texts were constrained by the lack of adequate literature 46 and the latter were mostly restricted to Theravada Buddhism He also claimed that he formulated most of his ideas independently 43 and only later realized the similarities with Buddhism 34 274 276 Schopenhauer read the Latin translation and praised the Upanishads in his main work The World as Will and Representation 1819 as well as in his Parerga and Paralipomena 1851 and commented In the whole world there is no study so beneficial and so elevating as that of the Upanishads It has been the solace of my life it will be the solace of my death 47 Schopenhauer in 1815 Portrait by Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl As the relationship with his mother fell to a new low in May 1814 he left Weimar and moved to Dresden 34 265 He continued his philosophical studies enjoyed the cultural life socialized with intellectuals and engaged in sexual affairs 34 284 His friends in Dresden were Johann Gottlob von Quandt Friedrich Laun Karl Christian Friedrich Krause and Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl a young painter who made a romanticized portrait of him in which he improved some of Schopenhauer s unattractive physical features 34 278 283 His criticisms of local artists occasionally caused public quarrels when he ran into them in public 34 282 Schopenhauer s main occupation during his stay in Dresden was his seminal philosophical work The World as Will and Representation which he started writing in 1814 and finished in 1818 48 He was recommended to the publisher Friedrich Arnold Brockhaus by Baron Ferdinand von Biedenfeld an acquaintance of his mother 34 285 Although Brockhaus accepted his manuscript Schopenhauer made a poor impression because of his quarrelsome and fussy attitude as well as very poor sales of the book after it was published in December 1818 34 285 289 In September 1818 while waiting for his book to be published and conveniently escaping an affair with a maid that caused an unwanted pregnancy 34 342 Schopenhauer left Dresden for a year long vacation in Italy 34 346 He visited Venice Bologna Florence Naples and Milan travelling alone or accompanied by mostly English tourists he met 34 350 He spent the winter months in Rome where he accidentally met his acquaintance Karl Witte and engaged in numerous quarrels with German tourists in the Caffe Greco among them Johann Friedrich Bohmer who also mentioned his insulting remarks and unpleasant character 34 348 349 He enjoyed art architecture and ancient ruins attended plays and operas and continued his philosophical contemplation and love affairs 34 346 350 One of his affairs supposedly became serious and for a while he contemplated marriage to a rich Italian noblewoman but despite his mentioning this several times no details are known and it may have been Schopenhauer exaggerating 49 34 345 He corresponded regularly with his sister Adele and became close to her as her relationship with Johanna and Gerstenbergk also deteriorated 34 344 She informed him about their financial troubles as the banking house of A L Muhl in Danzig in which her mother invested their whole savings and Arthur a third of his was near bankruptcy 34 351 Arthur offered to share his assets but his mother refused and became further enraged by his insulting comments 34 352 The women managed to receive only thirty percent of their savings while Arthur using his business knowledge took a suspicious and aggressive stance towards the banker and eventually received his part in full 34 354 356 The affair additionally worsened the relationships among all three members of the Schopenhauer family 34 352 354 He shortened his stay in Italy because of the trouble with Muhl and returned to Dresden 34 356 Disturbed by the financial risk and the lack of responses to his book he decided to take an academic position since it provided him with both income and an opportunity to promote his views 34 358 He contacted his friends at universities in Heidelberg Gottingen and Berlin and found Berlin most attractive 34 358 362 He scheduled his lectures to coincide with those of the famous philosopher G W F Hegel whom Schopenhauer described as a clumsy charlatan 50 He was especially appalled by Hegel s supposedly poor knowledge of natural sciences and tried to engage him in a quarrel about it already at his test lecture in March 1820 34 363 Hegel was also facing political suspicions at the time when many progressive professors were fired while Schopenhauer carefully mentioned in his application that he had no interest in politics 34 362 Despite their differences and the arrogant request to schedule lectures at the same time as his own Hegel still voted to accept Schopenhauer to the university 34 365 Only five students turned up to Schopenhauer s lectures and he dropped out of academia A late essay On University Philosophy expressed his resentment towards the work conducted in academies Later life Edit Sculpture of Arthur Schopenhauer by Giennadij Jerszow After his tenure in academia he continued to travel extensively visiting Leipzig Nuremberg Stuttgart Schaffhausen Vevey Milan and spending eight months in Florence 34 411 Before he left for his three year travel Schopenhauer had an incident with his Berlin neighbor 47 year old seamstress Caroline Louise Marquet The details of the August 1821 incident are unknown He claimed that he had just pushed her from his entrance after she had rudely refused to leave and that she had purposely fallen to the ground so that she could sue him She claimed that he had attacked her so violently that she had become paralyzed on her right side and unable to work She immediately sued him and the process lasted until May 1827 when a court found Schopenhauer guilty and forced him to pay her an annual pension until her death in 1842 34 408 411 Schopenhauer enjoyed Italy where he studied art and socialized with Italian and English nobles 34 411 414 It was his last visit to the country He left for Munich and stayed there for a year mostly recuperating from various health issues some of them possibly caused by venereal diseases the treatment his doctor used suggests syphilis 34 415 He contacted publishers offering to translate Hume into German and Kant into English but his proposals were declined 34 417 422 Returning to Berlin he began to study Spanish so he could read some of his favorite authors in their original language He liked Pedro Calderon de la Barca Lope de Vega Miguel de Cervantes and especially Baltasar Gracian 34 420 He also made failed attempts to publish his translations of their works A few attempts to revive his lectures again scheduled at the same time as Hegel s also failed as did his inquiries about relocating to other universities 34 429 432 During his Berlin years Schopenhauer occasionally mentioned his desire to marry and have a family 34 404 432 For a while he was unsuccessfully courting 17 year old Flora Weiss who was 22 years younger than himself 34 433 His unpublished writings from that time show that he was already very critical of monogamy but still not advocating polygyny instead musing about a polyamorous relationship that he called tetragamy 34 404 408 He had an on and off relationship with a young dancer Caroline Richter she also used the surname Medon after one of her ex lovers 34 403 They met when he was 33 and she was 19 and working at the Berlin Opera She had already had numerous lovers and a son out of wedlock and later gave birth to another son this time to an unnamed foreign diplomat she soon had another pregnancy but the child was stillborn 34 403 404 As Schopenhauer was preparing to escape from Berlin in 1831 due to a cholera epidemic he offered to take her with him on the condition that she left her young son behind 34 404 She refused and he went alone in his will he left her a significant sum of money but insisted that it should not be spent in any way on her second son 34 404 Schopenhauer claimed that in his last year in Berlin he had a prophetic dream that urged him to escape from the city 34 436 As he arrived in his new home in Frankfurt he supposedly had another supernatural experience an apparition of his dead father and his mother who was still alive 34 436 This experience led him to spend some time investigating paranormal phenomena and magic He was quite critical of the available studies and claimed that they were mostly ignorant or fraudulent but he did believe that there are authentic cases of such phenomena and tried to explain them through his metaphysics as manifestations of the will 34 437 452 Upon his arrival in Frankfurt he experienced a period of depression and declining health 34 454 He renewed his correspondence with his mother and she seemed concerned that he might commit suicide like his father 34 454 457 By now Johanna and Adele were living very modestly Johanna s writing did not bring her much income and her popularity was waning 34 458 Their correspondence remained reserved and Arthur seemed undisturbed by her death in 1838 34 460 His relationship with his sister grew closer and he corresponded with her until she died in 1849 34 463 In July 1832 Schopenhauer left Frankfurt for Mannheim but returned in July 1833 to remain there for the rest of his life except for a few short journeys 34 464 He lived alone except for a succession of pet poodles named Atman and Butz In 1836 he published On the Will in Nature In 1836 he sent his essay On the Freedom of the Will to the contest of the Royal Norwegian Society of Sciences and won the prize for the following year He sent another essay On the Basis of Morality to the Royal Danish Society for Scientific Studies but did not win the prize despite being the only contestant The Society was appalled that several distinguished contemporary philosophers were mentioned in a very offensive manner and claimed that the essay missed the point of the set topic and that the arguments were inadequate 34 483 Schopenhauer who had been very confident that he would win was enraged by this rejection He published both essays as The Two Basic Problems of Ethics The first edition published in 1841 again failed to draw attention to his philosophy In the preface to the second edition in 1860 he was still pouring insults on the Royal Danish Society 34 484 Two years later after some negotiations he managed to convince his publisher Brockhaus to print the second updated edition of The World as Will and Representation That book was again mostly ignored and the few reviews were mixed or negative Schopenhauer began to attract some followers mostly outside academia among practical professionals several of them were lawyers who pursued private philosophical studies He jokingly referred to them as evangelists and apostles 34 504 One of the most active early followers was Julius Frauenstadt who wrote numerous articles promoting Schopenhauer s philosophy He was also instrumental in finding another publisher after Brockhaus declined to publish Parerga and Paralipomena believing that it would be another failure 34 506 Though Schopenhauer later stopped corresponding with him claiming that he did not adhere closely enough to his ideas Frauenstadt continued to promote Schopenhauer s work 34 507 508 They renewed their communication in 1859 and Schopenhauer named him heir for his literary estate 34 508 Frauenstadt also became the editor of the first collected works of Schopenhauer 34 506 In 1848 Schopenhauer witnessed violent upheaval in Frankfurt after General Hans Adolf Erdmann von Auerswald and Prince Felix Lichnowsky were murdered He became worried for his own safety and property 34 514 Even earlier in life he had had such worries and kept a sword and loaded pistols near his bed to defend himself from thieves 34 465 He gave a friendly welcome to Austrian soldiers who wanted to shoot revolutionaries from his window and as they were leaving he gave one of the officers his opera glasses to help him monitor rebels 34 514 The rebellion passed without any loss to Schopenhauer and he later praised Alfred I Prince of Windisch Gratz for restoring order 34 515 He even modified his will leaving a large part of his property to a Prussian fund that helped soldiers who became invalids while fighting rebellion in 1848 or the families of soldiers who died in battle 34 517 As Young Hegelians were advocating change and progress Schopenhauer claimed that misery is natural for humans and that even if some utopian society were established people would still fight each other out of boredom or would starve due to overpopulation 34 515 1855 painting of Schopenhauer by Jules Lunteschutz In 1851 Schopenhauer published Parerga and Paralipomena which contains essays that are supplementary to his main work It was his first successful widely read book partly due to the work of his disciples who wrote praising reviews 34 524 The essays that proved most popular were the ones that actually did not contain the basic philosophical ideas of his system 34 539 Many academic philosophers considered him a great stylist and cultural critic but did not take his philosophy seriously 34 539 His early critics liked to point out similarities of his ideas to those Fichte and Schelling 34 381 386 or to claim that there were numerous contradictions in his philosophy 34 381 386 537 Both criticisms enraged Schopenhauer He was becoming less interested in intellectual fights but encouraged his disciples to do so 34 525 His private notes and correspondence show that he acknowledged some of the criticisms regarding contradictions inconsistencies and vagueness in his philosophy but claimed that he was not concerned about harmony and agreement in his propositions 34 394 and that some of his ideas should not be taken literally but instead as metaphors 34 510 Academic philosophers were also starting to notice his work In 1856 the University of Leipzig sponsored an essay contest about Schopenhauer s philosophy which was won by Rudolf Seydel s very critical essay 34 536 Schopenhauer s friend Jules Lunteschutz made the first of his four portraits of him which Schopenhauer did not particularly like which was soon sold to a wealthy landowner Carl Ferdinand Wiesike who built a house to display it