fbpx
Wikipedia

Noumenon

In philosophy, a noumenon (/ˈnmənɒn/, /ˈn-/; from Ancient Greek νoούμενον; plural noumena) is knowledge[1] posited as an object that exists independently of human sense.[2] The term noumenon is generally used in contrast with, or in relation to, the term phenomenon, which refers to any object of the senses. Immanuel Kant first developed the notion of the noumenon as part of his transcendental idealism, suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because human sensibility is merely receptive, it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwise unknowable to us.[3] In Kantian philosophy, the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable "thing-in-itself" (German: Ding an sich). However, the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant's work, and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result.

Etymology

The Greek word νοούμενoν, nooúmenon (plural νοούμενα, nooúmena) is the neuter middle-passive present participle of νοεῖν, noeîn, 'to think, to mean', which in turn originates from the word νοῦς, noûs, an Attic contracted form of νόος, nóos, 'perception, understanding, mind'.[a][4][5] A rough equivalent in English would be "something that is thought", or "the object of an act of thought".

Historical predecessors

Regarding the equivalent concepts in Plato, Ted Honderich writes: "Platonic Ideas and Forms are noumena, and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the senses... This dichotomy is the most characteristic feature of Plato's dualism; that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge, truths, and values is Plato's principal legacy to philosophy."[6]

Kantian noumena

Overview

As expressed in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, human understanding is structured by "concepts of the understanding" or pure categories of understanding, found prior to experience in the mind and which make outer experiences possible as counterpart to the rational faculties of the mind.[7][8]

By Kant's account, when one employs a concept to describe or categorize noumena (the objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis of the workings of the world), one is also employing a way of describing or categorizing phenomena (the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis). Kant posited methods by which human understanding makes sense of and thus intuits phenomena that appear to the mind: the concepts of the transcendental aesthetic, as well as that of the transcendental analytic, transcendental logic and transcendental deduction.[9][10][11] Taken together, Kant's "categories of understanding" are the principles of the human mind which necessarily are brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which we exist (that is, to understand, or attempt to understand, "things in themselves"). In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to the process that the human mind must exercise to understand or grasp the form of, and order among, phenomena. Kant asserts that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed.[citation needed] Humans can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but in doing so can never know the "things-in-themselves", the actual objects and dynamics of the natural world in their noumenal dimension - this being the negative, correlate to phenomena and that which escapes the limits of human understanding. By Kant's Critique, our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the various aspects of the universe, but cannot know these "things-in-themselves" (noumena) directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which the human rational faculties can reach the object of "things-in-themselves" by our observations of the manifestations of those things that can be perceived via the physical senses, that is, of phenomena, and by ordering these perceptions in the mind help infer the validity of our perceptions to the rational categories used to understand them in a rational system. This rational system (transcendental analytic), being the categories of the understanding as free from empirical contingency.[12][13]

According to Kant, objects of which we are cognizant via the physical senses are merely representations of unknown somethings—what Kant refers to as the transcendental object—as interpreted through the a priori or categories of the understanding. These unknown somethings are manifested within the noumenon—although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of these unknown somethings via our physical senses are bound by the limitations of the categories of the understanding and we are therefore never able to fully know the "thing-in-itself".[14]

Noumenon and the thing-in-itself

Many accounts of Kant's philosophy treat "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" as synonymous, and there is textual evidence for this relationship.[15] However, Stephen Palmquist holds that "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" are only loosely synonymous, inasmuch as they represent the same concept viewed from two different perspectives,[16][17] and other scholars also argue that they are not identical.[18] Schopenhauer criticised Kant for changing the meaning of "noumenon". However, this opinion is far from unanimous.[19] Kant's writings show points of difference between noumena and things-in-themselves. For instance, he regards things-in-themselves as existing:

...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.[20]

He is much more doubtful about noumena:

But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special [kind of] object, namely, an intelligible object; the [sort of] understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem. For we cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its object, not discursively through categories, but intuitively in a non-sensible intuition.[21]

