fbpx
Wikipedia

Aristotle

Aristotle (/ˈærɪstɒtəl/;[1] Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs, pronounced [aristotélɛːs]; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects including physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poetry, drama, music, rhetoric, psychology, linguistics, economics, politics, meteorology, geology, and government. As the founder of the Peripatetic school of philosophy in the Lyceum in Athens, he began the wider Aristotelian tradition that followed, which set the groundwork for the development of modern science.

Aristotle
Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos, c. 330 BC, with modern alabaster mantle
Born384 BC
Died322 BC (aged 61–62)
EducationPlatonic Academy
Notable work
EraAncient Greek philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Notable studentsAlexander the Great, Theophrastus, Aristoxenus
Main interests
Notable ideas
Aristotelianism

Little is known about Aristotle's life. He was born in the city of Stagira in Northern Greece during the Classical period. His father, Nicomachus, died when Aristotle was a child, and he was brought up by a guardian. At seventeen or eighteen years of age he joined Plato's Academy in Athens and remained there until the age of thirty-seven (c. 347 BC). Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of Philip II of Macedon, tutored his son Alexander the Great beginning in 343 BC. He established a library in the Lyceum which helped him to produce many of his hundreds of books on papyrus scrolls.

Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues for publication, only around a third of his original output has survived, none of it intended for publication. Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him. It was above all from his teachings that the West inherited its intellectual lexicon, as well as problems and methods of inquiry. As a result, his philosophy has exerted a unique influence on almost every form of knowledge in the West and it continues to be a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion.

Aristotle's views profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. The influence of physical science extended from Late Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages into the Renaissance, and were not replaced systematically until the Enlightenment and theories such as classical mechanics were developed. Some of Aristotle's zoological observations found in his biology, such as on the hectocotyl (reproductive) arm of the octopus, were disbelieved until the 19th century. He also influenced Judeo-Islamic philosophies during the Middle Ages, as well as Christian theology, especially the Neoplatonism of the Early Church and the scholastic tradition of the Catholic Church. Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as "The First Teacher", and among medieval Christians like Thomas Aquinas as simply "The Philosopher", while the poet Dante called him "the master of those who know". His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, and were studied by medieval scholars such as Peter Abelard and John Buridan. Aristotle's influence on logic continued well into the 19th century. In addition, his ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of virtue ethics.

Life

In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.[A]

Aristotle was born in 384 BC[B] in Stagira, Chalcidice,[2] about 55 km (34 miles) east of modern-day Thessaloniki.[3][4] His father, Nicomachus, was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon. While he was young, Aristotle learned about biology and medical information, which was taught by his father.[5] Both of Aristotle's parents died when he was about thirteen, and Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian.[6] Although little information about Aristotle's childhood has survived, he probably spent some time within the Macedonian palace, making his first connections with the Macedonian monarchy.[7]

 
School of Aristotle in Mieza, Macedonia, Greece

At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy.[8] He probably experienced the Eleusinian Mysteries as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Eleusinian Mysteries, "to experience is to learn" [παθείν μαθεĩν].[9] Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348/47 BC. The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the Academy's direction after control passed to Plato's nephew Speusippus, although it is possible that he feared the anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens at that time and left before Plato died.[10] Aristotle then accompanied Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor. After the death of Hermias, Aristotle travelled with his pupil Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos, where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island and its sheltered lagoon. While in Lesbos, Aristotle married Pythias, either Hermias's adoptive daughter or niece. She bore him a daughter, whom they also named Pythias. In 343 BC, Aristotle was invited by Philip II of Macedon to become the tutor to his son Alexander.[11][12]

Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of Macedon. During Aristotle's time in the Macedonian court, he gave lessons not only to Alexander but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander.[13] Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and Aristotle's own attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be "a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants".[13] By 335 BC, Aristotle had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stagira, who bore him a son whom he named after his father, Nicomachus. If the Suda – an uncritical compilation from the Middle Ages – is accurate, he may also have had an erômenos, Palaephatus of Abydus.[14]

 
Portrait bust of Aristotle; an Imperial Roman (1st or 2nd century AD) copy of a lost bronze sculpture made by Lysippos

This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works.[12] He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, On the Soul and Poetics. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance, and theatre."[15]

Near the end of his life, Alexander and Aristotle became estranged over Alexander's relationship with Persia and Persians. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but the only evidence of this is an unlikely claim made some six years after the death.[16] Following Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled. In 322 BC, Demophilus and Eurymedon the Hierophant reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety,[17] prompting him to flee to his mother's family estate in Chalcis, on Euboea, at which occasion he was said to have stated: "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy"[18][19][20] – a reference to Athens's trial and execution of Socrates. He died in Chalcis, Euboea[2][21][15] of natural causes later that same year, having named his student Antipater as his chief executor and leaving a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.[22]

Theoretical philosophy

Logic

With the Prior Analytics, Aristotle is credited with the earliest study of formal logic,[23] and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th-century advances in mathematical logic.[24] Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that with Aristotle logic reached its completion.[25]

Organon

One of Aristotle's types of syllogism[C]
In words In
terms[D]
In equations[E]
    All men are mortal.

    All Greeks are men.

All Greeks are mortal.
M a P

S a M

S a P
 

What is today called Aristotelian logic with its types of syllogism (methods of logical argument),[26] Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the Organon around 40 BC by Andronicus of Rhodes or others among his followers.[28] The books are:

  1. Categories
  2. On Interpretation
  3. Prior Analytics
  4. Posterior Analytics
  5. Topics
  6. On Sophistical Refutations
 
Plato (left) and Aristotle in Raphael's 1509 fresco, The School of Athens. Aristotle holds his Nicomachean Ethics and gestures to the earth, representing his view in immanent realism, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, indicating his Theory of Forms, and holds his Timaeus.[29][30]

The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in On Interpretation, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics)[31][32] and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory stricto sensu: the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The Rhetoric is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the Topics.[33]

Metaphysics

The word "metaphysics" appears to have been coined by the first century AD editor who assembled various small selections of Aristotle's works to the treatise we know by the name Metaphysics.[34] Aristotle called it "first philosophy", and distinguished it from mathematics and natural science (physics) as the contemplative (theoretikē) philosophy which is "theological" and studies the divine. He wrote in his Metaphysics (1026a16):

if there were no other independent things besides the composite natural ones, the study of nature would be the primary kind of knowledge; but if there is some motionless independent thing, the knowledge of this precedes it and is first philosophy, and it is universal in just this way, because it is first. And it belongs to this sort of philosophy to study being as being, both what it is and what belongs to it just by virtue of being.[35]

Substance

Aristotle examines the concepts of substance (ousia) and essence (to ti ên einai, "the what it was to be") in his Metaphysics (Book VII), and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form, a philosophical theory called hylomorphism. In Book VIII, he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the substratum, or the stuff of which it is composed. For example, the matter of a house is the bricks, stones, timbers, etc., or whatever constitutes the potential house, while the form of the substance is the actual house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other differentia that let us define something as a house. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.[36][34]

Immanent realism
 
Plato's forms exist as universals, like the ideal form of an apple. For Aristotle, both matter and form belong to the individual thing (hylomorphism).

Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle's ontology places the universal (katholou) in particulars (kath' hekaston), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a separately existing form which actual things imitate. For Aristotle, "form" is still what phenomena are based on, but is "instantiated" in a particular substance.[34]

Plato argued that all things have a universal form, which could be either a property or a relation to other things. When one looks at an apple, for example, one sees an apple, and one can also analyse a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple. Moreover, one can place an apple next to a book, so that one can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other. Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper universal form. Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated at some period of time, and that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the forms as existing separately from the things that participate in them, Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.[34][37]

Potentiality and actuality

Concerning the nature of change (kinesis) and its causes, as he outlines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption (319b–320a), he distinguishes coming-to-be (genesis, also translated as 'generation') from:

  1. growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
  2. locomotion, which is change in space; and
  3. alteration, which is change in quality.
 
Aristotle argued that a capability like playing the flute could be acquired – the potential made actual – by learning.

Coming-to-be is a change where the substrate of the thing that has undergone the change has itself changed. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing or being acted upon if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (dynamei) a plant, and if it is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate – being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise – acting). Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle of every change, and potentiality exists for the sake of the end, actuality, accordingly, is the end. Referring then to the previous example, it can be said that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do.[34]

For that for the sake of which (to hou heneka) a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see.[38]

In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a final cause or end. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, for example, "what is it that makes a man one"? Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same.[34][39]

Epistemology

Aristotle's immanent realism means his epistemology is based on the study of things that exist or happen in the world, and rises to knowledge of the universal, whereas for Plato epistemology begins with knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) and descends to knowledge of particular imitations of these.[33] Aristotle uses induction from examples alongside deduction, whereas Plato relies on deduction from a priori principles.[33]

Natural philosophy

Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences.[40] In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". However, his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.[40]

Physics

 
The four classical elements (fire, air, water, earth) of Empedocles and Aristotle illustrated with a burning log. The log releases all four elements as it is destroyed.

Five elements

In his On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by Empedocles, earth, water, air, and fire, to two of the four sensible qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. In the Empedoclean scheme, all matter was made of the four elements, in differing proportions. Aristotle's scheme added the heavenly aether, the divine substance of the heavenly spheres, stars and planets.[41]

Aristotle's elements[41]
Element Hot/Cold Wet/Dry Motion Modern state
of matter
Earth Cold Dry Down Solid
Water Cold Wet Down Liquid
Air Hot Wet Up Gas
Fire Hot Dry Up Plasma
Aether (divine
substance)
Circular
(in heavens)

Motion

Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the Physics (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in On the Heavens (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also: in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,[42][F] since Aristotle does not address friction.[43] With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.[44][G] This would imply the equation[44]

 ,

incorrect in modern physics.[44]

Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,[H] while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.[45][43][I]

 
Aristotle's laws of motion. In Physics he states that objects fall at a speed proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the fluid they are immersed in.[43] This is a correct approximation for objects in Earth's gravitational field moving in air or water.[45]

In the Physics (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,[J] ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:;[45][43]

 

Aristotle implies that in a vacuum the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible.[45][43] Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view"[43] that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative,[46] but other authors reject this.[43]

Archimedes corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they displace enough water; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not, as Aristotle thought, its elementary composition.[45]

Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the Early Modern period. John Philoponus (in the Middle Ages) and Galileo are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle's claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect.[40] A contrary opinion is given by Carlo Rovelli, who argues that Aristotle's physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity, that of objects in the Earth's gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air. In this system, heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones (whether friction is ignored, or not[45]), and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium.[44][K]

Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval theory of impetus.[45]

Four causes

 
Aristotle argued by analogy with woodwork that a thing takes its form from four causes: in the case of a table, the wood used (material cause), its design (formal cause), the tools and techniques used (efficient cause), and its decorative or practical purpose (final cause).[47]

Aristotle suggested that the reason for anything coming about can be attributed to four different types of simultaneously active factors. His term aitia is traditionally translated as "cause", but it does not always refer to temporal sequence; it might be better translated as "explanation", but the traditional rendering will be employed here.[48][49]

  • Material cause describes the material out of which something is composed. Thus the material cause of a table is wood. It is not about action. It does not mean that one domino knocks over another domino.[48]
  • The formal cause is its form, i.e., the arrangement of that matter. It tells one what a thing is, that a thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (i.e., macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. Plainly put, the formal cause is the idea in the mind of the sculptor that brings the sculpture into being. A simple example of the formal cause is the mental image or idea that allows an artist, architect, or engineer to create a drawing.[48]
  • The efficient cause is "the primary source", or that from which the change under consideration proceeds. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, non-living or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs. In the case of two dominoes, when the first is knocked over it causes the second also to fall over.[48] In the case of animals, this agency is a combination of how it develops from the egg, and how its body functions.[50]
  • The final cause (telos) is its purpose, the reason why a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause is the purpose or function that something is supposed to serve. This covers modern ideas of motivating causes, such as volition.[48] In the case of living things, it implies adaptation to a particular way of life.[50]

Optics

Aristotle describes experiments in optics using a camera obscura in Problems, book 15. The apparatus consisted of a dark chamber with a small aperture that let light in. With it, he saw that whatever shape he made the hole, the sun's image always remained circular. He also noted that increasing the distance between the aperture and the image surface magnified the image.[51]

Chance and spontaneity

According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things, "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.[52][53]

Astronomy

In astronomy, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."[54]

Geology and natural sciences

 
Aristotle noted that the ground level of the Aeolian islands changed before a volcanic eruption.

Aristotle was one of the first people to record any geological observations. He stated that geological change was too slow to be observed in one person's lifetime.[55][56] The geologist Charles Lyell noted that Aristotle described such change, including "lakes that had dried up" and "deserts that had become watered by rivers", giving as examples the growth of the Nile delta since the time of Homer, and "the upheaving of one of the Aeolian islands, previous to a volcanic eruption."'[57] Aristotle also made many observations about the hydrologic cycle and meteorology (including his major writings "Meteorologica"). For example, he made some of the earliest observations about desalination: he observed early – and correctly – that when seawater is heated, freshwater evaporates and that the oceans are then replenished by the cycle of rainfall and river runoff ("I have proved by experiment that salt water evaporated forms fresh and the vapor does not when it condenses condense into sea water again.")[58]

Biology

 
Among many pioneering zoological observations, Aristotle described the reproductive hectocotyl arm of the octopus (bottom left).

Empirical research

Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically,[59] and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of Lesbos and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos.[60][61] His data in History of Animals, Generation of Animals, Movement of Animals, and Parts of Animals are assembled from his own observations,[62] statements given by people with specialized knowledge such as beekeepers and fishermen, and less accurate accounts provided by travellers from overseas.[63] His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on botany have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.[64]

Aristotle reports on the sea-life visible from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the catfish, electric ray, and frogfish in detail, as well as cephalopods such as the octopus and paper nautilus. His description of the hectocotyl arm of cephalopods, used in sexual reproduction, was widely disbelieved until the 19th century.[65] He gives accurate descriptions of the four-chambered fore-stomachs of ruminants,[66] and of the ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark.[67]

He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function, so, among birds, the heron, which lives in marshes with soft mud and lives by catching fish, has a long neck and long legs, and a sharp spear-like beak, whereas ducks that swim have short legs and webbed feet.[68] Darwin, too, noted these sorts of differences between similar kinds of animal, but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of evolution.[69] Aristotle's writings can seem to modern readers close to implying evolution, but while Aristotle was aware that new mutations or hybridizations could occur, he saw these as rare accidents. For Aristotle, accidents, like heat waves in winter, must be considered distinct from natural causes. He was thus critical of Empedocles's materialist theory of a "survival of the fittest" origin of living things and their organs, and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results.[70] To put his views into modern terms, he nowhere says that different species can have a common ancestor, or that one kind can change into another, or that kinds can become extinct.[71]

Scientific style

 
Aristotle inferred growth laws from his observations on animals, including that brood size decreases with body mass, whereas gestation period increases. He was correct in these predictions, at least for mammals: data are shown for mouse and elephant.

Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense.[72] He used the ancient Greek term pepeiramenoi to mean observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection.[73] In Generation of Animals, he finds a fertilized hen's egg of a suitable stage and opens it to see the embryo's heart beating inside.[74][75]

Instead, he practiced a different style of science: systematically gathering data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these.;[76][77] This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as genomics. It does not result in the same certainty as experimental science, but it sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.[76]

From the data he collected and documented, Aristotle inferred quite a number of rules relating the life-history features of the live-bearing tetrapods (terrestrial placental mammals) that he studied. Among these correct predictions are the following. Brood size decreases with (adult) body mass, so that an elephant has fewer young (usually just one) per brood than a mouse. Lifespan increases with gestation period, and also with body mass, so that elephants live longer than mice, have a longer period of gestation, and are heavier. As a final example, fecundity decreases with lifespan, so long-lived kinds like elephants have fewer young in total than short-lived kinds like mice.[78]

Classification of living things

 
Aristotle recorded that the embryo of a dogfish was attached by a cord to a kind of placenta (the yolk sac), like a higher animal; this formed an exception to the linear scale from highest to lowest.[79]

Aristotle distinguished about 500 species of animals,[80][81] arranging these in the History of Animals in a graded scale of perfection, a nonreligious version of the scala naturae, with man at the top. His system had eleven grades of animal, from highest potential to lowest, expressed in their form at birth: the highest gave live birth to hot and wet creatures, the lowest laid cold, dry mineral-like eggs. Animals came above plants, and these in turn were above minerals.[82][83] He grouped what the modern zoologist would call vertebrates as the hotter "animals with blood", and below them the colder invertebrates as "animals without blood". Those with blood were divided into the live-bearing (mammals), and the egg-laying (birds, reptiles, fish). Those without blood were insects, crustacea (non-shelled – cephalopods, and shelled) and the hard-shelled molluscs (bivalves and gastropods). He recognised that animals did not exactly fit into a linear scale, and noted various exceptions, such as that sharks had a placenta like the tetrapods. To a modern biologist, the explanation, not available to Aristotle, is convergent evolution.[84] Philosophers of science have generally concluded that Aristotle was not interested in taxonomy,[85][86] but zoologists who studied this question recently think otherwise.[87][88][89] He believed that purposive final causes guided all natural processes; this teleological view justified his observed data as an expression of formal design.[90]

Aristotle's Scala naturae (highest to lowest)
Group Examples
(given by Aristotle)
Blood Legs Souls
(Rational,
Sensitive,
Vegetative)
Qualities
(HotCold,
WetDry)
Man Man with blood 2 legs R, S, V Hot, Wet
Live-bearing tetrapods Cat, hare with blood 4 legs S, V Hot, Wet
Cetaceans Dolphin, whale with blood none S, V Hot, Wet
Birds Bee-eater, nightjar with blood 2 legs S, V Hot, Wet, except Dry eggs
Egg-laying tetrapods Chameleon, crocodile with blood 4 legs S, V Cold, Wet except scales, eggs
Snakes Water snake, Ottoman viper with blood none S, V Cold, Wet except scales, eggs
Egg-laying fishes Sea bass, parrotfish with blood none S, V Cold, Wet, including eggs
(Among the egg-laying fishes):
placental selachians
Shark, skate with blood none S, V Cold, Wet, but placenta like tetrapods
Crustaceans Shrimp, crab without many legs S, V Cold, Wet except shell
Cephalopods Squid, octopus without tentacles S, V Cold, Wet
Hard-shelled animals Cockle, trumpet snail without none S, V Cold, Dry (mineral shell)
Larva-bearing insects Ant, cicada without 6 legs S, V Cold, Dry
Spontaneously generating Sponges, worms without none S, V Cold, Wet or Dry, from earth
Plants Fig without none V Cold, Dry
Minerals Iron without none none Cold, Dry

Psychology

Soul

 
Aristotle proposed a three-part structure for souls of plants, animals, and humans, making humans unique in having all three types of soul.

Aristotle's psychology, given in his treatise On the Soul (peri psychēs), posits three kinds of soul ("psyches"): the vegetative soul, the sensitive soul, and the rational soul. Humans have a rational soul. The human soul incorporates the powers of the other kinds: Like the vegetative soul it can grow and nourish itself; like the sensitive soul it can experience sensations and move locally. The unique part of the human, rational soul is its ability to receive forms of other things and to compare them using the nous (intellect) and logos (reason).[91]

For Aristotle, the soul is the form of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement (or in the case of plants, growth and chemical transformations, which Aristotle considers types of movement).[11] In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain.[92] Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and thought, which generally differed from the concepts of previous philosophers, with the exception of Alcmaeon.[93]

In On the Soul, Aristotle famously criticizes Plato's theory of the soul and develops his own in response to Plato's. The first criticism is against Plato's view of the soul in the Timaeus that the soul takes up space and is able to come into physical contact with bodies.[94] 20th-century scholarship overwhelmingly opposed Aristotle's interpretation of Plato and maintained that he had misunderstood Plato.[95] Today's scholars have tended to re-assess Aristotle's interpretation and have warmed up to it.[96] Aristotle's other criticism is that Plato's view of reincarnation entails that it is possible for a soul and its body to be mis-matched; in principle, Aristotle alleges, any soul can go with any body, according to Plato's theory.[97] Aristotle's claim that the soul is the form of a living being is meant to eliminate that possibility and thus rule out reincarnation.[98]

Memory

According to Aristotle in On the Soul, memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and an occurrence in the past.[99] In other words, a memory is a mental picture (phantasm) that can be recovered. Aristotle believed an impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes several changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when stimuli such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive all the impressions at once. These changes are the same as those involved in the operations of sensation, Aristotelian 'common sense', and thinking.[100][101]

Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that can develop from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in past experiences, both for previous experience and present experience.[102]

Because Aristotle believes people receive all kinds of sense perceptions and perceive them as impressions, people are continually weaving together new impressions of experiences. To search for these impressions, people search the memory itself.[103] Within the memory, if one experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when one retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory will stimulate the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed.[104] Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving the information stored in a memory impression.[105] Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.[106]

 
Senses, perception, memory, dreams, action in Aristotle's psychology. Impressions are stored in the sensorium (the heart), linked by his laws of association (similarity, contrast, and contiguity).