Schopenhauer seemed flattered and amused by this and would claim that it was his first chapel 34 540 As his fame increased copies of paintings and photographs of him were being sold and admirers were visiting the places where he had lived and written his works People visited Frankfurt s Englischer Hof to observe him dining Admirers gave him gifts and asked for autographs 34 541 He complained that he still felt isolated due to his not very social nature and the fact that many of his good friends had already died from old age 34 542 Grave at the Hauptfriedhof in Frankfurt He remained healthy in his own old age which he attributed to regular walks no matter the weather and always getting enough sleep 34 544 545 He had a great appetite and could read without glasses but his hearing had been declining since his youth and he developed problems with rheumatism 34 545 He remained active and lucid continued his reading writing and correspondence until his death 34 545 The numerous notes that he made during these years amongst others on aging were published posthumously under the title Senilia In the spring of 1860 his health began to decline and he experienced shortness of breath and heart palpitations in September he suffered inflammation of the lungs and although he was starting to recover he remained very weak 34 546 The last friend to visit him was Wilhelm Gwinner according to him Schopenhauer was concerned that he would not be able to finish his planned additions to Parerga and Paralipomena but was at peace with dying 34 546 547 He died of pulmonary respiratory failure 51 on 21 September 1860 while sitting at home on his couch He died at the age of 72 and had a funeral conducted by a Lutheran minister 52 53 Philosophy EditThe world as representation Edit Schopenhauer saw his philosophy as an extension of Kant s and used the results of Kantian epistemological investigation transcendental idealism as starting point for his own Kant had argued that the empirical world is merely a complex of appearances whose existence and connection occur only in our mental representations 54 Schopenhauer did not deny that the external world existed empirically but followed Kant in claiming that our knowledge and experience of the world is always indirect 55 Schopenhauer reiterates this in the first sentence of his main work The world is my representation Die Welt ist meine Vorstellung Everything that there is for cognition the entire world exists simply as an object in relation to a subject a representation to a subject Everything that belongs to the world is therefore subject dependent In Book One of The World as Will and Representation Schopenhauer considers the world from this angle that is insofar as it is representation Theory of perception Edit In November 1813 Goethe invited Schopenhauer to help him on his Theory of Colours Although Schopenhauer considered colour theory a minor matter 56 he accepted the invitation out of admiration for Goethe Nevertheless these investigations led him to his most important discovery in epistemology finding a demonstration for the a priori nature of causality Kant openly admitted that it was Hume s skeptical assault on causality that motivated the critical investigations in Critique of Pure Reason and gave an elaborate proof to show that causality is a priori After G E Schulze had made it plausible that Kant had not disproven Hume s skepticism it was up to those loyal to Kant s project to prove this important matter The difference between the approaches of Kant and Schopenhauer was this Kant simply declared that the empirical content of perception is given to us from outside an expression with which Schopenhauer often expressed his dissatisfaction 57 He on the other hand was occupied with the questions how do we get this empirical content of perception how is it possible to comprehend subjective sensations limited to my skin as the objective perception of things that lie outside of me 58 The sensations in the hand of a man born blind on feeling an object of cubic shape are quite uniform and the same on all sides and in every direction the edges it is true press upon a smaller portion of his hand still nothing at all like a cube is contained in these sensations His Understanding draws the immediate and intuitive conclusion from the resistance felt that this resistance must have a cause which then presents itself through that conclusion as a hard body and through the movements of his arms in feeling the object while the hand s sensation remains unaltered he constructs the cubic shape in Space If the representation of a cause and of Space together with their laws had not already existed within him the image of a cube could never have proceeded from those successive sensations in his hand 59 Causality is therefore not an empirical concept drawn from objective perceptions as Hume had maintained instead as Kant had said objective perception presupposes knowledge of causality 60 By this intellectual operation comprehending every effect in our sensory organs as having an external cause the external world arises With vision finding the cause is essentially simplified due to light acting in straight lines We are seldom conscious of the process that interprets the double sensation in both eyes as coming from one object that inverts the impressions on the retinas and that uses the change in the apparent position of an object relative to more distant objects provided by binocular vision to perceive depth and distance Schopenhauer stresses the importance of the intellectual nature of perception the senses furnish the raw material by which the intellect produces the world as representation He set out his theory of perception for the first time in On Vision and Colors 61 and in the subsequent editions of Fourfold Root an extensive exposition is given in 21 The world as will Edit Main article The World as Will and Representation In Book Two of The World as Will and Representation Schopenhauer considers what the world is beyond the aspect of it that appears to us that is the aspect of the world beyond representation the world considered in itself or noumena its inner essence The very being in itself of all things Schopenhauer argues is will Wille The empirical world that appears to us as representation has plurality and is ordered in a spatio temporal framework The world as thing in itself must exist outside the subjective forms of space and time Although the world manifests itself to our experience as a multiplicity of objects the objectivation of the will each element of this multiplicity has the same blind essence striving towards existence and life Human rationality is merely a secondary phenomenon that does not distinguish humanity from the rest of nature at the fundamental essential level The advanced cognitive abilities of human beings Schopenhauer argues serve the ends of willing an illogical directionless ceaseless striving that condemns the human individual to a life of suffering unredeemed by any final purpose Schopenhauer s philosophy of the will as the essential reality behind the world as representation is often called metaphysical voluntarism 3 For Schopenhauer understanding the world as will leads to ethical concerns see the ethics section below for further detail which he explores in the Fourth Book of The World as Will and Representation and again in his two prize essays on ethics On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality No individual human actions are free Schopenhauer argues because they are events in the world of appearance and thus are subject to the principle of sufficient reason a person s actions are a necessary consequence of motives and the given character of the individual human Necessity extends to the actions of human beings just as it does to every other appearance and thus we cannot speak of freedom of individual willing Albert Einstein quoted the Schopenhauerian idea that a man can do as he will but not will as he will 62 Yet the will as thing in itself is free as it exists beyond the realm of representation and thus is not constrained by any of the forms of necessity that are part of the principle of sufficient reason According to Schopenhauer salvation from our miserable existence can come through the will s being tranquillized by the metaphysical insight that reveals individuality to be merely an illusion The saint or great soul intuitively recognizes the whole comprehends its essence and finds that it is constantly passing away caught up in vain strivings inner conflict and perpetual suffering 63 The negation of the will in other words stems from the insight that the world in itself free from the forms of space and time is one Ascetic practices Schopenhauer remarks are used to aid the will s self abolition which brings about a blissful redemptive will less state of emptiness that is free from striving or suffering Art and aesthetics Edit Main article Arthur Schopenhauer s aesthetics In his main work Schopenhauer praised the Dutch Golden Age artists who directed such purely objective perception to the most insignificant objects and set up a lasting monument of their objectivity and spiritual peace in paintings of still life The aesthetic beholder does not contemplate this without emotion 64 For Schopenhauer human willing desiring craving etc is at the root of suffering A temporary way to escape this pain is through aesthetic contemplation Here one moves away from ordinary cognizance of individual things to cognizance of eternal Platonic Ideas in other words cognizance that is free from the service of will In aesthetic contemplation one no longer perceives an object of perception as something from which one is separated rather it is as if the object alone existed without anyone perceiving it and one can thus no longer separate the perceiver from the perception but the two have become one the entirety of consciousness entirely filled and occupied by a single perceptual image 65 Subject and object are no longer distinguishable and the Idea comes to the fore From this aesthetic immersion one is no longer an individual who suffers as a result of servitude to one s individual will but rather becomes a pure will less painless timeless subject of cognition The pure will less subject of cognition is cognizant only of Ideas not individual things this is a kind of cognition that is unconcerned with relations between objects according to the Principle of Sufficient Reason time space cause and effect and instead involves complete absorption in the object Art is the practical consequence of this brief aesthetic contemplation since it attempts to depict the essence pure Ideas of the world Music for Schopenhauer is the purest form of art because it is the one that depicts the will itself without it appearing as subject to the Principle of Sufficient Reason therefore as an individual object According to Daniel Albright Schopenhauer thought that music was the only art that did not merely copy ideas but actually embodied the will itself 66 He deemed music a timeless universal language comprehended everywhere that can imbue global enthusiasm if in possession of a significant melody 67 Mathematics Edit Schopenhauer s realist views on mathematics are evident in his criticism of contemporaneous attempts to prove the parallel postulate in Euclidean geometry Writing shortly before the discovery of hyperbolic geometry demonstrated the logical independence of the axiom and long before the general theory of relativity revealed that it does not necessarily express a property of physical space Schopenhauer criticized mathematicians for trying to use indirect concepts to prove what he held was directly evident from intuitive perception The Euclidean method of demonstration has brought forth from its own womb its most striking parody and caricature in the famous controversy over the theory of parallels and in the attempts repeated every year to prove the eleventh axiom also known as the fifth postulate The axiom asserts and that indeed through the indirect criterion of a third intersecting line that two lines inclined to each other for this is the precise meaning of less than two right angles if produced far enough must meet Now this truth is supposed to be too complicated to pass as self evident and therefore needs a proof but no such proof can be produced just because there is nothing more immediate 68 Throughout his writings 69 Schopenhauer criticized the logical derivation of philosophies and mathematics from mere concepts instead of from intuitive perceptions In fact it seems to me that the logical method is in this way reduced to an absurdity But it is precisely through the controversies over this together with the futile attempts to demonstrate the directly certain as merely indirectly certain that the independence and clearness of intuitive evidence appear in contrast with the uselessness and difficulty of logical proof a contrast as instructive as it is amusing The direct certainty will not be admitted here just because it is no merely logical certainty following from the concept and thus resting solely on the relation of predicate to subject according to the principle of contradiction But that eleventh axiom regarding parallel lines is a synthetic proposition a priori and as such has the guarantee of pure not empirical perception this perception is just as immediate and certain as is the principle of contradiction itself from which all proofs originally derive their certainty At bottom this holds good of every geometrical theorem Although Schopenhauer could see no justification for trying to prove Euclid s parallel postulate he did see a reason for examining another of Euclid s axioms 70 It surprises me that the eighth axiom 71 Figures that coincide with one another are equal to one another is not rather attacked For coinciding with one another is either a mere tautology or something quite empirical belonging not to pure intuition or perception but to external sensuous experience Thus it presupposes mobility of the figures but matter alone is movable in space Consequently this reference to coincidence with one another forsakes pure space the sole element of geometry in order to pass