fbpx
Wikipedia

George Berkeley

George Berkeley (/ˈbɑːrkli/;[5][6] 12 March 1685 – 14 January 1753) – known as Bishop Berkeley (Bishop of Cloyne of the Anglican Church of Ireland) – was an Anglo-Irish philosopher whose primary achievement was the advancement of a theory he called "immaterialism" (later referred to as "subjective idealism" by others). This theory denies the existence of material substance and instead contends that familiar objects like tables and chairs are ideas perceived by the mind and, as a result, cannot exist without being perceived. Berkeley is also known for his critique of abstraction, an important premise in his argument for immaterialism.[7]


George Berkeley
Bishop of Cloyne
Portrait of Berkeley by John Smybert, 1727
ChurchChurch of Ireland
DioceseCloyne
In office1734–1753
PredecessorEdward Synge
SuccessorJames Stopford
Orders
Ordination1709 (deacon)
1710 (priest)
Consecration18 January 1734
Personal details
Born(1685-03-12)12 March 1685
Died14 January 1753(1753-01-14) (aged 67)
Oxford, England
DenominationAnglican
SpouseAnne Forster
Children6
Education
Philosophy career
EducationTrinity College Dublin
(B.A., 1704; M.A. 1707)
Era18th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolSubjective idealism (phenomenalism)
Empiricism
Foundationalism[1]
Conceptualism[2]
Indirect realism[3]
InstitutionsTrinity College Dublin[4]
Main interests
Christianity, metaphysics, epistemology, language, mathematics, perception
Notable ideas
Subjective idealism (esse est percipi), master argument, passive obedience
Signature

In 1709, Berkeley published his first major work, An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision, in which he discussed the limitations of human vision and advanced the theory that the proper objects of sight are not material objects, but light and colour.[8] This foreshadowed his chief philosophical work, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, in 1710, which, after its poor reception, he rewrote in dialogue form and published under the title Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous in 1713.[9] In this book, Berkeley's views were represented by Philonous (Greek: "lover of mind"), while Hylas ("hyle", Greek: "matter") embodies the Irish thinker's opponents, in particular John Locke.

Berkeley argued against Isaac Newton's doctrine of absolute space, time and motion in De Motu[10] (On Motion), published 1721. His arguments were a precursor to the views of Ernst Mach and Albert Einstein.[11][12] In 1732, he published Alciphron, a Christian apologetic against the free-thinkers, and in 1734, he published The Analyst, a critique of the foundations of calculus, which was influential in the development of mathematics.[13]

Interest in Berkeley's work increased after World War II because he tackled many of the issues of paramount interest to philosophy in the 20th century, such as the problems of perception, the difference between primary and secondary qualities, and the importance of language.[14]

Biography

Ireland

Berkeley was born at his family home, Dysart Castle, near Thomastown, County Kilkenny, Ireland, the eldest son of William Berkeley, a cadet of the noble family of Berkeley whose ancestry can be traced back to the Anglo-Saxon period and who had served as feudal lords and landowners in Gloucester, England. Little is known of his mother. He was educated at Kilkenny College and attended Trinity College Dublin, where he was elected a Scholar in 1702, being awarded BA in 1704 and MA and a Fellowship in 1707. He remained at Trinity College after completion of his degree as a tutor and Greek lecturer.

His earliest publication was on mathematics, but the first that brought him notice was his An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision, first published in 1709. In the essay, Berkeley examines visual distance, magnitude, position and problems of sight and touch. While this work raised much controversy at the time, its conclusions are now accepted as an established part of the theory of optics.

The next publication to appear was the Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge in 1710, which had great success and gave him a lasting reputation, though few accepted his theory that nothing exists outside the mind. This was followed in 1713 by Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, in which he propounded his system of philosophy, the leading principle of which is that the world, as represented by our senses, depends for its existence on being perceived.

For this theory, the Principles gives the exposition and the Dialogues the defence. One of his main objectives was to combat the prevailing materialism of his time. The theory was largely received with ridicule, while even those such as Samuel Clarke and William Whiston, who did acknowledge his "extraordinary genius," were nevertheless convinced that his first principles were false.

England and Europe

Shortly afterwards, Berkeley visited England and was received into the circle of Addison, Pope and Steele. In the period between 1714 and 1720, he interspersed his academic endeavours with periods of extensive travel in Europe, including one of the most extensive Grand Tours of the length and breadth of Italy ever undertaken.[15] In 1721, he took Holy Orders in the Church of Ireland, earning his doctorate in divinity, and once again chose to remain at Trinity College Dublin, lecturing this time in Divinity and in Hebrew. In 1721/2 he was made Dean of Dromore and, in 1724, Dean of Derry.

In 1723, following her violent quarrel with Jonathan Swift, who had been her intimate friend for many years, Esther Vanhomrigh (for whom Swift had created the nickname "Vanessa") named Berkeley her co-heir along with the barrister Robert Marshall; her choice of legatees caused a good deal of surprise since she did not know either of them well, although Berkeley as a very young man had known her father. Swift said generously that he did not grudge Berkeley his inheritance, much of which vanished in a lawsuit in any event. A story that Berkeley and Marshall disregarded a condition of the inheritance that they must publish the correspondence between Swift and Vanessa is probably untrue.

In 1725, he began the project of founding a college in Bermuda for training ministers and missionaries in the colony, in pursuit of which he gave up his deanery with its income of £1100.

Marriage and America

 
A group portrait of Berkeley and his entourage by John Smibert
 

In 1728, he married Anne Forster, daughter of John Forster, Chief Justice of the Irish Common Pleas, and his first wife Rebecca Monck. He then went to America on a salary of £100 per annum. He landed near Newport, Rhode Island, where he bought a plantation at Middletown – the famous "Whitehall". Berkeley purchased several enslaved Africans to work on the plantation.[16][17] It has been claimed that "he introduced Palladianism into America by borrowing a design from [William] Kent's Designs of Inigo Jones for the door-case of his house in Rhode Island, Whitehall."[18] He also brought to New England John Smibert, the Scottish artist he "discovered" in Italy, who is generally regarded as the founding father of American portrait painting.[19] Meanwhile, he drew up plans for the ideal city he planned to build on Bermuda.[20] He lived at the plantation while he waited for funds for his college to arrive. The funds, however, were not forthcoming. "With the withdrawal from London of his own persuasive energies, opposition gathered force; and the Prime Minister, Walpole grew steadily more sceptical and lukewarm. At last it became clear that the essential Parliamentary grant would be not forthcoming"[21] and in 1732 he left America and returned to London.

He and Anne had four children who survived infancy: Henry, George, William and Julia, and at least two other children who died in infancy. William's death in 1751 was a great cause of grief to his father.

Episcopate in Ireland

Berkeley was nominated to be the Bishop of Cloyne in the Church of Ireland on 18 January 1734. He was consecrated as such on 19 May 1734. He was the Bishop of Cloyne until his death on 14 January 1753, although he died at Oxford (see below).

Humanitarian work

While living in London's Saville Street, he took part in efforts to create a home for the city's abandoned children. The Foundling Hospital was founded by royal charter in 1739, and Berkeley is listed as one of its original governors.

Last works

His last two publications were Siris: A Chain of Philosophical Reflexions and Inquiries Concerning the Virtues of Tarwater, And divers other Subjects connected together and arising one from another (1744) and Further Thoughts on Tar-water (1752). Pine tar is an effective antiseptic and disinfectant when applied to cuts on the skin, but Berkeley argued for the use of pine tar as a broad panacea for diseases. His 1744 work on tar-water sold more copies than any of his other books during Berkeley's lifetime.[22]

He remained at Cloyne until 1752, when he retired. With his wife and daughter Julia, he went to Oxford to live with his son George and supervise his education.[23] He died soon afterwards and was buried in Christ Church Cathedral, Oxford. His affectionate disposition and genial manners made him much loved and held in warm regard by many of his contemporaries. Anne outlived her husband by many years, and died in 1786.[24]

Contributions to philosophy

According to Berkeley there are only two kinds of things: spirits and ideas. Spirits are simple, active beings which produce and perceive ideas; ideas are passive beings which are produced and perceived.[25]

The use of the concepts of "spirit" and "idea" is central in Berkeley's philosophy. As used by him, these concepts are difficult to translate into modern terminology. His concept of "spirit" is close to the concept of "conscious subject" or of "mind", and the concept of "idea" is close to the concept of "sensation" or "state of mind" or "conscious experience".

Thus Berkeley denied the existence of matter as a metaphysical substance, but did not deny the existence of physical objects such as apples or mountains ("I do not argue against the existence of any one thing that we can apprehend, either by sense or reflection. That the things I see with mine eyes and touch with my hands do exist, really exist, I make not the least question. The only thing whose existence we deny, is that which philosophers call matter or corporeal substance. And in doing of this, there is no damage done to the rest of mankind, who, I dare say, will never miss it.", Principles #35). This basic claim of Berkeley's thought, his "idealism", is sometimes and somewhat derisively called "immaterialism" or, occasionally, subjective idealism. In Principles #3, he wrote, using a combination of Latin and English, esse is percipi (to be is to be perceived), most often if slightly inaccurately attributed to Berkeley as the pure Latin phrase esse est percipi.[26] The phrase appears associated with him in authoritative philosophical sources, e.g., "Berkeley holds that there are no such mind-independent things, that, in the famous phrase, esse est percipi (aut percipere)—to be is to be perceived (or to perceive)."[22]

Hence, human knowledge is reduced to two elements: that of spirits and of ideas (Principles #86). In contrast to ideas, a spirit cannot be perceived. A person's spirit, which perceives ideas, is to be comprehended intuitively by inward feeling or reflection (Principles #89). For Berkeley, we have no direct 'idea' of spirits, albeit we have good reason to believe in the existence of other spirits, for their existence explains the purposeful regularities we find in experience[27] ("It is plain that we cannot know the existence of other spirits otherwise than by their operations, or the ideas by them excited in us", Dialogues #145). This is the solution that Berkeley offers to the problem of other minds. Finally, the order and purposefulness of the whole of our experience of the world and especially of nature overwhelms us into believing in the existence of an extremely powerful and intelligent spirit that causes that order. According to Berkeley, reflection on the attributes of that external spirit leads us to identify it with God. Thus a material thing such as an apple consists of a collection of ideas (shape, color, taste, physical properties, etc.) which are caused in the spirits of humans by the spirit of God.

Theology

A convinced adherent of Christianity, Berkeley believed God to be present as an immediate cause of all our experiences.

He did not evade the question of the external source of the diversity of the sense data at the disposal of the human individual. He strove simply to show that the causes of sensations could not be things, because what we called things, and considered without grounds to be something different from our sensations, were built up wholly from sensations. There must consequently be some other external source of the inexhaustible diversity of sensations. The source of our sensations, Berkeley concluded, could only be God; He gave them to man, who had to see in them signs and symbols that carried God's word.[28]

Here is Berkeley's proof of the existence of God:

Whatever power I may have over my own thoughts, I find the ideas actually perceived by Sense have not a like dependence on my will. When in broad daylight I open my eyes, it is not in my power to choose whether I shall see or no, or to determine what particular objects shall present themselves to my view; and so likewise as to the hearing and other senses; the ideas imprinted on them are not creatures of my will. There is therefore some other Will or Spirit that produces them. (Berkeley. Principles #29)

As T. I. Oizerman explained:

Berkeley's mystic idealism (as Kant aptly christened it) claimed that nothing separated man and God (except materialist misconceptions, of course), since nature or matter did not exist as a reality independent of consciousness. The revelation of God was directly accessible to man, according to this doctrine; it was the sense-perceived world, the world of man's sensations, which came to him from on high for him to decipher and so grasp the divine purpose.[28]

Berkeley believed that God is not the distant engineer of Newtonian machinery that in the fullness of time led to the growth of a tree in the university quadrangle. Rather, the perception of the tree is an idea that God's mind has produced in the mind, and the tree continues to exist in the quadrangle when "nobody" is there, simply because God is an infinite mind that perceives all.

The philosophy of David Hume concerning causality and objectivity is an elaboration of another aspect of Berkeley's philosophy. A.A. Luce, the most eminent Berkeley scholar of the 20th century, constantly stressed the continuity of Berkeley's philosophy. The fact that Berkeley returned to his major works throughout his life, issuing revised editions with only minor changes, also counts against any theory that attributes to him a significant volte-face.[29]

Relativity arguments

John Locke (Berkeley's intellectual predecessor) states that we define an object by its primary and secondary qualities. He takes heat as an example of a secondary quality. If you put one hand in a bucket of cold water, and the other hand in a bucket of warm water, then put both hands in a bucket of lukewarm water, one of your hands is going to tell you that the water is cold and the other that the water is hot. Locke says that since two different objects (both your hands) perceive the water to be hot and cold, then the heat is not a quality of the water.

While Locke used this argument to distinguish primary from secondary qualities, Berkeley extends it to cover primary qualities in the same way. For example, he says that size is not a quality of an object because the size of the object depends on the distance between the observer and the object, or the size of the observer. Since an object is a different size to different observers, then size is not a quality of the object. Berkeley rejects shape with a similar argument and then asks: if neither primary qualities nor secondary qualities are of the object, then how can we say that there is anything more than the qualities we observe?[clarification needed]

Relativity is the idea that there is no objective, universal truth; it is a state of dependence in which the existence of one independent object is solely dependent on that of another. According to Locke, characteristics of primary qualities are mind-independent, such as shape, size, etc., whereas secondary qualities are mind-dependent, for example, taste and colour. George Berkeley refuted John Locke's belief on primary and secondary qualities because Berkeley believed that "we cannot abstract the primary qualities (e.g shape) from secondary ones (e.g colour)".[30] Berkeley argued that perception is dependent on the distance between the observer and the object, and "thus, we cannot conceive of mechanist material bodies which are extended but not (in themselves) colored".[30] What perceived can be the same type of quality, but completely opposite from each other because of different positions and perceptions, what we perceive can be different even when the same types of things consist of contrary qualities. Secondary qualities aid in people's conception of primary qualities in an object, like how the colour of an object leads people to recognize the object itself. More specifically, the colour red can be perceived in apples, strawberries, and tomatoes, yet we would not know what these might look like without its colour. We would also be unaware of what the colour red looked like if red paint, or any object that has a perceived red colour, failed to exist. From this, we can see that colours cannot exist on their own and can solely represent a group of perceived objects. Therefore, both primary and secondary qualities are mind-dependent: they cannot exist without our minds.

George Berkeley was a philosopher who was against rationalism and "classical" empiricism. He was a "subjective idealist" or "empirical idealist", who believed that reality is constructed entirely of immaterial, conscious minds and their ideas; everything that exists is somehow dependent on the subject perceiving it, except the subject themselves. He refuted the existence of abstract objects that many other philosophers believed to exist, notably Plato. According to Berkeley, "an abstract object does not exist in space or time and which is therefore entirely non-physical and non-mental";[31] however, this argument contradicts with his relativity argument. If "esse est percipi",[32] (Latin meaning that to exist is to be perceived) is true, then the objects in the relativity argument made by Berkeley can either exist or not. Berkeley believed that only the minds' perceptions and the Spirit that perceives are what exists in reality; what people perceive every day is only the idea of an object's existence, but the objects themselves are not perceived. Berkeley also discussed how, at times, materials cannot be perceived by oneself, and the mind of oneself cannot understand the objects. However, there also exists an "omnipresent, eternal mind"[33] that Berkeley believed to consist of God and the Spirit, both omniscient and all-perceiving. According to Berkeley, God is the entity who controls everything, yet Berkeley also argued that "abstract object[s] do not exist in space or time".[31] In other words, as Warnock argues, Berkeley "had recognized that he could not square with his own talk of spirits, of our minds and of God; for these are perceivers and not among objects of perception. Thus he says, rather weakly and without elucidation, that in addition to our ideas we also have notions—we know what it means to speak of spirits and their operations."[34]

However, the relativity argument violates the idea of immaterialism. Berkeley's immaterialism argues that "esse est percipi (aut percipere)",[35] which in English is to be is to be perceived (or to perceive). That is saying only what perceived or perceives is real, and without our perception or God's nothing can be real. Yet, if the relativity argument, also by Berkeley, argues that the perception of an object depends on the different positions, then this means that what perceived can either be real or not because the perception does not show that whole picture and the whole picture cannot be perceived. Berkeley also believes that "when one perceives mediately, one perceives one idea by means of perceiving another".[36] By this, it can be elaborated that if the standards of what perceived at first are different, what perceived after that can be different, as well. In the heat perception described above, one hand perceived the water to be hot and the other hand perceived the water to be cold due to relativity. If applying the idea "to be is to be perceived", the water should be both cold and hot because both perceptions are perceived by different hands. However, the water cannot be cold and hot at the same time for it self-contradicts, so this shows that what perceived is not always true because it sometimes can break the law of noncontradiction. In this case, "it would be arbitrary anthropocentrism to claim that humans have special access to the true qualities of objects".[4] The truth for different people can be different, and humans are limited to accessing the absolute truth due to relativity. Summing up, nothing can be absolutely true due to relativity or the two arguments, to be is to be perceived and the relativity argument, do not always work together.

