fbpx
Wikipedia

Logic

Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises in a topic-neutral way. When used as a countable noun, the term "a logic" refers to a logical formal system that articulates a proof system. Formal logic contrasts with informal logic, which is associated with informal fallacies, critical thinking, and argumentation theory. While there is no general agreement on how formal and informal logic are to be distinguished, one prominent approach associates their difference with whether the studied arguments are expressed in formal or informal languages. Logic plays a central role in multiple fields, such as philosophy, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics.

Logic studies valid forms of inference like the modus ponens.

Logic studies arguments, which consist of a set of premises together with a conclusion. Premises and conclusions are usually understood either as sentences or as propositions and are characterized by their internal structure; complex propositions are made up of simpler propositions linked to each other by propositional connectives like (and) or (if...then). The truth of a proposition usually depends on the denotations of its constituents. Logically true propositions constitute a special case, since their truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in them and not on the denotations of other terms.

Arguments can be either correct or incorrect. An argument is correct if its premises support its conclusion. The strongest form of support is found in deductive arguments: it is impossible for their premises to be true and their conclusion to be false. Deductive arguments contrast with ampliative arguments, which may arrive in their conclusion at new information that is not present in the premises. However, it is possible for all their premises to be true while their conclusion is still false. Many arguments found in everyday discourse and the sciences are ampliative arguments, sometimes divided into inductive and abductive arguments. Inductive arguments usually take the form of statistical generalizations, while abductive arguments are inferences to the best explanation. Arguments that fall short of the standards of correct reasoning are called fallacies.

Systems of logic are theoretical frameworks for assessing the correctness of reasoning and arguments. Logic has been studied since antiquity; early approaches include Aristotelian logic, Stoic logic, Anviksiki, and the Mohists. Modern formal logic has its roots in the work of late 19th-century mathematicians such as Gottlob Frege. While Aristotelian logic focuses on reasoning in the form of syllogisms, in the modern era its traditional dominance was replaced by classical logic, a set of fundamental logical intuitions shared by most logicians. It consists of propositional logic, which only considers the logical relations on the level of propositions, and first-order logic, which also articulates the internal structure of propositions using various linguistic devices, such as predicates and quantifiers. Extended logics accept the basic intuitions behind classical logic and extend it to other fields, such as metaphysics, ethics, and epistemology. Deviant logics, on the other hand, reject certain classical intuitions and provide alternative accounts of the fundamental laws of logic.

Definition

The word "logic" originates from the Greek word "logos", which has a variety of translations, such as reason, discourse, or language.[1][2] Logic is traditionally defined as the study of the laws of thought or correct reasoning,[3] and is usually understood in terms of inferences or arguments. Reasoning may be seen as the activity of drawing inferences whose outward expression is given in arguments.[3][4][5] An inference or an argument is a set of premises together with a conclusion. Logic is interested in whether arguments are good or inferences are valid, i.e. whether the premises support their conclusions.[6][7][8] These general characterizations apply to logic in the widest sense, since they are true both for formal and informal logic, but many definitions of logic focus on the more paradigmatic formal logic. In this narrower sense, logic is a formal science that studies how conclusions follow from premises in a topic-neutral way.[9][10][11] In this regard, logic is sometimes contrasted with the theory of rationality, which is wider since it covers all forms of good reasoning.[12]

 
Alfred Tarski was an influential defender of the idea that logical truth can be defined in terms of possible interpretations.[13][14]

As a formal science, logic contrasts with both the natural and social sciences in that it tries to characterize the inferential relations between premises and conclusions based on their structure alone.[15][16] This means that the actual content of these propositions, i.e. their specific topic, is not important for whether the inference is valid or not.[9][10] Valid inferences are characterized by the fact that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion: it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false.[8][17] The general logical structures characterizing valid inferences are called rules of inference.[6] In this sense, logic is often defined as the study of valid arguments.[4] This contrasts with another prominent characterization of logic as the science of logical truths.[18] A proposition is logically true if its truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in it. This means that it is true in all possible worlds and under all interpretations of its non-logical terms.[19] These two characterizations of logic are closely related to each other: an inference is valid if the material conditional from its premises to its conclusion is logically true.[18]

The term "logic" can also be used in a slightly different sense as a countable noun. In this sense, a logic is a logical formal system. Distinct logics differ from each other concerning the rules of inference they accept as valid and concerning the formal languages used to express them.[4][20][21] Starting in the late 19th century, many new formal systems have been proposed. There are various disagreements concerning what makes a formal system a logic.[4][21] For example, it has been suggested that only logically complete systems qualify as logics. For such reasons, some theorists deny that higher-order logics and fuzzy logic are logics in the strict sense.[4][22][23]

Formal and informal logic

Logic encompasses both formal and informal logic.[4][24] Formal logic is the traditionally dominant field,[17] but applying its insights to actual everyday arguments has prompted modern developments of informal logic,[24][25][26] which considers problems that formal logic on its own is unable to address.[17][26] Both provide criteria for assessing the correctness of arguments and distinguishing them from fallacies.[11][17] Various suggestions have been made concerning how to draw the distinction between the two, but there is no universally accepted answer.[26][27]

 
Formal logic needs to translate natural language arguments into a formal language, like first-order logic, in order to assess whether they are valid. In this example, the colors indicate how the English words correspond to the symbols.

The most literal approach sees the terms "formal" and "informal" as applying to the language used to express arguments.[24][25][28] On this view, formal logic studies arguments expressed in formal languages while informal logic studies arguments expressed in informal or natural languages.[17][26] This means that the inference from the formulas " " and " " to the conclusion " " is studied by formal logic. The inference from the English sentences "Al lit a cigarette" and "Bill stormed out of the room" to the sentence "Al lit a cigarette and Bill stormed out of the room", on the other hand, belongs to informal logic. Formal languages are characterized by their precision and simplicity.[28][17][26] They normally contain a very limited vocabulary and exact rules on how their symbols can be used to construct sentences, usually referred to as well-formed formulas.[29][30] This simplicity and exactness of formal logic make it capable of formulating precise rules of inference that determine whether a given argument is valid.[29] This approach brings with it the need to translate natural language arguments into the formal language before their validity can be assessed, a procedure that comes with various problems of its own.[31][15][26] Informal logic avoids some of these problems by analyzing natural language arguments in their original form without the need of translation.[11][24][32] But it faces problems associated with the ambiguity, vagueness, and context-dependence of natural language expressions.[17][33][34] A closely related approach applies the terms "formal" and "informal" not just to the language used, but more generally to the standards, criteria, and procedures of argumentation.[35]

Another approach draws the distinction according to the different types of inferences analyzed.[24][36][37] This perspective understands formal logic as the study of deductive inferences in contrast to informal logic as the study of non-deductive inferences, like inductive or abductive inferences.[24][37] The characteristic of deductive inferences is that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion. This means that if all the premises are true, it is impossible for the conclusion to be false.[8][17] For this reason, deductive inferences are in a sense trivial or uninteresting since they do not provide the thinker with any new information not already found in the premises.[38][39] Non-deductive inferences, on the other hand, are ampliative: they help the thinker learn something above and beyond what is already stated in the premises. They achieve this at the cost of certainty: even if all premises are true, the conclusion of an ampliative argument may still be false.[18][40][41]

One more approach tries to link the difference between formal and informal logic to the distinction between formal and informal fallacies.[24][26][35] This distinction is often drawn in relation to the form, content, and context of arguments. In the case of formal fallacies, the error is found on the level of the argument's form, whereas for informal fallacies, the content and context of the argument are responsible.[42][43][44] Formal logic abstracts away from the argument's content and is only interested in its form, specifically whether it follows a valid rule of inference.[9][10] In this regard, it is not important for the validity of a formal argument whether its premises are true or false. Informal logic, on the other hand, also takes the content and context of an argument into consideration.[17][26][28] A false dilemma, for example, involves an error of content by excluding viable options, as in "you are either with us or against us; you are not with us; therefore, you are against us".[45][43] For the strawman fallacy, on the other hand, the error is found on the level of context: a weak position is first described and then defeated, even though the opponent does not hold this position. But in another context, against an opponent that actually defends the strawman position, the argument is correct.[33][43]

Other accounts draw the distinction based on investigating general forms of arguments in contrast to particular instances, or on the study of logical constants instead of substantive concepts. A further approach focuses on the discussion of logical topics with or without formal devices, or on the role of epistemology for the assessment of arguments.[17][26]

Fundamental concepts

Premises, conclusions, and truth

Premises and conclusions

Premises and conclusions are the basic parts of inferences or arguments and therefore play a central role in logic. In the case of a valid inference or a correct argument, the conclusion follows from the premises, or in other words, the premises support the conclusion.[7][46] For instance, the premises "Mars is red" and "Mars is a planet" support the conclusion "Mars is a red planet". For most types of logic, it is accepted that premises and conclusions have to be truth-bearers.[7][46][i] This means that they have a truth value: they are either true or false. Thus contemporary philosophy generally sees them either as propositions or as sentences.[7] Propositions are the denotations of sentences and are usually understood as abstract objects.[48][49]

Propositional theories of premises and conclusions are often criticized because of the difficulties involved in specifying the identity criteria of abstract objects or because of naturalist considerations.[7] These objections are avoided by seeing premises and conclusions not as propositions but as sentences, i.e. as concrete linguistic objects like the symbols displayed on a page of a book. But this approach comes with new problems of its own: sentences are often context-dependent and ambiguous, meaning an argument's validity would not only depend on its parts but also on its context and on how it is interpreted.[7][50] Another approach is to understand premises and conclusions in psychological terms as thoughts or judgments. This position is known as psychologism and was heavily criticized around the turn of the 20th century.[7][51][52]

Internal structure

Premises and conclusions have internal structure. As propositions or sentences, they can be either simple or complex.[53][54] A complex proposition has other propositions as its constituents, which are linked to each other through propositional connectives like "and" or "if...then". Simple propositions, on the other hand, do not have propositional parts. But they can also be conceived as having an internal structure: they are made up of subpropositional parts, like singular terms and predicates.[46][53][54] For example, the simple proposition "Mars is red" can be formed by applying the predicate "red" to the singular term "Mars". In contrast, the complex proposition "Mars is red and Venus is white" is made up of two simple propositions connected by the propositional connective "and".[46]

Whether a proposition is true depends, at least in part, on its constituents.[54] For complex propositions formed using truth-functional propositional connectives, their truth only depends on the truth values of their parts.[46] But this relation is more complicated in the case of simple propositions and their subpropositional parts. These subpropositional parts have meanings of their own, like referring to objects or classes of objects.[46][55][56] Whether the simple proposition they form is true depends on their relation to reality, i.e. what the objects they refer to are like. This topic is studied by theories of reference.[56]

Logical truth

In some cases, a simple or a complex proposition is true independently of the substantive meanings of its parts.[3][57] For example, the complex proposition "if Mars is red, then Mars is red" is true independent of whether its parts, i.e. the simple proposition "Mars is red", are true or false. In such cases, the truth is called a logical truth: a proposition is logically true if its truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in it.[19][57][46] This means that it is true under all interpretations of its non-logical terms. In some modal logics, this notion can be understood equivalently as truth at all possible worlds.[19][58] Some theorists define logic as the study of logical truths.[18]

Truth tables

Truth tables can be used to show how logical connectives work or how the truth of complex propositions depends on their parts. They have a column for each input variable. Each row corresponds to one possible combination of the truth values these variables can take. The final columns present the truth values of the corresponding expressions as determined by the input values. For example, the expression " " uses the logical connective   (and). It could be used to express a sentence like "yesterday was Sunday and the weather was good". It is only true if both of its input variables,   ("yesterday was Sunday") and   ("the weather was good"), are true. In all other cases, the expression as a whole is false. Other important logical connectives are   (or),   (if...then), and   (not).[59][60] Truth tables can also be defined for more complex expressions that use several propositional connectives. For example, given the conditional proposition  , one can form truth tables of its inverse ( ), and its contraposition ( ).[61]

Truth table of various expression
p q pq pq pq ¬p¬q
T T T T T T
T F F T F T
F T F T T F
F F F F T T

Arguments and inferences

Logic is commonly defined in terms of arguments or inferences as the study of their correctness.[3][7] An argument is a set of premises together with a conclusion.[62][63] An inference is the process of reasoning from these premises to the conclusion.[7] But these terms are often used interchangeably in logic. Arguments are correct or incorrect depending on whether their premises support their conclusion. Premises and conclusions, on the other hand, are true or false depending on whether they are in accord with reality. In formal logic, a sound argument is an argument that is both correct and has only true premises.[64] Sometimes a distinction is made between simple and complex arguments. A complex argument is made up of a chain of simple arguments. These simple arguments constitute a chain because the conclusions of the earlier arguments are used as premises in the later arguments. For a complex argument to be successful, each link of the chain has to be successful.[7]

 
Argument terminology used in logic

Arguments and inferences are either are correct or incorrect. If they are correct then their premises support their conclusion. In the incorrect case, this support is missing. It can take different forms corresponding to the different types of reasoning.[65][40][66] The strongest form of support corresponds to deductive reasoning. But even arguments that are not deductively valid may still constitute good arguments because their premises offer non-deductive support to their conclusions. For such cases, the term ampliative or inductive reasoning is used.[18][40][66] Deductive arguments are associated with formal logic in contrast to the relation between ampliative arguments and informal logic.[24][36][67]

Deductive

A deductively valid argument is one whose premises guarantee the truth of its conclusion.[8][17] For instance, the argument "(1) all frogs are reptiles; (2) no cats are reptiles; (3) therefore no cats are frogs" is deductively valid. For deductive validity, it does not matter whether the premises or the conclusion are actually true. So the argument "(1) all frogs are mammals; (2) no cats are mammals; (3) therefore no cats are frogs" is also valid because the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises.[68]

Alfred Tarski holds that deductive arguments have three essential features: (1) they are formal, i.e. they depend only on the form of the premises and the conclusion; (2) they are a priori, i.e. no sense experience is needed to determine whether they obtain; (3) they are modal, i.e. that they hold by logical necessity for the given propositions, independent of any other circumstances.[8]

Because of the first feature, the focus on formality, deductive inference is usually identified with rules of inference.[69] Rules of inference specify how the premises and the conclusion have to be structured for the inference to be valid. Arguments that do not follow any rule of inference are deductively invalid.[70][71] The modus ponens is a prominent rule of inference. It has the form "p; if p, then q; therefore q".[71] Knowing that it has just rained ( ) and that after rain the streets are wet ( ), one can use modus ponens to deduce that the streets are wet ( ).[72]

The third feature can be expressed by stating that deductively valid inferences are truth-preserving: it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false.[6][40][73] Because of this feature, it is often asserted that deductive inferences are uninformative since the conclusion cannot arrive at new information not already present in the premises.[38][39] But this point is not always accepted since it would mean, for example, that most of mathematics is uninformative. A different characterization distinguishes between surface and depth information. On this view, deductive inferences are uninformative on the depth level but can be highly informative on the surface level, as may be the case for various mathematical proofs.[38][74][75]

Ampliative

Ampliative inferences, on the other hand, are informative even on the depth level. They are more interesting in this sense since the thinker may acquire substantive information from them and thereby learn something genuinely new.[76][40][41] But this feature comes with a certain cost: the premises support the conclusion in the sense that they make its truth more likely but they do not ensure its truth.[6][40][41] This means that the conclusion of an ampliative argument may be false even though all its premises are true. This characteristic is closely related to non-monotonicity and defeasibility: it may be necessary to retract an earlier conclusion upon receiving new information or in the light of new inferences drawn.[3][77][73] Ampliative reasoning plays a central role for many arguments found in everyday discourse and the sciences. Ampliative arguments are not automatically incorrect. Instead, they just follow different standards of correctness. The support they provide for their conclusion usually comes in degrees. This means that strong ampliative arguments make their conclusion very likely while weak ones are less certain. As a consequence, the line between correct and incorrect arguments is blurry in some cases, as when the premises offer weak but non-negligible support. This contrasts with deductive arguments, which are either valid or invalid with nothing in-between.[66][73][78]

The terminology used to categorize ampliative arguments is inconsistent. Some authors, like James Hawthorne, use the term "induction" to cover all forms of non-deductive arguments.[66][78][79] But in a more narrow sense, induction is only one type of ampliative argument besides abductive arguments.[73] Some philosophers, Leo Groarke, also allow conductive arguments as one more type.[24][80] In this narrow sense, induction is often defined as a form of statistical generalization.[81][82] In this case, the premises of an inductive argument are many individual observations that all show a certain pattern. The conclusion then is a general law that this pattern always obtains.[83] In this sense, one may infer that "all elephants are gray" based on one's past observations of the color of elephants.[73] A closely related form of inductive inference has as its conclusion not a general law but one more specific instance, as when it is inferred that an elephant one has not seen yet is also gray.[83] Some theorists, like Igor Douven, stipulate that inductive inferences rest only on statistical considerations in order to distinguish them from abductive inference.[73]

Abductive inference may or may not take statistical observations into consideration. In either case, the premises offer support for the conclusion because the conclusion is the best explanation of why the premises are true.[73][84] In this sense, abduction is also called the inference to the best explanation.[85] For example, given the premise that there is a plate with breadcrumbs in the kitchen in the early morning, one may infer the conclusion that one's house-mate had a midnight snack and was too tired to clean the table. This conclusion is justified because it is the best explanation of the current state of the kitchen.[73] For abduction, it is not sufficient that the conclusion explains the premises. For example, the conclusion that a burglar broke into the house last night, got hungry on the job, and had a midnight snack, would also explain the state of the kitchen. But this conclusion is not justified because it is not the best or most likely explanation.[73][84][85]

Fallacies

Not all arguments live up to the standards of correct reasoning. When they do not, they are usually referred to as fallacies. Their central aspect is not that their conclusion is false but that there is some flaw with the reasoning leading to this conclusion.[86][87] So the argument "it is sunny today; therefore spiders have eight legs" is fallacious even though the conclusion is true. Some theorists, like John Stuart Mill, give a more restrictive definition of fallacies by additionally requiring that they appear to be correct.[33][86] This way, genuine fallacies can be distinguished from mere mistakes of reasoning due to carelessness. This explains why people tend to commit fallacies: because they have an alluring element that seduces people into committing and accepting them.[86] However, this reference to appearances is controversial because it belongs to the field of psychology, not logic, and because appearances may be different for different people.[86][88]

 
Young America's dilemma: Shall I be wise and great, or rich and powerful? (poster from 1901) This is an example of a false Dilemma: an informal fallacy using a disjunctive premise that excludes viable alternatives.

