fbpx
Wikipedia

Mental representation

A mental representation (or cognitive representation), in philosophy of mind, cognitive psychology, neuroscience, and cognitive science, is a hypothetical internal cognitive symbol that represents external reality or its abstractions.[1][2]

Mental representation is the mental imagery of things that are not actually present to the senses.[3] In contemporary philosophy, specifically in fields of metaphysics such as philosophy of mind and ontology, a mental representation is one of the prevailing ways of explaining and describing the nature of ideas and concepts.

Mental representations (or mental imagery) enable representing things that have never been experienced as well as things that do not exist.[4] Our brains and mental imageries allow us to imagine things have either never happened or are impossible and do not exist. Although visual imagery is more likely to be recalled, mental imagery may involve representations in any of the sensory modalities, such as hearing, smell, or taste. Stephen Kosslyn proposes that images are used to help solve certain types of problems. We are able to visualize the objects in question and mentally represent the images to solve it.[4]

Mental representations also allow people to experience things right in front of them—however, the process of how the brain interprets and stores the representational content is debated.[5]

Representational theories of mind edit

Representationalism (also known as indirect realism) is the view that representations are the main way we access external reality.

The representational theory of mind attempts to explain the nature of ideas, concepts and other mental content in contemporary philosophy of mind, cognitive science and experimental psychology. In contrast to theories of naïve or direct realism, the representational theory of mind postulates the actual existence of mental representations which act as intermediaries between the observing subject and the objects, processes or other entities observed in the external world. These intermediaries stand for or represent to the mind the objects of that world.

The original or "classical" representational theory probably can be traced back to Thomas Hobbes and was a dominant theme in classical empiricism in general. According to this version of the theory, the mental representations were images (often called "ideas") of the objects or states of affairs represented. For modern adherents, such as Jerry Fodor and Steven Pinker, the representational system consists rather of an internal language of thought (i.e., mentalese). The contents of thoughts are represented in symbolic structures (the formulas of mentalese) which, analogously to natural languages but on a much more abstract level, possess a syntax and semantics very much like those of natural languages. For the Portuguese logician and cognitive scientist Luis M. Augusto, at this abstract, formal level, the syntax of thought is the set of symbol rules (i.e., operations, processes, etc. on and with symbol structures) and the semantics of thought is the set of symbol structures (concepts and propositions). Content (i.e., thought) emerges from the meaningful co-occurrence of both sets of symbols. For instance, "8 x 9" is a meaningful co-occurrence, whereas "CAT x §" is not; "x" is a symbol rule called for by symbol structures such as "8" and "9", but not by "CAT" and "§".[6]

Canadian philosopher P. Thagard noted in his work "Introduction to Cognitive Science", that "most cognitive scientists agree that knowledge in the human mind consists of mental representations" and that "cognitive science asserts: that people have mental procedures that operate by means of mental representations for the implementation of thinking and action"[7]

Strong vs weak, restricted vs unrestricted edit

There are two types of representationalism, strong and weak. Strong representationalism attempts to reduce phenomenal character to intentional content. On the other hand, weak representationalism claims only that phenomenal character supervenes on intentional content. Strong representationalism aims to provide a theory about the nature of phenomenal character, and offers a solution to the hard problem of consciousness. In contrast to this, weak representationalism does not aim to provide a theory of consciousness, nor does it offer a solution to the hard problem of consciousness.

Strong representationalism can be further broken down into restricted and unrestricted versions. The restricted version deals only with certain kinds of phenomenal states e.g. visual perception. Most representationalists endorse an unrestricted version of representationalism. According to the unrestricted version, for any state with phenomenal character that state's phenomenal character reduces to its intentional content. Only this unrestricted version of representationalism is able to provide a general theory about the nature of phenomenal character, as well as offer a potential solution to the hard problem of consciousness. The successful reduction of the phenomenal character of a state to its intentional content would provide a solution to the hard problem of consciousness once a physicalist account of intentionality is worked out.

Problems for the unrestricted version edit

When arguing against the unrestricted version of representationalism people will often bring up phenomenal mental states that appear to lack intentional content. The unrestricted version seeks to account for all phenomenal states. Thus, for it to be true, all states with phenomenal character must have intentional content to which that character is reduced. Phenomenal states without intentional content therefore serve as a counterexample to the unrestricted version. If the state has no intentional content its phenomenal character will not be reducible to that state's intentional content, for it has none to begin with.