New theory of vision

In his Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision, Berkeley frequently criticised the views of the Optic Writers, a title that seems to include Molyneux, Wallis, Malebranche and Descartes.[37] In sections 1–51, Berkeley argued against the classical scholars of optics by holding that: spatial depth, as the distance that separates the perceiver from the perceived object is itself invisible. That is, we do not see space directly or deduce its form logically using the laws of optics. Space for Berkeley is no more than a contingent expectation that visual and tactile sensations will follow one another in regular sequences that we come to expect through habit.

Berkeley goes on to argue that visual cues, such as the perceived extension or 'confusion' of an object, can only be used to indirectly judge distance, because the viewer learns to associate visual cues with tactile sensations. Berkeley gives the following analogy regarding indirect distance perception: one perceives distance indirectly just as one perceives a person's embarrassment indirectly. When looking at an embarrassed person, we infer indirectly that the person is embarrassed by observing the red colour on the person's face. We know through experience that a red face tends to signal embarrassment, as we've learned to associate the two.

The question concerning the visibility of space was central to the Renaissance perspective tradition and its reliance on classical optics in the development of pictorial representations of spatial depth. This matter was debated by scholars since the 11th-century Arab polymath and mathematician Alhazen (al-Hasan Ibn al-Haytham) affirmed in experimental contexts the visibility of space. This issue, which was raised in Berkeley's theory of vision, was treated at length in the Phenomenology of Perception of Maurice Merleau-Ponty, in the context of confirming the visual perception of spatial depth (la profondeur), and by way of refuting Berkeley's thesis.[38]

Berkeley wrote about the perception of size in addition to that of distance. He is frequently misquoted as believing in size–distance invariance—a view held by the Optic Writers. This idea is that we scale the image size according to distance in a geometrical manner. The error may have become commonplace because the eminent historian and psychologist E. G. Boring perpetuated it.[39] In fact, Berkeley argued that the same cues that evoke distance also evoke size, and that we do not first see size and then calculate distance.[40] It is worth quoting Berkeley's words on this issue (Section 53):

What inclines men to this mistake (beside the humour of making one see by geometry) is, that the same perceptions or ideas which suggest distance, do also suggest magnitude ... I say they do not first suggest distance, and then leave it to the judgement to use that as a medium, whereby to collect the magnitude; but they have as close and immediate a connexion with the magnitude as with the distance; and suggest magnitude as independently of distance, as they do distance independently of magnitude.

Berkeley claimed that his visual theories were “vindicated” by a 1728 report regarding the recovery of vision in a 13-year-old boy operated for congenital cataracts by surgeon William Cheselden. In 2021, the name of Cheselden's patient was published for the first time: Daniel Dolins.[41] Berkeley knew the Dolins family, had numerous social links to Cheselden, including the poet Alexander Pope, and Princess Caroline, to whom Cheselden's patient was presented.[41] The report misspelled Cheselden's name, used language typical of Berkeley, and may even have been ghost-written by Berkeley.[41] Unfortunately, Dolins was never able to see well enough to read, and there is no evidence that the surgery improved Dolins' vision at any point prior to his death at age 30.[41]

Philosophy of physics

"Berkeley's works display his keen interest in natural philosophy [...] from his earliest writings (Arithmetica, 1707) to his latest (Siris, 1744). Moreover, much of his philosophy is shaped fundamentally by his engagement with the science of his time."[42] The profundity of this interest can be judged from numerous entries in Berkeley's Philosophical Commentaries (1707–1708), e.g. "Mem. to Examine & accurately discuss the scholium of the 8th Definition of Mr Newton's Principia." (#316)

Berkeley argued that forces and gravity, as defined by Newton, constituted "occult qualities" that "expressed nothing distinctly". He held that those who posited "something unknown in a body of which they have no idea and which they call the principle of motion, are in fact simply stating that the principle of motion is unknown." Therefore, those who "affirm that active force, action, and the principle of motion are really in bodies are adopting an opinion not based on experience."[43] Forces and gravity existed nowhere in the phenomenal world. On the other hand, if they resided in the category of "soul" or "incorporeal thing", they "do not properly belong to physics" as a matter. Berkeley thus concluded that forces lay beyond any kind of empirical observation and could not be a part of proper science.[44] He proposed his theory of signs as a means to explain motion and matter without reference to the "occult qualities" of force and gravity.

Berkeley's razor

Berkeley's razor is a rule of reasoning proposed by the philosopher Karl Popper in his study of Berkeley's key scientific work De Motu.[10] Berkeley's razor is considered by Popper to be similar to Ockham's razor but "more powerful". It represents an extreme, empiricist view of scientific observation that states that the scientific method provides us with no true insight into the nature of the world. Rather, the scientific method gives us a variety of partial explanations about regularities that hold in the world and that are gained through experiment. The nature of the world, according to Berkeley, is only approached through proper metaphysical speculation and reasoning.[45] Popper summarises Berkeley's razor as such:

A general practical result—which I propose to call "Berkeley's razor"—of [Berkeley's] analysis of physics allows us a priori to eliminate from physical science all essentialist explanations. If they have a mathematical and predictive content they may be admitted qua mathematical hypotheses (while their essentialist interpretation is eliminated). If not they may be ruled out altogether. This razor is sharper than Ockham's: all entities are ruled out except those which are perceived.[46]

In another essay of the same book[47] titled "Three Views Concerning Human Knowledge", Popper argues that Berkeley is to be considered as an instrumentalist philosopher, along with Robert Bellarmine, Pierre Duhem and Ernst Mach. According to this approach, scientific theories have the status of serviceable fictions, useful inventions aimed at explaining facts, and without any pretension to being true. Popper contrasts instrumentalism with the above-mentioned essentialism and his own "critical rationalism".

Philosophy of mathematics

In addition to his contributions to philosophy, Berkeley was also very influential in the development of mathematics, although in a rather indirect sense. "Berkeley was concerned with mathematics and its philosophical interpretation from the earliest stages of his intellectual life."[7] Berkeley's "Philosophical Commentaries" (1707–1708) witness to his interest in mathematics:

Axiom. No reasoning about things whereof we have no idea. Therefore no reasoning about Infinitesimals. (#354)

Take away the signs from Arithmetic & Algebra, & pray what remains? (#767)

These are sciences purely Verbal, & entirely useless but for Practise in Societys of Men. No speculative knowledge, no comparison of Ideas in them. (#768)

In 1707, Berkeley published two treatises on mathematics. In 1734, he published The Analyst, subtitled A DISCOURSE Addressed to an Infidel Mathematician, a critique of calculus. Florian Cajori called this treatise "the most spectacular event of the century in the history of British mathematics."[48] However, a recent study suggests that Berkeley misunderstood Leibnizian calculus.[49] The mathematician in question is believed to have been either Edmond Halley, or Isaac Newton himself—though if to the latter, then the discourse was posthumously addressed, as Newton died in 1727. The Analyst represented a direct attack on the foundations and principles of calculus and, in particular, the notion of fluxion or infinitesimal change, which Newton and Leibniz used to develop the calculus. In his critique, Berkeley coined the phrase "ghosts of departed quantities", familiar to students of calculus. Ian Stewart's book From Here to Infinity captures the gist of his criticism.

Berkeley regarded his criticism of calculus as part of his broader campaign against the religious implications of Newtonian mechanics – as a defence of traditional Christianity against deism, which tends to distance God from His worshipers. Specifically, he observed that both Newtonian and Leibnizian calculus employed infinitesimals sometimes as positive, nonzero quantities and other times as a number explicitly equal to zero. Berkeley's key point in "The Analyst" was that Newton's calculus (and the laws of motion based in calculus) lacked rigorous theoretical foundations. He claimed that

In every other Science Men prove their Conclusions by their Principles, and not their Principles by the Conclusions. But if in yours you should allow your selves this unnatural way of proceeding, the Consequence would be that you must take up with Induction, and bid adieu to Demonstration. And if you submit to this, your Authority will no longer lead the way in Points of Reason and Science.[50]

Berkeley did not doubt that calculus produced real-world truth; simple physics experiments could verify that Newton's method did what it claimed to do. "The cause of Fluxions cannot be defended by reason",[51] but the results could be defended by empirical observation, Berkeley's preferred method of acquiring knowledge at any rate. Berkeley, however, found it paradoxical that "Mathematicians should deduce true Propositions from false Principles, be right in Conclusion, and yet err in the Premises." In The Analyst he endeavoured to show "how Error may bring forth Truth, though it cannot bring forth Science".[52] Newton's science, therefore, could not on purely scientific grounds justify its conclusions, and the mechanical, deistic model of the universe could not be rationally justified.[53]

The difficulties raised by Berkeley were still present in the work of Cauchy whose approach to calculus was a combination of infinitesimals and a notion of limit, and were eventually sidestepped by Weierstrass by means of his (ε, δ) approach, which eliminated infinitesimals altogether. More recently, Abraham Robinson restored infinitesimal methods in his 1966 book Non-standard analysis by showing that they can be used rigorously.

Moral philosophy

The tract A Discourse on Passive Obedience (1712) is considered Berkeley's major contribution to moral and political philosophy.

In A Discourse on Passive Obedience, Berkeley defends the thesis that people have "a moral duty to observe the negative precepts (prohibitions) of the law, including the duty not to resist the execution of punishment."[54] However, Berkeley does make exceptions to this sweeping moral statement, stating that we need not observe precepts of "usurpers or even madmen"[55] and that people can obey different supreme authorities if there are more than one claims to the highest authority.

Berkeley defends this thesis with deductive proof stemming from the laws of nature. First, he establishes that because God is perfectly good, the end to which he commands humans must also be good, and that end must not benefit just one person, but the entire human race. Because these commands—or laws—if practised, would lead to the general fitness of humankind, it follows that they can be discovered by the right reason—for example, the law to never resist supreme power can be derived from reason because this law is "the only thing that stands between us and total disorder".[54] Thus, these laws can be called the laws of nature, because they are derived from God—the creator of nature himself. "These laws of nature include duties never to resist the supreme power, lie under oath ... or do evil so that good may come of it."[54]

One may view Berkeley's doctrine on Passive Obedience as a kind of 'Theological Utilitarianism', insofar as it states that we have a duty to uphold a moral code which presumably is working towards the ends of promoting the good of humankind. However, the concept of 'ordinary' Utilitarianism is fundamentally different in that it "makes utility the one and only ground of obligation"[56]—that is, Utilitarianism is concerned with whether particular actions are morally permissible in specific situations, while Berkeley's doctrine is concerned with whether or not we should follow moral rules in any and all circumstances. Whereas Act Utilitarianism might, for example, justify a morally impermissible act in light of the specific situation, Berkeley's doctrine of Passive Obedience holds that it is never morally permissible to not follow a moral rule, even when it seems like breaking that moral rule might achieve the happiest ends. Berkeley holds that even though sometimes, the consequences of an action in a specific situation might be bad, the general tendencies of that action benefit humanity.

Other important sources for Berkeley's views on morality are Alciphron (1732), especially dialogues I–III, and the Discourse to Magistrates (1738)."[57] Passive Obedience is notable partly for containing one of the earliest statements of rule utilitarianism.[58]

Immaterialism

George Berkeley’s theory that matter does not exist comes from the belief that "sensible things are those only which are immediately perceived by sense."[59] Berkeley says in his book called The Principles of Human Knowledge that "the ideas of sense are stronger, livelier, and clearer than those of the imagination; and they are also steady, orderly and coherent."[60] From this we can tell that the things that we are perceiving are truly real rather than it just being a dream.

All knowledge comes from perception; what we perceive are ideas, not things in themselves; a thing in itself must be outside experience; so the world only consists of ideas and minds that perceive those ideas; a thing only exists so far as it perceives or is perceived.[61] Through this we can see that consciousness is considered something that exists to Berkeley due to its ability to perceive. "'To be,' said of the object, means to be perceived, 'esse est percipi'; 'to be', said of the subject, means to perceive or 'percipere'."[62] Having established this, Berkeley then attacks the "opinion strangely prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in a word all sensible objects have an existence natural or real, distinct from being perceived".[60] He believes this idea to be inconsistent because such an object with an existence independent of perception must have both sensible qualities, and thus be known (making it an idea), and also an insensible reality, which Berkeley believes is inconsistent.[63] Berkeley believes that the error arises because people think that perceptions can imply or infer something about the material object. Berkeley calls this concept abstract ideas. He rebuts this concept by arguing that people cannot conceive of an object without also imagining the sensual input of the object. He argues in Principles of Human Knowledge that, similar to how people can only sense matter with their senses through the actual sensation, they can only conceive of matter (or, rather, ideas of matter) through the idea of sensation of matter.[60] This implies that everything that people can conceive in regards to matter is only ideas about matter. Thus, matter, should it exist, must exist as collections of ideas, which can be perceived by the senses and interpreted by the mind. But if matter is just a collection of ideas, then Berkeley concludes that matter, in the sense of a material substance, does not exist as most philosophers of Berkeley's time believed. Indeed, if a person visualizes something, then it must have some colour, however dark or light; it cannot just be a shape of no colour at all if a person is to visualize it.[64]

Berkeley's ideas raised controversy because his argument refuted Descartes' worldview, which was expanded upon by Locke, and resulted in the rejection of Berkeley's form of empiricism by several philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. In Locke's worldview, "the world causes the perceptual ideas we have of it by the way it interacts with our senses."[61] This contradicts with Berkeley's worldview because not only does it suggest the existence of physical causes in the world, but in fact, there is no physical world beyond our ideas. The only causes that exist in Berkeley's worldview are those that are a result of the use of the will.

Berkeley's theory relies heavily on his form of empiricism, which in turn relies heavily on the senses. His empiricism can be defined by five propositions: all significant words stand for ideas; all knowledge of things is about ideas; all ideas come from without or from within; if from without it must be by the senses, and they are called sensations (the real things), if from within they are the operations of the mind, and are called thoughts.[64] Berkeley clarifies his distinction between ideas by saying they "are imprinted on the senses," "perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind," or "are formed by help of memory and imagination."[64] One refutation of his idea was: if someone leaves a room and stops perceiving that room does that room no longer exist? Berkeley answers this by claiming that it is still being perceived and the consciousness that is doing the perceiving is God. (This makes Berkeley's argument hinge upon an omniscient, omnipresent deity.) This claim is the only thing holding up his argument which is "depending for our knowledge of the world, and of the existence of other minds, upon a God that would never deceive us."[61] Berkeley anticipates a second objection, which he refutes in Principles of Human Knowledge. He anticipates that the materialist may take a representational materialist standpoint: although the senses can only perceive ideas, these ideas resemble (and thus can be compared to) the actual, existing object. Thus, through the sensing of these ideas, the mind can make inferences as to matter itself, even though pure matter is non-perceivable. Berkeley's objection to that notion is that "an idea can be like nothing but an idea; a colour or figure can be like nothing but another colour or figure".[60] Berkeley distinguishes between an idea, which is mind-dependent, and a material substance, which is not an idea and is mind-independent. As they are not alike, they cannot be compared, just as one cannot compare the colour red to something that is invisible, or the sound of music to silence, other than that one exists and the other does not. This is called the likeness principle: the notion that an idea can only be like (and thus compared to) another idea.

