fbpx
Wikipedia

Baruch Spinoza

Baruch (de) Spinoza[b] (24 November 1632 – 21 February 1677),[17][18][19] mostly known under his Latinized pen name Benedictus de Spinoza,[20] was a leading seventeenth-century philosopher of Portuguese-Jewish origin,[21] resident in the Dutch Republic, and, as young man, permanently expelled from the Jewish community. After his expulsion, Spinoza lived an outwardly simple life without religious affiliation; the center of his life was philosophy. He had a dedicated clandestine circle of supporters, a philosophical sect, who met to discuss the writings he shared with them.[22]

Baruch Spinoza
Born
Baruch Espinosa[8] /
Bento de Spinosa[9]

(1632-11-24)24 November 1632
Died21 February 1677(1677-02-21) (aged 44)
The Hague, Dutch Republic
Other namesBenedictus de Spinoza
EducationTalmud Torah of Amsterdam[10]
(withdrew)[11]
University of Leiden
(no degree)[12]
Era17th-century philosophy
Age of Enlightenment
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolCartesianism[1]
Conceptualism[2]
Correspondence theory of truth[a][4]
Direct realism[5]
Foundationalism (according to Hegel)[6]
Rationalism
Psychological Egoism[7]
Spinozism
Main interests
Signature

One of the foremost thinkers of the Age of Reason,[18] modern biblical criticism,[23] and 17th-century Rationalism, including modern conceptions of the self and the universe,[24] Spinoza came to be considered "one of the most important philosophers—and certainly the most radical—of the early modern period".[25] He was influenced by Stoicism, Maimonides, Machiavelli, Descartes, Hobbes, and a variety of heterodox Christian thinkers of his day. [19]

He challenged the divine origin of the Hebrew Bible, the nature of God, and the earthly power wielded by religious authorities, Jewish and Christian alike. He was frequently called an "atheist" by contemporaries, although nowhere in his work does Spinoza argue against the existence of god.[26][27] His theological studies were inseparable from his thinking on politics; he is grouped with Hobbes, Locke, Leibniz, and Kant, who "helped establish the genre of political writing called secular theology."[28]

He died unexpectedly at age 44 in 1677. Supporters swiftly removed unpublished manuscripts from his lodgings to prevent their destruction by authorities; they prepared his works with speed and secrecy for posthumous publication in both their original Latin and Dutch. His works were banned by Dutch authorities and later the Roman Catholic Church.[29][30]

Spinoza's philosophy encompasses nearly every area of philosophical discourse,[31] including metaphysics, epistemology, political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science. It earned Spinoza an enduring reputation as one of the most important and original thinkers of the seventeenth century, influencing philosophers ever since. He has been called "the renegade Jew who gave us modernity."[32]

Biography edit

 
Spinoza lived where the Moses and Aaron Church is located now, and there is strong evidence that he may have been born there.[33]

Family background edit

Both sides of Spinoza’s family were originally Sephardic Jews from Iberia. His immediate family migrated to Amsterdam, arriving in the early seventeenth century, as Sephardic Jews in the Netherlands were openly establishing a community and could practice their religion without persecution by the Inquisition. The family in Portugal were New Christians, forced converts (conversos) to Catholicism. In Portugal in the early sixteenth century, the crown initially looked the other way as outwardly Catholic New Christians practiced Judaism in private. The Portuguese Inquisition was not even established until 1536. As the Inquisition increasingly cracked down, more New Christians continued practicing Judaism in secrecy.[34] A legacy of the era was that many in Spinoza's family had both Christian and Jewish names.

Spinoza's father Michael married his cousin Rachael d’Espinosa, daughter of his uncle Abraham d’Espinosa. Such a pattern of intermarriage was fairly common in the Jewish merchant community, keeping commercial and religious ties strong, and secrets safe. Marrying his cousin Rachel gave Michael access to his uncle/father-in-law's commercial network and capital.