over to the material and empirical 68 This follows Kant s reasoning 72 Ethics Edit Main article On the Basis of Morality Schopenhauer asserts that the task of ethics is not to prescribe moral actions that ought to be done but to investigate moral actions As such he states that philosophy is always theoretical its task to explain what is given 73 According to Kant s transcendental idealism space and time are forms of our sensibility in which phenomena appear in multiplicity Reality in itself is free from multiplicity not in the sense that an object is one but that it is outside the possibility of multiplicity Two individuals though they appear distinct are in themselves not distinct 74 Appearances are entirely subordinated to the principle of sufficient reason The egoistic individual who focuses his aims on his own interests has to deal with empirical laws as well as he can What is relevant for ethics are individuals who can act against their own self interest If we take a man who suffers when he sees his fellow men living in poverty and consequently uses a significant part of his income to support their needs instead of his own pleasures then the simplest way to describe this is that he makes less distinction between himself and others than is usually made 75 Regarding how things appear to us the egoist asserts a gap between two individuals but the altruist experiences the sufferings of others as his own In the same way a compassionate man cannot hurt animals though they appear as distinct from himself What motivates the altruist is compassion The suffering of others is for him not a cold matter to which he is indifferent but he feels connectiveness to all beings Compassion is thus the basis of morality 76 Eternal justice Edit Schopenhauer calls the principle through which multiplicity appears the principium individuationis When we behold nature we see that it is a cruel battle for existence Individual manifestations of the will can maintain themselves only at the expense of others the will as the only thing that exists has no other option but to devour itself to experience pleasure This is a fundamental characteristic of the will and cannot be circumvented 77 Unlike temporal or human justice which requires time to repay an evil deed and has its seat in the state as requiting and punishing 78 eternal justice rules not the state but the world is not dependent upon human institutions is not subject to chance and deception is not uncertain wavering and erring but infallible fixed and sure 78 Eternal justice is not retributive because retribution requires time There are no delays or reprieves Instead punishment is tied to the offence to the point where the two become one Tormenter and tormented are one The Tormenter errs in that he believes he is not a partaker in the suffering the tormented in that he believes he is not a partaker in the guilt 78 Suffering is the moral outcome of our attachment to pleasure Schopenhauer deemed that this truth was expressed by the Christian dogma of original sin and in Eastern religions by the dogma of rebirth Quietism Edit He who sees through the principium individuationis and comprehends suffering in general as his own will see suffering everywhere and instead of fighting for the happiness of his individual manifestation will abhor life itself since he knows that it is inseparably connected with suffering For him a happy individual life in a world of suffering is like a beggar who dreams one night that he is a king 79 Those who have experienced this intuitive knowledge cannot affirm life but exhibit asceticism and quietism meaning that they are no longer sensitive to motives are not concerned about their individual welfare and accept without resistance the evil that others inflict on them They welcome poverty and neither seek nor flee death 79 Schopenhauer referred to asceticism as the denial of the will to live Human life is a ceaseless struggle for satisfaction and instead of continuing their struggle ascetics break it It does not matter if these ascetics adhere to the dogmata of Christianity or to Dharmic religions since their way of living is the result of intuitive knowledge The Christian mystic and the teacher of the Vedanta philosophy agree in this respect also they both regard all outward works and religious exercises as superfluous for him who has attained to perfection So much agreement in the case of such different ages and nations is a practical proof that what is expressed here is not as optimistic dullness likes to assert an eccentricity and perversity of the mind but an essential side of human nature which only appears so rarely because of its excellence 79 Psychology Edit Philosophers have not traditionally been impressed by the necessity of sex but Schopenhauer addressed sex and related concepts forthrightly one ought rather to be surprised that a thing sex which plays throughout so important a part in human life has hitherto practically been disregarded by philosophers altogether and lies before us as raw and untreated material 80 He named a force within man that he felt took invariable precedence over reason the Will to Live or Will to Life Wille zum Leben defined as an inherent drive within human beings and all creatures to stay alive a force that inveigles 81 us into reproducing Schopenhauer refused to conceive of love as either trifling or accidental but rather understood it as an immensely powerful force that lay unseen within man s psyche guaranteeing the quality of the human race The ultimate aim of all love affairs is more important than all other aims in man s life and therefore it is quite worthy of the profound seriousness with which everyone pursues it What is decided by it is nothing less than the composition of the next generation 82 It has often been argued that Schopenhauer s thoughts on sexuality foreshadowed the theory of evolution a claim met with satisfaction by Darwin as he included a quotation from Schopenhauer in his Descent of Man 83 This has also been noted about Freud s concepts of the libido and the unconscious mind and evolutionary psychology in general 84 Political and social thought Edit Politics Edit Bust in Frankfurt Schopenhauer s politics were an echo of his system of ethics which he elucidated in detail in his Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik the two essays On the Freedom of the Will and On the Basis of Morality In occasional political comments in his Parerga and Paralipomena and Manuscript Remains Schopenhauer described himself as a proponent of limited government Schopenhauer shared the view of Thomas Hobbes on the necessity of the state and state action to check the innate destructive tendencies of our species He also defended the independence of the legislative judicial and executive branches of power and a monarch as an impartial element able to practise justice in a practical and everyday sense not a cosmological one 85 He declared that monarchy is natural to man in almost the same way as it is to bees and ants to cranes in flight to wandering elephants to wolves in a pack in search of prey and to other animals 86 Intellect in monarchies he writes always has much better chances against stupidity its implacable and ever present foe than it has in republics but this is a great advantage 86 On the other hand Schopenhauer disparaged republicanism as being as unnatural to man as it is unfavorable to higher intellectual life and thus to the arts and sciences 87 By his own admission Schopenhauer did not give much thought to politics and several times he wrote proudly of how little attention he paid to political affairs of his day In a life that spanned several revolutions in French and German government and a few continent shaking wars he maintained his position of minding not the times but the eternities He wrote many disparaging remarks about Germany and the Germans A typical example is For a German it is even good to have somewhat lengthy words in his mouth for he thinks slowly and they give him time to reflect 88 Punishment Edit The State Schopenhauer claimed punishes criminals to prevent future crimes It places beside every possible motive for committing a wrong a more powerful motive for leaving it undone in the inescapable punishment Accordingly the criminal code is as complete a register as possible of counter motives to all criminal actions that can possibly be imagined 89 He claimed that this doctrine was not original to him but had appeared in the writings of Plato 90 Seneca Hobbes Pufendorf and Anselm Feuerbach Races and religions Edit Schopenhauer attributed civilizational primacy to the northern white races due to their sensitivity and creativity except for the ancient Egyptians and Hindus whom he saw as equal The highest civilization and culture apart from the ancient Hindus and Egyptians are found exclusively among the white races and even with many dark peoples the ruling caste or race is fairer in colour than the rest and has therefore evidently immigrated for example the Brahmans the Incas and the rulers of the South Sea Islands All this is due to the fact that necessity is the mother of invention because those tribes that emigrated early to the north and there gradually became white had to develop all their intellectual powers and invent and perfect all the arts in their struggle with need want and misery which in their many forms were brought about by the climate This they had to do in order to make up for the parsimony of nature and out of it all came their high civilization 91 Schopenhauer was fervently opposed to slavery Speaking of the treatment of slaves in the slave holding states of the United States he condemned those devils in human form those bigoted church going strict sabbath observing scoundrels especially the Anglican parsons among them for how they treat their innocent black brothers who through violence and injustice have fallen into their devil s claws The slave holding states of North America Schopenhauer writes are a disgrace to the whole of humanity 92 In his Metaphysics of Sexual Love Schopenhauer wrote Further the consideration as to the complexion is very decided Blondes prefer dark persons or brunettes but the latter seldom prefer the former The reason is that fair hair and blue eyes are in themselves a variation from the type almost an abnormity analogous to white mice or at least to grey horses In no part of the world not even in the vicinity of the pole are they indigenous except in Europe and are clearly of Scandinavian origin I may here express my opinion in passing that the white colour of the skin is not natural to man but that by nature he has a black or brown skin like our forefathers the Hindus that consequently a white man has never originally sprung from the womb of nature and that thus there is no such thing as a white race much as this is talked of but every white man is a faded or bleached one Forced into the strange world where he only exists like an exotic plant and like this requires in winter the hothouse in the course of thousands of years man became white The gipsies an Indian race which immigrated only about four centuries ago show the transition from the complexion of the Hindu to our own Therefore in sexual love nature strives to return to dark hair and brown eyes as the primitive type but the white colour of the skin has become a second nature though not so that the brown of the Hindu repels us Finally each one also seeks in the particular parts of the body the corrective of his own defects and aberrations and does so the more decidedly the more important the part is 93 Schopenhauer also maintained a marked metaphysical and political anti Judaism He argued that Christianity constituted a revolt against what he styled the materialistic basis of Judaism exhibiting an Indian influenced ethics reflecting the Aryan Vedic theme of spiritual self conquest He saw this as opposed to the ignorant drive toward earthly utopianism and superficiality of a worldly Jewish spirit Judaism is therefore the crudest and poorest of all religions and consists merely in an absurd and revolting theism It amounts to this that the kyrios Lord who has created the world desires to be worshipped and adored and so above all he is jealous is envious of his colleagues of all the other gods if sacrifices are made to them he is furious and his Jews have a bad time It is most deplorable that this religion has become the basis of the prevailing religion of Europe for it is a religion without any metaphysical tendency While all other religions endeavor to explain to the people by symbols the metaphysical significance of life the religion of the Jews is entirely immanent and furnishes nothing but a mere war cry in the struggle with other nations 94 Women Edit In his 1851 essay On Women Schopenhauer expressed opposition to what he called Teutonico Christian stupidity of reflexive unexamined reverence for the female abgeschmackten Weiberveneration 95 He wrote Women are directly fitted for acting as the nurses and teachers of our early childhood by the fact that they are themselves childish frivolous and short sighted He opined that women are deficient in artistic faculties and sense of justice and expressed his opposition to monogamy 96 He claimed that woman is by nature meant to obey The essay does give some compliments women are decidedly more sober in their judgment than men are and are more sympathetic to the suffering of others Schopenhauer s writings influenced many from Friedrich Nietzsche to nineteenth century feminists 97 His biological analysis of the difference between the sexes and their separate roles in the struggle for survival and reproduction anticipates some of the claims that were later ventured by sociobiologists and evolutionary psychologists 98 When the elderly Schopenhauer sat for a sculpture portrait by the Prussian sculptor Elisabet Ney in 1859 he was much impressed by the young woman s wit and independence as well as by her skill as a visual artist 99 After his time with Ney he told Richard Wagner s friend Malwida von Meysenbug I have not yet spoken my last word about women I believe that if a woman succeeds in withdrawing from the mass or rather raising