Fallacies are usually divided into formal and informal fallacies.[42][43][44] For formal fallacies, the source of the error is found in the form of the argument. For example, denying the antecedent is one type of formal fallacy, as in "if Othello is a bachelor, then he is male; Othello is not a bachelor; therefore Othello is not male".[89][90] But most fallacies fall into the category of informal fallacies, of which a great variety is discussed in the academic literature. The source of their error is usually found in the content or the context of the argument.[33][43][86] Informal fallacies are sometimes categorized as fallacies of ambiguity, fallacies of presumption, or fallacies of relevance. For fallacies of ambiguity, the ambiguity and vagueness of natural language are responsible for their flaw, as in "feathers are light; what is light cannot be dark; therefore feathers cannot be dark".[34][91][44] Fallacies of presumption have a wrong or unjustified premise but may be valid otherwise.[44][92] In the case of fallacies of relevance, the premises do not support the conclusion because they are not relevant to it.[44][91]

Definitory and strategic rules

The main focus of most logicians is to investigate the criteria according to which an argument is correct or incorrect. A fallacy is committed if these criteria are violated. In the case of formal logic, they are known as rules of inference.[65] They constitute definitory rules, which determine whether a certain inference is correct or which inferences are allowed. Definitory rules contrast with strategic rules. Strategic rules specify which inferential moves are necessary in order to reach a given conclusion based on a certain set of premises. This distinction does not just apply to logic but also to various games as well. In chess, for example, the definitory rules dictate that bishops may only move diagonally while the strategic rules describe how the allowed moves may be used to win a game, for example, by controlling the center and by defending one's king.[65][93][94]A third type of rules concerns empirical descriptive rules. They belong to the field of psychology and generalize how people actually draw inferences. It has been argued that logicians should give more emphasis to strategic rules since they are highly relevant for effective reasoning.[65]

Formal systems

A formal system of logic consists of a formal language together with a set of axioms and a proof system used to draw inferences from these axioms.[95][96] Some theorists also include a semantics that specifies how the expressions of the formal language relate to real objects.[97][98] The term "a logic" is used as a countable noun to refer to a particular formal system of logic.[4][99][21] Starting in the late 19th century, many new formal systems have been proposed.[4][22][21]

A formal language consists of an alphabet and syntactic rules. The alphabet is the set of basic symbols used in expressions. The syntactic rules determine how these symbols may be arranged to result in well-formed formulas.[100][101] For instance, the syntactic rules of propositional logic determine that " " is a well-formed formula but " " is not since the logical conjunction   requires terms on both sides.[102]

A proof system is a collection of rules that may be used to formulate formal proofs. In this regard, it may be understood as an inference machine that arrives at conclusions from a set of axioms. Rules in a proof system are defined in terms of the syntactic form of formulas independent of their specific content. For instance, the classical rule of conjunction introduction states that   follows from the premises   and  . Such rules can be applied sequentially, giving a mechanical procedure for generating conclusions from premises. There are several different types of proof systems including natural deduction and sequent calculi.[103][104]

A semantics is a system for mapping expressions of a formal language to their denotations. In many systems of logic, denotations are truth values. For instance, the semantics for classical propositional logic assigns the formula   the denotation "true" whenever   and   are true. From the semantic point of view, a premise entails a conclusion if the conclusion is true whenever the premise is true.[105][106][107]

A system of logic is sound when its proof system cannot derive a conclusion from a set of premises unless it is semantically entailed by them. In other words, its proof system cannot lead to false conclusions, as defined by the semantics. A system is complete when its proof system can derive every conclusion that is semantically entailed by its premises. In other words, its proof system can lead to any true conclusion, as defined by the semantics. Thus, soundness and completeness together describe a system whose notions of validity and entailment line up perfectly.[108][109][110]

Systems of logic

Systems of logic are theoretical frameworks for assessing the correctness of reasoning and arguments. For over two thousand years, Aristotelian logic was treated as the canon of logic in the Western world,[21][111][112] but modern developments in this field have led to a vast proliferation of logical systems.[113] One prominent categorization divides modern formal logical systems into classical logic, extended logics, and deviant logics.[4][113][114] Classical logic is to be distinguished from traditional or Aristotelian logic. It encompasses propositional logic and first-order logic. It is "classical" in the sense that it is based on various fundamental logical intuitions shared by most logicians.[3][115][116] These intuitions include the law of excluded middle, the double negation elimination, the principle of explosion, and the bivalence of truth.[117] It was originally developed to analyze mathematical arguments and was only later applied to other fields as well. Because of this focus on mathematics, it does not include logical vocabulary relevant to many other topics of philosophical importance, like the distinction between necessity and possibility, the problem of ethical obligation and permission, or the relations between past, present, and future.[118] Such issues are addressed by extended logics. They build on the fundamental intuitions of classical logic and expand it by introducing new logical vocabulary. This way, the exact logical approach is applied to fields like ethics or epistemology that lie beyond the scope of mathematics.[21][119][120]

Deviant logics, on the other hand, reject some of the fundamental intuitions of classical logic. Because of this, they are usually seen not as its supplements but as its rivals. Deviant logical systems differ from each other either because they reject different classical intuitions or because they propose different alternatives to the same issue.[113][114]

Informal logic is usually carried out in a less systematic way. It often focuses on more specific issues, like investigating a particular type of fallacy or studying a certain aspect of argumentation.[24] Nonetheless, some systems of informal logic have also been presented that try to provide a systematic characterization of the correctness of arguments.[86][121][122]

Aristotelian

Aristotelian logic encompasses a great variety of topics, including metaphysical theses about ontological categories and problems of scientific explanation. But in a more narrow sense, it is identical to term logic or syllogistics. A syllogism is a certain form of argument involving three propositions: two premises and a conclusion. Each proposition has three essential parts: a subject, a predicate, and a copula connecting the subject to the predicate.[111][112][123] For example, the proposition "Socrates is wise" is made up of the subject "Socrates", the predicate "wise", and the copula "is".[112] The subject and the predicate are the terms of the proposition. In this sense, Aristotelian logic does not contain complex propositions made up of various simple propositions. It differs in this aspect from propositional logic, in which any two propositions can be linked using a logical connective like "and" to form a new complex proposition.[111][124]

 
The square of opposition is often used to visualize the relations between the four basic categorical propositions in Aristotelian logic. It shows, for example, that the propositions "All S are P" and "Some S are not P" are contradictory, meaning that one of them has to be true while the other is false.

Aristotelian logic differs from predicate logic in that the subject is either universal, particular, indefinite, or singular. For example, the term "all humans" is a universal subject in the proposition "all humans are mortal". A similar proposition could be formed by replacing it with the particular term "some humans", the indefinite term "a human", or the singular term "Socrates".[111][123][125] In predicate logic, on the other hand, universal and particular propositions would be expressed by using a quantifier and two predicates.[111][126] Another key difference is that Aristotelian logic only includes predicates for simple properties of entities, but lacks predicates corresponding to relations between entities.[127] The predicate can be linked to the subject in two ways: either by affirming it or by denying it.[111][112] For example, the proposition "Socrates is not a cat" involves the denial of the predicate "cat" to the subject "Socrates". Using different combinations of subjects and predicates, a great variety of propositions and syllogisms can be formed. Syllogisms are characterized by the fact that the premises are linked to each other and to the conclusion by sharing one predicate in each case.[111][128][129] Thus, these three propositions contain three predicates, referred to as major term, minor term, and middle term.[112][128][129] The central aspect of Aristotelian logic involves classifying all possible syllogisms into valid and invalid arguments according to how the propositions are formed.[111][112][128] For example, the syllogism "all men are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore Socrates is mortal" is valid. The syllogism "all cats are mortal; Socrates is mortal; therefore Socrates is a cat", on the other hand, is invalid.[130]

Classical

Propositional logic

Propositional logic comprises formal systems in which formulae are built from atomic propositions using logical connectives. For instance, propositional logic represents the conjunction of two atomic propositions   and   as the complex formula  . Unlike predicate logic where terms and predicates are the smallest units, propositional logic takes full propositions with truth values as its most basic component.[131] Thus, propositional logics can only represent logical relationships that arise from the way complex propositions are built from simpler ones; it cannot represent inferences that results from the inner structure of a proposition.[132]

First-order logic

 
Gottlob Frege's Begriffschrift introduced the notion of quantifier in a graphical notation, which here represents the judgement that   is true.

First-order logic includes the same propositional connectives as propositional logic but differs from it because it articulates the internal structure of propositions. This happens through devices such as singular terms, which refer to particular objects, predicates, which refer to properties and relations, and quantifiers, which treat notions like "some" and "all".[133][46][56] For example, to express the proposition "this raven is black", one may use the predicate   for the property "black" and the singular term   referring to the raven to form the expression  . To express that some objects are black, the existential quantifier   is combined with the variable   to form the proposition  . First-order logic contains various rules of inference that determine how expressions articulated this way can form valid arguments, for example, that one may infer   from  .[134][135]

 
Gottlob Frege developed the first fully axiomatic system of first-order logic.[136]

The development of first-order logic is usually attributed to Gottlob Frege.[137][138] The analytical generality of first-order logic allowed the formalization of mathematics, drove the investigation of set theory, and allowed the development of Alfred Tarski's approach to model theory. It provides the foundation of modern mathematical logic.[139][140]

Extended

Modal logic

Modal logic is an extension of classical logic. In its original form, sometimes called "alethic modal logic", it introduces two new symbols:   expresses that something is possible while   expresses that something is necessary.[141][142] For example, if the formula   stands for the sentence "Socrates is a banker" then the formula   articulates the sentence "It is possible that Socrates is a banker".[143] In order to include these symbols in the logical formalism, modal logic introduces new rules of inference that govern what role they play in inferences. One rule of inference states that, if something is necessary, then it is also possible. This means that   follows from  . Another principle states that if a proposition is necessary then its negation is impossible and vice versa. This means that   is equivalent to  .[144][145][146]

Other forms of modal logic introduce similar symbols but associate different meanings with them to apply modal logic to other fields. For example, deontic logic concerns the field of ethics and introduces symbols to express the ideas of obligation and permission, i.e. to describe whether an agent has to perform a certain action or is allowed to perform it.[147] The modal operators in temporal modal logic articulate temporal relations. They can be used to express, for example, that something happened at one time or that something is happening all the time.[148] In epistemology, epistemic modal logic is used to represent the ideas of knowing something in contrast to merely believing it to be the case.[149]

Higher order logic

Higher-order logics extend classical logic not by using modal operators but by introducing new forms of quantification.[7][150][151] Quantifiers correspond to terms like "all" or "some". In classical first-order logic, quantifiers are only applied to individuals. The formula " " (some apples are sweet) is an example of the existential quantifier " " applied to the individual variable " ". In higher-order logics, quantification is also allowed over predicates. This increases its expressive power. For example, to express the idea that Mary and John share some qualities, one could use the formula " ". In this case, the existential quantifier is applied to the predicate variable " ".[7][150][152] The added expressive power is especially useful for mathematics since it allows for more succinct formulations of mathematical theories.[7] But it has various drawbacks in regard to its meta-logical properties and ontological implications, which is why first-order logic is still much more widely used.[7][151]

Deviant

Intuitionistic logic is a restricted version of classical logic.[153][119] It uses the same symbols but excludes certain rules of inference. For example, according to the law of double negation elimination, if a sentence is not not true, then it is true. This means that   follows from  . This is a valid rule of inference in classical logic but it is invalid in intuitionistic logic. Another classical principle not part of intuitionistic logic is the law of excluded middle. It states that for every sentence, either it or its negation is true. This means that every proposition of the form   is true.[154][119] These deviations from classical logic are based on the idea that truth is established by verification using a proof. Intuitionistic logic is especially prominent in the field of constructive mathematics, which emphasizes the need to find or construct a specific example in order to prove its existence.[119][155][156]

Multi-valued logics depart from classicality by rejecting the principle of bivalence which requires all propositions to be either true or false. For instance, Jan Łukasiewicz and Stephen Cole Kleene both proposed ternary logics which have a third truth value representing that a statement's truth value is indeterminate.[157][158][159] These logics have seen applications including to presupposition in linguistics. Fuzzy logics are multivalued logics that have an infinite number of "degrees of truth", represented by a real number between 0 and 1.[160]

Paraconsistent logics are logical systems that can deal with contradictions. They are formulated to avoid the principle of explosion: for them, it is not the case that anything follows from a contradiction.[119][161][162] They are often motivated by dialetheism, the view that contradictions are real or that reality itself is contradictory. Graham Priest is an influential contemporary proponent of this position and similar views have been ascribed to Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel.[161][162][163]

Informal

The pragmatic or dialogical approach to informal logic sees arguments as speech acts and not merely as a set of premises together with a conclusion.[86][121][122] As speech acts, they occur in a certain context, like a dialogue, which affects the standards of right and wrong arguments.[33][122] A prominent version by Douglas N. Walton understands a dialogue as a game between two players.[86] The initial position of each player is characterized by the propositions to which they are committed and the conclusion they intend to prove. Dialogues are games of persuasion: each player has the goal of convincing the opponent of their own conclusion.[33] This is achieved by making arguments: arguments are the moves of the game.[33][122] They affect to which propositions the players are committed. A winning move is a successful argument that takes the opponent's commitments as premises and shows how one's own conclusion follows from them. This is usually not possible straight away. For this reason, it is normally necessary to formulate a sequence of arguments as intermediary steps, each of which brings the opponent a little closer to one's intended conclusion. Besides these positive arguments leading one closer to victory, there are also negative arguments preventing the opponent's victory by denying their conclusion.[33] Whether an argument is correct depends on whether it promotes the progress of the dialogue. Fallacies, on the other hand, are violations of the standards of proper argumentative rules.[86][88] These standards also depend on the type of dialogue. For example, the standards governing the scientific discourse differ from the standards in business negotiations.[122]

The epistemic approach to informal logic, on the other hand, focuses on the epistemic role of arguments.[86][121] It is based on the idea that arguments aim to increase our knowledge. They achieve this by linking justified beliefs to beliefs that are not yet justified.[164] Correct arguments succeed at expanding knowledge while fallacies are epistemic failures: they do not justify the belief in their conclusion.[86][121] In this sense, logical normativity consists in epistemic success or rationality.[164] For example, the fallacy of begging the question is a fallacy because it fails to provide independent justification for its conclusion, even though it is deductively valid.[91][164] The Bayesian approach is one example of an epistemic approach.[86] Central to Bayesianism is not just whether the agent believes something but the degree to which they believe it, the so-called credence. Degrees of belief are understood as subjective probabilities in the believed proposition, i.e. as how certain the agent is that the proposition is true.[165][166][167] On this view, reasoning can be interpreted as a process of changing one's credences, often in reaction to new incoming information.[86] Correct reasoning, and the arguments it is based on, follows the laws of probability, for example, the principle of conditionalization. Bad or irrational reasoning, on the other hand, violates these laws.[121][166][168]

Areas of research

Logic is studied in various fields. In many cases, this is done by applying its formal method to specific topics outside its scope, like to ethics or computer science.[3][4] In other cases, logic itself is made the subject of research in another discipline. This can happen in diverse ways, like by investigating the philosophical presuppositions of fundamental logical concepts, by interpreting and analyzing logic through mathematical structures, or by studying and comparing abstract properties of formal logical systems.[3][169][170]

Philosophy of logic and philosophical logic

Philosophy of logic is the philosophical discipline studying the scope and nature of logic.[3][7] It investigates many presuppositions implicit in logic, like how to define its fundamental concepts or the metaphysical assumptions associated with them.[21] It is also concerned with how to classify the different logical systems and considers the ontological commitments they incur.[3] Philosophical logic is one of the areas within the philosophy of logic. It studies the application of logical methods to philosophical problems in fields like metaphysics, ethics, and epistemology.[21][118] This application usually happens in the form of extended or deviant logical systems.[120][22]

Metalogic

Metalogic is the field of inquiry studying the properties of formal logical systems. For example, when a new formal system is developed, metalogicians may investigate it to determine which formulas can be proven in it, whether an algorithm could be developed to find a proof for each formula, whether every provable formula in it is a tautology, and how it compares to other logical systems. A key issue in metalogic concerns the relation between syntax and semantics. The syntactic rules of a formal system determine how to deduce conclusions from premises, i.e. how to formulate proofs. The semantics of a formal system governs which sentences are true and which ones are false. This determines the validity of arguments since, for valid arguments, it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. The relation between syntax and semantics concerns issues like whether every valid argument is provable and whether every provable argument is valid. Other metalogical properties investigated include completeness, soundness, consistency, decidability, and expressive power. Metalogicians usually rely heavily on abstract mathematical reasoning when investigating and formulating metalogical proofs in order to arrive at precise and general conclusions on these topics.[171][172][173]

Mathematical logic

 
Bertrand Russell made various significant contributions to mathematical logic.[174]

Mathematical logic is the study of logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and computability theory.[175][176] Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal systems of logic. However, it can also include attempts to use logic to analyze mathematical reasoning or to establish logic-based foundations of mathematics.[177] The latter was a major concern in early 20th century mathematical logic, which pursued the program of logicism pioneered by philosopher-logicians such as Gottlob Frege, Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell. Mathematical theories were supposed to be logical tautologies, and the programme was to show this by means of a reduction of mathematics to logic. The various attempts to carry this out met with failure, from the crippling of Frege's project in his Grundgesetze by Russell's paradox, to the defeat of Hilbert's program by Gödel's incompleteness theorems.[178][179][180]

Set theory originated in the study of the infinite by Georg Cantor, and it has been the source of many of the most challenging and important issues in mathematical logic. They include Cantor's theorem, the status of the Axiom of Choice, the question of the independence of the continuum hypothesis, and the modern debate on large cardinal axioms.[181][182]

Computability theory is the branch of mathematical logic that investigates effective procedures to solve calculation problems. An example is the problem of finding a mechanical procedure that can decide for any positive integer whether it is a prime number. One of its main goals is to understand whether it is possible to solve a given problem using an algorithm. Computability theory uses various theoretical tools and models, such as Turing machines, to explore this issue.[183][184]

Computational logic

 
Conjunction (AND) is one of the basic operations of boolean logic. It can be electronically implemented in several ways, for example, by using two transistors.

Computational logic is the branch of logic and computer science that studies how to implement mathematical reasoning and logical formalisms using computers. This includes, for example, automatic theorem provers, which employ rules of inference to construct a proof step by step from a set of premises to the intended conclusion without human intervention.[185][186][187] Logic programming languages are designed specifically to express facts using logical formulas and to draw inferences from these facts. For example, Prolog is a logic programming language based on predicate logic.[188][189] Computer scientists also apply concepts from logic to problems in computing. The works of Claude Shannon were influential in this regard. He showed how Boolean logic can be used to understand and implement computer circuits.[190][191] This can be achieved using electronic logic gates, i.e. electronic circuits with one or more inputs and usually one output. The truth values of propositions are represented by different voltage levels. This way, logic functions can be simulated by applying the corresponding voltages to the inputs of the circuit and determining the value of the function by measuring the voltage of the output.[192]

Formal semantics of natural language

Formal semantics is a subfield of logic, linguistics, and the philosophy of language. The discipline of semantics studies the meaning of language. Formal semantics uses formal tools from the fields of symbolic logic and mathematics to give precise theories of the meaning of natural language expressions. It understands meaning usually in relation to truth conditions, i.e. it investigates in which situations a sentence would be true or false. One of its central methodological assumptions is the principle of compositionality, which states that the meaning of a complex expression is determined by the meanings of its parts and how they are combined. For example, the meaning of the verb phrase "walk and sing" depends on the meanings of the individual expressions "walk" and "sing". Many theories in formal semantics rely on model theory. This means that they employ set theory to construct a model and then interpret the meanings of expression in relation to the elements in this model. For example, the term "walk" may be interpreted as the set of all individuals in the model that share the property of walking. Early influential theorists in this field were Richard Montague and Barbara Partee, who focused their analysis on the English language.[193]

Epistemology of logic

The epistemology of logic investigates how one knows that an argument is valid or that a proposition is logically true.[194][195] This includes questions like how to justify that modus ponens is a valid rule of inference or that contradictions are false.[194] The traditionally dominant view is that this form of logical understanding belongs to knowledge a priori.[195] In this regard, it is often argued that the mind has a special faculty to examine relations between pure ideas and that this faculty is also responsible for apprehending logical truths.[196] A similar approach understands the rules of logic in terms of linguistic conventions. On this view, the laws of logic are trivial since they are true by definition: they just express the meanings of the logical vocabulary.[194][196][197]

Some theorists, like Hilary Putnam and Penelope Maddy, have objected to the view that logic is knowable a priori and hold instead that logical truths depend on the empirical world. This is usually combined with the claim that the laws of logic express universal regularities found in the structural features of the world and that they can be explored by studying general patterns of the fundamental sciences. For example, it has been argued that certain insights of quantum mechanics refute the principle of distributivity in classical logic, which states that the formula   is equivalent to  . This claim can be used as an empirical argument for the thesis that quantum logic is the correct logical system and should replace classical logic.[198][199][200]

History

 
 
 
 
Top row: Aristotle, who established the canon of western philosophy;[112] and Avicenna, who replaced Aristotelian logic in Islamic discourse.[201] Bottom row: William of Ockham, a major figure of medieval scholarly thought;[202] and the Principia Mathematica, which had a large impact on modern logic.