When Michael’s wife died in 1627, he married again to Hannah Deborah. His second wife brought a dowry to the marriage, which should not have been absorbed into the capital of the family business. This marriage proved fruitful, with five children who survived to adulthood. Michael was a successful, although not enormously wealthy, merchant in Amsterdam, prominent in the community. [15]

The first-born of his second marriage was Miriam, followed by Isaac (1631-49). Isaac d'Espinosa was expected to take over as head of family and its commercial enterprise.

Baruch Espinosa,[8] the third child and second son, was born on 24 November 1632 in the Jodenbuurt in Amsterdam, Netherlands. He was named as per tradition for his maternal grandfather.

Spinoza’s younger brother Gabriel (Abraham) was born in 1634, followed by another sister, Rebecca (Ribca). Spinoza’s sister Miriam married Samuel de Caceres, but Miriam died shortly after giving birth. Following Jewish tradition, the widower Samuel married his former sister-in-law Rebecca. Spinoza's sisters' marriages to Caceres and his honored place in the Spinoza family as a scholar, meant that Spinoza's own ambitions as a scholar were shunted aside. There was discord between Spinoza and his sister and brother-in-law over inheritance, which played out later when Spinoza broke with rabbinic authorities and the Jewish community.[35]

His mother, Hannah Déborah, Michael's second wife, died when Baruch was only six years old. Michael remarried to give his five children a mother figure. The third marriage was childless so that Spinoza and his siblings had no half- or step-siblings.[36]

Spinoza was related in a complicated way with the highly controversial figure in the Amsterdam Portuguese Jewish community, Uriel da Costa (1585-1640), through his mother’s family in Porto. DaCosta was twice sanctioned by rabbinic authorities, and committed suicide in 1640, when Spinoza was eight years old. He might not have known of the scandalous family connection until he was an adolescent.[37]

School days edit

Baruch's family spoke Portuguese, as did other Sephardim. He studied Hebrew at school and heard it Jewish liturgy; he knew Dutch, which he likely learned informally. He learned Latin only later as a young man. [38]

His name in contemporary documents before his 1656 expulsion from the Jewish community is given as the Portuguese "Bento"; his Hebrew name "Baruch" was used in the religious context. Following his expulsion at age 23, he used the Latinized version of his name, "Benedictus de Spinoza."

Spinoza had a traditional upbringing for a Jewish boy, attending a local religious school, the Keter Torah yeshiva of the Amsterdam Talmud Torah congregation headed by the learned and traditional senior Rabbi Saul Levi Morteira.[39] Teachers also included the less traditional Rabbi Manasseh ben Israel. Since Spinoza never reached the level of advanced study of the Torah,[15] the senior rabbis were unlikely to have had Spinoza as their pupil. Spinoza's end of schooling was due the unexpected death of his elder brother Isaac, who had been actively involved in the family business.[15]

The family business and intellectual explorations edit

When Spinoza's father, Michael, died in 1654, Spinoza had been actively involved in the running of the family business. Although Spinoza duly recited Kaddish, the Jewish prayer of mourning, for eleven months as required by Jewish law,[15] there is evidence that his relations with his father had been chilly.[citation needed]

As with other merchants in Amsterdam, the Spinozas' business was affected by the First Anglo-Dutch War in the years of 1652-1654, as well as by some commercial deals that soured, and found itself in severe difficulty. In addition Michael had absorbed the dowry of Spinoza's mother as regular capital for his business, rather than keeping it separate for her children after her death. As such, the money was at risk for collection by Michael's many creditors.

Spinoza was just 21 when his father died, in Dutch law a legal minor until age 25. Nonetheless, he and his younger brother Gabriel (Abraham) formed a business partnership, attempting to continue the family business, including collecting unpaid debts owed by merchants to their father's estate.