A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing-in-itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a kind of knowledge, whereas Kant insisted that the thing-in-itself is unknowable. Interpreters have debated whether the latter claim makes sense: it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing-in-itself (i.e., that it is unknowable). But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant's definition of the term, to the extent that anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing-in-itself knowable must be adopting a non-Kantian position.[22]

Positive and negative noumena

Kant also makes a distinction between positive and negative noumena:[23][24]

If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the term.[25]

But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in the positive sense of the term.[25]

The positive noumena, if they existed, would be immaterial entities that can only be apprehended by a special, non-sensory faculty: "intellectual intuition" (nicht sinnliche Anschauung).[25] Kant doubts that we have such a faculty, because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity, and its being represented, would be the same. He argues that humans have no way to apprehend positive noumena:

Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience. Doubtless, indeed, there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible entities; there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation whatsoever; but our concepts of understanding, being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition, could not in the least apply to them. That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood as being such only in a negative sense.[26]

The noumenon as a limiting concept

Even if noumena are unknowable, they are still needed as a limiting concept,[27] Kant tells us. Without them, there would be only phenomena, and since potentially we have complete knowledge of our phenomena, we would in a sense know everything. In his own words:

Further, the concept of a noumenon is necessary, to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves, and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge.[28]

What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon, is a negative extension; that is to say, understanding is not limited through sensibility; on the contrary, it itself limits sensibility by applying the term noumena to things in themselves (things not regarded as appearances). But in so doing it at the same time sets limits to itself, recognising that it cannot know these noumena through any of the categories, and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown something.[29]

Furthermore, for Kant, the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper bounds, making many questions of traditional metaphysics, such as the existence of God, the soul, and free will unanswerable by reason. Kant derives this from his definition of knowledge as "the determination of given representations to an object".[30] As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal, Kant is able to make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon "such knowledge that has to do only with appearances".[31] These questions are ultimately the "proper object of faith, but not of reason".[32]

The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations

Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing-in-itself. One is the dual object view, according to which the thing-in-itself is an entity distinct from the phenomena to which it gives rise. The other is the dual aspect view, according to which the thing-in-itself and the thing-as-it-appears are two "sides" of the same thing. This view is supported by the textual fact that "Most occurrences of the phrase 'things-in-themselves' are shorthand for the phrase, 'things considered in themselves' (Dinge an sich selbst betrachtet)."[33] Although we cannot see things apart from the way we do in fact perceive them via the physical senses, we can think them apart from our mode of sensibility (physical perception); thus making the thing-in-itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought.

Criticisms of Kant's noumenon

Pre-Kantian critique

Though the term noumenon did not come into common usage until Kant, the idea that undergirds it, that matter has an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena, had historically been subjected to criticism. George Berkeley, who pre-dated Kant, asserted that matter, independent of an observant mind, is metaphysically impossible. Qualities associated with matter, such as shape, color, smell, texture, weight, temperature, and sound are all dependent on minds, which allow only for relative perception, not absolute perception. The complete absence of such minds (and more importantly an omnipotent mind) would render those same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable. Berkeley called this philosophy immaterialism. Essentially there could be no such thing as matter without a mind.[34]

Schopenhauer's critique

Schopenhauer claimed that Kant used the word noumenon incorrectly. He explained in his "Critique of the Kantian philosophy", which first appeared as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation:

The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition, which Kant entirely overlooks, was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as φαινόμενα [phainomena] and νοούμενα [nooumena]; the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of the Eleatics, in Plato's doctrine of Ideas, in the dialectic of the Megarics, and later in the scholastics, in the conflict between nominalism and realism. This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato and Aristotle. But Kant, who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms φαινομένα and νοούμενα were already in use, then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless, and used them as designations of things in themselves and their appearances.[35]

The noumenon's original meaning of "that which is thought" is not compatible with the "thing-in-itself," the latter being Kant's term for things as they exist apart from their existence as images in the mind of an observer.[citation needed] In a footnote to this passage, Schopenhauer provides the following passage from the Outlines of Pyrrhonism (Bk. I, ch. 13) of Sextus Empiricus to demonstrate the original distinction between phenomenon and noumenon according to ancient philosophers: νοούμενα φαινομένοις ἀντετίθη Ἀναξαγόρας ('Anaxagoras opposed what is thought to what appears.')