herself above the mass she grows ceaselessly and more than a man 100 Pederasty Edit In the third expanded edition of The World as Will and Representation 1859 Schopenhauer added an appendix to his chapter on the Metaphysics of Sexual Love He wrote that pederasty has the benefit of preventing ill begotten children Concerning this he stated that the vice we are considering appears to work directly against the aims and ends of nature and that in a matter that is all important and of the greatest concern to her it must in fact serve these very aims although only indirectly as a means for preventing greater evils 101 Schopenhauer ends the appendix with the statement that by expounding these paradoxical ideas I wanted to grant to the professors of philosophy a small favour I have done so by giving them the opportunity of slandering me by saying that I defend and commend pederasty 102 Heredity and eugenics Edit Schopenhauer at age 58 on 16 May 1846 Schopenhauer viewed personality and intellect as inherited He quotes Horace s saying From the brave and good are the brave descended Odes iv 4 29 and Shakespeare s line from Cymbeline Cowards father cowards and base things sire base IV 2 to reinforce his hereditarian argument 103 Mechanistically Schopenhauer believed that a person inherits his intellect through his mother and personal character through the father 104 This belief in heritability of traits informed Schopenhauer s view of love placing it at the highest level of importance For Schopenhauer the final aim of all love intrigues be they comic or tragic is really of more importance than all other ends in human life What it all turns upon is nothing less than the composition of the next generation It is not the weal or woe of any one individual but that of the human race to come which is here at stake This view of the importance for the species of whom we choose to love was reflected in his views on eugenics or good breeding Here Schopenhauer wrote With our knowledge of the complete unalterability both of character and of mental faculties we are led to the view that a real and thorough improvement of the human race might be reached not so much from outside as from within not so much by theory and instruction as rather by the path of generation Plato had something of the kind in mind when in the fifth book of his Republic he explained his plan for increasing and improving his warrior caste If we could castrate all scoundrels and stick all stupid geese in a convent and give men of noble character a whole harem and procure men and indeed thorough men for all girls of intellect and understanding then a generation would soon arise which would produce a better age than that of Pericles 105 In another context Schopenhauer reiterated his eugenic thesis If you want Utopian plans I would say the only solution to the problem is the despotism of the wise and noble members of a genuine aristocracy a genuine nobility achieved by mating the most magnanimous men with the cleverest and most gifted women This proposal constitutes my Utopia and my Platonic Republic 106 Analysts e g Keith Ansell Pearson have suggested that Schopenhauer s anti egalitarianist sentiment and his support for eugenics influenced the neo aristocratic philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche who initially considered Schopenhauer his mentor 107 Animal welfare Edit Main article Arthur Schopenhauer s view on animal rights As a consequence of his monistic philosophy Schopenhauer was very concerned about animal welfare 108 109 For him all individual animals including humans are essentially phenomenal manifestations of the one underlying Will For him the word will designates force power impulse energy and desire it is the closest word we have that can signify both the essence of all external things and our own direct inner experience Since every living thing possesses will humans and animals are fundamentally the same and can recognize themselves in each other 110 For this reason he claimed that a good person would have sympathy for animals who are our fellow sufferers Compassion for animals is intimately associated with goodness of character and it may be confidently asserted that he who is cruel to living creatures cannot be a good man On the Basis of Morality 19 Nothing leads more definitely to a recognition of the identity of the essential nature in animal and human phenomena than a study of zoology and anatomy On the Basis of Morality chapter 8 111 The assumption that animals are without rights and the illusion that our treatment of them has no moral significance is a positively outrageous example of Western crudity and barbarity Universal compassion is the only guarantee of morality On the Basis of Morality chapter 8 112 In 1841 he praised the establishment in London of the Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals and in Philadelphia of the Animals Friends Society Schopenhauer went so far as to protest using the pronoun it in reference to animals because that led to treatment of them as though they were inanimate things 113 To reinforce his points Schopenhauer referred to anecdotal reports of the look in the eyes of a monkey who had been shot 114 and also the grief of a baby elephant whose mother had been killed by a hunter 115 Schopenhauer was very attached to his succession of pet poodles He criticized Spinoza s 116 belief that animals are a mere means for the satisfaction of humans 117 118 Intellectual interests and affinities Edit Indology Edit Photo of Schopenhauer 1852 Schopenhauer read the Latin translation of the ancient Hindu texts the Upanishads translated by French writer Anquetil du Perron 119 from the Persian translation of Prince Dara Shukoh entitled Sirre Akbar The Great Secret He was so impressed by its philosophy that he called it the production of the highest human wisdom and believed it contained superhuman concepts Schopenhauer considered India as the land of the most ancient and most pristine wisdom the place from which Europeans could trace their descent and the tradition by which they had been influenced in so many decisive ways 119 and regarded the Upanishads as the most profitable and elevating reading which is possible in the world It has been the solace of my life and will be the solace of my death 119 Schopenhauer was first introduced to Anquetil du Perron s translation by Friedrich Majer in 1814 119 They met during the winter of 1813 1814 in Weimar at the home of Schopenhauer s mother according to the biographer Safranski Majer was a follower of Herder and an early Indologist Schopenhauer did not begin serious study of the Indic texts until the summer of 1814 Safranski maintains that between 1815 and 1817 Schopenhauer had another important cross pollination with Indian thought in Dresden This was through his neighbor of two years Karl Christian Friedrich Krause Krause was then a minor and rather unorthodox philosopher who attempted to mix his own ideas with ancient Indian wisdom Krause had also mastered Sanskrit unlike Schopenhauer and they developed a professional relationship It was from Krause that Schopenhauer learned meditation and received the closest thing to expert advice concerning Indian thought 120 The view of things that all plurality is only apparent that in the endless series of individuals passing simultaneously and successively into and out of life generation after generation age after age there is but one and the same entity really existing which is present and identical in all alike this theory I say was of course known long before Kant indeed it may be carried back to the remotest antiquity It is the alpha and omega of the oldest book in the world the sacred Vedas whose dogmatic part or rather esoteric teaching is found in the Upanishads There in almost every page this profound doctrine lies enshrined with tireless repetition in countless adaptations by many varied parables and similes it is expounded and inculcated On the Basis of Morality chapter 4 121 The book Oupnekhat Upanishad always lay open on his table and he invariably studied it before going to bed He called the opening up of Sanskrit literature the greatest gift of our century and predicted that the philosophy and knowledge of the Upanishads would become the cherished faith of the West 122 Most noticeable in the case of Schopenhauer s work was the significance of the Chandogya Upanishad whose Mahavakya Tat Tvam Asi is mentioned throughout The World as Will and Representation 123 Buddhism Edit Schopenhauer noted a correspondence between his doctrines and the Four Noble Truths of Buddhism 124 Similarities centered on the principles that life involves suffering that suffering is caused by desire taṇha and that the extinction of desire leads to liberation Thus three of the four truths of the Buddha correspond to Schopenhauer s doctrine of the will 125 In Buddhism while greed and lust are always unskillful desire is ethically variable it can be skillful unskillful or neutral 126 For Schopenhauer will had ontological primacy over the intellect desire is prior to thought Schopenhauer felt this was similar to notions of puruṣartha or goals of life in Vedanta Hinduism In Schopenhauer s philosophy denial of the will is attained by personal experience of an extremely great suffering that leads to loss of the will to live or knowledge of the essential nature of life in the world through observation of the suffering of other people Buddhist nirvaṇa is not equivalent to the condition that Schopenhauer described as denial of the will Nirvaṇa is not the extinguishing of the person as some Western scholars have thought but only the extinguishing the literal meaning of nirvana of the flames of greed hatred and delusion that assail a person s character 127 Schopenhauer made the following statement in his discussion of religions 128 If I wished to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth I should have to concede to Buddhism pre eminence over the others In any case it must be a pleasure to me to see my doctrine in such close agreement with a religion that the majority of men on earth hold as their own for this numbers far more followers than any other And this agreement must be yet the more pleasing to me inasmuch as in my philosophizing I have certainly not been under its influence emphasis added For up till 1818 when my work appeared there was to be found in Europe only a very few accounts of Buddhism 129 Buddhist philosopher Keiji Nishitani sought to distance Buddhism from Schopenhauer 130 While Schopenhauer s philosophy may sound rather mystical in such a summary his methodology was resolutely empirical rather than speculative or transcendental Philosophy is a science and as such has no articles of faith accordingly in it nothing can be assumed as existing except what is either positively given empirically or demonstrated through indubitable conclusions 131 Also note This actual world of what is knowable in which we are and which is in us remains both the material and the limit of our consideration 132 The argument that Buddhism affected Schopenhauer s philosophy more than any other Dharmic faith loses credence since he did not begin a serious study of Buddhism until after the publication of The World as Will and Representation in 1818 133 Scholars have started to revise earlier views about Schopenhauer s discovery of Buddhism Proof of early interest and influence appears in Schopenhauer s 1815 16 notes transcribed and translated by Urs App about Buddhism They are included in a recent case study that traces Schopenhauer s interest in Buddhism and documents its influence 134 Other scholarly work questions how similar Schopenhauer s philosophy actually is to Buddhism 135 Magic and occultism Edit Some traditions in Western esotericism and parapsychology interested Schopenhauer and influenced his philosophical theories He praised animal magnetism as evidence for the reality of magic in his On the Will in Nature and went so far as to accept the division of magic into left hand and right hand magic although he doubted the existence of demons 136 Schopenhauer grounded magic in the Will and claimed all forms of magical transformation depended on the human Will not on ritual This theory notably parallels Aleister Crowley s system of magic and its emphasis on human will 136 Given the importance of the Will to Schopenhauer s overarching system this amounts to suggesting his whole philosophical system had magical powers 137 Schopenhauer rejected the theory of disenchantment and claimed philosophy should synthesize itself with magic which he believed amount to practical metaphysics 138 Neoplatonism including the traditions of Plotinus and to a lesser extent Marsilio Ficino has also been cited as an influence on Schopenhauer 139 Interests EditSchopenhauer had a wide range of interests from science and opera to occultism and literature In his student years Schopenhauer went more often to lectures in the sciences than philosophy He kept a strong interest as his personal library contained near to 200 books of scientific literature at his death and his works refer to scientific titles not found in the library 34 170 Many evenings were spent in the theatre opera and ballet Schopenhauer especially liked the operas of Mozart Rossini and Bellini 140 Schopenhauer considered music the highest art and played the flute during his whole life 34 30 As a polyglot he knew German Italian Spanish French English Latin and ancient Greek and was an avid reader of poetry and literature He particularly revered Goethe Petrarch Calderon and Shakespeare If Goethe had not been sent into the world simultaneously with Kant in order to counterbalance him so to speak in the spirit of the age the latter would have been haunted like a nightmare many an aspiring mind and would have oppressed it with great affliction But now the two have an infinitely wholesome effect from opposite directions and will probably raise the German spirit to a height surpassing even that of antiquity 34 240 In philosophy his most important influences were according to himself Kant Plato and the Upanishads Concerning the Upanishads and Vedas he writes in The World as Will and Representation