fbpx
Wikipedia

Positivism

Positivism is a philosophical school that holds that all genuine knowledge is either true by definition or positive—meaning a posteriori facts derived by reason and logic from sensory experience.[1][2] Other ways of knowing, such as intuition, introspection, or religious faith, are rejected or considered meaningless.

A portrait of Auguste Comte, the founder of modern positivism

Although the positivist approach has been a recurrent theme in the history of western thought, modern positivism was first articulated in the early 19th century by Auguste Comte.[3][4] His school of sociological positivism holds that society, like the physical world, operates according to general laws.[5] After Comte, positivist schools arose in logic, psychology, economics, historiography, and other fields of thought. Generally, positivists attempted to introduce scientific methods to their respective fields. Since the turn of the 20th century, positivism has declined under criticism from antipositivists and critical theorists, among others, for its alleged scientism, reductionism, overgeneralizations, and methodological limitations.

Etymology edit

The English noun positivism was re-imported in the 19th century from the French word positivisme, derived from positif in its philosophical sense of 'imposed on the mind by experience'. The corresponding adjective (Latin: positīvus) has been used in a similar sense to discuss law (positive law compared to natural law) since the time of Chaucer.[6]

Background edit

Kieran Egan argues that positivism can be traced to the philosophy side of what Plato described as the quarrel between philosophy and poetry, later reformulated by Wilhelm Dilthey as a quarrel between the natural sciences (German: Naturwissenschaften) and the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften).[7][8][9]

In the early nineteenth century, massive advances in the natural sciences encouraged philosophers to apply scientific methods to other fields. Thinkers such as Henri de Saint-Simon, Pierre-Simon Laplace and Auguste Comte believed that the scientific method, the circular dependence of theory and observation, must replace metaphysics in the history of thought.[10]

Positivism in the social sciences edit

Comte's positivism edit

 
Comte first laid out his theory of positivism in The Course in Positive Philosophy

Auguste Comte (1798–1857) first described the epistemological perspective of positivism in The Course in Positive Philosophy, a series of texts published between 1830 and 1842. These texts were followed in 1844 by A General View of Positivism (published in French 1848, English in 1865). The first three volumes of the Course dealt chiefly with the physical sciences already in existence (mathematics, astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology), whereas the latter two emphasized the inevitable coming of social science. Observing the circular dependence of theory and observation in science, and classifying the sciences in this way, Comte may be regarded as the first philosopher of science in the modern sense of the term.[11][12] For him, the physical sciences had necessarily to arrive first, before humanity could adequately channel its efforts into the most challenging and complex "Queen science" of human society itself. His View of Positivism therefore set out to define the empirical goals of sociological method.

The most important thing to determine was the natural order in which the sciences stand—not how they can be made to stand, but how they must stand, irrespective of the wishes of any one. ... This Comte accomplished by taking as the criterion of the position of each the degree of what he called "positivity," which is simply the degree to which the phenomena can be exactly determined. This, as may be readily seen, is also a measure of their relative complexity, since the exactness of a science is in inverse proportion to its complexity. The degree of exactness or positivity is, moreover, that to which it can be subjected to mathematical demonstration, and therefore mathematics, which is not itself a concrete science, is the general gauge by which the position of every science is to be determined. Generalizing thus, Comte found that there were five great groups of phenomena of equal classificatory value but of successively decreasing positivity. To these he gave the names astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology, and sociology.

— Lester F. Ward, The Outlines of Sociology (1898), [13]

Comte offered an account of social evolution, proposing that society undergoes three phases in its quest for the truth according to a general "law of three stages". Comte intended to develop a secular-scientific ideology in the wake of European secularisation.

Comte's stages were (1) the theological, (2) the metaphysical, and (3) the positive.[14] The theological phase of man was based on whole-hearted belief in all things with reference to God. God, Comte says, had reigned supreme over human existence pre-Enlightenment. Humanity's place in society was governed by its association with the divine presences and with the church. The theological phase deals with humankind's accepting the doctrines of the church (or place of worship) rather than relying on its rational powers to explore basic questions about existence. It dealt with the restrictions put in place by the religious organization at the time and the total acceptance of any "fact" adduced for society to believe.[15]

Comte describes the metaphysical phase of humanity as the time since the Enlightenment, a time steeped in logical rationalism, to the time right after the French Revolution. This second phase states that the universal rights of humanity are most important. The central idea is that humanity is invested with certain rights that must be respected. In this phase, democracies and dictators rose and fell in attempts to maintain the innate rights of humanity.[16]

The final stage of the trilogy of Comte's universal law is the scientific, or positive, stage. The central idea of this phase is that individual rights are more important than the rule of any one person. Comte stated that the idea of humanity's ability to govern itself makes this stage inherently different from the rest. There is no higher power governing the masses and the intrigue of any one person can achieve anything based on that individual's free will. The third principle is most important in the positive stage.[17] Comte calls these three phases the universal rule in relation to society and its development. Neither the second nor the third phase can be reached without the completion and understanding of the preceding stage. All stages must be completed in progress.[18]

Comte believed that the appreciation of the past and the ability to build on it towards the future was key in transitioning from the theological and metaphysical phases. The idea of progress was central to Comte's new science, sociology. Sociology would "lead to the historical consideration of every science" because "the history of one science, including pure political history, would make no sense unless it was attached to the study of the general progress of all of humanity".[19] As Comte would say: "from science comes prediction; from prediction comes action".[20] It is a philosophy of human intellectual development that culminated in science. The irony of this series of phases is that though Comte attempted to prove that human development has to go through these three stages, it seems that the positivist stage is far from becoming a realization. This is due to two truths: The positivist phase requires having a complete understanding of the universe and world around us and requires that society should never know if it is in this positivist phase. Anthony Giddens argues that since humanity constantly uses science to discover and research new things, humanity never progresses beyond the second metaphysical phase.[18]

 
Positivist temple in Porto Alegre, Brazil

Comte's fame today owes in part to Emile Littré, who founded The Positivist Review in 1867. As an approach to the philosophy of history, positivism was appropriated by historians such as Hippolyte Taine. Many of Comte's writings were translated into English by the Whig writer, Harriet Martineau, regarded by some as the first female sociologist. Debates continue to rage as to how much Comte appropriated from the work of his mentor, Saint-Simon.[21] He was nevertheless influential: Brazilian thinkers turned to Comte's ideas about training a scientific elite in order to flourish in the industrialization process. Brazil's national motto, Ordem e Progresso ("Order and Progress") was taken from the positivism motto, "Love as principle, order as the basis, progress as the goal", which was also influential in Poland.[citation needed]

In later life, Comte developed a 'religion of humanity' for positivist societies in order to fulfil the cohesive function once held by traditional worship. In 1849, he proposed a calendar reform called the 'positivist calendar'. For close associate John Stuart Mill, it was possible to distinguish between a "good Comte" (the author of the Course in Positive Philosophy) and a "bad Comte" (the author of the secular-religious system).[11] The system was unsuccessful but met with the publication of Darwin's On the Origin of Species to influence the proliferation of various secular humanist organizations in the 19th century, especially through the work of secularists such as George Holyoake and Richard Congreve. Although Comte's English followers, including George Eliot and Harriet Martineau, for the most part rejected the full gloomy panoply of his system, they liked the idea of a religion of humanity and his injunction to "vivre pour autrui" ("live for others", from which comes the word "altruism").[22]

The early sociology of Herbert Spencer came about broadly as a reaction to Comte; writing after various developments in evolutionary biology, Spencer attempted (in vain) to reformulate the discipline in what we might now describe as socially Darwinistic terms.[citation needed]

Early followers of Comte edit

Within a few years, other scientific and philosophical thinkers began creating their own definitions for positivism. These included Émile Zola, Emile Hennequin, Wilhelm Scherer, and Dimitri Pisarev. Fabien Magnin was the first working-class adherent to Comte's ideas, and became the leader of a movement known as "Proletarian Positivism". Comte appointed Magnin as his successor as president of the Positive Society in the event of Comte's death. Magnin filled this role from 1857 to 1880, when he resigned.[23] Magnin was in touch with the English positivists Richard Congreve and Edward Spencer Beesly. He established the Cercle des prolétaires positivistes in 1863 which was affiliated to the First International. Eugène Sémérie was a psychiatrist who was also involved in the Positivist movement, setting up a positivist club in Paris after the foundation of the French Third Republic in 1870. He wrote: "Positivism is not only a philosophical doctrine, it is also a political party which claims to reconcile order—the necessary basis for all social activity—with Progress, which is its goal."[24]

Durkheim's positivism edit

 
Émile Durkheim

The modern academic discipline of sociology began with the work of Émile Durkheim (1858–1917). While Durkheim rejected much of the details of Comte's philosophy, he retained and refined its method, maintaining that the social sciences are a logical continuation of the natural ones into the realm of human activity, and insisting that they may retain the same objectivity, rationalism, and approach to causality.[25] Durkheim set up the first European department of sociology at the University of Bordeaux in 1895, publishing his Rules of the Sociological Method (1895).[26] In this text he argued: "[o]ur main goal is to extend scientific rationalism to human conduct... What has been called our positivism is but a consequence of this rationalism."[13]

Durkheim's seminal monograph, Suicide (1897), a case study of suicide rates amongst Catholic and Protestant populations, distinguished sociological analysis from psychology or philosophy.[27] By carefully examining suicide statistics in different police districts, he attempted to demonstrate that Catholic communities have a lower suicide rate than Protestants, something he attributed to social (as opposed to individual or psychological) causes. He developed the notion of objective sui generis "social facts" to delineate a unique empirical object for the science of sociology to study.[25] Through such studies, he posited, sociology would be able to determine whether a given society is 'healthy' or 'pathological', and seek social reform to negate organic breakdown or "social anomie". Durkheim described sociology as the "science of institutions, their genesis and their functioning".[28]

David Ashley and David M. Orenstein have alleged, in a consumer textbook published by Pearson Education, that accounts of Durkheim's positivism are possibly exaggerated and oversimplified; Comte was the only major sociological thinker to postulate that the social realm may be subject to scientific analysis in exactly the same way as natural science, whereas Durkheim saw a far greater need for a distinctly sociological scientific methodology. His lifework was fundamental in the establishment of practical social research as we know it today—techniques which continue beyond sociology and form the methodological basis of other social sciences, such as political science, as well of market research and other fields.[29]

Historical positivism edit

In historiography, historical or documentary positivism is the belief that historians should pursue the objective truth of the past by allowing historical sources to "speak for themselves", without additional interpretation.[30][31] In the words of the French historian Fustel de Coulanges, as a positivist, "It is not I who am speaking, but history itself". The heavy emphasis placed by historical positivists on documentary sources led to the development of methods of source criticism, which seek to expunge bias and uncover original sources in their pristine state.[30]

The origin of the historical positivist school is particularly associated with the 19th-century German historian Leopold von Ranke, who argued that the historian should seek to describe historical truth "wie es eigentlich gewesen ist" ("as it actually was")—though subsequent historians of the concept, such as Georg Iggers, have argued that its development owed more to Ranke's followers than Ranke himself.[32]

Historical positivism was critiqued in the 20th century by historians and philosophers of history from various schools of thought, including Ernst Kantorowicz in Weimar Germany—who argued that "positivism ... faces the danger of becoming Romantic when it maintains that it is possible to find the Blue Flower of truth without preconceptions"—and Raymond Aron and Michel Foucault in postwar France, who both posited that interpretations are always ultimately multiple and there is no final objective truth to recover.[33][31][34] In his posthumously published 1946 The Idea of History, the English historian R. G. Collingwood criticized historical positivism for conflating scientific facts with historical facts, which are always inferred and cannot be confirmed by repetition, and argued that its focus on the "collection of facts" had given historians "unprecedented mastery over small-scale problems", but "unprecedented weakness in dealing with large-scale problems".[35]

Historicist arguments against positivist approaches in historiography include that history differs from sciences like physics and ethology in subject matter and method;[36][37][38] that much of what history studies is nonquantifiable, and therefore to quantify is to lose in precision; and that experimental methods and mathematical models do not generally apply to history, so that it is not possible to formulate general (quasi-absolute) laws in history.[38]

Other subfields edit

In psychology the positivist movement was influential in the development of operationalism. The 1927 philosophy of science book The Logic of Modern Physics in particular, which was originally intended for physicists, coined the term operational definition, which went on to dominate psychological method for the whole century.[39]

In economics, practicing researchers tend to emulate the methodological assumptions of classical positivism, but only in a de facto fashion: the majority of economists do not explicitly concern themselves with matters of epistemology.[40] Economic thinker Friedrich Hayek (see "Law, Legislation and Liberty") rejected positivism in the social sciences as hopelessly limited in comparison to evolved and divided knowledge. For example, much (positivist) legislation falls short in contrast to pre-literate or incompletely defined common or evolved law.