Logic was developed independently in several cultures during antiquity. One major early contributor was Aristotle, who developed term logic in his Organon and Prior Analytics.[203][204][205] Aristotle's system of logic was responsible for the introduction of hypothetical syllogism,[206] temporal modal logic,[207][208] and inductive logic,[209] as well as influential vocabulary such as terms, predicables, syllogisms and propositions. Aristotelian logic was highly regarded in classical and medieval times, both in Europe and the Middle East. It remained in wide use in the West until the early 19th century.[210][112] It has now been superseded by later work, though many of its key insights are still present in modern systems of logic.[211][212]

Ibn Sina (Avicenna) was the founder of Avicennian logic, which replaced Aristotelian logic as the dominant system of logic in the Islamic world.[213][201] It also had a significant influence on Western medieval writers such as Albertus Magnus and William of Ockham.[214][215] Ibn Sina wrote on the hypothetical syllogism[216] and on the propositional calculus.[217] He developed an original "temporally modalized" syllogistic theory, involving temporal logic and modal logic.[218] He also made use of inductive logic, such as his methods of agreement, difference, and concomitant variation, which are critical to the scientific method.[216] Fakhr al-Din al-Razi was another influential Muslim logician. He criticised Aristotlian syllogistics and formulated an early system of inductive logic, foreshadowing the system of inductive logic developed by John Stuart Mill.[219]

During the Middle Ages, many translations and interpretations of Aristotelian logic were made. Of particular influence were the works of Boethius. Besides translating Aristotle's work into Latin, he also produced various text-books on logic.[220][221] Later, the work of Islamic philosophers such as Ibn Sina and Ibn Rushd (Averroes) were drawn on. This expanded the range of ancient works available to medieval Christian scholars since more Greek work was available to Muslim scholars that had been preserved in Latin commentaries. In 1323, William of Ockham's influential Summa Logicae was released. It is a comprehensive treatise on logic that discusses many fundamental concepts of logic and provides a systematic exposition of different types of propositions and their truth conditions.[221][213][222]

In Chinese philosophy, the School of Names and Mohism were particularly influential. The School of Names focused on the use of language and on paradoxes. For example, Gongsun Long proposed the white horse paradox, which defends the thesis that a white horse is not a horse. The school of Mohism also acknowledged the importance of language for logic and tried to relate the ideas in these fields to the realm of ethics.[223][224]

In India, the study of logic was primarily pursued by the schools of Nyaya, Buddhism, and Jainism. It was not treated as a separate academic discipline and discussions of its topics usually happened in the context of epistemology and theories of dialogue or argumentation.[225] In Nyaya, inference is understood as a source of knowledge (pramāṇa). It follows the perception of an object and tries to arrive at certain conclusions, for example, about the cause of this object.[226] A similar emphasis on the relation to epistemology is also found in Buddhist and Jainist schools of logic, where inference is used to expand the knowledge gained through other sources.[227][228] Some of the later theories of Nyaya, belonging to the Navya-Nyāya school, resemble modern forms of logic, such as Gottlob Frege's distinction between sense and reference and his definition of number.[229]

The syllogistic logic developed by Aristotle predominated in the West until the mid-19th century, when interest in the foundations of mathematics stimulated the development of modern symbolic logic.[112][230] It is often argued that Gottlob Frege’s Begriffsschrift gave birth to modern logic. Other pioneers of the field were Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who conceived the idea of a universal formal language, George Boole, who invented Boolean algebra as a mathematical system of logic, and Charles Peirce, who developed the logic of relatives, as well as Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell, who condensed many of these insights in their work Principia Mathematica. Modern logic introduced various new notions, such as the concepts of functions, quantifiers, and relational predicates. A hallmark of modern symbolic logic is its use of formal language to codify its insights in a very precise manner. This contrasts with the approach of earlier logicians, who relied mainly on natural language.[231] Of particular influence was the development of first-order logic, which is usually treated as the standard system of modern logic.[232]

See also

References

Notes

  1. ^ However, there are some forms of logic, like imperative logic, where this may not be the case.[47]

Citations

  1. ^ Pépin, Jean (2004). "Logos". Encyclopedia of Religion. ISBN 978-0-02-865733-2. from the original on 29 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  2. ^ "logic". etymonline.com. from the original on 29 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Hintikka, Jaakko J. "Philosophy of logic". Encyclopedia Britannica. from the original on 28 April 2015. Retrieved 21 November 2021.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Haack, Susan (1978). "1. 'Philosophy of logics'". Philosophy of Logics. London and New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–10. ISBN 978-0-521-29329-7. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  5. ^ Schlesinger, I. M.; Keren-Portnoy, Tamar; Parush, Tamar (1 January 2001). The Structure of Arguments. John Benjamins Publishing. p. 220. ISBN 978-90-272-2359-3.
  6. ^ a b c d Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 13.
  7. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o Audi, Robert (1999). "Philosophy of logic". The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-64379-6. from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  8. ^ a b c d e McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 12 November 2021. Retrieved 20 November 2021.
  9. ^ a b c MacFarlane, John (2017). "Logical Constants: 4. Topic neutrality". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 17 March 2020. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  10. ^ a b c Corkum, Philip (2015). "Generality and Logical Constancy". Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia. 71 (4): 753–767. doi:10.17990/rpf/2015_71_4_0753. ISSN 0870-5283. JSTOR 43744657.
  11. ^ a b c Blair, J. Anthony; Johnson, Ralph H. (2000). "Informal Logic: An Overview". Informal Logic. 20 (2): 93–107. doi:10.22329/il.v20i2.2262. from the original on 9 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  12. ^ Hofweber 2021.
  13. ^ Gómez-Torrente, Mario (2022). "Alfred Tarski: 3. Logical consequence". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 25 September 2022.
  14. ^ McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence, Model-Theoretic Conceptions". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 25 September 2022.
  15. ^ a b Magnus, P. D. (2005). "1.4 Deductive validity". Forall X: An Introduction to Formal Logic. Victoria, BC, Canada: State University of New York Oer Services. pp. 8–9. ISBN 978-1-64176-026-3. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  16. ^ Mattingly, James (28 October 2022). The SAGE Encyclopedia of Theory in Science, Technology, Engineering, and Mathematics. SAGE Publications. p. 512. ISBN 978-1-5063-5328-9.
  17. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Craig, Edward (1996). "Formal and informal logic". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-07310-3. from the original on 16 January 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  18. ^ a b c d e Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 16.
  19. ^ a b c Gómez-Torrente, Mario (2019). "Logical Truth". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 2 October 2021. Retrieved 22 November 2021.
  20. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 16-7.
  21. ^ a b c d e f g h Jacquette, Dale (2006). "Introduction: Philosophy of logic today". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 1–12. ISBN 978-0-444-51541-4. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  22. ^ a b c Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 31-2.
  23. ^ Haack, Susan (15 December 1996). Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism. University of Chicago Press. pp. 229–30. ISBN 978-0-226-31133-3.
  24. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Groarke, Leo (2021). "Informal Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 12 January 2022. Retrieved 31 December 2021.
  25. ^ a b Audi, Robert (1999). "Informal logic". The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-64379-6. from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  26. ^ a b c d e f g h i Johnson, Ralph H. (1999). "The Relation Between Formal and Informal Logic". Argumentation. 13 (3): 265–274. doi:10.1023/A:1007789101256. S2CID 141283158. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  27. ^ van Eemeren, Frans H.; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2021). "Informal Logic". Handbook of Argumentation Theory. Springer Netherlands. pp. 1–45. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-6883-3_7-1. ISBN 978-94-007-6883-3. from the original on 31 December 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  28. ^ a b c Honderich, Ted (2005). "logic, informal". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. from the original on 29 January 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  29. ^ a b Craig, Edward (1996). "Formal languages and systems". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-07310-3. from the original on 16 January 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  30. ^ Simpson, R. L. (17 March 2008). Essentials of Symbolic Logic - Third Edition. Broadview Press. p. 14. ISBN 978-1-77048-495-5.
  31. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 22-3.
  32. ^ Eemeren, Frans H. van; Grootendorst, Rob; Johnson, Ralph H.; Plantin, Christian; Willard, Charles A. (5 November 2013). Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory: A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and Contemporary Developments. Routledge. p. 169. ISBN 978-1-136-68804-1.
  33. ^ a b c d e f g h Walton, Douglas N. (1987). "1. A new model of argument". Informal Fallacies: Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms. John Benjamins. pp. 1–32. ISBN 978-1-55619-010-0. from the original on 2 March 2022. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  34. ^ a b Engel, S. Morris (1982). "2. The medium of language". With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies. pp. 59–92. ISBN 978-0-312-08479-0. from the original on 1 March 2022. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  35. ^ a b Blair, J. Anthony; Johnson, Ralph H. (1987). "The Current State of Informal Logic". Informal Logic. 9 (2): 147–51. doi:10.22329/il.v9i2.2671. from the original on 30 December 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  36. ^ a b Weddle, Perry (26 July 2011). "36. Informal logic and the eductive-inductive distinction". Argumentation 3. De Gruyter Mouton. pp. 383–8. doi:10.1515/9783110867718.383. ISBN 978-3-11-086771-8. from the original on 31 December 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  37. ^ a b Blair, J. Anthony (20 October 2011). Groundwork in the Theory of Argumentation: Selected Papers of J. Anthony Blair. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 47. ISBN 978-94-007-2363-4.
  38. ^ a b c Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 14.
  39. ^ a b D'Agostino, Marcello; Floridi, Luciano (2009). "The Enduring Scandal of Deduction: Is Propositional Logic Really Uninformative?". Synthese. 167 (2): 271–315. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9409-4. hdl:2299/2995. ISSN 0039-7857. JSTOR 40271192. S2CID 9602882.
  40. ^ a b c d e f Backmann, Marius (1 June 2019). "Varieties of Justification—How (Not) to Solve the Problem of Induction". Acta Analytica. 34 (2): 235–255. doi:10.1007/s12136-018-0371-6. ISSN 1874-6349. S2CID 125767384.
  41. ^ a b c "Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  42. ^ a b Vleet, Van Jacob E. (2010). "Introduction". Informal Logical Fallacies: A Brief Guide. Upa. pp. ix–x. ISBN 978-0-7618-5432-6. from the original on 28 February 2022. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  43. ^ a b c d e Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 29 April 2010. Retrieved 19 March 2021.
  44. ^ a b c d e Stump, David J. "Fallacy, Logical". encyclopedia.com. from the original on 15 February 2021. Retrieved 20 March 2021.
  45. ^ Maltby, John; Day, Liz; Macaskill, Ann (2007). Personality, Individual Differences and Intelligence. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-129760-9.
  46. ^ a b c d e f g h Honderich, Ted (2005). "philosophical logic". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. from the original on 29 January 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  47. ^ Haack, Susan (1974). Deviant Logic: Some Philosophical Issues. CUP Archive. p. 51. ISBN 978-0-521-20500-9.
  48. ^ Falguera, José L.; Martínez-Vidal, Concha; Rosen, Gideon (2021). "Abstract Objects". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 22 January 2021. Retrieved 7 January 2022.
  49. ^ Tondl, L. (6 December 2012). Problems of Semantics: A Contribution to the Analysis of the Language Science. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 111. ISBN 978-94-009-8364-9.
  50. ^ Pietroski, Paul (2021). "Logical Form: 1. Patterns of Reason". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 2 October 2021. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  51. ^ Kusch, Martin (2020). "Psychologism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 29 December 2020. Retrieved 30 November 2021.
  52. ^ Rush, Penelope (2014). "Introduction". The Metaphysics of Logic. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–10. ISBN 978-1-107-03964-3. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  53. ^ a b King, Jeffrey C. (2019). "Structured Propositions". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 25 October 2021. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  54. ^ a b c Pickel, Bryan (1 July 2020). "Structured propositions and trivial composition". Synthese. 197 (7): 2991–3006. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-1853-1. ISSN 1573-0964. S2CID 49729020.
  55. ^ Craig, Edward (1996). "Philosophy of logic". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-07310-3. from the original on 16 January 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  56. ^ a b c Michaelson, Eliot; Reimer, Marga (2019). "Reference". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  57. ^ a b MacFarlane, John (2017). "Logical Constants". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 17 March 2020. Retrieved 21 November 2021.
  58. ^ Jago, Mark (24 April 2014). The Impossible: An Essay on Hyperintensionality. OUP Oxford. p. 41. ISBN 978-0-19-101915-9.
  59. ^ Magnus, P. D. (2005). "3. Truth tables". Forall X: An Introduction to Formal Logic. Victoria, BC, Canada: State University of New York Oer Services. pp. 35–45. ISBN 978-1-64176-026-3. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  60. ^ Angell, Richard B. (1964). Reasoning and Logic. Ardent Media. p. 164. ISBN 978-0-89197-375-1.
  61. ^ Tarski, Alfred (6 January 1994). Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences. Oxford University Press. p. 40. ISBN 978-0-19-802139-1.
  62. ^ Blackburn, Simon (1 January 2008). "argument". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954143-0. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  63. ^ Stairs, Allen (29 September 2017). A Thinker's Guide to the Philosophy of Religion. Routledge. p. 343. ISBN 978-1-351-21981-5.
  64. ^ Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl; Rodych, Victor (3 September 2018). Introduction to Logic. Routledge. p. 30. ISBN 978-1-351-38697-5.
  65. ^ a b c d Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 20.
  66. ^ a b c d IEP Staff. "Deductive and Inductive Arguments". from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 6 January 2022.
  67. ^ Eemeren, Frans H. van; Garssen, Bart (11 February 2009). Pondering on Problems of Argumentation: Twenty Essays on Theoretical Issues. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 191. ISBN 978-1-4020-9165-0.
  68. ^ Evans, Jonathan St. B. T. (18 April 2005). "8. Deductive Reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. p. 169. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0.
  69. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 13-4.
  70. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 13-14.
  71. ^ a b Blackburn, Simon (24 March 2016). "rule of inference". A Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-873530-4. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  72. ^ Dick, Anthony S.; Müller, Ulrich (6 July 2017). Advancing Developmental Science: Philosophy, Theory, and Method. Taylor & Francis. p. 157. ISBN 978-1-351-70456-4.
  73. ^ a b c d e f g h i Douven, Igor (2021). "Abduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 7 September 2021. Retrieved 24 August 2021.
  74. ^ Sagüillo, José M. (2014). "Hintikka on Information and Deduction". Teorema: Revista Internacional de Filosofía. 33 (2): 75–88. ISSN 0210-1602. JSTOR 43047609.
  75. ^ Hintikka, Jaakko (1970). "Information, Deduction, and the A Priori". Noûs. 4 (2): 135–152. doi:10.2307/2214318. ISSN 0029-4624. JSTOR 2214318.
  76. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 14-6.
  77. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 13, 16.
  78. ^ a b Hawthorne, James (2021). "Inductive Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 21 January 2022. Retrieved 6 January 2022.
  79. ^ Wilbanks, Jan J. (1 March 2010). "Defining Deduction, Induction, and Validity". Argumentation. 24 (1): 107–124. doi:10.1007/s10503-009-9131-5. ISSN 1572-8374. S2CID 144481717. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  80. ^ Possin, Kevin (2016). "Conductive Arguments: Why is This Still a Thing?". Informal Logic. 36 (4): 563–593. doi:10.22329/il.v36i4.4527. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  81. ^ Scott, John; Marshall, Gordon (2009). "analytic induction". A Dictionary of Sociology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953300-8. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  82. ^ HOUDE, R.; CAMACHO, L. (2003). "Induction". New Catholic Encyclopedia. ISBN 978-0-7876-4004-0. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  83. ^ a b Borchert, Donald (2006). "Induction". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. from the original on 12 January 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  84. ^ a b Koslowski, Barbara (2017). "Abductive reasoning and explanation". The Routledge International Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315725697. ISBN 978-1-315-72569-7. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  85. ^ a b Cummings, Louise (5 April 2010). "Abduction". The Routledge Pragmatics Encyclopedia. Routledge. p. 1. ISBN 978-1-135-21457-9. from the original on 8 January 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  86. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 29 March 2021. Retrieved 18 March 2021.
  87. ^ Chatfield, Tom (23 October 2017). Critical Thinking: Your Guide to Effective Argument, Successful Analysis and Independent Study. SAGE. p. 194. ISBN 978-1-5264-1877-7.
  88. ^ a b Walton, Douglas N. (1987). "3. Logic of propositions". Informal Fallacies: Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms. John Benjamins. pp. 63–96. ISBN 978-1-55619-010-0. from the original on 2 March 2022. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  89. ^ Sternberg, Robert J. "Thought". Encyclopædia Britannica. from the original on 13 October 2021. Retrieved 14 October 2021.
  90. ^ Stone, Mark A. (2012). "Denying the Antecedent: Its Effective Use in Argumentation". Informal Logic. 32 (3): 327–356. doi:10.22329/il.v32i3.3681. from the original on 28 February 2022. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  91. ^ a b c Mackie, J. L. (1967). "Fallacies". encyclopedia.com. from the original on 15 April 2021. Retrieved 19 March 2021.
  92. ^ Engel, S. Morris (1982). "4. Fallacies of presumption". With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies. pp. 143–212. ISBN 978-0-312-08479-0. from the original on 1 March 2022. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  93. ^ Pedemonte, Bettina (25 June 2018). "Strategic vs Definitory Rules: Their Role in Abductive Argumentation and their Relationship with Deductive Proof". Eurasia Journal of Mathematics, Science and Technology Education. 14 (9): em1589. doi:10.29333/ejmste/92562. ISSN 1305-8215. S2CID 126245285. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 8 January 2022.
  94. ^ Hintikka, Jaakko J. "Logical systems". Encyclopædia Britannica. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  95. ^ Boris, Kulik; Alexander, Fridman (30 November 2017). N-ary Relations for Logical Analysis of Data and Knowledge. IGI Global. p. 74. ISBN 978-1-5225-2783-1.
  96. ^ Cook, Roy T. (20 March 2009). Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh University Press. p. 124. ISBN 978-0-7486-3197-1.
  97. ^ Gensler, Harry J. (12 February 2010). The A to Z of Logic. Scarecrow Press. p. 43. ISBN 978-1-4617-3182-5.
  98. ^ Font, Josep Maria; Jansana, Ramon (2 March 2017). A General Algebraic Semantics for Sentential Logics. Cambridge University Press. p. 8. ISBN 978-1-107-16797-1.
  99. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 21, 28.
  100. ^ Moore, Terence; Carling, Christine (28 October 1982). Understanding Language: Towards a Post-Chomskyan Linguistics. Springer. p. 53. ISBN 978-1-349-16895-8.
  101. ^ Enderton, Herbert (2001). "Sentential Logic". A mathematical introduction to logic. Elsevier. pp. 12, 13. ISBN 978-0-12-238452-3.
  102. ^ Lepore, Ernest; Cumming, Sam (14 September 2012). Meaning and Argument: An Introduction to Logic Through Language. John Wiley & Sons. p. 5. ISBN 978-1-118-45521-0.
  103. ^ Wasilewska, Anita (3 November 2018). Logics for Computer Science: Classical and Non-Classical. Springer. pp. 145–6. ISBN 978-3-319-92591-2.
  104. ^ Rathjen, Michael; Sieg, Wilfried (2022). "Proof Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 4 March 2023.
  105. ^ Sider, Theodore (2010). Logic for Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 34–42. ISBN 978-0-19-957558-9.
  106. ^ Shapiro, Stewart; Kouri Kissel, Teresa (2021). "Classical Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 3 May 1998. Retrieved 21 August 2021.
  107. ^ Bimbo, Katalin (2 April 2016). J. Michael Dunn on Information Based Logics. Springer. pp. 8–9. ISBN 978-3-319-29300-4.
  108. ^ Restall, Greg; Standefer, Shawn (3 January 2023). Logical Methods. MIT Press. p. 91. ISBN 978-0-262-54484-9.
  109. ^ Enderton, Herbert (2001). A mathematical introduction to logic. Elsevier. Chapter 2.5. ISBN 978-0-12-238452-3.
  110. ^ van Dalen, Dirk (1994). Logic and Structure. Springer. Chapter 1.5. ISBN 0-387-57839-0.
  111. ^ a b c d e f g h Smith, Robin (2020). "Aristotle's Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 26 December 2021. Retrieved 1 January 2022.
  112. ^ a b c d e f g h i Groarke, Louis F. "Aristotle: Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 29 December 2021. Retrieved 1 January 2022.
  113. ^ a b c Haack, Susan (1996). "1. 'Alternative' in 'Alternative Logic'". Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-31133-3. from the original on 8 December 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  114. ^ a b Wolf, Robert G. (1978). "Are Relevant Logics Deviant?". Philosophia. 7 (2): 327–340. doi:10.1007/BF02378819. S2CID 143697796. from the original on 16 December 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  115. ^ Hintikka & Sandu 2006, p. 27-8.
  116. ^ Bäck, Allan T. (21 June 2016). Aristotle's Theory of Predication. Brill. p. 317. ISBN 978-90-04-32109-0.
  117. ^ Shapiro, Stewart; Kouri Kissel, Teresa (2021). "Classical Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 3 May 1998. Retrieved 4 December 2021.
  118. ^ a b Burgess, John P. (2009). "1. Classical logic". Philosophical Logic. Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-15633-0. from the original on 16 December 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  119. ^ a b c d e Borchert, Donald (2006). "Logic, Non-Classical". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. from the original on 12 January 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  120. ^ a b Goble, Lou (2001). "Introduction". The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-20692-7. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  121. ^ a b c d e Korb, Kevin (2004). "Bayesian Informal Logic and Fallacy". Informal Logic. 24 (1): 41–70. doi:10.22329/il.v24i1.2132. from the original on 10 November 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  122. ^ a b c d e Ritola, Juho (1 December 2008). "Walton's Informal Logic: A Pragmatic Approach". Informal Logic. 28 (4): 335. doi:10.22329/il.v28i4.2856.
  123. ^ a b Bobzien, Susanne (2020). "Ancient Logic: 2. Aristotle". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 28 August 2018. Retrieved 3 January 2022.
  124. ^ Magnus, P. D. (2005). "2.2 Connectives". Forall X: An Introduction to Formal Logic. Victoria, BC, Canada: State University of New York Oer Services. ISBN 978-1-64176-026-3. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  125. ^ Hintikka, Jaakko J.; Spade, Paul Vincent. "history of logic – Aristotle". Encyclopædia Britannica. from the original on 4 January 2022. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  126. ^ Goertzel, Ben; Geisweiller, Nil; Coelho, Lucio; Janičić, Predrag; Pennachin, Cassio (2 December 2011). Real-World Reasoning: Toward Scalable, Uncertain Spatiotemporal, Contextual and Causal Inference. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 43–4. ISBN 978-94-91216-11-4.
  127. ^ Westerståhl, Dag (1989). "Aristotelian Syllogisms and Generalized Quantifiers". Studia Logica. 48 (4): 577–585. doi:10.1007/BF00370209. S2CID 32089424. from the original on 4 January 2022. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  128. ^ a b c Hurley, Patrick J. (2015). "4. Categorical Syllogisms". Logic: The Essentials. Wadsworth. ISBN 978-1-305-59041-0. from the original on 4 January 2022. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  129. ^ a b Copi, Irving Marmer; Cohen, Carl; McMahon, Kenneth (1953). "6. Categorical Syllogisms". Introduction to Logic. New York, NY, USA: Macmillan. ISBN 978-1-138-50086-0. from the original on 4 January 2022. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  130. ^ Spriggs, John (5 January 2012). GSN - The Goal Structuring Notation: A Structured Approach to Presenting Arguments. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 20-2. ISBN 978-1-4471-2312-5.
  131. ^ Brody, Boruch A. (2006). Encyclopedia of philosophy. Vol. 5. Donald M. Borchert (2nd ed.). Detroit: Thomson Gale/Macmillan Reference USA. pp. 535–536. ISBN 0-02-865780-2. OCLC 61151356. The two most important types of logical calculi are propositional (or sentential) calculi and functional (or predicate) calculi. A propositional calculus is a system containing propositional variables and connectives (some also contain propositional constants) but not individual or functional variables or constants. In the extended propositional calculus, quantifiers whose operator variables are propositional variables are added.
  132. ^ Klement, Kevin C. "Propositional Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  133. ^ Shapiro, Stewart; Kouri Kissel, Teresa (2022). "Classical Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 13 March 2023.
  134. ^ Nolt, John (2021). "Free Logic: 1. The Basics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 10 September 2022.
  135. ^ Magnus, P. D. (2005). "4 Quantified logic". Forall X: An Introduction to Formal Logic. Victoria, BC, Canada: State University of New York Oer Services. ISBN 978-1-64176-026-3. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  136. ^ Klement, Kevin C. "Frege, Gottlob". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 September 2022.
  137. ^ Hintikka, Jaakko J.; Spade, Paul Vincent. "history of logic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 10 September 2022.
  138. ^ Okeke, Johnathan Chimakonam. Proof in Alonzo Church's and Alan Turing's Mathematical Logic: Undecidability of First Order Logic. Universal-Publishers. p. 122. ISBN 978-1-61233-951-1.
  139. ^ Ewald, William (2019). "The Emergence of First-Order Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 10 September 2022.
  140. ^ Schreiner, Wolfgang (22 October 2021). Thinking Programs: Logical Modeling and Reasoning About Languages, Data, Computations, and Executions. Springer Nature. p. 22. ISBN 978-3-030-80507-4.
  141. ^ Garson, James (2023). "Modal Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: 1. What is Modal Logic?. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  142. ^ Sadegh-Zadeh, Kazem (6 April 2015). Handbook of Analytic Philosophy of Medicine. Springer. p. 983. ISBN 978-94-017-9579-1.
  143. ^ Fitch, G. W. (18 December 2014). Saul Kripke. Routledge. p. 17. ISBN 978-1-317-48917-7.
  144. ^ Garson, James (2023). "Modal Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: 2. Modal Logics. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  145. ^ Carnielli, Walter; Pizzi, Claudio (15 September 2008). Modalities and Multimodalities. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 3. ISBN 978-1-4020-8590-1.
  146. ^ Benthem, Johan van. "Modal Logic: Contemporary View: 1. Modal Notions and Reasoning Patterns: a First Pass". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  147. ^ Garson, James (2023). "Modal Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: 3. Deontic Logics. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  148. ^ Garson, James (2023). "Modal Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: 4. Temporal Logics. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  149. ^ Rendsvig, Rasmus; Symons, John (2021). "Epistemic Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  150. ^ a b Väänänen, Jouko (2021). "Second-order and Higher-order Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 30 October 2021. Retrieved 23 November 2021.
  151. ^ a b Ketland, Jeffrey (2005). "Second Order Logic". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  152. ^ Daintith, John; Wright, Edmund (10 July 2008). "predicate calculus". A Dictionary of Computing. ISBN 978-0-19-923400-4. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  153. ^ Moschovakis, Joan (2022). "Intuitionistic Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Introduction. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  154. ^ Moschovakis, Joan (2022). "Intuitionistic Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: 1. Rejection of Tertium Non Datur. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  155. ^ Bridges, Douglas; Ishihara, Hajime; Rathjen, Michael; Schwichtenberg, Helmut (30 April 2023). Handbook of Constructive Mathematics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 73–4. ISBN 978-1-316-51086-5.
  156. ^ Friend, Michele (5 December 2014). Introducing Philosophy of Mathematics. Routledge. p. 101. ISBN 978-1-317-49379-2.
  157. ^ Sider, Theodore (2010). Logic for Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Chapter 3.4. ISBN 978-0-19-957558-9.
  158. ^ Gamut, L.T.F. (1991). Logic, Language and Meaning Vol 1: Introduction to Logic. University of Chicago Press. 5.5. ISBN 978-0-226-28085-1.
  159. ^ Zegarelli, Mark (2010), Logic For Dummies, John Wiley & Sons, p. 30, ISBN 978-1-118-05307-2, from the original on 14 May 2015, retrieved 7 March 2015
  160. ^ Hájek, Petr (2006). "Fuzzy Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 11 July 2010. Retrieved 16 May 2009.
  161. ^ a b Priest, Graham; Tanaka, Koji; Weber, Zach (2018). "Paraconsistent Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 December 2021.
  162. ^ a b Weber, Zach. "Paraconsistent Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 12 December 2021.
  163. ^ Haack, Susan (1996). "Introduction". Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-31133-3.
  164. ^ a b c Siegel, Harvey; Biro, John (1997). "Epistemic Normativity, Argumentation, and Fallacies". Argumentation. 11 (3): 277–292. doi:10.1023/A:1007799325361. S2CID 126269789. from the original on 28 February 2022. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  165. ^ Olsson, Erik J. (2018). "Bayesian Epistemology". Introduction to Formal Philosophy. Springer. pp. 431–442. ISBN 978-3-030-08454-7. from the original on 16 May 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  166. ^ a b Hájek, Alan; Lin, Hanti (2017). "A Tale of Two Epistemologies?". Res Philosophica. 94 (2): 207–232. doi:10.11612/resphil.1540. S2CID 160029122. from the original on 4 January 2022. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  167. ^ Hartmann, Stephan; Sprenger, Jan (2010). "Bayesian Epistemology". The Routledge Companion to Epistemology. London: Routledge. pp. 609–620. ISBN 978-0-415-96219-3. from the original on 16 May 2021. Retrieved 4 January 2022.
  168. ^ Talbott, William (2016). "Bayesian Epistemology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 1 April 2021. Retrieved 6 March 2021.
  169. ^ Gödel, Kurt (1984). "Russell's mathematical logic". Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings (2 ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 447–469. ISBN 978-0-521-29648-9. from the original on 11 January 2022. Retrieved 9 January 2022.
  170. ^ Monk, J. Donald (1976). "Introduction". Mathematical Logic. Springer. pp. 1–9. doi:10.1007/978-1-4684-9452-5_1. ISBN 978-1-4684-9452-5. from the original on 9 January 2022. Retrieved 9 January 2022.
  171. ^ Gensler, Harry J. (2006). The A to Z of Logic. Scarecrow Press. pp. xliii–xliv. ISBN 9781461731825.
  172. ^ Sider, Theodore (2010). Logic for Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 4–6. ISBN 978-0-19-957558-9.
  173. ^ Schagrin, Morton L. "metalogic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  174. ^ Irvine, Andrew David (2022). "Bertrand Russell". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 September 2022.
  175. ^ Li, Wei (26 February 2010). Mathematical Logic: Foundations for Information Science. Springer Science & Business Media. p. ix. ISBN 978-3-7643-9977-1.
  176. ^ Rautenberg, Wolfgang (1 July 2010). A Concise Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Springer. p. 15. ISBN 978-1-4419-1221-3.
  177. ^ Stolyar, Abram Aronovich (1 January 1984). Introduction to Elementary Mathematical Logic. Courier Corporation. pp. 3–6. ISBN 978-0-486-64561-2.
  178. ^ Hintikka, Jaakko J.; Spade, Paul Vincent. "History of logic – Gödel's incompleteness theorems". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  179. ^ Linsky, Bernard (9 June 2011). The Evolution of Principia Mathematica: Bertrand Russell's Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition. Cambridge University Press. p. 4. ISBN 978-1-139-49733-6.
  180. ^ Richardson, Alan W. (1998). Carnap's Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism. Cambridge University Press. p. 15. ISBN 978-0-521-43008-1.
  181. ^ Bagaria, Joan (2021). "Set Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  182. ^ Cunningham, Daniel. "Set Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  183. ^ Borchert, Donald, ed. (2006). "Computability Theory". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 9780028657905.
  184. ^ Leary, Christopher C.; Kristiansen, Lars (2015). A Friendly Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Suny. p. 195. ISBN 978-1-942341-07-9.
  185. ^ Paulson, Lawrence C. (February 2018). "Computational logic: its origins and applications". Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 474 (2210): 1–14. doi:10.1098/rspa.2017.0872. PMID 29507522. S2CID 3805901.
  186. ^ Castaño, Arnaldo Pérez (23 May 2018). Practical Artificial Intelligence: Machine Learning, Bots, and Agent Solutions Using C#. Apress. p. 2. ISBN 978-1-4842-3357-3.
  187. ^ Wile, Bruce; Goss, John; Roesner, Wolfgang (26 May 2005). Comprehensive Functional Verification: The Complete Industry Cycle. Elsevier. p. 447. ISBN 978-0-08-047664-3.
  188. ^ Clocksin, William F.; Mellish, Christopher S. (2003). "The Relation of Prolog to Logic". Programming in Prolog: Using the ISO Standard. Springer. pp. 237–257. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-55481-0_10. ISBN 978-3-642-55481-0.
  189. ^ Daintith, John (2004). "Logic Programming Languages". A Dictionary of Computing. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-860877-6.
  190. ^ O'Regan, Gerard (21 June 2016). Introduction to the History of Computing: A Computing History Primer. Springer. p. 49. ISBN 978-3-319-33138-6.
  191. ^ Calderbank, Robert; Sloane, Neil J. A. (April 2001). "Claude Shannon (1916–2001)". Nature. 410 (6830): 768. doi:10.1038/35071223. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 11298432. S2CID 4402158.
  192. ^ Daintith, John (2004). "Logic Gate". A Dictionary of Computing. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-860877-6.
  193. ^ Janssen, Theo M. V.; Zimmermann, Thomas Ede (2021). "Montague Semantics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. pp. 3–4. Retrieved 10 March 2023.
    Partee, Barbara H. (2016). Aloni, Maria; Dekker, Paul (eds.). The Cambridge handbook of formal semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-02839-5.
    King, Jeffrey C. (2 September 2009). "Formal Semantics". The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language: 557–8. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199552238.003.0023. ISBN 978-0199552238.
    Coppock, Elizabeth; Champollion, Lucas (2019). Invitation to formal semantics (PDF). pp. 3–4. (PDF) from the original on 21 January 2020. Retrieved 25 October 2021.