Berkeley attempted to show how ideas manifest themselves into different objects of knowledge:

It is evident to anyone who takes a survey of the objects of human knowledge, that they are either ideas actually imprinted on the senses; or else such as are perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind; or lastly ideas formed by help of memory and imagination—either compounding, dividing, or barely representing those originally perceived in the aforesaid ways". (Berkeley's emphasis.)[65]

Berkeley also attempted to prove the existence of God throughout his beliefs in immaterialism.[4]

Influence

Berkeley's Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge was published three years before the publication of Arthur Collier's Clavis Universalis, which made assertions similar to those of Berkeley's.[66] However, there seemed to have been no influence or communication between the two writers.[67]

German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer once wrote of him: "Berkeley was, therefore, the first to treat the subjective starting-point really seriously and to demonstrate irrefutably its absolute necessity. He is the father of idealism ...".[68]

Berkeley is considered one of the originators of British empiricism.[69] A linear development is often traced from three great "British Empiricists", leading from Locke through Berkeley to Hume.[70]

Berkeley influenced many modern philosophers, especially David Hume. Thomas Reid admitted that he put forward a drastic criticism of Berkeleianism after he had been an admirer of Berkeley's philosophical system for a long time.[71] Berkeley's "thought made possible the work of Hume and thus Kant, notes Alfred North Whitehead."[72] Some authors[who?] draw a parallel between Berkeley and Edmund Husserl.[clarification needed][73]

When Berkeley visited America, the American educator Samuel Johnson visited him, and the two later corresponded. Johnson convinced Berkeley to establish a scholarship program at Yale, and to donate a large number of books as well as his plantation to the college when the philosopher returned to England. It was one of Yale's largest and most important donations; it doubled its library holdings, improved the college's financial position and brought Anglican religious ideas and English culture into New England.[74] Johnson also took Berkeley's philosophy and used parts of it as a framework for his own American Practical Idealism school of philosophy. As Johnson's philosophy was taught to about half the graduates of American colleges between 1743 and 1776,[75] and over half of the contributors to the Declaration of Independence were connected to it,[76] Berkeley's ideas were indirectly a foundation of the American Mind.

Outside of America, during Berkeley's lifetime his philosophical ideas were comparatively uninfluential.[77] But interest in his doctrine grew from the 1870s when Alexander Campbell Fraser, "the leading Berkeley scholar of the nineteenth century",[78] published The Works of George Berkeley. A powerful impulse to serious studies in Berkeley's philosophy was given by A. A. Luce and Thomas Edmund Jessop, "two of the twentieth century's foremost Berkeley scholars",[79] thanks to whom Berkeley scholarship was raised to the rank of a special area of historico-philosophical science. In addition, the philosopher Colin Murray Turbayne wrote extensively on Berkeley's use of language as a model for visual, physiological, natural and metaphysical relationships.[80][81][82][83]

The proportion of Berkeley scholarship, in literature on the history of philosophy, is increasing. This can be judged from the most comprehensive bibliographies on George Berkeley. During the period of 1709–1932, about 300 writings on Berkeley were published. That amounted to 1.5 publications per annum. During the course of 1932–79, over one thousand works were brought out, i.e., 20 works per annum. Since then, the number of publications has reached 30 per annum.[84] In 1977 publication began in Ireland of a special journal on Berkeley's life and thought (Berkeley Studies). In 1988, the Australian philosopher Colin Murray Turbayne established the International Berkeley Essay Prize Competition at the University of Rochester in an effort to advance scholarship and research on the works of Berkeley.[85][86]

Other than philosophy, Berkeley also influenced modern psychology with his work on John Locke's theory of association and how it could be used to explain how humans gain knowledge in the physical world. He also used the theory to explain perception, stating that all qualities were, as Locke would call them, "secondary qualities", therefore perception laid entirely in the perceiver and not in the object. These are both topics today studied in modern psychology.[87]

Appearances in literature

Lord Byron's Don Juan references immaterialism in the Eleventh Canto:

When Bishop Berkeley said 'there was no matter,'
And proved it—'t was no matter what he said:
They say his system 't is in vain to batter,
Too subtle for the airiest human head;
And yet who can believe it? I would shatter
Gladly all matters down to stone or lead,
Or adamant, to find the world a spirit,
And wear my head, denying that I wear it.

Herman Melville humorously references Berkeley in Chapter 20 of Mardi (1849), when outlining a character's belief of being on board a ghostship:

And here be it said, that for all his superstitious misgivings about the brigantine; his imputing to her something equivalent to a purely phantom-like nature, honest Jarl was nevertheless exceedingly downright and practical in all hints and proceedings concerning her. Wherein, he resembled my Right Reverend friend, Bishop Berkeley–truly, one of your lords spiritual—who, metaphysically speaking, holding all objects to be mere optical delusions, was, notwithstanding, extremely matter-of-fact in all matters touching matter itself. Besides being pervious to the points of pins, and possessing a palate capable of appreciating plum-puddings:—which sentence reads off like a pattering of hailstones.

James Joyce references Berkeley's philosophy in the third episode of Ulysses (1922):

Who watches me here? Who ever anywhere will read these written words? Signs on a white field. Somewhere to someone in your flutiest voice. The good bishop of Cloyne took the veil of the temple out of his shovel hat: veil of space with coloured emblems hatched on its field. Hold hard. Coloured on a flat: yes, that's right. Flat I see, then think distance, near, far, flat I see, east, back. Ah, see now!

In commenting on a review of Ada or Ardor, author Vladimir Nabokov alludes to Berkeley's philosophy as informing his novel:

And finally I owe no debt whatsoever (as Mr. Leonard seems to think) to the famous Argentine essayist and his rather confused compilation "A New Refutation of Time." Mr. Leonard would have lost less of it had he gone straight to Berkeley and Bergson. (Strong Opinions, pp. 2892–90)

James Boswell, in the part of his Life of Samuel Johnson covering the year 1763, recorded Johnson's opinion of one aspect of Berkeley's philosophy:

After we came out of the church, we stood talking for some time together of Bishop Berkeley's ingenious sophistry to prove the non-existence of matter, and that every thing in the universe is merely ideal. I observed, that though we are satisfied his doctrine is untrue, it is impossible to refute it. I shall never forget the alacrity with which Johnson answered, striking his foot with mighty force against a large stone, till he rebounded from it,– "I refute it thus."

Commemoration

Both the University of California, Berkeley, and the city of Berkeley, California, were named after him, although the pronunciation has evolved to suit American English: (/ˈbɜːrkli/ BURK-lee). The naming was suggested in 1866 by Frederick H. Billings, a trustee of the then College of California. Billings was inspired by Berkeley's Verses on the Prospect of Planting Arts and Learning in America, particularly the final stanza: "Westward the course of empire takes its way; the first four Acts already past, a fifth shall close the Drama with the day; time's noblest offspring is the last".[88]

The Town of Berkley, currently the least populated town in Bristol County, Massachusetts, was founded on 18 April 1735 and named after the renowned philosopher. It is located 40 miles south of Boston and 25 miles north of Middletown, Rhode Island.

A residential college and an Episcopal seminary at Yale University also bear Berkeley's name.

Berkeley Preparatory School in Tampa, Florida, a private school affiliated with the Episcopal Church, is also named for him.

"Bishop Berkeley's Gold Medals" are two awards given annually at Trinity College Dublin, "provided outstanding merit is shown", to candidates answering a special examination in Greek. The awards were founded in 1752 by Berkeley.[89]

An Ulster History Circle blue plaque commemorating him is located in Bishop Street Within, city of Derry.

Berkeley's farmhouse in Middletown, Rhode Island, is preserved as Whitehall Museum House, also known as Berkeley House, and was listed on the National Register of Historic Places in 1970. St. Columba's Chapel, located in the same town, was formerly named "The Berkeley Memorial Chapel," and the appellation still survives at the end of the formal name of the parish, "St. Columba's, the Berkeley Memorial Chapel".

Writings

Original publications

  • Arithmetica (1707)
  • Miscellanea Mathematica (1707)
  • Philosophical Commentaries or Common-Place Book (1707–08, notebooks)
  • An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision (1709)
  • A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I (1710)
  • Passive Obedience, or the Christian doctrine of not resisting the Supreme Power (1712)
  • Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (1713)
  • An Essay Towards Preventing the Ruin of Great Britain (1721)
  • De Motu (1721)
  • A Proposal for Better Supplying Churches in our Foreign Plantations, and for converting the Savage Americans to Christianity by a College to be erected in the Summer Islands (1725)
  • A Sermon preached before the incorporated Society for the Propagation of the Gospel in Foreign Parts (1732)
  • Alciphron, or the Minute Philosopher (1732)
  • Essays toward a new theory of vision (in Italian). Venezia: Francesco Storti (2.). 1732.
  • The Theory of Vision, or Visual Language, shewing the immediate presence and providence of a Deity, vindicated and explained (1733)
  • The Analyst: a Discourse addressed to an Infidel Mathematician (1734)
  • A Defence of Free-thinking in Mathematics, with Appendix concerning Mr. Walton's vindication of Sir Isaac Newton's Principle of Fluxions (1735)
  • Reasons for not replying to Mr. Walton's Full Answer (1735)
  • The Querist, containing several queries proposed to the consideration of the public (three parts, 1735–37).
  • A Discourse addressed to Magistrates and Men of Authority (1736)
  • Siris, a chain of philosophical reflections and inquiries, concerning the virtues of tar-water (1744).
  • A Letter to the Roman Catholics of the Diocese of Cloyne (1745)
  • A Word to the Wise, or an exhortation to the Roman Catholic clergy of Ireland (1749)
  • Maxims concerning Patriotism (1750)
  • Farther Thoughts on Tar-water (1752)
  • Miscellany (1752)

Collections

  • The Works of George Berkeley, D.D. Late Bishop of Cloyne in Ireland. To which is added, an account of his life, and several of his letters to Thomas Prior, Esq. Dean Gervais, and Mr. Pope, &c. &c. Printed for George Robinson, Pater Noster Row, 1784. Two volumes.
  • The Works of George Berkeley, D.D., formerly Bishop of Cloyne: Including Many of His Writings Hitherto Unpublished; With Prefaces, Annotations, His Life and Letters, and an Account of His Philosophy. Ed. by Alexander Campbell Fraser. In 4 Volumes. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1901.
    • Vol. 1
    • Vol. 2
    • Vol. 3
    • Vol. 4
  • The Works of George Berkeley. Ed. by A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop. Nine volumes. Edinburgh and London, 1948–1957.
  • Ewald, William B., ed., 1996. From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, 2 vols. Oxford Uni. Press.
    • 1707. Of Infinites, 16–19.
    • 1709. Letter to Samuel Molyneaux, 19–21.
    • 1721. De Motu, 37–54.
    • 1734. The Analyst, 60–92.