In jurisprudence, "legal positivism" essentially refers to the rejection of natural law; thus its common meaning with philosophical positivism is somewhat attenuated and in recent generations generally emphasizes the authority of human political structures as opposed to a "scientific" view of law.

Logical positivism edit

 
Moritz Schlick, the founding father of logical positivism and the Vienna Circle

Logical positivism (later and more accurately called logical empiricism) is a school of philosophy that combines empiricism, the idea that observational evidence is indispensable for knowledge of the world, with a version of rationalism, the idea that our knowledge includes a component that is not derived from observation.

Logical positivism grew from the discussions of a group called the "First Vienna Circle", which gathered at the Café Central before World War I. After the war Hans Hahn, a member of that early group, helped bring Moritz Schlick to Vienna. Schlick's Vienna Circle, along with Hans Reichenbach's Berlin Circle, propagated the new doctrines more widely in the 1920s and early 1930s.

It was Otto Neurath's advocacy that made the movement self-conscious and more widely known. A 1929 pamphlet written by Neurath, Hahn, and Rudolf Carnap summarized the doctrines of the Vienna Circle at that time. These included the opposition to all metaphysics, especially ontology and synthetic a priori propositions; the rejection of metaphysics not as wrong but as meaningless (i.e., not empirically verifiable); a criterion of meaning based on Ludwig Wittgenstein's early work (which he himself later set out to refute); the idea that all knowledge should be codifiable in a single standard language of science; and above all the project of "rational reconstruction," in which ordinary-language concepts were gradually to be replaced by more precise equivalents in that standard language. However, the project is widely considered to have failed.[41][42]

After moving to the United States, Carnap proposed a replacement for the earlier doctrines in his Logical Syntax of Language. This change of direction, and the somewhat differing beliefs of Reichenbach and others, led to a consensus that the English name for the shared doctrinal platform, in its American exile from the late 1930s, should be "logical empiricism."[citation needed] While the logical positivist movement is now considered dead, it has continued to influence philosophical development.[43]

Criticism edit

Historically, positivism has been criticized for its reductionism, i.e., for contending that all "processes are reducible to physiological, physical or chemical events," "social processes are reducible to relationships between and actions of individuals," and that "biological organisms are reducible to physical systems."[44]

The consideration that laws in physics may not be absolute but relative, and, if so, this might be even more true of social sciences, was stated, in different terms, by G. B. Vico in 1725.[37][45] Vico, in contrast to the positivist movement, asserted the superiority of the science of the human mind (the humanities, in other words), on the grounds that natural sciences tell us nothing about the inward aspects of things.[46]

Wilhelm Dilthey fought strenuously against the assumption that only explanations derived from science are valid.[9] He reprised Vico's argument that scientific explanations do not reach the inner nature of phenomena[9] and it is humanistic knowledge that gives us insight into thoughts, feelings and desires.[9] Dilthey was in part influenced by the historism of Leopold von Ranke (1795–1886).[9]

The contestation over positivism is reflected both in older debates (see the Positivism dispute) and current ones over the proper role of science in the public sphere. Public sociology—especially as described by Michael Burawoy—argues that sociologists should use empirical evidence to display the problems of society so they might be changed.[47]

Antipositivism edit

At the turn of the 20th century, the first wave of German sociologists formally introduced methodological antipositivism, proposing that research should concentrate on human cultural norms, values, symbols, and social processes viewed from a subjective perspective. Max Weber, one such thinker, argued that while sociology may be loosely described as a 'science' because it is able to identify causal relationships (especially among ideal types), sociologists should seek relationships that are not as "ahistorical, invariant, or generalizable" as those pursued by natural scientists.[48][49] Weber regarded sociology as the study of social action, using critical analysis and verstehen techniques. The sociologists Georg Simmel, Ferdinand Tönnies, George Herbert Mead, and Charles Cooley were also influential in the development of sociological antipositivism, whilst neo-Kantian philosophy, hermeneutics, and phenomenology facilitated the movement in general.

Critical rationalism and postpositivism edit

In the mid-twentieth century, several important philosophers and philosophers of science began to critique the foundations of logical positivism. In his 1934 work The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Karl Popper argued against verificationism. A statement such as "all swans are white" cannot actually be empirically verified, because it is impossible to know empirically whether all swans have been observed. Instead, Popper argued that at best an observation can falsify a statement (for example, observing a black swan would prove that not all swans are white).[50] Popper also held that scientific theories talk about how the world really is (not about phenomena or observations experienced by scientists), and critiqued the Vienna Circle in his Conjectures and Refutations.[51][52] W. V. O. Quine and Pierre Duhem went even further. The Duhem–Quine thesis states that it is impossible to experimentally test a scientific hypothesis in isolation, because an empirical test of the hypothesis requires one or more background assumptions (also called auxiliary assumptions or auxiliary hypotheses); thus, unambiguous scientific falsifications are also impossible.[53] Thomas Kuhn, in his 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, put forward his theory of paradigm shifts. He argued that it is not simply individual theories but whole worldviews that must occasionally shift in response to evidence.[54][50]

Together, these ideas led to the development of critical rationalism and postpositivism.[55] Postpositivism is not a rejection of the scientific method, but rather a reformation of positivism to meet these critiques. It reintroduces the basic assumptions of positivism: the possibility and desirability of objective truth, and the use of experimental methodology. Postpositivism of this type is described in social science guides to research methods.[56] Postpositivists argue that theories, hypotheses, background knowledge and values of the researcher can influence what is observed.[57] Postpositivists pursue objectivity by recognizing the possible effects of biases.[57][50][58] While positivists emphasize quantitative methods, postpositivists consider both quantitative and qualitative methods to be valid approaches.[58]

In the early 1960s, the positivism dispute arose between the critical theorists (see below) and the critical rationalists over the correct solution to the value judgment dispute (Werturteilsstreit). While both sides accepted that sociology cannot avoid a value judgement that inevitably influences subsequent conclusions, the critical theorists accused the critical rationalists of being positivists; specifically, of asserting that empirical questions can be severed from their metaphysical heritage and refusing to ask questions that cannot be answered with scientific methods. This contributed to what Karl Popper termed the "Popper Legend", a misconception among critics and admirers of Popper that he was, or identified himself as, a positivist.[59]

Critical theory edit

Although Karl Marx's theory of historical materialism drew upon positivism, the Marxist tradition would also go on to influence the development of antipositivist critical theory.[60] Critical theorist Jürgen Habermas critiqued pure instrumental rationality (in its relation to the cultural "rationalisation" of the modern West) as a form of scientism, or science "as ideology".[61] He argued that positivism may be espoused by "technocrats" who believe in the inevitability of social progress through science and technology.[62][63] New movements, such as critical realism, have emerged in order to reconcile postpositivist aims with various so-called 'postmodern' perspectives on the social acquisition of knowledge.

Max Horkheimer criticized the classic formulation of positivism on two grounds. First, he claimed that it falsely represented human social action.[64] The first criticism argued that positivism systematically failed to appreciate the extent to which the so-called social facts it yielded did not exist 'out there', in the objective world, but were themselves a product of socially and historically mediated human consciousness.[64] Positivism ignored the role of the 'observer' in the constitution of social reality and thereby failed to consider the historical and social conditions affecting the representation of social ideas.[64] Positivism falsely represented the object of study by reifying social reality as existing objectively and independently of the labour that actually produced those conditions.[64] Secondly, he argued, representation of social reality produced by positivism was inherently and artificially conservative, helping to support the status quo, rather than challenging it.[64] This character may also explain the popularity of positivism in certain political circles. Horkheimer argued, in contrast, that critical theory possessed a reflexive element lacking in the positivistic traditional theory.[64]

Some scholars today hold the beliefs critiqued in Horkheimer's work, but since the time of his writing critiques of positivism, especially from philosophy of science, have led to the development of postpositivism. This philosophy greatly relaxes the epistemological commitments of logical positivism and no longer claims a separation between the knower and the known. Rather than dismissing the scientific project outright, postpositivists seek to transform and amend it, though the exact extent of their affinity for science varies vastly. For example, some postpositivists accept the critique that observation is always value-laden, but argue that the best values to adopt for sociological observation are those of science: skepticism, rigor, and modesty. Just as some critical theorists see their position as a moral commitment to egalitarian values, these postpositivists see their methods as driven by a moral commitment to these scientific values. Such scholars may see themselves as either positivists or antipositivists.[65]

Other criticisms edit

During the later twentieth century, positivism began to fall out of favor with scientists as well. Later in his career, German theoretical physicist Werner Heisenberg, Nobel laureate for his pioneering work in quantum mechanics, distanced himself from positivism:

The positivists have a simple solution: the world must be divided into that which we can say clearly and the rest, which we had better pass over in silence. But can any one conceive of a more pointless philosophy, seeing that what we can say clearly amounts to next to nothing? If we omitted all that is unclear we would probably be left with completely uninteresting and trivial tautologies.[66]

In the early 1970s, urbanists of the quantitative school like David Harvey started to question the positivist approach itself, saying that the arsenal of scientific theories and methods developed so far in their camp were "incapable of saying anything of depth and profundity" on the real problems of contemporary cities.[67]

According the Catholic Encyclopedia, the Positivism has also come under fire on religious and philosophical grounds, whose proponents state that truth begins in sense experience, but does not end there. Positivism fails to prove that there are not abstract ideas, laws, and principles, beyond particular observable facts and relationships and necessary principles, or that we cannot know them. Nor does it prove that material and corporeal things constitute the whole order of existing beings, and that our knowledge is limited to them. According to positivism, our abstract concepts or general ideas are mere collective representations of the experimental order—for example; the idea of "man" is a kind of blended image of all the men observed in our experience.[68] This runs contrary to a Platonic or Christian ideal, where an idea can be abstracted from any concrete determination, and may be applied identically to an indefinite number of objects of the same class[citation needed] From the idea's perspective, Platonism is more precise. Defining an idea as a sum of collective images is imprecise and more or less confused, and becomes more so as the collection represented increases. An idea defined explicitly always remains clear.

Other new movements, such as critical realism, have emerged in opposition to positivism. Critical realism seeks to reconcile the overarching aims of social science with postmodern critiques. Experientialism, which arose with second generation cognitive science, asserts that knowledge begins and ends with experience itself.[69][70] In other words, it rejects the positivist assertion that a portion of human knowledge is a priori.