  194. ^ a b c Warren, Jared (3 August 2020). "6. The Epistemology of Logic". Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-008615-2.
  195. ^ a b Schechter, Joshua. "Epistemology of Logic – Bibliography – PhilPapers". philpapers.org. Retrieved 11 September 2022.
  196. ^ a b Gómez-Torrente, Mario (2019). "Logical Truth". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 September 2022.
  197. ^ Warren, Jared (3 August 2020). "1. What is Conventionalism". Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-008615-2.
  198. ^ Chua, Eugene (2017). "An Empirical Route to Logical 'Conventionalism'". Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. 10455: 631–636. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_43. ISBN 978-3-662-55664-1.
  199. ^ Wilce, Alexander (2021). "Quantum Logic and Probability Theory: 2.1 Realist Quantum Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  200. ^ Putnam, H. (1969). "Is Logic Empirical?". Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 5: 216–241. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-3381-7_5. ISBN 978-94-010-3383-1.
  201. ^ a b Lagerlund, Henrik. "The Aftermath of Syllogism: Aristotelian Logical Argument from Avicenna to Hegel". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved 29 September 2022.
  202. ^ Spade, Paul Vincent; Panaccio, Claude (2019). "William of Ockham: 3. Logic and Semantics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 September 2022.
  203. ^ Kline 1972, p. 53, "A major achievement of Aristotle was the founding of the science of logic".
  204. ^ Łukasiewicz, Jan (1957). Aristotle's syllogistic from the standpoint of modern formal logic (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-19-824144-7.
  205. ^ Liu, Shiyong; Guo, Kaizhong (7 March 2023). Error Logic: Paving Pathways for Intelligent Error Identification and Management. Springer Nature. p. 15. ISBN 978-3-031-00820-7.
  206. ^ Lear, Jonathan (1980). Aristotle and Logical Theory. CUP Archive. p. 34. ISBN 978-0-521-31178-6.
  207. ^ Knuuttila, Simo (30 November 1980). Reforging the Great Chain of Being: Studies of the History of Modal Theories. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 71. ISBN 978-90-277-1125-0.
  208. ^ Fisher, Michael David; Gabbay, Dov M.; Vila, Lluis (1 March 2005). Handbook of Temporal Reasoning in Artificial Intelligence. Elsevier. p. 119. ISBN 978-0-08-053336-0.
  209. ^ Berman, Harold J. (1 July 2009). Law and Revolution, the Formation of the Western Legal Tradition. Harvard University Press. p. 133. ISBN 978-0-674-02085-6.
  210. ^ Frede, Michael. "Aristotle". Michigan Technological University. Michigan Technological University. Retrieved 1 November 2022.
  211. ^ Ewald, William (2019). "The Emergence of First-Order Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  212. ^ Smith, Robin (2022). "Aristotle's Logic: Introduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  213. ^ a b Dag Nikolaus Hasse (19 September 2008). "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 14 July 2010. Retrieved 13 October 2009.
  214. ^ Washell, Richard F. (1973). "Logic, Language, and Albert the Great". Journal of the History of Ideas. 34 (3): 445–50. doi:10.2307/2708963. JSTOR 2708963.
  215. ^ Kneale & Kneale 1962, pp. 229, 266.
  216. ^ a b Goodman, Lenn Evan (2003). Islamic humanism. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 155. ISBN 0-19-513580-6.
  217. ^ Goodman, Lenn Evan (1992). Avicenna. London: Routledge. p. 188. ISBN 0-415-01929-X.
  218. ^ Hintikka, Jaakko J.; Spade, Paul Vincent. . Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 12 October 2007.
  219. ^ Iqbal, Mohammad (22 May 2013). "THE SPIRIT OF MUSLIM CULTURE". The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam. Stanford University Press. pp. 99–115. ISBN 978-0-8047-8686-7.
  220. ^ Marenbon, John (2021). "Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Introduction; 3. The Logical Text-Books: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  221. ^ a b Hintikka, Jaakko J.; Spade, Paul Vincent. "History of logic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 23 September 2022.
  222. ^ Spade, Paul Vincent; Panaccio, Claude (2019). "William of Ockham". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 3.1 The Summa of Logic: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  223. ^ Willman, Marshall D. (2022). "Logic and Language in Early Chinese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Introduction: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 March 2023.
  224. ^ Rošker, Jana S. (May 2015). "Classical Chinese Logic: Philosophy Compass". Philosophy Compass. 10 (5): 301–309. doi:10.1111/phc3.12226.
  225. ^ Sarukkai, Sundar; Chakraborty, Mihir Kumar (9 December 2022). Handbook of Logical Thought in India. Springer Nature. pp. 117–8. ISBN 978-81-322-2577-5.
  226. ^ Dasti, Matthew R. "Nyaya". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. lead section; 1b. Inference. Retrieved 12 March 2023.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: location (link)
  227. ^ Emmanuel, Steven M. (23 November 2015). A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 320–2. ISBN 978-1-119-14466-3.
  228. ^ Vidyabhusana, Satis Chandra (1988). A History of Indian Logic: Ancient, Mediaeval and Modern Schools. Motilal Banarsidass Publisher. p. 221. ISBN 978-81-208-0565-1.
  229. ^ Chakrabarti, Kisor Kumar (June 1976). "Some Comparisons Between Frege's Logic and Navya-Nyaya Logic". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 36 (4): 554–563. doi:10.2307/2106873. JSTOR 2106873.
  230. ^ Haaparanta, Leila (2009). "1. Introduction". The development of modern logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 3–5. ISBN 978-0-19-513731-6.
  231. ^ Haaparanta, Leila (2009). "1. Introduction". The development of modern logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 4–6. ISBN 978-0-19-513731-6.
  232. ^ Ewald, William (2019). "The Emergence of First-Order Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. lead paragraph; 11. Conclusions: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 12 March 2023.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: location (link)

Bibliography

  • Brookshear, J. Glenn (1989). Theory of computation: formal languages, automata, and complexity. Redwood City, Calif.: Benjamin/Cummings Pub. Co. ISBN 978-0-8053-0143-4.
  • Cohen, Robert S.; Wartofsky, Marx W. (6 December 2012). Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary Physics. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-010-2656-7.
  • Gabbay, Dov M.; Guenthner, Franz (14 October 2011). Handbook of Philosophical Logic: Volume I: Elements of Classical Logic. Springer Netherlands. ISBN 978-94-009-7068-7.
  • Haack, Susan (15 December 1996). Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-31133-3.
  • Hintikka, Jaakko; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". In Jacquette, D. (ed.). Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. ISBN 978-0-444-51541-4. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  • Hofweber, Thomas (2021). "Logic and Ontology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  • Kline, Morris (1972). Mathematical Thought From Ancient to Modern Times. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-506135-2.
  • Kneale, William; Kneale, Martha (1962). The Development of Logic. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824773-9.
  • Smith, Barry (1989). "Logic and the Sachverhalt". The Monist. 72 (1): 52–69. doi:10.5840/monist19897212.
  • Whitehead, Alfred North; Russell, Bertrand (1910). Principia Mathematica. Rough Draft Printing. ISBN 978-1-60386-437-4.