Aristotle believed the chain of thought, which ends in recollection of certain impressions, was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and contiguity, described in his laws of association. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. According to Aristotle, association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to rise and be recalled.[107][108]

Dreams

Aristotle describes sleep in On Sleep and Wakefulness.[109] Sleep takes place as a result of overuse of the senses[110] or of digestion,[111] so it is vital to the body.[110] While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function as they do during wakefulness. Since a person cannot sense during sleep they cannot have desire, which is the result of sensation. However, the senses are able to work during sleep,[112] albeit differently,[109] unless they are weary.[110]

Dreams do not involve actually sensing a stimulus. In dreams, sensation is still involved, but in an altered manner.[110] Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then looks away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and the stimulus is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression.[109] When the body is awake and the senses are functioning properly, a person constantly encounters new stimuli to sense and so the impressions of previously perceived stimuli are ignored.[110] However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed as there are no new distracting sensory experiences.[109] So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left and not the exact stimuli, dreams do not resemble the actual waking experience.[113] During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind. Aristotle compares a sleeping person to a person who is overtaken by strong feelings toward a stimulus. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere because they are so overtaken by their feelings. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person.[109] This leads the person to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd in nature.[109] In De Anima iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images in the absence of perception to the faculty of imagination, phantasia.[11]

One component of Aristotle's theory of dreams disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned naturalistically that instances in which dreams do resemble future events are simply coincidences.[114] Aristotle claimed that a dream is first established by the fact that the person is asleep when they experience it. If a person had an image appear for a moment after waking up or if they see something in the dark it is not considered a dream because they were awake when it occurred. Secondly, any sensory experience that is perceived while a person is asleep does not qualify as part of a dream. For example, if, while a person is sleeping, a door shuts and in their dream they hear a door is shut, this sensory experience is not part of the dream. Lastly, the images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.[113]

Practical philosophy

Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.[40]

Virtues and their accompanying vices[15]
Too little Virtuous mean Too much
Humbleness High-mindedness Vainglory
Lack of purpose Right ambition Over-ambition
Spiritlessness Good temper Irascibility
Rudeness Civility Obsequiousness
Cowardice Courage Rashness
Insensibility Self-control Intemperance
Sarcasm Sincerity Boastfulness
Boorishness Wit Buffoonery
Shamelessness Modesty Shyness
Callousness Just resentment Spitefulness
Pettiness Generosity Vulgarity
Meanness Liberality Wastefulness

Ethics

Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, most notably including the Nicomachean Ethics.[115]

Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (ergon) of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the psuchē (soul) in accordance with reason (logos). Aristotle identified such an optimum activity (the virtuous mean, between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency[15]) of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action, eudaimonia, generally translated as "happiness" or sometimes "well-being". To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character (ēthikē aretē), often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence.[116]

Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (phronesis) and their intellect (nous) can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.[117]

Politics

In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family, which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part".[118] He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality.[119] Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.[120]

 
Aristotle's classifications of political constitutions

The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (polis) which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (koinōnia). The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with social contract theory, according to which individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences".[L]

In Protrepticus, the character 'Aristotle' states:[121]

For we all agree that the most excellent man should rule, i.e., the supreme by nature, and that the law rules and alone is authoritative; but the law is a kind of intelligence, i.e. a discourse based on intelligence. And again, what standard do we have, what criterion of good things, that is more precise than the intelligent man? For all that this man will choose, if the choice is based on his knowledge, are good things and their contraries are bad. And since everybody chooses most of all what conforms to their own proper dispositions (a just man choosing to live justly, a man with bravery to live bravely, likewise a self-controlled man to live with self-control), it is clear that the intelligent man will choose most of all to be intelligent; for this is the function of that capacity. Hence it's evident that, according to the most authoritative judgment, intelligence is supreme among goods.[121]

As Plato's disciple Aristotle was rather critical concerning democracy and, following the outline of certain ideas from Plato's Statesman, he developed a coherent theory of integrating various forms of power into a so-called mixed state:

It is … constitutional to take … from oligarchy that offices are to be elected, and from democracy that this is not to be on a property-qualification. This then is the mode of the mixture; and the mark of a good mixture of democracy and oligarchy is when it is possible to speak of the same constitution as a democracy and as an oligarchy.

— Aristotle. Politics, Book 4, 1294b.10–18

To illustrate this approach, Aristotle proposed a first-of-its-kind mathematical model of voting, albeit textually described, where the democratic principle of "one voter–one vote" is combined with the oligarchic "merit-weighted voting"; for relevant quotes and their translation into mathematical formulas see.[122]

Economics

Aristotle made substantial contributions to economic thought, especially to thought in the Middle Ages.[123] In Politics, Aristotle addresses the city, property, and trade. His response to criticisms of private property, in Lionel Robbins's view, anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists, as it related to the overall utility of social arrangements.[123] Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society, and that although private property is often blamed for social strife, such evils in fact come from human nature. In Politics, Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of money.[123] Money came into use because people became dependent on one another, importing what they needed and exporting the surplus. For the sake of convenience, people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable, such as iron or silver.[124]

Aristotle's discussions on retail and interest was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a profit. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.[124]

Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable".[124] He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".[124]

Rhetoric and poetics

 
The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods (1784) by Bénigne Gagneraux. In his Poetics, Aristotle uses the tragedy Oedipus Tyrannus by Sophocles as an example of how the perfect tragedy should be structured, with a generally good protagonist who starts the play prosperous, but loses everything through some hamartia (fault).[125]

Aristotle's Rhetoric proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ethos (an appeal to the speaker's character), pathos (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and logos (an appeal to logical reasoning).[126] He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: epideictic (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), forensic (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and deliberative (speeches calling on an audience to make a decision on an issue).[127] Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical proofs: enthymeme (proof by syllogism) and paradeigma (proof by example).[128]

Aristotle writes in his Poetics that epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry, painting, sculpture, music, and dance are all fundamentally acts of mimesis ("imitation"), each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner.[129][130] He applies the term mimesis both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist's intention[129] and contends that the audience's realisation of the mimesis is vital to understanding the work itself.[129] Aristotle states that mimesis is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals[129][131] and that all human artistry "follows the pattern of nature".[129] Because of this, Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what Stephen Halliwell calls "highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes."[132] For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation – through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.[133]

While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry.[134] The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the catharsis of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic.[135] Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop.[136]

Views on women

Aristotle's analysis of procreation describes an active, ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive female element. The biological differences are a result of the fact that the female body is well-suited for reproduction, which changes her body temperature, which in turn makes her, in Aristotle's view, incapable of participating in political life.[137] On this ground, proponents of feminist metaphysics have accused Aristotle of misogyny[138] and sexism.[139] However, Aristotle gave equal weight to women's happiness as he did to men's, and commented in his Rhetoric that the things that lead to happiness need to be in women as well as men.[M]

Influence

More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived.[141][142][143] He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher Bryan Magee, "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did".[144] Among countless other achievements, Aristotle was the founder of formal logic,[145] pioneered the study of zoology, and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method.[2][146][147] Taneli Kukkonen, writing in The Classical Tradition, observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind."[147] Jonathan Barnes wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".[148]Aristotle has been called the father of logic, biology, political science, zoology, embryology, natural law, scientific method, rhetoric, psychology, realism, criticism, individualism, teleology, and meteorology.[150]

On his successor, Theophrastus

 
Frontispiece to a 1644 version of Theophrastus's Historia Plantarum, originally written around 300 BC

Aristotle's pupil and successor, Theophrastus, wrote the History of Plants, a pioneering work in botany. Some of his technical terms remain in use, such as carpel from carpos, fruit, and pericarp, from pericarpion, seed chamber.[151] Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was, instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned.[152][153]

On later Greek philosophers

The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic school. Aristotle's students included Aristoxenus, Dicaearchus, Demetrius of Phalerum, Eudemos of Rhodes, Harpalus, Hephaestion, Mnason of Phocis, Nicomachus, and Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"[154]

On Hellenistic science

After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly.[155] It is not until the age of Alexandria under the Ptolemies that advances in biology can be again found.

The first medical teacher at Alexandria, Herophilus of Chalcedon, corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between veins and arteries, noting that the latter pulse while the former do not.[156] Though a few ancient atomists such as Lucretius challenged the teleological viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, natural theology) would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. Ernst Mayr states that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance."[157]

On Byzantine scholars

Greek Christian scribes played a crucial role in the preservation of Aristotle by copying all the extant Greek language manuscripts of the corpus. The first Greek Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus, Elias, and David in the sixth century, and Stephen of Alexandria in the early seventh century.[158] John Philoponus stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle's views on the eternity of the world, movement, and other elements of Aristotelian thought.[159] Philoponus questioned Aristotle's teaching of physics, noting its flaws and introducing the theory of impetus to explain his observations.[160]

After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by Eustratius and Michael of Ephesus reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries, apparently sponsored by Anna Comnena.[161]

On the medieval Islamic world

 
Islamic portrayal of Aristotle, c. 1220

Aristotle was one of the most revered Western thinkers in early Islamic theology. Most of the still extant works of Aristotle,[162] as well as a number of the original Greek commentaries, were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers, scientists and scholars. Averroes, Avicenna and Alpharabius, who wrote on Aristotle in great depth, also influenced Thomas Aquinas and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers. Alkindus greatly admired Aristotle's philosophy,[163] and Averroes spoke of Aristotle as the "exemplar" for all future philosophers.[164] Medieval Muslim scholars regularly described Aristotle as the "First Teacher".[162] The title was later used by Western philosophers (as in the famous poem of Dante) who were influenced by the tradition of Islamic philosophy.[165]

On medieval Europe

With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early medieval Latin West, Aristotle was practically unknown there from c. AD 600 to c. 1100 except through the Latin translation of the Organon made by Boethius. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made, both from Arabic translations, such as those by Gerard of Cremona,[167] and from the original Greek, such as those by James of Venice and William of Moerbeke. After the Scholastic Thomas Aquinas wrote his Summa Theologica, working from Moerbeke's translations and calling Aristotle "The Philosopher",[168] the demand for Aristotle's writings grew, and the Greek manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the Renaissance.[169] These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. Scholars such as Boethius, Peter Abelard, and John Buridan worked on Aristotelian logic.[170]

The medieval English poet Chaucer describes his student as being happy by having

at his beddes heed
Twenty bookes, clad in blak or reed,
Of aristotle and his philosophie,[171]

A cautionary medieval tale held that Aristotle advised his pupil Alexander to avoid the king's seductive mistress, Phyllis, but was himself captivated by her, and allowed her to ride him. Phyllis had secretly told Alexander what to expect, and he witnessed Phyllis proving that a woman's charms could overcome even the greatest philosopher's male intellect. Artists such as Hans Baldung produced a series of illustrations of the popular theme.[172][166]

The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in The Divine Comedy:

Dante
L'Inferno, Canto IV. 131–135
Translation
Hell

vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
seder tra filosofica famiglia.
Tutti lo miran, tutti onor li fanno:
quivi vid'ïo Socrate e Platone
che 'nnanzi a li altri più presso li stanno;

I saw the Master there of those who know,
Amid the philosophic family,
By all admired, and by all reverenced;
There Plato too I saw, and Socrates,
Who stood beside him closer than the rest.

Besides Dante's fellow poets, the classical figure that most influenced the Comedy is Aristotle. Dante built up the philosophy of the Comedy with the works of Aristotle as a foundation, just as the scholastics used Aristotle as the basis for their thinking. Dante knew Aristotle directly from Latin translations of his works and indirectly through quotations in the works of Albert Magnus.[173] Dante even acknowledges Aristotle's influence explicitly in the poem, specifically when Virgil justifies the Inferno's structure by citing the Nicomachean Ethics.[174]

On medieval Judaism

Moses Maimonides (considered to be the foremost intellectual figure of medieval Judaism)[175] adopted Aristotelianism from the Islamic scholars and based his Guide for the Perplexed on it and that became the basis of Jewish scholastic philosophy. Maimonides also considered Aristotle to be the greatest philosopher that ever lived, and styled him as the "chief of the philosophers".[176][177][178] Also, in his letter to Samuel ibn Tibbon, Maimonides observes that there is no need for Samuel to study the writings of philosophers who preceded Aristotle because the works of the latter are "sufficient by themselves and [superior] to all that were written before them. His intellect, Aristotle's is the extreme limit of human intellect, apart from him upon whom the divine emanation has flowed forth to such an extent that they reach the level of prophecy, there being no level higher".[179]

On Early Modern scientists

 
William Harvey's De Motu Cordis, 1628, showed that the blood circulated, contrary to classical era thinking.

In the Early Modern period, scientists such as William Harvey in England and Galileo Galilei in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like Galen, establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment. Harvey demonstrated the circulation of the blood, establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body's heat, as Aristotle thought.[180] Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle's physics, proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight.[181]

On 18th/19th-century thinkers

The 19th-century German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle.[182] Aristotle rigidly separated action from production, and argued for the deserved subservience of some people ("natural slaves"),[183] and the natural superiority (virtue, arete) of others. It was Martin Heidegger, not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition.[184]

The English mathematician George Boole fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of algebraic logic in his 1854 book The Laws of Thought. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check validity, and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.[185]

Charles Darwin regarded Aristotle as the most important contributor to the subject of biology. In an 1882 letter he wrote that "Linnaeus and Cuvier have been my two gods, though in very different ways, but they were mere schoolboys to old Aristotle".[186][187] Also, in later editions of the book "On the Origin of Species', Darwin traced evolutionary ideas as far back as Aristotle;[188] the text he cites is a summary by Aristotle of the ideas of the earlier Greek philosopher Empedocles.[189]

James Joyce's favoured philosopher was Aristotle, whom he considered to be "the greatest thinker of all times".[190] Samuel Taylor Coleridge said: Everybody is born either a Platonist or an Aristotelian.[191] Ayn Rand acknowledged Aristotle as her greatest influence[192] and remarked that in the history of philosophy she could only recommend "three A's"—Aristotle, Aquinas, and Ayn Rand.[193] She also regarded Aristotle as the greatest of all philosophers.[194]Karl Marx considered Aristotle to be the "greatest thinker of antiquity", and called him a "giant thinker", a "genius", and "the great scholar".[195][196][197]

Modern rejection and rehabilitation

 
"That most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander".[147] Illustration by Charles Laplante [fr], 1866

During the 20th century, Aristotle's work was widely criticized. The philosopher Bertrand Russell argued that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell called Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell stated that these errors made it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembered what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.[12]

The Dutch historian of science Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis wrote that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses.[198] In 1985, the biologist Peter Medawar could still state in "pure seventeenth century"[199] tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".[199][200]

By the start of the 21st century, however, Aristotle was taken more seriously: Kukkonen noted that "In the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition."[147] Alasdair MacIntyre has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans.[201] Kukkonen observed, too, that "that most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander" remained current, as in the 2004 film Alexander, while the "firm rules" of Aristotle's theory of drama have ensured a role for the Poetics in Hollywood.[147]

Biologists continue to be interested in Aristotle's thinking. Armand Marie Leroi has reconstructed Aristotle's biology,[202] while Niko Tinbergen's four questions, based on Aristotle's four causes, are used to analyse animal behaviour; they examine function, phylogeny, mechanism, and ontogeny.[203][204]

Surviving works

Corpus Aristotelicum

 
First page of a 1566 edition of the Nicomachean Ethics in Greek and Latin

The works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are collected in the Corpus Aristotelicum. These texts, as opposed to Aristotle's lost works, are technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle's school.[205] Reference to them is made according to the organization of Immanuel Bekker's Royal Prussian Academy edition (Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica, Berlin, 1831–1870), which in turn is based on ancient classifications of these works.[206]

Loss and preservation

Aristotle wrote his works on papyrus scrolls, the common writing medium of that era.[N] His writings are divisible into two groups: the "exoteric", intended for the public, and the "esoteric", for use within the Lyceum school.[208][O][209] Aristotle's "lost" works stray considerably in characterization from the surviving Aristotelian corpus. Whereas the lost works appear to have been originally written with a view to subsequent publication, the surviving works mostly resemble lecture notes not intended for publication.[210][208] Cicero's description of Aristotle's literary style as "a river of gold" must have applied to the published works, not the surviving notes.[P] A major question in the history of Aristotle's works is how the exoteric writings were all lost, and how the ones now possessed came to be found.[212] The consensus is that Andronicus of Rhodes collected the esoteric works of Aristotle's school which existed in the form of smaller, separate works, distinguished them from those of Theophrastus and other Peripatetics, edited them, and finally compiled them into the more cohesive, larger works as they are known today.[213][214]

Legacy

Depictions

Paintings

Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including Lucas Cranach the Elder,[215] Justus van Gent, Raphael, Paolo Veronese, Jusepe de Ribera,[216] Rembrandt,[217] and Francesco Hayez over the centuries. Among the best-known depictions is Raphael's fresco The School of Athens, in the Vatican's Apostolic Palace, where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural vanishing point, reflecting their importance.[218] Rembrandt's Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic Jonathan Jones writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."[219][220]

Sculptures

Eponyms

The Aristotle Mountains in Antarctica are named after Aristotle. He was the first person known to conjecture, in his book Meteorology, the existence of a landmass in the southern high-latitude region and called it Antarctica.[221] Aristoteles is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle's name.[222]

See also

References

Notes

  1. ^ See Shields 2012, pp. 3–16; Düring 1957 covers ancient biographies of Aristotle.
  2. ^ That these dates (the first half of the Olympiad year 384/383 BC, and in 322 shortly before the death of Demosthenes) are correct was shown by August Boeckh (Kleine Schriften VI 195); for further discussion, see Felix Jacoby on FGrHist 244 F 38. Ingemar Düring, Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition, Göteborg, 1957, p. 253
  3. ^ This type of syllogism, with all three terms in 'a', is known by the traditional (medieval) mnemonic Barbara.[26]
  4. ^ M is the Middle (here, Men), S is the Subject (Greeks), P is the Predicate (mortal).[26]
  5. ^ The first equation can be read as 'It is not true that there exists an x such that x is a man and that x is not mortal.'[27]
  6. ^ Rhett Allain notes that Newton's First Law is "essentially a direct reply to Aristotle, that the natural state is not to change motion.[42]
  7. ^ Leonard Susskind comments that Aristotle had clearly never gone ice skating or he would have seen that it takes force to stop an object.[44]
  8. ^ For heavenly bodies like the Sun, Moon, and stars, the observed motions are "to a very good approximation" circular around the Earth's centre, (for example, the apparent rotation of the sky because of the rotation of the Earth, and the rotation of the moon around the Earth) as Aristotle stated.[45]
  9. ^ Drabkin quotes numerous passages from Physics and On the Heavens (De Caelo) which state Aristotle's laws of motion.[43]
  10. ^ Drabkin agrees that density is treated quantitatively in this passage, but without a sharp definition of density as weight per unit volume.[43]
  11. ^ Philoponus and Galileo correctly objected that for the transient phase (still increasing in speed) with heavy objects falling a short distance, the law does not apply: Galileo used balls on a short incline to show this. Rovelli notes that "Two heavy balls with the same shape and different weight do fall at different speeds from an aeroplane, confirming Aristotle's theory, not Galileo's."[45]
  12. ^ For a different reading of social and economic processes in the Nicomachean Ethics and Politics see Polanyi, Karl (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78–115.
  13. ^ "Where, as among the Lacedaemonians, the state of women is bad, almost half of human life is spoilt."[140]
  14. ^ "When the Roman dictator Sulla invaded Athens in 86 BC, he brought back to Rome a fantastic prize – Aristotle's library. Books then were papyrus rolls, from 10 to 20 feet long, and since Aristotle's death in 322 BC, worms and damp had done their worst. The rolls needed repairing, and the texts clarifying and copying on to new papyrus (imported from Egypt – Moses' bulrushes). The man in Rome who put Aristotle's library in order was a Greek scholar, Tyrannio."[207]
  15. ^ Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics 1102a26–27. Aristotle himself never uses the term "esoteric" or "acroamatic". For other passages where Aristotle speaks of exōterikoi logoi, see W.D. Ross, Aristotle's Metaphysics (1953), vol. 2 pp= 408–410. Ross defends an interpretation according to which the phrase, at least in Aristotle's own works, usually refers generally to "discussions not peculiar to the Peripatetic school", rather than to specific works of Aristotle's own.
  16. ^ "veniet flumen orationis aureum fundens Aristoteles", (Google translation: "Aristotle will come pouring forth a golden stream of eloquence").[211]
  17. ^ Compare the medieval tale of Phyllis and Alexander above.