Positivism today edit

Echoes of the "positivist" and "antipositivist" debate persist today, though this conflict is hard to define. Authors writing in different epistemological perspectives do not phrase their disagreements in the same terms and rarely actually speak directly to each other.[71] To complicate the issues further, few practising scholars explicitly state their epistemological commitments, and their epistemological position thus has to be guessed from other sources such as choice of methodology or theory. However, no perfect correspondence between these categories exists, and many scholars critiqued as "positivists" are actually postpositivists.[72] One scholar has described this debate in terms of the social construction of the "other", with each side defining the other by what it is not rather than what it is, and then proceeding to attribute far greater homogeneity to their opponents than actually exists.[71] Thus, it is better to understand this not as a debate but as two different arguments: the "antipositivist" articulation of a social meta-theory which includes a philosophical critique of scientism, and "positivist" development of a scientific research methodology for sociology with accompanying critiques of the reliability and validity of work that they see as violating such standards. Strategic positivism aims to bridge these two arguments.

Social sciences edit

While most social scientists today are not explicit about their epistemological commitments, articles in top American sociology and political science journals generally follow a positivist logic of argument.[73][74] It can be thus argued that "natural science and social science [research articles] can therefore be regarded with a good deal of confidence as members of the same genre".[73]

In contemporary social science, strong accounts of positivism have long since fallen out of favour. Practitioners of positivism today acknowledge in far greater detail observer bias and structural limitations. Modern positivists generally eschew metaphysical concerns in favour of methodological debates concerning clarity, replicability, reliability and validity.[75] This positivism is generally equated with "quantitative research" and thus carries no explicit theoretical or philosophical commitments. The institutionalization of this kind of sociology is often credited to Paul Lazarsfeld,[25] who pioneered large-scale survey studies and developed statistical techniques for analyzing them. This approach lends itself to what Robert K. Merton called middle-range theory: abstract statements that generalize from segregated hypotheses and empirical regularities rather than starting with an abstract idea of a social whole.[76]

In the original Comtean usage, the term "positivism" roughly meant the use of scientific methods to uncover the laws according to which both physical and human events occur, while "sociology" was the overarching science that would synthesize all such knowledge for the betterment of society. "Positivism is a way of understanding based on science"; people don't rely on the faith in God but instead on the science behind humanity. "Antipositivism" formally dates back to the start of the twentieth century, and is based on the belief that natural and human sciences are ontologically and epistemologically distinct. Neither of these terms is used any longer in this sense.[25] There are no fewer than twelve distinct epistemologies that are referred to as positivism.[77] Many of these approaches do not self-identify as "positivist", some because they themselves arose in opposition to older forms of positivism, and some because the label has over time become a term of abuse[25] by being mistakenly linked with a theoretical empiricism. The extent of antipositivist criticism has also become broad, with many philosophies broadly rejecting the scientifically based social epistemology and other ones only seeking to amend it to reflect 20th century developments in the philosophy of science. However, positivism (understood as the use of scientific methods for studying society) remains the dominant approach to both the research and the theory construction in contemporary sociology, especially in the United States.[25]

The majority of articles published in leading American sociology and political science journals today are positivist (at least to the extent of being quantitative rather than qualitative).[73][74] This popularity may be because research utilizing positivist quantitative methodologies holds a greater prestige[clarification needed] in the social sciences than qualitative work; quantitative work is easier to justify, as data can be manipulated to answer any question.[78][need quotation to verify] Such research is generally perceived as being more scientific and more trustworthy, and thus has a greater impact on policy and public opinion (though such judgments are frequently contested by scholars doing non-positivist work).[78][need quotation to verify]

Natural sciences edit

The key features of positivism as of the 1950s, as defined in the "received view",[79] are:

  1. A focus on science as a product, a linguistic or numerical set of statements;
  2. A concern with axiomatization, that is, with demonstrating the logical structure and coherence of these statements;
  3. An insistence on at least some of these statements being testable; that is, amenable to being verified, confirmed, or shown to be false by the empirical observation of reality. Statements that would, by their nature, be regarded as untestable included the teleological; thus positivism rejects much of classical metaphysics.
  4. The belief that science is markedly cumulative;
  5. The belief that science is predominantly transcultural;
  6. The belief that science rests on specific results that are dissociated from the personality and social position of the investigator;
  7. The belief that science contains theories or research traditions that are largely commensurable;
  8. The belief that science sometimes incorporates new ideas that are discontinuous from old ones;
  9. The belief that science involves the idea of the unity of science, that there is, underlying the various scientific disciplines, basically one science about one real world.
  10. The belief that science is nature and nature is science; and out of this duality, all theories and postulates are created, interpreted, evolve, and are applied.
 
Stephen Hawking

Stephen Hawking was a recent high-profile advocate of positivism in the physical sciences. In The Universe in a Nutshell (p. 31) he wrote:

Any sound scientific theory, whether of time or of any other concept, should in my opinion be based on the most workable philosophy of science: the positivist approach put forward by Karl Popper and others. According to this way of thinking, a scientific theory is a mathematical model that describes and codifies the observations we make. A good theory will describe a large range of phenomena on the basis of a few simple postulates and will make definite predictions that can be tested. ... If one takes the positivist position, as I do, one cannot say what time actually is. All one can do is describe what has been found to be a very good mathematical model for time and say what predictions it makes.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ John J. Macionis, Linda M. Gerber, Sociology, Seventh Canadian Edition, Pearson Canada
  2. ^ Larrain, Jorge (1979). The Concept of Ideology. London: Hutchinson. p. 197. one of the features of positivism is precisely its postulate that scientific knowledge is the paradigm of valid knowledge, a postulate that indeed is never proved nor intended to be proved.
  3. ^ Cohen, Louis; Maldonado, Antonio (2007). "Research Methods In Education". British Journal of Educational Studies. 55 (4): 9. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8527.2007.00388_4.x. S2CID 143761151..
  4. ^ "Auguste Comte". Sociology Guide. from the original on 7 September 2008. Retrieved 2 October 2008.
  5. ^ Macionis, John J. (2012). Sociology 14th Edition. Boston: Pearson. p. 11. ISBN 978-0-205-11671-3.
  6. ^ Le petit Robert s. v. 'positivisme'; OED s. v. positive
  7. ^ Egan, Kieran (1997). The Educated Mind. University of Chicago Press. pp. 115–116. ISBN 978-0-226-19036-5. Positivism is marked by the final recognition that science provides the only valid form of knowledge and that facts are the only possible objects of knowledge; philosophy is thus recognized as essentially no different from science [...] Ethics, politics, social interactions, and all other forms of human life about which knowledge was possible would eventually be drawn into the orbit of science [...] The positivists' program for mapping the inexorable and immutable laws of matter and society seemed to allow no greater role for the contribution of poets than had Plato. [...] What Plato represented as the quarrel between philosophy and poetry is resuscitated in the "two cultures" quarrel of more recent times between the humanities and the sciences.
  8. ^ Saunders, T. J. Introduction to Ion. London: Penguin Books, 1987, p. 46
  9. ^ a b c d e Wallace and Gach (2008) p. 27 17 June 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  10. ^ Hobsbawm, Eric (1975). The Age of Capital: 1848–1875. New York City: Charles Scribner's Sons.
  11. ^ a b Auguste Comte 11 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  12. ^ "OpenStax". openstax.org. Retrieved 9 April 2021.
  13. ^ a b Durkheim, Emile. 1895. The Rules of the Sociological Method. Cited in Wacquant (1992).
  14. ^ Giddens, Positivism and Sociology, 1
  15. ^ Mill, Auguste Comte and Positivism 3
  16. ^ Richard von Mises, Positivism: A Study In Human Understanding, 5 (Paperback, Dover Books, 1968 ISBN 0-486-21867-8)
  17. ^ Mill, Auguste Comte and Positivism, 4
  18. ^ a b Giddens, Positivism and Sociology, 9
  19. ^ Mary Pickering, Auguste Comte: An Intellectual Biography, Volume I, 622
  20. ^ Mary Pickering, Auguste Comte: An Intellectual Biography, Volume I, 566
  21. ^ Pickering, Mary (1993) Auguste Comte: an intellectual biography Cambridge University Press, p. 192
  22. ^ "Comte's secular religion is no vague effusion of humanistic piety, but a complete system of belief and ritual, with liturgy and sacraments, priesthood and pontiff, all organized around the public veneration of Humanity, the Nouveau Grand-Être Suprême (New Supreme Great Being), later to be supplemented in a positivist trinity by the Grand Fétish (the Earth) and the Grand Milieu (Destiny)" According to Davies (pp. 28–29), Comte's austere and "slightly dispiriting" philosophy of humanity viewed as alone in an indifferent universe (which can only be explained by "positive" science) and with nowhere to turn but to each other, was even more influential in Victorian England than the theories of Charles Darwin or Karl Marx.
  23. ^ Pickering, Mary (2009). Auguste Comte: Volume 3: An Intellectual Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 561.
  24. ^ Sémérie, Eugène. "Founding of a Positivist Club". Marxists Internet Archive. from the original on 15 July 2018. Retrieved 6 March 2017.
  25. ^ a b c d e f Wacquant, Loic. 1992. "Positivism." In Bottomore, Tom and William Outhwaite, ed., The Blackwell Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Social Thought
  26. ^ Gianfranco Poggi (2000). Durkheim. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  27. ^ Craig J. Calhoun (2002). Classical Sociological Theory. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 104. ISBN 978-0-631-21348-2. from the original on 23 June 2016. Retrieved 7 November 2015.
  28. ^ Durkheim, Émile [1895] "The Rules of Sociological Method" 8th edition, trans. Sarah A. Solovay and John M. Mueller, ed. George E. G. Catlin (1938, 1964 edition), p. 45
  29. ^ Ashley D, Orenstein DM (2005). Sociological theory: Classical statements (6th ed.). Boston, MA: Pearson Education. pp. 94–98, 100–104.
  30. ^ a b Munz, Peter (1993). Philosophical Darwinism: On the Origin of Knowledge by Means of Natural Selection. London: Routledge. p. 94. ISBN 9781134884841.
  31. ^ a b Flynn, Thomas R. (1997). Sartre, Foucault, and Historical Reason. Vol. 1. Chicago: Chicago University Press. p. 4. ISBN 9780226254692.
  32. ^ Martin, Luther H. (2014). Deep History, Secular Theory: Historical and Scientific Studies of Religion. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. p. 343. ISBN 9781614515005.
  33. ^ Lerner, Robert E. (2017). Ernst Kantorowicz: A Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press. p. 129. ISBN 9780691183022.
  34. ^ Shank, J. B. (2008). The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment. Chicago: Chicago University Press. p. 24. ISBN 9780226749471.
  35. ^ Collingwood, R. G. (1946). The Idea of History. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 131–33.
  36. ^ Raymond Boudon and François Bourricaud, A Critical Dictionary of Sociology 3 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine, Routledge, 1989: "Historicism", p. 198.
  37. ^ a b Wallace, Edwin R. and Gach, John (2008) History of Psychiatry and Medical Psychology: With an Epilogue on Psychiatry and the Mind-Body Relation. p. 14 16 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  38. ^ a b Wallace and Gach (2008) p. 28 8 November 2015 at the Wayback Machine
  39. ^ Koch, Sigmund (1992) Psychology's Bridgman vs. Bridgman's Bridgman: An Essay in Reconstruction., in Theory and Psychology vol. 2 no. 3 (1992) p. 275
  40. ^ "Lawrence A. Boland, Economic Positivism positivists.org 2012". from the original on 17 February 2015. Retrieved 18 February 2015.
  41. ^ Bunge, M. A. (1996). Finding Philosophy in Social Science. Yale University Press. p. 317. ISBN 9780300066067. LCCN lc96004399. from the original on 4 June 2016. Retrieved 7 November 2015. To conclude, logical positivism was progressive compared with the classical positivism of Ptolemy, Hume, d'Alembert, Comte, Mill, and Mach. It was even more so by comparison with its contemporary rivals—neo-Thomisism, neo-Kantianism, intuitionism, dialectical materialism, phenomenology, and existentialism. However, neo-positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science, whether natural or social. It failed because it remained anchored to sense-data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics, overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis, and denounced realism and materialism as metaphysical nonsense. Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers, notably Popper (1959 [1935], 1963), logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists. Regrettably, the anti-positivism fashionable in the metatheory of social science is often nothing but an excuse for sloppiness and wild speculation.
  42. ^ . 7 August 2000. Archived from the original on 7 January 2014. Retrieved 30 June 2012. The upshot is that the positivists seem caught between insisting on the V.C. [Verifiability Criterion]—but for no defensible reason—or admitting that the V.C. requires a background language, etc., which opens the door to relativism, etc.
  43. ^ Hanfling, Oswald (2003). "Logical Positivism". Routledge History of Philosophy. Vol. IX. Routledge. pp. 193–194.
  44. ^ Alan Bullock and Stephen Trombley, [Eds] The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought, London: Harper-Collins, 1999, pp. 669–737
  45. ^ Giambattista Vico, Principi di scienza nuova, Opere, ed. Fausto Nicolini (Milan: R. Ricciardi, 1953), pp. 365–905.
  46. ^ Morera, Esteve (1990) p. 13 Gramsci's Historicism: A Realist Interpretation 16 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  47. ^ Burawoy, Michael: "For Public Sociology" 21 April 2015 at the Wayback Machine (American Sociological Review, February 2005
  48. ^ Ashley D, Orenstein DM (2005). Sociological theory: Classical statements (6th ed.). Boston, MA: Pearson Education. pp. 239–240.
  49. ^ Ashley D, Orenstein DM (2005). Sociological theory: Classical statements (6th ed.). Boston, MA: Pearson Education. p. 241.
  50. ^ a b c Miller, Katherine (2007). Communication theories : perspectives, processes, and contexts (2nd ed.). Beijing: Peking University Press. pp. 35–45. ISBN 9787301124314.
  51. ^ Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, p. 256 Routledge, London, 1963
  52. ^ Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 1934, 1959 (1st English ed.)
  53. ^ Harding 1976, p. X: "The physicist can never subject an isolated hypothesis to experimental test, but only a whole group of hypotheses" (Duhem)... "Duhem denies that unambiguous falsification procedures do exist in science."
  54. ^ Thomas, David 1979 Naturalism and social sciences, ch. Paradigms and social science, p.161
  55. ^ Bergman, Mats (2016). "Positivism". The International Encyclopedia of Communication Theory and Philosophy. p. 1–5. doi:10.1002/9781118766804.wbiect248. ISBN 9781118766804.
  56. ^ Trochim, William. "Social Research Methods Knowledge Base". socialresearchmethods.net.
  57. ^ a b Robson, Colin (2002). Real World Research. A Resource for Social Scientists and Practitioner-Researchers (Second ed.). Malden: Blackwell. p. 624. ISBN 978-0-631-21305-5.
  58. ^ a b Taylor, Thomas R.; Lindlof, Bryan C. (2011). Qualitative communication research methods (3rd ed.). Thousand Oaks, Calif.: SAGE. p. 5–13. ISBN 978-1412974738.
  59. ^ Friedrich Stadler, The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism, Springer, 2015, p. 250.
  60. ^ "Main Currents of Marxism" by Leszek Kolakowski pp. 327, 331
  61. ^ Jürgen Habermas, Technik und Wissenschaft als Ideologie, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1968, chap. 1.
  62. ^ Schunk, Learning Theories: An Educational Perspective, 5th, 315
  63. ^ Outhwaite, William, 1988 Habermas: Key Contemporary Thinkers, Polity Press (Second Edition 2009), ISBN 978-0-7456-4328-1 p. 68
  64. ^ a b c d e f Fagan, Andrew. "Theodor Adorno (1903-1969)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 24 February 2012. Retrieved 24 February 2012.
  65. ^ Tittle, Charles. 2004. "The Arrogance of Public Sociology". Social Forces, June 2004, 82(4)
  66. ^ Heisenberg, Werner (1971). "Positivism, Metaphysics and Religion". Physics and Beyond: Encounters and Conversations. World Perspectives vol. 42. Translated by Pomerans, Arnold J. New York: Harper & Row. p. 213. ISBN 9780049250086. LCCN 78095963. OCLC 15379872.
  67. ^ Portugali, Juval and Han Meyer, Egbert Stolk (2012) Complexity Theories of Cities Have Come of Age p. 51 10 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  68. ^ "Positivism".
  69. ^ Varela, F. J., Thompson, E. T., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. The MIT Press.
  70. ^ Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought. Basic books.
  71. ^ a b Hanson, Barbara. 2008. "Wither Qualitative/Quantitative?: Grounds for Methodological Convergence." Quality and Quantity 42:97–111.
  72. ^ Bryman, Alan. 1984. "The Debate about Quantitative and Qualitative Research: A Question of Method or Epistemology?." The British Journal of Sociology 35:75–92.
  73. ^ a b c Holmes, Richard. 1997. "Genre analysis, and the social sciences: An investigation of the structure of research article discussion sections in three disciplines". English For Specific Purposes, vol. 16, num. 4:321–337.
  74. ^ a b Brett, Paul. 1994. "A genre analysis of the results section of sociology articles". English For Specific Purposes. Vol 13, Num 1:47–59.
  75. ^ Gartell, David, and Gartell, John. 1996. "Positivism in sociological practice: 1967–1990". Canadian Review of Sociology, Vol. 33 No. 2.
  76. ^ Boudon, Raymond. 1991. "Review: What Middle-Range Theories are". Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 20 Num. 4 pp. 519–522.
  77. ^ Halfpenny, Peter. Positivism and Sociology: Explaining Social Life. London:Allen and Unwin, 1982.
  78. ^ a b Grant, Linda; Ward, Kathryn B.; Xue Lan Rong (1987). "Is There An Association between Gender and Methods in Sociological Research?". American Sociological Review. 52 (6): 856–862. doi:10.2307/2095839. JSTOR 2095839.
  79. ^ Hacking, I. (ed.) 1981. Scientific revolutions. Oxford Univ. Press, New York.