If the reader has also received the benefit of the Vedas the access to which by means of the Upanishads is in my eyes the greatest privilege which this still young century 1818 may claim before all previous centuries if then the reader I say has received his initiation in primeval Indian wisdom and received it with an open heart he will be prepared in the very best way for hearing what I have to tell him It will not sound to him strange as to many others much less disagreeable for I might if it did not sound conceited contend that every one of the detached statements which constitute the Upanishads may be deduced as a necessary result from the fundamental thoughts which I have to enunciate though those deductions themselves are by no means to be found there 141 Thoughts on other philosophers EditGiordano Bruno and Spinoza Edit Schopenhauer saw Bruno and Spinoza as philosophers not bound to their age or nation Both were fulfilled by the thought that as manifold the appearances of the world may be it is still one being that appears in all of them Consequently there is no place for God as creator of the world in their philosophy but God is the world itself 142 143 Schopenhauer expressed regret that Spinoza stuck for the presentation of his philosophy with the concepts of scholasticism and Cartesian philosophy and tried to use geometrical proofs that do not hold because of vague and overly broad definitions Bruno on the other hand who knew much about nature and ancient literature presented his ideas with Italian vividness and is amongst philosophers the only one who comes near Plato s poetic and dramatic power of exposition 142 143 Schopenhauer noted that their philosophies do not provide any ethics and it is therefore very remarkable that Spinoza called his main work Ethics In fact it could be considered complete from the standpoint of life affirmation if one completely ignores morality and self denial 144 It is yet even more remarkable that Schopenhauer mentions Spinoza as an example of the denial of the will if one uses the French biography by Jean Maximilien Lucas 145 as the key to Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione 146 Immanuel Kant Edit Schopenhauer s philosophy took Kant s work as its foundation While he praised Kant s greatness he nonetheless included a highly detailed criticism of Kantian philosophy as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation See also Critique of the Kantian philosophy and Schopenhauer s criticism of Kant s schemata The importance of Kant for Schopenhauer in philosophy as well as on a personal level cannot be overstated Kant s philosophy was the foundation of Schopenhauer s and he had high praise for the Transcendental Aesthetic section of Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Schopenhauer maintained that Kant stands in the same relation to philosophers such as Berkeley and Plato as Copernicus to Hicetas Philolaus and Aristarchus Kant succeeded in demonstrating what previous philosophers merely asserted Schopenhauer writes about Kant s influence on his work in the preface to the second edition of The World as Will and Representation I have already explained in the preface to the first edition that my philosophy is founded on that of Kant and therefore presupposes a thorough knowledge of it I repeat this here For Kant s teaching produces in the mind of everyone who has comprehended it a fundamental change which is so great that it may be regarded as an intellectual new birth It alone is able really to remove the inborn realism which proceeds from the original character of the intellect which neither Berkeley nor Malebranche succeed in doing for they remain too much in the universal while Kant goes into the particular and indeed in a way that is quite unexampled both before and after him and which has quite a peculiar and we might say immediate effect upon the mind in consequence of which it undergoes a complete undeception and forthwith looks at all things in another light Only in this way can any one become susceptible to the more positive expositions which I have to give On the other hand he who has not mastered the Kantian philosophy whatever else he may have studied is as it were in a state of innocence that is to say he remains in the grasp of that natural and childish realism in which we are all born and which fits us for everything possible with the single exception of philosophy 147 In his study room one bust was of Buddha the other was of Kant 148 The bond which Schopenhauer felt with the philosopher of Konigsberg is demonstrated in an unfinished poem he dedicated to Kant included in volume 2 of the Parerga With my eyes I followed thee into the blue sky And there thy flight dissolved from view Alone I stayed in the crowd below Thy word and thy book my only solace Through the strains of thy inspiring wordsI sought to dispel the dreary solitude Strangers on all sides surround me The world is desolate and life interminable 149 Schopenhauer dedicated one fifth of his main work The World as Will and Representation to a detailed criticism of the Kantian philosophy Schopenhauer praised Kant for his distinction between appearance and the thing in itself whereas the general consensus in German idealism was that this was the weakest spot of Kant s theory 61 since according to Kant causality can find application on objects of experience only and consequently things in themselves cannot be the cause of appearances The inadmissibility of this reasoning was also acknowledged by Schopenhauer He insisted that this was a true conclusion drawn from false premises 150 Post Kantian school Edit The leading figures of post Kantian philosophy Johann Gottlieb Fichte F W J Schelling and G W F Hegel were not respected by Schopenhauer He argued that they were not philosophers at all for they lacked the first requirement of a philosopher namely a seriousness and honesty of inquiry 151 Rather they were merely sophists who excelling in the art of beguiling the public pursued their own selfish interests such as professional advancement within the university system Diatribes against the vacuity dishonesty pomposity and self interest of these contemporaries are to be found throughout Schopenhauer s published writings The following passage is an example All this explains the painful impression with which we are seized when after studying genuine thinkers we come to the writings of Fichte and Schelling or even to the presumptuously scribbled nonsense of Hegel produced as it was with a boundless though justified confidence in German stupidity With those genuine thinkers one always found an honest investigation of truth and just as honest an attempt to communicate their ideas to others Therefore whoever reads Kant Locke Hume Malebranche Spinoza and Descartes feels elevated and agreeably impressed This is produced through communion with a noble mind which has and awakens ideas and which thinks and sets one thinking The reverse of all this takes place when we read the above mentioned three German sophists An unbiased reader opening one of their books and then asking himself whether this is the tone of a thinker wanting to instruct or that of a charlatan wanting to impress cannot be five minutes in any doubt here everything breathes so much of dishonesty 152 Schopenhauer deemed Schelling the most talented of the three and wrote that he would recommend his elucidatory paraphrase of the highly important doctrine of Kant concerning the intelligible character if he had been honest enough to admit he was parroting Kant instead of hiding this relation in a cunning manner 153 Schopenhauer reserved his most unqualified damning condemnation for Hegel whom he considered less worthy than Fichte or Schelling Whereas Fichte was merely a windbag Windbeutel Hegel was a commonplace inane loathsome repulsive and ignorant charlatan 154 The philosophers Karl Popper and Mario Bunge agreed with this distinction 155 156 Hegel Schopenhauer wrote in the preface to his Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics not only performed no service to philosophy but he has had a detrimental influence on philosophy and thereby on German literature in general really a downright stupefying or we could even say a pestilential influence which it is therefore the duty of everyone capable of thinking for himself and judging for himself to counteract in the most express terms at every opportunity 157 Schopenhauer s split with Friedrich Nietzsche Edit The early relationship between Schopenhauer and Friedrich Nietzsche were marked by a close and scholarly connection but later Nietzsche abandoned his former enthusiasm for Schopenhauer s philosophy because he came to conceive of Schopenhauer s advocacy of quietism as symptomatic of decadence Later Nietzsche realised the ardent anti semitism by Schopenhauer and his early friend Richard Wagner Both Schopenhauer and Wagner accused Nietzsche of Judeophilia and pandering to Jewish interests a standpoint Nietzsche could not accept logically and historically While both philosophers did not discredit each other s work the questions of anti Judaism and differing methodologies regarding ethics and asceticism were the major reasons why Nietzsche distanced himself from Schopenhauer and Wagner in his later years 158 159 Influence and legacy Edit Sculpture of Schopenhauer by Elisabeth Ney Schopenhauer remained the most influential German philosopher until the First World War 160 His philosophy was a starting point for a new generation of philosophers including Julius Bahnsen Paul Deussen Lazar von Hellenbach Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann Ernst Otto Lindner Philipp Mainlander Friedrich Nietzsche Olga Plumacher and Agnes Taubert His legacy shaped the intellectual debate and forced movements that were utterly opposed to him neo Kantianism and positivism to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored and in doing so he changed them markedly 160 The French writer Maupassant commented that to day even those who execrate him seem to carry in their own souls particles of his thought 161 Other philosophers of the 19th century who cited his influence include Hans Vaihinger Volkelt Solovyov and Weininger Schopenhauer was well read by physicists most notably Einstein Schrodinger Wolfgang Pauli 162 and Majorana 14 Einstein described Schopenhauer s thoughts as a continual consolation and called him a genius 163 In his Berlin study three figures hung on the wall Faraday Maxwell Schopenhauer 164 Konrad Wachsmann recalled He often sat with one of the well worn Schopenhauer volumes and as he sat there he seemed so pleased as if he were engaged with a serene and cheerful work 165 When Erwin Schrodinger discovered Schopenhauer the greatest savant of the West he considered switching his study of physics to philosophy 166 He maintained the idealistic views during the rest of his life 167 Wolfgang Pauli accepted the main tenet of Schopenhauer s metaphysics that the thing in itself is will 168 But most of all Schopenhauer is famous for his influence on artists Richard Wagner became one of the earliest and most famous adherents of the Schopenhauerian philosophy 169 The admiration was not mutual and Schopenhauer proclaimed I remain faithful to Rossini and Mozart 170 So he has been nicknamed the artist s philosopher 1 See also Influence of Schopenhauer on Tristan und Isolde Schopenhauer depicted on a 500 million Danzig papiermark note 1923 Under the influence of Schopenhauer Leo Tolstoy became convinced that the truth of all religions lies in self renunciation When he read Schopenhauer s philosophy Tolstoy exclaimed at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection 171 He said that what he has written in War and Peace is also said by Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Representation 172 Jorge Luis Borges remarked that the reason he had never attempted to write a systematic account of his world view despite his penchant for philosophy and metaphysics in particular was because Schopenhauer had already written it for him 173 Other figures in literature who were strongly influenced by Schopenhauer were Thomas Mann Thomas Hardy Afanasy Fet J K Huysmans and George Santayana 174 In Herman Melville s final years while he wrote Billy Budd he read Schopenhauer s essays and marked them heavily Scholar Brian Yothers notes that Melville marked numerous misanthropic and even suicidal remarks suggesting an attraction to the most extreme sorts of solitude but he also made note of Schopenhauer s reflection on the moral ambiguities of genius 175 Schopenhauer s attraction to and discussions of both Eastern and Western religions in conjunction with each other made an impression on Melville in his final years Sergei Prokofiev although initially reluctant to engage with works noted for their pessimism became fascinated with Schopenhauer after reading Aphorisms on the Wisdom of Life in Parerga and Paralipomena With his truths Schopenhauer gave me a spiritual world and an awareness of happiness 176 Friedrich Nietzsche owed the awakening of his philosophical interest to reading The World as Will and Representation and admitted that he was one of the few philosophers that he respected dedicating to him his essay Schopenhauer als Erzieher 177 one of his Untimely Meditations Commemorative stamp of the Deutsche Bundespost Early in his career Ludwig Wittgenstein adopted Schopenhauer s epistemological idealism and some traits of Schopenhauer s influence particularly Schopenhauerian transcendentalism can be observed in the Tractatus Logico Philosophicus 178 179 Later on Wittgenstein rejected epistemological transcendental idealism for Gottlob Frege s conceptual realism In later years Wittgenstein became highly dismissive of Schopenhauer describing him as an ultimately shallow thinker 23 180 His friend Bertrand Russell had a low opinion on the philosopher and even came to attack him in his History of Western Philosophy for hypocritically praising asceticism yet not acting upon it 181 Opposite to Russell on the foundations of mathematics the Dutch mathematician L E J Brouwer incorporated Kant s and Schopenhauer s ideas in the philosophical school of