A common example of this kind of state are moods. Moods are states with phenomenal character that are generally thought to not be directed at anything in particular. Moods are thought to lack directedness, unlike emotions, which are typically thought to be directed at particular things. People conclude that because moods are undirected they are also nonintentional i.e. they lack intentionality or aboutness. Because they are not directed at anything they are not about anything. Because they lack intentionality they will lack any intentional content. Lacking intentional content their phenomenal character will not be reducible to intentional content, refuting the representational doctrine.

Though emotions are typically considered as having directedness and intentionality this idea has also been called into question. One might point to emotions a person all of a sudden experiences that do not appear to be directed at or about anything in particular. Emotions elicited by listening to music are another potential example of undirected, nonintentional emotions. Emotions aroused in this way do not seem to necessarily be about anything, including the music that arouses them.[8]

Responses edit

In response to this objection, a proponent of representationalism might reject the undirected non-intentionality of moods, and attempt to identify some intentional content they might plausibly be thought to possess. The proponent of representationalism might also reject the narrow conception of intentionality as being directed at a particular thing, arguing instead for a broader kind of intentionality.

There are three alternative kinds of directedness/intentionality one might posit for moods.[8]

  • Outward directedness: What it is like to be in mood M is to have a certain kind of outwardly focused representational content.
  • Inward directedness: What it is like to be in mood M is to have a certain kind of inwardly focused representational content.
  • Hybrid directedness: What it is like to be in mood M is to have both a certain kind of outwardly focused representational content and a certain kind of inwardly focused representational content.

In the case of outward directedness, moods might be directed at either the world as a whole, a changing series of objects in the world, or unbound emotion properties projected by people onto things in the world. In the case of inward directedness, moods are directed at the overall state of a person's body. In the case of hybrid, directedness moods are directed at some combination of inward and outward things.

Further objections edit

Even if one can identify some possible intentional content for moods we might still question whether that content is able to sufficiently capture the phenomenal character of the mood states they are a part of. Amy Kind contends that in the case of all the previously mentioned kinds of directedness (outward, inward, and hybrid) the intentional content supplied to the mood state is not capable of sufficiently capturing the phenomenal aspects of the mood states.[8] In the case of inward directedness, the phenomenology of the mood does not seem tied to the state of one's body, and even if one's mood is reflected by the overall state of one's body that person will not necessarily be aware of it, demonstrating the insufficiency of the intentional content to adequately capture the phenomenal aspects of the mood. In the case of outward directedness, the phenomenology of the mood and its intentional content does not seem to share the corresponding relation they should given that the phenomenal character is supposed to reduce to the intentional content. Hybrid directedness, if it can even get off the ground, faces the same objection.

Philosophers edit

There is a wide debate on what kinds of representations exist. There are several philosophers who bring about different aspects of the debate. Such philosophers include Alex Morgan, Gualtiero Piccinini, and Uriah Kriegel.

Alex Morgan edit

There are "job description" representations.[1] That is representations that represent something—have intentionality, have a special relation—the represented object does not need to exist, and content plays a causal role in what gets represented:.

Structural representations are also important.[1] These types of representations are basically mental maps that we have in our minds that correspond exactly to those objects in the world (the intentional content). According to Morgan, structural representations are not the same as mental representations—there is nothing mental about them: plants can have structural representations.

There are also internal representations.[1] These types of representations include those that involve future decisions, episodic memories, or any type of projection into the future.

Gualtiero Piccinini edit

In Gualtiero Piccinini's forthcoming work, he discusses topics on natural and nonnatural mental representations. He relies on the natural definition of mental representations given by Grice (1957)[9] where P entails that P. e.g. Those spots mean measles, entails that the patient has measles. Then there are nonnatural representations: P does not entail P. e.g. The 3 rings on the bell of a bus mean the bus is full—the rings on the bell are independent of the fullness of the bus—we could have assigned something else (just as arbitrary) to signify that the bus is full.

Uriah Kriegel edit

There are also objective and subjective mental representations.[10] Objective representations are closest to tracking theories—where the brain simply tracks what is in the environment. Subjective representations can vary person-to-person. The relationship between these two types of representation can vary.

  1. Objective varies, but the subjective does not: e.g. brain-in-a-vat
  2. Subjective varies, but the objective does not: e.g. color-inverted world
  3. All representations found in objective and none in the subjective: e.g. thermometer
  4. All representations found in subjective and none in the objective: e.g. an agent that experiences in a void.