References edit

  • Amory, Frederic. "Euclides da Cunha and Brazilian Positivism". Luso-Brazilian Review. 36 (1 (Summer 1999)): 87–94.
  • Armenteros, Carolina. 2017. "The Counterrevolutionary Comte: Theorist of the Two Powers and Enthusiastic Medievalist." In The Anthem Companion to Auguste Comte, edited by Andrew Wernick, 91–116. London: Anthem.
  • Annan, Noel. 1959. The Curious Strength of Positivism in English Political Thought. London: Oxford University Press.
  • Ardao, Arturo. 1963. "Assimilation and Transformation of Positivism in Latin America." Journal of the History of Ideas 24 (4):515–22.
  • Bevir, Mark (1993). "Ernest Belfort Bax: Marxist, Idealist, Positivist". Journal of the History of Ideas. 54 (1): 119–35. doi:10.2307/2709863. JSTOR 2709863.
  • Bevir, Mark. 2002. "Sidney Webb: Utilitarianism, Positivism, and Social Democracy." The Journal of Modern History 74 (2):217–252.
  • Bevir, Mark. 2011. The Making of British Socialism. Princeton. PA: Princeton University Press.
  • Bourdeau, Michel. 2006. Les trois états: Science, théologie et métaphysique chez Auguste Comte. Paris: Éditions du Cerf.
  • Bourdeau, Michel, Mary Pickering, and Warren Schmaus, eds. 2018. Love, Order and Progress. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
  • Bryant, Christopher G. A. 1985. Positivism in Social Theory and Research. New York: St. Martin's Press.
  • Claeys, Gregory. 2010. Imperial Sceptics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Claeys, Gregory. 2018. "Professor Beesly, Positivism and the International: the Patriotism Issue." In "Arise Ye Wretched of the Earth": The First International in a Global Perspective, edited by Fabrice Bensimon, Quinton Deluermoz and Jeanne Moisand. Leiden: Brill.
  • De Boni, Carlo. 2013. Storia di un'utopia. La religione dell'Umanità di Comte e la sua circolazione nel mondo. Milano: Mimesis.
  • Dixon, Thomas. 2008. The Invention of Altruism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Feichtinger, Johannes, Franz L. Fillafer, and Jan Surman, eds. 2018. The Worlds of Positivism. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Forbes, Geraldine Handcock. 2003. "The English Positivists and India." In Essays on Indian Renaissance, edited by Raj Kumar, 151–63. Discovery: New Delhi.
  • Gane, Mike. 2006. Auguste Comte. London: Routledge.
  • Giddens, Anthony. Positivism and Sociology. Heinemann. London. 1974.
  • Gilson, Gregory D. and Irving W. Levinson, eds. Latin American Positivism: New Historical and Philosophic Essays (Lexington Books; 2012) 197 pages; Essays on positivism in the intellectual and political life of Brazil, Colombia, and Mexico.
  • Harp, Gillis J. 1995. Positivist Republic: Auguste Comte and the Reconstruction of American Liberalism, 1865-1920. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  • Harrison, Royden. 1965. Before the Socialists. London: Routledge.
  • Hoecker-Drysdale, Susan. 2001. "Harriet Martineau and the Positivism of Auguste Comte." In Harriet Martineau: Theoretical and Methodological Perspectives, edited by Michael R. Hill and Susan Hoecker-Drysdale, 169–90. London: Routledge.
  • Kremer-Marietti, Angèle. L'Anthropologie positiviste d'Auguste Comte, Librairie Honoré Champion, Paris, 1980.
  • Kremer-Marietti, Angèle. Le positivisme, Collection "Que sais-je?", Paris, PUF, 1982.
  • LeGouis, Catherine. Positivism and Imagination: Scientism and Its Limits in Emile Hennequin, Wilhelm Scherer and Dmitril Pisarev. Bucknell University Press. London: 1997.
  • Lenzer, Gertrud, ed. 2009. The Essential Writings of Auguste Comte and Positivism. London: Transaction.
  • "Positivism." Marxists Internet Archive. Web. 23 Feb. 2012.
  • McGee, John Edwin. 1931. A Crusade for Humanity. London: Watts.
  • Mill, John Stuart. Auguste Comte and Positivism.
  • Mises, Richard von. Positivism: A Study In Human Understanding. Harvard University Press. Cambridge, Massachusetts: 1951.
  • Petit, Annie. Le Système d'Auguste Comte. De la science à la religion par la philosophie. Vrin, Paris (2016).
  • Pickering, Mary. Auguste Comte: An Intellectual Biography. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge, England; 1993.
  • Quin, Malcolm. 1924. Memoirs of a Positivist. London: George Allen & Unwin.
  • Richard Rorty (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism.
  • Scharff, Robert C. 1995. Comte After Positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Schunk, Dale H. Learning Theories: An Educational Perspective, 5th. Pearson, Merrill Prentice Hall. 1991, 1996, 2000, 2004, 2008.
  • Simon, W. M. 1963. European Positivism in the Nineteenth Century. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Sutton, Michael. 1982. Nationalism, Positivism and Catholicism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Trindade, Helgio. 2003. "La république positiviste chex Comte." In Auguste Comte: Trajectoires positivistes 1798–1998, edited by Annie Petit, 363–400. Paris: L'Harmattan.
  • Turner, Mark. 2000. "Defining Discourses: The "Westminster Review", "Fortnightly Review", and Comte's Positivism." Victorian Periodicals Review 33 (3):273–282.
  • Wernick, Andrew. 2001. Auguste Comte and the Religion of Humanity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Whatmore, Richard. 2005. "Comte, Auguste (1798-1857)." In Encyclopaedia of Nineteenth-Century Thought, edited by Gregory Claeys, 123–8. London: Routledge.
  • Whetsell, Travis and Patricia M. Shields. "The Dynamics of Positivism in the Study of Public Administration: A Brief Intellectual History and Reappraisal", Administration & Society. doi:10.1177/0095399713490157.
  • Wils, Kaat. 2005. De omweg van de wetenschap: het positivisme en de Belgische en Nederlandse intellectuele cultuur, 1845–1914. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.
  • Wilson, Matthew. 2018. "British Comtism and Modernist Design." Modern Intellectual History x (xx):1–32.
  • Wilson, Matthew. 2018. Moralising Space: the Utopian Urbanism of the British Positivists, 1855–1920. London: Routledge.
  • Wilson, Matthew. 2020. "Rendering sociology: on the utopian positivism of Harriet Martineau and the ‘Mumbo Jumbo club." Journal of Interdisciplinary History of Ideas 8 (16):1–42.
  • Woll, Allen L. 1976. "Positivism and History in Nineteenth-Century Chile." Journal of the History of Ideas 37 (3):493–506.
  • Woodward, Ralph Lee, ed. 1971. Positivism in Latin America, 1850–1900. Lexington: Heath.
  • Wright, T. R. 1986. The Religion of Humanity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wright, T. R. 1981. "George Eliot and Positivism: A Reassessment." The Modern Language Review 76 (2):257–72.
  • Wunderlich, Roger. 1992. Low Living and High Thinking at Modern Times, New York. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
  • Zea, Leopoldo. 1974. Positivism in Mexico. Austin: University of Texas Press.