Citations

  1. ^ Collins English Dictionary.
  2. ^ a b c Aristotle (Greek philosopher).
  3. ^ McLeisch 1999, p. 5.
  4. ^ Aristoteles-Park in Stagira.
  5. ^ Borchers, Timothy A.; Hundley, Heather (2018). Rhetorical theory : an introduction (Second ed.). Long Grove, Illinois. ISBN 978-1-4786-3580-2. OCLC 1031145493.
  6. ^ Hall 2018, p. 14.
  7. ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 4.
  8. ^ Blits 1999, pp. 58–63.
  9. ^ Evans 2006.
  10. ^ Aristotle 1984, pp. Introduction.
  11. ^ a b c Shields 2016.
  12. ^ a b c Russell 1972.
  13. ^ a b Green 1991, pp. 58–59.
  14. ^ Smith 2007, p. 88.
  15. ^ a b c d Humphreys 2009.
  16. ^ Green 1991, p. 460.
  17. ^ Filonik 2013, pp. 72–73.
  18. ^ Jones 1980, p. 216.
  19. ^ Gigon 2017, p. 41.
  20. ^ Düring 1957, p. T44a-e.
  21. ^ Britton, Bianca (27 May 2016). "Is this Aristotle's tomb?". CNN. Retrieved 21 January 2023.
  22. ^ Haase 1992, p. 3862.
  23. ^ Degnan 1994, pp. 81–89.
  24. ^ Corcoran 2009, pp. 1–20.
  25. ^ Kant 1787, pp. Preface.
  26. ^ a b c Lagerlund 2016.
  27. ^ Predicate Logic.
  28. ^ Pickover 2009, p. 52.
  29. ^ School of Athens.
  30. ^ Stewart 2019.
  31. ^ Prior Analytics, pp. 24b18–20.
  32. ^ Bobzien 2015.
  33. ^ a b c Smith 2017.
  34. ^ a b c d e f Cohen 2000.
  35. ^ Aristotle 1999, p. 111.
  36. ^ Metaphysics, p. VIII 1043a 10–30.
  37. ^ Lloyd 1968, pp. 43–47.
  38. ^ Metaphysics, p. IX 1050a 5–10.
  39. ^ Metaphysics, p. VIII 1045a–b.
  40. ^ a b c d Wildberg 2016.
  41. ^ a b Lloyd 1968, pp. 133–139, 166–169.
  42. ^ a b Allain 2016.
  43. ^ a b c d e f g h i Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84.
  44. ^ a b c d e Susskind 2011.
  45. ^ a b c d e f g h i Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40.
  46. ^ Carteron 1923, pp. 1–32 and passim.
  47. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 88–90.
  48. ^ a b c d e Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107.
  49. ^ Hankinson 1998, p. 159.
  50. ^ a b Leroi 2015, pp. 91–92, 369–373.
  51. ^ Lahanas.
  52. ^ Physics, p. 2.6.
  53. ^ Miller 1973, pp. 204–213.
  54. ^ Meteorology, p. 1. 8.
  55. ^ Moore 1956, p. 13.
  56. ^ Meteorology, p. Book 1, Part 14.
  57. ^ Lyell 1832, p. 17.
  58. ^ Aristotle (1952). Meteorologica, Chapter II. Translated by Lee, H.D.P. (Loeb Classical Library ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. p. 156. Retrieved 22 January 2021.
  59. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 7.
  60. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 14.
  61. ^ Thompson 1910, p. Prefatory Note.
  62. ^ "Darwin's Ghosts, By Rebecca Stott". independent.co.uk. 2 June 2012. Retrieved 19 June 2012.
  63. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 196, 248.
  64. ^ Day 2013, pp. 5805–5816.
  65. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 66–74, 137.
  66. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 118–119.
  67. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 73.
  68. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 135–136.
  69. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 206.
  70. ^ Sedley 2007, p. 189.
  71. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 273.
  72. ^ Taylor 1922, p. 42.
  73. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 361–365.
  74. ^ Leroi 2011.
  75. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 197–200.
  76. ^ a b Leroi 2015, pp. 365–368.
  77. ^ Taylor 1922, p. 49.
  78. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 408.
  79. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 72–74.
  80. ^ Bergstrom & Dugatkin 2012, p. 35.
  81. ^ Rhodes 1974, p. 7.
  82. ^ Mayr 1982, pp. 201–202.
  83. ^ Lovejoy 1976.
  84. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 111–119.
  85. ^ Lennox, James G. (2001). Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 346. ISBN 0-521-65976-0.
  86. ^ Sandford, Stella (3 December 2019). "From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category is "Sex"?". Redescriptions: Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory. 22 (1): 4–17. doi:10.33134/rds.314. ISSN 2308-0914. S2CID 210140121.
  87. ^ Voultsiadou, Eleni; Vafidis, Dimitris (1 January 2007). "Marine invertebrate diversity in Aristotle's zoology". Contributions to Zoology. 76 (2): 103–120. doi:10.1163/18759866-07602004. ISSN 1875-9866. S2CID 55152069.
  88. ^ von Lieven, Alexander Fürst; Humar, Marcel (2008). "A Cladistic Analysis of Aristotle's Animal Groups in the "Historia animalium"". History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences. 30 (2): 227–262. ISSN 0391-9714. JSTOR 23334371. PMID 19203017.
  89. ^ Laurin, Michel; Humar, Marcel (2022). "Phylogenetic signal in characters from Aristotle's History of Animals". Comptes Rendus Palevol (in French). 21 (1): 1–16. doi:10.5852/cr-palevol2022v21a1. S2CID 245863171.
  90. ^ Mason 1979, pp. 43–44.
  91. ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 156–163.
  92. ^ Mason 1979, p. 45.
  93. ^ Guthrie 2010, p. 348.
  94. ^ On the Soul I.3 406b26-407a10. For some scholarship, see Carter, Jason W. 2017. ‘Aristotle’s Criticism of Timaean Psychology’ Rhizomata 5: 51-78 and Douglas R. Campbell. 2022. "Located in Space: Plato’s Theory of Psychic Motion" Ancient Philosophy 42 (2): 419-442.
  95. ^ For instance, W.D. Ross argued that Aristotle "may well be criticized as having taken [Plato's] myth as if it were sober prose." See Ross, William D. ed. 1961. Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Oxford University Press. The quotation is from page 189.
  96. ^ See, e.g., Douglas R. Campbell, "Located in Space: Plato's Theory of Psychic Motion," Ancient Philosophy 42 (2): 419-442. 2022.
  97. ^ On the Soul I.3.407b14–27. Christopher Shields summarizes it thus: "We might think that an old leather-bound edition of Machiavelli’s The Prince could come to bear the departed soul of Richard Nixon. Aristotle regards this sort of view as worthy of ridicule.” See Shields, C. 2016. Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Oxford University Press. The quotation is from page 133.
  98. ^ There's a large scholarly discussion of this dialectic between Plato and Aristotle here: Douglas R. Campbell, "The Soul’s Tool: Plato on the Usefulness of the Body," Elenchos 43 (1): 7-27. 2022.
  99. ^ Bloch 2007, p. 12.
  100. ^ Bloch 2007, p. 61.
  101. ^ Carruthers 2007, p. 16.
  102. ^ Bloch 2007, p. 25.
  103. ^ Warren 1921, p. 30.
  104. ^ Warren 1921, p. 25.
  105. ^ Carruthers 2007, p. 19.
  106. ^ Warren 1921, p. 296.
  107. ^ Warren 1921, p. 259.
  108. ^ Sorabji 2006, p. 54.
  109. ^ a b c d e f Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423.
  110. ^ a b c d e Shute 1941, pp. 115–118.
  111. ^ Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–23.
  112. ^ Shute 1941, pp. 115–18.
  113. ^ a b Modrak 2009, pp. 169–181.
  114. ^ Webb 1990, pp. 174–184.
  115. ^ Kraut 2001.
  116. ^ Nicomachean Ethics Book I. See for example chapter 7.
  117. ^ Nicomachean Ethics, p. Book VI.
  118. ^ Politics, pp. 1253a19–124.
  119. ^ Aristotle 2009, pp. 320–321.
  120. ^ Ebenstein & Ebenstein 2002, p. 59.
  121. ^ a b Hutchinson & Johnson 2015, p. 22.
  122. ^ Tangian 2020, pp. 35–38.
  123. ^ a b c Robbins 2000, pp. 20–24.
  124. ^ a b c d Aristotle 1948, pp. 16–28.
  125. ^ Kaufmann 1968, pp. 56–60.
  126. ^ Garver 1994, pp. 109–110.
  127. ^ Rorty 1996, pp. 3–7.
  128. ^ Grimaldi 1998, p. 71.
  129. ^ a b c d e Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159.
  130. ^ Poetics, p. I 1447a.
  131. ^ Poetics, p. IV.
  132. ^ Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–59.
  133. ^ Poetics, p. III.
  134. ^ Poetics, p. VI.
  135. ^ Poetics, p. XXVI.
  136. ^ Aesop 1998, pp. Introduction, xi–xii.
  137. ^ See Marguerite Deslauriers, "Sexual Difference in Aristotle's Politics and His Biology," Classical World 102 3 (2009): 215-231.
  138. ^ Freeland 1998.
  139. ^ Morsink 1979, pp. 83–112.
  140. ^ Rhetoric, p. Book I, Chapter 5.
  141. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 8.
  142. ^ Aristotle's Influence 2018.
  143. ^ Garner., Dwight (14 March 2014). . The New York Times. Archived from the original on 1 April 2021.
  144. ^ Magee 2010, p. 34.
  145. ^ Guthrie 1990, p. 156.
  146. ^ Durant 2006, p. 92.
  147. ^ a b c d e Kukkonen 2010, pp. 70–77.
  148. ^ Barnes 1982, p. 86.
  149. ^ Leroi 2015, p. 352.
  150. ^ * "the father of logic": Wentzel Van Huyssteen, Encyclopedia of Science and Religion: A-I, p. 27
    • "the father of biology": S. C. Datt, S. B. Srivastava, Science and society, p. 93.[149]
    • "the father of political science": N. Jayapalan, Aristotle, p. 12, Jonathan Wolff, Lectures on the History of Moral and Political Philosophy, p. 48.
    • the "father of zoology": Josef Rudolf Winkler, A Book of Beetles, p. 12
    • "the father of embryology": D.R. Khanna, Text Book Of Embryology, p. 2
    • "the father of natural law": Shellens, Max Solomon (1959). "Aristotle on Natural Law". Natural Law Forum. 4 (1): 72–100. doi:10.1093/ajj/4.1.72.
    • "the father of scientific method": Shuttleworth, Martyn. "History of the Scientific Method". Explorable., Riccardo Pozzo (2004) The impact of Aristotelianism on modern philosophy. CUA Press. p. 41. ISBN 0-8132-1347-9
    • "the father of psychology": Margot Esther Borden, Psychology in the Light of the East, p. 4
    • "the father of realism": Russell L. Hamm, Philosophy and Education: Alternatives in Theory and Practice, p. 58
    • "the father of criticism": Nagendra Prasad, Personal Bias in Literary Criticism: Dr. Johnson, Matthew Arnold, T.S. Eliot, p. 70. Lord Henry Home Kames, Elements of Criticism, p. 237.
    • "the father of meteorology":"What is meteorology?". Meteorological Office.. Archived from the original on 21 July 2016. Retrieved 16 June 2015.
    • "the father of individualism": Allan Gotthelf, Gregory Salmieri, A Companion to Ayn Rand, p. 325.
    • "the father of teleology": Malcolm Owen Slavin, Daniel H. Kriegman, The Adaptive Design of the Human Psyche: Psychoanalysis, Evolutionary Biology, and the Therapeutic Process, p. 292.
  151. ^ Hooker 1831, p. 219.
  152. ^ Mayr 1982, pp. 90–91.
  153. ^ Mason 1979, p. 46.
  154. ^ Plutarch 1919, p. Part 1, 7:7.
  155. ^ Annas 2001, p. 252.
  156. ^ Mason 1979, p. 56.
  157. ^ Mayr 1985, pp. 90–94.
  158. ^ Sorabji 1990, pp. 20, 28, 35–36.
  159. ^ Sorabji 1990, pp. 233–724.
  160. ^ Lindberg 1992, p. 162.
  161. ^ Sorabji 1990, pp. 20–21, 28–29, 393–406, 407–408.
  162. ^ a b Kennedy-Day 1998.
  163. ^ Staley 1989.
  164. ^ Averroes 1953, p. III, 2, 43.
  165. ^ Nasr 1996, pp. 59–60.
  166. ^ a b Phyllis and Aristotle.
  167. ^ Hasse 2014.
  168. ^ Aquinas 2013.
  169. ^ Kuhn 2018.
  170. ^ Lagerlund.
  171. ^ Allen & Fisher 2011, p. 17.
  172. ^ Aristotle Phyllis.
  173. ^ Lafferty, Roger. "The Philosophy of Dante", pg. 4
  174. ^ Inferno, Canto XI, lines 70-115, Mandelbaum translation.
  175. ^ "Moses Maimonides". Britannica.
  176. ^ Levi ben Gershom, The Wars of the Lord: Book one, Immortality of the soul, p. 35.
  177. ^ Leon Simon, Aspects Of The Hebrew Genius: A Volume Of Essays On Jewish Literature And Thought (1910), p. 127.
  178. ^ Herbert A. Davidson, Herbert A. |q (Herbert Alan) Davidson, Professor of Hebrew Emeritus Herbert Davidson, Moses Maimonides: The Man and His Works, p. 98.
  179. ^ Menachem Kellner, Maimonides on Judaism and the Jewish People, p. 77.
  180. ^ Aird 2011, pp. 118–29.
  181. ^ Machamer 2017.
  182. ^ Durant 2006, p. 86.
  183. ^ Deslauriers & Destrée 2013, pp. 102, 106–107.
  184. ^ Sikka 1997, p. 265.
  185. ^ Boole 2003.
  186. ^ Wilkins, John (2009). Species: a history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press. p. 15. ISBN 978-0-520-27139-5. OCLC 314379168.
  187. ^ Pasipoularides, Ares (2010). The heart's vortex: intracardiac blood flow phenomena. Shelton, Connecticut: People's Medical Publishing House. p. 118. ISBN 978-1-60795-033-2. OCLC 680621287.
  188. ^ Darwin 1872, p. xiii
  189. ^ Aristotle, Physics, translated by Hardie, R. P. and Gayle, R. K. and hosted by MIT's Internet Classics Archive, retrieved 23 April 2009
  190. ^ O'Rourke, F. (2009). Philosophy. In J. McCourt (Ed.), James Joyce in Context (Literature in Context, pp. 320-331). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511576072.029
  191. ^ William Robert Wians, Aristotle's Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, p. 1.
  192. ^ Burns 2009, p. 2.
  193. ^ Sciabarra 1995, p. 12.
  194. ^ James P. Sterba, From Rationality to Equality, p. 94.
  195. ^ F. Novotny, The Posthumous Life of Plato, p. 573
  196. ^ Matt Vidal, Tony Smith, Tomás Rotta, Paul Prew, The Oxford Handbook of Karl Marx, p. 215.
  197. ^ Judith A. Swanson, C. David Corbin, Aristotle's 'Politics': A Reader's Guide, p. 146.
  198. ^ Dijksterhuis 1969, p. 72.
  199. ^ a b Leroi 2015, p. 353.
  200. ^ Medawar & Medawar 1984, p. 28.
  201. ^ Knight 2007, pp. passim.
  202. ^ Leroi 2015.
  203. ^ MacDougall-Shackleton 2011, pp. 2076–2085.
  204. ^ Hladký & Havlíček 2013.
  205. ^ Barnes 1995, p. 9.
  206. ^ Aristotelis Opera.
  207. ^ When libraries were 2001.
  208. ^ a b Barnes 1995, p. 12.
  209. ^ House 1956, p. 35.
  210. ^ Irwin & Fine 1996, pp. xi–xii.
  211. ^ Cicero 1874.
  212. ^ Barnes & Griffin 1999, pp. 1–69.
  213. ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 16.
  214. ^ Barnes 1995, pp. 10–15.
  215. ^ Lucas Cranach the Elder.
  216. ^ Lee & Robinson 2005.
  217. ^ Aristotle with Bust 2002.
  218. ^ Phelan 2002.
  219. ^ Held 1969.
  220. ^ Jones 2002.
  221. ^ Aristotle Mountains.
  222. ^ Aristoteles.