intuitionism where mathematics is considered as a purely mental activity instead of an analytic activity wherein objective properties of reality are revealed Brouwer was also influenced by Schopenhauer s metaphysics and wrote an essay on mysticism Schopenhauer s philosophy has made its way into a novel The Schopenhauer Cure by American existential psychiatrist and emeritus professor of psychiatry Irvin Yalom Schopenhauer s philosophy and the discussions on philosophical pessimism it has engendered has been the focus of contemporary thinkers such as David Benatar Thomas Ligotti and Eugene Thacker Their work also served as an inspiration for the popular HBO TV series True Detective as well as Life Is Beautiful 182 In this regard Schopenhauer is sometimes considered the founding father of today s antinatalism 183 Selected bibliography EditOn the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde 1813 On Vision and Colors Ueber das Sehn und die Farben 1816 ISBN 978 0 85496 988 3 Theory of Colors Theoria colorum physiologica 1830 The World as Will and Representation alternatively translated in English as The World as Will and Idea original German is Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung vol 1 1818 1819 vol 2 1844 Vol 1 Dover edition 1966 ISBN 978 0 486 21761 1 Vol 2 Dover edition 1966 ISBN 978 0 486 21762 8 Peter Smith Publisher hardcover set 1969 ISBN 978 0 8446 2885 1 Everyman Paperback combined abridged edition 290 pp ISBN 978 0 460 87505 9 The Art of Being Right Eristische Dialektik Die Kunst Recht zu Behalten 1831 On the Will in Nature Ueber den Willen in der Natur 1836 ISBN 978 0 85496 999 9 On the Freedom of the Will Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens 1839 ISBN 978 0 631 14552 3 On the Basis of Morality Ueber die Grundlage der Moral 1840 The Two Basic Problems of Ethics On the Freedom of the Will On the Basis of Morality Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens Ueber das Fundament der Moral 1841 Parerga and Paralipomena 2 vols 1851 Reprint Oxford Clarendon Press 2 vols 1974 English translation by E F J Payne 184 Printings 1974 Hardcover by ISBN Vols 1 and 2 ISBN 978 0 19 519813 3 Vol 1 ISBN Vol 2 ISBN 978 0 19 824527 8 1974 1980 Paperback Vol 1 ISBN 978 0 19 824634 3 Vol 2 ISBN 978 0 19 824635 0 2001 Paperback Vol 1 ISBN 978 0 19 924220 7 Vol 2 ISBN 978 0 19 924221 4 Essays and Aphorisms being excerpts from Volume 2 of Parerga und Paralipomena selected and translated by R J Hollingdale with Introduction by R J Hollingdale Penguin Classics 1970 Paperback 1973 ISBN 978 0 14 044227 4 An Enquiry concerning Ghost seeing and what is connected therewith Versuch uber das Geistersehn und was damit zusammenhangt 1851 Arthur Schopenhauer Manuscript Remains Volume II Berg Publishers Ltd ISBN 978 0 85496 539 7Online Edit Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at Project Gutenberg The Art of Controversy Die Kunst Recht zu behalten bilingual The Art of Being Right Studies in Pessimism audiobook from LibriVox The World as Will and Idea at Internet Archive Volume I Volume II Volume III On the fourfold root of the principle of sufficient reason and On the will in nature Two essays Internet Archive Translated by Mrs Karl Hillebrand 1903 Cornell University Library Historical Monographs Collection Reprinted by Cornell University Library Digital Collections Facsimile edition of Schopenhauer s manuscripts in SchopenhauerSource Essays of SchopenhauerSee also EditAntinatalism Existential nihilism Eye of a needle God in Buddhism Massacre of the Innocents Guido Reni Misotheism Mortal coil Nihilism Post Schopenhauerian pessimismReferences Edit a b Arthur Schopenhauer 1788 1860 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Frederick C Beiser reviews the commonly held position that Schopenhauer was a transcendental idealist and he rejects it Though it is deeply heretical from the standpoint of transcendental idealism Schopenhauer s objective standpoint involves a form of transcendental realism i e the assumption of the independent reality of the world of experience Beiser 2016 p 40 a b Voluntarism philosophy Britannica com Arthur Schopenhauer Arthur Schopenhauer The World as Will and Presentation Volume 1 Routledge 2016 p 211 the world is a mere presentation object for a subject Lennart Svensson Borderline A Traditionalist Outlook for Modern Man Numen Books 2015 p 71 Schopenhauer said that the world is our conception A world without a perceiver would in that case be an impossibility But we can he said gain knowledge about Essential Reality for looking into ourselves by introspection This is one of many examples of the anthropic principle The world is there for the sake of man a b The World as Will and Representation vol 3 Ch 50 a b Dale Jacquette ed 2007 Schopenhauer Philosophy and the Arts Cambridge University Press p 162 ISBN 978 0 521 04406 6 For Kant the mathematical sublime as seen for example in the starry heavens suggests to imagination the infinite which in turn leads by subtle turns of contemplation to the concept of God Schopenhauer s atheism will have none of this and he rightly observes that despite adopting Kant s distinction between the dynamical and mathematical sublime his theory of the sublime making reference to the struggles and sufferings of struggles and sufferings of Will is unlike Kant s Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 Book 4 For the philosopher these accounts of the lives of holy self denying men badly as they are generally written and mixed as they are with superstition and nonsense are because of the significance of the material immeasurably more instructive and important than even Plutarch and Livy But the spirit of this development of Christianity is certainly nowhere so fully and powerfully expressed as in the writings of the German mystics in the works of Meister Eckhard and in that justly famous book Die Deutsche Theologie Howard Don A December 2005 Albert Einstein as a Philosopher of Science PDF Physics Today 58 12 34 40 Bibcode 2005PhT 58l 34H doi 10 1063 1 2169442 archived PDF from the original on 9 October 2022 retrieved 8 March 2015 via University of Notre Dame Notre Dame IN author s personal webpage From Schopenhauer he had learned to regard the independence of spatially separated systems as virtually a necessary a priori assumption Einstein regarded his separation principle descended from Schopenhauer s principium individuationis as virtually an axiom for any future fundamental physics Schopenhauer stressed the essential structuring role of space and time in individuating physical systems and their evolving states This view implies that difference of location suffices to make two systems different in the sense that each has its own real physical state independent of the state of the other For Schopenhauer the mutual independence of spatially separated systems was a necessary a priori truth Frederick C Beiser After Hegel German Philosophy 1840 1900 Princeton University Press 2014 p 49 Dilthey s conception of a worldview as he finally formulated it in Das Wesen der Philosophie shows a large debt to Schopenhauer Like his great forebear Dilthey believed that philosophy had first and foremost an ethical function that its main purpose was to address the puzzle of the world John Gray Forget everything you know Profiles People The Independent London 3 September 2002 Archived from the original on 9 April 2010 Retrieved 12 March 2010 Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin 1973 Wittgenstein s Vienna New York Simon and Schuster p 74 Kraus himself was no philosopher even less a scientist If Kraus s views have a philosophical ancestry this comes most assuredly from Schopenhauer for alone among the great philosophers Schopenhauer was a kindred spirit a man of philosophical profundity with a strange talent for polemic and aphorism a literary as weIl as philosophical genius Schopenhauer indeed was the only philosopher who at all appealed to Kraus Kerr R B 1932 Anthony M Ludovici The prophet of anti feminism www anthonymludovici com Retrieved 5 May 2019 a b Bassani Giuseppe Franco 15 December 2006 Societa Italiana di Fisica ed Ettore Majorana Scientific Papers Springer p xl ISBN 978 3 540 48091 4 His interest in philosophy which had always been great increased and prompted him to reflect deeply on the works of various philosophers in particular Schopenhauer Magee Bryan 1997 Confessions of a Philosopher Ch 16 B F McGuinness Moritz Schlick pp 336 37 Once again one has to understand Schlick s world conception which he took over from Schopenhauer s world as representation and as will To will something and here Schlick is heavily influenced by Schopenhauer Maertz Gregory 1994 Elective Affinities Tolstoy and Schopenhauer Wiener Slavistisches Jahrbuch Harrassowitz Verlag 40 53 62 ISSN 0084 0041 JSTOR 24748326 Wells John C 2008 Longman Pronunciation Dictionary 3rd ed Longman ISBN 978 1 4058 8118 0 Arthur Schopenhauer 2004 Essays and Aphorisms Penguin Classics p 23 ISBN 978 0 14 044227 4 The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary Schopenhauer Oxford University Press 1991 p 1298 ISBN 978 0 19 861248 3 See the book length study about oriental influences on the genesis of Schopenhauer s philosophy by Urs App Schopenhauer s Compass An Introduction to Schopenhauer s Philosophy and its Origins Wil UniversityMedia 2014 ISBN 978 3 906000 03 9 Hergenhahn B R 2009 An Introduction to the History of Psychology 6th ed Cengage Learning p 216 ISBN 978 0 495 50621 8 Although Schopenhauer was an atheist he realized that his philosophy of denial had been part of several great religions for example Christianity Hinduism and Buddhism Arthur Schopenhauer 2004 Essays and Aphorisms Penguin Classics pp 22 36 ISBN 978 0 14 044227 4 but there has been none who tried with so great a show of learning to demonstrate that the pessimistic outlook is justified that life itself is really bad It is to this end that Schopenhauer s metaphysic of will and idea exists Studies in Pessimism audiobook from LibriVox David A Leeming Kathryn Madden Stanton Marlan eds 2009 Encyclopedia of Psychology and Religion Volume 2 Springer p 824 ISBN 978 0 387 71801 9 A more accurate statement might be that for a German rather than a French or British writer of that time Schopenhauer was an honest and open atheist Addressed in Cate Curtis Friedrich Nietzsche Chapter 7 a b Culture amp Value p 24 1933 34 Albert Einstein in Mein Glaubensbekenntnis August 1932 I do not believe in free will Schopenhauer s words Man can do what he wants but he cannot will what he wants Der Mensch kann wohl tun was er will aber er kann nicht wollen was er will accompany me in all situations throughout my life and reconcile me with the actions of others even if they are rather painful to me This awareness of the lack of free will keeps me from taking myself and my fellow men too seriously as acting and deciding individuals and from losing my temper Schopenhauer s clearer actual words were You can do what you will but in any given moment of your life you can will only one definite thing and absolutely nothing other than that one thing Du kannst tun was du willst aber du kannst in jedem gegebenen Augenblick deines Lebens nur ein Bestimmtes wollen und schlechterdings nichts anderes als dieses eine On the Freedom of the Will Ch II Magee Bryan The Philosophy of Schopenhauer ISBN 978 0 19 823722 8 Maertz Gregory 1994 Elective Affinities Tolstoy and Schopenhauer Wiener Slavistisches Jahrbuch Harrassowitz Verlag 40 53 62 ISSN 0084 0041 JSTOR 24748326 Melville Herman Melville s Marginalia Melville s Marginalia Online Retrieved 1 September 2020 Punsly Kathryn 2012 The Influence of Nietzsche and Schopenhauer on Hermann Hesse CMC Senior Theses Paper 347 https scholarship claremont edu cgi viewcontent cgi article 1353 amp context cmc theses Retrieved on 19 March 2021 Wicks Robert 2011 Schopenhauer s The world as will and representation a reader s guide London Continuum ISBN 978 0 8264 3181 3 OCLC 721337622 a b c d e Shapshay Sandra Schopenhauer s Aesthetics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Edward N Zalta ed https plato stanford edu archives sum2018 entries schopenhauer aesthetics Retrieved on 19 March 2021 Wicks Robert 2018 Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Schonberg s Library Alphabetical List www schoenberg at Retrieved 19 March 2021 Schopenhauer Arthur Gunter Zoller Eric F J Payne 1999 Chronology Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will Cambridge University Press p xxx ISBN 978 0 521 57766 3 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao ap aq ar as at au av aw ax ay az ba bb bc bd be bf bg bh bi bj bk bl bm bn bo bp bq br bs bt bu bv bw bx by bz ca cb cc cd ce cf cg ch ci cj ck cl cm cn co cp cq cr cs ct cu cv cw cx cy cz da db dc dd de df dg dh di dj dk dl dm dn do dp dq dr ds dt du dv dw dx dy Cartwright David E 2010 Schopenhauer A Biography Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 82598 6 Bullock A B 1920 The Supreme Human Tragedy And Other Essays C W Daniel p 53 Retrieved 22 October 2022 Safranski 1990 pg 12 Wallace W 2003 Life of Arthur Schopenhauer Honolulu University Press of the Pacific p 59 ISBN 978 1 4102 0641 1 Durant Will The Story of Philosophy Garden City Publishing Co Inc New York p 350 Schopenhauer A Pessimist in the Optimistic Month of May Germanic American Institute Archived from the original on 11 June 2010 Retrieved 12 March 2010 Full text of Selected Essays Of Schopenhauer Retrieved 12 March 2010 a b Fredriksson Einar H 2001 The Dutch Publishing Scene Elsevier and North Holland A Century of Science Publishing A Collection of Essays Amsterdam IOS Press pp 61 76 ISBN 978 4 274 90424 0 Willson A Leslie 1961 Friedrich Majer Romantic Indologist Texas Studies in Literature and Language 3 1 40 49 ISSN 0040 4691 JSTOR 40753707 a b c Clarke 1997 pp 67 68 Clarke 1997 pp 67 69 Clarke 1997 pp 273 Clarke 1997 p 69 Schopenhauer Arthur 22 April 2019 The world as will and idea ISBN 978 1 950330 23 2 OCLC 1229105608 Although the first volume was published by December 1818 it was printed with a title page erroneously giving the year as 1819 see Braunschweig Yael 2013 Schopenhauer and Rossinian Universiality On the