External links edit

  • The full text of the 1911 Encyclopædia Britannica article "Positivism" at Wikisource
  • Porto Alegre, Brazil
  • Posnan, Poland
  • Positivists Worldwide
  • Maison d'Auguste Comte, France

positivism, other, uses, disambiguation, philosophical, school, that, holds, that, genuine, knowledge, either, true, definition, positive, meaning, posteriori, facts, derived, reason, logic, from, sensory, experience, other, ways, knowing, such, intuition, int. For other uses see Positivism disambiguation Positivism is a philosophical school that holds that all genuine knowledge is either true by definition or positive meaning a posteriori facts derived by reason and logic from sensory experience 1 2 Other ways of knowing such as intuition introspection or religious faith are rejected or considered meaningless A portrait of Auguste Comte the founder of modern positivismAlthough the positivist approach has been a recurrent theme in the history of western thought modern positivism was first articulated in the early 19th century by Auguste Comte 3 4 His school of sociological positivism holds that society like the physical world operates according to general laws 5 After Comte positivist schools arose in logic psychology economics historiography and other fields of thought Generally positivists attempted to introduce scientific methods to their respective fields Since the turn of the 20th century positivism has declined under criticism from antipositivists and critical theorists among others for its alleged scientism reductionism overgeneralizations and methodological limitations Contents 1 Etymology 2 Background 3 Positivism in the social sciences 3 1 Comte s positivism 3 2 Early followers of Comte 3 3 Durkheim s positivism 3 4 Historical positivism 3 5 Other subfields 4 Logical positivism 5 Criticism 5 1 Antipositivism 5 2 Critical rationalism and postpositivism 5 3 Critical theory 5 4 Other criticisms 6 Positivism today 6 1 Social sciences 6 2 Natural sciences 7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 10 External linksEtymology editThe English noun positivism was re imported in the 19th century from the French word positivisme derived from positif in its philosophical sense of imposed on the mind by experience The corresponding adjective Latin positivus has been used in a similar sense to discuss law positive law compared to natural law since the time of Chaucer 6 Background editKieran Egan argues that positivism can be traced to the philosophy side of what Plato described as the quarrel between philosophy and poetry later reformulated by Wilhelm Dilthey as a quarrel between the natural sciences German Naturwissenschaften and the humanities Geisteswissenschaften 7 8 9 In the early nineteenth century massive advances in the natural sciences encouraged philosophers to apply scientific methods to other fields Thinkers such as Henri de Saint Simon Pierre Simon Laplace and Auguste Comte believed that the scientific method the circular dependence of theory and observation must replace metaphysics in the history of thought 10 Positivism in the social sciences editComte s positivism edit nbsp Comte first laid out his theory of positivism in The Course in Positive PhilosophyAuguste Comte 1798 1857 first described the epistemological perspective of positivism in The Course in Positive Philosophy a series of texts published between 1830 and 1842 These texts were followed in 1844 by A General View of Positivism published in French 1848 English in 1865 The first three volumes of the Course dealt chiefly with the physical sciences already in existence mathematics astronomy physics chemistry biology whereas the latter two emphasized the inevitable coming of social science Observing the circular dependence of theory and observation in science and classifying the sciences in this way Comte may be regarded as the first philosopher of science in the modern sense of the term 11 12 For him the physical sciences had necessarily to arrive first before humanity could adequately channel its efforts into the most challenging and complex Queen science of human society itself His View of Positivism therefore set out to define the empirical goals of sociological method The most important thing to determine was the natural order in which the sciences stand not how they can be made to stand but how they must stand irrespective of the wishes of any one This Comte accomplished by taking as the criterion of the position of each the degree of what he called positivity which is simply the degree to which the phenomena can be exactly determined This as may be readily seen is also a measure of their relative complexity since the exactness of a science is in inverse proportion to its complexity The degree of exactness or positivity is moreover that to which it can be subjected to mathematical demonstration and therefore mathematics which is not itself a concrete science is the general gauge by which the position of every science is to be determined Generalizing thus Comte found that there were five great groups of phenomena of equal classificatory value but of successively decreasing positivity To these he gave the names astronomy physics chemistry biology and sociology Lester F Ward The Outlines of Sociology 1898 13 Comte offered an account of social evolution proposing that society undergoes three phases in its quest for the truth according to a general law of three stages Comte intended to develop a secular scientific ideology in the wake of European secularisation Comte s stages were 1 the theological 2 the metaphysical and 3 the positive 14 The theological phase of man was based on whole hearted belief in all things with reference to God God Comte says had reigned supreme over human existence pre Enlightenment Humanity s place in society was governed by its association with the divine presences and with the church The theological phase deals with humankind s accepting the doctrines of the church or place of worship rather than relying on its rational powers to explore basic questions about existence It dealt with the restrictions put in place by the religious organization at the time and the total acceptance of any fact adduced for society to believe 15 Comte describes the metaphysical phase of humanity as the time since the Enlightenment a time steeped in logical rationalism to the time right after the French Revolution This second phase states that the universal rights of humanity are most important The central idea is that humanity is invested with certain rights that must be respected In this phase democracies and dictators rose and fell in attempts to maintain the innate rights of humanity 16 The final stage of the trilogy of Comte s universal law is the scientific or positive stage The central idea of this phase is that individual rights are more important than the rule of any one person Comte stated that the idea of humanity s ability to govern itself makes this stage inherently different from the rest There is no higher power governing the masses and the intrigue of any one person can achieve anything based on that individual s free will The third principle is most important in the positive stage 17 Comte calls these three phases the universal rule in relation to society and its development Neither the second nor the third phase can be reached without the completion and understanding of the preceding stage All stages must be completed in progress 18 Comte believed that the appreciation of the past and the ability to build on it towards the future was key in transitioning from the theological and metaphysical phases The idea of progress was central to Comte s new science sociology Sociology would lead to the historical consideration of every science because the history of one science including pure political history would make no sense unless it was attached to the study of the general progress of all of humanity 19 As Comte would say from science comes prediction from prediction comes action 20 It is a philosophy of human intellectual development that culminated in science The irony of this series of phases is that though Comte attempted to prove that human development has to go through these three stages it seems that the positivist stage is far from becoming a realization This is due to two truths The positivist phase requires having a complete understanding of the universe and world around us and requires that society should never know if it is in this positivist phase Anthony Giddens argues that since humanity constantly uses science to discover and research new things humanity never progresses beyond the second metaphysical phase 18 nbsp Positivist temple in Porto Alegre BrazilComte s fame today owes in part to Emile Littre who founded The Positivist Review in 1867 As an approach to the philosophy of history positivism was appropriated by historians such as Hippolyte Taine Many of Comte s writings were translated into English by the Whig writer Harriet Martineau regarded by some as the first female sociologist Debates continue to rage as to how much Comte appropriated from the work of his mentor Saint Simon 21 He was nevertheless influential Brazilian thinkers turned to Comte s ideas about training a scientific elite in order to flourish in the industrialization process Brazil s national motto Ordem e Progresso Order and Progress was taken from the positivism motto Love as principle order as the basis progress as the goal which was also influential in Poland citation needed In later life Comte developed a religion of humanity for positivist societies in order to fulfil the cohesive function once held by traditional worship In 1849 he proposed a calendar reform called the positivist calendar For close associate John Stuart Mill it was possible to distinguish between a good Comte the author of the Course in Positive Philosophy and a bad Comte the author of the secular religious system 11 The system was unsuccessful but met with the publication of Darwin s On the Origin of Species to influence the proliferation of various secular humanist organizations in the 19th century especially through the work of secularists such as George Holyoake and Richard Congreve Although Comte s English followers including George Eliot and Harriet Martineau for the most part rejected the full gloomy panoply of his system they liked the idea of a religion of humanity and his injunction to vivre pour autrui live for others from which comes the word altruism 22 The early sociology of Herbert Spencer came about broadly as a reaction to Comte writing after various developments in evolutionary biology Spencer attempted in vain to reformulate the discipline in what we might now describe as socially Darwinistic terms citation needed Early followers of Comte edit Within a few years other scientific and philosophical thinkers began creating their own definitions for positivism These included Emile Zola Emile Hennequin Wilhelm Scherer and Dimitri Pisarev Fabien Magnin was the first working class adherent to Comte s ideas and became the leader of a movement known as Proletarian Positivism Comte appointed Magnin as his successor as president of the Positive Society in the event of Comte s death Magnin filled this role from 1857 to 1880 when he resigned 23 Magnin was in touch with the English positivists Richard Congreve and Edward Spencer Beesly He established the Cercle des proletaires positivistes in 1863 which was affiliated to the First International Eugene Semerie was a psychiatrist who was also involved in the Positivist movement setting up a positivist club in Paris after the foundation of the French Third Republic in 1870 He wrote Positivism is not only a philosophical doctrine it is also a political party which claims to reconcile order the necessary basis for all social activity with Progress which is its goal 24 Durkheim s positivism edit nbsp Emile DurkheimThe modern academic discipline of sociology began with the work of Emile Durkheim 1858 1917 While Durkheim rejected much of the details of Comte s philosophy he retained and refined its method maintaining that the social sciences are a logical continuation of the natural ones into the realm of human activity and insisting that they may retain the same objectivity rationalism and approach to causality 25 Durkheim set up the first European department of sociology at the University of Bordeaux in 1895 publishing his Rules of the Sociological Method 1895 26 In this text he argued o ur main goal is to extend scientific rationalism to human conduct What has been called our positivism is but a consequence of this rationalism 13 Durkheim s seminal monograph Suicide 1897 a case study of suicide rates amongst Catholic and Protestant populations distinguished sociological analysis from psychology or philosophy 27 By carefully examining suicide statistics in different police districts he attempted to demonstrate that Catholic communities have a lower suicide rate than Protestants something he attributed to social as opposed to individual or psychological causes He developed the notion of objective sui generis social facts to delineate a unique empirical object for the science of sociology to study 25 Through such studies he posited sociology would be able to determine whether a given society is healthy or pathological and seek social reform to negate organic breakdown or social anomie Durkheim described sociology as the science of institutions their genesis and their functioning 28 David Ashley and David M Orenstein have alleged in a consumer textbook published by Pearson Education that accounts of Durkheim s positivism are possibly exaggerated and oversimplified Comte was the only major sociological thinker to postulate that the social realm may be subject to scientific analysis in exactly the same way as natural science whereas Durkheim saw a far greater need for a distinctly sociological scientific methodology His lifework was fundamental in the establishment of practical social research as we know it today techniques which continue beyond sociology and form the