Eliminativists think that subjective representations do not exist. Reductivists think subjective representations are reducible to objective. Non-reductivists think that subjective representations are real and distinct.[10]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d Morgan, Alex (2014). "Representations Gone Mental" (PDF). Synthese. 191 (2): 213–44. doi:10.1007/s11229-013-0328-7. S2CID 18194442.
  2. ^ Marr, David (2010). Vision. A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262514620.
  3. ^ Mckellar, Peter (1957). Imagination and thinking: A psychological analysis. Oxford, England.
  4. ^ a b Robert J. Sternberg (2009). Cognitive Psychology. Cengage Learning. ISBN 9780495506294.
  5. ^ Pearson, Joel; Kosslyn, Stephen M. (2015-08-18). "The heterogeneity of mental representation: Ending the imagery debate". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 112 (33): 10089–10092. doi:10.1073/pnas.1504933112. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 4547292. PMID 26175024.
  6. ^ Augusto, Luis M. (2014). "Unconscious representations 2: Towards an integrated cognitive architecture". Axiomathes. 24: 19–43. doi:10.1007/s10516-012-9207-y. S2CID 122896502.
  7. ^ Thagard, P. (1996). Mind. Introduction to Cognitive Science.
  8. ^ a b c Kind, Amy (2014). Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. New York: Routledge. p. 118.
  9. ^ Grice, H.P. (1957). "Meaning". Philosophical Review. 66 (3): 377–388. doi:10.2307/2182440. JSTOR 2182440.
  10. ^ a b Kriegel, Uriah (2014). Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. Routledge. pp. 161–79.

Further reading edit

  • Augusto, Luis M. (2013). 'Unconscious Representations 1: Belying the Traditional Model of Human Cognition.' Axiomathes 23.4, 645–663.
  • Goldman, Alvin I (2014). '.' Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. ed. Uriah Kriegel. New York, NY: Routledge, 91-108.
  • Henrich, J. & Boyd, R. (2002). Culture and cognition: Why cultural evolution does not require replication of representations. Culture and Cognition, 2, 87–112. Full text
  • Kind, Amy (2014). '.' Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. ed. Uriah Kriegel. New York, NY: Routledge, 113–34.
  • Kriegel, Uriah (2014). '.' Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. ed. Uriah Kriegel. New York, NY: Routledge, 161–79.
  • Rupert, Robert D.(2014). '.' Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. ed. Uriah Kriegel. New York, NY: Routledge, 180–95.
  • Shapiro, Lawrence (2014). 'When Is Cognition Embodied.' Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. ed. Uriah Kriegel. New York, NY: Routledge, 73–90.