Italianate in Schopenhauer s Metaphysics of Music The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini Historiography Analysis Criticism Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 297 n 7 ISBN 978 0 521 76805 4 Safranski Rudiger 1991 Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy Harvard University Press p 244 Schopenhauer Arthur Author s preface to On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of sufficient reason p 1 On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason on Wikisource Dale Jacquette The Philosophy of Schopenhauer Routledge 2015 Biographical sketch Schopenhauer his life and philosophy by H Zimmern 1932 G Allen amp Unwin Lewis Peter 15 February 2013 Arthur Schopenhauer 2013 Reaktion Books ISBN 978 1 78023 069 6 Kant Immanuel Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Translated by Paul Carus 52c See the quotation of Schopenhauer in Storm Jason Josephson 2021 Metamodernism The Future of Theory Chicago University of Chicago Press pp 36 37 ISBN 978 0 226 78665 0 Letter to Goethe on 23 January 1816 Ich weiss dass durch mich die Wahrheit geredet hat in dieser kleinen Sache wie dereinst in grossern Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy But the whole teaching of Kant contains really nothing more about this than the oft repeated meaningless expression The empirical element in perception is given from without always through the same meaningless metaphorical expression The empirical perception is given us Schopenhauer Arthur On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 21 For sensation is and remains a process within the organism and is limited as such to the region within the skin it cannot therefore contain any thing which lies beyond that region or in other words anything that is outside us It is only when the Understanding begins to apply its sole form the causal law that a powerful transformation takes place by which subjective sensation becomes objective perception Schopenhauer Arthur On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 21 Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 4 The contrary doctrine that the law of causality results from experience which was the scepticism of Hume is first refuted by this For the independence of the knowledge of causality of all experience that is its a priori character can only be deduced from the dependence of all experience upon it and this deduction can only be accomplished by proving in the manner here indicated and explained in the passages referred to above that the knowledge of causality is included in perception in general to which all experience belongs and therefore in respect of experience is completely a priori does not presuppose it but is presupposed by it as a condition a b David E Cartwright Edward E Erdmann Introduction to On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason Cambridge University Press pp xvi xvii He had also rehearsed for the first time his physiological arguments for the intellectual nature of intuition Anschauung objective perception in his On Vision and Colours and he had discussed how his philosophy was corroborated by the sciences in On Will in Nature Like the German Idealists Schopenhauer was convinced that Kant s great unknown the thing in itself is the weak point of the critical philosophy Einstein Albert 1935 The World as I See It p 14 Snowball Publishing ISBN 1 4948 7706 6 The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 68 The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 38 The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 34 Daniel Albright Modernism and Music 2004 p 39 footnote 34 Schopenhauer Arthur 1970 Essays and Aphorisms 10 Penguin Classics p 162 ISBN 978 0 14 044227 4 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location link a b The World as Will and Representation vol 2 ch 13 I wanted in this way to stress and demonstrate the great difference indeed opposition between knowledge of perception and abstract or reflected knowledge Hitherto this difference has received too little attention and its establishment is a fundamental feature of my philosophy The World as Will and Representation vol 2 ch 7 p 88 trans Payne This comment by Schopenhauer was called an acute observation by Sir Thomas L Heath In his translation of The Elements vol 1 Book I Note on Common Notion 4 Heath made this judgment and also noted that Schopenhauer s remark was a criticism in advance of Helmholtz theory Helmholtz had maintained that geometry requires us to assume the actual existence of rigid bodies and their free mobility in space and is therefore dependent on mechanics What Schopenhauer calls the eighth axiom is Euclid s Common Notion 4 Motion of an object in space does not belong in a pure science and consequently not in geometry For the fact that something is movable cannot be cognized a priori but can be cognized only through experience Kant Critique of Pure Reason B 155 Note Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 53 Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 23 Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 66 Schopenhauer Arthur On the Basis of Morality 19 Schopenhauer Arthur Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 2 173 a b c The World as Will and Idea Vol 1 63 a b c Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 68 Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Supplements to the Fourth Book The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary Schopenhauer Oxford University Press 1991 p 1298 ISBN 978 0 19 861248 3 Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Supplements to the Fourth Book Darwin Charles The Descent of Man p 586 Nearly a century before Freud in Schopenhauer there is for the first time an explicit philosophy of the unconscious and of the body Safranski p 345 The World as Will and Representation Vol 2 Ch 47 a b Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 2 On Jurisprudence and Politics 127 trans Payne p 254 Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 2 On Jurisprudence and Politics 127 trans Payne p 255 The World as Will and Representation Vol 2 Ch 12 Schopenhauer The World as Will and Representation Vol I 62 he who attempts to punish in accordance with reason does not retaliate on account of the past wrong for he could not undo something which has been done but for the future so that neither the wrongdoer himself nor others who see him being punished will do wrong again Plato Protagoras 324 B Plato wrote that punishment should be an example to other men not to offend Plato Laws Book IX 863 Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 2 On Philosophy and Natural Science 92 trans Payne p 158 159 Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 2 On Ethics 114 trans Payne p 212 The Metaphysics of Sexual Love the Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia Fragments for the History of Philosophy Parerga and Paralipomena Volume I trans Payne p 126 Arthur Schopenhauer Ueber die Weiber aboq org Rodgers environmentalist and Thompson in Philosophers Behaving Badly call Schopenhauer a misogynist without rival in Western philosophy Feminism and the Limits of Equality PA Cain Ga L Rev 1989 Julian Young 23 June 2005 Schopenhauer Psychology Press p 242 ISBN 978 0 415 33346 7 Long Sandra Salser Spring 1984 Arthur Schopenhauer and Elisabet Ney Southwest Review 69 2 130 47 JSTOR 43469632 Safranski 1990 Chapter 24 p 348 Schopenhauer 1969 p 566 Schopenhauer 1969 p 567 Payne The World as Will and Representation Vol II p 519 On the Suffering of the World 1970 p 35 Penguin Books Great Ideas Schopenhauer Arthur 1969 E F J Payne ed The World as Will and Representation Vol II New York Dover Publications p 527 ISBN 978 0 486 21762 8 Essays and Aphorisms trans R J Hollingdale Middlesex London 1970 p 154 Nietzsche and Modern German Thought by K Ansell Pearson 1991 Psychology Press Christina Gerhardt Thinking With Animals in Schopenhauer Horkheimer and Adorno Critical Theory and Animals Ed John Sanbonmatsu Lanham Rowland 2011 137 157 Stephen Puryear Schopenhauer on the Rights of Animals European Journal of Philosophy 25 2 2017 250 269 Unlike the intellect it the Will does not depend on the perfection of the organism but is essentially the same in all animals as what is known to us so intimately Accordingly the animal has all the emotions of humans such as joy grief fear anger love hatred strong desire envy and so on The great difference between human and animal rests solely on the intellect s degrees of perfection On the Will in Nature Physiology and Pathology Quoted in Schopenhauer Arthur 1994 Philosophical Writings London Continuum p 233 ISBN 978 0 8264 0729 0 Quoted in Ryder Richard 2000 Animal Revolution Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism Oxford Berg Publishers p 57 ISBN 978 1 85973 330 1 in English all animals are of the neuter gender and so are represented by the pronoun it just as if they were inanimate things The effect of this artifice is quite revolting especially in the case of primates such as dogs monkeys and the like On the Basis of Morality 19 I recall having read of an Englishman who while hunting in India had shot a monkey he could not forget the look which the dying animal gave him and since then had never again fired at monkeys On the Basis of Morality 19 Sir William Harris describes how he shot his first elephant a female The next morning he went to look for the dead animal all the other elephants had fled from the neighborhood except a young one who had spent the night with its dead mother Forgetting all fear he came toward the sportsmen with the clearest and liveliest evidence of inconsolable grief and put his tiny trunk round them in order to appeal to them for help Harris says he was then filled with real remorse for what he had done and felt as if he had committed a murder On the basis of morality 19 His contempt for animals who as mere things for our use are declared by him to be without rights in conjunction with Pantheism is at the same time absurd and abominable The World as Will and Representation Vol 2 Chapter 50 Spinoza Ethics Pt IV Prop XXXVII Note I Still I do not deny that beasts feel what I deny is that we may not consult our own advantage and use them as we please treating them in a way which best suits us for their nature is not like ours This is the exact opposite of Schopenhauer s doctrine Also Ethics Appendix 26 whatsoever there be in nature beside man a regard for our advantage does not call on us to preserve but to preserve or destroy according to its various capacities and to adapt to our use as best we may Such are the matters which I engage to prove in Prop xviii of this Part whereby it is plain that the law against the slaughtering of animals is founded rather on vain superstition and womanish pity than on sound reason The rational quest of what is useful to us further teaches us the necessity of associating ourselves with our fellow men but not with beasts or things whose nature is different from our own we have the same rights in respect to them as they have in respect to us Nay as everyone s right is defined by his virtue or power men have far greater rights over beasts than beasts have over men Still I affirm that beasts feel But I also affirm that we may consult our own advantage and use them as we please treating them in the way which best suits us for their nature is not like ours and their emotions are naturally different from human emotions Ethics Part 4 Prop 37 Note 1 a b c d Clarke 1997 p 68 Christopher McCoy 3 4 Schopenhauer Arthur 1840 Part IV On the Basis of Morality Translated by Bullock Arthur Brodrick London Swan Sonnenschein published 1908 pp 269 271 via Internet Archive Dutt Purohit Bhagavan Western Indologists A Study in Motives Archived from the original on 2 August 2010 Retrieved 9 May 2009 Christopher McCoy 54 56 Abelson Peter April 1993 Schopenhauer and Buddhism Archived 28 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine Philosophy East and West Volume 43 Number 2 pp 255 278 University of Hawaii Press Retrieved on 12 April 2008 Janaway Christopher Self and World in Schopenhauer s Philosophy pp 28 ff David Burton Buddhism Knowledge and Liberation A Philosophical Study Ashgate Publishing Ltd 2004 p 22 John J Holder Early Buddhist Discourses Hackett Publishing Company 2006 p xx Schopenhauer is often said to be the first modern Western philosopher to attempt integration of his work with Eastern ways of thinking That he was the first is true but the claim that he was influenced by Indian thought needs qualification There is a remarkable correspondence in broad terms between some central Schopenhauerian doctrines and Buddhism notably in the views that empirical existence is suffering that suffering originates in desires and that salvation can be attained by the extinction of desires These three truths of the Buddha are mirrored closely in the essential structure of the doctrine of the will On this see Dorothea W Dauer Schopenhauer as Transmitter of Buddhist Ideas Note also the discussion by Bryan Magee The Philosophy of Schopenhauer pp 14 15 316 321 Janaway Christopher Self and World in Schopenhauer s Philosophy p 28 f The World as Will and Representation Vol 2 Ch 17 Artistic detachment in Japan and the West psychic distance in comparative aesthetics by S Odin 2001 University of Hawaii Press Parerga amp Paralipomena vol I p 106 trans E F J Payne World as Will and Representation vol I p 273 trans E F J Payne Christopher McCoy 3 App Urs Arthur Schopenhauer and China Sino Platonic Papers Nr 200 April 2010 PDF 8 7 Mb PDF 164 p Schopenhauer s early notes on Buddhism reproduced in Appendix This study provides an overview of the actual discovery of Buddhism by Schopenhauer Hutton Kenneth Compassion in Schopenhauer and Santideva Journal of Buddhist Ethics Vol 21 2014 a b Josephson Storm Jason 2017 The Myth of Disenchantment Magic Modernity and the Birth of the Human Sciences Chicago University of Chicago Press pp 187 188 ISBN 978 0 226 40336 6 Quote from Josephson Storm 2017 p 188 Josephson Storm 2017 pp 188 189 Anderson Mark 2009 Experimental Subversions of Modernity Pure Modernity Philosophy and the One Sophia