methodological basis of other social sciences such as political science as well of market research and other fields 29 Historical positivism edit In historiography historical or documentary positivism is the belief that historians should pursue the objective truth of the past by allowing historical sources to speak for themselves without additional interpretation 30 31 In the words of the French historian Fustel de Coulanges as a positivist It is not I who am speaking but history itself The heavy emphasis placed by historical positivists on documentary sources led to the development of methods of source criticism which seek to expunge bias and uncover original sources in their pristine state 30 The origin of the historical positivist school is particularly associated with the 19th century German historian Leopold von Ranke who argued that the historian should seek to describe historical truth wie es eigentlich gewesen ist as it actually was though subsequent historians of the concept such as Georg Iggers have argued that its development owed more to Ranke s followers than Ranke himself 32 Historical positivism was critiqued in the 20th century by historians and philosophers of history from various schools of thought including Ernst Kantorowicz in Weimar Germany who argued that positivism faces the danger of becoming Romantic when it maintains that it is possible to find the Blue Flower of truth without preconceptions and Raymond Aron and Michel Foucault in postwar France who both posited that interpretations are always ultimately multiple and there is no final objective truth to recover 33 31 34 In his posthumously published 1946 The Idea of History the English historian R G Collingwood criticized historical positivism for conflating scientific facts with historical facts which are always inferred and cannot be confirmed by repetition and argued that its focus on the collection of facts had given historians unprecedented mastery over small scale problems but unprecedented weakness in dealing with large scale problems 35 Historicist arguments against positivist approaches in historiography include that history differs from sciences like physics and ethology in subject matter and method 36 37 38 that much of what history studies is nonquantifiable and therefore to quantify is to lose in precision and that experimental methods and mathematical models do not generally apply to history so that it is not possible to formulate general quasi absolute laws in history 38 Other subfields edit In psychology the positivist movement was influential in the development of operationalism The 1927 philosophy of science book The Logic of Modern Physics in particular which was originally intended for physicists coined the term operational definition which went on to dominate psychological method for the whole century 39 In economics practicing researchers tend to emulate the methodological assumptions of classical positivism but only in a de facto fashion the majority of economists do not explicitly concern themselves with matters of epistemology 40 Economic thinker Friedrich Hayek see Law Legislation and Liberty rejected positivism in the social sciences as hopelessly limited in comparison to evolved and divided knowledge For example much positivist legislation falls short in contrast to pre literate or incompletely defined common or evolved law In jurisprudence legal positivism essentially refers to the rejection of natural law thus its common meaning with philosophical positivism is somewhat attenuated and in recent generations generally emphasizes the authority of human political structures as opposed to a scientific view of law Logical positivism editMain article Logical positivism nbsp Moritz Schlick the founding father of logical positivism and the Vienna CircleLogical positivism later and more accurately called logical empiricism is a school of philosophy that combines empiricism the idea that observational evidence is indispensable for knowledge of the world with a version of rationalism the idea that our knowledge includes a component that is not derived from observation Logical positivism grew from the discussions of a group called the First Vienna Circle which gathered at the Cafe Central before World War I After the war Hans Hahn a member of that early group helped bring Moritz Schlick to Vienna Schlick s Vienna Circle along with Hans Reichenbach s Berlin Circle propagated the new doctrines more widely in the 1920s and early 1930s It was Otto Neurath s advocacy that made the movement self conscious and more widely known A 1929 pamphlet written by Neurath Hahn and Rudolf Carnap summarized the doctrines of the Vienna Circle at that time These included the opposition to all metaphysics especially ontology and synthetic a priori propositions the rejection of metaphysics not as wrong but as meaningless i e not empirically verifiable a criterion of meaning based on Ludwig Wittgenstein s early work which he himself later set out to refute the idea that all knowledge should be codifiable in a single standard language of science and above all the project of rational reconstruction in which ordinary language concepts were gradually to be replaced by more precise equivalents in that standard language However the project is widely considered to have failed 41 42 After moving to the United States Carnap proposed a replacement for the earlier doctrines in his Logical Syntax of Language This change of direction and the somewhat differing beliefs of Reichenbach and others led to a consensus that the English name for the shared doctrinal platform in its American exile from the late 1930s should be logical empiricism citation needed While the logical positivist movement is now considered dead it has continued to influence philosophical development 43 Criticism editHistorically positivism has been criticized for its reductionism i e for contending that all processes are reducible to physiological physical or chemical events social processes are reducible to relationships between and actions of individuals and that biological organisms are reducible to physical systems 44 The consideration that laws in physics may not be absolute but relative and if so this might be even more true of social sciences was stated in different terms by G B Vico in 1725 37 45 Vico in contrast to the positivist movement asserted the superiority of the science of the human mind the humanities in other words on the grounds that natural sciences tell us nothing about the inward aspects of things 46 Wilhelm Dilthey fought strenuously against the assumption that only explanations derived from science are valid 9 He reprised Vico s argument that scientific explanations do not reach the inner nature of phenomena 9 and it is humanistic knowledge that gives us insight into thoughts feelings and desires 9 Dilthey was in part influenced by the historism of Leopold von Ranke 1795 1886 9 The contestation over positivism is reflected both in older debates see the Positivism dispute and current ones over the proper role of science in the public sphere Public sociology especially as described by Michael Burawoy argues that sociologists should use empirical evidence to display the problems of society so they might be changed 47 Antipositivism edit Main article Antipositivism At the turn of the 20th century the first wave of German sociologists formally introduced methodological antipositivism proposing that research should concentrate on human cultural norms values symbols and social processes viewed from a subjective perspective Max Weber one such thinker argued that while sociology may be loosely described as a science because it is able to identify causal relationships especially among ideal types sociologists should seek relationships that are not as ahistorical invariant or generalizable as those pursued by natural scientists 48 49 Weber regarded sociology as the study of social action using critical analysis and verstehen techniques The sociologists Georg Simmel Ferdinand Tonnies George Herbert Mead and Charles Cooley were also influential in the development of sociological antipositivism whilst neo Kantian philosophy hermeneutics and phenomenology facilitated the movement in general Critical rationalism and postpositivism edit Main articles Postpositivism and Critical rationalism In the mid twentieth century several important philosophers and philosophers of science began to critique the foundations of logical positivism In his 1934 work The Logic of Scientific Discovery Karl Popper argued against verificationism A statement such as all swans are white cannot actually be empirically verified because it is impossible to know empirically whether all swans have been observed Instead Popper argued that at best an observation can falsify a statement for example observing a black swan would prove that not all swans are white 50 Popper also held that scientific theories talk about how the world really is not about phenomena or observations experienced by scientists and critiqued the Vienna Circle in his Conjectures and Refutations 51 52 W V O Quine and Pierre Duhem went even further The Duhem Quine thesis states that it is impossible to experimentally test a scientific hypothesis in isolation because an empirical test of the hypothesis requires one or more background assumptions also called auxiliary assumptions or auxiliary hypotheses thus unambiguous scientific falsifications are also impossible 53 Thomas Kuhn in his 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions put forward his theory of paradigm shifts He argued that it is not simply individual theories but whole worldviews that must occasionally shift in response to evidence 54 50 Together these ideas led to the development of critical rationalism and postpositivism 55 Postpositivism is not a rejection of the scientific method but rather a reformation of positivism to meet these critiques It reintroduces the basic assumptions of positivism the possibility and desirability of objective truth and the use of experimental methodology Postpositivism of this type is described in social science guides to research methods 56 Postpositivists argue that theories hypotheses background knowledge and values of the researcher can influence what is observed 57 Postpositivists pursue objectivity by recognizing the possible effects of biases 57 50 58 While positivists emphasize quantitative methods postpositivists consider both quantitative and qualitative methods to be valid approaches 58 In the early 1960s the positivism dispute arose between the critical theorists see below and the critical rationalists over the correct solution to the value judgment dispute Werturteilsstreit While both sides accepted that sociology cannot avoid a value judgement that inevitably influences subsequent conclusions the critical theorists accused the critical rationalists of being positivists specifically of asserting that empirical questions can be severed from their metaphysical heritage and refusing to ask questions that cannot be answered with scientific methods This contributed to what Karl Popper termed the Popper Legend a misconception among critics and admirers of Popper that he was or identified himself as a positivist 59 Critical theory edit Main article Critical Theory Although Karl Marx s theory of historical materialism drew upon positivism the Marxist tradition would also go on to influence the development of antipositivist critical theory 60 Critical theorist Jurgen Habermas critiqued pure instrumental rationality in its relation to the cultural rationalisation of the modern West as a form of scientism or science as ideology 61 He argued that positivism may be espoused by technocrats who believe in the inevitability of social progress through science and technology 62 63 New movements such as critical realism have emerged in order to reconcile postpositivist aims with various so called postmodern perspectives on the social acquisition of knowledge Max Horkheimer criticized the classic formulation of positivism on two grounds First he claimed that it falsely represented human social action 64 The first criticism argued that positivism systematically failed to appreciate the extent to which the so called social facts it yielded did not exist out there in the objective world but were themselves a product of socially and historically mediated human consciousness 64 Positivism ignored the role of the observer in the constitution of social reality and thereby failed to consider the historical and social conditions affecting the representation of social ideas 64 Positivism falsely represented the object of study by reifying social reality as existing objectively and independently of the labour that actually produced those conditions 64 Secondly he argued representation of social reality produced by positivism was inherently and artificially conservative helping to support the status quo rather than challenging it 64 This character may also explain the popularity of positivism in certain political circles Horkheimer argued in contrast that critical theory possessed a reflexive element lacking in the positivistic traditional theory 64 Some scholars today hold the beliefs critiqued in Horkheimer s work but since the time of his writing critiques of positivism especially from philosophy of science have led to the development of postpositivism This philosophy greatly relaxes the epistemological commitments of logical positivism and no longer claims a separation between the knower and the known Rather than dismissing the scientific project outright postpositivists seek to transform and amend it though the exact extent of their affinity for science varies vastly For example some postpositivists accept the critique that observation is always value laden but argue that the best values to adopt for sociological observation are those of science skepticism rigor and modesty Just as some critical theorists see their position as a moral commitment to egalitarian values these postpositivists see their methods as driven by a