External links edit

mental, representation, mental, representation, cognitive, representation, philosophy, mind, cognitive, psychology, neuroscience, cognitive, science, hypothetical, internal, cognitive, symbol, that, represents, external, reality, abstractions, mental, imagery,. A mental representation or cognitive representation in philosophy of mind cognitive psychology neuroscience and cognitive science is a hypothetical internal cognitive symbol that represents external reality or its abstractions 1 2 Mental representation is the mental imagery of things that are not actually present to the senses 3 In contemporary philosophy specifically in fields of metaphysics such as philosophy of mind and ontology a mental representation is one of the prevailing ways of explaining and describing the nature of ideas and concepts Mental representations or mental imagery enable representing things that have never been experienced as well as things that do not exist 4 Our brains and mental imageries allow us to imagine things have either never happened or are impossible and do not exist Although visual imagery is more likely to be recalled mental imagery may involve representations in any of the sensory modalities such as hearing smell or taste Stephen Kosslyn proposes that images are used to help solve certain types of problems We are able to visualize the objects in question and mentally represent the images to solve it 4 Mental representations also allow people to experience things right in front of them however the process of how the brain interprets and stores the representational content is debated 5 Contents 1 Representational theories of mind 1 1 Strong vs weak restricted vs unrestricted 1 2 Problems for the unrestricted version 1 3 Responses 1 4 Further objections 2 Philosophers 2 1 Alex Morgan 2 2 Gualtiero Piccinini 2 3 Uriah Kriegel 3 See also 4 References 5 Further reading 6 External linksRepresentational theories of mind editRepresentationalism also known as indirect realism is the view that representations are the main way we access external reality The representational theory of mind attempts to explain the nature of ideas concepts and other mental content in contemporary philosophy of mind cognitive science and experimental psychology In contrast to theories of naive or direct realism the representational theory of mind postulates the actual existence of mental representations which act as intermediaries between the observing subject and the objects processes or other entities observed in the external world These intermediaries stand for or represent to the mind the objects of that world The original or classical representational theory probably can be traced back to Thomas Hobbes and was a dominant theme in classical empiricism in general According to this version of the theory the mental representations were images often called ideas of the objects or states of affairs represented For modern adherents such as Jerry Fodor and Steven Pinker the representational system consists rather of an internal language of thought i e mentalese The contents of thoughts are represented in symbolic structures the formulas of mentalese which analogously to natural languages but on a much more abstract level possess a syntax and semantics very much like those of natural languages For the Portuguese logician and cognitive scientist Luis M Augusto at this abstract formal level the syntax of thought is the set of symbol rules i e operations processes etc on and with symbol structures and the semantics of thought is the set of symbol structures concepts and propositions Content i e thought emerges from the meaningful co occurrence of both sets of symbols For instance 8 x 9 is a meaningful co occurrence whereas CAT x is not x is a symbol rule called for by symbol structures such as 8 and 9 but not by CAT and 6 Canadian philosopher P Thagard noted in his work Introduction to Cognitive Science that most cognitive scientists agree that knowledge in the human mind consists of mental representations and that cognitive science asserts that people have mental procedures that operate by means of mental representations for the implementation of thinking and action 7 Strong vs weak restricted vs unrestricted edit There are two types of representationalism strong and weak Strong representationalism attempts to reduce phenomenal character to intentional content On the other hand weak representationalism claims only that phenomenal character supervenes on intentional content Strong representationalism aims to provide a theory about the nature of phenomenal character and offers a solution to the hard problem of consciousness In contrast to this weak representationalism does not aim to provide a theory of consciousness nor does it offer a solution to the hard problem of consciousness Strong representationalism can be further broken down into restricted and unrestricted versions The restricted version deals only with certain kinds of phenomenal states e g visual perception Most representationalists endorse an unrestricted version of representationalism According to the unrestricted version for any state with phenomenal character that state s phenomenal character reduces to its intentional content Only this unrestricted version of representationalism is able to provide a general theory about the nature of phenomenal character as well as offer a potential solution to the hard problem of consciousness The successful reduction of the phenomenal character of a state to its intentional content would provide a solution to the hard problem of consciousness once a physicalist account of intentionality is worked out Problems for the unrestricted version edit When arguing against the unrestricted version of representationalism people will often bring up phenomenal mental states that appear to lack intentional content The unrestricted version seeks to account for all phenomenal states Thus for it to be true all states with phenomenal character must have intentional content to which that character is reduced Phenomenal states without intentional content therefore serve as a counterexample to the unrestricted version If the state has no intentional content its phenomenal character will not be reducible to that state s intentional content for it has none to begin with A common example of this kind of state are moods Moods are states with phenomenal character that are generally thought to not be directed at anything in particular Moods are thought to lack directedness unlike emotions which are typically thought to be directed at particular things People conclude that because moods are undirected they are also nonintentional i e they lack intentionality or aboutness Because they are not directed at anything they are not about anything Because they lack intentionality they will lack any intentional content Lacking intentional content their phenomenal character will not be reducible to intentional content refuting the representational doctrine Though emotions are typically considered as having directedness and intentionality this idea has also been called into question One might point to emotions a person all of a sudden experiences that do not appear to be directed at or about anything in particular Emotions elicited by listening to music are another potential example of undirected nonintentional emotions Emotions aroused in this way do not seem to necessarily be about anything including the music that arouses them 8 Responses edit In response to this objection a proponent of representationalism might reject the undirected non intentionality of moods and attempt to identify