Spinoza had continued to support the synagogue financially and attend services. When his sister Rebekah disputed his inheritance seeking it for herself, he sued her to seek a court judgment, won the case, but then renounced his claim to the court's judgment in his favor and assigned his inheritance to her.[40]

In March 1656, Spinoza filed suit with the Amsterdam municipal authorities to be declared an orphan, since he was still a legal minor. He sought relief through Dutch law, not through judgment by Jewish authorities, from whom he had become increasingly estranged, but not openly as yet. He won the civil lawsuit, which allowed him to inherit his mother's estate without it being subject to his father's creditors and devote himself chiefly to the study of philosophy, especially the system expounded by Descartes, and to optics.[41]

At some point between 1654 and 1658, Spinoza began to study Latin with Franciscus van den Enden. Van den Enden was a former Jesuit who was a political radical, and likely introduced Spinoza to scholastic and modern philosophy, including that of Descartes.[42][43] Spinoza adopted the Latin name Benedictus de Spinoza, began boarding with Van den Enden, and began teaching in his school.[42][43]

During this period Spinoza also became acquainted with the Collegiants, an anti-clerical sect of Remonstrants with tendencies towards rationalism, and with the liberal faction among the Mennonites who had existed for a century but were close to the Remonstrants.[44] Many of his friends belonged to dissident Christian groups which met regularly as discussion groups and which typically rejected the authority of established churches as well as traditional dogmas.[21] In the second half of the 1650s and the first half of the 1660s Spinoza became acquainted with several persons who would themselves emerge as unorthodox thinkers: this group, known as the Spinoza Circle,[45] included Pieter Balling , Jarig Jelles , Lodewijk Meyer, Johannes Bouwmeester and Adriaen Koerbagh.

Expulsion from the Jewish community edit

 
Spinoza and the Rabbis by Samuel Hirszenberg (1907)
 
Spinoza's name crossed out on the list of pupils of Ets Haim
 
Seal with Spinoza's initials and the Latin word meaning "caution"

Spinoza did not openly break with Jewish authorities until after his father's death in 1654. He challenged the prevailing dogmas of Judaism, and particularly the insistence on non-Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch. His break was not sudden; rather, it appears to have been the result of a lengthy internal struggle as well as a degree of filial piety. Nevertheless, after he was branded as a heretic, Spinoza's clashes with authority became more pronounced. He was later attacked on the steps of the synagogue by a knife-wielding assailant shouting "Heretic!" He was apparently quite shaken by this attack and for years kept (and wore) his torn cloak, unmended, as a reminder.[40]

On 27 July 1656, the Sepharadi Talmud Torah congregation of Amsterdam, which included Aboab de Fonseca,[46] issued a writ of herem (Hebrew: חרם‎, a kind of ban, shunning, ostracism, expulsion, or excommunication) against the 23-year-old Spinoza.[40][47][48] The Talmud Torah congregation issued censures routinely, on matters great and small, so such an edict was not unusual.[49]

The language of Spinoza's censure is unusually harsh, however, and does not appear in any other censure known to have been issued by the Portuguese Jewish community in Amsterdam.[50] The exact reason for expelling Spinoza is not stated.[51] The censure refers only to the "abominable heresies [horrendas heregias] that he practised and taught", to his "monstrous deeds", and to the testimony of witnesses "in the presence of the said Espinoza". There is no record of such testimony, but there appear to have been several likely reasons for the issuance of the censure.[52]

Spinoza began publicly expressing radical religious views that were highly controversial. Spinoza biographer Steven Nadler wrote: "No doubt he was giving utterance to just those ideas that would soon appear in his philosophical treatises. In those works, Spinoza denies the immortality of the soul; strongly rejects the notion of a providential god—the god of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob; and claims that the [Mosiac] Law was neither literally given by God nor any longer binding on Jews." [53]

The Amsterdam Jewish community was largely composed of Spanish and Portuguese conversos, "New Christians", who had respectively migrated from Spain via Portugal to escape the Spanish Inquisition and Portuguese conversos, following the establishment of the Portuguese Inquisition, with their children and grandchildren. Amsterdam was tolerant of religious diversity so long as it was practiced discreetly. Jews were not legally confined to a ghetto and the city presented economic opportunities for those willing to move.[54] This community must have been concerned to protect its reputation from any association with Spinoza lest his controversial views provide the basis for their own possible persecution or expulsion.[55]