Sources

  • Aesop (1998). The Complete Fables By Aesop. Translated by Temple, Olivia; Temple, Robert. Penguin Classics. ISBN 978-0-14-044649-4.
  • Aird, W. C. (2011). "Discovery of the cardiovascular system: from Galen to William Harvey". Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis. 9: 118–129. doi:10.1111/j.1538-7836.2011.04312.x. PMID 21781247. S2CID 12092592.
  • Allain, Rhett (21 March 2016). "I'm So Totally Over Newton's Laws of Motion". Wired. Retrieved 11 May 2018.
  • Allen, Mark; Fisher, John H. (2011). The Complete Poetry and Prose of Geoffrey Chaucer. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-15-506041-8.
  • Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.
  • Annas, Julia (2001). Classical Greek Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-285357-8.
  • Aquinas, Thomas (2013). Summa Theologica. e-artnow. ISBN 978-80-7484-292-4.
  • Aristoteles (31 January 2019) [1831]. Bekker, Immanuel (ed.). "Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica Aristoteles graece". apud Georgium Reimerum. Retrieved 31 January 2019 – via Internet Archive.
  • "Aristoteles". Gazetteer of Planetary Nomenclature. United States Geological Survey. Retrieved 19 March 2018.
  • "Aristoteles-Park in Stagira". Dimos Aristoteli. Retrieved 20 March 2018.
  • Humphreys, Justin (2009). "Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • "Aristotle (Greek philosopher)". Britannica.com. Britannica Online Encyclopedia. from the original on 22 April 2009. Retrieved 26 April 2009.
  • Aristotle. "Metaphysics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
  • Aristotle. "Meteorology". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
  • Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive.
  • Aristotle. "On the Soul". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
  • Aristotle. "Physics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 31 January 2019.
  • Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
  • Aristotle. "Politics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
  • Aristotle. "Prior Analytics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive.
  • Aristotle. . Translated by Roberts, W. Rhys. Archived from the original on 13 February 2015.
  • "Aristotle Mountains". SCAR Composite Antarctic Gazetteer. Programma Nazionale di Ricerche in Antartide. Department of the Environment and Energy, Australian Antarctic Division, Australian Government. Retrieved 1 March 2018.
  • Aristotle (1948). Monroe, Arthur E. (ed.). Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith. Harvard University Press.
  • Aristotle (1984). Lord, Carnes (ed.). The Politics. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-92184-6.
  • Aristotle (2009) [1995]. Politics. Translated by Ernest Barker and revised with introduction and notes by R.F. Stalley (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953873-7.
  • Aristotle (1999). Aristotle's Metaphysics. Translated by Sachs, Joe. Green Lion Press.
  • "Aristotle and Phyllis". Art Institute Chicago. Retrieved 22 March 2018.
  • "Aristotle definition and meaning". www.collinsdictionary.com. Collins English Dictionary.
  • "Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653)". The Guardian. 27 July 2002. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
  • Averroes (1953). Crawford, F. Stuart (ed.). Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros. Mediaeval Academy of America. OCLC 611422373.
  • Barnes, Jonathan (1982). Aristotle: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-285408-7.
  • Barnes, Jonathan (1995). "Life and Work". The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42294-9.
  • Barnes, Jonathan; Griffin, Miriam Tamara (1999). Philosophia Togata: Plato and Aristotle at Rome. II. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-815222-4.
  • Bergstrom, Carl T.; Dugatkin, Lee Alan (2012). Evolution. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-92592-0.
  • Blits, Kathleen C. (15 April 1999). "Aristotle: Form, function, and comparative anatomy". The Anatomical Record. 257 (2): 58–63. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1097-0185(19990415)257:2<58::AID-AR6>3.0.CO;2-I. PMID 10321433.
  • Bloch, David (2007). Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. ISBN 978-90-04-16046-0.
  • Bobzien, Susanne (2015). "Ancient Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Boole, George (2003) [1854]. The Laws of Thought. Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-1-59102-089-9.
  • Campbell, Michael. "Behind the Name: Meaning, Origin and History of the Name "Aristotle"". Behind the Name. Retrieved 6 April 2012.
  • Carruthers, Mary (2007). The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture. ISBN 978-0-521-42973-3.
  • Carteron, Henri (1923). Notion de Force dans le Systeme d'Aristote (in French). J. Vrin.
  • Cicero, Marcus Tullius (1874). "Book II, chapter XXXVIII, § 119". In Reid, James S. (ed.). The Academica of Cicero 106–43 BC. Macmillan.
  • Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018.
  • Corcoran, John (2009). "Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic". History and Philosophy of Logic. 30: 1–20. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.650.463. doi:10.1080/01445340802228362. S2CID 8514675.
  • Day, J. (2013). "Botany meets archaeology: people and plants in the past". Journal of Experimental Botany. 64 (18): 5805–5816. doi:10.1093/jxb/ert068. PMID 23669575.
  • Degnan, Michael (1994). "Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic". Philosophical Books. 35 (2 (April 1994)): 81–89. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0149.1994.tb02858.x.
  • Deslauriers, Marguerite; Destrée, Pierre (2013). The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-00468-9.
  • Dijksterhuis, Eduard Jan (1969). The Mechanization of the World Picture. Translated by C. Dikshoorn. Princeton University Press.
  • Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584.
  • Durant, Will (2006) [1926]. The Story of Philosophy. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-73916-4.
  • Düring, Ingemar (1957). Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition. By Ingemar Düring. Almqvist & Wiksell in Komm.
  • Ebenstein, Alan; Ebenstein, William (2002). Introduction to Political Thinkers. Wadsworth Group.
  • Evans, Nancy (2006). "Diotima and Demeter as Mystagogues in Plato's Symposium". Hypatia. 21 (2): 1–27. doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2006.tb01091.x. ISSN 1527-2001. S2CID 143750010.
  • Filonik, Jakub (2013). "Athenian impiety trials: a reappraisal". Dike. 16 (16): 72–73. doi:10.13130/1128-8221/4290.
  • Freeland, Cynthia A. (1998). Feminist Interpretations of Aristotle. Penn State University Press. ISBN 978-0-271-01730-3.
  • Garver, Eugene (1994). Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-28425-5.
  • Gigon, Olof (2017) [1965]. Vita Aristotelis Marciana. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-082017-1.
  • Green, Peter (1991). Alexander of Macedon. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-27586-7.
  • Grimaldi, William M. A. (1998). "Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle's Rhetoric". In Enos, Richard Leo; Agnew, Lois Peters (eds.). Landmark Essays on Aristotelian Rhetoric. Landmark Essays. Vol. 14. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. p. 71. ISBN 978-1-880393-32-1.
  • Guthrie, W. (2010). A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-29420-1.
  • Guthrie, W. (1990). A history of Greek philosophy Vol. 6: Aristotle: An Encounter. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-38760-6.
  • Haase, Wolfgang (1992). Philosophie, Wissenschaften, Technik. Philosophie (Doxographica [Forts. ]). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-013699-9.
  • Hall, Edith (2018). Aristotle's Way: How Ancient Wisdom Can Change Your Life. The Bodley Head. ISBN 978-1-84792-407-0.
  • Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4.
  • Hankinson, R.J. (1998). Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199246564.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-823745-7.
  • Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2014). "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Held, Julius (1969). Rembrandt's Aristotle and Other Rembrandt Studies. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-03862-9.
  • Hladký, V.; Havlíček, J (2013). "Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes" (PDF). Human Ethology Bulletin. 28 (4): 3–11.
  • Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244.
  • Hooker, Sir William Jackson (1831). The British Flora: Comprising the Phaenogamous, Or Flowering Plants, and the Ferns. Longman. OCLC 17317293.
  • House, Humphry (1956). Aristotle's Poetics. Rupert Hart-Davis.
  • Hutchinson, D. S.; Johnson, Monte Ransome (2015). "Exhortation to Philosophy" (PDF). Protrepticus. p. 22.
  • Irwin, Terence; Fine, Gail, eds. (1996). Aristotle: Introductory Readings. Hackett Pub. ISBN 978-0-87220-339-6.
  • Jones, Jonathan (27 July 2002). "Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653)". The Guardian. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
  • Jones, W. T. (1980). The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ISBN 978-0-15-538312-8.
  • Kant, Immanuel (1787). Critique of Pure Reason (Second ed.). OCLC 2323615.
  • Kantor, J. R. (1963). The Scientific Evolution of Psychology, Volume I. Principia Press. ISBN 978-0-911188-25-7.
  • Kaufmann, Walter Arnold (1968). Tragedy and Philosophy. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02005-1.
  • Kennedy-Day, Kiki (1998). "Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor and Francis. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-H002-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6.
  • Knight, Kelvin (2007). Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics & Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre. Polity Press. ISBN 978-0-7456-1977-4.
  • Kraut, Richard (1 May 2001). "Aristotle's Ethics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 March 2018.
  • Kuhn, Heinrich (2018). "Aristotelianism in the Renaissance". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Kukkonen, Taneli (2010). Grafton, Anthony; et al. (eds.). The classical tradition. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0.
  • Lagerlund, Henrik (2016). "Medieval Theories of the Syllogism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Lagerlund, Henrik. "Medieval Theories of the Syllogism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Lahanas, Michael. . Mlahanas.de. Archived from the original on 11 April 2009. Retrieved 26 April 2009.
  • Lee, Ellen Wardwell; Robinson, Anne (2005). Indianapolis Museum of Art: Highlights of the Collection. Indianapolis Museum of Art. ISBN 978-0-936260-77-8.
  • Leroi, Armand Marie (Presenter) (3 May 2011). "Aristotle's Lagoon: Embryo Inside a Chicken's Egg". BBC. Retrieved 17 November 2016.
  • Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.
  • Lindberg, David (1992). The Beginnings of Western Science. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-48205-7.
  • Lloyd, G. E. R. (1968). The critic of Plato. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-09456-6.
  • Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). Causes and correlations. Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.
  • Lovejoy, Arthur O. (31 January 1976). The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36153-9.
  • "Lucas Cranach the Elder| Phyllis and Aristotle". Sotheby's. 2008. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
  • Lyell, Charles (1832). Principles of Geology. J. Murray, 1832. OCLC 609586345.
  • MacDougall-Shackleton, Scott A. (27 July 2011). "The levels of analysis revisited". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 366 (1574): 2076–2085. doi:10.1098/rstb.2010.0363. PMC 3130367. PMID 21690126.
  • Machamer, Peter (2017). "Galileo Galilei". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Magee, Bryan (2010). The Story of Philosophy. Dorling Kindersley. ISBN 978-0-241-24126-4.
  • Mason, Stephen F. (1979). A History of the Sciences. Collier Books. ISBN 978-0-02-093400-4. OCLC 924760574.
  • Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought. Belknap Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2.
  • Mayr, Ernst (1985). The Growth of Biological Thought. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2.
  • McLeisch, Kenneth Cole (1999). Aristotle: The Great Philosophers. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-92392-7.
  • Medawar, Peter B.; Medawar, J. S. (1984). Aristotle to Zoos: a philosophical dictionary of biology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283043-2.
  • Miller, Willard M. (1973). "Aristotle on Necessity, Chance, and Spontaneity". New Scholasticism. 47 (2): 204–213. doi:10.5840/newscholas197347237.
  • Modrak, Deborah (2009). "Dreams and Method in Aristotle". Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research. 20: 169–181.
  • Moore, Ruth (1956). The Earth We Live On. Alfred A. Knopf. OCLC 1024467091.
  • Morsink, Johannes (Spring 1979). "Was Aristotle's Biology Sexist?". Journal of the History of Biology. 12 (1): 83–112. doi:10.1007/bf00128136. JSTOR 4330727. PMID 11615776. S2CID 6090923.
  • Nasr, Seyyed Hossein (1996). The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia. Curzon Press. ISBN 978-0-7007-0314-2.
  • Phelan, Joseph (September 2002). "The Philosopher as Hero: Raphael's The School of Athens". ArtCyclopedia. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
  • "Phyllis and Aristotle". 1 February 2019 – via Musee du Louvre.
  • Pickover, Clifford A. (2009). The Math Book: From Pythagoras to the 57th Dimension, 250 Milestones in the History of Mathematics. Sterling. ISBN 978-1-4027-5796-9.
  • "Plutarch – Life of Alexander (Part 1 of 7)". penelope.uchicago.edu. Loeb Classical Library. 1919. Retrieved 31 January 2019.
  • "Predicate Logic" (PDF). University of Texas. (PDF) from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 29 March 2018.
  • Rhodes, Frank Harold Trevor (1974). Evolution. Golden Press. ISBN 978-0-307-64360-5.
  • Robbins, Lionel (2000). Medema, Steven G.; Samuels, Warren J. (eds.). A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures. Princeton University Press.
  • Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (1996). "Structuring Rhetoric". In Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (ed.). Essays on Aristotle's Rhetoric. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-20227-6.
  • Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681.
  • Russell, Bertrand (1972). A history of western philosophy. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-31400-2.
  • Sedley, David (2007). Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-25364-3.
  • Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. OUP USA. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9.
  • Shields, Christopher (2016). "Aristotle's Psychology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.).
  • Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202.
  • Sikka, Sonya (1997). Forms of Transcendence: Heidegger and Medieval Mystical Theology. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-3345-4.
  • Smith, Robin (2017). "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Smith, William George (2007) [1869]. Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology. J. Walton. Retrieved 30 January 2019 – via Internet Archive.
  • Sorabji, R. (2006). Aristotle on Memory (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 54. And this is exactly why we hunt for the successor, starting in our thoughts from the present or from something else, and from something similar, or opposite, or neighbouring. By this means recollection occurs...
  • Sorabji, Richard (1990). Aristotle Transformed. Duckworth. ISBN 978-0-7156-2254-4.
  • Staley, Kevin (1989). "Al-Kindi on Creation: Aristotle's Challenge to Islam". Journal of the History of Ideas. 50 (3): 355–370. doi:10.2307/2709566. JSTOR 2709566.
  • Susskind, Leonard (3 October 2011). "Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3". The Theoretical Minimum. Retrieved 11 May 2018.
  • Taylor, Henry Osborn (1922). . Greek Biology and Medicine. Archived from the original on 27 March 2006. Retrieved 3 January 2017.
  • "The School of Athens by Raphael". Visual Arts Cork. Retrieved 22 March 2018.
  • Stewart, Jessica (2019). "The Story Behind Raphael's Masterpiece 'The School of Athens'". My Modern Met. Retrieved 29 March 2019. Plato's gesture toward the sky is thought to indicate his Theory of Forms. ... Conversely, Aristotle's hand is a visual representation of his belief that knowledge comes from experience. Empiricism, as it is known, theorizes that humans must have concrete evidence to support their ideas
  • Tangian, Andranik (2020). Analytical theory of democracy. Vols. 1 and 2. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-39691-6. ISBN 978-3-030-39690-9. S2CID 216190330.
  • Thompson, D'Arcy (1910). Ross, W. D.; Smith, J. A. (eds.). . The works of Aristotle translated into English. Clarendon Press. OCLC 39273217. Archived from the original on 9 August 2019. Retrieved 19 March 2018.
  • Warren, Howard C. (1921). A History of the Association of Psychology. ISBN 978-0-598-91975-5. OCLC 21010604.
  • Webb, Wilse (1990). Dreamtime and dreamwork: Decoding the language of the night. Jeremy P. Tarcher. ISBN 978-0-87477-594-5.
  • "When libraries were on a roll". The Telegraph. 19 May 2001. Archived from the original on 10 January 2022. Retrieved 29 June 2017.
  • Wildberg (2016). "John Philoponus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Zalta, Edward N., ed. (2018). "Aristotle's Influence". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.).
  • Darwin, Charles (1872), The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (6th ed.), London: John Murray, retrieved 9 January 2009
  • Burns, Jennifer (2009). Goddess of the Market: Ayn Rand and the American Right. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-532487-7.
  • Sciabarra, Chris Matthew (1995). Ayn Rand: The Russian Radical. University Park, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press. ISBN 978-0-271-01440-1.

Further reading

The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.

  • Ackrill, J. L. (1997). Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford University Press.
  • Ackrill, J.L. (1981). Aristotle the Philosopher. Oxford University Press.
  • Adler, Mortimer J. (1978). Aristotle for Everybody. Macmillan.
  • Ammonius (1991). Cohen, S. Marc; Matthews, Gareth B (eds.). On Aristotle's Categories. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2688-9.
  • Aristotle (1908–1952). The Works of Aristotle Translated into English Under the Editorship of W.D. Ross, 12 vols. Clarendon Press. These translations are available in several places online; see External links.
  • Bakalis, Nikolaos. (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing, ISBN 978-1-4120-4843-9.
  • Bocheński, I. M. (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. North-Holland.
  • Bolotin, David (1998). An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing. Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works.
  • Burnyeat, Myles F. et al. (1979). Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy.
  • Cantor, Norman F.; Klein, Peter L., eds. (1969). Ancient Thought: Plato and Aristotle. Monuments of Western Thought. Vol. 1. Blaisdell.
  • Chappell, V. (1973). "Aristotle's Conception of Matter". Journal of Philosophy. 70 (19): 679–696. doi:10.2307/2025076. JSTOR 2025076.
  • Code, Alan (1995). Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76.
  • Cohen, S. Marc; Reeve, C. D. C. (21 November 2020). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.).
  • Ferguson, John (1972). Aristotle. Twayne Publishers. ISBN 978-0-8057-2064-8.
  • De Groot, Jean (2014). Aristotle's Empiricism: Experience and Mechanics in the 4th century BC, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-83-4.
  • Frede, Michael (1987). Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Fuller, B.A.G. (1923). Aristotle. History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 3. Cape.
  • Gendlin, Eugene T. (2012). Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima 27 March 2017 at the Wayback Machine, Volume 1: Books I & II; Volume 2: Book III. The Focusing Institute.
  • Gill, Mary Louise (1989). Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton University Press.
  • Guthrie, W.K.C. (1981). A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 6. Cambridge University Press.
  • Halper, Edward C. (2009). One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books Alpha – Delta. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-21-6.
  • Halper, Edward C. (2005). One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The Central Books. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-05-6.
  • Irwin, Terence H. (1988). Aristotle's First Principles (PDF). Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 0-19-824290-5.
  • Jaeger, Werner (1948). Robinson, Richard (ed.). Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development (2nd ed.). Clarendon Press.
  • Jori, Alberto (2003). Aristotele, Bruno Mondadori (Prize 2003 of the "International Academy of the History of Science"), ISBN 978-88-424-9737-0.
  • Kiernan, Thomas P., ed. (1962). Aristotle Dictionary. Philosophical Library.
  • Knight, Kelvin (2007). Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre, Polity Press.
  • Lewis, Frank A. (1991). Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge University Press.
  • Lord, Carnes (1984). Introduction to The Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago University Press.
  • Loux, Michael J. (1991). Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Maso, Stefano (Ed.), Natali, Carlo (Ed.), Seel, Gerhard (Ed.) (2012) Reading Aristotle: Physics VII. 3: What is Alteration? Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-73-5.
  • McKeon, Richard (1973). Introduction to Aristotle (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.
  • Owen, G. E. L. (1965c). "The Platonism of Aristotle". Proceedings of the British Academy. 50: 125–150. [Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R.R.K. Sorabji, eds.(1975). Articles on Aristotle Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth 14–34.]
  • Pangle, Lorraine Smith (2002). Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511498282. ISBN 978-0-511-49828-2.
  • Plato (1979). Allen, Harold Joseph; Wilbur, James B (eds.). The Worlds of Plato and Aristotle. Prometheus Books.
  • Reeve, C. D. C. (2000). Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle's Metaphysics. Hackett.
  • Rose, Lynn E. (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Charles C Thomas.
  • Ross, Sir David (1995). Aristotle (6th ed.). Routledge.
  • Scaltsas, T. (1994). Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics. Cornell University Press.
  • Strauss, Leo (1964). "On Aristotle's Politics", in The City and Man, Rand McNally.
  • Swanson, Judith (1992). The Public and the Private in Aristotle's Political Philosophy. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2319-2.
  • Veatch, Henry B. (1974). Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation. Indiana University Press.
  • Woods, M. J. (1991b). "Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics". Aristotle and the Later Tradition. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Vol. Suppl. pp. 41–56.

External links

Collections of works
  • Works by Aristotle in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
  • At Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  • Works by Aristotle at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by or about Aristotle at Internet Archive
  • Works by Aristotle at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  
  • Works by Aristotle at Open Library
  • (in English and Greek) Perseus Project at Tufts University
  • At the University of Adelaide 15 February 2017 at the Wayback Machine
  • (in Greek and French) P. Remacle
  • The 11-volume 1837 Bekker edition of Aristotle's Works in Greek (PDF · )