Further reading

External links

logic, this, article, about, study, correct, reasoning, other, uses, disambiguation, disambiguation, study, correct, reasoning, includes, both, formal, informal, logic, formal, logic, science, deductively, valid, inferences, logical, truths, formal, science, i. This article is about the study of correct reasoning For other uses see Logic disambiguation and Logician disambiguation Logic is the study of correct reasoning It includes both formal and informal logic Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises in a topic neutral way When used as a countable noun the term a logic refers to a logical formal system that articulates a proof system Formal logic contrasts with informal logic which is associated with informal fallacies critical thinking and argumentation theory While there is no general agreement on how formal and informal logic are to be distinguished one prominent approach associates their difference with whether the studied arguments are expressed in formal or informal languages Logic plays a central role in multiple fields such as philosophy mathematics computer science and linguistics Logic studies valid forms of inference like the modus ponens Logic studies arguments which consist of a set of premises together with a conclusion Premises and conclusions are usually understood either as sentences or as propositions and are characterized by their internal structure complex propositions are made up of simpler propositions linked to each other by propositional connectives like displaystyle land and or displaystyle to if then The truth of a proposition usually depends on the denotations of its constituents Logically true propositions constitute a special case since their truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in them and not on the denotations of other terms Arguments can be either correct or incorrect An argument is correct if its premises support its conclusion The strongest form of support is found in deductive arguments it is impossible for their premises to be true and their conclusion to be false Deductive arguments contrast with ampliative arguments which may arrive in their conclusion at new information that is not present in the premises However it is possible for all their premises to be true while their conclusion is still false Many arguments found in everyday discourse and the sciences are ampliative arguments sometimes divided into inductive and abductive arguments Inductive arguments usually take the form of statistical generalizations while abductive arguments are inferences to the best explanation Arguments that fall short of the standards of correct reasoning are called fallacies Systems of logic are theoretical frameworks for assessing the correctness of reasoning and arguments Logic has been studied since antiquity early approaches include Aristotelian logic Stoic logic Anviksiki and the Mohists Modern formal logic has its roots in the work of late 19th century mathematicians such as Gottlob Frege While Aristotelian logic focuses on reasoning in the form of syllogisms in the modern era its traditional dominance was replaced by classical logic a set of fundamental logical intuitions shared by most logicians It consists of propositional logic which only considers the logical relations on the level of propositions and first order logic which also articulates the internal structure of propositions using various linguistic devices such as predicates and quantifiers Extended logics accept the basic intuitions behind classical logic and extend it to other fields such as metaphysics ethics and epistemology Deviant logics on the other hand reject certain classical intuitions and provide alternative accounts of the fundamental laws of logic Contents 1 Definition 1 1 Formal and informal logic 2 Fundamental concepts 2 1 Premises conclusions and truth 2 1 1 Premises and conclusions 2 1 2 Internal structure 2 1 3 Logical truth 2 1 4 Truth tables 2 2 Arguments and inferences 2 2 1 Deductive 2 2 2 Ampliative 2 3 Fallacies 2 4 Definitory and strategic rules 2 5 Formal systems 3 Systems of logic 3 1 Aristotelian 3 2 Classical 3 2 1 Propositional logic 3 2 2 First order logic 3 3 Extended 3 3 1 Modal logic 3 3 2 Higher order logic 3 4 Deviant 3 5 Informal 4 Areas of research 4 1 Philosophy of logic and philosophical logic 4 2 Metalogic 4 3 Mathematical logic 4 4 Computational logic 4 5 Formal semantics of natural language 5 Epistemology of logic 6 History 7 See also 8 References 8 1 Notes 8 2 Citations 8 3 Bibliography 9 Further reading 10 External linksDefinition EditThe word logic originates from the Greek word logos which has a variety of translations such as reason discourse or language 1 2 Logic is traditionally defined as the study of the laws of thought or correct reasoning 3 and is usually understood in terms of inferences or arguments Reasoning may be seen as the activity of drawing inferences whose outward expression is given in arguments 3 4 5 An inference or an argument is a set of premises together with a conclusion Logic is interested in whether arguments are good or inferences are valid i e whether the premises support their conclusions 6 7 8 These general characterizations apply to logic in the widest sense since they are true both for formal and informal logic but many definitions of logic focus on the more paradigmatic formal logic In this narrower sense logic is a formal science that studies how conclusions follow from premises in a topic neutral way 9 10 11 In this regard logic is sometimes contrasted with the theory of rationality which is wider since it covers all forms of good reasoning 12 Alfred Tarski was an influential defender of the idea that logical truth can be defined in terms of possible interpretations 13 14 As a formal science logic contrasts with both the natural and social sciences in that it tries to characterize the inferential relations between premises and conclusions based on their structure alone 15 16 This means that the actual content of these propositions i e their specific topic is not important for whether the inference is valid or not 9 10 Valid inferences are characterized by the fact that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false 8 17 The general logical structures characterizing valid inferences are called rules of inference 6 In this sense logic is often defined as the study of valid arguments 4 This contrasts with another prominent characterization of logic as the science of logical truths 18 A proposition is logically true if its truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in it This means that it is true in all possible worlds and under all interpretations of its non logical terms 19 These two characterizations of logic are closely related to each other an inference is valid if the material conditional from its premises to its conclusion is logically true 18 The term logic can also be used in a slightly different sense as a countable noun In this sense a logic is a logical formal system Distinct logics differ from each other concerning the rules of inference they accept as valid and concerning the formal languages used to express them 4 20 21 Starting in the late 19th century many new formal systems have been proposed There are various disagreements concerning what makes a formal system a logic 4 21 For example it has been suggested that only logically complete systems qualify as logics For such reasons some theorists deny that higher order logics and fuzzy logic are logics in the strict sense 4 22 23 Formal and informal logic Edit Logic encompasses both formal and informal logic 4 24 Formal logic is the traditionally dominant field 17 but applying its insights to actual everyday arguments has prompted modern developments of informal logic 24 25 26 which considers problems that formal logic on its own is unable to address 17 26 Both provide criteria for assessing the correctness of arguments and distinguishing them from fallacies 11 17 Various suggestions have been made concerning how to draw the distinction between the two but there is no universally accepted answer 26 27 Formal logic needs to translate natural language arguments into a formal language like first order logic in order to assess whether they are valid In this example the colors indicate how the English words correspond to the symbols The most literal approach sees the terms formal and informal as applying to the language used to express arguments 24 25 28 On this view formal logic studies arguments expressed in formal languages while informal logic studies arguments expressed in informal or natural languages 17 26 This means that the inference from the formulas P displaystyle P and Q displaystyle Q to the conclusion P Q displaystyle P land Q is studied by formal logic The inference from the English sentences Al lit a cigarette and Bill stormed out of the room to the sentence Al lit a cigarette and Bill stormed out of the room on the other hand belongs to informal logic Formal languages are characterized by their precision and simplicity 28 17 26 They normally contain a very limited vocabulary and exact rules on how their symbols can be used to construct sentences usually referred to as well formed formulas 29 30 This simplicity and exactness of formal logic make it capable of formulating precise rules of inference that determine whether a given argument is valid 29 This approach brings with it the need to translate natural language arguments into the formal language before their validity can be assessed a procedure that comes with various problems of its own 31 15 26 Informal logic avoids some of these problems by analyzing natural language arguments in their original form without the need of translation 11 24 32 But it faces problems associated with the ambiguity vagueness and context dependence of natural language expressions 17 33 34 A closely related approach applies the terms formal and informal not just to the language used but more generally to the standards criteria and procedures of argumentation 35 Another approach draws the distinction according to the different types of inferences analyzed 24 36 37 This perspective understands formal logic as the study of deductive inferences in contrast to informal logic as the study of non deductive inferences like inductive or abductive inferences 24 37 The characteristic of deductive inferences is that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion This means that if all the premises are true it is impossible for the conclusion to be false 8 17 For this reason deductive inferences are in a sense trivial or uninteresting since they do not provide the thinker with any new information not already found in the premises 38 39 Non deductive inferences on the other hand are ampliative they help the thinker learn something above and beyond what is already stated in the premises They achieve this at the cost of certainty even if all premises are true the conclusion of an ampliative argument may still be false 18 40 41 One more approach tries to link the difference between formal and informal logic to the distinction between formal and informal fallacies 24 26 35 This distinction is often drawn in relation to the form content and context of arguments In the case of formal fallacies the error is found on the level of the argument s form whereas for informal fallacies the content and context of the argument are responsible 42 43 44 Formal logic abstracts away from the argument s content and is only interested in its form specifically whether it follows a valid rule of inference 9 10 In this regard it is not important for the validity of a formal argument whether its premises are true or false Informal logic on the other hand also takes the content and context of an argument into consideration 17 26 28 A false dilemma for example involves an error of content by excluding viable options as in you are either with us or against us you are not with us therefore you are against us 45 43 For the strawman fallacy on the other hand the error is found on the level of context a weak position is first described and then defeated even though the opponent does not hold this position But in another context against an opponent that actually defends the strawman position the argument is correct 33 43 Other accounts draw the distinction based on investigating general forms of arguments in contrast to particular instances or on the study of logical constants instead of substantive concepts A further approach focuses on the discussion of logical topics with or without formal devices or on the role of epistemology for the assessment of arguments 17 26 Fundamental concepts EditPremises conclusions and truth Edit Premises and conclusions Edit Main article Premise Premises and conclusions are the basic parts of inferences or arguments and therefore play a central role in logic In the case of a valid inference or a correct argument the conclusion follows from the premises or in other words the premises support the conclusion 7 46 For instance the premises Mars is red and Mars is a planet support the conclusion Mars is a red planet For most types of logic it is accepted that premises and conclusions have to be truth bearers 7 46 i This means that they have a truth value they are either true or false Thus contemporary philosophy generally sees them either as propositions or as sentences 7 Propositions are the denotations of sentences and are usually understood as abstract objects 48 49 Propositional theories of premises and conclusions are often criticized because of the difficulties involved in specifying the identity criteria of abstract objects or because of naturalist considerations 7 These objections are avoided by seeing premises and conclusions not as propositions but as sentences i e as concrete linguistic objects like the symbols displayed on a page of a book But this approach comes with new problems of its own sentences are often context dependent and ambiguous meaning an argument s validity would not only depend on its parts but also on its context and on how it is interpreted 7 50 Another approach is to understand premises and conclusions in psychological terms as thoughts or judgments This position is known as psychologism and was heavily criticized around the turn of the 20th century 7 51 52 Internal structure Edit Premises and conclusions have internal structure As propositions or sentences they can be either simple or complex 53 54 A complex proposition has other propositions as its constituents which are linked to each other through propositional connectives like and or if then Simple propositions on the other hand do not have propositional parts But they can also be conceived as having an internal structure they are made up of subpropositional parts like singular terms and predicates 46 53 54 For example the simple proposition Mars is red can be formed by applying the predicate red to the singular term Mars In contrast the complex proposition Mars is red and Venus is white is made up of two simple propositions connected by the propositional connective and 46 Whether a proposition is true depends at least in part on its constituents 54 For complex propositions formed using truth functional propositional connectives their truth only depends on the truth values of their parts 46 But this relation is more complicated in the case of simple propositions and their subpropositional parts These subpropositional parts have meanings of their own like referring to objects or classes of objects 46 55 56 Whether the simple proposition they form is true depends on their relation to reality i e what the objects they refer to are like This topic is studied by theories of reference 56 Logical truth Edit Main article Logical truth In some cases a simple or a complex proposition is true independently of the substantive meanings of its parts 3 57 For example the complex proposition if Mars is red then Mars is red is true independent of whether its parts i e the simple proposition Mars is red are true or false In such cases the truth is called a logical truth a proposition is logically true if its truth depends only on the logical vocabulary used in it 19 57 46 This means that it is true under all interpretations of its non logical terms In some modal logics this notion can be understood equivalently as truth at all possible worlds 19 58 Some theorists define logic as the study of logical truths 18 Truth tables Edit Truth tables can be used to show how logical connectives work or how the truth of complex propositions depends on their parts They have a column for each input variable Each row corresponds to one possible combination of the truth values these variables can take The final columns present the truth values of the corresponding expressions as determined by the input values For example the expression p q displaystyle p land q uses the logical connective displaystyle land and It could be used to express a sentence like yesterday was Sunday and the weather was good It is only true if both of its input variables p displaystyle p yesterday was Sunday and q displaystyle q the weather was good are true In all other cases the expression as a whole is false Other important logical connectives are displaystyle lor or displaystyle to if then and displaystyle lnot not 59 60 Truth tables can also be defined for more complex expressions that use several propositional connectives For example given the conditional proposition p q displaystyle p to q one can form truth tables of its inverse p q displaystyle lnot p to lnot q and its contraposition q p displaystyle lnot q to lnot p 61 Truth table of various expression p q p q p q p q p qT T T T T TT F F T F TF T F T T FF F F F T TArguments and inferences Edit Main articles Argument and inference Logic is commonly defined in terms of arguments or inferences as the study of their correctness 3 7 An argument is a set of premises together with a conclusion 62 63 An inference is the process of reasoning from these premises to the conclusion 7 But these terms are often used interchangeably in logic Arguments are correct or incorrect depending on whether their premises support their conclusion Premises and conclusions on the other hand are true or false depending on whether they are in accord with reality In formal logic a sound argument is an argument that is both correct and has only true premises 64 Sometimes a distinction is made between simple and complex arguments A complex argument is made up of a chain of simple arguments These simple arguments constitute a chain because the conclusions of the earlier arguments are used as premises in the later arguments For a complex argument to be successful each link of the chain has to be successful 7 Argument terminology used in logic Arguments and inferences are either are correct or incorrect If they are correct then their premises support their conclusion In the incorrect case this support is missing It can take different forms corresponding to the different types of reasoning 65 40 66 The strongest form of support corresponds to deductive reasoning But even arguments that are not deductively valid may still constitute good arguments because their premises offer non deductive support to their conclusions For such cases the term ampliative or inductive reasoning is used 18 40 66 Deductive arguments are associated with formal logic in contrast to the relation between ampliative arguments and informal logic 24 36 67 Deductive Edit A deductively valid argument is one whose premises guarantee the truth of its conclusion 8 17 For instance the argument 1 all frogs are reptiles 2 no cats are reptiles 3 therefore no cats are frogs is deductively valid For deductive validity it does not matter whether the premises or the conclusion are actually true So the argument 1 all frogs are mammals 2 no cats are mammals 3 therefore no cats are frogs is also valid because the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises 68 Alfred Tarski holds that deductive arguments have three essential features 1 they are formal i e they depend only on the form of the premises and the conclusion 2 they are a priori i e no sense experience is needed to determine whether they obtain 3 they are modal i e that they hold by logical necessity for the given propositions independent of any other circumstances 8 Because of the first feature the focus on formality deductive inference is usually identified with rules of inference 69 Rules of inference specify how the premises and the conclusion have to be structured for the inference to be valid Arguments that do not follow any rule of inference are deductively invalid 70 71 The modus ponens is a prominent rule of inference It has the form p if p then q therefore q 71 Knowing that it has just rained p displaystyle p and that after rain the streets are wet p q displaystyle p to q one can use modus ponens to deduce that the streets are wet q displaystyle q 72 The third feature can be expressed by stating that deductively valid inferences are truth preserving it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false 6 40 73 Because of this feature it is often asserted that deductive inferences are uninformative since the conclusion cannot arrive at new information not already present in the premises 38 39 But this point is not always accepted since it would mean for example that most of mathematics is uninformative A different characterization distinguishes between surface and depth information On this view deductive inferences are uninformative on the depth level but can be highly informative on the surface level as may be the case for various mathematical proofs 38 74 75 Ampliative Edit Ampliative inferences on the other hand are informative even on the depth level They are more interesting in this sense since the thinker may acquire substantive information from them and thereby learn something genuinely new 76 40 41 But this feature comes with a certain cost the premises support the conclusion in the sense that they make its truth more likely but they do not ensure its truth 6 40 41 This means that the conclusion of an ampliative argument may be false even though all its premises are true This characteristic is closely related to non monotonicity and defeasibility it may be necessary to retract an earlier conclusion upon receiving new information or in the light of new inferences drawn 3 77 73 Ampliative reasoning plays a central role for many arguments found in everyday discourse and the sciences Ampliative arguments are not automatically incorrect Instead they just follow different standards of correctness The support they provide for their conclusion usually comes in degrees This means that strong ampliative arguments make their conclusion very likely while weak ones are less certain As a consequence the line between correct and incorrect arguments is blurry in some cases as when the premises offer weak but non negligible support This contrasts with deductive arguments which are either valid or invalid with nothing in between 66 73 78 The terminology used to categorize ampliative arguments is inconsistent Some authors like James Hawthorne use the term induction to cover all forms of non deductive arguments 66 78 79 But in a more narrow sense induction is only one type of ampliative argument besides abductive arguments 73 Some philosophers Leo Groarke also allow conductive arguments as one more type 24 80 In this narrow sense induction is often defined as a form of statistical generalization 81 82 In this case the premises of an inductive argument are many individual observations that all show a certain pattern The conclusion then is a general law that this pattern always obtains 83 In this sense one may infer that all elephants are gray based on one s past observations of the color of elephants 73 A closely related form of inductive inference has as its conclusion not a general law but one more specific instance as when it is inferred that an elephant one has not seen yet is also gray 83 Some theorists like Igor Douven stipulate that inductive inferences rest only on statistical considerations in order to distinguish them from abductive inference 73 Abductive inference may or may not take statistical observations into consideration In either case the premises offer support for the conclusion because the conclusion is the best explanation of why the premises are true 73 84 In this sense abduction is also called the inference to the best explanation 85 For example given the premise that there is a plate with breadcrumbs in the kitchen in the early morning one may infer the conclusion that one s house mate had a midnight snack and was too tired to clean the table This conclusion is justified because it is the best explanation of the current state of the kitchen 73 For abduction it is not sufficient that the conclusion explains the premises For example the conclusion that a burglar broke into the house last night got hungry on the job and had a midnight snack would also explain the state of the kitchen But this conclusion