There is little evidence that the Amsterdam municipal authorities were directly involved in Spinoza's censure itself. But "in 1619, the town council expressly ordered [the Portuguese Jewish community] to regulate their conduct and ensure that the members of the community kept to a strict observance of Jewish law."[56] Other evidence makes it clear that the danger of upsetting the civil authorities was never far from mind, such as bans adopted by the synagogue on public wedding or funeral processions and on discussing religious matters with Christians, lest such activity might "disturb the liberty we enjoy".[57] Thus, the issuance of Spinoza's censure was almost certainly, in part, an exercise in self-censorship by the Portuguese Jewish community in Amsterdam.[58]

 
Ban in Portuguese of Baruch Spinoza by his Portuguese Jewish synagogue community of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, 6 Av 5416 (27 July 1656)

It appears likely that Spinoza had already taken the initiative to separate himself from the Talmud Torah congregation and was vocally expressing his hostility to Judaism itself, also through his philosophical works, such as the Part I of Ethics.[59] He had probably stopped attending services at the synagogue, either after the lawsuit with his sister or after the knife attack on its steps. He might already have been voicing the view expressed later in his Theological-Political Treatise that the civil authorities should suppress Judaism as harmful to the Jews themselves. Either for financial or other reasons,[60][43] he had in any case effectively stopped contributing to the synagogue by March 1656.

He had also committed the "monstrous deed", contrary to the regulations of the synagogue and the views of some rabbinical authorities (including Maimonides), of filing suit in a civil court rather than with the synagogue authorities[41]—to renounce his father's heritage, no less. Upon being notified of the issuance of the censure, he is reported to have said: "Very well; this does not force me to do anything that I would not have done of my own accord, had I not been afraid of a scandal."[61] Thus, unlike most of the censure issued routinely by the Amsterdam congregation to discipline its members, the censure issued against Spinoza did not lead to repentance and so was never withdrawn. After the censure, Spinoza is said to have addressed an Apologia (defense), written in Spanish, to the elders of the synagogue, "in which he defended his views as orthodox, and condemned the rabbis for accusing him of 'horrible practices and other enormities' merely because he had neglected ceremonial observances".[61] This apologia does not survive, but some of its contents may later have been included in his Theological-Political Treatise.[61]

Spinoza's expulsion from the Jewish community did not lead to his conversion to Christianity. Spinoza used the Latinized name Benedictus de Spinoza and maintained a close association with the Collegiants (a liberal Protestant sect of Remonstrants) and Quakers,[62] even moved to a town near the Collegiants' headquarters, and was buried at the Protestant Church, Nieuwe Kerk, The Hague, since burial was a sectarian matter and he was ineligible to be buried in the Jewish cemetery.[63]

There is no evidence he maintained any sense of Jewish identity. "Spinoza did not envision secular Judaism. To be a secular and assimilated Jew is, in his view, nonsense."[64] Spinoza scholar Yirmiyahu Yovel raises the question of whether or not Spinoza could be categorized as the first "secular Jew" since he was still regarded as a Jew although he did not adhere to Jewish law or belong to the Jewish community. Yovel writes that Spinoza "exemplifies the situation of the modern Jew—secular, assimilationist, or national—without himself falling neatly into any of these categories. Countless Jews in the coming centuries were to find themselves in a similar predicament."[65]

Career as a philosopher edit

 
Study room of Spinoza in Rijnsburg

Spinoza spent his remaining 22 years writing and studying as a private scholar,[21] initially teaching in the school of his Latin tutor, Franciscus Van den Enden, with whom he boarded for a time, and later, upon leaving Amsterdam, earning a living as a lens grinder. He also received some financial assistance from supporters of his intellectual stance. After the herem, the Amsterdam municipal authorities expelled Spinoza from Amsterdam, "responding to the appeals of the rabbis, and also of the Calvinist clergy, who had been vicariously offended by the existence of a free thinker in the synagogue".