aristotle, other, uses, disambiguation, greek, Ἀριστοτέλης, aristotélēs, pronounced, aristotélɛːs, ancient, greek, philosopher, polymath, writings, cover, broad, range, subjects, including, physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poe. For other uses see Aristotle disambiguation Aristotle ˈ aer ɪ s t ɒ t el 1 Greek Ἀristotelhs Aristoteles pronounced aristotelɛːs 384 322 BC was an Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath His writings cover a broad range of subjects including physics biology zoology metaphysics logic ethics aesthetics poetry drama music rhetoric psychology linguistics economics politics meteorology geology and government As the founder of the Peripatetic school of philosophy in the Lyceum in Athens he began the wider Aristotelian tradition that followed which set the groundwork for the development of modern science AristotleRoman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos c 330 BC with modern alabaster mantleBorn384 BCStagira Chalcidian LeagueDied322 BC aged 61 62 Chalcis Euboea Macedonian EmpireEducationPlatonic AcademyNotable workOrganon Physics Metaphysics Nicomachean Ethics Politics Rhetoric PoeticsEraAncient Greek philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolPeripatetic schoolNotable studentsAlexander the Great Theophrastus AristoxenusMain interestsLogic Natural Philosophy Metaphysics Ethics Politics Rhetoric PoeticsNotable ideasAristotelianism Theoretical philosophy Aristotelian logic syllogismFour causesGenus and differentiaHylomorphism substance essence accidentHypokeimenonPotentiality and actualityTheory of universalsUnmoved mover Natural philosophy Aristotelian biologyAristotelian physicsCommon senseEternity of the worldFive witsHorror vacuiTheory of elements aetherRational animal Practical philosophy Aristotelian ethicsCatharsisDeliberative epideictic and forensic rhetoricEnthymeme and ParadeigmaFamily as a model for the stateGolden meanKyklosMagnanimityMimesisNatural slaveryIntellectual virtues sophia episteme nous phronesis techneThree appeals ethos logos pathosViews on womenInfluences Plato Socrates Heraclitus Parmenides Empedocles Phaleas Hippodamus HippiasInfluenced Averroism Avicennism Literary Neo Aristotelianism Maimonideanism Objectivism Peripatetics Scholasticism Llullism Neo Scotism Second Thomism etc additionally Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism See List of writers influenced by Aristotle Commentaries on Aristotle Pseudo AristotleLittle is known about Aristotle s life He was born in the city of Stagira in Northern Greece during the Classical period His father Nicomachus died when Aristotle was a child and he was brought up by a guardian At seventeen or eighteen years of age he joined Plato s Academy in Athens and remained there until the age of thirty seven c 347 BC Shortly after Plato died Aristotle left Athens and at the request of Philip II of Macedon tutored his son Alexander the Great beginning in 343 BC He established a library in the Lyceum which helped him to produce many of his hundreds of books on papyrus scrolls Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues for publication only around a third of his original output has survived none of it intended for publication Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him It was above all from his teachings that the West inherited its intellectual lexicon as well as problems and methods of inquiry As a result his philosophy has exerted a unique influence on almost every form of knowledge in the West and it continues to be a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion Aristotle s views profoundly shaped medieval scholarship The influence of physical science extended from Late Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages into the Renaissance and were not replaced systematically until the Enlightenment and theories such as classical mechanics were developed Some of Aristotle s zoological observations found in his biology such as on the hectocotyl reproductive arm of the octopus were disbelieved until the 19th century He also influenced Judeo Islamic philosophies during the Middle Ages as well as Christian theology especially the Neoplatonism of the Early Church and the scholastic tradition of the Catholic Church Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as The First Teacher and among medieval Christians like Thomas Aquinas as simply The Philosopher while the poet Dante called him the master of those who know His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic and were studied by medieval scholars such as Peter Abelard and John Buridan Aristotle s influence on logic continued well into the 19th century In addition his ethics though always influential gained renewed interest with the modern advent of virtue ethics Contents 1 Life 2 Theoretical philosophy 2 1 Logic 2 1 1 Organon 2 2 Metaphysics 2 2 1 Substance 2 2 1 1 Immanent realism 2 2 1 2 Potentiality and actuality 2 3 Epistemology 3 Natural philosophy 3 1 Physics 3 1 1 Five elements 3 1 2 Motion 3 1 3 Four causes 3 1 4 Optics 3 1 5 Chance and spontaneity 3 2 Astronomy 3 3 Geology and natural sciences 3 4 Biology 3 4 1 Empirical research 3 4 2 Scientific style 3 4 3 Classification of living things 3 5 Psychology 3 5 1 Soul 3 5 2 Memory 3 5 3 Dreams 4 Practical philosophy 4 1 Ethics 4 2 Politics 4 3 Economics 4 4 Rhetoric and poetics 4 5 Views on women 5 Influence 5 1 On his successor Theophrastus 5 2 On later Greek philosophers 5 3 On Hellenistic science 5 4 On Byzantine scholars 5 5 On the medieval Islamic world 5 6 On medieval Europe 5 7 On medieval Judaism 5 8 On Early Modern scientists 5 9 On 18th 19th century thinkers 5 10 Modern rejection and rehabilitation 6 Surviving works 6 1 Corpus Aristotelicum 6 2 Loss and preservation 7 Legacy 7 1 Depictions 7 2 Eponyms 8 See also 9 References 9 1 Notes 9 2 Citations 9 3 Sources 10 Further reading 11 External linksLifeIn general the details of Aristotle s life are not well established The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points A Aristotle was born in 384 BC B in Stagira Chalcidice 2 about 55 km 34 miles east of modern day Thessaloniki 3 4 His father Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon While he was young Aristotle learned about biology and medical information which was taught by his father 5 Both of Aristotle s parents died when he was about thirteen and Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian 6 Although little information about Aristotle s childhood has survived he probably spent some time within the Macedonian palace making his first connections with the Macedonian monarchy 7 School of Aristotle in Mieza Macedonia Greece At the age of seventeen or eighteen Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at Plato s Academy 8 He probably experienced the Eleusinian Mysteries as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Eleusinian Mysteries to experience is to learn pa8ein ma8eĩn 9 Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348 47 BC The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the Academy s direction after control passed to Plato s nephew Speusippus although it is possible that he feared the anti Macedonian sentiments in Athens at that time and left before Plato died 10 Aristotle then accompanied Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor After the death of Hermias Aristotle travelled with his pupil Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island and its sheltered lagoon While in Lesbos Aristotle married Pythias either Hermias s adoptive daughter or niece She bore him a daughter whom they also named Pythias In 343 BC Aristotle was invited by Philip II of Macedon to become the tutor to his son Alexander 11 12 Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of Macedon During Aristotle s time in the Macedonian court he gave lessons not only to Alexander but also to two other future kings Ptolemy and Cassander 13 Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest and Aristotle s own attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric In one famous example he counsels Alexander to be a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians to look after the former as after friends and relatives and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants 13 By 335 BC Aristotle had returned to Athens establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years While in Athens his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stagira who bore him a son whom he named after his father Nicomachus If the Suda an uncritical compilation from the Middle Ages is accurate he may also have had an eromenos Palaephatus of Abydus 14 Portrait bust of Aristotle an Imperial Roman 1st or 2nd century AD copy of a lost bronze sculpture made by Lysippos This period in Athens between 335 and 323 BC is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works 12 He wrote many dialogues of which only fragments have survived Those works that have survived are in treatise form and were not for the most part intended for widespread publication they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students His most important treatises include Physics Metaphysics Nicomachean Ethics Politics On the Soul and Poetics Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to logic metaphysics mathematics physics biology botany ethics politics agriculture medicine dance and theatre 15 Near the end of his life Alexander and Aristotle became estranged over Alexander s relationship with Persia and Persians A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander s death but the only evidence of this is an unlikely claim made some six years after the death 16 Following Alexander s death anti Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled In 322 BC Demophilus and Eurymedon the Hierophant reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety 17 prompting him to flee to his mother s family estate in Chalcis on Euboea at which occasion he was said to have stated I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy 18 19 20 a reference to Athens s trial and execution of Socrates He died in Chalcis Euboea 2 21 15 of natural causes later that same year having named his student Antipater as his chief executor and leaving a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife 22 Theoretical philosophyLogic Main article Term logic Further information Non Aristotelian logic With the Prior Analytics Aristotle is credited with the earliest study of formal logic 23 and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th century advances in mathematical logic 24 Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that with Aristotle logic reached its completion 25 Organon Main article Organon One of Aristotle s types of syllogism C In words In terms D In equations E All men are mortal All Greeks are men All Greeks are mortal M a PS a MS a P What is today called Aristotelian logic with its types of syllogism methods of logical argument 26 Aristotle himself would have labelled analytics The term logic he reserved to mean dialectics Most of Aristotle s work is probably not in its original form because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the Organon around 40 BC by Andronicus of Rhodes or others among his followers 28 The books are Categories On Interpretation Prior Analytics Posterior Analytics Topics On Sophistical Refutations Plato left and Aristotle in Raphael s 1509 fresco The School of Athens Aristotle holds his Nicomachean Ethics and gestures to the earth representing his view in immanent realism whilst Plato gestures to the heavens indicating his Theory of Forms and holds his Timaeus 29 30 The order of the books or the teachings from which they are composed is not certain but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle s writings It goes from the basics the analysis of simple terms in the Categories the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in On Interpretation to the study of more complex forms namely syllogisms in the Analytics 31 32 and dialectics in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory stricto sensu the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning The Rhetoric is not conventionally included but it states that it relies on the Topics 33 Metaphysics Main article Metaphysics Aristotle The word metaphysics appears to have been coined by the first century AD editor who assembled various small selections of Aristotle s works to the treatise we know by the name Metaphysics 34 Aristotle called it first philosophy and distinguished it from mathematics and natural science physics as the contemplative theoretike philosophy which is theological and studies the divine He wrote in his Metaphysics 1026a16 if there were no other independent things besides the composite natural ones the study of nature would be the primary kind of knowledge but if there is some motionless independent thing the knowledge of this precedes it and is first philosophy and it is universal in just this way because it is first And it belongs to this sort of philosophy to study being as being both what it is and what belongs to it just by virtue of being 35 Substance Further information Hylomorphism Aristotle examines the concepts of substance ousia and essence to ti en einai the what it was to be in his Metaphysics Book VII and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form a philosophical theory called hylomorphism In Book VIII he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the substratum or the stuff of which it is composed For example the matter of a house is the bricks stones timbers etc or whatever constitutes the potential house while the form of the substance is the actual house namely covering for bodies and chattels or any other differentia that let us define something as a house The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form 36 34 Immanent realism Main article Aristotle s theory of universals Plato s forms exist as universals like the ideal form of an apple For Aristotle both matter and form belong to the individual thing hylomorphism Like his teacher Plato Aristotle s philosophy aims at the universal Aristotle s ontology places the universal katholou in particulars kath hekaston things in the world whereas for Plato the universal is a separately existing form which actual things imitate For Aristotle form is still what phenomena are based on but is instantiated in a particular substance 34 Plato argued that all things have a universal form which could be either a property or a relation to other things When one looks at an apple for example one sees an apple and one can also analyse a form of an apple In this distinction there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple Moreover one can place an apple next to a book so that one can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things For example it is possible that there is no particular good in existence but good is still a proper universal form Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point arguing that all universals are instantiated at some period of time and that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things In addition Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals Where Plato spoke of the forms as existing separately from the things that participate in them Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated So according to Aristotle the form of apple exists within each apple rather than in the world of the forms 34 37 Potentiality and actuality Concerning the nature of change kinesis and its causes as he outlines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption 319b 320a he distinguishes coming to be genesis also translated as generation from growth and diminution which is change in quantity locomotion which is change in space and alteration which is change in quality Aristotle argued that a capability like playing the flute could be acquired the potential made actual by learning Coming to be is a change where the substrate of the thing that has undergone the change has itself changed In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality dynamis and actuality entelecheia in association with the matter and the form Referring to potentiality this is what a thing is capable of doing or being acted upon if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else For example the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially dynamei a plant and if it is not prevented by something it will become a plant Potentially beings can either act poiein or be acted upon paschein which can be either innate or learned For example the eyes possess the potentiality of sight innate being acted upon while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning exercise acting Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality Because the end telos is the principle of every change and potentiality exists for the sake of the end actuality accordingly is the end Referring then to the previous example it can be said that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do 34 For that for the sake of which to hou heneka a thing is is its principle and the becoming is for the sake of the end and the actuality is the end and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired For animals do not see in order that they may have sight but they have sight that they may see 38 In summary the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities which is also a final cause or end Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula in time and in substantiality With this definition of the particular substance i e matter and form Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings for example what is it that makes a man one Since according to Plato there are two Ideas animal and biped how then is man a unity However according to Aristotle the potential being matter and the actual one form are one and the same 34 39 Epistemology Aristotle s immanent realism means his epistemology is based on the study of things that exist or happen in the world and rises to knowledge of the universal whereas for Plato epistemology begins with knowledge of universal Forms or ideas and descends to knowledge of particular imitations of these 33 Aristotle uses induction from examples alongside deduction whereas Plato relies on deduction from a priori principles 33 Natural philosophyAristotle s natural philosophy spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics biology and other natural sciences 40 In Aristotle s terminology natural philosophy is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics biology and other natural sciences Aristotle s work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning which he also would describe as science However his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term scientific method For Aristotle all science dianoia is either practical poetical or theoretical Metaphysics 1025b25 His practical science includes ethics and politics his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry his theoretical science covers physics mathematics and metaphysics 40 Physics The four classical elements fire air water earth of Empedocles and Aristotle illustrated with a burning log The log releases all four elements as it is destroyed Main article Aristotelian physics Five elements Main article Classical element In his On Generation and Corruption Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by Empedocles earth water air and fire to two of the four sensible qualities hot cold wet and dry In the Empedoclean scheme all matter was made of the four elements in differing proportions Aristotle s scheme added the heavenly aether the divine substance of the heavenly spheres stars and planets 41 Aristotle s elements 41 Element Hot Cold Wet Dry Motion Modern stateof matterEarth Cold Dry Down SolidWater Cold Wet Down LiquidAir Hot Wet Up GasFire Hot Dry Up PlasmaAether divinesubstance Circular in heavens Motion Further information History of classical mechanics Aristotle describes two kinds of motion violent or unnatural motion such as that of a thrown stone in the Physics 254b10 and natural motion such as of a falling object in On the Heavens 300a20 In violent motion as soon as the agent stops causing it the motion stops also in other words the natural state of an object is to be at rest 42 F since Aristotle does not address friction 43 With this understanding it can be observed that as Aristotle stated heavy objects on the ground say require more force to make them move and objects pushed with greater force move faster 44 G This would imply the equation 44 F m v displaystyle F mv dd incorrect in modern physics 44 Natural motion depends on the element concerned the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens H while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up like fire as is observed or down like earth towards their natural resting places 45 43 I Aristotle s laws of motion In Physics he states that objects fall at a speed proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the fluid they are immersed in 43 This is a correct approximation for objects in Earth s gravitational field moving in air or water 45 In the Physics 215a25 Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law that the speed v of a falling body is proportional say with constant c to its weight W and inversely proportional to the density J r of the fluid in which it is falling 45 43 v c W r displaystyle v c frac W rho dd Aristotle implies that in a vacuum the speed of fall would become infinite and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible 45 43 Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws Henri Carteron held the extreme view 43 that Aristotle s concept of force was basically qualitative 46 but other authors reject this 43 Archimedes corrected Aristotle s theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places metal boats can float if they displace enough water floating depends in Archimedes scheme on the mass and volume of the object not as Aristotle thought its elementary composition 45 Aristotle s writings on motion remained influential until the Early Modern period John Philoponus in the Middle Ages and Galileo are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle s claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect 40 A contrary opinion is given by Carlo Rovelli who argues that Aristotle s physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity that of objects in the Earth s gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air In this system heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones whether friction is ignored or not 45 and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium 44 K Newton s forced motion corresponds to Aristotle s violent motion with its external agent but Aristotle s assumption that the agent s effect stops immediately it stops acting e g the ball leaves the thrower s hand has awkward consequences he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it resulting in the Medieval theory of impetus 45 Four causes Main article Four causes Aristotle argued by analogy with woodwork that a thing takes its form from four causes in the case of a table the wood used material cause its design formal cause the tools and techniques used efficient cause and its decorative or practical purpose final cause 47 Aristotle suggested that the reason for anything coming about can be attributed to four different types of simultaneously active factors His term aitia is traditionally translated as cause but it does not always refer to temporal sequence it might be better translated as explanation but the traditional rendering will be employed here 48 49 Material cause describes the material out of which something is composed Thus the material cause of a table is wood It is not about action It does not mean that one domino knocks over another domino 48 The formal cause is its form i e the arrangement of that matter It tells one what a thing is that a thing is determined by the definition form pattern essence whole synthesis or archetype It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws as the whole i e macrostructure is the cause of its parts a relationship known as the whole part causation Plainly put the formal cause is the idea in the mind of the sculptor that brings the sculpture into being A simple example of the formal cause is the mental image or idea that allows an artist architect or engineer to create a drawing 48 The efficient cause is the primary source or that from which the change under consideration proceeds It identifies what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed and so suggests all sorts of agents non living or living acting as the sources of change or movement or rest Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect this covers the modern definitions of cause as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs In the case of two dominoes when the first is knocked over it causes the second also to fall over 48 In the case of animals this agency is a combination of how it develops from the egg and how its body functions 50 The final cause telos is its purpose the reason why a thing exists or is done including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities The final cause is the purpose or function that something is supposed to serve This covers modern ideas of motivating causes such as volition 48 In the case of living things it implies adaptation to a particular way of life 50 Optics Further information History of optics Aristotle describes experiments in optics using a camera obscura in Problems book 15 The apparatus consisted of a dark chamber with a small aperture that let light in With it he saw that whatever shape he made the hole the sun s image always remained circular He also noted that increasing the distance between the aperture and the image surface magnified the image 51 Chance and spontaneity Further information Accident philosophy According to Aristotle spontaneity and chance are causes of some things distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things from what is spontaneous There is also more a specific kind of chance which Aristotle names luck that only applies to people s moral choices 52 53 Astronomy Further information History of astronomy In astronomy Aristotle refuted Democritus s claim that the Milky Way was made up of those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun s rays pointing out correctly that if the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun then the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them 54 Geology and natural sciences Further information History of geology Aristotle noted that the ground level of the Aeolian islands changed before a volcanic eruption Aristotle was one of the first people to record any geological observations He stated that geological change was too slow to be observed