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Ontology

References

  1. ^ "Formal Epistemology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  2. ^ . Archived from the original on 2011-09-28. Retrieved 2015-09-10. 1. intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself, not as it is known through perception; 2. The of-itself-unknown and unknowable rational object, or thing-in-itself, which is distinguished from the phenomenon through which it is apprehended by the physical senses, and by which it is interpreted and understood; – so used in the philosophy of Kant and his followers.
  3. ^ "noumenon | philosophy". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2017-09-04.
  4. ^ νοεῖν, νοῦς, νόος. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project.
  5. ^ Harper, Douglas. "noumenon". Online Etymology Dictionary.
  6. ^ Honderich, Ted, ed. (31 August 1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 657. ISBN 0198661320. Retrieved 2014-10-28.
  7. ^ Hanna, Robert (2009). Completing the Picture of Kant's Metaphysics of Judgment. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant's metaphysics.
  9. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
  10. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Transcendental Aesthetic", p. 310 ff.
  11. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
  12. ^ See, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
  13. ^ See also, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
  14. ^ Kant 1999, p. 27, A256/B312.
  15. ^ Immanuel Kant (1781) Critique of Pure Reason, for example in A254/B310, p. 362 (Guyer and Wood), "The concept of a noumenon, i.e., of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing-in-itself [...]"; But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout. The first reference to thing-in-itself comes many pages (A30) before the first reference to noumenon (A250). For a secondary or tertiary source, see: "Noumenon" in the Encyclopædia Britannica
  16. ^ "Noumenon: the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object. The term 'negative noumenon' refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition, while 'positive noumenon' refers to the (quite mistaken) attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object. These two terms are sometimes used loosely as synonyms for 'transcendental object' and 'thing-in-itself', respectively. (Cf. phenomenon.)" – Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms
  17. ^ Thing-in-itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain knowledge of it via the physical senses. Hence the thing-in-itself is, by definition, unknowable via the physical senses. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon. (Cf. appearance.)" – Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms. Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article, "Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge", Dialectica 40:2 (1986), pp.121–151; revised and reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist's book, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  18. ^ Oizerman, T. I., "Kant's Doctrine of the "Things in Themselves" and Noumena", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 41, No. 3, Mar., 1981, 333–350; Karin de Boer, "Kant's Multi-Layered Conception of Things in Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.
  19. ^ "Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought to be used. A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear, without any claim to represent an exhaustive overview. Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen, who equates 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon', equates 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', distinguishes 'positive noumenon' and 'negative noumenon', and treats 'negative noumenon' as equivalent to 'transcendental object' [pp. 4:148-50, 154-5, 192]. Al-Azm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate 'phenomenon' and 'appearance', though they both carefully distinguish 'thing-in-itself' from 'negative noumenon' and 'positive noumenon' [A4:520; W21:165, 313–5; s.a. W9:162]. Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair, as well as 'thing-in-itself' and 'positive noumenon', but distinguishes between 'transcendental object', 'negative noumenon' and 'thing-in-itself' [G11: 201]. By contrast, Bird and George both distinguish between 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', but not between 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon' [B20:18,19, 53–7; G7:513-4n]; and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between 'thing-in-itself' and 'transcendental object' as well.[2] Gram equates 'thing-in-itself' not with 'noumenon', but with 'phenomenon' [G13:1,5-6]! Allison cites different official meanings for each term, yet he tends to equate 'thing-in-itself' at times with 'negative noumenon' and at times with 'transcendental-object', usually ignoring the role of the 'positive noumenon' [A7:94; A10:58,69]. And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing-in-itself seems to be connected with each of the other object-terms by regarding it as 'Kant's umbrella term'.[3]" Stephen Palmquist on Kant's object terms
  20. ^ Kant 1999, Bxxvi-xxvii.
  21. ^ Kant 1999, p. 273, A256, B312.
  22. ^ "The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", Cogito 3:2 (March 1985), pp.101–115; revised and reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  23. ^ Mattey, G. J.
  24. ^ Lecture notes by G. J. Mattey 2010-06-12 at the Wayback Machine
  25. ^ a b c Kant 1999, p. 267 (NKS), A250/B307.
  26. ^ Kant 1999, p. 270 (NKS), B309.
  27. ^ Allison, H (2006). "Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism". Kantian Review. 11: 1–28. doi:10.1017/S1369415400002223. S2CID 171078596.
  28. ^ Kant 1999, A253/B310.
  29. ^ Kant 1999, p. 273, A256/B312.
  30. ^ Kant 1999, p. 156, B/137.
  31. ^ Kant 1999, p. 24, B/xx..
  32. ^ Rohmann, Chris. "Kant" A World of Ideas: A Dictionary of Important Theories, Concepts, Beliefs, and Thnkers. Ballantine Books, 1999.
  33. ^ Mattey, GJ. "Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason".
  34. ^ Anon., "Caird's Philosophy of Kant", Saturday Review of Politics, Literature, Science and Art, vol 44, Nov 3, 1877, pp. 559-60.
  35. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (2014). The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1. Translated by Norman, Judith; Welchman, Alistair; Janaway, Christopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 506. ISBN 9780521871846.