See also

References

  1. ^ Fumerton, Richard (21 February 2000). "Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 August 2018.
  2. ^ David Bostock, Philosophy of Mathematics: An Introduction, Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, p. 43: "All of Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume supposed that mathematics is a theory of our ideas, but none of them offered any argument for this conceptualist claim, and apparently took it to be uncontroversial."
  3. ^ The Problem of Perception (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy): "Paraphrasing David Hume (1739 ...; see also Locke 1690, Berkeley 1710, Russell 1912): nothing is ever directly present to the mind in perception except perceptual appearances."
  4. ^ a b c Downing, Lisa. "George Berkeley". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 9 December 2019.
  5. ^ Watson, Richard A. (1993–1994). (PDF). Berkeley Newsletter (13): 1–3. Archived from the original (PDF) on 3 July 2013. Retrieved 8 November 2010.
  6. ^ "Berkeley" entry in Collins English Dictionary.
  7. ^ a b Douglas M. Jesseph (2005). "Berkeley's philosophy of mathematics". In Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 266. ISBN 978-0-521-45033-1.
  8. ^ See Berkeley, George (1709). An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision (2 ed.). Dublin: Jeremy Pepyat.
  9. ^ Turbayne, C. M. (September 1959). "Berkeley's Two Concepts of Mind". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 20 (1): 85–92. doi:10.2307/2104957. JSTOR 2104957.
    Repr. in Engle, Gale; Taylor, Gabriele (1968). Berkeley's Principles of Human Knowledge: Critical Studies. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. pp. 24–33. In this collection of essays, Turbayne's work comprised two papers that had been published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research:
  10. ^ a b Berkeley's Philosophical Writings, New York: Collier, 1974, Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 64-22680
  11. ^ Popper, K.R. (1 May 1953). "A note on Berkeley as precursor of Mach". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. IV (13): 26–36. doi:10.1093/bjps/IV.13.26. S2CID 123072861.
  12. ^ Also published: Conjectures and Refutations, Volume I, "A note on Berkeley as precursor of Mach and Einstein", Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969.
  13. ^ jhollandtranslations.com
  14. ^ Turbayne, Colin, ed. (1982). Berkeley: critical and interpretive essays. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 978-0-8166-1065-5.
  15. ^ Edward Chaney, 'George Berkeley's Grand Tours: The Immaterialist as Connoisseur of Art and Architecture', in E. Chaney, The Evolution of the Grand Tour: Anglo-Italian Cultural Relations since the Renaissance, 2nd ed. London, Routledge. 2000 ISBN 0714644749
  16. ^ "First Scholarship Fund". www.yaleslavery.org. Retrieved 28 June 2020.
  17. ^ Humphreys, Joe. "What to do about George Berkeley, Trinity figurehead and slave owner?". The Irish Times.
  18. ^ Chaney, Edward. The Evolution of the Grand Tour: Anglo-Italian Cultural Relations Since the Renaissance (Frank Cass Publishers, 2000), 324.
  19. ^ "John Smibert". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 15 August 2016.
  20. ^ E. Chaney, "George Berkeley's Grand Tours",Evolution of the Grand Tour, p. 324
  21. ^ Geoffrey J. Warnock, Introduction to: George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Open Court La Salle, 1986, p. 9.
  22. ^ a b Downing, Lisa, "George Berkeley", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Retrieved 21 August 2013.
  23. ^ Downing, Lisa (2013). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  24. ^ Pope, in his Satires, Epistles, and Odes of Horace (Epilogue to the Satires, Dialogue ii, line 73) refers to God granting "To Berkeley every Virtue under Heaven".
  25. ^ Bettcher T. M. Berkeley: A Guide for the Perplexed. Continuum Publishing, 2008. p. 14.
  26. ^ Fogelin, Robert Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge. Routledge, 2001. p. 27.
  27. ^ Fogelin, Robert Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge. Routledge, 2001. pp. 74–75.
  28. ^ "Berkeley, George | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 24 June 2022.
  29. ^ a b Downing, Lisa. "George Berkeley". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 11 December 2019.
  30. ^ a b Balaguer, Mark (12 May 2004). "Platonism in Metaphysics". Retrieved 11 December 2019.
  31. ^ George, Berkeley. The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne (PDF). London: Thomas Nelson and Sons. Retrieved 11 December 2019.
  32. ^ "The Cambridge History of English and American Literature in 18 Volumes (1907–21)".
  33. ^ G. Warnock, Introduction to G. Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Open Court La Salle, 1986, p. 29.
  34. ^ George, Berkeley. The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne (PDF). London: Thomas Nelson and Sons. Retrieved 9 December 2019.
  35. ^ "George Berkeley (1685–1753)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 9 December 2019.
  36. ^ Schwartz, R, 1994. Vision: Variations on some Berkeleian themes. Oxford: Blackwell, p. 54.
  37. ^ For recent studies on this topic refer to: Nader El-Bizri, 'La perception de la profondeur: Alhazen, Berkeley et Merleau-Ponty', Oriens-Occidens: Cahiers du centre d'histoire des sciences et des philosophies arabes et médiévales, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique Vol. 5 (2004), pp. 171–84. See also: Nader El-Bizri, "A Philosophical Perspective on Alhazen's Optics", Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, Vol. 15 (2005), pp. 189–218 (Cambridge University Press journal), doi:10.1017/S0957423905000172.
  38. ^ Boring E. G., 1942. Sensation and perception in the history of experimental psychology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, pp. 223, 298.
  39. ^ Ross H. E., Plug, C., 1998. "The history of size constancy and size illusions." In Walsh, V. & Kulikowski, J. (Eds). Perceptual constancy: Why things look as they do. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 499–528.
  40. ^ a b c d Leffler, CT; Schwartz, SG (February 2021). "The First Cataract Surgeons in the British Isles". American Journal of Ophthalmology. 230: 75–122. doi:10.1016/j.ajo.2021.03.009. PMC 8446104. PMID 33744237.
  41. ^ Lisa Downing (2005). "Berkeley's natural philosophy and philosophy of science". In Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 230. ISBN 978-0-521-45033-1.
  42. ^ De Motu, in Berkeley, George, and Jessop, T.E. The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne. London: Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd., 1948–1957, 4:36–37
  43. ^ Downing, Lisa. Berkeley's Case Against Realism About Dynamics. In Robert G. Muehlmann (ed.), Berkeley's Metaphysics: Structural, Interpretive, and Critical Essays. The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995
  44. ^ "To be of service to reckoning and mathematical demonstrations is one thing, to set forth the nature of things is another" (De Motu), cited by G. Warnock in the introduction to A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Open Court La Salle, 1986, p. 24.
  45. ^ Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, New York: Routledge, 2002, p. 231.
  46. ^ K. Popper Conjectures and Refutations, Part I, 3.
  47. ^ Florian Cajori (2010). A History of the Conceptions of Limits and Fluxions in Great Britain, from Newton to Woodhouse. BiblioBazaar. ISBN 978-1-143-05698-7.
  48. ^ Katz, Mikhail; Sherry, David (2012), "Leibniz's Infinitesimals: Their Fictionality, Their Modern Implementations, and Their Foes from Berkeley to Russell and Beyond", Erkenntnis, 78 (3): 571–625, arXiv:1205.0174, doi:10.1007/s10670-012-9370-y, S2CID 119329569
  49. ^ The Analyst, in Berkeley, George, and Jessop, T.E. The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne. London: Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd., 1948–1957, 4:76
  50. ^ Defence of Free-Thinking in Mathematics, in Berkeley, George, and Jessop, T.E. The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne. London: Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd., 1948–1957, 4:113
  51. ^ The Analyst, in Berkeley, George, and Jessop, T.E. The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne. London: Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd., 1948–1957, 4:77
  52. ^ Cantor, Geoffrey. "Berkeley's The Analyst Revisited". Isis, Vol. 75, No. 4 (Dec. 1984), pp. 668–83. JSTOR 232412. doi:10.1086/353648.
  53. ^ a b c Häyry, Matti. "Passive Obedience and Berkeley's Moral Philosophy." Berkeley Studies 23 (2012): 3–13.
  54. ^ Berkeley, George. Passive Obedience: Or, the Christian Doctrine of Not Resisting the Supreme Power, Proved and Vindicated ... In a Discourse Deliver'd at the College-chapel. By George Berkeley, M.A. Fellow of Trinity-College, Dublin. London: Printed for H. Clements, 1712. Print.
  55. ^ "Berkeley's Theory of Morals". www.ditext.com. Retrieved 27 May 2016.
  56. ^ Jakapi, Roomet. "Was Berkeley a Utilitarian?" // Lemetti, Juhana and Piirimäe, Eva, eds. Human Nature as the Basis of Morality and Society in Early Modern Philosophy. Acta Philosophica Fennica 83. Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland, 2007. p. 53. (The article contains extensive cover of literature on the topic from Alexander Campbell Fraser to up-to-date investigations including Matti Häyry's article on Berkeley's ethics.)
  57. ^ Hooker, Brad (2008). "Rule Consequentialism." In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  58. ^ Berkeley, George, and Howard Robinson. Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009.
  59. ^ a b c d Berkeley, George. "Principles of Human Knowledge." The Empiricists: Locke, Berkeley, and Hume. Anchor Books, 1974, pp. 151–62.
  60. ^ a b c Buckingham, Will. "To Be Is To Be Perceived". The Philosophy Book: Big Ideas Simply Explained, DK Publishing, New York, 2011, pp. 138–41.
  61. ^ The Editors of Encyclopædia Britannica. "George Berkeley". Encyclopædia Britannica, Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc., 2012. Accessed 15 March 2017.
  62. ^ Flage, Daniel E. "George Berkeley". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, www.iep.utm.edu/berkeley. Accessed 20 May 2019.
  63. ^ a b c Urmson, J. O., et al. "The Attack on Matter". British Empiricists, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992, pp. 106–24.
  64. ^ George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Open Court La Salle, 1986, p. 65.
  65. ^ Reid T.; Ed. by William Hamilton (1852). "The Works of Thomas Reid, now fully collected". Edinburgh: Maclachlan and Stewart. Retrieved 1 December 2010see: "Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man" II:X{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link), p. 287.
  66. ^ Reid T.; Ed. by William Hamilton (1852). "The Works of Thomas Reid, now fully collected". Edinburgh: Maclachlan and Stewart. Retrieved 1 December 2010see: "Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man" VI:VII{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link), p. 464.
  67. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy," § 12
  68. ^ Rick Grush 20 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine syllabus Empiricism (J. Locke, G. Berkeley, D. Hume) 15 November 2009 at the Wayback Machine
  69. ^ McCracken, Charles J. and Tipton, Ian, eds., Berkeley's Principles and Dialogues: Background Source Materials. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 5 (The editor's Introduction 6 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine).
  70. ^ Reid T. "Inquiry into the Human Mind, Dedication.
  71. ^ Cited from: Steinkraus, W. E. Berkeley, epistemology, and science // Idealistic Studies. Worcester, 1984. Vol. 14, no. 3. p. 184.
  72. ^ Philipse, H. "Transcendental Idealism" in The Cambridge Companion to Husserl. Ed. by Barry Smith & David Woodruff Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995, pp. 239–322. (The paper constitutes a discussion on the relation between Husserl's transcendental idealism and the idealist positions of Berkeley and Kant.)
  73. ^ Hoeveler, J. David, Creating the American Mind: Intellect and Politics in the Colonial Colleges, Rowman & Littlefield, 2007, ISBN 978-0742548398, p. 63
  74. ^ Olsen, Neil C., Pursuing Happiness: The Organizational Culture of the Continental Congress, Nonagram Publications, 2013, ISBN 978-1480065505, p. 179
  75. ^ Olsen, Neil C., Pursuing Happiness: The Organizational Culture of the Continental Congress, Nonagram Publications, 2013, ISBN 978-1480065505, p. 299
  76. ^ See:
    • Bracken, Harry M. (1965). The Early Reception of Berkeley's Immaterialism (1965 revision of the 1959 ed.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. p. 1.
    • McCracken, Charles J. and Tipton, Ian, eds., Berkeley's Principles and Dialogues: Background Source Materials. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 6 (Editor's Introduction 6 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine).
  77. ^ Charles J. McCracken "Berkeley's Realism" // New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought. Ed. by S. H. Daniel. New York: Humanity Books, 2008, p. 24. ISBN 978-1-59102-557-3.
  78. ^ Charles J. McCracken "Berkeley's Realism", New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought. Ed. by S. H. Daniel. New York: Humanity Books, 2008, p. 25. ISBN 978-1-59102-557-3.
  79. ^ The Rhetoric of Empiricism. Jules David Law. Cornell University Press, London, 1993, ISBN 0-8014-2706-1 p. 98 on books.google.com
  80. ^ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 20, No. 1, Sept. 1959 pp.85-92 "Berkeley's Two Concepts of Mind", Colin Murray Turbayne on JSTOR.org
  81. ^ Dialectic Vol. 8, No. 3, Sept. 15, 1954 pp.210-227 "Berkeley and Russell On Space", Colin Murray Turbayne on JSTOR.org
  82. ^ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 22, No. 3, March 1962, pp. 383-386 "Berkeley's Two Concepts of Mind Part II", Colin Murray Turbayne on JSTOR.org
  83. ^ See:
    • Jessop T. E., Luce A. A. A bibliography of George Berkeley. 2 edn., Springer, 1973. ISBN 978-90-247-1577-0
    • Turbayne C. M. A Bibliography of George Berkeley 1963–1979 // Berkeley: Critical and Interpretive Essays. (EPUP, Google Books) Ed. by C. M. Turbayne. Manchester, 1982. pp. 313–29.
    • Parigi, Silvia. Berkeley Bibliography (1979–2010) 3 July 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  84. ^ International Berkeley Society – Turbayne Essay Prize on internationalberkeleysociety.org
  85. ^ University of Rochester – Department of Philosophy – George Berkeley Essay Prize Competition on sas.rochester.edu
  86. ^ Schultz, Duane P. (2008). A History of Modern Psychology (ninth ed.). Belmont, CA: Thomas Higher Education. ISBN 978-0-495-09799-0.
  87. ^ "Why Is Berkeley Called Berkeley?". Berkeley Historical Society. Retrieved 15 August 2016.
  88. ^ Prizes and Other Awards, Trinity College Dublin – Calendar 2016–17, p. 369. Retrieved 16 April 2017.

Sources

Bibliographic resources

  • Jessop T. E., Luce A. A. A bibliography of George Berkeley 2 edn., Springer, 1973. ISBN 978-90-247-1577-0
  • Turbayne C. M. A Bibliography of George Berkeley 1963–1979 in: Berkeley: Critical and Interpretive Essays – via Google Books, Manchester, 1982. pp. 313–29.
  • Berkeley Bibliography (1979–2010) 3 July 2013 at the Wayback Machine – A Supplement to those of Jessop and Turbayne by Silvia Parigi.
  • A Bibliography on George Berkeley – About 300 works from the 19th century to our days.

Philosophical studies

  • Daniel, Stephen H. (ed.), Re-examining Berkeley's Philosophy, Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007.
  • Daniel, Stephen H. (ed.), New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought, Amherst: Humanity Books, 2008.
  • Dicker, Georges, Berkeley's Idealism. A Critical Examination, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
  • Gaustad, Edwin. George Berkeley in America. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959.
  • Pappas, George S., Berkeley's Thought, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000.
  • Stoneham, Tom, Berkeley's World: An Examination of the Three Dialogues, Oxford University Press, 2002.
  • Warnock, Geoffrey J., Berkeley, Penguin Books, 1953.
  • Winkler, Kenneth P., The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Attribution

Further reading

  • Adamson, Robert; Mitchell, John Malcolm (1911). "Berkeley, George" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 3 (11th ed.). pp. 779–781.
  • R.H. Nichols; F A. Wray (1935). The History of the Foundling Hospital. London: Oxford Univ. Press. p. 349.
  • John Daniel Wild (1962). George Berkeley: a study of his life and philosophy. New York: Russell & Russell.
  • Brook, Richard J. (1973). Berkeley's Philosophy of Science. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. ISBN 978-90-247-1555-8.
  • Turbayne, Colin Murray (1982). Berkeley Critical and Interpretive Essays. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 0-8166-1065-7.
  • Muehlmann, Robert G. (1992). Berkeley's Ontology. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. ISBN 0-87220-146-5.
    • "Shows a thorough mastery of the literature on Berkeley, along with very perceptive remarks about the strength and weaknesses of most of the central commentators. ... Exhibits a mastery of all the material, both primary and secondary ..." Charles Larmore, for the Editorial Board, Journal of Philosophy.
    • R. Muehlmann is one of the Berkeley Prize Winners.
  • Edward Chaney (2000), 'George Berkeley's Grand Tours: The Immaterialist as Connoisseur of Art and Architecture', in E. Chaney, The Evolution of the Grand Tour: Anglo-Italian Cultural Relations since the Renaissance, 2nd ed. London, Routledge. ISBN 0714644749
  • Paul Strathern (2000). Berkeley in ninety minutes. Ivan R. Dee. ISBN 978-1-56663-291-1.
  • Fogelin, Robert (2001). Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge. Routledge.
  • Costica Bradatan (2006), The Other Bishop Berkeley. An Exercise in Reenchantment, Fordham University Press, New York
  • New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought. Ed. by S. H. Daniel. New York: Humanity Books, 2008, 319 pp. ISBN 978-1-59102-557-3.
Secondary literature available on the Internet
  • Most sources listed below are suggested by Dr. Talia M. Bettcher in Berkeley: a Guide for the Perplexed (2008). See the textbook's description.
  • Johnston G. A. (1923). The Development of Berkeley's Philosophy. London: Macmillan.
  • Luce, A. A. Berkeley and Malebranche. A Study in the Origins of Berkeley's Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1934 (2nd edn, with additional Preface, 1967).
  • Russell B. Berkeley // Bertrand Russell A History of Western Philosophy 3:1:16 (1945)
  • Turbayne, Colin Murray (1959). "Berkeley's Two Concepts of Mind" - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 20, No. 1, Sept. 1959, pp. 85-92 on JSTOR.org
  • Turbayne, Colin Murray (1962). "Berkeley's Two Concepts of Mind Part II" - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 22, No. 3, March 1962, pp. 383-386 on JSTOR.org
  • Olscamp, Paul J. (1970). The Moral Philosophy of George Berkeley. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. olscamp moral philosophy of george berkeley.
    • Reviewed by: Désirée Park. Studi internazionali filosofici 3 (1971):228–30; G. J. Warnock. Journal of Philosophy 69, 15 (1972):460–62; Günter Gawlick "Menschheitsglück und Wille Gottes: Neues Licht auf Berkeleys Ethik." Philosophische Rundschau 1–2 (January 1973):24–42; H. M. Bracken. Eighteenth-Century Studies 3 (1973): 396–97; and Stanley Grean. Journal of the History of Philosophy 12, 3 (1974): 398–403.
  • Tipton, I. C. Berkeley, The Philosophy of Immaterialism London: Methuen, 1974. ISBN 978-0-416-70440-2
    • "Ian C. Tipton, one of the world's great Berkeley scholars and longtime president of the International Berkeley Society. ... Of the many works about Berkeley that were published in the twentieth century, few rival in importance his Berkeley: The Philosophy of Immaterialism ... The philosophical insight, combined with the mastery of Berkeley's texts, that Ian brought to this work make it one of the masterpieces of Berkeley scholarship. It is not surprising therefore that, when the Garland Publishing Company brought out, late in 1980s, a 15-volume collection of major works on Berkeley, Ian's book was one of only two full-length studies of Berkeley published after 1935 to be included" (Charles J. McCracken. In Memoriam: Ian C. Tipton // The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006), p. 4).
  • Winkler, Kenneth P. Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989. ISBN 978-0198249078
  • Walmsley, Peter (1990). The Rhetoric of Berkeley's Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521374132.
  • Berman, David. George Berkeley: Idealism and the Man. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.
  • Muehlmann, Robert G., ed. (1995). Berkeley's Metaphysics. Structural, Interpretive, and Critical Essays. Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State Press. ISBN 978-0-271-02656-5.
  • The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. (EPUP, Google Books). Ed. by Kenneth P. Winkler. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005. ISBN 978-0521450331
  • Daniel, Stephen H., ed. Reexamining Berkeley's Philosophy. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007. ISBN 978-0802093486
  • Roberts, John. A Metaphysics for the Mob: The Philosophy of George Berkeley (EPUP, Google Books). New York: Oxford University Press, 2007. – 172 p. ISBN 978-0-19-531393-2