in one person s lifetime 55 56 The geologist Charles Lyell noted that Aristotle described such change including lakes that had dried up and deserts that had become watered by rivers giving as examples the growth of the Nile delta since the time of Homer and the upheaving of one of the Aeolian islands previous to a volcanic eruption 57 Aristotle also made many observations about the hydrologic cycle and meteorology including his major writings Meteorologica For example he made some of the earliest observations about desalination he observed early and correctly that when seawater is heated freshwater evaporates and that the oceans are then replenished by the cycle of rainfall and river runoff I have proved by experiment that salt water evaporated forms fresh and the vapor does not when it condenses condense into sea water again 58 Biology Main article Aristotle s biology Among many pioneering zoological observations Aristotle described the reproductive hectocotyl arm of the octopus bottom left Empirical research Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically 59 and biology forms a large part of his writings He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of Lesbos and the surrounding seas including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos 60 61 His data in History of Animals Generation of Animals Movement of Animals and Parts of Animals are assembled from his own observations 62 statements given by people with specialized knowledge such as beekeepers and fishermen and less accurate accounts provided by travellers from overseas 63 His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident his works on botany have been lost but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived 64 Aristotle reports on the sea life visible from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen He describes the catfish electric ray and frogfish in detail as well as cephalopods such as the octopus and paper nautilus His description of the hectocotyl arm of cephalopods used in sexual reproduction was widely disbelieved until the 19th century 65 He gives accurate descriptions of the four chambered fore stomachs of ruminants 66 and of the ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark 67 He notes that an animal s structure is well matched to function so among birds the heron which lives in marshes with soft mud and lives by catching fish has a long neck and long legs and a sharp spear like beak whereas ducks that swim have short legs and webbed feet 68 Darwin too noted these sorts of differences between similar kinds of animal but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of evolution 69 Aristotle s writings can seem to modern readers close to implying evolution but while Aristotle was aware that new mutations or hybridizations could occur he saw these as rare accidents For Aristotle accidents like heat waves in winter must be considered distinct from natural causes He was thus critical of Empedocles s materialist theory of a survival of the fittest origin of living things and their organs and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results 70 To put his views into modern terms he nowhere says that different species can have a common ancestor or that one kind can change into another or that kinds can become extinct 71 Scientific style Aristotle inferred growth laws from his observations on animals including that brood size decreases with body mass whereas gestation period increases He was correct in these predictions at least for mammals data are shown for mouse and elephant Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense 72 He used the ancient Greek term pepeiramenoi to mean observations or at most investigative procedures like dissection 73 In Generation of Animals he finds a fertilized hen s egg of a suitable stage and opens it to see the embryo s heart beating inside 74 75 Instead he practiced a different style of science systematically gathering data discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals and inferring possible causal explanations from these 76 77 This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field such as genomics It does not result in the same certainty as experimental science but it sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed In this sense Aristotle s biology is scientific 76 From the data he collected and documented Aristotle inferred quite a number of rules relating the life history features of the live bearing tetrapods terrestrial placental mammals that he studied Among these correct predictions are the following Brood size decreases with adult body mass so that an elephant has fewer young usually just one per brood than a mouse Lifespan increases with gestation period and also with body mass so that elephants live longer than mice have a longer period of gestation and are heavier As a final example fecundity decreases with lifespan so long lived kinds like elephants have fewer young in total than short lived kinds like mice 78 Classification of living things Further information Scala naturae Aristotle recorded that the embryo of a dogfish was attached by a cord to a kind of placenta the yolk sac like a higher animal this formed an exception to the linear scale from highest to lowest 79 Aristotle distinguished about 500 species of animals 80 81 arranging these in the History of Animals in a graded scale of perfection a nonreligious version of the scala naturae with man at the top His system had eleven grades of animal from highest potential to lowest expressed in their form at birth the highest gave live birth to hot and wet creatures the lowest laid cold dry mineral like eggs Animals came above plants and these in turn were above minerals 82 83 He grouped what the modern zoologist would call vertebrates as the hotter animals with blood and below them the colder invertebrates as animals without blood Those with blood were divided into the live bearing mammals and the egg laying birds reptiles fish Those without blood were insects crustacea non shelled cephalopods and shelled and the hard shelled molluscs bivalves and gastropods He recognised that animals did not exactly fit into a linear scale and noted various exceptions such as that sharks had a placenta like the tetrapods To a modern biologist the explanation not available to Aristotle is convergent evolution 84 Philosophers of science have generally concluded that Aristotle was not interested in taxonomy 85 86 but zoologists who studied this question recently think otherwise 87 88 89 He believed that purposive final causes guided all natural processes this teleological view justified his observed data as an expression of formal design 90 Aristotle s Scala naturae highest to lowest Group Examples given by Aristotle Blood Legs Souls Rational Sensitive Vegetative Qualities Hot Cold Wet Dry Man Man with blood 2 legs R S V Hot WetLive bearing tetrapods Cat hare with blood 4 legs S V Hot WetCetaceans Dolphin whale with blood none S V Hot WetBirds Bee eater nightjar with blood 2 legs S V Hot Wet except Dry eggsEgg laying tetrapods Chameleon crocodile with blood 4 legs S V Cold Wet except scales eggsSnakes Water snake Ottoman viper with blood none S V Cold Wet except scales eggsEgg laying fishes Sea bass parrotfish with blood none S V Cold Wet including eggs Among the egg laying fishes placental selachians Shark skate with blood none S V Cold Wet but placenta like tetrapodsCrustaceans Shrimp crab without many legs S V Cold Wet except shellCephalopods Squid octopus without tentacles S V Cold WetHard shelled animals Cockle trumpet snail without none S V Cold Dry mineral shell Larva bearing insects Ant cicada without 6 legs S V Cold DrySpontaneously generating Sponges worms without none S V Cold Wet or Dry from earthPlants Fig without none V Cold DryMinerals Iron without none none Cold DryPsychology Soul Further information On the Soul Aristotle proposed a three part structure for souls of plants animals and humans making humans unique in having all three types of soul Aristotle s psychology given in his treatise On the Soul peri psyches posits three kinds of soul psyches the vegetative soul the sensitive soul and the rational soul Humans have a rational soul The human soul incorporates the powers of the other kinds Like the vegetative soul it can grow and nourish itself like the sensitive soul it can experience sensations and move locally The unique part of the human rational soul is its ability to receive forms of other things and to compare them using the nous intellect and logos reason 91 For Aristotle the soul is the form of a living being Because all beings are composites of form and matter the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings e g the ability to initiate movement or in the case of plants growth and chemical transformations which Aristotle considers types of movement 11 In contrast to earlier philosophers but in accordance with the Egyptians he placed the rational soul in the heart rather than the brain 92 Notable is Aristotle s division of sensation and thought which generally differed from the concepts of previous philosophers with the exception of Alcmaeon 93 In On the Soul Aristotle famously criticizes Plato s theory of the soul and develops his own in response to Plato s The first criticism is against Plato s view of the soul in the Timaeus that the soul takes up space and is able to come into physical contact with bodies 94 20th century scholarship overwhelmingly opposed Aristotle s interpretation of Plato and maintained that he had misunderstood Plato 95 Today s scholars have tended to re assess Aristotle s interpretation and have warmed up to it 96 Aristotle s other criticism is that Plato s view of reincarnation entails that it is possible for a soul and its body to be mis matched in principle Aristotle alleges any soul can go with any body according to Plato s theory 97 Aristotle s claim that the soul is the form of a living being is meant to eliminate that possibility and thus rule out reincarnation 98 Memory According to Aristotle in On the Soul memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal appearance and an occurrence in the past 99 In other words a memory is a mental picture phantasm that can be recovered Aristotle believed an impression is left on a semi fluid bodily organ that undergoes several changes in order to make a memory A memory occurs when stimuli such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive all the impressions at once These changes are the same as those involved in the operations of sensation Aristotelian common sense and thinking 100 101 Aristotle uses the term memory for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that can develop from sensation and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents Memory is of the past prediction is of the future and sensation is of the present Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly A transitional channel is needed and located in past experiences both for previous experience and present experience 102 Because Aristotle believes people receive all kinds of sense perceptions and perceive them as impressions people are continually weaving together new impressions of experiences To search for these impressions people search the memory itself 103 Within the memory if one experience is offered instead of a specific memory that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for Recollection occurs when one retrieved experience naturally follows another If the chain of images is needed one memory will stimulate the next When people recall experiences they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed 104 Recollection is thus the self directed activity of retrieving the information stored in a memory impression 105 Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity such as numbers and words Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed 106 Senses perception memory dreams action in Aristotle s psychology Impressions are stored in the sensorium the heart linked by his laws of association similarity contrast and contiguity Aristotle believed the chain of thought which ends in recollection of certain impressions was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity contrast and contiguity described in his laws of association Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience According to Aristotle association is the power innate in a mental state which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences allowing them to rise and be recalled 107 108 Dreams Further information Dream Other Aristotle describes sleep in On Sleep and Wakefulness 109 Sleep takes place as a result of overuse of the senses 110 or of digestion 111 so it is vital to the body 110 While a person is asleep the critical activities which include thinking sensing recalling and remembering do not function as they do during wakefulness Since a person cannot sense during sleep they cannot have desire which is the result of sensation However the senses are able to work during sleep 112 albeit differently 109 unless they are weary 110 Dreams do not involve actually sensing a stimulus In dreams sensation is still involved but in an altered manner 110 Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water and then looks away the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion When a person perceives a stimulus and the stimulus is no longer the focus of their attention it leaves an impression 109 When the body is awake and the senses are functioning properly a person constantly encounters new stimuli to sense and so the impressions of previously perceived stimuli are ignored 110 However during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed as there are no new distracting sensory experiences 109 So dreams result from these lasting impressions Since impressions are all that are left and not the exact stimuli dreams do not resemble the actual waking experience 113 During sleep a person is in an altered state of mind Aristotle compares a sleeping person to a person who is overtaken by strong feelings toward a stimulus For example a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere because they are so overtaken by their feelings Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams like the infatuated person 109 This leads the person to believe the dream is real even when the dreams are absurd in nature 109 In De Anima iii 3 Aristotle ascribes the ability to create to store and to recall images in the absence of perception to the faculty of imagination phantasia 11 One component of Aristotle s theory of dreams disagrees with previously held beliefs He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being Aristotle reasoned naturalistically that instances in which dreams do resemble future events are simply coincidences 114 Aristotle claimed that a dream is first established by the fact that the person is asleep when they experience it If a person had an image appear for a moment after waking up or if they see something in the dark it is not considered a dream because they were awake when it occurred Secondly any sensory experience that is perceived while a person is asleep does not qualify as part of a dream For example if while a person is sleeping a door shuts and in their dream they hear a door is shut this sensory experience is not part of the dream Lastly the images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences 113 Practical philosophyAristotle s practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics politics economics and rhetoric 40 Virtues and their accompanying vices 15 Too little Virtuous mean Too muchHumbleness High mindedness VaingloryLack of purpose Right ambition Over ambitionSpiritlessness Good temper IrascibilityRudeness Civility ObsequiousnessCowardice Courage RashnessInsensibility Self control IntemperanceSarcasm Sincerity BoastfulnessBoorishness Wit BuffooneryShamelessness Modesty ShynessCallousness Just resentment SpitefulnessPettiness Generosity VulgarityMeanness Liberality WastefulnessEthics Main article Aristotelian ethics Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study i e one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake He wrote several treatises on ethics most notably including the Nicomachean Ethics 115 Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function ergon of a thing An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see because the proper function of an eye is sight Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans and that this function must be an activity of the psuche soul in accordance with reason logos Aristotle identified such an optimum activity the virtuous mean between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency 15 of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action eudaimonia generally translated as happiness or sometimes well being To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character ethike arete often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence 116 Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated not deliberately but by teachers and experience leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom phronesis and their intellect nous can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker or in other words a philosopher 117 Politics Main article Politics Aristotle In addition to his works on ethics which address the individual Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community Moreover he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family which in turn is prior to the individual for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part 118 He famously stated that man is by nature a political animal and argued that humanity s defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality 119 Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others Aristotle s conception of the city is organic and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner 120 Aristotle s classifications of political constitutions The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle s understanding Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires the natural community according to Aristotle was the city polis which functions as a political community or partnership koinōnia The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life and to perform beautiful acts The political partnership must be regarded therefore as being for the sake of noble actions not for the sake of living together This is distinguished from modern approaches beginning with social contract theory according to which individuals leave the state of nature because of fear of violent death or its inconveniences L In Protrepticus the character Aristotle states 121 For we all agree that the most excellent man should rule i e the supreme by nature and that the law rules and alone is authoritative but the law is a kind of intelligence i e a discourse based on intelligence And again what standard do we have what criterion of good things that is more precise than the intelligent man For all that this man will choose if the choice is based on his knowledge are good things and their contraries are bad And since everybody chooses most of all what conforms to their own proper dispositions a just man choosing to live justly a man with bravery to live bravely likewise a self controlled man to live with self control it is clear that the intelligent man will choose most of all to be intelligent for this is the function of that capacity Hence it s evident that according to the most authoritative judgment intelligence is supreme among goods 121 As Plato s disciple Aristotle was rather critical concerning democracy and following the outline of certain ideas from Plato s Statesman he developed a coherent theory of integrating various forms of power into a so called mixed state It is constitutional to take from oligarchy that offices are to be elected and from democracy that this is not to be on a property qualification This then is the mode of the mixture and the mark of a good mixture of democracy and oligarchy is when it is possible to speak of the same constitution as a democracy and as an oligarchy Aristotle Politics Book 4 1294b 10 18 To illustrate this approach Aristotle proposed a first of its kind mathematical model of voting albeit textually described where the democratic principle of one voter one vote is combined with the oligarchic merit weighted voting for relevant quotes and their translation into mathematical formulas see 122 Economics Main article Politics Aristotle Aristotle made substantial contributions to economic thought especially to thought in the Middle Ages 123 In Politics Aristotle addresses the city property and trade His response to criticisms of private property in Lionel Robbins s view anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists as it related to the overall utility of social arrangements 123 Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society and that although private property is often blamed for social strife such evils in fact come from human nature In Politics Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of money 123 Money came into use because people became dependent on one another importing what they needed and exporting the surplus For the sake of convenience people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable such as iron or silver 124 Aristotle s discussions on retail and interest was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages He had a low opinion of retail believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household retail trade seeks to make a profit It thus uses goods as a means to an end rather than as an end unto itself He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural Similarly Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural as it makes a gain out of the money itself and not from its use 124 Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them commensurable 124 He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange making it a sort of security That is if we do not want a thing now we shall be able to get it when we do want it 124 Rhetoric and poetics Main articles Rhetoric Aristotle and Poetics Aristotle The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods 1784 by Benigne Gagneraux In his Poetics Aristotle uses the tragedy Oedipus Tyrannus by Sophocles as an example of how the perfect tragedy should be structured with a generally good protagonist who starts the play prosperous but loses everything through some hamartia fault 125 Aristotle s Rhetoric proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience ethos an appeal to the speaker s character pathos an appeal to the audience s emotion and logos an appeal to logical reasoning 126 He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres epideictic ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame forensic judicial speeches over guilt or innocence and deliberative speeches calling on an audience to make a decision on an issue 127 Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical proofs enthymeme proof by syllogism and paradeigma proof by example 128 Aristotle writes in his Poetics that epic poetry tragedy comedy dithyrambic poetry painting sculpture music and dance are all fundamentally acts of mimesis imitation each varying in imitation by medium object and manner 129 130 He applies the term mimesis both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist s intention 129 and contends that the audience s realisation of the mimesis is vital to understanding the work itself 129 Aristotle states that mimesis is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals 129 131 and that all human artistry follows the pattern of nature 129 Because of this Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what Stephen Halliwell calls highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes 132 For example music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone and poetry with language The forms also differ in their object of imitation Comedy for instance is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average Lastly the forms differ in their manner of imitation through narrative or character through change or no change and through drama or no drama 133 While it is believed that Aristotle s Poetics originally comprised two books one on comedy and one on tragedy only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements plot structure character style thought spectacle and lyric poetry 134 The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story and the plot not the characters is the chief focus of tragedy Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear and is meant to effect the catharsis of those same emotions Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on which if either is superior epic or tragic mimesis He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music is more unified and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope it can be considered superior to epic 135 Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles folklore and proverbs he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop 136 Views on women Main article Aristotle s views on women Further information Aristotle s biology Inheritance Aristotle s analysis of procreation describes an active ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert passive female element The biological differences are a result of the fact that the female body is well suited for reproduction which changes her body temperature which in turn makes her in Aristotle s view incapable of participating in political life 137 On this ground proponents of feminist metaphysics have accused Aristotle of misogyny 138 and sexism 139 However Aristotle gave equal weight to women s happiness as he did to men s and commented in his Rhetoric that the things that lead to happiness need to be in women as well as men M InfluenceFurther information List of writers influenced by Aristotle More than 2300 years after his death Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived 141 142 143 He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence and he was the founder of many new fields According to the philosopher Bryan Magee it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did 144 Among countless other achievements Aristotle was the founder of formal logic 145 pioneered the study of zoology and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method 2 146 147 Taneli Kukkonen writing in The Classical Tradition observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched and his reach in influencing every branch of intellectual enterprise including Western ethical and political theory theology rhetoric and literary analysis is equally long As a result Kukkonen argues any analysis of reality today will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind 147 Jonathan Barnes wrote that