Perennis ISBN 978 1 59731 094 9 Carnegy Patrick Wagner and the Art of the Theatre p 51 The World as Will and Representation Preface to the first edition p xiii a b Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy Note 5 a b Handschriftlicher Nachlass Vorlesungen und Abhandlungen Gutenberg Spiegel Abschnitt Handschriftlicher Nachlass 588 Es kann daher eine vollkommen wahre Philosophie geben die ganz von der Verneinung des Lebens abstrahirt diese ganz ignorirt Vie de Spinoza Wikisource fr wikisource org The World as Will and Representation 68 We might to a certain extent regard the well known French biography of Spinoza as a case in point if we used as a key to it that noble introduction to his very insufficient essay De Emendatione Intellects a passage which I can also recommend as the most effectual means I know of stilling the storm of the passions Arthur Schopenhauer World as Will and Representation Vol 1 Preface of the Second Edition Jerauld McGill Vivian 1931 Schopenhauer Pessimist and Pagan p 320 Parerga and Paralipomena Short Philosophical Essays Volume 2 trans Payne p 655 656 Schopenhauer Arthur The World as Will and Representation Vol 1 Criticism of the Kantian philosophy Translated by J Kemp With the proof of the thing in itself it has happened to Kant precisely as with that of the a priori nature of the law of causality Both doctrines are true but their proof is false They thus belong to the class of true conclusions from false premises Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 1 Appendix to Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real trans E J Payne Oxford 1974 p 21 Parerga and Paralipomena Vol 1 Appendix to Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real trans E J Payne Oxford 1974 p 23 Schopenhauer Arthur On the Freedom of the Will p 82 Parerga and Paralipomena Vol I Fragments for the History of Philosophy Sec 13 trans E J Payne Oxford 1974 p 96 Popper Karl 1946 The Open Society and Her Enemies Nature 157 3987 52 Bibcode 1946Natur 157 387R doi 10 1038 157387a0 S2CID 4074331 Bunge Mario 2020 Mario Bunge nos dijo Se puede ignorar la filosofia pero no evitarla Filosofia amp Co a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint uses authors parameter link The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics Preface to the First Edition trans Christopher Janaway Cambridge 2009 p 15 The Rise and Fall of Nietzschean Anti Semitism Chapter Princeton University Press Accessed 10 April 2023 Conway D Nietzsche s Revaluation of Schopenhauer as Educator Boston University Press Accessed 10 April 2023 a b Beiser Frederick C 2008 Weltschmerz Pessimism in German Philosophy 1860 1900 Oxford Oxford University Press pp 14 16 ISBN 978 0 19 876871 5 Arthur Schopenhauer was the most famous and influential philosopher in Germany from 1860 until the First World War Schopenhauer had a profound influence on two intellectual movements of the late 19th century that were utterly opposed to him neo Kantianism and positivism He forced these movements to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored and in doing so he changed them markedly Schopenhauer set the agenda for his age Beside Schopenhauer s Corpse Howard Don 1997 A Peek behind the Veil of Maya Einstein Schopenhauer and the Historical Background of the Conception of Space as a Ground for the Individuation of Physical Systems University of Pittsburgh Press Pauli greatly admired Schopenhauer Pauli wrote sympathetically about extrasensory perception noting approvingly that even such a thoroughly critical philosopher as Schopenhauer not only regarded parapsychological effects going far beyond what is secured by scientific evidence as possible but even considered them as a support for his philosophy Isaacson Walter 2007 Einstein His Life and Universe New York Simon amp Schuster p 367 ISBN 978 0 7432 6474 7 Howard 1997 p 87 Howard 1997 p 92 Halpern Paul 2015 Einstein s Dice and Schrodinger s Cat How Two Great Minds Battled Quantum Randomness to Create a Unified Theory of Physics p 189 ISBN 978 0 465 04065 0 Howard 1997 p 132 Raymond B Marcin Schopenhauers Metaphysics and Contemporary Quantum Theory David Lindorff referred to Schopenhauer as Pauli s favorite philosopher and Pauli himself often expressed his agreement with the main tenet of Schopenhauer s philosophy Suzanne Gieser cited a 1952 letter from Pauli to Carl Jung in which Pauli indicated that while he accepted Schopenhauer s main tenet that the thing in itself of all reality is will See e g Magee 2000 276 278 Nicholas Mathew Benjamin Walton The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini Historiography Analysis Criticism p 296 Tolstoy s letter to Afanasy Fet on 30 August 1869 Do you know what this summer has meant for me Constant raptures over Schopenhauer and a whole series of spiritual delights as I ve never experienced before I have brought all of his works and read him over and over Kant too by the way Assuredly no student has ever learned and discovered so much in one semester as I have during this summer I do not know if I shall ever change my opinion but at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men You say he is so so he has written a few things on philosophy What is so so It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection I have started to translate him Won t you help me Indeed I cannot understand how his name can be unknown The only explanation for this can only be the one he so often repeats that is that there is scarcely anyone but idiots in the world Thompson Caleb 2009 Quietism from the Side of Happiness Tolstoy Schopenhauer War and Peace Common Knowledge 15 3 395 411 doi 10 1215 0961754X 2009 020 Magee 1997 p 413 Caleb Flamm Matthew 2002 Santayana and Schopenhauer Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society 38 3 413 431 JSTOR 40320900 A thinker of whom it is well known that Santayana had an early deep admiration namely Schopenhauer Yothers Brian 2015 Sacred Uncertainty Religious Difference and The Shape of Melville s Career Evanston Illinois Northwestern University Press p 13 ISBN 978 0 8101 3071 5 Morrison Simon 2008 Sergey Prokofiev and His World Princeton University Press pp 19 20 ISBN 978 0 691 13895 4 Schopenhauer as Educator Glock Hans Johann 2017 A Companion to Wittgenstein Sussex UK Wiley Blackwell p 60 Glock Hans Johann 2000 The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer New York NY Cambridge University Press p 424 Malcolm Norman Ludwig Wittgenstein A Memoir Oxford University Press 1958 p 6 Russell Bertrand 1946 History of Western Philosophy Start of 2nd paragraph George Allen and Unwin LTD p 786 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location link Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of True Detective The Wall Street Journal 12 February 2014 M Morioka What Is Antinatalism and Other Essays pp 8 12 Eric Francis Jules Payne 17 February 1895 12 January 1983 Sources Edit Albright Daniel 2004 Modernism and Music An Anthology of Sources University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 01267 4 Beiser Frederick C Weltschmerz Pessimism in German Philosophy 1860 1900 Oxford Oxford University Press 2016 Cartwright David E 2010 Schopenhauer A Biography Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 82598 6 Clarke John James 1997 Oriental Enlightenment The Encounter Between Asian and Western Thought Abingdon Oxfordshire Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 13376 0 Hannan Barbara The Riddle of the World A Reconsideration of Schopenhauer s Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press 2009 Magee Bryan Confessions of a Philosopher Random House 1998 ISBN 978 0 375 50028 2 Chapters 20 21 Safranski Rudiger 1990 Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 79275 3 orig German Schopenhauer und Die wilden Jahre der Philosophie Carl Hanser Verlag 1987 Thomas Mann editor The Living Thoughts of Schopenhauer Longmans Green amp Co 1939Further reading EditBiographies Edit Frederick Copleston Arthur Schopenhauer philosopher of pessimism Burns Oates amp Washbourne 1946 O F Damm Arthur Schopenhauer eine Biographie Reclam 1912 Kuno Fischer Arthur Schopenhauer Heidelberg Winter 1893 revised as Schopenhauers Leben Werke und Lehre Heidelberg Winter 1898 Eduard Grisebach Schopenhauer Geschichte seines Lebens Berlin Hofmann 1876 D W Hamlyn Schopenhauer London Routledge amp Kegan Paul 1980 1985 Heinrich Hasse Schopenhauer Reinhardt 1926 Arthur Hubscher Arthur Schopenhauer Ein Lebensbild Leipzig Brockhaus 1938 Thomas Mann Schopenhauer Bermann Fischer 1938 Matthews Jack Schopenhauer s Will Das Testament Nine Point Publishing 2015 ISBN 978 0 9858278 8 5 A recent creative biography by philosophical novelist Jack Matthews Rudiger Safranski Schopenhauer und die wilden Jahre der Philosophie Eine Biographie hard cover Carl Hanser Verlag Munchen 1987 ISBN 978 3 446 14490 3 pocket edition Fischer ISBN 978 3 596 14299 6 Rudiger Safranski Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy trans Ewald Osers London Weidenfeld and Nicolson 1989 Walther Schneider Schopenhauer Eine Biographie Vienna Bermann Fischer 1937 William Wallace Life of Arthur Schopenhauer London Scott 1890 repr St Clair Shores Mich Scholarly Press 1970 Helen Zimmern Arthur Schopenhauer His Life and His Philosophy London Longmans Green amp Co 1876 Other books Edit App Urs Arthur Schopenhauer and China Sino Platonic Papers Nr 200 April 2010 PDF 8 7 Mb PDF 164 p Contains extensive appendixes with transcriptions and English translations of Schopenhauer s early notes about Buddhism and Indian philosophy Schopenhauers Kompass Die Geburt einer Philosophie UniversityMedia Rorschach Kyoto 2011 ISBN 978 3 906000 02 2 Atwell John Schopenhauer on the Character of the World The Metaphysics of Will Schopenhauer The Human Character Edwards Anthony An Evolutionary Epistemological Critique of Schopenhauer s Metaphysics 123 Books 2011 Copleston Frederick Schopenhauer Philosopher of Pessimism 1946 reprinted London Search Press 1975 Gardiner Patrick 1963 Schopenhauer Penguin Books Schopenhauer A Very Short introduction Janaway Christopher 2003 Self and World in Schopenhauer s Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 825003 6 Magee Bryan The Philosophy of Schopenhauer Oxford University Press 1988 reprint 1997 ISBN 978 0 19 823722 8 Neymeyr Barbara 1996 reprint 2011 Asthetische Autonomie als Abnormitat Kritische Analysen zu Schopenhauers Asthetik im Horizont seiner Willensmetaphysik Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie Band 42 Walter de Gruyter Berlin New York 1996 ISBN 3 11 015229 0 reprint 2011 De Gruyter Berlin Boston Mannion Gerard Schopenhauer Religion and Morality The Humble Path to Ethics Ashgate Press New Critical Thinking in Philosophy Series 2003 314pp Trottier Danick L influence de la philosophie schopenhauerienne dans la vie et l oeuvre de Richard Wagner et Qu est ce qui seduit obsede magnetise le philosophe dans l art des sons deux etudes en esthetique musicale Universite du Quebec a Montreal Departement de musique 2000 Zimmern Helen Arthur Schopenhauer his Life and Philosophy London Longman and Co 1876 Kastrup Bernardo Decoding Schopenhauer s Metaphysics The key to understanding how it solves the hard problem of consciousness and the paradoxes of quantum mechanics Winchester Washington iff Books 2020 de Botton Alain The Consolations of Philosophy Hamish Hamilton London 2000 ISBN 0 14 027661 0 Chapter Consolation for a Broken Heart Fiction Edit Poschenrieder Christoph Die Welt ist im Kopf Diogenes Zurich 2010 ISBN 978 3 257 06741 5 The novel accompanies Schopenhauer on a trip to Italy Yalom Irvin D The Schopenhauer Cure HarperCollins New York City 2005 ISBN 978 0 06 093810 9 The novel switches between the current events happening around a therapy group and the psychobiography of Arthur Schopenhauer Kortmann Christian Happy Hour Schopenhauer Roman einer Bibliotherapie Turia Kant Wien Berlin 2022 ISBN 978 3 98514 030 5 In the novel Schopenhauer lives in the 21st century and comments on current events in original quotations J T Frederick In Arthur s Nature Theorism Press 2020 ISBN 978 0 6451802 0 6 Schopenhauer faces punishment for alleged assault and battery Articles Edit Abelson Peter 1993 Schopenhauer and Buddhism Philosophy East and West 43 2 255 78 doi 10 2307 1399616 JSTOR 1399616 Archived from the original on 28 June 2011 Retrieved 25 October 2007 Jimenez Camilo 2006 Tagebuch eines Ehrgeizigen Arthur Schopenhauers Studienjahre in Berlin Avinus Magazin in German Luchte James 2009 The Body of Sublime Knowledge The Aesthetic Phenomenology of Arthur Schopenhauer Heythrop Journal Volume 50 Number 2 pp 228 242 Mazard Eisel 2005 Schopenhauer and the Empirical Critique of Idealism in the History of Ideas On Schopenhauer s debated place in the history of European philosophy and his relation to his predecessors Sangharakshita 2004 Schopenhauer and aesthetic appreciation Young Christopher Brook Andrew 1994 Schopenhauer and Freud International Journal of Psychoanalysis 75 101 18 PMID 8005756 Oxenford s Iconoclasm in German Philosophy See p 388 Thacker Eugene 2020 A Philosophy in Ruins An Unquiet Void Introduction to Arthur Schopenhauer On the Suffering of the World Repeater Books ISBN 978 1 913462 03 1External links EditArthur Schopenhauer at Wikipedia s sister projects Media from Commons Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Arthur Schopenhauer at Internet Archive Works by Arthur Schopenhauer at LibriVox public domain audiobooks Wicks Robert Spring 2019 Arthur Schopenhauer In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Center for the Study of Language and Information Arthur Schopenhauer an article by Mary Troxell in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2011 Schopenhauersource Reproductions of Schopenhauer s manuscripts Kant s philosophy as rectified by Schopenhauer Timeline of German Philosophers A Quick Introduction to Schopenhauer Ross Kelley L 1998 Arthur Schopenhauer 1788 1860 Two short essays on Schopenhauer s life and work and on his dim view of academia Portal Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Arthur Schopenhauer amp oldid 1150765837, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.