Bibliography

  • Kant, Immanuel (1999). Critique of Pure Reason (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521657297.

External links

  • The surd of metaphysics; an inquiry into the question: Are there things-in-themselves? (1903) by Paul Carus, 1852–1919

noumenon, this, article, about, philosophical, concept, other, uses, disambiguation, confused, with, numinous, also, noema, philosophy, noumenon, from, ancient, greek, νoούμενον, plural, noumena, knowledge, posited, object, that, exists, independently, human, . This article is about the philosophical concept For other uses see Noumenon disambiguation Not to be confused with Numinous See also Noema In philosophy a noumenon ˈ n uː m e n ɒ n ˈ n aʊ from Ancient Greek nooymenon plural noumena is knowledge 1 posited as an object that exists independently of human sense 2 The term noumenon is generally used in contrast with or in relation to the term phenomenon which refers to any object of the senses Immanuel Kant first developed the notion of the noumenon as part of his transcendental idealism suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because human sensibility is merely receptive it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwise unknowable to us 3 In Kantian philosophy the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable thing in itself German Ding an sich However the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant s work and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result Contents 1 Etymology 2 Historical predecessors 3 Kantian noumena 3 1 Overview 3 2 Noumenon and the thing in itself 3 3 Positive and negative noumena 3 4 The noumenon as a limiting concept 3 5 The dual object and dual aspect interpretations 4 Criticisms of Kant s noumenon 4 1 Pre Kantian critique 4 2 Schopenhauer s critique 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 Bibliography 9 External linksEtymology EditThe Greek word nooymenon nooumenon plural nooymena nooumena is the neuter middle passive present participle of noeῖn noein to think to mean which in turn originates from the word noῦs nous an Attic contracted form of noos noos perception understanding mind a 4 5 A rough equivalent in English would be something that is thought or the object of an act of thought Historical predecessors EditRegarding the equivalent concepts in Plato Ted Honderich writes Platonic Ideas and Forms are noumena and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the senses This dichotomy is the most characteristic feature of Plato s dualism that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge truths and values is Plato s principal legacy to philosophy 6 Kantian noumena EditOverview Edit As expressed in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason human understanding is structured by concepts of the understanding or pure categories of understanding found prior to experience in the mind and which make outer experiences possible as counterpart to the rational faculties of the mind 7 8 By Kant s account when one employs a concept to describe or categorize noumena the objects of inquiry investigation or analysis of the workings of the world one is also employing a way of describing or categorizing phenomena the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry investigation or analysis Kant posited methods by which human understanding makes sense of and thus intuits phenomena that appear to the mind the concepts of the transcendental aesthetic as well as that of the transcendental analytic transcendental logic and transcendental deduction 9 10 11 Taken together Kant s categories of understanding are the principles of the human mind which necessarily are brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which we exist that is to understand or attempt to understand things in themselves In each instance the word transcendental refers to the process that the human mind must exercise to understand or grasp the form of and order among phenomena Kant asserts that to transcend a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed citation needed Humans can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways but in doing so can never know the things in themselves the actual objects and dynamics of the natural world in their noumenal dimension this being the negative correlate to phenomena and that which escapes the limits of human understanding By Kant s Critique our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways perhaps even closely accurate ways with the structure and order of the various aspects of the universe but cannot know these things in themselves noumena directly Rather we must infer the extent to which the human rational faculties can reach the object of things in themselves by our observations of the manifestations of those things that can be perceived via the physical senses that is of phenomena and by ordering these perceptions in the mind help infer the validity of our perceptions to the rational categories used to understand them in a rational system This rational system transcendental analytic being the categories of the understanding as free from empirical