External links

  • George Berkeley at the Eighteenth-Century Poetry Archive (ECPA)
  • Downing, Lisa. "George Berkeley". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • George Berkeley 14 June 2010 at the Wayback Machine in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Berkeley's Philosophy of Science in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • International Berkeley Society
  • A list of the published works by and about Berkeley as well as online links
  • Berkeley's Life and Works 12 July 2012 at the Wayback Machine
  • Works by George Berkeley at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by or about George Berkeley at Internet Archive
  • Works by George Berkeley at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  
  • Another perspective on how Berkeley framed his immaterialism
  • Original texts and discussion concerning The Analyst controversy
  • O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "George Berkeley", MacTutor History of Mathematics archive, University of St Andrews
  • Contains more easily readable versions of New Theory of Vision, Principles of Human Knowledge, Three Dialogues, and Alciphron
  • at the Wayback Machine (archived 17 March 2006).
  • (1887–1971):
  • Broad, C. D. Berkeley's Argument About Material Substance New York: 1975 (Repr. of the 1942 ed. publ. by the British Academy, London.)
  • Broad, C. D. Berkeley's Denial of Material Substance – Published in: The Philosophical Review Vol. LXIII (1954).
  • Rick Grush 20 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine syllabus
  • Berkeley's (1734) – digital facsimile.