He spent a brief time in or near the village of Ouderkerk aan de Amstel, but returned soon afterwards to Amsterdam and lived there quietly for several years, giving private philosophy lessons and grinding lenses, before leaving the city in 1660 or 1661.[61] During this time in Amsterdam, Spinoza wrote his Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being, which he never published in his lifetime—assuming with good reason that it might get suppressed. Two Dutch translations of it survive, discovered about 1810.[61]

In 1660 or 1661, Spinoza moved from Amsterdam to Rijnsburg (near Leiden), the center of Dutch Remonstrants known as the Collegiants.[66] In Rijnsburg, he began work on his Descartes' "Principles of Philosophy" as well as on his masterpiece, the Ethics. In 1663, he returned briefly to Amsterdam, where he finished and published Descartes' "Principles of Philosophy", the only work published in his lifetime under his own name, and then moved the same year to Voorburg.

In Voorburg, Spinoza continued work on his magnum opus, eventually entitled Ethics, and corresponded with scientists, philosophers, and theologians throughout Europe. He published in Latin, anonymously, and with false printer information Theological-Political Treatise (TTP) in 1670, in defense of secular and constitutional government, and in support of Jan de Witt, the Grand Pensionary of Holland, against the Stadtholder, the Prince of Orange.

Leibniz visited Spinoza and claimed that Spinoza's life was in danger when supporters of the Prince of Orange murdered de Witt in 1672.[67] While the TTP was published anonymously, the work did not long remain so, and de Witt's enemies characterized it as "forged in Hell by a renegade Jew and the Devil, and issued with the knowledge of Jan de Witt". It was condemned in 1673 by the Synod of the Dutch Reformed Church and formally banned in 1674.[68]

In 1670, Spinoza moved to The Hague, where he lived on a small pension from Jan de Witt and a small annuity from the brother of his dead friend, Simon de Vries.[69] He worked on the Ethics, wrote an unfinished Hebrew grammar, began his Political Treatise (TP), left unfinished at his death, wrote two scientific essays ("On the Rainbow" and "On the Calculation of Chances"), and began a Dutch translation of the Bible (which he later destroyed).[69] Spinoza was offered the chair of philosophy at the University of Heidelberg, but he refused it, perhaps because of the possibility that it might in some way curb his freedom of thought.[70]

Spinoza also corresponded with Peter Serrarius, a radical Protestant and millenarian merchant. Serrarius was a patron to Spinoza after Spinoza was expelled from the Jewish community. He acted as an intermediary for Spinoza's correspondence, sending and receiving letters of the philosopher to and from third parties. Spinoza and Serrarius maintained their relationship until Serrarius' death in 1669.[71]

By the beginning of the 1660s, Spinoza's name became more widely known. The Secretary of the British Royal Society Henry Oldenburg paid him visits and became a correspondent with Spinoza for the rest of his life.[72] In 1676, Leibniz came to the Hague to discuss the unpublished Ethics, Spinoza's principal philosophical work, parts of which apparently had circulated in manuscript form.[73]

Lens-grinding and optics edit

Spinoza earned a modest living from lens-grinding and instrument making, yet he was involved in important optical investigations of the day while living in Voorburg, through correspondence and friendships with scientist Christiaan Huygens and mathematician Johannes Hudde, including debate over microscope design with Huygens, favouring small objectives[74] and collaborating on calculations for a prospective 40-foot (12 m) focal length telescope which would have been one of the largest in Europe at the time.[75] He was known for making not just lenses but also telescopes and microscopes.[76] The quality of Spinoza's lenses was much praised by Christiaan Huygens, among others.[77] In fact, his technique and instruments were so esteemed that Constantijn Huygens ground a "clear and bright" telescope lens with focal length of 42 feet (13 m) in 1687 from one of Spinoza's grinding dishes, ten years after his death.[78] He was said by anatomist Theodor Kerckring to have produced an "excellent" microscope, the quality of which was the foundation of Kerckring's anatomy claims.[79] During his time as a lens and instrument maker, he was also supported by small but regular donations from close friends.[21]

Death and burial edit

 
Burial monument of Spinoza at the churchyard of the Nieuwe Kerk (The Hague).