moral commitment to these scientific values Such scholars may see themselves as either positivists or antipositivists 65 Other criticisms editDuring the later twentieth century positivism began to fall out of favor with scientists as well Later in his career German theoretical physicist Werner Heisenberg Nobel laureate for his pioneering work in quantum mechanics distanced himself from positivism The positivists have a simple solution the world must be divided into that which we can say clearly and the rest which we had better pass over in silence But can any one conceive of a more pointless philosophy seeing that what we can say clearly amounts to next to nothing If we omitted all that is unclear we would probably be left with completely uninteresting and trivial tautologies 66 In the early 1970s urbanists of the quantitative school like David Harvey started to question the positivist approach itself saying that the arsenal of scientific theories and methods developed so far in their camp were incapable of saying anything of depth and profundity on the real problems of contemporary cities 67 According the Catholic Encyclopedia the Positivism has also come under fire on religious and philosophical grounds whose proponents state that truth begins in sense experience but does not end there Positivism fails to prove that there are not abstract ideas laws and principles beyond particular observable facts and relationships and necessary principles or that we cannot know them Nor does it prove that material and corporeal things constitute the whole order of existing beings and that our knowledge is limited to them According to positivism our abstract concepts or general ideas are mere collective representations of the experimental order for example the idea of man is a kind of blended image of all the men observed in our experience 68 This runs contrary to a Platonic or Christian ideal where an idea can be abstracted from any concrete determination and may be applied identically to an indefinite number of objects of the same class citation needed From the idea s perspective Platonism is more precise Defining an idea as a sum of collective images is imprecise and more or less confused and becomes more so as the collection represented increases An idea defined explicitly always remains clear Other new movements such as critical realism have emerged in opposition to positivism Critical realism seeks to reconcile the overarching aims of social science with postmodern critiques Experientialism which arose with second generation cognitive science asserts that knowledge begins and ends with experience itself 69 70 In other words it rejects the positivist assertion that a portion of human knowledge is a priori Positivism today editEchoes of the positivist and antipositivist debate persist today though this conflict is hard to define Authors writing in different epistemological perspectives do not phrase their disagreements in the same terms and rarely actually speak directly to each other 71 To complicate the issues further few practising scholars explicitly state their epistemological commitments and their epistemological position thus has to be guessed from other sources such as choice of methodology or theory However no perfect correspondence between these categories exists and many scholars critiqued as positivists are actually postpositivists 72 One scholar has described this debate in terms of the social construction of the other with each side defining the other by what it is not rather than what it is and then proceeding to attribute far greater homogeneity to their opponents than actually exists 71 Thus it is better to understand this not as a debate but as two different arguments the antipositivist articulation of a social meta theory which includes a philosophical critique of scientism and positivist development of a scientific research methodology for sociology with accompanying critiques of the reliability and validity of work that they see as violating such standards Strategic positivism aims to bridge these two arguments Social sciences edit While most social scientists today are not explicit about their epistemological commitments articles in top American sociology and political science journals generally follow a positivist logic of argument 73 74 It can be thus argued that natural science and social science research articles can therefore be regarded with a good deal of confidence as members of the same genre 73 In contemporary social science strong accounts of positivism have long since fallen out of favour Practitioners of positivism today acknowledge in far greater detail observer bias and structural limitations Modern positivists generally eschew metaphysical concerns in favour of methodological debates concerning clarity replicability reliability and validity 75 This positivism is generally equated with quantitative research and thus carries no explicit theoretical or philosophical commitments The institutionalization of this kind of sociology is often credited to Paul Lazarsfeld 25 who pioneered large scale survey studies and developed statistical techniques for analyzing them This approach lends itself to what Robert K Merton called middle range theory abstract statements that generalize from segregated hypotheses and empirical regularities rather than starting with an abstract idea of a social whole 76 In the original Comtean usage the term positivism roughly meant the use of scientific methods to uncover the laws according to which both physical and human events occur while sociology was the overarching science that would synthesize all such knowledge for the betterment of society Positivism is a way of understanding based on science people don t rely on the faith in God but instead on the science behind humanity Antipositivism formally dates back to the start of the twentieth century and is based on the belief that natural and human sciences are ontologically and epistemologically distinct Neither of these terms is used any longer in this sense 25 There are no fewer than twelve distinct epistemologies that are referred to as positivism 77 Many of these approaches do not self identify as positivist some because they themselves arose in opposition to older forms of positivism and some because the label has over time become a term of abuse 25 by being mistakenly linked with a theoretical empiricism The extent of antipositivist criticism has also become broad with many philosophies broadly rejecting the scientifically based social epistemology and other ones only seeking to amend it to reflect 20th century developments in the philosophy of science However positivism understood as the use of scientific methods for studying society remains the dominant approach to both the research and the theory construction in contemporary sociology especially in the United States 25 The majority of articles published in leading American sociology and political science journals today are positivist at least to the extent of being quantitative rather than qualitative 73 74 This popularity may be because research utilizing positivist quantitative methodologies holds a greater prestige clarification needed in the social sciences than qualitative work quantitative work is easier to justify as data can be manipulated to answer any question 78 need quotation to verify Such research is generally perceived as being more scientific and more trustworthy and thus has a greater impact on policy and public opinion though such judgments are frequently contested by scholars doing non positivist work 78 need quotation to verify Natural sciences edit See also Constructive empiricism The key features of positivism as of the 1950s as defined in the received view 79 are A focus on science as a product a linguistic or numerical set of statements A concern with axiomatization that is with demonstrating the logical structure and coherence of these statements An insistence on at least some of these statements being testable that is amenable to being verified confirmed or shown to be false by the empirical observation of reality Statements that would by their nature be regarded as untestable included the teleological thus positivism rejects much of classical metaphysics The belief that science is markedly cumulative The belief that science is predominantly transcultural The belief that science rests on specific results that are dissociated from the personality and social position of the investigator The belief that science contains theories or research traditions that are largely commensurable The belief that science sometimes incorporates new ideas that are discontinuous from old ones The belief that science involves the idea of the unity of science that there is underlying the various scientific disciplines basically one science about one real world The belief that science is nature and nature is science and out of this duality all theories and postulates are created interpreted evolve and are applied nbsp Stephen HawkingStephen Hawking was a recent high profile advocate of positivism in the physical sciences In The Universe in a Nutshell p 31 he wrote Any sound scientific theory whether of time or of any other concept should in my opinion be based on the most workable philosophy of science the positivist approach put forward by Karl Popper and others According to this way of thinking a scientific theory is a mathematical model that describes and codifies the observations we make A good theory will describe a large range of phenomena on the basis of a few simple postulates and will make definite predictions that can be tested If one takes the positivist position as I do one cannot say what time actually is All one can do is describe what has been found to be a very good mathematical model for time and say what predictions it makes See also editCliodynamics Cientifico Charvaka Determinism Godel s incompleteness theorems London Positivist Society Nature versus nurture Scientific politics Sociological naturalism The New Paul and Virginia Vladimir SolovyovNotes edit John J Macionis Linda M Gerber Sociology Seventh Canadian Edition Pearson Canada Larrain Jorge 1979 The Concept of Ideology London Hutchinson p 197 one of the features of positivism is precisely its postulate that scientific knowledge is the paradigm of valid knowledge a postulate that indeed is never proved nor intended to be proved Cohen Louis Maldonado Antonio 2007 Research Methods In Education British Journal of Educational Studies 55 4 9 doi 10 1111 j 1467 8527 2007 00388 4 x S2CID 143761151 Auguste Comte Sociology Guide Archived from the original on 7 September 2008 Retrieved 2 October 2008 Macionis John J 2012 Sociology 14th Edition Boston Pearson p 11 ISBN 978 0 205 11671 3 Le petit Robert s v positivisme OED s v positive Egan Kieran 1997 The Educated Mind University of Chicago Press pp 115 116 ISBN 978 0 226 19036 5 Positivism is marked by the final recognition that science provides the only valid form of knowledge and that facts are the only possible objects of knowledge philosophy is thus recognized as essentially no different from science Ethics politics social interactions and all other forms of human life about which knowledge was possible would eventually be drawn into the orbit of science The positivists program for mapping the inexorable and immutable laws of matter and society seemed to allow no greater role for the contribution of poets than had Plato What Plato represented as the quarrel between philosophy and poetry is resuscitated in the two cultures quarrel of more recent times between the humanities and the sciences Saunders T J Introduction to Ion London Penguin Books 1987 p 46 a b c d e Wallace and Gach 2008 p 27 Archived 17 June 2016 at the Wayback Machine Hobsbawm Eric 1975 The Age of Capital 1848 1875 New York City Charles Scribner s Sons a b Auguste Comte Archived 11 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy OpenStax openstax org Retrieved 9 April 2021 a b Durkheim Emile 1895 The Rules of the Sociological Method Cited in Wacquant 1992 Giddens Positivism and Sociology 1 Mill Auguste Comte and Positivism 3 Richard von Mises Positivism A Study In Human Understanding 5 Paperback Dover Books 1968 ISBN 0 486 21867 8 Mill Auguste Comte and Positivism 4 a b Giddens Positivism and Sociology 9 Mary Pickering Auguste Comte An Intellectual Biography Volume I 622 Mary Pickering Auguste Comte An Intellectual Biography Volume I 566 Pickering Mary 1993 Auguste Comte an intellectual biography Cambridge University Press p 192 Comte s secular religion is no vague effusion of humanistic piety but a complete system of belief and ritual with liturgy and sacraments priesthood and pontiff all organized around the public veneration of Humanity the Nouveau Grand Etre Supreme New Supreme Great Being later to be supplemented in a positivist trinity by the Grand Fetish the Earth and the Grand Milieu Destiny According to Davies pp 28 29 Comte s austere and slightly dispiriting philosophy of humanity viewed as alone in an indifferent universe which can only be explained by positive science and with nowhere to turn but to each other was even more influential in Victorian England than the theories of Charles Darwin or Karl Marx Pickering Mary 2009 Auguste Comte Volume 3 An Intellectual Biography Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 561 Semerie Eugene Founding of a Positivist Club Marxists Internet Archive Archived from the original on 15 July 2018 Retrieved 6 March 2017 a b c d e f Wacquant Loic 1992 Positivism In Bottomore Tom and William Outhwaite ed The Blackwell Dictionary of Twentieth Century Social Thought Gianfranco Poggi 2000 Durkheim Oxford Oxford University Press Craig J Calhoun 2002 Classical Sociological Theory Wiley Blackwell p 104 ISBN 978 0 631 21348 2 Archived from the original on 23 June 2016 Retrieved 7 November 2015 Durkheim Emile 1895 The Rules of Sociological Method 8th edition trans Sarah A Solovay and John M Mueller ed George E G Catlin 1938 1964 edition p 45 Ashley D Orenstein DM 2005 Sociological theory Classical