an account of Aristotle s intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought 148 Aristotle has been called the father of logic biology political science zoology embryology natural law scientific method rhetoric psychology realism criticism individualism teleology and meteorology 150 On his successor Theophrastus Main articles Theophrastus and Historia Plantarum Theophrastus Frontispiece to a 1644 version of Theophrastus s Historia Plantarum originally written around 300 BC Aristotle s pupil and successor Theophrastus wrote the History of Plants a pioneering work in botany Some of his technical terms remain in use such as carpel from carpos fruit and pericarp from pericarpion seed chamber 151 Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned 152 153 On later Greek philosophers Further information Peripatetic school The immediate influence of Aristotle s work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic school Aristotle s students included Aristoxenus Dicaearchus Demetrius of Phalerum Eudemos of Rhodes Harpalus Hephaestion Mnason of Phocis Nicomachus and Theophrastus Aristotle s influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter s bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists botanists and researchers He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle s geography was clearly wrong when the old philosopher released his works to the public Alexander complained Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men s common property 154 On Hellenistic science Further information Ancient Greek medicine After Theophrastus the Lyceum failed to produce any original work Though interest in Aristotle s ideas survived they were generally taken unquestioningly 155 It is not until the age of Alexandria under the Ptolemies that advances in biology can be again found The first medical teacher at Alexandria Herophilus of Chalcedon corrected Aristotle placing intelligence in the brain and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation Herophilus also distinguished between veins and arteries noting that the latter pulse while the former do not 156 Though a few ancient atomists such as Lucretius challenged the teleological viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life teleology and after the rise of Christianity natural theology would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries Ernst Mayr states that there was nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance 157 On Byzantine scholars See also Commentaries on Aristotle and Byzantine Aristotelianism Greek Christian scribes played a crucial role in the preservation of Aristotle by copying all the extant Greek language manuscripts of the corpus The first Greek Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus Elias and David in the sixth century and Stephen of Alexandria in the early seventh century 158 John Philoponus stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle s views on the eternity of the world movement and other elements of Aristotelian thought 159 Philoponus questioned Aristotle s teaching of physics noting its flaws and introducing the theory of impetus to explain his observations 160 After a hiatus of several centuries formal commentary by Eustratius and Michael of Ephesus reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries apparently sponsored by Anna Comnena 161 On the medieval Islamic world Further information Logic in Islamic philosophy and Transmission of the Greek Classics Islamic portrayal of Aristotle c 1220 Aristotle was one of the most revered Western thinkers in early Islamic theology Most of the still extant works of Aristotle 162 as well as a number of the original Greek commentaries were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers scientists and scholars Averroes Avicenna and Alpharabius who wrote on Aristotle in great depth also influenced Thomas Aquinas and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers Alkindus greatly admired Aristotle s philosophy 163 and Averroes spoke of Aristotle as the exemplar for all future philosophers 164 Medieval Muslim scholars regularly described Aristotle as the First Teacher 162 The title was later used by Western philosophers as in the famous poem of Dante who were influenced by the tradition of Islamic philosophy 165 On medieval Europe Woodcut of Aristotle ridden by Phyllis by Hans Baldung 1515 166 Further information Aristotelianism and Syllogism Medieval With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early medieval Latin West Aristotle was practically unknown there from c AD 600 to c 1100 except through the Latin translation of the Organon made by Boethius In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made both from Arabic translations such as those by Gerard of Cremona 167 and from the original Greek such as those by James of Venice and William of Moerbeke After the Scholastic Thomas Aquinas wrote his Summa Theologica working from Moerbeke s translations and calling Aristotle The Philosopher 168 the demand for Aristotle s writings grew and the Greek manuscripts returned to the West stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the Renaissance 169 These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages Scholars such as Boethius Peter Abelard and John Buridan worked on Aristotelian logic 170 The medieval English poet Chaucer describes his student as being happy by having at his beddes heed Twenty bookes clad in blak or reed Of aristotle and his philosophie 171 A cautionary medieval tale held that Aristotle advised his pupil Alexander to avoid the king s seductive mistress Phyllis but was himself captivated by her and allowed her to ride him Phyllis had secretly told Alexander what to expect and he witnessed Phyllis proving that a woman s charms could overcome even the greatest philosopher s male intellect Artists such as Hans Baldung produced a series of illustrations of the popular theme 172 166 The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in The Divine Comedy DanteL Inferno Canto IV 131 135 TranslationHellvidi l maestro di color che sanno seder tra filosofica famiglia Tutti lo miran tutti onor li fanno quivi vid io Socrate e Platone che nnanzi a li altri piu presso li stanno I saw the Master there of those who know Amid the philosophic family By all admired and by all reverenced There Plato too I saw and Socrates Who stood beside him closer than the rest Besides Dante s fellow poets the classical figure that most influenced the Comedy is Aristotle Dante built up the philosophy of the Comedy with the works of Aristotle as a foundation just as the scholastics used Aristotle as the basis for their thinking Dante knew Aristotle directly from Latin translations of his works and indirectly through quotations in the works of Albert Magnus 173 Dante even acknowledges Aristotle s influence explicitly in the poem specifically when Virgil justifies the Inferno s structure by citing the Nicomachean Ethics 174 On medieval Judaism Moses Maimonides considered to be the foremost intellectual figure of medieval Judaism 175 adopted Aristotelianism from the Islamic scholars and based his Guide for the Perplexed on it and that became the basis of Jewish scholastic philosophy Maimonides also considered Aristotle to be the greatest philosopher that ever lived and styled him as the chief of the philosophers 176 177 178 Also in his letter to Samuel ibn Tibbon Maimonides observes that there is no need for Samuel to study the writings of philosophers who preceded Aristotle because the works of the latter are sufficient by themselves and superior to all that were written before them His intellect Aristotle s is the extreme limit of human intellect apart from him upon whom the divine emanation has flowed forth to such an extent that they reach the level of prophecy there being no level higher 179 On Early Modern scientists William Harvey s De Motu Cordis 1628 showed that the blood circulated contrary to classical era thinking In the Early Modern period scientists such as William Harvey in England and Galileo Galilei in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like Galen establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment Harvey demonstrated the circulation of the blood establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body s heat as Aristotle thought 180 Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle s physics proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight 181 On 18th 19th century thinkers The 19th century German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle 182 Aristotle rigidly separated action from production and argued for the deserved subservience of some people natural slaves 183 and the natural superiority virtue arete of others It was Martin Heidegger not Nietzsche who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition 184 The English mathematician George Boole fully accepted Aristotle s logic but decided to go under over and beyond it with his system of algebraic logic in his 1854 book The Laws of Thought This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations enables it to solve equations as well as check validity and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms not just two 185 Charles Darwin regarded Aristotle as the most important contributor to the subject of biology In an 1882 letter he wrote that Linnaeus and Cuvier have been my two gods though in very different ways but they were mere schoolboys to old Aristotle 186 187 Also in later editions of the book On the Origin of Species Darwin traced evolutionary ideas as far back as Aristotle 188 the text he cites is a summary by Aristotle of the ideas of the earlier Greek philosopher Empedocles 189 James Joyce s favoured philosopher was Aristotle whom he considered to be the greatest thinker of all times 190 Samuel Taylor Coleridge said Everybody is born either a Platonist or an Aristotelian 191 Ayn Rand acknowledged Aristotle as her greatest influence 192 and remarked that in the history of philosophy she could only recommend three A s Aristotle Aquinas and Ayn Rand 193 She also regarded Aristotle as the greatest of all philosophers 194 Karl Marx considered Aristotle to be the greatest thinker of antiquity and called him a giant thinker a genius and the great scholar 195 196 197 Modern rejection and rehabilitation That most enduring of romantic images Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander 147 Illustration by Charles Laplante fr 1866 During the 20th century Aristotle s work was widely criticized The philosopher Bertrand Russell argued that almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine Russell called Aristotle s ethics repulsive and labelled his logic as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy Russell stated that these errors made it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle until one remembered what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors 12 The Dutch historian of science Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis wrote that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by proceed ing so readily to frame a theory of such a general character on limited evidence from their senses 198 In 1985 the biologist Peter Medawar could still state in pure seventeenth century 199 tones that Aristotle had assembled a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay imperfect observation wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility 199 200 By the start of the 21st century however Aristotle was taken more seriously Kukkonen noted that In the best 20th century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition 147 Alasdair MacIntyre has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans 201 Kukkonen observed too that that most enduring of romantic images Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander remained current as in the 2004 film Alexander while the firm rules of Aristotle s theory of drama have ensured a role for the Poetics in Hollywood 147 Biologists continue to be interested in Aristotle s thinking Armand Marie Leroi has reconstructed Aristotle s biology 202 while Niko Tinbergen s four questions based on Aristotle s four causes are used to analyse animal behaviour they examine function phylogeny mechanism and ontogeny 203 204 Surviving worksCorpus Aristotelicum Main article Corpus Aristotelicum First page of a 1566 edition of the Nicomachean Ethics in Greek and Latin The works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are collected in the Corpus Aristotelicum These texts as opposed to Aristotle s lost works are technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle s school 205 Reference to them is made according to the organization of Immanuel Bekker s Royal Prussian Academy edition Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica Berlin 1831 1870 which in turn is based on ancient classifications of these works 206 Loss and preservation Further information Recovery of AristotleAristotle wrote his works on papyrus scrolls the common writing medium of that era N His writings are divisible into two groups the exoteric intended for the public and the esoteric for use within the Lyceum school 208 O 209 Aristotle s lost works stray considerably in characterization from the surviving Aristotelian corpus Whereas the lost works appear to have been originally written with a view to subsequent publication the surviving works mostly resemble lecture notes not intended for publication 210 208 Cicero s description of Aristotle s literary style as a river of gold must have applied to the published works not the surviving notes P A major question in the history of Aristotle s works is how the exoteric writings were all lost and how the ones now possessed came to be found 212 The consensus is that Andronicus of Rhodes collected the esoteric works of Aristotle s school which existed in the form of smaller separate works distinguished them from those of Theophrastus and other Peripatetics edited them and finally compiled them into the more cohesive larger works as they are known today 213 214 LegacyDepictions PaintingsAristotle has been depicted by major artists including Lucas Cranach the Elder 215 Justus van Gent Raphael Paolo Veronese Jusepe de Ribera 216 Rembrandt 217 and Francesco Hayez over the centuries Among the best known depictions is Raphael s fresco The School of Athens in the Vatican s Apostolic Palace where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image at the architectural vanishing point reflecting their importance 218 Rembrandt s Aristotle with a Bust of Homer too is a celebrated work showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age as the art critic Jonathan Jones writes this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world ensnaring us in its musty glowing pitch black terrible knowledge of time 219 220 Nuremberg Chronicle anachronistically shows Aristotle in a medieval scholar s clothing Ink and watercolour on paper 1493 Aristotle by Justus van Gent Oil on panel c 1476 Phyllis and Aristotle by Lucas Cranach the Elder Oil on panel 1530 Aristotle by Paolo Veronese Biblioteka Marciana Oil on canvas 1560s Aristotle and Campaspe Q Alessandro Turchi attrib Oil on canvas 1713 Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera Oil on canvas 1637 Aristotle with a Bust of Homer by Rembrandt Oil on canvas 1653 Aristotle by Johann Jakob Dorner the Elder Oil on canvas by 1813 Aristotle by Francesco Hayez Oil on canvas 1811Sculptures Roman copy of 1st or 2nd century from original bronze by Lysippos Louvre Museum Roman copy of 117 138 AD of Greek original Palermo Regional Archeology Museum Relief of Aristotle and Plato by Luca della Robbia Florence Cathedral 1437 1439 Stone statue in niche Gladstone s Library Hawarden Wales 1899 Bronze statue University of Freiburg Germany 1915Eponyms The Aristotle Mountains in Antarctica are named after Aristotle He was the first person known to conjecture in his book Meteorology the existence of a landmass in the southern high latitude region and called it Antarctica 221 Aristoteles is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle s name 222 See alsoAristotelian Society Conimbricenses PerfectionismReferencesNotes See Shields 2012 pp 3 16 During 1957 covers ancient biographies of Aristotle That these dates the first half of the Olympiad year 384 383 BC and in 322 shortly before the death of Demosthenes are correct was shown by August Boeckh Kleine Schriften VI 195 for further discussion see Felix Jacoby on FGrHist 244 F 38 Ingemar During Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition Goteborg 1957 p 253 This type of syllogism with all three terms in a is known by the traditional medieval mnemonic Barbara 26 M is the Middle here Men S is the Subject Greeks P is the Predicate mortal 26 The first equation can be read as It is not true that there exists an x such that x is a man and that x is not mortal 27 Rhett Allain notes that Newton s First Law is essentially a direct reply to Aristotle that the natural state is not to change motion 42 Leonard Susskind comments that Aristotle had clearly never gone ice skating or he would have seen that it takes force to stop an object 44 For heavenly bodies like the Sun Moon and stars the observed motions are to a very good approximation circular around the Earth s centre for example the apparent rotation of the sky because of the rotation of the Earth and the rotation of the moon around the Earth as Aristotle stated 45 Drabkin quotes numerous passages from Physics and On the Heavens De Caelo which state Aristotle s laws of motion 43 Drabkin agrees that density is treated quantitatively in this passage but without a sharp definition of density as weight per unit volume 43 Philoponus and Galileo correctly objected that for the transient phase still increasing in speed with heavy objects falling a short distance the law does not apply Galileo used balls on a short incline to show this Rovelli notes that Two heavy balls with the same shape and different weight do fall at different speeds from an aeroplane confirming Aristotle s theory not Galileo s 45 For a different reading of social and economic processes in the Nicomachean Ethics and Politics see Polanyi Karl 1957 Aristotle Discovers the Economy in Primitive Archaic and Modern Economies Essays of Karl Polanyi ed G Dalton Boston 1971 78 115 Where as among the Lacedaemonians the state of women is bad almost half of human life is spoilt 140 When the Roman dictator Sulla invaded Athens in 86 BC he brought back to Rome a fantastic prize Aristotle s library Books then were papyrus rolls from 10 to 20 feet long and since Aristotle s death in 322 BC worms and damp had done their worst The rolls needed repairing and the texts clarifying and copying on to new papyrus imported from Egypt Moses bulrushes The man in Rome who put Aristotle s library in order was a Greek scholar Tyrannio 207 Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 1102a26 27 Aristotle himself never uses the term esoteric or acroamatic For other passages where Aristotle speaks of exōterikoi logoi see W D Ross Aristotle s Metaphysics 1953 vol 2 pp 408 410 Ross defends an interpretation according to which the phrase at least in Aristotle s own works usually refers generally to discussions not peculiar to the Peripatetic school rather than to specific works of Aristotle s own veniet flumen orationis aureum fundens Aristoteles Google translation Aristotle will come pouring forth a golden stream of eloquence 211 Compare the medieval tale of Phyllis and Alexander above Citations Collins English Dictionary a b c Aristotle Greek philosopher McLeisch 1999 p 5 Aristoteles Park in Stagira Borchers Timothy A Hundley Heather 2018 Rhetorical theory an introduction Second ed Long Grove Illinois ISBN 978 1 4786 3580 2 OCLC 1031145493 Hall 2018 p 14 Anagnostopoulos 2013 p 4 Blits 1999 pp 58 63 Evans 2006 Aristotle 1984 pp Introduction a b c Shields 2016 a b c Russell 1972 a b Green 1991 pp 58 59 Smith 2007 p 88 a b c d Humphreys 2009 Green 1991 p 460 Filonik 2013 pp 72 73 Jones 1980 p 216 Gigon 2017 p 41 During 1957 p T44a e Britton Bianca 27 May 2016 Is this Aristotle s tomb CNN Retrieved 21 January 2023 Haase 1992 p 3862 Degnan 1994 pp 81 89 Corcoran 2009 pp 1 20 Kant 1787 pp Preface a b c Lagerlund 2016 Predicate Logic Pickover 2009 p 52 School of Athens Stewart 2019 Prior Analytics pp 24b18 20 Bobzien 2015 a b c Smith 2017 a b c d e f Cohen 2000 Aristotle 1999 p 111 Metaphysics p VIII 1043a 10 30 Lloyd 1968 pp 43 47 Metaphysics p IX 1050a 5 10 Metaphysics p VIII 1045a b a b c d Wildberg 2016 a b Lloyd 1968 pp 133 139 166 169 a b Allain 2016 a b c d e f g h i Drabkin 1938 pp 60 84 a b c d e Susskind 2011 a b c d e f g h i Rovelli 2015 pp 23 40 Carteron 1923 pp 1 32 and passim Leroi 2015 pp 88 90 a b c d e Lloyd 1996 pp 96 100 106 107 Hankinson 1998 p 159 a b Leroi 2015 pp 91 92 369 373 Lahanas Physics p 2 6 Miller 1973 pp 204 213 Meteorology p 1 8 Moore 1956 p 13 Meteorology p Book 1 Part 14 Lyell 1832 p 17 Aristotle 1952 Meteorologica Chapter II Translated by Lee H D P Loeb Classical Library ed Cambridge MA Harvard University Press p 156 Retrieved 22 January 2021 Leroi 2015 p 7 Leroi 2015 p 14 Thompson 1910 p Prefatory Note Darwin s Ghosts By Rebecca Stott independent co uk 2 June 2012 Retrieved 19 June 2012 Leroi 2015 pp 196 248 Day 2013 pp 5805 5816 Leroi 2015 pp 66 74 137 Leroi 2015 pp 118 119 Leroi 2015 p 73 Leroi 2015 pp 135 136 Leroi 2015 p 206 Sedley 2007 p 189 Leroi 2015 p 273 Taylor 1922 p 42 Leroi 2015 pp 361 365 Leroi 2011 Leroi 2015 pp 197 200 a b Leroi 2015 pp 365 368 Taylor 1922 p 49 Leroi 2015 p 408 Leroi 2015 pp 72 74 Bergstrom amp Dugatkin 2012 p 35 Rhodes 1974 p 7 Mayr 1982 pp 201 202 Lovejoy 1976 Leroi 2015 pp 111 119 Lennox James G 2001 Aristotle s Philosophy of Biology Studies in the Origins of Life Science Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 346 ISBN 0 521 65976 0 Sandford Stella 3 December 2019 From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification What Kind of Category is Sex Redescriptions Political Thought Conceptual History and Feminist Theory 22 1 4 17 doi 10 33134 rds 314 ISSN 2308 0914 S2CID 210140121 Voultsiadou Eleni Vafidis Dimitris 1 January 2007 Marine invertebrate diversity in Aristotle s zoology Contributions to Zoology 76 2 103 120 doi 10 1163 18759866 07602004 ISSN 1875 9866 S2CID 55152069 von Lieven Alexander Furst Humar Marcel 2008 A Cladistic Analysis of Aristotle s Animal Groups in the Historia animalium History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 30 2 227 262 ISSN 0391 9714 JSTOR 23334371 PMID 19203017 Laurin Michel Humar Marcel 2022 Phylogenetic signal in characters from Aristotle s History of Animals Comptes Rendus Palevol in French 21 1 1 16 doi 10 5852 cr palevol2022v21a1 S2CID 245863171 Mason 1979 pp 43 44 Leroi 2015 pp 156 163 Mason 1979 p 45 Guthrie 2010 p 348 On the Soul I 3 406b26 407a10 For some scholarship see Carter Jason W 2017 Aristotle s Criticism of Timaean Psychology Rhizomata 5 51 78 and Douglas R Campbell 2022 Located in Space Plato s Theory of Psychic Motion Ancient Philosophy 42 2 419 442 For instance W D Ross argued that Aristotle may well be criticized as having taken Plato s myth as if it were sober prose See Ross William D ed 1961 Aristotle De Anima Oxford Oxford University Press The quotation is from page 189 See e g Douglas R Campbell Located in Space Plato s Theory of Psychic Motion Ancient Philosophy 42 2 419 442 2022 On the Soul I 3 407b14 27 Christopher Shields summarizes it thus We might think that an old leather bound edition of Machiavelli s The Prince could come to bear the departed soul of Richard Nixon Aristotle regards this sort of view as worthy of ridicule See Shields C 2016 Aristotle De Anima Oxford Oxford University Press The quotation is from page 133 There s a large scholarly discussion of this dialectic between Plato and Aristotle here Douglas R Campbell The Soul s Tool Plato on the Usefulness of the Body Elenchos 43 1 7 27 2022 Bloch 2007 p 12 Bloch 2007 p 61 Carruthers 2007 p 16 Bloch 2007 p 25 Warren 1921 p 30 Warren 1921 p 25 Carruthers 2007 p 19 Warren 1921 p 296 Warren 1921 p 259 Sorabji 2006 p 54 a b c d e f Holowchak 1996 pp 405 423 a b c d e Shute 1941 pp 115 118 Holowchak 1996 pp 405 23 Shute 1941 pp 115 18 a b Modrak 2009 pp 169 181 Webb 1990 pp 174 184 Kraut 2001 Nicomachean Ethics Book I See for example chapter 7 Nicomachean Ethics p Book VI Politics pp 1253a19 124 Aristotle 2009 pp 320 321 Ebenstein amp Ebenstein 2002 p 59 a b Hutchinson amp Johnson 2015 p 22 Tangian 2020 pp 35 38 a b c Robbins 2000 pp 20 24 a b c d Aristotle 1948 pp 16 28 Kaufmann 1968 pp 56 60 Garver 1994 pp 109 110 Rorty 1996 pp 3 7 Grimaldi 1998 p 71 a b c d e Halliwell 2002 pp 152 159 Poetics p I 1447a Poetics p IV Halliwell 2002 pp 152 59 Poetics p III Poetics p VI Poetics p XXVI Aesop 1998 pp Introduction xi xii See Marguerite Deslauriers Sexual Difference in Aristotle s Politics and His Biology Classical World 102 3 2009 215 231 Freeland 1998 Morsink 1979 pp 83 112 Rhetoric p Book I Chapter 5 Leroi 2015 p 8 Aristotle s Influence 2018 Garner Dwight 14 March 2014 Who s More Famous Than Jesus The New York Times Archived from the original on 1 April 2021 Magee 2010 p 34 Guthrie 1990 p 156 Durant 2006 p 92 a b c d e Kukkonen 2010 pp 70 77 Barnes 1982 p 86 Leroi 2015 p 352 the father of logic Wentzel Van Huyssteen Encyclopedia of Science and Religion A I p 27 the father of biology S C Datt S B Srivastava Science and society p 93 149 the father of political science N Jayapalan Aristotle p 12 Jonathan Wolff Lectures on the History of Moral and Political Philosophy p 48 the father of zoology Josef Rudolf Winkler A Book of Beetles p 12 the father of embryology D R Khanna Text Book Of Embryology p 2 the father of natural law Shellens Max Solomon 1959 Aristotle on Natural Law Natural Law Forum 4 1 72 100 doi 10 1093 ajj 4 1 72 the father of scientific method Shuttleworth Martyn History of the Scientific Method Explorable Riccardo Pozzo 2004 The impact of Aristotelianism on modern philosophy CUA Press p 41 ISBN 0 8132 1347 9 the father of psychology Margot Esther Borden Psychology in the Light of the East p 4 the father of realism Russell L Hamm Philosophy and Education Alternatives in Theory and Practice p 58 the father of criticism Nagendra Prasad Personal Bias in Literary Criticism Dr Johnson Matthew Arnold T S Eliot p 70 Lord Henry Home Kames Elements of Criticism p 237 the father of meteorology What is meteorology Meteorological Office 94 05 01 Meteorology Archived from the original on 21 July 2016 Retrieved 16 June 2015 the father of individualism Allan Gotthelf Gregory Salmieri A Companion to Ayn Rand p 325 the father of teleology Malcolm Owen Slavin Daniel H Kriegman The Adaptive Design of the Human Psyche Psychoanalysis Evolutionary Biology and the Therapeutic Process p 292 Hooker 1831 p 219 Mayr 1982 pp 90 91 Mason 1979 p 46 Plutarch 1919 p Part 1 7 7 Annas 2001 p 252 Mason 