is not justified because it is not the best or most likely explanation 73 84 85 Fallacies Edit Not all arguments live up to the standards of correct reasoning When they do not they are usually referred to as fallacies Their central aspect is not that their conclusion is false but that there is some flaw with the reasoning leading to this conclusion 86 87 So the argument it is sunny today therefore spiders have eight legs is fallacious even though the conclusion is true Some theorists like John Stuart Mill give a more restrictive definition of fallacies by additionally requiring that they appear to be correct 33 86 This way genuine fallacies can be distinguished from mere mistakes of reasoning due to carelessness This explains why people tend to commit fallacies because they have an alluring element that seduces people into committing and accepting them 86 However this reference to appearances is controversial because it belongs to the field of psychology not logic and because appearances may be different for different people 86 88 Young America s dilemma Shall I be wise and great or rich and powerful poster from 1901 This is an example of a false Dilemma an informal fallacy using a disjunctive premise that excludes viable alternatives Fallacies are usually divided into formal and informal fallacies 42 43 44 For formal fallacies the source of the error is found in the form of the argument For example denying the antecedent is one type of formal fallacy as in if Othello is a bachelor then he is male Othello is not a bachelor therefore Othello is not male 89 90 But most fallacies fall into the category of informal fallacies of which a great variety is discussed in the academic literature The source of their error is usually found in the content or the context of the argument 33 43 86 Informal fallacies are sometimes categorized as fallacies of ambiguity fallacies of presumption or fallacies of relevance For fallacies of ambiguity the ambiguity and vagueness of natural language are responsible for their flaw as in feathers are light what is light cannot be dark therefore feathers cannot be dark 34 91 44 Fallacies of presumption have a wrong or unjustified premise but may be valid otherwise 44 92 In the case of fallacies of relevance the premises do not support the conclusion because they are not relevant to it 44 91 Definitory and strategic rules Edit The main focus of most logicians is to investigate the criteria according to which an argument is correct or incorrect A fallacy is committed if these criteria are violated In the case of formal logic they are known as rules of inference 65 They constitute definitory rules which determine whether a certain inference is correct or which inferences are allowed Definitory rules contrast with strategic rules Strategic rules specify which inferential moves are necessary in order to reach a given conclusion based on a certain set of premises This distinction does not just apply to logic but also to various games as well In chess for example the definitory rules dictate that bishops may only move diagonally while the strategic rules describe how the allowed moves may be used to win a game for example by controlling the center and by defending one s king 65 93 94 A third type of rules concerns empirical descriptive rules They belong to the field of psychology and generalize how people actually draw inferences It has been argued that logicians should give more emphasis to strategic rules since they are highly relevant for effective reasoning 65 Formal systems Edit Main article Formal system A formal system of logic consists of a formal language together with a set of axioms and a proof system used to draw inferences from these axioms 95 96 Some theorists also include a semantics that specifies how the expressions of the formal language relate to real objects 97 98 The term a logic is used as a countable noun to refer to a particular formal system of logic 4 99 21 Starting in the late 19th century many new formal systems have been proposed 4 22 21 A formal language consists of an alphabet and syntactic rules The alphabet is the set of basic symbols used in expressions The syntactic rules determine how these symbols may be arranged to result in well formed formulas 100 101 For instance the syntactic rules of propositional logic determine that P Q displaystyle P land Q is a well formed formula but Q displaystyle land Q is not since the logical conjunction displaystyle land requires terms on both sides 102 A proof system is a collection of rules that may be used to formulate formal proofs In this regard it may be understood as an inference machine that arrives at conclusions from a set of axioms Rules in a proof system are defined in terms of the syntactic form of formulas independent of their specific content For instance the classical rule of conjunction introduction states that P Q displaystyle P land Q follows from the premises P displaystyle P and Q displaystyle Q Such rules can be applied sequentially giving a mechanical procedure for generating conclusions from premises There are several different types of proof systems including natural deduction and sequent calculi 103 104 A semantics is a system for mapping expressions of a formal language to their denotations In many systems of logic denotations are truth values For instance the semantics for classical propositional logic assigns the formula P Q displaystyle P land Q the denotation true whenever P displaystyle P and Q displaystyle Q are true From the semantic point of view a premise entails a conclusion if the conclusion is true whenever the premise is true 105 106 107 A system of logic is sound when its proof system cannot derive a conclusion from a set of premises unless it is semantically entailed by them In other words its proof system cannot lead to false conclusions as defined by the semantics A system is complete when its proof system can derive every conclusion that is semantically entailed by its premises In other words its proof system can lead to any true conclusion as defined by the semantics Thus soundness and completeness together describe a system whose notions of validity and entailment line up perfectly 108 109 110 Systems of logic EditSystems of logic are theoretical frameworks for assessing the correctness of reasoning and arguments For over two thousand years Aristotelian logic was treated as the canon of logic in the Western world 21 111 112 but modern developments in this field have led to a vast proliferation of logical systems 113 One prominent categorization divides modern formal logical systems into classical logic extended logics and deviant logics 4 113 114 Classical logic is to be distinguished from traditional or Aristotelian logic It encompasses propositional logic and first order logic It is classical in the sense that it is based on various fundamental logical intuitions shared by most logicians 3 115 116 These intuitions include the law of excluded middle the double negation elimination the principle of explosion and the bivalence of truth 117 It was originally developed to analyze mathematical arguments and was only later applied to other fields as well Because of this focus on mathematics it does not include logical vocabulary relevant to many other topics of philosophical importance like the distinction between necessity and possibility the problem of ethical obligation and permission or the relations between past present and future 118 Such issues are addressed by extended logics They build on the fundamental intuitions of classical logic and expand it by introducing new logical vocabulary This way the exact logical approach is applied to fields like ethics or epistemology that lie beyond the scope of mathematics 21 119 120 Deviant logics on the other hand reject some of the fundamental intuitions of classical logic Because of this they are usually seen not as its supplements but as its rivals Deviant logical systems differ from each other either because they reject different classical intuitions or because they propose different alternatives to the same issue 113 114 Informal logic is usually carried out in a less systematic way It often focuses on more specific issues like investigating a particular type of fallacy or studying a certain aspect of argumentation 24 Nonetheless some systems of informal logic have also been presented that try to provide a systematic characterization of the correctness of arguments 86 121 122 Aristotelian Edit Aristotelian logic encompasses a great variety of topics including metaphysical theses about ontological categories and problems of scientific explanation But in a more narrow sense it is identical to term logic or syllogistics A syllogism is a certain form of argument involving three propositions two premises and a conclusion Each proposition has three essential parts a subject a predicate and a copula connecting the subject to the predicate 111 112 123 For example the proposition Socrates is wise is made up of the subject Socrates the predicate wise and the copula is 112 The subject and the predicate are the terms of the proposition In this sense Aristotelian logic does not contain complex propositions made up of various simple propositions It differs in this aspect from propositional logic in which any two propositions can be linked using a logical connective like and to form a new complex proposition 111 124 The square of opposition is often used to visualize the relations between the four basic categorical propositions in Aristotelian logic It shows for example that the propositions All S are P and Some S are not P are contradictory meaning that one of them has to be true while the other is false Aristotelian logic differs from predicate logic in that the subject is either universal particular indefinite or singular For example the term all humans is a universal subject in the proposition all humans are mortal A similar proposition could be formed by replacing it with the particular term some humans the indefinite term a human or the singular term Socrates 111 123 125 In predicate logic on the other hand universal and particular propositions would be expressed by using a quantifier and two predicates 111 126 Another key difference is that Aristotelian logic only includes predicates for simple properties of entities but lacks predicates corresponding to relations between entities 127 The predicate can be linked to the subject in two ways either by affirming it or by denying it 111 112 For example the proposition Socrates is not a cat involves the denial of the predicate cat to the subject Socrates Using different combinations of subjects and predicates a great variety of propositions and syllogisms can be formed Syllogisms are characterized by the fact that the premises are linked to each other and to the conclusion by sharing one predicate in each case 111 128 129 Thus these three propositions contain three predicates referred to as major term minor term and middle term 112 128 129 The central aspect of Aristotelian logic involves classifying all possible syllogisms into valid and invalid arguments according to how the propositions are formed 111 112 128 For example the syllogism all men are mortal Socrates is a man therefore Socrates is mortal is valid The syllogism all cats are mortal Socrates is mortal therefore Socrates is a cat on the other hand is invalid 130 Classical Edit Propositional logic Edit Main article Propositional calculus Propositional logic comprises formal systems in which formulae are built from atomic propositions using logical connectives For instance propositional logic represents the conjunction of two atomic propositions P displaystyle P and Q displaystyle Q as the complex formula P Q displaystyle P land Q Unlike predicate logic where terms and predicates are the smallest units propositional logic takes full propositions with truth values as its most basic component 131 Thus propositional logics can only represent logical relationships that arise from the way complex propositions are built from simpler ones it cannot represent inferences that results from the inner structure of a proposition 132 First order logic Edit Gottlob Frege s Begriffschrift introduced the notion of quantifier in a graphical notation which here represents the judgement that x F x displaystyle forall x F x is true Main article First order logic First order logic includes the same propositional connectives as propositional logic but differs from it because it articulates the internal structure of propositions This happens through devices such as singular terms which refer to particular objects predicates which refer to properties and relations and quantifiers which treat notions like some and all 133 46 56 For example to express the proposition this raven is black one may use the predicate B displaystyle B for the property black and the singular term r displaystyle r referring to the raven to form the expression B r displaystyle B r To express that some objects are black the existential quantifier displaystyle exists is combined with the variable x displaystyle x to form the proposition x B x displaystyle exists xB x First order logic contains various rules of inference that determine how expressions articulated this way can form valid arguments for example that one may infer x B x displaystyle exists xB x from B r displaystyle B r 134 135 Gottlob Frege developed the first fully axiomatic system of first order logic 136 The development of first order logic is usually attributed to Gottlob Frege 137 138 The analytical generality of first order logic allowed the formalization of mathematics drove the investigation of set theory and allowed the development of Alfred Tarski s approach to model theory It provides the foundation of modern mathematical logic 139 140 Extended Edit Modal logic Edit Main article Modal logic Modal logic is an extension of classical logic In its original form sometimes called alethic modal logic it introduces two new symbols displaystyle Diamond expresses that something is possible while displaystyle Box expresses that something is necessary 141 142 For example if the formula B s displaystyle B s stands for the sentence Socrates is a banker then the formula B s displaystyle Diamond B s articulates the sentence It is possible that Socrates is a banker 143 In order to include these symbols in the logical formalism modal logic introduces new rules of inference that govern what role they play in inferences One rule of inference states that if something is necessary then it is also possible This means that A displaystyle Diamond A follows from A displaystyle Box A Another principle states that if a proposition is necessary then its negation is impossible and vice versa This means that A displaystyle Box A is equivalent to A displaystyle lnot Diamond lnot A 144 145 146 Other forms of modal logic introduce similar symbols but associate different meanings with them to apply modal logic to other fields For example deontic logic concerns the field of ethics and introduces symbols to express the ideas of obligation and permission i e to describe whether an agent has to perform a certain action or is allowed to perform it 147 The modal operators in temporal modal logic articulate temporal relations They can be used to express for example that something happened at one time or that something is happening all the time 148 In epistemology epistemic modal logic is used to represent the ideas of knowing something in contrast to merely believing it to be the case 149 Higher order logic Edit Main article Higher order logic Higher order logics extend classical logic not by using modal operators but by introducing new forms of quantification 7 150 151 Quantifiers correspond to terms like all or some In classical first order logic quantifiers are only applied to individuals The formula x A p p l e x S w e e t x displaystyle exists x Apple x land Sweet x some apples are sweet is an example of the existential quantifier displaystyle exists applied to the individual variable x displaystyle x In higher order logics quantification is also allowed over predicates This increases its expressive power For example to express the idea that Mary and John share some qualities one could use the formula Q Q m a r y Q j o h n displaystyle exists Q Q mary land Q john In this case the existential quantifier is applied to the predicate variable Q displaystyle Q 7 150 152 The added expressive power is especially useful for mathematics since it allows for more succinct formulations of mathematical theories 7 But it has various drawbacks in regard to its meta logical properties and ontological implications which is why first order logic is still much more widely used 7 151 Deviant Edit Intuitionistic logic is a restricted version of classical logic 153 119 It uses the same symbols but excludes certain rules of inference For example according to the law of double negation elimination if a sentence is not not true then it is true This means that A displaystyle A follows from A displaystyle lnot lnot A This is a valid rule of inference in classical logic but it is invalid in intuitionistic logic Another classical principle not part of intuitionistic logic is the law of excluded middle It states that for every sentence either it or its negation is true This means that every proposition of the form A A displaystyle A lor lnot A is true 154 119 These deviations from classical logic are based on the idea that truth is established by verification using a proof Intuitionistic logic is especially prominent in the field of constructive mathematics which emphasizes the need to find or construct a specific example in order to prove its existence 119 155 156 Multi valued logics depart from classicality by rejecting the principle of bivalence which requires all propositions to be either true or false For instance Jan Lukasiewicz and Stephen Cole Kleene both proposed ternary logics which have a third truth value representing that a statement s truth value is indeterminate 157 158 159 These logics have seen applications including to presupposition in linguistics Fuzzy logics are multivalued logics that have an infinite number of degrees of truth represented by a real number between 0 and 1 160 Paraconsistent logics are logical systems that can deal with contradictions They are formulated to avoid the principle of explosion for them it is not the case that anything follows from a contradiction 119 161 162 They are often motivated by dialetheism the view that contradictions are real or that reality itself is contradictory Graham Priest is an influential contemporary proponent of this position and similar views have been ascribed to Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 161 162 163 Informal Edit The pragmatic or dialogical approach to informal logic sees arguments as speech acts and not merely as a set of premises together with a conclusion 86 121 122 As speech acts they occur in a certain context like a dialogue which affects the standards of right and wrong arguments 33 122 A prominent version by Douglas N Walton understands a dialogue as a game between two players 86 The initial position of each player is characterized by the propositions to which they are committed and the conclusion they intend to prove Dialogues are games of persuasion each player has the goal of convincing the opponent of their own conclusion 33 This is achieved by making arguments arguments are the moves of the game 33 122 They affect to which propositions the players are committed A winning move is a successful argument that takes the opponent s commitments as premises and shows how one s own conclusion follows from them This is usually not possible straight away For this reason it is normally necessary to formulate a sequence of arguments as intermediary steps each of which brings the opponent a little closer to one s intended conclusion Besides these positive arguments leading one closer to victory there are also negative arguments preventing the opponent s victory by denying their conclusion 33 Whether an argument is correct depends on whether it promotes the progress of the dialogue Fallacies on the other hand are violations of the standards of proper argumentative rules 86 88 These standards also depend on the type of dialogue For example the standards governing the scientific discourse differ from the standards in business negotiations 122 The epistemic approach to informal logic on the other hand focuses on the epistemic role of arguments 86 121 It is based on the idea that arguments aim to increase our knowledge They achieve this by linking justified beliefs to beliefs that are not yet justified 164 Correct arguments succeed at expanding knowledge while fallacies are epistemic failures they do not justify the belief in their conclusion 86 121 In this sense logical normativity consists in epistemic success or rationality 164 For example the fallacy of begging the question is a fallacy because it fails to provide independent justification for its conclusion even though it is deductively valid 91 164 The Bayesian approach is one example of an epistemic approach 86 Central to Bayesianism is not just whether the agent believes something but the degree to which they believe it the so called credence Degrees of belief are understood as subjective probabilities in the believed proposition i e as how certain the agent is that the proposition is true 165 166 167 On this view reasoning can be interpreted as a process of changing one s credences often in reaction to new incoming information 86 Correct reasoning and the arguments it is based on follows the laws of probability for example the principle of conditionalization Bad or irrational reasoning on the other hand violates these laws 121 166 168 Areas of research EditLogic is studied in various fields In many cases this is done by applying its formal method to specific topics outside its scope like to ethics or computer science 3 4 In other cases logic itself is made the subject of research in another discipline This can happen in diverse ways like by investigating the philosophical presuppositions of fundamental logical concepts by interpreting and analyzing logic through mathematical structures or by studying and comparing abstract properties of formal logical systems 3 169 170 Philosophy of logic and philosophical logic Edit Main articles Philosophy of logic and Philosophical logic Philosophy of logic is the philosophical discipline studying the scope and nature of logic 3 7 It investigates many presuppositions implicit in logic like how to define its fundamental concepts or the metaphysical assumptions associated with them 21 It is also concerned with how to classify the different logical systems and considers the ontological commitments they incur 3 Philosophical logic is one of the areas within the philosophy of logic It studies the application of logical methods to philosophical problems in fields like metaphysics ethics and epistemology 21 118 This application usually happens in the form of extended or deviant logical systems 120 22 Metalogic Edit Main article Metalogic Metalogic is the field of inquiry studying the properties of formal logical systems For example when a new formal system is developed metalogicians may investigate it to determine which formulas can be proven in it whether an algorithm could be developed to find a proof for each formula whether every provable formula in it is a tautology and how it compares to other logical systems A key issue in metalogic concerns the relation between syntax and semantics The syntactic rules of a formal system determine how to deduce conclusions from premises i e how to formulate proofs The semantics of a formal system governs which sentences are true and which ones are false This determines the validity of arguments since for valid arguments it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false The relation between syntax and semantics concerns issues like whether every valid argument is provable and whether every provable argument is valid Other metalogical properties investigated include completeness soundness consistency decidability and expressive power Metalogicians usually rely heavily on abstract mathematical reasoning when investigating and formulating metalogical proofs in order to arrive at precise and general conclusions on these topics 171 172 173 Mathematical logic Edit Main article Mathematical logic Bertrand Russell made various significant contributions to mathematical logic 174 Mathematical logic is the study of logic within mathematics Major subareas include model theory proof theory set theory and computability theory 175 176 Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal systems of logic However it can also include attempts to use logic to analyze mathematical reasoning or to establish logic based foundations of mathematics 177 The latter was a major concern in early 20th century mathematical logic which pursued the program of logicism pioneered by philosopher logicians such as Gottlob