george, berkeley, other, people, named, disambiguation, ɑːr, march, 1685, january, 1753, known, bishop, berkeley, bishop, cloyne, anglican, church, ireland, anglo, irish, philosopher, whose, primary, achievement, advancement, theory, called, immaterialism, lat. For other people named George Berkeley see George Berkeley disambiguation George Berkeley ˈ b ɑːr k l i 5 6 12 March 1685 14 January 1753 known as Bishop Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne of the Anglican Church of Ireland was an Anglo Irish philosopher whose primary achievement was the advancement of a theory he called immaterialism later referred to as subjective idealism by others This theory denies the existence of material substance and instead contends that familiar objects like tables and chairs are ideas perceived by the mind and as a result cannot exist without being perceived Berkeley is also known for his critique of abstraction an important premise in his argument for immaterialism 7 The Right ReverendGeorge BerkeleyBishop of CloynePortrait of Berkeley by John Smybert 1727ChurchChurch of IrelandDioceseCloyneIn office1734 1753PredecessorEdward SyngeSuccessorJames StopfordOrdersOrdination1709 deacon 1710 priest Consecration18 January 1734Personal detailsBorn 1685 03 12 12 March 1685Dysart Castle near Thomastown County Kilkenny IrelandDied14 January 1753 1753 01 14 aged 67 Oxford EnglandDenominationAnglicanSpouseAnne ForsterChildren6EducationPhilosophy careerEducationTrinity College Dublin B A 1704 M A 1707 Era18th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolSubjective idealism phenomenalism EmpiricismFoundationalism 1 Conceptualism 2 Indirect realism 3 InstitutionsTrinity College Dublin 4 Main interestsChristianity metaphysics epistemology language mathematics perceptionNotable ideasSubjective idealism esse est percipi master argument passive obedienceInfluences Bayle John Locke Isaac Newton Nicolas MalebrancheInfluenced David Hume Edmund Burke Joseph De Maistre Immanuel Kant Thomas Reid Arthur Schopenhauer John Stuart Mill Ernst Mach Bertrand Russell Jorge Luis BorgesSignatureIn 1709 Berkeley published his first major work An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision in which he discussed the limitations of human vision and advanced the theory that the proper objects of sight are not material objects but light and colour 8 This foreshadowed his chief philosophical work A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge in 1710 which after its poor reception he rewrote in dialogue form and published under the title Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous in 1713 9 In this book Berkeley s views were represented by Philonous Greek lover of mind while Hylas hyle Greek matter embodies the Irish thinker s opponents in particular John Locke Berkeley argued against Isaac Newton s doctrine of absolute space time and motion in De Motu 10 On Motion published 1721 His arguments were a precursor to the views of Ernst Mach and Albert Einstein 11 12 In 1732 he published Alciphron a Christian apologetic against the free thinkers and in 1734 he published The Analyst a critique of the foundations of calculus which was influential in the development of mathematics 13 Interest in Berkeley s work increased after World War II because he tackled many of the issues of paramount interest to philosophy in the 20th century such as the problems of perception the difference between primary and secondary qualities and the importance of language 14 Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Ireland 1 2 England and Europe 1 3 Marriage and America 1 4 Episcopate in Ireland 1 5 Humanitarian work 1 6 Last works 2 Contributions to philosophy 2 1 Theology 2 2 Relativity arguments 2 3 New theory of vision 2 4 Philosophy of physics 2 5 Berkeley s razor 2 6 Philosophy of mathematics 2 7 Moral philosophy 2 8 Immaterialism 3 Influence 4 Appearances in literature 5 Commemoration 6 Writings 6 1 Original publications 6 2 Collections 7 See also 8 References 9 Sources 9 1 Bibliographic resources 9 2 Philosophical studies 10 Further reading 11 External linksBiography EditIreland Edit This section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed January 2018 Learn how and when to remove this template message Berkeley was born at his family home Dysart Castle near Thomastown County Kilkenny Ireland the eldest son of William Berkeley a cadet of the noble family of Berkeley whose ancestry can be traced back to the Anglo Saxon period and who had served as feudal lords and landowners in Gloucester England Little is known of his mother He was educated at Kilkenny College and attended Trinity College Dublin where he was elected a Scholar in 1702 being awarded BA in 1704 and MA and a Fellowship in 1707 He remained at Trinity College after completion of his degree as a tutor and Greek lecturer His earliest publication was on mathematics but the first that brought him notice was his An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision first published in 1709 In the essay Berkeley examines visual distance magnitude position and problems of sight and touch While this work raised much controversy at the time its conclusions are now accepted as an established part of the theory of optics The next publication to appear was the Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge in 1710 which had great success and gave him a lasting reputation though few accepted his theory that nothing exists outside the mind This was followed in 1713 by Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous in which he propounded his system of philosophy the leading principle of which is that the world as represented by our senses depends for its existence on being perceived For this theory the Principles gives the exposition and the Dialogues the defence One of his main objectives was to combat the prevailing materialism of his time The theory was largely received with ridicule while even those such as Samuel Clarke and William Whiston who did acknowledge his extraordinary genius were nevertheless convinced that his first principles were false England and Europe Edit Shortly afterwards Berkeley visited England and was received into the circle of Addison Pope and Steele In the period between 1714 and 1720 he interspersed his academic endeavours with periods of extensive travel in Europe including one of the most extensive Grand Tours of the length and breadth of Italy ever undertaken 15 In 1721 he took Holy Orders in the Church of Ireland earning his doctorate in divinity and once again chose to remain at Trinity College Dublin lecturing this time in Divinity and in Hebrew In 1721 2 he was made Dean of Dromore and in 1724 Dean of Derry In 1723 following her violent quarrel with Jonathan Swift who had been her intimate friend for many years Esther Vanhomrigh for whom Swift had created the nickname Vanessa named Berkeley her co heir along with the barrister Robert Marshall her choice of legatees caused a good deal of surprise since she did not know either of them well although Berkeley as a very young man had known her father Swift said generously that he did not grudge Berkeley his inheritance much of which vanished in a lawsuit in any event A story that Berkeley and Marshall disregarded a condition of the inheritance that they must publish the correspondence between Swift and Vanessa is probably untrue In 1725 he began the project of founding a college in Bermuda for training ministers and missionaries in the colony in pursuit of which he gave up his deanery with its income of 1100 Marriage and America Edit A group portrait of Berkeley and his entourage by John Smibert Whitehall Berkeley s home in Middletown Rhode Island In 1728 he married Anne Forster daughter of John Forster Chief Justice of the Irish Common Pleas and his first wife Rebecca Monck He then went to America on a salary of 100 per annum He landed near Newport Rhode Island where he bought a plantation at Middletown the famous Whitehall Berkeley purchased several enslaved Africans to work on the plantation 16 17 It has been claimed that he introduced Palladianism into America by borrowing a design from William Kent s Designs of Inigo Jones for the door case of his house in Rhode Island Whitehall 18 He also brought to New England John Smibert the Scottish artist he discovered in Italy who is generally regarded as the founding father of American portrait painting 19 Meanwhile he drew up plans for the ideal city he planned to build on Bermuda 20 He lived at the plantation while he waited for funds for his college to arrive The funds however were not forthcoming With the withdrawal from London of his own persuasive energies opposition gathered force and the Prime Minister Walpole grew steadily more sceptical and lukewarm At last it became clear that the essential Parliamentary grant would be not forthcoming 21 and in 1732 he left America and returned to London He and Anne had four children who survived infancy Henry George William and Julia and at least two other children who died in infancy William s death in 1751 was a great cause of grief to his father Episcopate in Ireland Edit Berkeley was nominated to be the Bishop of Cloyne in the Church of Ireland on 18 January 1734 He was consecrated as such on 19 May 1734 He was the Bishop of Cloyne until his death on 14 January 1753 although he died at Oxford see below Humanitarian work Edit While living in London s Saville Street he took part in efforts to create a home for the city s abandoned children The Foundling Hospital was founded by royal charter in 1739 and Berkeley is listed as one of its original governors Last works Edit His last two publications were Siris A Chain of Philosophical Reflexions and Inquiries Concerning the Virtues of Tarwater And divers other Subjects connected together and arising one from another 1744 and Further Thoughts on Tar water 1752 Pine tar is an effective antiseptic and disinfectant when applied to cuts on the skin but Berkeley argued for the use of pine tar as a broad panacea for diseases His 1744 work on tar water sold more copies than any of his other books during Berkeley s lifetime 22 He remained at Cloyne until 1752 when he retired With his wife and daughter Julia he went to Oxford to live with his son George and supervise his education 23 He died soon afterwards and was buried in Christ Church Cathedral Oxford His affectionate disposition and genial manners made him much loved and held in warm regard by many of his contemporaries Anne outlived her husband by many years and died in 1786 24 Contributions to philosophy EditMain article Subjective idealism According to Berkeley there are only two kinds of things spirits and ideas Spirits are simple active beings which produce and perceive ideas ideas are passive beings which are produced and perceived 25 The use of the concepts of spirit and idea is central in Berkeley s philosophy As used by him these concepts are difficult to translate into modern terminology His concept of spirit is close to the concept of conscious subject or of mind and the concept of idea is close to the concept of sensation or state of mind or conscious experience Thus Berkeley denied the existence of matter as a metaphysical substance but did not deny the existence of physical objects such as apples or mountains I do not argue against the existence of any one thing that we can apprehend either by sense or reflection That the things I see with mine eyes and touch with my hands do exist really exist I make not the least question The only thing whose existence we deny is that which philosophers call matter or corporeal substance And in doing of this there is no damage done to the rest of mankind who I dare say will never miss it Principles 35 This basic claim of Berkeley s thought his idealism is sometimes and somewhat derisively called immaterialism or occasionally subjective idealism In Principles 3 he wrote using a combination of Latin and English esse is percipi to be is to be perceived most often if slightly inaccurately attributed to Berkeley as the pure Latin phrase esse est percipi 26 The phrase appears associated with him in authoritative philosophical sources e g Berkeley holds that there are no such mind independent things that in the famous phrase esse est percipi aut percipere to be is to be perceived or to perceive 22 Hence human knowledge is reduced to two elements that of spirits and of ideas Principles 86 In contrast to ideas a spirit cannot be perceived A person s spirit which perceives ideas is to be comprehended intuitively by inward feeling or reflection Principles 89 For Berkeley we have no direct idea of spirits albeit we have good reason to believe in the existence of other spirits for their existence explains the purposeful regularities we find in experience 27 It is plain that we cannot know the existence of other spirits otherwise than by their operations or the ideas by them excited in us Dialogues 145 This is the solution that Berkeley offers to the problem of other minds Finally the order and purposefulness of the whole of our experience of the world and especially of nature overwhelms us into believing in the existence of an extremely powerful and intelligent spirit that causes that order According to Berkeley reflection on the attributes of that external spirit leads us to identify it with God Thus a material thing such as an apple consists of a collection of ideas shape color taste physical properties etc which are caused in the spirits of humans by the spirit of God Theology Edit A convinced adherent of Christianity Berkeley believed God to be present as an immediate cause of all our experiences He did not evade the question of the external source of the diversity of the sense data at the disposal of the human individual He strove simply to show that the causes of sensations could not be things because what we called things and considered without grounds to be something different from our sensations were built up wholly from sensations There must consequently be some other external source of the inexhaustible diversity of sensations The source of our sensations Berkeley concluded could only be God He gave them to man who had to see in them signs and symbols that carried God s word 28 Here is Berkeley s proof of the existence of God Whatever power I may have over my own thoughts I find the ideas actually perceived by Sense have not a like dependence on my will When in broad daylight I open my eyes it is not in my power to choose whether I shall see or no or to determine what particular objects shall present themselves to my view and so likewise as to the hearing and other senses the ideas imprinted on them are not creatures of my will There is therefore some other Will or Spirit that produces them Berkeley Principles 29 As T I Oizerman explained Berkeley s mystic idealism as Kant aptly christened it claimed that nothing separated man and God except materialist misconceptions of course since nature or matter did not exist as a reality independent of consciousness The revelation of God was directly accessible to man according to this doctrine it was the sense perceived world the world of man s sensations which came to him from on high for him to decipher and so grasp the divine purpose 28 Berkeley believed that God is not the distant engineer of Newtonian machinery that in the fullness of time led to the growth of a tree in the university quadrangle Rather the perception of the tree is an idea that God s mind has produced in the mind and the tree continues to exist in the quadrangle when nobody is there simply because God is an infinite mind that perceives all The philosophy of David Hume concerning causality and objectivity is an elaboration of another aspect of Berkeley s philosophy A A Luce the most eminent Berkeley scholar of the 20th century constantly stressed the continuity of Berkeley s philosophy The fact that Berkeley returned to his major works throughout his life issuing revised editions with only minor changes also counts against any theory that attributes to him a significant volte face 29 Relativity arguments Edit See also Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous John Locke Berkeley s intellectual predecessor states that we define an object by its primary and secondary qualities He takes heat as an example of a secondary quality If you put one hand in a bucket of cold water and the other hand in a bucket of warm water then put both hands in a bucket of lukewarm water one of your hands is going to tell you that the water is cold and the other that the water is hot Locke says that since two different objects both your hands perceive the water to be hot and cold then the heat is not a quality of the water While Locke used this argument to distinguish primary from secondary qualities Berkeley extends it to cover primary qualities in the same way For example he says that size is not a quality of an object because the size of the object depends on the distance between the observer and the object or the size of the observer Since an object is a different size to different observers then size is not a quality of the object Berkeley rejects shape with a similar argument and then asks if neither primary qualities nor secondary qualities are of the object then how can we say that there is anything more than the qualities we observe clarification needed Relativity is the idea that there is no objective universal truth it is a state of dependence in which the existence of one independent object is solely dependent on that of another According to Locke characteristics of primary qualities are mind independent such as shape size etc whereas secondary qualities are mind dependent for example taste and colour George Berkeley refuted John Locke s belief on primary and secondary qualities because Berkeley believed that we cannot abstract the primary qualities e g shape from secondary ones e g colour 30 Berkeley argued that perception is dependent on the distance between the observer and the object and thus we cannot conceive of mechanist material bodies which are extended but not in themselves colored 30 What perceived can be the same type of quality but completely opposite from each other because of different positions and perceptions what we perceive can be different even when the same types of things consist of contrary qualities Secondary qualities aid in people s conception of primary qualities in an object like how the colour of an object leads people to recognize the object itself More specifically the colour red can be perceived in apples strawberries and tomatoes yet we would not know what these might look like without its colour We would also be unaware of what the colour red looked like if red paint or any object that has a perceived red colour failed to exist From this we can see that colours cannot exist on their own and can solely represent a group of perceived objects Therefore both primary and secondary qualities are mind dependent they cannot exist without our minds George Berkeley was a philosopher who was against rationalism and classical empiricism He was a subjective idealist or empirical idealist who believed that reality is constructed entirely of immaterial conscious minds and their ideas everything that exists is somehow dependent on the subject perceiving it except the subject themselves He refuted the existence of abstract objects that many other philosophers believed to exist notably Plato According to Berkeley an abstract object does not exist in space or time and which is therefore entirely non physical and non mental 31 however this argument contradicts with his relativity argument If esse est percipi 32 Latin meaning that to exist is to be perceived is true then the objects in the relativity argument made by Berkeley can either exist or not Berkeley believed that only the minds perceptions and the Spirit that perceives are what exists in reality what people perceive every day is only the idea of an object s existence but the objects themselves are not perceived Berkeley also discussed how at times materials cannot be perceived by oneself and the mind of oneself cannot understand the objects However there also exists an omnipresent eternal mind 33 that Berkeley believed to consist of God and the Spirit both omniscient and all perceiving According to Berkeley God is the entity who controls everything yet Berkeley also argued that abstract object s do not exist in space or time 31 In other words as Warnock argues Berkeley had recognized that he could not square with his own talk of spirits of our minds and of God for these are perceivers and not among objects of perception Thus he says rather weakly and without elucidation that in addition to our ideas we also have notions we know what it means to speak of spirits and their operations 34 However the relativity argument violates the idea of immaterialism Berkeley s immaterialism argues that esse est percipi aut percipere 35 which in English is to be is to be perceived or to perceive That is saying only what perceived or perceives is real and without our perception or God s nothing can be real Yet if the relativity argument also by Berkeley argues that the perception of an object depends on the different positions then this means that what perceived can either be real or not because the perception does not show that whole picture and the whole picture cannot be perceived Berkeley also believes that when one perceives mediately one perceives one idea by means of perceiving another 36 By this it can be elaborated that if the standards of what perceived at first are different what perceived after that can be different as well In the heat perception described above one hand perceived the water to be hot and the other hand perceived the water to be cold due to relativity If applying the idea to be is to be perceived the water should be both cold and hot because both perceptions are perceived by different hands However the water cannot be cold and hot at the same time for it self contradicts so this shows that what perceived is not always true because it sometimes can break the law of noncontradiction In this case it would be arbitrary anthropocentrism to claim that humans have special access to the true qualities of objects 4 The truth for different people can be different and humans are limited to accessing the absolute truth due to relativity Summing up nothing can be absolutely true due to relativity or the two arguments to be is to be perceived and the relativity argument do not always work together New theory of vision Edit In his Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision Berkeley frequently criticised the views of the Optic Writers a title that seems to include Molyneux Wallis Malebranche and Descartes 37 In sections 1 51 Berkeley argued against the classical scholars of optics by holding that spatial depth as the distance that separates the perceiver from the perceived object is itself invisible That is we do not see space directly or deduce its form logically using the laws of optics Space for Berkeley is no more than a contingent expectation that visual and tactile sensations will follow one another in regular sequences that we come to expect through habit Berkeley goes on to argue that visual cues such as the perceived extension or confusion of an object can only be used to indirectly judge distance because the viewer learns to associate visual cues with tactile sensations Berkeley gives the following analogy regarding indirect distance perception one perceives distance indirectly just as one perceives a person s embarrassment indirectly When looking at an embarrassed person we infer indirectly that the person is embarrassed by observing the red colour on the person s face We know through experience that a red face tends to signal embarrassment as we ve learned to associate the two The question concerning the visibility of space was central to the Renaissance perspective tradition and its reliance on classical optics in the development of pictorial representations of spatial depth This matter was debated by scholars since the 11th century Arab polymath and mathematician Alhazen al Hasan Ibn al Haytham affirmed in experimental contexts the visibility of space This issue which was raised in Berkeley s theory of vision was treated at length in the Phenomenology of Perception of Maurice Merleau Ponty in the context of confirming the visual perception of spatial depth la profondeur and by way of refuting Berkeley s thesis 38 Berkeley wrote about the perception of size in addition to that of distance He is frequently misquoted as believing in size distance invariance a view held by the Optic Writers This idea is that we scale the image size according to distance in a geometrical manner The error may have become commonplace because the eminent historian and psychologist E G Boring perpetuated it 39 In fact Berkeley argued that the same cues that evoke distance also evoke size and that we do not first see size and then calculate distance 40 It is worth quoting Berkeley s words on this issue Section 53 What inclines men to this mistake beside the humour of making one see by geometry is that the same perceptions or ideas which suggest distance do also suggest magnitude I say they do not first suggest distance and then leave it to the judgement to use that as a medium