Spinoza's health began to fail in 1676, dying in The Hague on 21 February 1677 at the age of 44, attended by a physician friend, Georg Herman Schuller. Although he had been ill with some form of lung affliction, described as "ex phthisi [from consumption]", perhaps complicated by silicosis brought on by grinding glass lenses,[80] his death on that particular day was unexpected by himself or his landlord and landlady with whom he lived, and he died without leaving a will.[81][82] His personal belongings and papers, most importantly his unpublished manuscripts, were stored in a cabinet attached to his writing desk, and were taken away for safekeeping from seizure by those wishing to suppress his writings. They do not appear in the inventory of his possessions at death. There were assertions that he had repented his philosophical stances on his deathbed, but all credible evidence points to his dying unrepentant and in tranquility.[83] The first biography of Spinoza[84] by Lutheran preacher Johannes Colerus (1647-1707), was prompted to investigate Spinoza's last days.[85]

Spinoza was buried in the Nieuwe Kerk (New Church) on the Spui four days after his death, on 25 February, inside the church, with six others in the same vault. At the time there was no memorial plaque for Spinoza. In the 18th century, the vault was emptied and the remains disposed of, with the "remnants scattered over the earth of the churchyard." The memorial plaque visitors now see is outside, where some of his remains are part of the churchyard's soil.[86]

Writings edit

Spinoza published little in his lifetime and most of his formal writings were in Latin, which would have reached only a small number of readers. His supporters published his works posthumously, in Latin and in Dutch, with other translations to European languages following. A descriptive bibliography has been published that contextualizes all aspects of the publication history of Spinoza's writings from manuscript to print.[87]

The reaction to the anonymously published work, Theologico-Political Treatise (TTP)(1670), was extremely unfavorable. Spinoza abstained from publishing further, but his writings circulated among his supporters during his lifetime. Wary and independent, he wore a signet ring which he used to mark his letters and which was engraved with the word caute (Latin for "cautiously") underneath a rose, itself a symbol of secrecy.[88]

The Ethics and all other works, apart from the Descartes' Principles of Philosophy and the Theologico-Political Treatise, were published after his 1677 death. The Opera Posthuma was edited by his friends in secrecy to prevent confiscation and destruction of manuscripts. The Ethics contains many still-unresolved obscurities and is written with a forbidding mathematical structure modeled on Euclid's geometry[21] and has been described as a "superbly cryptic masterwork".[89]

Major publications edit

  • c. 1660. Korte Verhandeling van God, de mensch en deszelvs welstand (A Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being).
  • 1662. Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione (On the Improvement of the Understanding) (unfinished).
  • 1663. Principia philosophiae cartesianae (The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, translated by Samuel Shirley, with an Introduction and Notes by Steven Barbone and Lee Rice, Indianapolis, 1998). Gallica (in Latin).
  • 1670. Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (A Theologico-Political Treatise).
  • 1675–76. Tractatus Politicus (unfinished) ()
  • 1677. Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata (The Ethics, finished 1674, but published posthumously)
  • 1677. Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae (Hebrew Grammar).[90]
  • Morgan, Michael L. (ed.), 2002. Spinoza: Complete Works, with the Translation of Samuel Shirley, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-87220-620-5.
  • Edwin Curley (ed.), 1985, 2016. The Collected Works of Spinoza (two volumes), Princeton: Princeton University Press.(Not including the Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae).
  • Spruit, Leen and Pina Totaro, 2011. The Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza's Ethica, Leiden: Brill.

Correspondence edit

 
Letter from Spinoza to Leibniz, with his BdS seal

Few letters are extant for such an important intellectual figure and none before 1661. Spinoza engaged in correspondence from December 1664 to June 1665 with Willem van Blijenbergh, an amateur Calvinist theologian, who questioned Spinoza on the definition of evil. Later in 1665, Spinoza notified Oldenburg that he had started to work on a new book, the Theologico-Political Treatise, published in 1670. Leibniz disagreed harshly with Spinoza in his own manuscript "Refutation of Spinoza",[91] but he is also known to have met with Spinoza on at least one occasion[72][92] (as mentioned above), and his own work bears some striking resemblances to specific important parts of Spinoza's philosophy (see: Monadology).