Frege Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell Mathematical theories were supposed to be logical tautologies and the programme was to show this by means of a reduction of mathematics to logic The various attempts to carry this out met with failure from the crippling of Frege s project in his Grundgesetze by Russell s paradox to the defeat of Hilbert s program by Godel s incompleteness theorems 178 179 180 Set theory originated in the study of the infinite by Georg Cantor and it has been the source of many of the most challenging and important issues in mathematical logic They include Cantor s theorem the status of the Axiom of Choice the question of the independence of the continuum hypothesis and the modern debate on large cardinal axioms 181 182 Computability theory is the branch of mathematical logic that investigates effective procedures to solve calculation problems An example is the problem of finding a mechanical procedure that can decide for any positive integer whether it is a prime number One of its main goals is to understand whether it is possible to solve a given problem using an algorithm Computability theory uses various theoretical tools and models such as Turing machines to explore this issue 183 184 Computational logic Edit Main articles Computational logic and Logic in computer science Conjunction AND is one of the basic operations of boolean logic It can be electronically implemented in several ways for example by using two transistors Computational logic is the branch of logic and computer science that studies how to implement mathematical reasoning and logical formalisms using computers This includes for example automatic theorem provers which employ rules of inference to construct a proof step by step from a set of premises to the intended conclusion without human intervention 185 186 187 Logic programming languages are designed specifically to express facts using logical formulas and to draw inferences from these facts For example Prolog is a logic programming language based on predicate logic 188 189 Computer scientists also apply concepts from logic to problems in computing The works of Claude Shannon were influential in this regard He showed how Boolean logic can be used to understand and implement computer circuits 190 191 This can be achieved using electronic logic gates i e electronic circuits with one or more inputs and usually one output The truth values of propositions are represented by different voltage levels This way logic functions can be simulated by applying the corresponding voltages to the inputs of the circuit and determining the value of the function by measuring the voltage of the output 192 Formal semantics of natural language Edit Main article Formal semantics natural language Formal semantics is a subfield of logic linguistics and the philosophy of language The discipline of semantics studies the meaning of language Formal semantics uses formal tools from the fields of symbolic logic and mathematics to give precise theories of the meaning of natural language expressions It understands meaning usually in relation to truth conditions i e it investigates in which situations a sentence would be true or false One of its central methodological assumptions is the principle of compositionality which states that the meaning of a complex expression is determined by the meanings of its parts and how they are combined For example the meaning of the verb phrase walk and sing depends on the meanings of the individual expressions walk and sing Many theories in formal semantics rely on model theory This means that they employ set theory to construct a model and then interpret the meanings of expression in relation to the elements in this model For example the term walk may be interpreted as the set of all individuals in the model that share the property of walking Early influential theorists in this field were Richard Montague and Barbara Partee who focused their analysis on the English language 193 Epistemology of logic EditThe epistemology of logic investigates how one knows that an argument is valid or that a proposition is logically true 194 195 This includes questions like how to justify that modus ponens is a valid rule of inference or that contradictions are false 194 The traditionally dominant view is that this form of logical understanding belongs to knowledge a priori 195 In this regard it is often argued that the mind has a special faculty to examine relations between pure ideas and that this faculty is also responsible for apprehending logical truths 196 A similar approach understands the rules of logic in terms of linguistic conventions On this view the laws of logic are trivial since they are true by definition they just express the meanings of the logical vocabulary 194 196 197 Some theorists like Hilary Putnam and Penelope Maddy have objected to the view that logic is knowable a priori and hold instead that logical truths depend on the empirical world This is usually combined with the claim that the laws of logic express universal regularities found in the structural features of the world and that they can be explored by studying general patterns of the fundamental sciences For example it has been argued that certain insights of quantum mechanics refute the principle of distributivity in classical logic which states that the formula A B C displaystyle A land B lor C is equivalent to A B A C displaystyle A land B lor A land C This claim can be used as an empirical argument for the thesis that quantum logic is the correct logical system and should replace classical logic 198 199 200 History EditMain article History of logic Top row Aristotle who established the canon of western philosophy 112 and Avicenna who replaced Aristotelian logic in Islamic discourse 201 Bottom row William of Ockham a major figure of medieval scholarly thought 202 and the Principia Mathematica which had a large impact on modern logic Logic was developed independently in several cultures during antiquity One major early contributor was Aristotle who developed term logic in his Organon and Prior Analytics 203 204 205 Aristotle s system of logic was responsible for the introduction of hypothetical syllogism 206 temporal modal logic 207 208 and inductive logic 209 as well as influential vocabulary such as terms predicables syllogisms and propositions Aristotelian logic was highly regarded in classical and medieval times both in Europe and the Middle East It remained in wide use in the West until the early 19th century 210 112 It has now been superseded by later work though many of its key insights are still present in modern systems of logic 211 212 Ibn Sina Avicenna was the founder of Avicennian logic which replaced Aristotelian logic as the dominant system of logic in the Islamic world 213 201 It also had a significant influence on Western medieval writers such as Albertus Magnus and William of Ockham 214 215 Ibn Sina wrote on the hypothetical syllogism 216 and on the propositional calculus 217 He developed an original temporally modalized syllogistic theory involving temporal logic and modal logic 218 He also made use of inductive logic such as his methods of agreement difference and concomitant variation which are critical to the scientific method 216 Fakhr al Din al Razi was another influential Muslim logician He criticised Aristotlian syllogistics and formulated an early system of inductive logic foreshadowing the system of inductive logic developed by John Stuart Mill 219 During the Middle Ages many translations and interpretations of Aristotelian logic were made Of particular influence were the works of Boethius Besides translating Aristotle s work into Latin he also produced various text books on logic 220 221 Later the work of Islamic philosophers such as Ibn Sina and Ibn Rushd Averroes were drawn on This expanded the range of ancient works available to medieval Christian scholars since more Greek work was available to Muslim scholars that had been preserved in Latin commentaries In 1323 William of Ockham s influential Summa Logicae was released It is a comprehensive treatise on logic that discusses many fundamental concepts of logic and provides a systematic exposition of different types of propositions and their truth conditions 221 213 222 In Chinese philosophy the School of Names and Mohism were particularly influential The School of Names focused on the use of language and on paradoxes For example Gongsun Long proposed the white horse paradox which defends the thesis that a white horse is not a horse The school of Mohism also acknowledged the importance of language for logic and tried to relate the ideas in these fields to the realm of ethics 223 224 In India the study of logic was primarily pursued by the schools of Nyaya Buddhism and Jainism It was not treated as a separate academic discipline and discussions of its topics usually happened in the context of epistemology and theories of dialogue or argumentation 225 In Nyaya inference is understood as a source of knowledge pramaṇa It follows the perception of an object and tries to arrive at certain conclusions for example about the cause of this object 226 A similar emphasis on the relation to epistemology is also found in Buddhist and Jainist schools of logic where inference is used to expand the knowledge gained through other sources 227 228 Some of the later theories of Nyaya belonging to the Navya Nyaya school resemble modern forms of logic such as Gottlob Frege s distinction between sense and reference and his definition of number 229 The syllogistic logic developed by Aristotle predominated in the West until the mid 19th century when interest in the foundations of mathematics stimulated the development of modern symbolic logic 112 230 It is often argued that Gottlob Frege s Begriffsschrift gave birth to modern logic Other pioneers of the field were Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz who conceived the idea of a universal formal language George Boole who invented Boolean algebra as a mathematical system of logic and Charles Peirce who developed the logic of relatives as well as Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell who condensed many of these insights in their work Principia Mathematica Modern logic introduced various new notions such as the concepts of functions quantifiers and relational predicates A hallmark of modern symbolic logic is its use of formal language to codify its insights in a very precise manner This contrasts with the approach of earlier logicians who relied mainly on natural language 231 Of particular influence was the development of first order logic which is usually treated as the standard system of modern logic 232 See also Edit Philosophy portalCritical thinking Analysis of facts to form a judgment List of logicians List of logic journals List of logic symbols Logic puzzle Puzzle deriving from the mathematics field of deduction Outline of logic Overview of and topical guide to logic Logos Concept in philosophy religion rhetoric and psychology Logical reasoning Process of drawing correct inferences Vector logicReferences EditNotes Edit However there are some forms of logic like imperative logic where this may not be the case 47 Citations Edit Pepin Jean 2004 Logos Encyclopedia of Religion ISBN 978 0 02 865733 2 Archived from the original on 29 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 logic etymonline com Archived from the original on 29 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 a b c d e f g h i j Hintikka Jaakko J Philosophy of logic Encyclopedia Britannica Archived from the original on 28 April 2015 Retrieved 21 November 2021 a b c d e f g h i j Haack Susan 1978 1 Philosophy of logics Philosophy of Logics London and New York Cambridge University Press pp 1 10 ISBN 978 0 521 29329 7 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Schlesinger I M Keren Portnoy Tamar Parush Tamar 1 January 2001 The Structure of Arguments John Benjamins Publishing p 220 ISBN 978 90 272 2359 3 a b c d Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 13 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o Audi Robert 1999 Philosophy of logic The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 64379 6 Archived from the original on 14 April 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 a b c d e McKeon Matthew Logical Consequence Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 12 November 2021 Retrieved 20 November 2021 a b c MacFarlane John 2017 Logical Constants 4 Topic neutrality The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 17 March 2020 Retrieved 4 December 2021 a b c Corkum Philip 2015 Generality and Logical Constancy Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 71 4 753 767 doi 10 17990 rpf 2015 71 4 0753 ISSN 0870 5283 JSTOR 43744657 a b c Blair J Anthony Johnson Ralph H 2000 Informal Logic An Overview Informal Logic 20 2 93 107 doi 10 22329 il v20i2 2262 Archived from the original on 9 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Hofweber 2021 Gomez Torrente Mario 2022 Alfred Tarski 3 Logical consequence The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 25 September 2022 McKeon Matthew Logical Consequence Model Theoretic Conceptions Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 25 September 2022 a b Magnus P D 2005 1 4 Deductive validity Forall X An Introduction to Formal Logic Victoria BC Canada State University of New York Oer Services pp 8 9 ISBN 978 1 64176 026 3 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Mattingly James 28 October 2022 The SAGE Encyclopedia of Theory in Science Technology Engineering and Mathematics SAGE Publications p 512 ISBN 978 1 5063 5328 9 a b c d e f g h i j k Craig Edward 1996 Formal and informal logic Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 07310 3 Archived from the original on 16 January 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 a b c d e Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 16 a b c Gomez Torrente Mario 2019 Logical Truth The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 2 October 2021 Retrieved 22 November 2021 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 16 7 a b c d e f g h Jacquette Dale 2006 Introduction Philosophy of logic today Philosophy of Logic North Holland pp 1 12 ISBN 978 0 444 51541 4 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 a b c Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 31 2 Haack Susan 15 December 1996 Deviant Logic Fuzzy Logic Beyond the Formalism University of Chicago Press pp 229 30 ISBN 978 0 226 31133 3 a b c d e f g h i j Groarke Leo 2021 Informal Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 12 January 2022 Retrieved 31 December 2021 a b Audi Robert 1999 Informal logic The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 64379 6 Archived from the original on 14 April 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 a b c d e f g h i Johnson Ralph H 1999 The Relation Between Formal and Informal Logic Argumentation 13 3 265 274 doi 10 1023 A 1007789101256 S2CID 141283158 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 van Eemeren Frans H Garssen Bart Krabbe Erik C W Snoeck Henkemans A Francisca Verheij Bart Wagemans Jean H M 2021 Informal Logic Handbook of Argumentation Theory Springer Netherlands pp 1 45 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 6883 3 7 1 ISBN 978 94 007 6883 3 Archived from the original on 31 December 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b c Honderich Ted 2005 logic informal The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on 29 January 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b Craig Edward 1996 Formal languages and systems Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 07310 3 Archived from the original on 16 January 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Simpson R L 17 March 2008 Essentials of Symbolic Logic Third Edition Broadview Press p 14 ISBN 978 1 77048 495 5 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 22 3 Eemeren Frans H van Grootendorst Rob Johnson Ralph H Plantin Christian Willard Charles A 5 November 2013 Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and Contemporary Developments Routledge p 169 ISBN 978 1 136 68804 1 a b c d e f g h Walton Douglas N 1987 1 A new model of argument Informal Fallacies Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms John Benjamins pp 1 32 ISBN 978 1 55619 010 0 Archived from the original on 2 March 2022 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b Engel S Morris 1982 2 The medium of language With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies pp 59 92 ISBN 978 0 312 08479 0 Archived from the original on 1 March 2022 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b Blair J Anthony Johnson Ralph H 1987 The Current State of Informal Logic Informal Logic 9 2 147 51 doi 10 22329 il v9i2 2671 Archived from the original on 30 December 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b Weddle Perry 26 July 2011 36 Informal logic and the eductive inductive distinction Argumentation 3 De Gruyter Mouton pp 383 8 doi 10 1515 9783110867718 383 ISBN 978 3 11 086771 8 Archived from the original on 31 December 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b Blair J Anthony 20 October 2011 Groundwork in the Theory of Argumentation Selected Papers of J Anthony Blair Springer Science amp Business Media p 47 ISBN 978 94 007 2363 4 a b c Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 14 a b D Agostino Marcello Floridi Luciano 2009 The Enduring Scandal of Deduction Is Propositional Logic Really Uninformative Synthese 167 2 271 315 doi 10 1007 s11229 008 9409 4 hdl 2299 2995 ISSN 0039 7857 JSTOR 40271192 S2CID 9602882 a b c d e f Backmann Marius 1 June 2019 Varieties of Justification How Not to Solve the Problem of Induction Acta Analytica 34 2 235 255 doi 10 1007 s12136 018 0371 6 ISSN 1874 6349 S2CID 125767384 a b c Deductive and Inductive Arguments Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 28 May 2010 Retrieved 4 December 2021 a b Vleet Van Jacob E 2010 Introduction Informal Logical Fallacies A Brief Guide Upa pp ix x ISBN 978 0 7618 5432 6 Archived from the original on 28 February 2022 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b c d e Dowden Bradley Fallacies Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 29 April 2010 Retrieved 19 March 2021 a b c d e Stump David J Fallacy Logical encyclopedia com Archived from the original on 15 February 2021 Retrieved 20 March 2021 Maltby John Day Liz Macaskill Ann 2007 Personality Individual Differences and Intelligence Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 129760 9 a b c d e f g h Honderich Ted 2005 philosophical logic The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on 29 January 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 Haack Susan 1974 Deviant Logic Some Philosophical Issues CUP Archive p 51 ISBN 978 0 521 20500 9 Falguera Jose L Martinez Vidal Concha Rosen Gideon 2021 Abstract Objects The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 January 2021 Retrieved 7 January 2022 Tondl L 6 December 2012 Problems of Semantics A Contribution to the Analysis of the Language Science Springer Science amp Business Media p 111 ISBN 978 94 009 8364 9 Pietroski Paul 2021 Logical Form 1 Patterns of Reason The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 2 October 2021 Retrieved 4 December 2021 Kusch Martin 2020 Psychologism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 29 December 2020 Retrieved 30 November 2021 Rush Penelope 2014 Introduction The Metaphysics of Logic Cambridge University Press pp 1 10 ISBN 978 1 107 03964 3 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 8 January 2022 a b King Jeffrey C 2019 Structured Propositions The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 25 October 2021 Retrieved 4 December 2021 a b c Pickel Bryan 1 July 2020 Structured propositions and trivial composition Synthese 197 7 2991 3006 doi 10 1007 s11229 018 1853 1 ISSN 1573 0964 S2CID 49729020 Craig Edward 1996 Philosophy of logic Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 07310 3 Archived from the original on 16 January 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 a b c Michaelson Eliot Reimer Marga 2019 Reference The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 4 December 2021 a b MacFarlane John 2017 Logical Constants The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 17 March 2020 Retrieved 21 November 2021 Jago Mark 24 April 2014 The Impossible An Essay on Hyperintensionality OUP Oxford p 41 ISBN 978 0 19 101915 9 Magnus P D 2005 3 Truth tables Forall X An Introduction to Formal Logic Victoria BC Canada State University of New York Oer Services pp 35 45 ISBN 978 1 64176 026 3 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Angell Richard B 1964 Reasoning and Logic Ardent Media p 164 ISBN 978 0 89197 375 1 Tarski Alfred 6 January 1994 Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences Oxford University Press p 40 ISBN 978 0 19 802139 1 Blackburn Simon 1 January 2008 argument The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 954143 0 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 Stairs Allen 29 September 2017 A Thinker s Guide to the Philosophy of Religion Routledge p 343 ISBN 978 1 351 21981 5 Copi Irving M Cohen Carl Rodych Victor 3 September 2018 Introduction to Logic Routledge p 30 ISBN 978 1 351 38697 5 a b c d Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 20 a b c d IEP Staff Deductive and Inductive Arguments Archived from the original on 28 May 2010 Retrieved 6 January 2022 Eemeren Frans H van Garssen Bart 11 February 2009 Pondering on Problems of Argumentation Twenty Essays on Theoretical Issues Springer Science amp Business Media p 191 ISBN 978 1 4020 9165 0 Evans Jonathan St B T 18 April 2005 8 Deductive Reasoning In Morrison Robert ed The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning Cambridge University Press p 169 ISBN 978 0 521 82417 0 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 13 4 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 13 14 a b Blackburn Simon 24 March 2016 rule of inference A Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 873530 4 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 Dick Anthony S Muller Ulrich 6 July 2017 Advancing Developmental Science Philosophy Theory and Method Taylor amp Francis p 157 ISBN 978 1 351 70456 4 a b c d e f g h i Douven Igor 2021 Abduction The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 7 September 2021 Retrieved 24 August 2021 Saguillo Jose M 2014 Hintikka on Information and Deduction Teorema Revista Internacional de Filosofia 33 2 75 88 ISSN 0210 1602 JSTOR 43047609 Hintikka Jaakko 1970 Information Deduction and the A Priori Nous 4 2 135 152 doi 10 2307 2214318 ISSN 0029 4624 JSTOR 2214318 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 14 6 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 13 16 a b Hawthorne James 2021 Inductive Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 21 January 2022 Retrieved 6 January 2022 Wilbanks Jan J 1 March 2010 Defining Deduction Induction and Validity Argumentation 24 1 107 124 doi 10 1007 s10503 009 9131 5 ISSN 1572 8374 S2CID 144481717 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 Possin Kevin 2016 Conductive Arguments Why is This Still a Thing Informal Logic 36 4 563 593 doi 10 22329 il v36i4 4527 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 Scott John Marshall Gordon 2009 analytic induction A Dictionary of Sociology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 953300 8 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 HOUDE R CAMACHO L 2003 Induction New Catholic Encyclopedia ISBN 978 0 7876 4004 0 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 a b Borchert Donald 2006 Induction Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on 12 January 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b Koslowski Barbara 2017 Abductive reasoning and explanation The Routledge International Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning Routledge doi 10 4324 9781315725697 ISBN 978 1 315 72569 7 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 a b Cummings Louise 5 April 2010 Abduction The Routledge Pragmatics Encyclopedia Routledge p 1 ISBN 978 1 135 21457 9 Archived from the original on 8 January 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 a b c d e f g h i j k l m Hansen Hans 2020 Fallacies The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 29 March 2021 Retrieved 18 March 2021 Chatfield Tom 23 October 2017 Critical Thinking Your Guide to Effective Argument Successful Analysis and Independent Study SAGE p 194 ISBN 978 1 5264 1877 7 a b Walton Douglas N 1987 3 Logic of propositions Informal Fallacies Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms John Benjamins pp 63 96 ISBN 978 1 55619 010 0 Archived from the original on 2 March 2022 Retrieved 2 January 2022 Sternberg Robert J Thought Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 13 October 2021 Retrieved 14 October 