whereby to collect the magnitude but they have as close and immediate a connexion with the magnitude as with the distance and suggest magnitude as independently of distance as they do distance independently of magnitude Berkeley claimed that his visual theories were vindicated by a 1728 report regarding the recovery of vision in a 13 year old boy operated for congenital cataracts by surgeon William Cheselden In 2021 the name of Cheselden s patient was published for the first time Daniel Dolins 41 Berkeley knew the Dolins family had numerous social links to Cheselden including the poet Alexander Pope and Princess Caroline to whom Cheselden s patient was presented 41 The report misspelled Cheselden s name used language typical of Berkeley and may even have been ghost written by Berkeley 41 Unfortunately Dolins was never able to see well enough to read and there is no evidence that the surgery improved Dolins vision at any point prior to his death at age 30 41 Philosophy of physics Edit See also De Motu Berkeley s essay Berkeley s works display his keen interest in natural philosophy from his earliest writings Arithmetica 1707 to his latest Siris 1744 Moreover much of his philosophy is shaped fundamentally by his engagement with the science of his time 42 The profundity of this interest can be judged from numerous entries in Berkeley s Philosophical Commentaries 1707 1708 e g Mem to Examine amp accurately discuss the scholium of the 8th Definition of Mr Newton s Principia 316 Berkeley argued that forces and gravity as defined by Newton constituted occult qualities that expressed nothing distinctly He held that those who posited something unknown in a body of which they have no idea and which they call the principle of motion are in fact simply stating that the principle of motion is unknown Therefore those who affirm that active force action and the principle of motion are really in bodies are adopting an opinion not based on experience 43 Forces and gravity existed nowhere in the phenomenal world On the other hand if they resided in the category of soul or incorporeal thing they do not properly belong to physics as a matter Berkeley thus concluded that forces lay beyond any kind of empirical observation and could not be a part of proper science 44 He proposed his theory of signs as a means to explain motion and matter without reference to the occult qualities of force and gravity Berkeley s razor Edit Berkeley s razor is a rule of reasoning proposed by the philosopher Karl Popper in his study of Berkeley s key scientific work De Motu 10 Berkeley s razor is considered by Popper to be similar to Ockham s razor but more powerful It represents an extreme empiricist view of scientific observation that states that the scientific method provides us with no true insight into the nature of the world Rather the scientific method gives us a variety of partial explanations about regularities that hold in the world and that are gained through experiment The nature of the world according to Berkeley is only approached through proper metaphysical speculation and reasoning 45 Popper summarises Berkeley s razor as such A general practical result which I propose to call Berkeley s razor of Berkeley s analysis of physics allows us a priori to eliminate from physical science all essentialist explanations If they have a mathematical and predictive content they may be admitted qua mathematical hypotheses while their essentialist interpretation is eliminated If not they may be ruled out altogether This razor is sharper than Ockham s all entities are ruled out except those which are perceived 46 In another essay of the same book 47 titled Three Views Concerning Human Knowledge Popper argues that Berkeley is to be considered as an instrumentalist philosopher along with Robert Bellarmine Pierre Duhem and Ernst Mach According to this approach scientific theories have the status of serviceable fictions useful inventions aimed at explaining facts and without any pretension to being true Popper contrasts instrumentalism with the above mentioned essentialism and his own critical rationalism Philosophy of mathematics Edit In addition to his contributions to philosophy Berkeley was also very influential in the development of mathematics although in a rather indirect sense Berkeley was concerned with mathematics and its philosophical interpretation from the earliest stages of his intellectual life 7 Berkeley s Philosophical Commentaries 1707 1708 witness to his interest in mathematics Axiom No reasoning about things whereof we have no idea Therefore no reasoning about Infinitesimals 354 Take away the signs from Arithmetic amp Algebra amp pray what remains 767 These are sciences purely Verbal amp entirely useless but for Practise in Societys of Men No speculative knowledge no comparison of Ideas in them 768 In 1707 Berkeley published two treatises on mathematics In 1734 he published The Analyst subtitled A DISCOURSE Addressed to an Infidel Mathematician a critique of calculus Florian Cajori called this treatise the most spectacular event of the century in the history of British mathematics 48 However a recent study suggests that Berkeley misunderstood Leibnizian calculus 49 The mathematician in question is believed to have been either Edmond Halley or Isaac Newton himself though if to the latter then the discourse was posthumously addressed as Newton died in 1727 The Analyst represented a direct attack on the foundations and principles of calculus and in particular the notion of fluxion or infinitesimal change which Newton and Leibniz used to develop the calculus In his critique Berkeley coined the phrase ghosts of departed quantities familiar to students of calculus Ian Stewart s book From Here to Infinity captures the gist of his criticism Berkeley regarded his criticism of calculus as part of his broader campaign against the religious implications of Newtonian mechanics as a defence of traditional Christianity against deism which tends to distance God from His worshipers Specifically he observed that both Newtonian and Leibnizian calculus employed infinitesimals sometimes as positive nonzero quantities and other times as a number explicitly equal to zero Berkeley s key point in The Analyst was that Newton s calculus and the laws of motion based in calculus lacked rigorous theoretical foundations He claimed that In every other Science Men prove their Conclusions by their Principles and not their Principles by the Conclusions But if in yours you should allow your selves this unnatural way of proceeding the Consequence would be that you must take up with Induction and bid adieu to Demonstration And if you submit to this your Authority will no longer lead the way in Points of Reason and Science 50 Berkeley did not doubt that calculus produced real world truth simple physics experiments could verify that Newton s method did what it claimed to do The cause of Fluxions cannot be defended by reason 51 but the results could be defended by empirical observation Berkeley s preferred method of acquiring knowledge at any rate Berkeley however found it paradoxical that Mathematicians should deduce true Propositions from false Principles be right in Conclusion and yet err in the Premises In The Analyst he endeavoured to show how Error may bring forth Truth though it cannot bring forth Science 52 Newton s science therefore could not on purely scientific grounds justify its conclusions and the mechanical deistic model of the universe could not be rationally justified 53 The difficulties raised by Berkeley were still present in the work of Cauchy whose approach to calculus was a combination of infinitesimals and a notion of limit and were eventually sidestepped by Weierstrass by means of his e d approach which eliminated infinitesimals altogether More recently Abraham Robinson restored infinitesimal methods in his 1966 book Non standard analysis by showing that they can be used rigorously Moral philosophy Edit See also Passive obedience The tract A Discourse on Passive Obedience 1712 is considered Berkeley s major contribution to moral and political philosophy In A Discourse on Passive Obedience Berkeley defends the thesis that people have a moral duty to observe the negative precepts prohibitions of the law including the duty not to resist the execution of punishment 54 However Berkeley does make exceptions to this sweeping moral statement stating that we need not observe precepts of usurpers or even madmen 55 and that people can obey different supreme authorities if there are more than one claims to the highest authority Berkeley defends this thesis with deductive proof stemming from the laws of nature First he establishes that because God is perfectly good the end to which he commands humans must also be good and that end must not benefit just one person but the entire human race Because these commands or laws if practised would lead to the general fitness of humankind it follows that they can be discovered by the right reason for example the law to never resist supreme power can be derived from reason because this law is the only thing that stands between us and total disorder 54 Thus these laws can be called the laws of nature because they are derived from God the creator of nature himself These laws of nature include duties never to resist the supreme power lie under oath or do evil so that good may come of it 54 One may view Berkeley s doctrine on Passive Obedience as a kind of Theological Utilitarianism insofar as it states that we have a duty to uphold a moral code which presumably is working towards the ends of promoting the good of humankind However the concept of ordinary Utilitarianism is fundamentally different in that it makes utility the one and only ground of obligation 56 that is Utilitarianism is concerned with whether particular actions are morally permissible in specific situations while Berkeley s doctrine is concerned with whether or not we should follow moral rules in any and all circumstances Whereas Act Utilitarianism might for example justify a morally impermissible act in light of the specific situation Berkeley s doctrine of Passive Obedience holds that it is never morally permissible to not follow a moral rule even when it seems like breaking that moral rule might achieve the happiest ends Berkeley holds that even though sometimes the consequences of an action in a specific situation might be bad the general tendencies of that action benefit humanity Other important sources for Berkeley s views on morality are Alciphron 1732 especially dialogues I III and the Discourse to Magistrates 1738 57 Passive Obedience is notable partly for containing one of the earliest statements of rule utilitarianism 58 Immaterialism Edit George Berkeley s theory that matter does not exist comes from the belief that sensible things are those only which are immediately perceived by sense 59 Berkeley says in his book called The Principles of Human Knowledge that the ideas of sense are stronger livelier and clearer than those of the imagination and they are also steady orderly and coherent 60 From this we can tell that the things that we are perceiving are truly real rather than it just being a dream All knowledge comes from perception what we perceive are ideas not things in themselves a thing in itself must be outside experience so the world only consists of ideas and minds that perceive those ideas a thing only exists so far as it perceives or is perceived 61 Through this we can see that consciousness is considered something that exists to Berkeley due to its ability to perceive To be said of the object means to be perceived esse est percipi to be said of the subject means to perceive or percipere 62 Having established this Berkeley then attacks the opinion strangely prevailing amongst men that houses mountains rivers and in a word all sensible objects have an existence natural or real distinct from being perceived 60 He believes this idea to be inconsistent because such an object with an existence independent of perception must have both sensible qualities and thus be known making it an idea and also an insensible reality which Berkeley believes is inconsistent 63 Berkeley believes that the error arises because people think that perceptions can imply or infer something about the material object Berkeley calls this concept abstract ideas He rebuts this concept by arguing that people cannot conceive of an object without also imagining the sensual input of the object He argues in Principles of Human Knowledge that similar to how people can only sense matter with their senses through the actual sensation they can only conceive of matter or rather ideas of matter through the idea of sensation of matter 60 This implies that everything that people can conceive in regards to matter is only ideas about matter Thus matter should it exist must exist as collections of ideas which can be perceived by the senses and interpreted by the mind But if matter is just a collection of ideas then Berkeley concludes that matter in the sense of a material substance does not exist as most philosophers of Berkeley s time believed Indeed if a person visualizes something then it must have some colour however dark or light it cannot just be a shape of no colour at all if a person is to visualize it 64 Berkeley s ideas raised controversy because his argument refuted Descartes worldview which was expanded upon by Locke and resulted in the rejection of Berkeley s form of empiricism by several philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries In Locke s worldview the world causes the perceptual ideas we have of it by the way it interacts with our senses 61 This contradicts with Berkeley s worldview because not only does it suggest the existence of physical causes in the world but in fact there is no physical world beyond our ideas The only causes that exist in Berkeley s worldview are those that are a result of the use of the will Berkeley s theory relies heavily on his form of empiricism which in turn relies heavily on the senses His empiricism can be defined by five propositions all significant words stand for ideas all knowledge of things is about ideas all ideas come from without or from within if from without it must be by the senses and they are called sensations the real things if from within they are the operations of the mind and are called thoughts 64 Berkeley clarifies his distinction between ideas by saying they are imprinted on the senses perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind or are formed by help of memory and imagination 64 One refutation of his idea was if someone leaves a room and stops perceiving that room does that room no longer exist Berkeley answers this by claiming that it is still being perceived and the consciousness that is doing the perceiving is God This makes Berkeley s argument hinge upon an omniscient omnipresent deity This claim is the only thing holding up his argument which is depending for our knowledge of the world and of the existence of other minds upon a God that would never deceive us 61 Berkeley anticipates a second objection which he refutes in Principles of Human Knowledge He anticipates that the materialist may take a representational materialist standpoint although the senses can only perceive ideas these ideas resemble and thus can be compared to the actual existing object Thus through the sensing of these ideas the mind can make inferences as to matter itself even though pure matter is non perceivable Berkeley s objection to that notion is that an idea can be like nothing but an idea a colour or figure can be like nothing but another colour or figure 60 Berkeley distinguishes between an idea which is mind dependent and a material substance which is not an idea and is mind independent As they are not alike they cannot be compared just as one cannot compare the colour red to something that is invisible or the sound of music to silence other than that one exists and the other does not This is called the likeness principle the notion that an idea can only be like and thus compared to another idea Berkeley attempted to show how ideas manifest themselves into different objects of knowledge It is evident to anyone who takes a survey of the objects of human knowledge that they are either ideas actually imprinted on the senses or else such as are perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind or lastly ideas formed by help of memory and imagination either compounding dividing or barely representing those originally perceived in the aforesaid ways Berkeley s emphasis 65 Berkeley also attempted to prove the existence of God throughout his beliefs in immaterialism 4 Influence EditBerkeley s Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge was published three years before the publication of Arthur Collier s Clavis Universalis which made assertions similar to those of Berkeley s 66 However there seemed to have been no influence or communication between the two writers 67 German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer once wrote of him Berkeley was therefore the first to treat the subjective starting point really seriously and to demonstrate irrefutably its absolute necessity He is the father of idealism 68 Berkeley is considered one of the originators of British empiricism 69 A linear development is often traced from three great British Empiricists leading from Locke through Berkeley to Hume 70 Berkeley influenced many modern philosophers especially David Hume Thomas Reid admitted that he put forward a drastic criticism of Berkeleianism after he had been an admirer of Berkeley s philosophical system for a long time 71 Berkeley s thought made possible the work of Hume and thus Kant notes Alfred North Whitehead 72 Some authors who draw a parallel between Berkeley and Edmund Husserl clarification needed 73 When Berkeley visited America the American educator Samuel Johnson visited him and the two later corresponded Johnson convinced Berkeley to establish a scholarship program at Yale and to donate a large number of books as well as his plantation to the college when the philosopher returned to England It was one of Yale s largest and most important donations it doubled its library holdings improved the college s financial position and brought Anglican religious ideas and English culture into New England 74 Johnson also took Berkeley s philosophy and used parts of it as a framework for his own American Practical Idealism school of philosophy As Johnson s philosophy was taught to about half the graduates of American colleges between 1743 and 1776 75 and over half of the contributors to the Declaration of Independencewere connected to it 76 Berkeley s ideas were indirectly a foundation of the American Mind Outside of America during Berkeley s lifetime his philosophical ideas were comparatively uninfluential 77 But interest in his doctrine grew from the 1870s when Alexander Campbell Fraser the leading Berkeley scholar of the nineteenth century 78 published The Works of George Berkeley A powerful impulse to serious studies in Berkeley s philosophy was given by A A Luce and Thomas Edmund Jessop two of the twentieth century s foremost Berkeley scholars 79 thanks to whom Berkeley scholarship was raised to the rank of a special area of historico philosophical science In addition the philosopher Colin Murray Turbayne wrote extensively on Berkeley s use of language as a model for visual physiological natural and metaphysical relationships 80 81 82 83 The proportion of Berkeley scholarship in literature on the history of philosophy is increasing This can be judged from the most comprehensive bibliographies on George Berkeley During the period of 1709 1932 about 300 writings on Berkeley were published That amounted to 1 5 publications per annum During the course of 1932 79 over one thousand works were brought out i e 20 works per annum Since then the number of publications has reached 30 per annum 84 In 1977 publication began in Ireland of a special journal on Berkeley s life and thought Berkeley Studies In 1988 the Australian philosopher Colin Murray Turbayne established the International Berkeley Essay Prize Competition at the University of Rochester in an effort to advance scholarship and research on the works of Berkeley 85 86 Other than philosophy Berkeley also influenced modern psychology with his work on John Locke s theory of association and how it could be used to explain how humans gain knowledge in the physical world He also used the theory to explain perception stating that all qualities were as Locke would call them secondary qualities therefore perception laid entirely in the perceiver and not in the object These are both topics today studied in modern psychology 87 Appearances in literature EditLord Byron s Don Juan references immaterialism in the Eleventh Canto When Bishop Berkeley said there was no matter And proved it t was no matter what he said They say his system t is in vain to batter Too subtle for the airiest human head And yet who can believe it I would shatter Gladly all matters down to stone or lead Or adamant to find the world a spirit And wear my head denying that I wear it Herman Melville humorously references Berkeley in Chapter 20 of Mardi 1849 when outlining a character s belief of being on board a ghostship And here be it said that for all his superstitious misgivings about the brigantine his imputing to her something equivalent to a purely phantom like nature honest Jarl was nevertheless exceedingly downright and practical in all hints and proceedings concerning her Wherein he resembled my Right Reverend friend Bishop Berkeley truly one of your lords spiritual who metaphysically speaking holding all objects to be mere optical delusions was notwithstanding extremely matter of fact in all matters touching matter itself Besides being pervious to the points of pins and possessing a palate capable of appreciating plum puddings which sentence reads off like a pattering of hailstones James Joyce references Berkeley s philosophy in the third episode of Ulysses 1922 Who watches me here Who ever anywhere will read these written words Signs on a white field Somewhere to someone in your flutiest voice The good bishop of Cloyne took the veil of the temple out of his shovel hat veil of space with coloured emblems hatched on its field Hold hard Coloured on a flat yes that s right Flat I see then think distance near far flat I see east back Ah see now In commenting on a review of Ada or Ardor author Vladimir Nabokov alludes to Berkeley s philosophy as informing his novel And finally I owe no debt whatsoever as Mr Leonard seems to think to the famous Argentine essayist and his rather confused compilation A New Refutation of Time Mr Leonard would have lost less of it had he gone straight to Berkeley and Bergson Strong Opinions pp 2892 90 James Boswell in the part of his Life of Samuel Johnson covering the year 1763 recorded Johnson s opinion of one aspect of Berkeley s philosophy After we came out of the church we stood talking for some time together of Bishop Berkeley s ingenious sophistry to prove the non existence of matter and that every thing in the universe is merely ideal I observed that though we are satisfied his doctrine is untrue it is impossible to refute it I shall never forget the alacrity with which Johnson answered striking his foot with mighty force against a large stone till he rebounded from it I refute it thus Commemoration EditBoth the University of California Berkeley and the city of Berkeley California were named after him although the pronunciation has evolved to suit American English ˈ b ɜːr k l i BURK lee The naming was suggested in 1866 by Frederick H Billings a trustee of the then College of California Billings was inspired by Berkeley s Verses on the Prospect of Planting Arts and Learning in America particularly the final stanza Westward the course of empire takes its way the first four Acts already past a fifth shall close the Drama with the day time s noblest offspring is the last 88 The Town of Berkley currently the least populated town in Bristol County Massachusetts was founded on 18 April 1735 and named after the renowned philosopher It is located 40 miles south of Boston and 25 miles north of Middletown Rhode Island A residential college and an Episcopal seminary at Yale University also bear Berkeley s name Berkeley Preparatory School in Tampa Florida a private school affiliated with the Episcopal Church is also named for him Bishop Berkeley s Gold Medals are two awards given annually at Trinity College Dublin provided outstanding merit is shown to candidates answering a special examination in Greek The awards were founded in 1752 by Berkeley 89 An Ulster History Circle blue plaque commemorating him is located in Bishop Street Within city of Derry Berkeley s farmhouse in Middletown Rhode Island is preserved as Whitehall Museum House also known as Berkeley House and was listed on the National Register of Historic Places in 1970 St Columba s Chapel located in the same town was formerly named The Berkeley Memorial Chapel and the appellation still survives at the end of the formal name of the parish St Columba s the Berkeley Memorial Chapel Writings EditOriginal publications Edit Arithmetica 1707 Miscellanea Mathematica 1707 Philosophical Commentaries or Common Place Book 1707 08 notebooks