In a letter, written in December 1675 and sent to Albert Burgh, who wanted to defend Catholicism, Spinoza clearly explained his view of both Catholicism and Islam. He stated that both religions are made "to deceive the people and to constrain the minds of men". He also states that Islam far surpasses Catholicism in doing so.[93][94] The Tractatus de Deo, Homine, ejusque Felicitate (Treatise on God, man and his happiness) was one of the last Spinoza's works to be published, between 1851[95] and 1862.[96]

Philosophy edit

Spinoza's philosophy is explicated in his two major publications originally written in Latin, the Tratacus Theologico-Politicus (TTP) (1670) and the Ethics, published posthumously in Latin and Dutch.

Tractatus Theologico-Politicus edit

Despite its being published in Latin rather than a vernacular language, this 1670 treatise published in Spinoza's lifetime caused a huge reaction, described as "one of the most significant events in European intellectual history,"[97] with a prolonged furore "that has no parallel in early modern intellectual history."[98]

Ethics edit

The Ethics has been associated with that of Leibniz and René Descartes as part of the rationalist school of thought,[92] which includes the assumption that ideas correspond to reality perfectly, in the same way that mathematics is supposed to be an exact representation of the world. The writings of René Descartes have been described as "Spinoza's starting point".[89] Spinoza's first publication was his 1663 geometric exposition of proofs using Euclid's model with definitions and axioms of Descartes' Principles of Philosophy. Following Descartes, Spinoza aimed to understand truth through logical deductions from 'clear and distinct ideas', a process which always begins from the 'self-evident truths' of axioms.[99]

Metaphysics edit

Spinoza's metaphysics consists of one thing, substance, and its modifications (modes). Early in The Ethics Spinoza argues that there is only one substance, which is absolutely infinite, self-caused, and eternal. He calls this substance "God", or "Nature". In fact, he takes these two terms to be synonymous (in the Latin the phrase he uses is "Deus sive Natura"). For Spinoza the whole of the natural universe is made of one substance, God, or, what is the same, Nature, and its modifications (modes).

It cannot be overemphasized how the rest of Spinoza's philosophy—his philosophy of mind, his epistemology, his psychology, his moral philosophy, his political philosophy, and his philosophy of religion—flows more or less directly from the metaphysical underpinnings in Part I of the Ethics.[100]

Substance, attributes, and modes edit

These are the fundamental concepts with which Spinoza sets forth a vision of Being, illuminated by his awareness of God. They may seem strange at first sight. To the question "What is?" he replies: "Substance, its attributes, and modes".

Following Maimonides, Spinoza defined substance as "that which is in itself and is conceived through itself", meaning that it can be understood without any reference to anything external.[102] Being conceptually independent also means that the same thing is ontologically independent, depending on nothing else for its existence and being the 'cause of itself' (causa sui).[102] A mode is something which cannot exist independently but rather must do so as part of something else on which it depends, including properties (for example colour), relations (such as size) and individual things.[103] Modes can be further divided into 'finite' and 'infinite' ones, with the latter being evident in every finite mode (he gives the examples of "motion" and "rest").[104] The traditional understanding of an attribute in philosophy is similar to Spinoza's modes, though he uses that word differently.[103] To him, an attribute is "that which the intellect perceives as constituting the essence of substance", and there are possibly an infinite number of them.[105] It is the essential nature which is "attributed" to reality by intellect.[106]

 
Probable portrait of Spinoza, by Barend Graat, 1666.

Spinoza defined God as "a substance consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence", and since "no cause or reason" can prevent such a being from existing, it therefore must exist.[106] This is a form of the ontological argument, which is claimed to prove the existence of God, but Spinoza went further in stating that it showed that only God exists.[107] Accordingly, he stated that "Whatever is, is in God, and nothing can exist or be conceived without God".[107] This means that God is identical with the universe, an idea which he encapsulated in the phrase "Deus sive Natura" ('God or Nature'), which has been interpreted by some as atheism or pantheism.[108] God can be known either through the attribute of extension or the attribute of thought.[109] Thought and extension represent giving complete accounts of the world in mental or physical terms.[110] To this end, he says that "the mind and the body are one and the same thing, which is conceived now under the attribute of thought, now under the attribute of extension".[111]