statements 6th ed Boston MA Pearson Education pp 94 98 100 104 a b Munz Peter 1993 Philosophical Darwinism On the Origin of Knowledge by Means of Natural Selection London Routledge p 94 ISBN 9781134884841 a b Flynn Thomas R 1997 Sartre Foucault and Historical Reason Vol 1 Chicago Chicago University Press p 4 ISBN 9780226254692 Martin Luther H 2014 Deep History Secular Theory Historical and Scientific Studies of Religion Berlin Walter de Gruyter p 343 ISBN 9781614515005 Lerner Robert E 2017 Ernst Kantorowicz A Life Princeton Princeton University Press p 129 ISBN 9780691183022 Shank J B 2008 The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment Chicago Chicago University Press p 24 ISBN 9780226749471 Collingwood R G 1946 The Idea of History Oxford Oxford University Press pp 131 33 Raymond Boudon and Francois Bourricaud A Critical Dictionary of Sociology Archived 3 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine Routledge 1989 Historicism p 198 a b Wallace Edwin R and Gach John 2008 History of Psychiatry and Medical Psychology With an Epilogue on Psychiatry and the Mind Body Relation p 14 Archived 16 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine a b Wallace and Gach 2008 p 28 Archived 8 November 2015 at the Wayback Machine Koch Sigmund 1992 Psychology s Bridgman vs Bridgman s Bridgman An Essay in Reconstruction in Theory and Psychology vol 2 no 3 1992 p 275 Lawrence A Boland Economic Positivism positivists org 2012 Archived from the original on 17 February 2015 Retrieved 18 February 2015 Bunge M A 1996 Finding Philosophy in Social Science Yale University Press p 317 ISBN 9780300066067 LCCN lc96004399 Archived from the original on 4 June 2016 Retrieved 7 November 2015 To conclude logical positivism was progressive compared with the classical positivism of Ptolemy Hume d Alembert Comte Mill and Mach It was even more so by comparison with its contemporary rivals neo Thomisism neo Kantianism intuitionism dialectical materialism phenomenology and existentialism However neo positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science whether natural or social It failed because it remained anchored to sense data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis and denounced realism and materialism as metaphysical nonsense Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers notably Popper 1959 1935 1963 logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists Regrettably the anti positivism fashionable in the metatheory of social science is often nothing but an excuse for sloppiness and wild speculation Popper Falsifiability and the Failure of Positivism 7 August 2000 Archived from the original on 7 January 2014 Retrieved 30 June 2012 The upshot is that the positivists seem caught between insisting on the V C Verifiability Criterion but for no defensible reason or admitting that the V C requires a background language etc which opens the door to relativism etc Hanfling Oswald 2003 Logical Positivism Routledge History of Philosophy Vol IX Routledge pp 193 194 Alan Bullock and Stephen Trombley Eds The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought London Harper Collins 1999 pp 669 737 Giambattista Vico Principi di scienza nuova Opere ed Fausto Nicolini Milan R Ricciardi 1953 pp 365 905 Morera Esteve 1990 p 13 Gramsci s Historicism A Realist Interpretation Archived 16 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine Burawoy Michael For Public Sociology Archived 21 April 2015 at the Wayback Machine American Sociological Review February 2005 Ashley D Orenstein DM 2005 Sociological theory Classical statements 6th ed Boston MA Pearson Education pp 239 240 Ashley D Orenstein DM 2005 Sociological theory Classical statements 6th ed Boston MA Pearson Education p 241 a b c Miller Katherine 2007 Communication theories perspectives processes and contexts 2nd ed Beijing Peking University Press pp 35 45 ISBN 9787301124314 Karl Popper Conjectures and Refutations p 256 Routledge London 1963 Karl Popper The Logic of Scientific Discovery 1934 1959 1st English ed Harding 1976 p Xharvnb error no target CITEREFHarding1976 help The physicist can never subject an isolated hypothesis to experimental test but only a whole group of hypotheses Duhem Duhem denies that unambiguous falsification procedures do exist in science Thomas David 1979 Naturalism and social sciences ch Paradigms and social science p 161 Bergman Mats 2016 Positivism The International Encyclopedia of Communication Theory and Philosophy p 1 5 doi 10 1002 9781118766804 wbiect248 ISBN 9781118766804 Trochim William Social Research Methods Knowledge Base socialresearchmethods net a b Robson Colin 2002 Real World Research A Resource for Social Scientists and Practitioner Researchers Second ed Malden Blackwell p 624 ISBN 978 0 631 21305 5 a b Taylor Thomas R Lindlof Bryan C 2011 Qualitative communication research methods 3rd ed Thousand Oaks Calif SAGE p 5 13 ISBN 978 1412974738 Friedrich Stadler The Vienna Circle Studies in the Origins Development and Influence of Logical Empiricism Springer 2015 p 250 Main Currents of Marxism by Leszek Kolakowski pp 327 331 Jurgen Habermas Technik und Wissenschaft als Ideologie Frankfurt am Main Suhrkamp 1968 chap 1 Schunk Learning Theories An Educational Perspective 5th 315 Outhwaite William 1988 Habermas Key Contemporary Thinkers Polity Press Second Edition 2009 ISBN 978 0 7456 4328 1 p 68 a b c d e f Fagan Andrew Theodor Adorno 1903 1969 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 24 February 2012 Retrieved 24 February 2012 Tittle Charles 2004 The Arrogance of Public Sociology Social Forces June 2004 82 4 Heisenberg Werner 1971 Positivism Metaphysics and Religion Physics and Beyond Encounters and Conversations World Perspectives vol 42 Translated by Pomerans Arnold J New York Harper amp Row p 213 ISBN 9780049250086 LCCN 78095963 OCLC 15379872 Portugali Juval and Han Meyer Egbert Stolk 2012 Complexity Theories of Cities Have Come of Age p 51 Archived 10 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine Positivism Varela F J Thompson E T amp Rosch E 1991 The Embodied Mind Cognitive Science and Human Experience The MIT Press Lakoff G amp Johnson M 1999 Philosophy in the Flesh The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought Basic books a b Hanson Barbara 2008 Wither Qualitative Quantitative Grounds for Methodological Convergence Quality and Quantity 42 97 111 Bryman Alan 1984 The Debate about Quantitative and Qualitative Research A Question of Method or Epistemology The British Journal of Sociology 35 75 92 a b c Holmes Richard 1997 Genre analysis and the social sciences An investigation of the structure of research article discussion sections in three disciplines English For Specific Purposes vol 16 num 4 321 337 a b Brett Paul 1994 A genre analysis of the results section of sociology articles English For Specific Purposes Vol 13 Num 1 47 59 Gartell David and Gartell John 1996 Positivism in sociological practice 1967 1990 Canadian Review of Sociology Vol 33 No 2 Boudon Raymond 1991 Review What Middle Range Theories are Contemporary Sociology Vol 20 Num 4 pp 519 522 Halfpenny Peter Positivism and Sociology Explaining Social Life London Allen and Unwin 1982 a b Grant Linda Ward Kathryn B Xue Lan Rong 1987 Is There An Association between Gender and Methods in Sociological Research American Sociological Review 52 6 856 862 doi 10 2307 2095839 JSTOR 2095839 Hacking I ed 1981 Scientific revolutions Oxford Univ Press New York References editAmory Frederic Euclides da Cunha and Brazilian Positivism Luso Brazilian Review 36 1 Summer 1999 87 94 Armenteros Carolina 2017 The Counterrevolutionary Comte Theorist of the Two Powers and Enthusiastic Medievalist In The Anthem Companion to Auguste Comte edited by Andrew Wernick 91 116 London Anthem Annan Noel 1959 The Curious Strength of Positivism in English Political Thought London Oxford University Press Ardao Arturo 1963 Assimilation and Transformation of Positivism in Latin America Journal of the History of Ideas 24 4 515 22 Bevir Mark 1993 Ernest Belfort Bax Marxist Idealist Positivist Journal of the History of Ideas 54 1 119 35 doi 10 2307 2709863 JSTOR 2709863 Bevir Mark 2002 Sidney Webb Utilitarianism Positivism and Social Democracy The Journal of Modern History 74 2 217 252 Bevir Mark 2011 The Making of British Socialism Princeton PA Princeton University Press Bourdeau Michel 2006 Les trois etats Science theologie et metaphysique chez Auguste Comte Paris Editions du Cerf Bourdeau Michel Mary Pickering and Warren Schmaus eds 2018 Love Order and Progress Pittsburgh PA University of Pittsburgh Press Bryant Christopher G A 1985 Positivism in Social Theory and Research New York St Martin s Press Claeys Gregory 2010 Imperial Sceptics Cambridge Cambridge University Press Claeys Gregory 2018 Professor Beesly Positivism and the International the Patriotism Issue In Arise Ye Wretched of the Earth The First International in a Global Perspective edited by Fabrice Bensimon Quinton Deluermoz and Jeanne Moisand Leiden Brill De Boni Carlo 2013 Storia di un utopia La religione dell Umanita di Comte e la sua circolazione nel mondo Milano Mimesis Dixon Thomas 2008 The Invention of Altruism Oxford Oxford University Press Feichtinger Johannes Franz L Fillafer and Jan Surman eds 2018 The Worlds of Positivism London Palgrave Macmillan Forbes Geraldine Handcock 2003 The English Positivists and India In Essays on Indian Renaissance edited by Raj Kumar 151 63 Discovery New Delhi Gane Mike 2006 Auguste Comte London Routledge Giddens Anthony Positivism and Sociology Heinemann London 1974 Gilson Gregory D and Irving W Levinson eds Latin American Positivism New Historical and Philosophic Essays Lexington Books 2012 197 pages Essays on positivism in the intellectual and political life of Brazil Colombia and Mexico Harp Gillis J 1995 Positivist Republic Auguste Comte and the Reconstruction of American Liberalism 1865 1920 University Park PA Pennsylvania State University Press Harrison Royden 1965 Before the Socialists London Routledge Hoecker Drysdale Susan 2001 Harriet Martineau and the Positivism of Auguste Comte In Harriet Martineau Theoretical and Methodological Perspectives edited by Michael R Hill and Susan Hoecker Drysdale 169 90 London Routledge Kremer Marietti Angele L Anthropologie positiviste d Auguste Comte Librairie Honore Champion Paris 1980 Kremer Marietti Angele Le positivisme Collection Que sais je Paris PUF 1982 LeGouis Catherine Positivism and Imagination Scientism and Its Limits in Emile Hennequin Wilhelm Scherer and Dmitril Pisarev Bucknell University Press London 1997 Lenzer Gertrud ed 2009 The Essential Writings of Auguste Comte and Positivism London Transaction Positivism Marxists Internet Archive Web 23 Feb 2012 McGee John Edwin 1931 A Crusade for Humanity London Watts Mill John Stuart Auguste Comte and Positivism Mises Richard von Positivism A Study In Human Understanding Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts 1951 Petit Annie Le Systeme d Auguste Comte De la science a la religion par la philosophie Vrin Paris 2016 Pickering Mary Auguste Comte An Intellectual Biography Cambridge University Press Cambridge England 1993 Quin Malcolm 1924 Memoirs of a Positivist London George Allen amp Unwin Richard Rorty 1982 Consequences of Pragmatism Scharff Robert C 1995 Comte After Positivism Cambridge Cambridge University Press Schunk Dale H Learning Theories An Educational Perspective 5th Pearson Merrill Prentice Hall 1991 1996 2000 2004 2008 Simon W M 1963 European Positivism in the Nineteenth Century Ithaca NY Cornell University Press Sutton Michael 1982 Nationalism Positivism and Catholicism Cambridge Cambridge University Press Trindade Helgio 2003 La republique positiviste chex Comte In Auguste Comte Trajectoires positivistes 1798 1998 edited by Annie Petit 363 400 Paris L Harmattan Turner Mark 2000 Defining Discourses The Westminster Review Fortnightly Review and Comte s Positivism Victorian Periodicals Review 33 3 273 282 Wernick Andrew 2001 Auguste Comte and the Religion of Humanity Cambridge Cambridge University Press Whatmore Richard 2005 Comte Auguste 1798 1857 In Encyclopaedia of Nineteenth Century Thought edited by Gregory Claeys 123 8 London Routledge Whetsell Travis and Patricia M Shields The Dynamics of Positivism in the Study of Public Administration A Brief Intellectual History and Reappraisal Administration amp Society doi 10 1177 0095399713490157 Wils Kaat 2005 De omweg van de wetenschap het positivisme en de Belgische en Nederlandse intellectuele cultuur 1845 1914 Amsterdam Amsterdam University Press Wilson Matthew 2018 British Comtism and Modernist Design Modern Intellectual History x xx 1 32 Wilson Matthew 2018 Moralising Space the Utopian Urbanism of the British Positivists 1855 1920 London Routledge Wilson Matthew 2020 Rendering sociology on the utopian positivism of Harriet Martineau and the Mumbo Jumbo club Journal of Interdisciplinary History of Ideas 8 16 1 42 Woll Allen L 1976 Positivism and History in Nineteenth Century Chile Journal of the History of Ideas 37 3 493 506 Woodward Ralph Lee ed 1971 Positivism in Latin America 1850 1900 Lexington Heath Wright T R 1986 The Religion of Humanity Cambridge Cambridge University Press Wright T R 1981 George Eliot and Positivism A Reassessment The Modern Language Review 76 2 257 72 Wunderlich Roger 1992 Low Living and High Thinking at Modern Times New York Syracuse NY Syracuse University Press Zea Leopoldo 1974 Positivism in Mexico Austin University of Texas Press External links editThe full text of the 1911 Encyclopaedia Britannica article Positivism at Wikisource Parana Brazil Porto Alegre Brazil Rio de Janeiro Brazil Posnan Poland Positivists Worldwide Maison d Auguste Comte France Portals nbsp Philosophy nbsp Society nbsp SciencePositivism at Wikipedia s sister projects nbsp Definitions from Wiktionary nbsp Media from Commons nbsp Quotations from Wikiquote nbsp Texts from Wikisource Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Positivism amp oldid 1177873057, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.