1979 p 56 Mayr 1985 pp 90 94 Sorabji 1990 pp 20 28 35 36 Sorabji 1990 pp 233 724 Lindberg 1992 p 162 Sorabji 1990 pp 20 21 28 29 393 406 407 408 a b Kennedy Day 1998 Staley 1989 Averroes 1953 p III 2 43 Nasr 1996 pp 59 60 a b Phyllis and Aristotle Hasse 2014 Aquinas 2013 Kuhn 2018 Lagerlund Allen amp Fisher 2011 p 17 Aristotle Phyllis Lafferty Roger The Philosophy of Dante pg 4 Inferno Canto XI lines 70 115 Mandelbaum translation Moses Maimonides Britannica Levi ben Gershom The Wars of the Lord Book one Immortality of the soul p 35 Leon Simon Aspects Of The Hebrew Genius A Volume Of Essays On Jewish Literature And Thought 1910 p 127 Herbert A Davidson Herbert A q Herbert Alan Davidson Professor of Hebrew Emeritus Herbert Davidson Moses Maimonides The Man and His Works p 98 Menachem Kellner Maimonides on Judaism and the Jewish People p 77 Aird 2011 pp 118 29 Machamer 2017 Durant 2006 p 86 Deslauriers amp Destree 2013 pp 102 106 107 Sikka 1997 p 265 Boole 2003 Wilkins John 2009 Species a history of the idea Berkeley University of California Press p 15 ISBN 978 0 520 27139 5 OCLC 314379168 Pasipoularides Ares 2010 The heart s vortex intracardiac blood flow phenomena Shelton Connecticut People s Medical Publishing House p 118 ISBN 978 1 60795 033 2 OCLC 680621287 Darwin 1872 p xiii Aristotle Physics translated by Hardie R P and Gayle R K and hosted by MIT s Internet Classics Archive retrieved 23 April 2009 O Rourke F 2009 Philosophy In J McCourt Ed James Joyce in Context Literature in Context pp 320 331 Cambridge Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 CBO9780511576072 029 William Robert Wians Aristotle s Philosophical Development Problems and Prospects p 1 Burns 2009 p 2 Sciabarra 1995 p 12 James P Sterba From Rationality to Equality p 94 F Novotny The Posthumous Life of Plato p 573 Matt Vidal Tony Smith Tomas Rotta Paul Prew The Oxford Handbook of Karl Marx p 215 Judith A Swanson C David Corbin Aristotle s Politics A Reader s Guide p 146 Dijksterhuis 1969 p 72 a b Leroi 2015 p 353 Medawar amp Medawar 1984 p 28 Knight 2007 pp passim Leroi 2015 MacDougall Shackleton 2011 pp 2076 2085 Hladky amp Havlicek 2013 Barnes 1995 p 9 Aristotelis Opera When libraries were 2001 a b Barnes 1995 p 12 House 1956 p 35 Irwin amp Fine 1996 pp xi xii Cicero 1874 Barnes amp Griffin 1999 pp 1 69 Anagnostopoulos 2013 p 16 Barnes 1995 pp 10 15 Lucas Cranach the Elder Lee amp Robinson 2005 Aristotle with Bust 2002 Phelan 2002 Held 1969 Jones 2002 Aristotle Mountains Aristoteles Sources Aesop 1998 The Complete Fables By Aesop Translated by Temple Olivia Temple Robert Penguin Classics ISBN 978 0 14 044649 4 Aird W C 2011 Discovery of the cardiovascular system from Galen to William Harvey Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis 9 118 129 doi 10 1111 j 1538 7836 2011 04312 x PMID 21781247 S2CID 12092592 Allain Rhett 21 March 2016 I m So Totally Over Newton s Laws of Motion Wired Retrieved 11 May 2018 Allen Mark Fisher John H 2011 The Complete Poetry and Prose of Geoffrey Chaucer Cengage Learning ISBN 978 0 15 506041 8 Anagnostopoulos Georgios 2013 A Companion to Aristotle Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 1 118 59243 4 Annas Julia 2001 Classical Greek Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 285357 8 Aquinas Thomas 2013 Summa Theologica e artnow ISBN 978 80 7484 292 4 Aristoteles 31 January 2019 1831 Bekker Immanuel ed Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica Aristoteles graece apud Georgium Reimerum Retrieved 31 January 2019 via Internet Archive Aristoteles Gazetteer of Planetary Nomenclature United States Geological Survey Retrieved 19 March 2018 Aristoteles Park in Stagira Dimos Aristoteli Retrieved 20 March 2018 Humphreys Justin 2009 Aristotle 384 322 B C E Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Aristotle Greek philosopher Britannica com Britannica Online Encyclopedia Archived from the original on 22 April 2009 Retrieved 26 April 2009 Aristotle Metaphysics classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Retrieved 30 January 2019 Aristotle Meteorology classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Retrieved 30 January 2019 Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Aristotle On the Soul classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Retrieved 30 January 2019 Aristotle Physics classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Retrieved 31 January 2019 Aristotle Poetics classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Retrieved 30 January 2019 Aristotle Politics classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Retrieved 30 January 2019 Aristotle Prior Analytics classics mit edu The Internet Classics Archive Aristotle Rhetoric Translated by Roberts W Rhys Archived from the original on 13 February 2015 Aristotle Mountains SCAR Composite Antarctic Gazetteer Programma Nazionale di Ricerche in Antartide Department of the Environment and Energy Australian Antarctic Division Australian Government Retrieved 1 March 2018 Aristotle 1948 Monroe Arthur E ed Politics Ethics In Early Economic Thought Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith Harvard University Press Aristotle 1984 Lord Carnes ed The Politics University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 92184 6 Aristotle 2009 1995 Politics Translated by Ernest Barker and revised with introduction and notes by R F Stalley 1st ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 953873 7 Aristotle 1999 Aristotle sMetaphysics Translated by Sachs Joe Green Lion Press Aristotle and Phyllis Art Institute Chicago Retrieved 22 March 2018 Aristotle definition and meaning www collinsdictionary com Collins English Dictionary Aristotle with a Bust of Homer Rembrandt 1653 The Guardian 27 July 2002 Retrieved 23 March 2018 Averroes 1953 Crawford F Stuart ed Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros Mediaeval Academy of America OCLC 611422373 Barnes Jonathan 1982 Aristotle A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 285408 7 Barnes Jonathan 1995 Life and Work The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 42294 9 Barnes Jonathan Griffin Miriam Tamara 1999 Philosophia Togata Plato and Aristotle at Rome II Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 815222 4 Bergstrom Carl T Dugatkin Lee Alan 2012 Evolution Norton ISBN 978 0 393 92592 0 Blits Kathleen C 15 April 1999 Aristotle Form function and comparative anatomy The Anatomical Record 257 2 58 63 doi 10 1002 SICI 1097 0185 19990415 257 2 lt 58 AID AR6 gt 3 0 CO 2 I PMID 10321433 Bloch David 2007 Aristotle on Memory and Recollection ISBN 978 90 04 16046 0 Bobzien Susanne 2015 Ancient Logic In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Boole George 2003 1854 The Laws of Thought Prometheus Books ISBN 978 1 59102 089 9 Campbell Michael Behind the Name Meaning Origin and History of the Name Aristotle Behind the Name Retrieved 6 April 2012 Carruthers Mary 2007 The Book of Memory A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture ISBN 978 0 521 42973 3 Carteron Henri 1923 Notion de Force dans le Systeme d Aristote in French J Vrin Cicero Marcus Tullius 1874 Book II chapter XXXVIII 119 In Reid James S ed The Academica of Cicero 106 43 BC Macmillan Cohen S Marc 8 October 2000 Aristotle s Metaphysics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Retrieved 14 November 2018 Corcoran John 2009 Aristotle s Demonstrative Logic History and Philosophy of Logic 30 1 20 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 650 463 doi 10 1080 01445340802228362 S2CID 8514675 Day J 2013 Botany meets archaeology people and plants in the past Journal of Experimental Botany 64 18 5805 5816 doi 10 1093 jxb ert068 PMID 23669575 Degnan Michael 1994 Recent Work in Aristotle s Logic Philosophical Books 35 2 April 1994 81 89 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0149 1994 tb02858 x Deslauriers Marguerite Destree Pierre 2013 The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle s Politics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 00468 9 Dijksterhuis Eduard Jan 1969 The Mechanization of the World Picture Translated by C Dikshoorn Princeton University Press Drabkin Israel E 1938 Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle The American Journal of Philology 59 1 60 84 doi 10 2307 290584 JSTOR 90584 Durant Will 2006 1926 The Story of Philosophy Simon amp Schuster ISBN 978 0 671 73916 4 During Ingemar 1957 Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition By Ingemar During Almqvist amp Wiksell in Komm Ebenstein Alan Ebenstein William 2002 Introduction to Political Thinkers Wadsworth Group Evans Nancy 2006 Diotima and Demeter as Mystagogues in Plato s Symposium Hypatia 21 2 1 27 doi 10 1111 j 1527 2001 2006 tb01091 x ISSN 1527 2001 S2CID 143750010 Filonik Jakub 2013 Athenian impiety trials a reappraisal Dike 16 16 72 73 doi 10 13130 1128 8221 4290 Freeland Cynthia A 1998 Feminist Interpretations of Aristotle Penn State University Press ISBN 978 0 271 01730 3 Garver Eugene 1994 Aristotle s Rhetoric An Art of Character University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 28425 5 Gigon Olof 2017 1965 Vita Aristotelis Marciana Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 082017 1 Green Peter 1991 Alexander of Macedon University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 27586 7 Grimaldi William M A 1998 Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle s Rhetoric In Enos Richard Leo Agnew Lois Peters eds Landmark Essays on Aristotelian Rhetoric Landmark Essays Vol 14 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates p 71 ISBN 978 1 880393 32 1 Guthrie W 2010 A History of Greek Philosophy Vol 1 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 29420 1 Guthrie W 1990 A history of Greek philosophy Vol 6 Aristotle An Encounter Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 38760 6 Haase Wolfgang 1992 Philosophie Wissenschaften Technik Philosophie Doxographica Forts Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 013699 9 Hall Edith 2018 Aristotle s Way How Ancient Wisdom Can Change Your Life The Bodley Head ISBN 978 1 84792 407 0 Halliwell Stephen 2002 Inside and Outside the Work of Art The Aesthetics of Mimesis Ancient Texts and Modern Problems Princeton University Press pp 152 59 ISBN 978 0 691 09258 4 Hankinson R J 1998 Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 0199246564 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 823745 7 Hasse Dag Nikolaus 2014 Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Held Julius 1969 Rembrandt s Aristotle and Other Rembrandt Studies Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 03862 9 Hladky V Havlicek J 2013 Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian Comparison of Tinbergen s Four Whys and Aristotle s Four Causes PDF Human Ethology Bulletin 28 4 3 11 Holowchak Mark 1996 Aristotle on Dreaming What Goes on in Sleep when the Big Fire goes out Ancient Philosophy 16 2 405 423 doi 10 5840 ancientphil199616244 Hooker Sir William Jackson 1831 The British Flora Comprising the Phaenogamous Or Flowering Plants and the Ferns Longman OCLC 17317293 House Humphry 1956 Aristotle s Poetics Rupert Hart Davis Hutchinson D S Johnson Monte Ransome 2015 Exhortation to Philosophy PDF Protrepticus p 22 Irwin Terence Fine Gail eds 1996 Aristotle Introductory Readings Hackett Pub ISBN 978 0 87220 339 6 Jones Jonathan 27 July 2002 Aristotle with a Bust of Homer Rembrandt 1653 The Guardian Retrieved 23 March 2018 Jones W T 1980 The Classical Mind A History of Western Philosophy Harcourt Brace Jovanovich ISBN 978 0 15 538312 8 Kant Immanuel 1787 Critique of Pure Reason Second ed OCLC 2323615 Kantor J R 1963 The Scientific Evolution of Psychology Volume I Principia Press ISBN 978 0 911188 25 7 Kaufmann Walter Arnold 1968 Tragedy and Philosophy Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 02005 1 Kennedy Day Kiki 1998 Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Taylor and Francis doi 10 4324 9780415249126 H002 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Knight Kelvin 2007 Aristotelian Philosophy Ethics amp Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre Polity Press ISBN 978 0 7456 1977 4 Kraut Richard 1 May 2001 Aristotle s Ethics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 19 March 2018 Kuhn Heinrich 2018 Aristotelianism in the Renaissance In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Kukkonen Taneli 2010 Grafton Anthony et al eds The classical tradition Belknap Press of Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 03572 0 Lagerlund Henrik 2016 Medieval Theories of the Syllogism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Lagerlund Henrik Medieval Theories of the Syllogism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Lahanas Michael Optics and ancient Greeks Mlahanas de Archived from the original on 11 April 2009 Retrieved 26 April 2009 Lee Ellen Wardwell Robinson Anne 2005 Indianapolis Museum of Art Highlights of the Collection Indianapolis Museum of Art ISBN 978 0 936260 77 8 Leroi Armand Marie Presenter 3 May 2011 Aristotle s Lagoon Embryo Inside a Chicken s Egg BBC Retrieved 17 November 2016 Leroi Armand Marie 2015 The Lagoon How Aristotle Invented Science Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 4088 3622 4 Lindberg David 1992 The Beginnings of Western Science University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 48205 7 Lloyd G E R 1968 The critic of Plato Aristotle The Growth and Structure of His Thought Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 09456 6 Lloyd G E R 1996 Causes and correlations Adversaries and Authorities Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 55695 8 Lovejoy Arthur O 31 January 1976 The Great Chain of Being A Study of the History of an Idea Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 36153 9 Lucas Cranach the Elder Phyllis and Aristotle Sotheby s 2008 Retrieved 23 March 2018 Lyell Charles 1832 Principles of Geology J Murray 1832 OCLC 609586345 MacDougall Shackleton Scott A 27 July 2011 The levels of analysis revisited Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences 366 1574 2076 2085 doi 10 1098 rstb 2010 0363 PMC 3130367 PMID 21690126 Machamer Peter 2017 Galileo Galilei In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Magee Bryan 2010 The Story of Philosophy Dorling Kindersley ISBN 978 0 241 24126 4 Mason Stephen F 1979 A History of the Sciences Collier Books ISBN 978 0 02 093400 4 OCLC 924760574 Mayr Ernst 1982 The Growth of Biological Thought Belknap Press ISBN 978 0 674 36446 2 Mayr Ernst 1985 The Growth of Biological Thought Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 36446 2 McLeisch Kenneth Cole 1999 Aristotle The Great Philosophers Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 92392 7 Medawar Peter B Medawar J S 1984 Aristotle to Zoos a philosophical dictionary of biology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 283043 2 Miller Willard M 1973 Aristotle on Necessity Chance and Spontaneity New Scholasticism 47 2 204 213 doi 10 5840 newscholas197347237 Modrak Deborah 2009 Dreams and Method in Aristotle Skepsis A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research 20 169 181 Moore Ruth 1956 The Earth We Live On Alfred A Knopf OCLC 1024467091 Morsink Johannes Spring 1979 Was Aristotle s Biology Sexist Journal of the History of Biology 12 1 83 112 doi 10 1007 bf00128136 JSTOR 4330727 PMID 11615776 S2CID 6090923 Nasr Seyyed Hossein 1996 The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia Curzon Press ISBN 978 0 7007 0314 2 Phelan Joseph September 2002 The Philosopher as Hero Raphael s The School of Athens ArtCyclopedia Retrieved 23 March 2018 Phyllis and Aristotle 1 February 2019 via Musee du Louvre Pickover Clifford A 2009 The Math Book From Pythagoras to the 57th Dimension 250 Milestones in the History of Mathematics Sterling ISBN 978 1 4027 5796 9 Plutarch Life of Alexander Part 1 of 7 penelope uchicago edu Loeb Classical Library 1919 Retrieved 31 January 2019 Predicate Logic PDF University of Texas Archived PDF from the original on 29 March 2018 Retrieved 29 March 2018 Rhodes Frank Harold Trevor 1974 Evolution Golden Press ISBN 978 0 307 64360 5 Robbins Lionel 2000 Medema Steven G Samuels Warren J eds A History of Economic Thought The LSE Lectures Princeton University Press Rorty Amelie Oksenberg 1996 Structuring Rhetoric In Rorty Amelie Oksenberg ed Essays on Aristotle sRhetoric University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 20227 6 Rovelli Carlo 2015 Aristotle s Physics A Physicist s Look Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 1 23 40 arXiv 1312 4057 doi 10 1017 apa 2014 11 S2CID 44193681 Russell Bertrand 1972 A history of western philosophy Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 0 671 31400 2 Sedley David 2007 Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 25364 3 Shields Christopher 2012 The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle OUP USA ISBN 978 0 19 518748 9 Shields Christopher 2016 Aristotle s Psychology In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Shute Clarence 1941 The Psychology of Aristotle An Analysis of the Living Being Columbia University Press OCLC 936606202 Sikka Sonya 1997 Forms of Transcendence Heidegger and Medieval Mystical Theology SUNY Press ISBN 978 0 7914 3345 4 Smith Robin 2017 Aristotle s Logic In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Smith William George 2007 1869 Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology J Walton Retrieved 30 January 2019 via Internet Archive Sorabji R 2006 Aristotle on Memory 2nd ed Chicago University of Chicago Press p 54 And this is exactly why we hunt for the successor starting in our thoughts from the present or from something else and from something similar or opposite or neighbouring By this means recollection occurs Sorabji Richard 1990 Aristotle Transformed Duckworth ISBN 978 0 7156 2254 4 Staley Kevin 1989 Al Kindi on Creation Aristotle s Challenge to Islam Journal of the History of Ideas 50 3 355 370 doi 10 2307 2709566 JSTOR 2709566 Susskind Leonard 3 October 2011 Classical Mechanics Lectures 2 3 The Theoretical Minimum Retrieved 11 May 2018 Taylor Henry Osborn 1922 Chapter 3 Aristotle s Biology Greek Biology and Medicine Archived from the original on 27 March 2006 Retrieved 3 January 2017 The School of Athens by Raphael Visual Arts Cork Retrieved 22 March 2018 Stewart Jessica 2019 The Story Behind Raphael s Masterpiece The School of Athens My Modern Met Retrieved 29 March 2019 Plato s gesture toward the sky is thought to indicate his Theory of Forms Conversely Aristotle s hand is a visual representation of his belief that knowledge comes from experience Empiricism as it is known theorizes that humans must have concrete evidence to support their ideas Tangian Andranik 2020 Analytical theory of democracy Vols 1 and 2 Studies in Choice and Welfare Cham Switzerland Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 030 39691 6 ISBN 978 3 030 39690 9 S2CID 216190330 Thompson D Arcy 1910 Ross W D Smith J A eds Historia animalium The works of Aristotle translated into English Clarendon Press OCLC 39273217 Archived from the original on 9 August 2019 Retrieved 19 March 2018 Warren Howard C 1921 A History of the Association of Psychology ISBN 978 0 598 91975 5 OCLC 21010604 Webb Wilse 1990 Dreamtime and dreamwork Decoding the language of the night Jeremy P Tarcher ISBN 978 0 87477 594 5 When libraries were on a roll The Telegraph 19 May 2001 Archived from the original on 10 January 2022 Retrieved 29 June 2017 Wildberg 2016 John Philoponus In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Zalta Edward N ed 2018 Aristotle s Influence Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2018 ed Darwin Charles 1872 The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life 6th ed London John Murray retrieved 9 January 2009 Burns Jennifer 2009 Goddess of the Market Ayn Rand and the American Right New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 532487 7 Sciabarra Chris Matthew 1995 Ayn Rand The Russian Radical University Park Pennsylvania Pennsylvania State University Press ISBN 978 0 271 01440 1 Further readingThe secondary literature on Aristotle is vast The following is only a small selection Ackrill J L 1997 Essays on Plato and Aristotle Oxford University Press Ackrill J L 1981 Aristotle the Philosopher Oxford University Press Adler Mortimer J 1978 Aristotle for Everybody Macmillan Ammonius 1991 Cohen S Marc Matthews Gareth B eds On Aristotle s Categories Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 2688 9 Aristotle 1908 1952 The Works of Aristotle Translated into English Under the Editorship of W D Ross 12 vols Clarendon Press These translations are available in several places online see External links Bakalis Nikolaos 2005 Handbook of Greek Philosophy From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments Trafford Publishing ISBN 978 1 4120 4843 9 Bochenski I M 1951 Ancient Formal Logic North Holland Bolotin David 1998 An Approach to Aristotle s Physics With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing Albany SUNY Press A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle s scientific works Burnyeat Myles F et al 1979 Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle s Metaphysics Oxford Sub faculty of Philosophy Cantor Norman F Klein Peter L eds 1969 Ancient Thought Plato and Aristotle Monuments of Western Thought Vol 1 Blaisdell Chappell V 1973 Aristotle s Conception of Matter Journal of Philosophy 70 19 679 696 doi 10 2307 2025076 JSTOR 2025076 Code Alan 1995 Potentiality in Aristotle s Science and Metaphysics Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76 Cohen S Marc Reeve C D C 21 November 2020 Aristotle s Metaphysics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2020 ed Ferguson John 1972 Aristotle Twayne Publishers ISBN 978 0 8057 2064 8 De Groot Jean 2014 Aristotle s Empiricism Experience and Mechanics in the 4th century BC Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 83 4 Frede Michael 1987 Essays in Ancient Philosophy Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press Fuller B A G 1923 Aristotle History of Greek Philosophy Vol 3 Cape Gendlin Eugene T 2012 Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle s De Anima Archived 27 March 2017 at the Wayback Machine Volume 1 Books I amp II Volume 2 Book III The Focusing Institute Gill Mary Louise 1989 Aristotle on Substance The Paradox of Unity Princeton University Press Guthrie W K C 1981 A History of Greek Philosophy Vol 6 Cambridge University Press Halper Edward C 2009 One and Many in Aristotle s Metaphysics Volume 1 Books Alpha Delta Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 21 6 Halper Edward C 2005 One and Many in Aristotle s Metaphysics Volume 2 The Central Books Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 05 6 Irwin Terence H 1988 Aristotle s First Principles PDF Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN 0 19 824290 5 Jaeger Werner 1948 Robinson Richard ed Aristotle Fundamentals of the History of His Development 2nd ed Clarendon Press Jori Alberto 2003 Aristotele Bruno Mondadori Prize 2003 of the International Academy of the History of Science ISBN 978 88 424 9737 0 Kiernan Thomas P ed 1962 Aristotle Dictionary Philosophical Library Knight Kelvin 2007 Aristotelian Philosophy Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre Polity Press Lewis Frank A 1991 Substance and Predication in Aristotle Cambridge University Press Lord Carnes 1984 Introduction toThe Politics by Aristotle Chicago University Press Loux Michael J 1991 Primary Ousia An Essay on Aristotle s Metaphysics Z and H Ithaca NY Cornell University Press Maso Stefano Ed Natali Carlo Ed Seel Gerhard Ed 2012 Reading Aristotle Physics VII 3 What is Alteration Proceedings of the International ESAP HYELE Conference Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 73 5 McKeon Richard 1973 Introduction to Aristotle 2nd ed University of Chicago Press Owen G E L 1965c The Platonism of Aristotle Proceedings of the British Academy 50 125 150 Reprinted in J Barnes M Schofield and R R K Sorabji eds 1975 Articles on Aristotle Vol 1 Science London Duckworth 14 34 Pangle Lorraine Smith 2002 Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship doi 10 1017 CBO9780511498282 ISBN 978 0 511 49828 2 Plato 1979 Allen Harold Joseph Wilbur James B eds The Worlds of Plato and Aristotle Prometheus Books Reeve C D C 2000 Substantial Knowledge Aristotle s Metaphysics Hackett Rose Lynn E 1968 Aristotle s Syllogistic Charles C Thomas Ross Sir David 1995 Aristotle 6th ed Routledge Scaltsas T 1994 Substances and Universals in Aristotle s Metaphysics Cornell University Press Strauss Leo 1964 On Aristotle s Politics in The City and Man Rand McNally Swanson Judith 1992 The Public and the Private in Aristotle s Political Philosophy Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 2319 2 Veatch Henry B 1974 Aristotle A Contemporary Appreciation Indiana University Press Woods M J 1991b Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle s Metaphysics Aristotle and the Later Tradition Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Vol Suppl pp 41 56 External linksAristotle at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Media from Commons Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Resources from Wikiversity Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article Ἀristotelhs Aristotle at PhilPapers 2553 Aristotle at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project At the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Aristotle general article BiologyEthicsLogicMetaphysicsMotion and its Place in NaturePoeticsPolitics At the Internet Classics Archive From the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Aristotle general article Aristotle in the RenaissanceBiologyCausalityCommentators on AristotleEthicsLogicMathematicsMetaphysicsNatural philosophyNon contradictionPolitical theoryPsychologyRhetoric Turner William 1907 Aristotle Catholic Encyclopedia Vol 1 Laertius Diogenes 1925 The Peripatetics Aristotle Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 1 5 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library Collections of worksWorks by Aristotle in eBook form at Standard Ebooks At Massachusetts Institute of Technology Works by Aristotle at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Aristotle at Internet Archive Works by Aristotle at LibriVox public domain audiobooks Works by Aristotle at Open Library in English and Greek Perseus Project at Tufts University At the University of Adelaide Archived 15 February 2017 at the Wayback Machine in Greek and French P Remacle The 11 volume 1837 Bekker edition of Aristotle s Works in Greek PDF DJVU Portals Physics Biology Earth science Psychology Philosophy Politics Economics Literature Biography Ancient Greece History of science Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Aristotle amp oldid 1137560247, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.