An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision 1709 A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge Part I 1710 Passive Obedience or the Christian doctrine of not resisting the Supreme Power 1712 Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous 1713 An Essay Towards Preventing the Ruin of Great Britain 1721 De Motu 1721 A Proposal for Better Supplying Churches in our Foreign Plantations and for converting the Savage Americans to Christianity by a College to be erected in the Summer Islands 1725 A Sermon preached before the incorporated Society for the Propagation of the Gospel in Foreign Parts 1732 Alciphron or the Minute Philosopher 1732 Essays toward a new theory of vision in Italian Venezia Francesco Storti 2 1732 The Theory of Vision or Visual Language shewing the immediate presence and providence of a Deity vindicated and explained 1733 The Analyst a Discourse addressed to an Infidel Mathematician 1734 A Defence of Free thinking in Mathematics with Appendix concerning Mr Walton s vindication of Sir Isaac Newton s Principle of Fluxions 1735 Reasons for not replying to Mr Walton s Full Answer 1735 The Querist containing several queries proposed to the consideration of the public three parts 1735 37 A Discourse addressed to Magistrates and Men of Authority 1736 Siris a chain of philosophical reflections and inquiries concerning the virtues of tar water 1744 A Letter to the Roman Catholics of the Diocese of Cloyne 1745 A Word to the Wise or an exhortation to the Roman Catholic clergy of Ireland 1749 Maxims concerning Patriotism 1750 Farther Thoughts on Tar water 1752 Miscellany 1752 Collections Edit The Works of George Berkeley D D Late Bishop of Cloyne in Ireland To which is added an account of his life and several of his letters to Thomas Prior Esq Dean Gervais and Mr Pope amp c amp c Printed for George Robinson Pater Noster Row 1784 Two volumes The Works of George Berkeley D D formerly Bishop of Cloyne Including Many of His Writings Hitherto Unpublished With Prefaces Annotations His Life and Letters and an Account of His Philosophy Ed by Alexander Campbell Fraser In 4 Volumes Oxford Clarendon Press 1901 Vol 1 Vol 2 Vol 3 Vol 4 The Works of George Berkeley Ed by A A Luce and T E Jessop Nine volumes Edinburgh and London 1948 1957 Ewald William B ed 1996 From Kant to Hilbert A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics 2 vols Oxford Uni Press 1707 Of Infinites 16 19 1709 Letter to Samuel Molyneaux 19 21 1721 De Motu 37 54 1734 The Analyst 60 92 See also EditList of people on stamps of Ireland Solipsism Tlon Uqbar Orbis Tertius Yogacara and consciousness only schools of thoughtReferences Edit Fumerton Richard 21 February 2000 Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 19 August 2018 David Bostock Philosophy of Mathematics An Introduction Wiley Blackwell 2009 p 43 All of Descartes Locke Berkeley and Hume supposed that mathematics is a theory of our ideas but none of them offered any argument for this conceptualist claim and apparently took it to be uncontroversial The Problem of Perception Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Paraphrasing David Hume 1739 see also Locke 1690 Berkeley 1710 Russell 1912 nothing is ever directly present to the mind in perception except perceptual appearances a b c Downing Lisa George Berkeley Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Retrieved 9 December 2019 Watson Richard A 1993 1994 Berkeley Is Pronounced Barclay PDF Berkeley Newsletter 13 1 3 Archived from the original PDF on 3 July 2013 Retrieved 8 November 2010 Berkeley entry in Collins English Dictionary a b Douglas M Jesseph 2005 Berkeley s philosophy of mathematics In Kenneth P Winkler ed The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 266 ISBN 978 0 521 45033 1 See Berkeley George 1709 An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision 2 ed Dublin Jeremy Pepyat Turbayne C M September 1959 Berkeley s Two Concepts of Mind Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 1 85 92 doi 10 2307 2104957 JSTOR 2104957 Repr in Engle Gale Taylor Gabriele 1968 Berkeley s Principles of Human Knowledge Critical Studies Belmont CA Wadsworth pp 24 33 In this collection of essays Turbayne s work comprised two papers that had been published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Berkeley s Two Concepts of Mind C Turbayne s reply to S A Grave A Note on Berkeley s Conception of the Mind Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 1962 vol 22 No 4 JSTOR 2105263 doi 10 2307 2105263 a b Berkeley s Philosophical Writings New York Collier 1974 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 64 22680 Popper K R 1 May 1953 A note on Berkeley as precursor of Mach The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science IV 13 26 36 doi 10 1093 bjps IV 13 26 S2CID 123072861 Also published Conjectures and Refutations Volume I A note on Berkeley as precursor of Mach and Einstein Routledge and Kegan Paul 1969 jhollandtranslations com Turbayne Colin ed 1982 Berkeley critical and interpretive essays Minneapolis MN University of Minnesota Press ISBN 978 0 8166 1065 5 Edward Chaney George Berkeley s Grand Tours The Immaterialist as Connoisseur of Art and Architecture in E Chaney The Evolution of the Grand Tour Anglo Italian Cultural Relations since the Renaissance 2nd ed London Routledge 2000 ISBN 0714644749 First Scholarship Fund www yaleslavery org Retrieved 28 June 2020 Humphreys Joe What to do about George Berkeley Trinity figurehead and slave owner The Irish Times Chaney Edward The Evolution of the Grand Tour Anglo Italian Cultural Relations Since the Renaissance Frank Cass Publishers 2000 324 John Smibert Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 15 August 2016 E Chaney George Berkeley s Grand Tours Evolution of the Grand Tour p 324 Geoffrey J Warnock Introduction to George Berkeley A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge Open Court La Salle 1986 p 9 a b Downing Lisa George Berkeley The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2013 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Retrieved 21 August 2013 Downing Lisa 2013 Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2013 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Pope in his Satires Epistles and Odes of Horace Epilogue to the Satires Dialogue ii line 73 refers to God granting To Berkeley every Virtue under Heaven Bettcher T M Berkeley A Guide for the Perplexed Continuum Publishing 2008 p 14 Fogelin Robert Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge Routledge 2001 p 27 Fogelin Robert Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge Routledge 2001 pp 74 75 a b Oizerman T I The Main Trends in Philosophy A Theoretical Analysis of the History of Philosophy Moscow 1988 p 78 Berkeley George Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 24 June 2022 a b Downing Lisa George Berkeley Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Retrieved 11 December 2019 a b Balaguer Mark 12 May 2004 Platonism in Metaphysics Retrieved 11 December 2019 George Berkeley The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne PDF London Thomas Nelson and Sons Retrieved 11 December 2019 The Cambridge History of English and American Literature in 18 Volumes 1907 21 G Warnock Introduction to G Berkeley A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge Open Court La Salle 1986 p 29 George Berkeley The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne PDF London Thomas Nelson and Sons Retrieved 9 December 2019 George Berkeley 1685 1753 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 9 December 2019 Schwartz R 1994 Vision Variations on some Berkeleian themes Oxford Blackwell p 54 For recent studies on this topic refer to Nader El Bizri La perception de la profondeur Alhazen Berkeley et Merleau Ponty Oriens Occidens Cahiers du centre d histoire des sciences et des philosophies arabes et medievales Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique Vol 5 2004 pp 171 84 See also Nader El Bizri A Philosophical Perspective on Alhazen s Optics Arabic Sciences and Philosophy Vol 15 2005 pp 189 218 Cambridge University Press journal doi 10 1017 S0957423905000172 Boring E G 1942 Sensation and perception in the history of experimental psychology New York Appleton Century Crofts pp 223 298 Ross H E Plug C 1998 The history of size constancy and size illusions In Walsh V amp Kulikowski J Eds Perceptual constancy Why things look as they do Cambridge Cambridge University Press 499 528 a b c d Leffler CT Schwartz SG February 2021 The First Cataract Surgeons in the British Isles American Journal of Ophthalmology 230 75 122 doi 10 1016 j ajo 2021 03 009 PMC 8446104 PMID 33744237 Lisa Downing 2005 Berkeley s natural philosophy and philosophy of science In Kenneth P Winkler ed The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 230 ISBN 978 0 521 45033 1 De Motu in Berkeley George and Jessop T E The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne London Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd 1948 1957 4 36 37 Downing Lisa Berkeley s Case Against Realism About Dynamics In Robert G Muehlmann ed Berkeley s Metaphysics Structural Interpretive and Critical Essays The Pennsylvania State University Press 1995 To be of service to reckoning and mathematical demonstrations is one thing to set forth the nature of things is another De Motu cited by G Warnock in the introduction to A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge Open Court La Salle 1986 p 24 Karl Popper Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge New York Routledge 2002 p 231 K Popper Conjectures and Refutations Part I 3 Florian Cajori 2010 A History of the Conceptions of Limits and Fluxions in Great Britain from Newton to Woodhouse BiblioBazaar ISBN 978 1 143 05698 7 Katz Mikhail Sherry David 2012 Leibniz s Infinitesimals Their Fictionality Their Modern Implementations and Their Foes from Berkeley to Russell and Beyond Erkenntnis 78 3 571 625 arXiv 1205 0174 doi 10 1007 s10670 012 9370 y S2CID 119329569 The Analyst in Berkeley George and Jessop T E The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne London Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd 1948 1957 4 76 Defence of Free Thinking in Mathematics in Berkeley George and Jessop T E The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne London Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd 1948 1957 4 113 The Analyst in Berkeley George and Jessop T E The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne London Thomas Nelson and Son Ltd 1948 1957 4 77 Cantor Geoffrey Berkeley s The Analyst Revisited Isis Vol 75 No 4 Dec 1984 pp 668 83 JSTOR 232412 doi 10 1086 353648 a b c Hayry Matti Passive Obedience and Berkeley s Moral Philosophy Berkeley Studies 23 2012 3 13 Berkeley George Passive Obedience Or the Christian Doctrine of Not Resisting the Supreme Power Proved and Vindicated In a Discourse Deliver d at the College chapel By George Berkeley M A Fellow of Trinity College Dublin London Printed for H Clements 1712 Print Berkeley s Theory of Morals www ditext com Retrieved 27 May 2016 Jakapi Roomet Was Berkeley a Utilitarian Lemetti Juhana and Piirimae Eva eds Human Nature as the Basis of Morality and Society in Early Modern Philosophy Acta Philosophica Fennica 83 Helsinki Philosophical Society of Finland 2007 p 53 The article contains extensive cover of literature on the topic from Alexander Campbell Fraser to up to date investigations including Matti Hayry s article on Berkeley s ethics Hooker Brad 2008 Rule Consequentialism In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Berkeley George and Howard Robinson Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues Oxford Oxford University Press 2009 a b c d Berkeley George Principles of Human Knowledge The Empiricists Locke Berkeley and Hume Anchor Books 1974 pp 151 62 a b c Buckingham Will To Be Is To Be Perceived The Philosophy Book Big Ideas Simply Explained DK Publishing New York 2011 pp 138 41 The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica George Berkeley Encyclopaedia Britannica Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc 2012 Accessed 15 March 2017 Flage Daniel E George Berkeley Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy www iep utm edu berkeley Accessed 20 May 2019 a b c Urmson J O et al The Attack on Matter British Empiricists Oxford University Press Oxford 1992 pp 106 24 George Berkeley A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge Open Court La Salle 1986 p 65 Reid T Ed by William Hamilton 1852 The Works of Thomas Reid now fully collected Edinburgh Maclachlan and Stewart Retrieved 1 December 2010 see Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man II X a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint postscript link p 287 Reid T Ed by William Hamilton 1852 The Works of Thomas Reid now fully collected Edinburgh Maclachlan and Stewart Retrieved 1 December 2010 see Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man VI VII a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint postscript link p 464 Parerga and Paralipomena Vol I Fragments for the History of Philosophy 12 Rick Grush Archived 20 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine syllabus Empiricism J Locke G Berkeley D Hume Archived 15 November 2009 at the Wayback Machine McCracken Charles J and Tipton Ian eds Berkeley s Principles and Dialogues Background Source Materials Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2000 p 5 The editor s Introduction Archived 6 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine Reid T Inquiry into the Human Mind Dedication Cited from Steinkraus W E Berkeley epistemology and science Idealistic Studies Worcester 1984 Vol 14 no 3 p 184 Philipse H Transcendental Idealism in The Cambridge Companion to Husserl Ed by Barry Smith amp David Woodruff Smith Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1995 pp 239 322 The paper constitutes a discussion on the relation between Husserl s transcendental idealism and the idealist positions of Berkeley and Kant Hoeveler J David Creating the American Mind Intellect and Politics in the Colonial Colleges Rowman amp Littlefield 2007 ISBN 978 0742548398 p 63 Olsen Neil C Pursuing Happiness The Organizational Culture of the Continental Congress Nonagram Publications 2013 ISBN 978 1480065505 p 179 Olsen Neil C Pursuing Happiness The Organizational Culture of the Continental Congress Nonagram Publications 2013 ISBN 978 1480065505 p 299 See Bracken Harry M 1965 The Early Reception of Berkeley s Immaterialism 1965 revision of the 1959 ed The Hague Martinus Nijhoff p 1 McCracken Charles J and Tipton Ian eds Berkeley s Principles and Dialogues Background Source Materials Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2000 p 6 Editor s Introduction Archived 6 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine Charles J McCracken Berkeley s Realism New Interpretations of Berkeley s Thought Ed by S H Daniel New York Humanity Books 2008 p 24 ISBN 978 1 59102 557 3 Charles J McCracken Berkeley s Realism New Interpretations of Berkeley s Thought Ed by S H Daniel New York Humanity Books 2008 p 25 ISBN 978 1 59102 557 3 The Rhetoric of Empiricism Jules David Law Cornell University Press London 1993 ISBN 0 8014 2706 1 p 98 on books google com Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 20 No 1 Sept 1959 pp 85 92 Berkeley s Two Concepts of Mind Colin Murray Turbayne on JSTOR org Dialectic Vol 8 No 3 Sept 15 1954 pp 210 227 Berkeley and Russell On Space Colin Murray Turbayne on JSTOR org Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 22 No 3 March 1962 pp 383 386 Berkeley s Two Concepts of Mind Part II Colin Murray Turbayne on JSTOR org See Jessop T E Luce A A A bibliography of George Berkeley 2 edn Springer 1973 ISBN 978 90 247 1577 0 Turbayne C M A Bibliography of George Berkeley 1963 1979 Berkeley Critical and Interpretive Essays EPUP Google Books Ed by C M Turbayne Manchester 1982 pp 313 29 Parigi Silvia Berkeley Bibliography 1979 2010 Archived 3 July 2013 at the Wayback Machine International Berkeley Society Turbayne Essay Prize on internationalberkeleysociety org University of Rochester Department of Philosophy George Berkeley Essay Prize Competition on sas rochester edu Schultz Duane P 2008 A History of Modern Psychology ninth ed Belmont CA Thomas Higher Education ISBN 978 0 495 09799 0 Why Is Berkeley Called Berkeley Berkeley Historical Society Retrieved 15 August 2016 Prizes and Other Awards Trinity College Dublin Calendar 2016 17 p 369 Retrieved 16 April 2017 Sources EditBibliographic resources Edit Jessop T E Luce A A A bibliography of George Berkeley 2 edn Springer 1973 ISBN 978 90 247 1577 0 Turbayne C M A Bibliography of George Berkeley 1963 1979 in Berkeley Critical and Interpretive Essays via Google Books Manchester 1982 pp 313 29 Berkeley Bibliography 1979 2010 Archived 3 July 2013 at the Wayback Machine A Supplement to those of Jessop and Turbayne by Silvia Parigi A Bibliography on George Berkeley About 300 works from the 19th century to our days Philosophical studies Edit Daniel Stephen H ed Re examining Berkeley s Philosophy Toronto University of Toronto Press 2007 Daniel Stephen H ed New Interpretations of Berkeley s Thought Amherst Humanity Books 2008 Dicker Georges Berkeley s Idealism A Critical Examination Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2011 Gaustad Edwin George Berkeley in America New Haven Yale University Press 1959 Pappas George S Berkeley s Thought Ithaca Cornell University Press 2000 Stoneham Tom Berkeley s World An Examination of the Three Dialogues Oxford University Press 2002 Warnock Geoffrey J Berkeley Penguin Books 1953 Winkler Kenneth P The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2005 Attribution This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Cousin John William 1910 A Short Biographical Dictionary of English Literature London J M Dent amp Sons via Wikisource Further reading EditSee also Category George Berkeley scholars Adamson Robert Mitchell John Malcolm 1911 Berkeley George Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 3 11th ed pp 779 781 R H Nichols F A Wray 1935 The History of the Foundling Hospital London Oxford Univ Press p 349 John Daniel Wild 1962 George Berkeley a study of his life and philosophy New York Russell amp Russell Brook Richard J 1973 Berkeley s Philosophy of Science The Hague Martinus Nijhoff ISBN 978 90 247 1555 8 Turbayne Colin Murray 1982 Berkeley Critical and Interpretive Essays Minneapolis MN University of Minnesota Press ISBN 0 8166 1065 7 Muehlmann Robert G 1992 Berkeley s Ontology Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 0 87220 146 5 Shows a thorough mastery of the literature on Berkeley along with very perceptive remarks about the strength and weaknesses of most of the central commentators Exhibits a mastery of all the material both primary and secondary Charles Larmore for the Editorial Board Journal of Philosophy R Muehlmann is one of the Berkeley Prize Winners Edward Chaney 2000 George Berkeley s Grand Tours The Immaterialist as Connoisseur of Art and Architecture in E Chaney The Evolution of the Grand Tour Anglo Italian Cultural Relations since the Renaissance 2nd ed London Routledge ISBN 0714644749 Paul Strathern 2000 Berkeley in ninety minutes Ivan R Dee ISBN 978 1 56663 291 1 Fogelin Robert 2001 Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge Routledge Costica Bradatan 2006 The Other Bishop Berkeley An Exercise in Reenchantment Fordham University Press New York New Interpretations of Berkeley s Thought Ed by S H Daniel New York Humanity Books 2008 319 pp ISBN 978 1 59102 557 3 For reviews see Reviewed by Marc A Hight Archived 15 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine Hampden Sydney College Reviewed by Thomas M Lennon Archived 17 October 2013 at the Wayback Machine Berkeley Studies 19 2008 51 56 Secondary literature available on the InternetMost sources listed below are suggested by Dr Talia M Bettcher in Berkeley a Guide for the Perplexed 2008 See the textbook s description Johnston G A 1923 The Development of Berkeley s Philosophy London Macmillan Luce A A Berkeley and Malebranche A Study in the Origins of Berkeley s Thought Oxford Oxford University Press 1934 2nd edn with additional Preface 1967 Russell B Berkeley Bertrand Russell A History of Western Philosophy 3 1 16 1945 Turbayne Colin Murray 1959 Berkeley s Two Concepts of Mind Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 20 No 1 Sept 1959 pp 85 92 on JSTOR org Turbayne Colin Murray 1962 Berkeley s Two Concepts of Mind Part II Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 22 No 3 March 1962 pp 383 386 on JSTOR org Olscamp Paul J 1970 The Moral Philosophy of George Berkeley The Hague Martinus Nijhoff olscamp moral philosophy of george berkeley Reviewed by Desiree Park Studi internazionali filosofici 3 1971 228 30 G J Warnock Journal of Philosophy 69 15 1972 460 62 Gunter Gawlick Menschheitsgluck und Wille Gottes Neues Licht auf Berkeleys Ethik Philosophische Rundschau 1 2 January 1973 24 42 H M Bracken Eighteenth Century Studies 3 1973 396 97 and Stanley Grean Journal of the History of Philosophy 12 3 1974 398 403 Tipton I C Berkeley The Philosophy of Immaterialism London Methuen 1974 ISBN 978 0 416 70440 2 Ian C Tipton one of the world s great Berkeley scholars and longtime president of the International Berkeley Society Of the many works about Berkeley that were published in the twentieth century few rival in importance his Berkeley The Philosophy of Immaterialism The philosophical insight combined with the mastery of Berkeley s texts that Ian brought to this work make it one of the masterpieces of Berkeley scholarship It is not surprising therefore that when the Garland Publishing Company brought out late in 1980s a 15 volume collection of major works on Berkeley Ian s book was one of only two full length studies of Berkeley published after 1935 to be included Charles J McCracken In Memoriam Ian C Tipton The Berkeley Newsletter 17 2006 p 4 Winkler Kenneth P Berkeley An Interpretation Oxford Clarendon Press 1989 ISBN 978 0198249078 Walmsley Peter 1990 The Rhetoric of Berkeley s Philosophy Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521374132 Berman David George Berkeley Idealism and the Man Oxford Clarendon Press 1994 Muehlmann Robert G ed 1995 Berkeley s Metaphysics Structural Interpretive and Critical Essays Pennsylvania Pennsylvania State Press ISBN 978 0 271 02656 5 The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley EPUP Google Books Ed by Kenneth P Winkler Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2005 ISBN 978 0521450331 Daniel Stephen H ed Reexamining Berkeley s Philosophy Toronto University of Toronto Press 2007 ISBN 978 0802093486 Roberts John A Metaphysics for the Mob The Philosophy of George Berkeley EPUP Google Books New York Oxford University Press 2007 172 p ISBN 978 0 19 531393 2 Reviewed by Marc A Hight Archived 15 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine University of Tartu Hampden Sydney CollegeExternal links EditThis article s use of external links may not follow Wikipedia s policies or guidelines Please improve this article by removing excessive or inappropriate external links and converting useful links where appropriate into footnote references March 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Wikisource has original works by or about George Berkeley Wikiquote has quotations related to George Berkeley George Berkeley at the Eighteenth Century Poetry Archive ECPA Downing Lisa George Berkeley In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy George Berkeley Archived 14 June 2010 at the Wayback Machine in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Berkeley s Philosophy of Science in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy International Berkeley Society A list of the published works by and about Berkeley as well as online links Berkeley s Life and Works Archived 12 July 2012 at the Wayback Machine Works by George Berkeley at Project Gutenberg Works by or about George Berkeley at Internet Archive Works by George Berkeley at LibriVox public domain audiobooks Another perspective on how Berkeley framed his immaterialism Original texts and discussion concerning The Analyst controversy O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F George Berkeley MacTutor History of Mathematics archive University of St Andrews Contains more easily readable versions of New Theory of Vision Principles of Human Knowledge Three Dialogues and Alciphron An extensive compendium of online resources including a gallery of Berkeley s images A version of Berkeley s PHK condensed and rewritten for faster reading at the Wayback Machine archived 17 March 2006 Electronic Texts for philosopher Charlie Dunbar 1887 1971 Broad C D Berkeley s Argument About Material Substance New York 1975 Repr of the 1942 ed publ by the British Academy London Broad C D Berkeley s Denial of Material Substance Published in The Philosophical Review Vol LXIII 1954 Rick Grush Archived 20 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine syllabus Empiricism J Locke G Berkeley D Hume Berkeley s 1734 The Analyst digital facsimile Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title George Berkeley amp oldid 1152125750, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.