contingency 12 13 According to Kant objects of which we are cognizant via the physical senses are merely representations of unknown somethings what Kant refers to as the transcendental object as interpreted through the a priori or categories of the understanding These unknown somethings are manifested within the noumenon although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of these unknown somethings via our physical senses are bound by the limitations of the categories of the understanding and we are therefore never able to fully know the thing in itself 14 Noumenon and the thing in itself Edit Many accounts of Kant s philosophy treat noumenon and thing in itself as synonymous and there is textual evidence for this relationship 15 However Stephen Palmquist holds that noumenon and thing in itself are only loosely synonymous inasmuch as they represent the same concept viewed from two different perspectives 16 17 and other scholars also argue that they are not identical 18 Schopenhauer criticised Kant for changing the meaning of noumenon However this opinion is far from unanimous 19 Kant s writings show points of difference between noumena and things in themselves For instance he regards things in themselves as existing though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears 20 He is much more doubtful about noumena But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special kind of object namely an intelligible object the sort of understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem For we cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its object not discursively through categories but intuitively in a non sensible intuition 21 A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing in itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a kind of knowledge whereas Kant insisted that the thing in itself is unknowable Interpreters have debated whether the latter claim makes sense it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing in itself i e that it is unknowable But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant s definition of the term to the extent that anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing in itself knowable must be adopting a non Kantian position 22 Positive and negative noumena Edit Kant also makes a distinction between positive and negative noumena 23 24 If by noumenon we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the term 25 But if we understand by it an object of a non sensible intuition we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition namely the intellectual which is not that which we possess and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility This would be noumenon in the positive sense of the term 25 The positive noumena if they existed would be immaterial entities that can only be apprehended by a special non sensory faculty intellectual intuition nicht sinnliche Anschauung 25 Kant doubts that we have such a faculty because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity and its being represented would be the same He argues that humans have no way to apprehend positive noumena Since however such a type of intuition intellectual intuition forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience Doubtless indeed there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible entities there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation whatsoever but our concepts of understanding being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition could not in the least apply to them That therefore which we entitle noumenon must be understood as being such only in a negative sense 26 The noumenon as a limiting concept Edit Even if noumena are unknowable they are still needed as a limiting concept 27 Kant tells us Without them there would be only phenomena and since potentially we have complete knowledge of our phenomena we would in a sense know everything In his own words Further the concept of a noumenon is necessary to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge 28 What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon is a negative extension that is to say understanding is not limited through sensibility on the contrary it itself limits sensibility by applying the term noumena to things in themselves things not regarded as appearances But in so doing it at the same time sets limits to itself recognising that it cannot know these noumena through any of the categories and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown something 29 Furthermore for Kant the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper bounds making many questions of traditional metaphysics such as the existence of God the soul and free will unanswerable by reason Kant derives this from his definition of knowledge as the determination of given representations to an object 30 As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal Kant is able to make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon such knowledge that has to do only with appearances 31 These questions are ultimately the proper object of faith but not of reason 