2021 Stone Mark A 2012 Denying the Antecedent Its Effective Use in Argumentation Informal Logic 32 3 327 356 doi 10 22329 il v32i3 3681 Archived from the original on 28 February 2022 Retrieved 8 January 2022 a b c Mackie J L 1967 Fallacies encyclopedia com Archived from the original on 15 April 2021 Retrieved 19 March 2021 Engel S Morris 1982 4 Fallacies of presumption With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies pp 143 212 ISBN 978 0 312 08479 0 Archived from the original on 1 March 2022 Retrieved 2 January 2022 Pedemonte Bettina 25 June 2018 Strategic vs Definitory Rules Their Role in Abductive Argumentation and their Relationship with Deductive Proof Eurasia Journal of Mathematics Science and Technology Education 14 9 em1589 doi 10 29333 ejmste 92562 ISSN 1305 8215 S2CID 126245285 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 8 January 2022 Hintikka Jaakko J Logical systems Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 4 December 2021 Boris Kulik Alexander Fridman 30 November 2017 N ary Relations for Logical Analysis of Data and Knowledge IGI Global p 74 ISBN 978 1 5225 2783 1 Cook Roy T 20 March 2009 Dictionary of Philosophical Logic Edinburgh University Press p 124 ISBN 978 0 7486 3197 1 Gensler Harry J 12 February 2010 The A to Z of Logic Scarecrow Press p 43 ISBN 978 1 4617 3182 5 Font Josep Maria Jansana Ramon 2 March 2017 A General Algebraic Semantics for Sentential Logics Cambridge University Press p 8 ISBN 978 1 107 16797 1 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 21 28 Moore Terence Carling Christine 28 October 1982 Understanding Language Towards a Post Chomskyan Linguistics Springer p 53 ISBN 978 1 349 16895 8 Enderton Herbert 2001 Sentential Logic A mathematical introduction to logic Elsevier pp 12 13 ISBN 978 0 12 238452 3 Lepore Ernest Cumming Sam 14 September 2012 Meaning and Argument An Introduction to Logic Through Language John Wiley amp Sons p 5 ISBN 978 1 118 45521 0 Wasilewska Anita 3 November 2018 Logics for Computer Science Classical and Non Classical Springer pp 145 6 ISBN 978 3 319 92591 2 Rathjen Michael Sieg Wilfried 2022 Proof Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 4 March 2023 Sider Theodore 2010 Logic for Philosophy Oxford University Press pp 34 42 ISBN 978 0 19 957558 9 Shapiro Stewart Kouri Kissel Teresa 2021 Classical Logic In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 3 May 1998 Retrieved 21 August 2021 Bimbo Katalin 2 April 2016 J Michael Dunn on Information Based Logics Springer pp 8 9 ISBN 978 3 319 29300 4 Restall Greg Standefer Shawn 3 January 2023 Logical Methods MIT Press p 91 ISBN 978 0 262 54484 9 Enderton Herbert 2001 A mathematical introduction to logic Elsevier Chapter 2 5 ISBN 978 0 12 238452 3 van Dalen Dirk 1994 Logic and Structure Springer Chapter 1 5 ISBN 0 387 57839 0 a b c d e f g h Smith Robin 2020 Aristotle s Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 26 December 2021 Retrieved 1 January 2022 a b c d e f g h i Groarke Louis F Aristotle Logic Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 29 December 2021 Retrieved 1 January 2022 a b c Haack Susan 1996 1 Alternative in Alternative Logic Deviant Logic Fuzzy Logic Beyond the Formalism Chicago and London University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 31133 3 Archived from the original on 8 December 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b Wolf Robert G 1978 Are Relevant Logics Deviant Philosophia 7 2 327 340 doi 10 1007 BF02378819 S2CID 143697796 Archived from the original on 16 December 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Hintikka amp Sandu 2006 p 27 8 Back Allan T 21 June 2016 Aristotle s Theory of Predication Brill p 317 ISBN 978 90 04 32109 0 Shapiro Stewart Kouri Kissel Teresa 2021 Classical Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 3 May 1998 Retrieved 4 December 2021 a b Burgess John P 2009 1 Classical logic Philosophical Logic Princeton NJ USA Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 15633 0 Archived from the original on 16 December 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b c d e Borchert Donald 2006 Logic Non Classical Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on 12 January 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b Goble Lou 2001 Introduction The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 0 631 20692 7 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b c d e Korb Kevin 2004 Bayesian Informal Logic and Fallacy Informal Logic 24 1 41 70 doi 10 22329 il v24i1 2132 Archived from the original on 10 November 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 a b c d e Ritola Juho 1 December 2008 Walton s Informal Logic A Pragmatic Approach Informal Logic 28 4 335 doi 10 22329 il v28i4 2856 a b Bobzien Susanne 2020 Ancient Logic 2 Aristotle The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 28 August 2018 Retrieved 3 January 2022 Magnus P D 2005 2 2 Connectives Forall X An Introduction to Formal Logic Victoria BC Canada State University of New York Oer Services ISBN 978 1 64176 026 3 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Hintikka Jaakko J Spade Paul Vincent history of logic Aristotle Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 4 January 2022 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Goertzel Ben Geisweiller Nil Coelho Lucio Janicic Predrag Pennachin Cassio 2 December 2011 Real World Reasoning Toward Scalable Uncertain Spatiotemporal Contextual and Causal Inference Springer Science amp Business Media pp 43 4 ISBN 978 94 91216 11 4 Westerstahl Dag 1989 Aristotelian Syllogisms and Generalized Quantifiers Studia Logica 48 4 577 585 doi 10 1007 BF00370209 S2CID 32089424 Archived from the original on 4 January 2022 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b c Hurley Patrick J 2015 4 Categorical Syllogisms Logic The Essentials Wadsworth ISBN 978 1 305 59041 0 Archived from the original on 4 January 2022 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b Copi Irving Marmer Cohen Carl McMahon Kenneth 1953 6 Categorical Syllogisms Introduction to Logic New York NY USA Macmillan ISBN 978 1 138 50086 0 Archived from the original on 4 January 2022 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Spriggs John 5 January 2012 GSN The Goal Structuring Notation A Structured Approach to Presenting Arguments Springer Science amp Business Media p 20 2 ISBN 978 1 4471 2312 5 Brody Boruch A 2006 Encyclopedia of philosophy Vol 5 Donald M Borchert 2nd ed Detroit Thomson Gale Macmillan Reference USA pp 535 536 ISBN 0 02 865780 2 OCLC 61151356 The two most important types of logical calculi are propositional or sentential calculi and functional or predicate calculi A propositional calculus is a system containing propositional variables and connectives some also contain propositional constants but not individual or functional variables or constants In the extended propositional calculus quantifiers whose operator variables are propositional variables are added Klement Kevin C Propositional Logic Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 23 September 2022 Shapiro Stewart Kouri Kissel Teresa 2022 Classical Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 13 March 2023 Nolt John 2021 Free Logic 1 The Basics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 10 September 2022 Magnus P D 2005 4 Quantified logic Forall X An Introduction to Formal Logic Victoria BC Canada State University of New York Oer Services ISBN 978 1 64176 026 3 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Klement Kevin C Frege Gottlob Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 29 September 2022 Hintikka Jaakko J Spade Paul Vincent history of logic Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 10 September 2022 Okeke Johnathan Chimakonam Proof in Alonzo Church s and Alan Turing s Mathematical Logic Undecidability of First Order Logic Universal Publishers p 122 ISBN 978 1 61233 951 1 Ewald William 2019 The Emergence of First Order Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 10 September 2022 Schreiner Wolfgang 22 October 2021 Thinking Programs Logical Modeling and Reasoning About Languages Data Computations and Executions Springer Nature p 22 ISBN 978 3 030 80507 4 Garson James 2023 Modal Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 What is Modal Logic Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Sadegh Zadeh Kazem 6 April 2015 Handbook of Analytic Philosophy of Medicine Springer p 983 ISBN 978 94 017 9579 1 Fitch G W 18 December 2014 Saul Kripke Routledge p 17 ISBN 978 1 317 48917 7 Garson James 2023 Modal Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2 Modal Logics Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Carnielli Walter Pizzi Claudio 15 September 2008 Modalities and Multimodalities Springer Science amp Business Media p 3 ISBN 978 1 4020 8590 1 Benthem Johan van Modal Logic Contemporary View 1 Modal Notions and Reasoning Patterns a First Pass Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 11 March 2023 Garson James 2023 Modal Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 3 Deontic Logics Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Garson James 2023 Modal Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 4 Temporal Logics Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Rendsvig Rasmus Symons John 2021 Epistemic Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 a b Vaananen Jouko 2021 Second order and Higher order Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 30 October 2021 Retrieved 23 November 2021 a b Ketland Jeffrey 2005 Second Order Logic Encyclopedia of Philosophy ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Daintith John Wright Edmund 10 July 2008 predicate calculus A Dictionary of Computing ISBN 978 0 19 923400 4 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Moschovakis Joan 2022 Intuitionistic Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Introduction Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Moschovakis Joan 2022 Intuitionistic Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 Rejection of Tertium Non Datur Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Bridges Douglas Ishihara Hajime Rathjen Michael Schwichtenberg Helmut 30 April 2023 Handbook of Constructive Mathematics Cambridge University Press pp 73 4 ISBN 978 1 316 51086 5 Friend Michele 5 December 2014 Introducing Philosophy of Mathematics Routledge p 101 ISBN 978 1 317 49379 2 Sider Theodore 2010 Logic for Philosophy Oxford University Press Chapter 3 4 ISBN 978 0 19 957558 9 Gamut L T F 1991 Logic Language and Meaning Vol 1 Introduction to Logic University of Chicago Press 5 5 ISBN 978 0 226 28085 1 Zegarelli Mark 2010 Logic For Dummies John Wiley amp Sons p 30 ISBN 978 1 118 05307 2 archived from the original on 14 May 2015 retrieved 7 March 2015 Hajek Petr 2006 Fuzzy Logic In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 11 July 2010 Retrieved 16 May 2009 a b Priest Graham Tanaka Koji Weber Zach 2018 Paraconsistent Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 December 2021 a b Weber Zach Paraconsistent Logic Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 12 December 2021 Haack Susan 1996 Introduction Deviant Logic Fuzzy Logic Beyond the Formalism Chicago and London University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 31133 3 a b c Siegel Harvey Biro John 1997 Epistemic Normativity Argumentation and Fallacies Argumentation 11 3 277 292 doi 10 1023 A 1007799325361 S2CID 126269789 Archived from the original on 28 February 2022 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Olsson Erik J 2018 Bayesian Epistemology Introduction to Formal Philosophy Springer pp 431 442 ISBN 978 3 030 08454 7 Archived from the original on 16 May 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 a b Hajek Alan Lin Hanti 2017 A Tale of Two Epistemologies Res Philosophica 94 2 207 232 doi 10 11612 resphil 1540 S2CID 160029122 Archived from the original on 4 January 2022 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Hartmann Stephan Sprenger Jan 2010 Bayesian Epistemology The Routledge Companion to Epistemology London Routledge pp 609 620 ISBN 978 0 415 96219 3 Archived from the original on 16 May 2021 Retrieved 4 January 2022 Talbott William 2016 Bayesian Epistemology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 1 April 2021 Retrieved 6 March 2021 Godel Kurt 1984 Russell s mathematical logic Philosophy of Mathematics Selected Readings 2 ed Cambridge University Press pp 447 469 ISBN 978 0 521 29648 9 Archived from the original on 11 January 2022 Retrieved 9 January 2022 Monk J Donald 1976 Introduction Mathematical Logic Springer pp 1 9 doi 10 1007 978 1 4684 9452 5 1 ISBN 978 1 4684 9452 5 Archived from the original on 9 January 2022 Retrieved 9 January 2022 Gensler Harry J 2006 The A to Z of Logic Scarecrow Press pp xliii xliv ISBN 9781461731825 Sider Theodore 2010 Logic for Philosophy Oxford University Press pp 4 6 ISBN 978 0 19 957558 9 Schagrin Morton L metalogic Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 23 September 2022 Irvine Andrew David 2022 Bertrand Russell The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 29 September 2022 Li Wei 26 February 2010 Mathematical Logic Foundations for Information Science Springer Science amp Business Media p ix ISBN 978 3 7643 9977 1 Rautenberg Wolfgang 1 July 2010 A Concise Introduction to Mathematical Logic Springer p 15 ISBN 978 1 4419 1221 3 Stolyar Abram Aronovich 1 January 1984 Introduction to Elementary Mathematical Logic Courier Corporation pp 3 6 ISBN 978 0 486 64561 2 Hintikka Jaakko J Spade Paul Vincent History of logic Godel s incompleteness theorems Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 23 September 2022 Linsky Bernard 9 June 2011 The Evolution of Principia Mathematica Bertrand Russell s Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition Cambridge University Press p 4 ISBN 978 1 139 49733 6 Richardson Alan W 1998 Carnap s Construction of the World The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism Cambridge University Press p 15 ISBN 978 0 521 43008 1 Bagaria Joan 2021 Set Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 23 September 2022 Cunningham Daniel Set Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 23 September 2022 Borchert Donald ed 2006 Computability Theory Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan ISBN 9780028657905 Leary Christopher C Kristiansen Lars 2015 A Friendly Introduction to Mathematical Logic Suny p 195 ISBN 978 1 942341 07 9 Paulson Lawrence C February 2018 Computational logic its origins and applications Proceedings of the Royal Society A Mathematical Physical and Engineering Sciences 474 2210 1 14 doi 10 1098 rspa 2017 0872 PMID 29507522 S2CID 3805901 Castano Arnaldo Perez 23 May 2018 Practical Artificial Intelligence Machine Learning Bots and Agent Solutions Using C Apress p 2 ISBN 978 1 4842 3357 3 Wile Bruce Goss John Roesner Wolfgang 26 May 2005 Comprehensive Functional Verification The Complete Industry Cycle Elsevier p 447 ISBN 978 0 08 047664 3 Clocksin William F Mellish Christopher S 2003 The Relation of Prolog to Logic Programming in Prolog Using the ISO Standard Springer pp 237 257 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 55481 0 10 ISBN 978 3 642 55481 0 Daintith John 2004 Logic Programming Languages A Dictionary of Computing Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 860877 6 O Regan Gerard 21 June 2016 Introduction to the History of Computing A Computing History Primer Springer p 49 ISBN 978 3 319 33138 6 Calderbank Robert Sloane Neil J A April 2001 Claude Shannon 1916 2001 Nature 410 6830 768 doi 10 1038 35071223 ISSN 1476 4687 PMID 11298432 S2CID 4402158 Daintith John 2004 Logic Gate A Dictionary of Computing Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 860877 6 Janssen Theo M V Zimmermann Thomas Ede 2021 Montague Semantics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University pp 3 4 Retrieved 10 March 2023 Partee Barbara H 2016 Aloni Maria Dekker Paul eds The Cambridge handbook of formal semantics Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 02839 5 King Jeffrey C 2 September 2009 Formal Semantics The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language 557 8 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199552238 003 0023 ISBN 978 0199552238 Coppock Elizabeth Champollion Lucas 2019 Invitation to formal semantics PDF pp 3 4 Archived PDF from the original on 21 January 2020 Retrieved 25 October 2021 a b c Warren Jared 3 August 2020 6 The Epistemology of Logic Shadows of Syntax Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 008615 2 a b Schechter Joshua Epistemology of Logic Bibliography PhilPapers philpapers org Retrieved 11 September 2022 a b Gomez Torrente Mario 2019 Logical Truth The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 September 2022 Warren Jared 3 August 2020 1 What is Conventionalism Shadows of Syntax Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 008615 2 Chua Eugene 2017 An Empirical Route to Logical Conventionalism Logic Rationality and Interaction Lecture Notes in Computer Science 10455 631 636 doi 10 1007 978 3 662 55665 8 43 ISBN 978 3 662 55664 1 Wilce Alexander 2021 Quantum Logic and Probability Theory 2 1 Realist Quantum Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Putnam H 1969 Is Logic Empirical Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 216 241 doi 10 1007 978 94 010 3381 7 5 ISBN 978 94 010 3383 1 a b Lagerlund Henrik The Aftermath of Syllogism Aristotelian Logical Argument from Avicenna to Hegel Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews Retrieved 29 September 2022 Spade Paul Vincent Panaccio Claude 2019 William of Ockham 3 Logic and Semantics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 29 September 2022 Kline 1972 p 53 A major achievement of Aristotle was the founding of the science of logic Lukasiewicz Jan 1957 Aristotle s syllogistic from the standpoint of modern formal logic 2nd ed Oxford University Press p 7 ISBN 978 0 19 824144 7 Liu Shiyong Guo Kaizhong 7 March 2023 Error Logic Paving Pathways for Intelligent Error Identification and Management Springer Nature p 15 ISBN 978 3 031 00820 7 Lear Jonathan 1980 Aristotle and Logical Theory CUP Archive p 34 ISBN 978 0 521 31178 6 Knuuttila Simo 30 November 1980 Reforging the Great Chain of Being Studies of the History of Modal Theories Springer Science amp Business Media p 71 ISBN 978 90 277 1125 0 Fisher Michael David Gabbay Dov M Vila Lluis 1 March 2005 Handbook of Temporal Reasoning in Artificial Intelligence Elsevier p 119 ISBN 978 0 08 053336 0 Berman Harold J 1 July 2009 Law and Revolution the Formation of the Western Legal Tradition Harvard University Press p 133 ISBN 978 0 674 02085 6 Frede Michael Aristotle Michigan Technological University Michigan Technological University Retrieved 1 November 2022 Ewald William 2019 The Emergence of First Order Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 23 September 2022 Smith Robin 2022 Aristotle s Logic Introduction The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 a b Dag Nikolaus Hasse 19 September 2008 Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 14 July 2010 Retrieved 13 October 2009 Washell Richard F 1973 Logic Language and Albert the Great Journal of the History of Ideas 34 3 445 50 doi 10 2307 2708963 JSTOR 2708963 Kneale amp Kneale 1962 pp 229 266 a b Goodman Lenn Evan 2003 Islamic humanism New York Oxford University Press p 155 ISBN 0 19 513580 6 Goodman Lenn Evan 1992 Avicenna London Routledge p 188 ISBN 0 415 01929 X Hintikka Jaakko J Spade Paul Vincent History of logic Arabic logic Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 12 October 2007 Iqbal Mohammad 22 May 2013 THE SPIRIT OF MUSLIM CULTURE The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam Stanford University Press pp 99 115 ISBN 978 0 8047 8686 7 Marenbon John 2021 Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Introduction 3 The Logical Text Books Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint location link a b Hintikka Jaakko J Spade Paul Vincent History of logic Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 23 September 2022 Spade Paul Vincent Panaccio Claude 2019 William of Ockham The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 3 1 The Summa of Logic Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint location link Willman Marshall D 2022 Logic and Language in Early Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Introduction Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 11 March 2023 Rosker Jana S May 2015 Classical Chinese Logic Philosophy Compass Philosophy Compass 10 5 301 309 doi 10 1111 phc3 12226 Sarukkai Sundar Chakraborty Mihir Kumar 9 December 2022 Handbook of Logical Thought in India Springer Nature pp 117 8 ISBN 978 81 322 2577 5 Dasti Matthew R Nyaya Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy lead section 1b Inference Retrieved 12 March 2023 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint location link Emmanuel Steven M 23 November 2015 A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons pp 320 2 ISBN 978 1 119 14466 3 Vidyabhusana Satis Chandra 1988 A History of Indian Logic Ancient Mediaeval and Modern Schools Motilal Banarsidass Publisher p 221 ISBN 978 81 208 0565 1 Chakrabarti Kisor Kumar June 1976 Some Comparisons Between Frege s Logic and Navya Nyaya Logic Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 4 554 563 doi 10 2307 2106873 JSTOR 2106873 Haaparanta Leila 2009 1 Introduction The development of modern logic Oxford Oxford University Press pp 3 5 ISBN 978 0 19 513731 6 Haaparanta Leila 2009 1 Introduction The development of modern logic Oxford Oxford University Press pp 4 6 ISBN 978 0 19 513731 6 Ewald William 2019 The Emergence of First Order Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy lead paragraph 11 Conclusions Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 12 March 2023 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint location link Bibliography Edit Brookshear J Glenn 1989 Theory of computation formal languages automata and complexity Redwood City Calif Benjamin Cummings Pub Co ISBN 978 0 8053 0143 4 Cohen Robert S Wartofsky Marx W 6 December 2012 Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary Physics Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 010 2656 7 Gabbay Dov M Guenthner Franz 14 October 2011 Handbook of Philosophical Logic Volume I Elements of Classical Logic Springer Netherlands ISBN 978 94 009 7068 7 Haack Susan 15 December 1996 Deviant Logic Fuzzy Logic Beyond the Formalism University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 31133 3 Hintikka Jaakko Sandu Gabriel 2006 What is Logic In Jacquette D ed Philosophy of Logic North Holland pp 13 39 ISBN 978 0 444 51541 4 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Hofweber Thomas 2021 Logic and Ontology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Kline Morris 1972 Mathematical Thought From Ancient to Modern Times Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 506135 2 Kneale William Kneale Martha 1962 The Development of Logic Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824773 9 Smith Barry 1989 Logic and the Sachverhalt The Monist 72 1 52 69 doi 10 5840 monist19897212 Whitehead Alfred North Russell Bertrand 1910 Principia Mathematica Rough Draft Printing ISBN 978 1 60386 437 4 Further reading EditBarwise Jon 1989 Handbook of Mathematical Logic Burlington Elsevier ISBN 978 0 08 093364 1 Belnap Nuel 1977 A useful four valued logic In Dunn J Michael Epstein George eds Modern uses of multiple valued logic invited papers from the Fifth International Symposium on Multiple Valued Logic held at Indiana University Bloomington Indiana May 13 16 1975 Dordrecht Holland Springer ISBN 978 90 277 0747 5 Bochenski Jozef Maria 1959 A Precis of Mathematical Logic Springer Netherlands ISBN 978 94 017 0592 9 Bochenski Jozef Maria 1970 A History of Formal Logic Chelsea Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 8284 0238 5 Finkelstein David 6 December 2012 Matter Space and Logic In Cohen Robert S Wartofsky Marx W eds Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science 1966 1968 Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 010 3381 7 Harper Robert 2001 Logic Online Etymology Dictionary Archived from the original on 6 February 2009 Retrieved 8 May 2009 Hilbert David Ackermann Wilhelm 21 November 2013 Grundzuge der theoretischen Logik in German Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 662 41928 1 Hodges Wilfrid 29 November 2001 Logic Penguin Adult ISBN 978 0 14 100314 6 Hughes R I G 1993 A Philosophical Companion to First order Logic Hackett Publishing ISBN 978 0 87220 181 1 Mendelson Elliott 8 June 2015 Introduction to Mathematical Logic Sixth Edition Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 4822 3772 6 External links EditLogic at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Media from Commons News from Wikinews Quotations from Wikiquote a, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.