some intentional content they might plausibly be thought to possess The proponent of representationalism might also reject the narrow conception of intentionality as being directed at a particular thing arguing instead for a broader kind of intentionality There are three alternative kinds of directedness intentionality one might posit for moods 8 Outward directedness What it is like to be in mood M is to have a certain kind of outwardly focused representational content Inward directedness What it is like to be in mood M is to have a certain kind of inwardly focused representational content Hybrid directedness What it is like to be in mood M is to have both a certain kind of outwardly focused representational content and a certain kind of inwardly focused representational content In the case of outward directedness moods might be directed at either the world as a whole a changing series of objects in the world or unbound emotion properties projected by people onto things in the world In the case of inward directedness moods are directed at the overall state of a person s body In the case of hybrid directedness moods are directed at some combination of inward and outward things Further objections edit Even if one can identify some possible intentional content for moods we might still question whether that content is able to sufficiently capture the phenomenal character of the mood states they are a part of Amy Kind contends that in the case of all the previously mentioned kinds of directedness outward inward and hybrid the intentional content supplied to the mood state is not capable of sufficiently capturing the phenomenal aspects of the mood states 8 In the case of inward directedness the phenomenology of the mood does not seem tied to the state of one s body and even if one s mood is reflected by the overall state of one s body that person will not necessarily be aware of it demonstrating the insufficiency of the intentional content to adequately capture the phenomenal aspects of the mood In the case of outward directedness the phenomenology of the mood and its intentional content does not seem to share the corresponding relation they should given that the phenomenal character is supposed to reduce to the intentional content Hybrid directedness if it can even get off the ground faces the same objection Philosophers editThere is a wide debate on what kinds of representations exist There are several philosophers who bring about different aspects of the debate Such philosophers include Alex Morgan Gualtiero Piccinini and Uriah Kriegel Alex Morgan edit There are job description representations 1 That is representations that represent something have intentionality have a special relation the represented object does not need to exist and content plays a causal role in what gets represented Structural representations are also important 1 These types of representations are basically mental maps that we have in our minds that correspond exactly to those objects in the world the intentional content According to Morgan structural representations are not the same as mental representations there is nothing mental about them plants can have structural representations There are also internal representations 1 These types of representations include those that involve future decisions episodic memories or any type of projection into the future Gualtiero Piccinini edit In Gualtiero Piccinini s forthcoming work he discusses topics on natural and nonnatural mental representations He relies on the natural definition of mental representations given by Grice 1957 9 where P entails that P e g Those spots mean measles entails that the patient has measles Then there are nonnatural representations P does not entail P e g The 3 rings on the bell of a bus mean the bus is full the rings on the bell are independent of the fullness of the bus we could have assigned something else just as arbitrary to signify that the bus is full Uriah Kriegel edit There are also objective and subjective mental representations 10 Objective representations are closest to tracking theories where the brain simply tracks what is in the environment Subjective representations can vary person to person The relationship between these two types of representation can vary Objective varies but the subjective does not e g brain in a vat Subjective varies but the objective does not e g color inverted world All representations found in objective and none in the subjective e g thermometer All representations found in subjective and none in the objective e g an agent that experiences in a void Eliminativists think that subjective representations do not exist Reductivists think subjective representations are reducible to objective Non reductivists think that subjective representations are real and distinct 10 See also editBasic beliefs Cognitive model Dynamical systems Conceptual space Condensation psychology Knowledge representation Mental model Mindset Object of the mind Paradigm Perception Representative realism Schema psychology Set psychology Social constructionism Visual space WorldviewReferences edit a b c d Morgan Alex 2014 Representations Gone Mental PDF Synthese 191 2 213 44 doi 10 1007 s11229 013 0328 7 S2CID 18194442 Marr David 2010 Vision A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information The MIT Press ISBN 978 0262514620 Mckellar Peter 1957 Imagination and thinking A psychological analysis Oxford England a b Robert J Sternberg 2009 Cognitive Psychology Cengage Learning ISBN 9780495506294 Pearson Joel Kosslyn Stephen M 2015 08 18 The heterogeneity of mental representation Ending the imagery debate Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 112 33 10089 10092 doi 10 1073 pnas 1504933112 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 4547292 PMID 26175024 Augusto Luis M 2014 Unconscious representations 2 Towards an integrated cognitive architecture Axiomathes 24 19 43 doi 10 1007 s10516 012 9207 y S2CID 122896502 Thagard P 1996 Mind Introduction to Cognitive Science a b c Kind Amy 2014 Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind New York Routledge p 118 Grice H P 1957 Meaning Philosophical Review 66 3 377 388 doi 10 2307 2182440 JSTOR 2182440 a b Kriegel Uriah 2014 Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind Routledge pp 161 79 Further reading editAugusto Luis M 2013 Unconscious Representations 1 Belying the Traditional Model of Human Cognition Axiomathes 23 4 645 663 Preprint Goldman Alvin I 2014 The Bodily Formats Approach to Embodied Cognition Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind ed Uriah Kriegel New York NY Routledge 91 108 Henrich J amp Boyd R 2002 Culture and cognition Why cultural evolution does not require replication of representations Culture and Cognition 2 87 112 Full text Kind Amy 2014 The Case against Representationalism about Moods Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind ed Uriah Kriegel New York NY Routledge 113 34 Kriegel Uriah 2014 Two Notions of Mental Representation Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind ed Uriah Kriegel New York NY Routledge 161 79 Rupert Robert D 2014 The Sufficiency of Objective Representation Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind ed Uriah Kriegel New York NY Routledge 180 95 Shapiro Lawrence 2014 When Is Cognition Embodied Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind ed Uriah Kriegel New York NY Routledge 73 90 External links editMental Representation Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Mental representation amp oldid 1214317200, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.