32 The dual object and dual aspect interpretations Edit Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing in itself One is the dual object view according to which the thing in itself is an entity distinct from the phenomena to which it gives rise The other is the dual aspect view according to which the thing in itself and the thing as it appears are two sides of the same thing This view is supported by the textual fact that Most occurrences of the phrase things in themselves are shorthand for the phrase things considered in themselves Dinge an sich selbst betrachtet 33 Although we cannot see things apart from the way we do in fact perceive them via the physical senses we can think them apart from our mode of sensibility physical perception thus making the thing in itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought Criticisms of Kant s noumenon EditPre Kantian critique Edit Though the term noumenon did not come into common usage until Kant the idea that undergirds it that matter has an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena had historically been subjected to criticism George Berkeley who pre dated Kant asserted that matter independent of an observant mind is metaphysically impossible Qualities associated with matter such as shape color smell texture weight temperature and sound are all dependent on minds which allow only for relative perception not absolute perception The complete absence of such minds and more importantly an omnipotent mind would render those same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable Berkeley called this philosophy immaterialism Essentially there could be no such thing as matter without a mind 34 Schopenhauer s critique Edit Schopenhauer claimed that Kant used the word noumenon incorrectly He explained in his Critique of the Kantian philosophy which first appeared as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition which Kant entirely overlooks was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as fainomena phainomena and nooymena nooumena the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of the Eleatics in Plato s doctrine of Ideas in the dialectic of the Megarics and later in the scholastics in the conflict between nominalism and realism This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato and Aristotle But Kant who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms fainomena and nooymena were already in use then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless and used them as designations of things in themselves and their appearances 35 The noumenon s original meaning of that which is thought is not compatible with the thing in itself the latter being Kant s term for things as they exist apart from their existence as images in the mind of an observer citation needed In a footnote to this passage Schopenhauer provides the following passage from the Outlines of Pyrrhonism Bk I ch 13 of Sextus Empiricus to demonstrate the original distinction between phenomenon and noumenon according to ancient philosophers nooymena fainomenois ἀnteti8h Ἀna3agoras Anaxagoras opposed what is thought to what appears See also EditAlways already Anatta Condition of possibility Essence energies distinction Haecceity Hypokeimenon Ineffability Master argument by George Berkeley Observation Qualia Schopenhauer s criticism of the Kantian philosophy Transcendental idealism UnobservableNotes Edit OntologyReferences Edit Formal Epistemology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2021 Noumenon Definition of Noumenon by Webster s Online Dictionary Archived from the original on 2011 09 28 Retrieved 2015 09 10 1 intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself not as it is known through perception 2 The of itself unknown and unknowable rational object or thing in itself which is distinguished from the phenomenon through which it is apprehended by the physical senses and by which it is interpreted and understood so used in the philosophy of Kant and his followers noumenon philosophy Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 2017 09 04 noeῖn noῦs noos Liddell Henry George Scott Robert A Greek English Lexicon at the Perseus Project Harper Douglas noumenon Online Etymology Dictionary Honderich Ted ed 31 August 1995 The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press p 657 ISBN 0198661320 Retrieved 2014 10 28 Hanna Robert 2009 Completing the Picture of Kant s Metaphysics of Judgment Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant s metaphysics The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan 1967 1996 Volume 4 Kant Immanuel section on Critique of Pure Reason Theme and Preliminaries p 308 ff The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan 1967 1996 Volume 4 Kant Immanuel section on Transcendental Aesthetic p 310 ff The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan 1967 1996 Volume 4 Kant Immanuel section on Pure Concepts of the Understanding p 311 ff See e g The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan 1967 1996 Volume 4 Kant Immanuel section on Critique of Pure Reason Theme and Preliminaries p 308 ff See also e g The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan 1967 1996 Volume 4 Kant Immanuel section on Pure Concepts of the Understanding p 311 ff Kant 1999 p 27 A256 B312 Immanuel Kant 1781 Critique of Pure Reason for example in A254 B310 p 362 Guyer and Wood The concept of a noumenon i e of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing in itself But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout The first reference to thing in itself comes many pages A30 before the first reference to noumenon A250 For a secondary or tertiary source see Noumenon in the Encyclopaedia Britannica Noumenon the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object The term negative noumenon refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition while positive noumenon refers to the quite mistaken attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object These two terms are sometimes used loosely as synonyms for transcendental object and thing in itself respectively Cf phenomenon Glossary of Kant s Technical Terms Thing in itself an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain knowledge of it via the physical senses Hence the thing in itself is by definition unknowable via the physical senses Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon Cf appearance Glossary of Kant s Technical Terms Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant s Theory of Knowledge Dialectica 40 2 1986 pp 121 151 revised and reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist s book Kant s System of Perspectives Lanham University Press of America 1993 Oizerman T I Kant s Doctrine of the Things in Themselves and Noumena Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 41 No 3 Mar 1981 333 350 Karin de Boer Kant s Multi Layered Conception of Things in Themselves Transcendental Objects and Monads Kant Studien 105 2 2014 221 260 Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought to be used A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear without any claim to represent an exhaustive overview Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen who equates thing in itself and noumenon equates appearance and phenomenon distinguishes positive noumenon and negative noumenon and treats negative noumenon as equivalent to transcendental object pp 4 148 50 154 5 192 Al Azm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate phenomenon and appearance though they both carefully distinguish thing in itself from negative noumenon and positive noumenon A4 520 W21 165 313 5 s a W9 162 Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair as well as thing in itself and positive noumenon but distinguishes between transcendental object negative noumenon and thing in itself G11 201 By contrast Bird and George both distinguish between appearance and phenomenon but not between thing in itself and noumenon B20 18 19 53 7 G7 513 4n and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between thing in itself and transcendental object as well 2 Gram equates thing in itself not with noumenon but with phenomenon G13 1 5 6 Allison cites different official meanings for each term yet he tends to equate thing in itself at times with negative noumenon and at times with transcendental object usually ignoring the role of the positive noumenon A7 94 A10 58 69 And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing in itself seems to be connected with each of the other object terms by regarding it as Kant s umbrella term 3 Stephen Palmquist on Kant s object terms Kant 1999 Bxxvi xxvii Kant 1999 p 273 A256 B312 The Radical Unknowability of Kant s Thing in Itself Cogito 3 2 March 1985 pp 101 115 revised and reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist Kant s System of Perspectives Lanham University Press of America 1993 Mattey G J Lecture notes by G J Mattey Archived 2010 06 12 at the Wayback Machine a b c Kant 1999 p 267 NKS A250 B307 Kant 1999 p 270 NKS B309 Allison H 2006 Transcendental Realism Empirical Realism and Transcendental Idealism Kantian Review 11 1 28 doi 10 1017 S1369415400002223 S2CID 171078596 Kant 1999 A253 B310 Kant 1999 p 273 A256 B312 Kant 1999 p 156 B 137 Kant 1999 p 24 B xx Rohmann Chris Kant A World of Ideas A Dictionary of Important Theories Concepts Beliefs and Thnkers Ballantine Books 1999 Mattey GJ Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason Anon Caird s Philosophy of Kant Saturday Review of Politics Literature Science and Art vol 44 Nov 3 1877 pp 559 60 Schopenhauer Arthur 2014 The World as Will and Representation Volume 1 Translated by Norman Judith Welchman Alistair Janaway Christopher Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 506 ISBN 9780521871846 Bibliography EditKant Immanuel 1999 Critique of Pure Reason The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521657297 External links Edit Look up noumenon in Wiktionary the free dictionary The surd of metaphysics an inquiry into the question Are there things in themselves 1903 by Paul Carus 1852 1919 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Noumenon amp oldid 1140131906, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.