After stating his proof for God's existence, Spinoza addresses who "God" is. Spinoza believed that God is "the sum of the natural and physical laws of the universe and certainly not an individual entity or creator".[112] Spinoza attempts to prove that God is just the substance of the universe by first stating that substances do not share attributes or essences and then demonstrating that God is a "substance" with an infinite number of attributes, thus the attributes possessed by any other substances must also be possessed by God. Therefore, God is just the sum of all the substances of the universe. God is the only substance in the universe, and everything is a part of God. This view was described by Charles Hartshorne as Classical Pantheism.[113]

Spinoza argues that "things could not have been produced by God in any other way or in any other order than is the case".[114] Therefore, concepts such as 'freedom' and 'chance' have little meaning.[108] This picture of Spinoza's determinism is illuminated in Ethics: "the infant believes that it is by free will that it seeks the breast; the angry boy believes that by free will he wishes vengeance; the timid man thinks it is with free will he seeks flight; the drunkard believes that by a free command of his mind he speaks the things which when sober he wishes he had left unsaid. … All believe that they speak by a free command of the mind, whilst, in truth, they have no power to restrain the impulse which they have to speak."[115] In his letter to G. H. Schuller (Letter 58), he wrote: "men are conscious of their desire and unaware of the causes by which [their desires] are determined."[116] He also held that knowledge of true causes of passive emotion can transform it into an active emotion, thus anticipating one of the key ideas of Sigmund Freud's psychoanalysis.[117]

According to Professor Eric Schliesser, Spinoza was skeptical regarding the possibility of knowledge of nature and as a consequence at odds with scientists like Galileo and Huygens.[118]

Causality edit

Though the principle of sufficient reason is most commonly associated with Gottfried Leibniz,[119] it is arguably found in its strongest form in Spinoza's philosophy.[120] Within the context of Spinoza's philosophical system, the principle can be understood to unify causation and explanation.[121] What this means is that for Spinoza, questions regarding the reason why a given phenomenon is the way it is (or exists) are always answerable, and are always answerable in terms of the relevant cause(s). This constitutes a rejection of teleological, or final causation, except possibly in a more restricted sense for human beings.[122][page needed][121] Given this, Spinoza's views regarding causality and modality begin to make much more sense.

Spinoza has also been described as an "Epicurean materialist",[89] specifically in reference to his opposition to Cartesian mind-body dualism. This view was held by Epicureans before him, as they believed that atoms with their probabilistic paths were the only substance that existed fundamentally.[123][124] Spinoza, however, deviated significantly from Epicureans by adhering to strict determinism, much like the Stoics before him, in contrast to the Epicurean belief in the probabilistic path of atoms, which is more in line with contemporary thought on quantum mechanics.[123][125]

The emotions edit

One thing which seems, on the surface, to distinguish Spinoza's view of the emotions from both Descartes' and Hume's pictures of them is that he takes the emotions to be cognitive in some important respect. Jonathan Bennett claims that "Spinoza mainly saw emotions as caused by cognitions. [However] he did not say this clearly enough and sometimes lost sight of it entirely."[126] Spinoza provides several demonstrations which purport to show truths about how human emotions work. The picture presented is, according to Bennett, "unflattering, coloured as it is by universal egoism".[127]

Ethical philosophy edit

Spinoza's notion of blessedness figures centrally in his ethical philosophy. Blessedness (or salvation or freedom), Spinoza thinks,

consists...in a constant and eternal love of God, or in God's love for men.(E5P36s)[122][page needed]

And this means, as Jonathan Bennett explains, that "Spinoza wants "blessedness" to stand for the most elevated and desirable state one could possibly be in."[128] Here, understanding what is meant by 'most elevated and desirable state' requires understanding Spinoza's notion of conatus (read: striving, but not necessarily with any teleological baggage) and that "perfection" refers not to (moral) value, but to completeness. Given that individuals are identified as mere modifications of the infinite Substance, it follows that no individual can ever be fully complete, i.e., perfect, or blessed. Absolute perfection, is, as noted above, reserved solely for Substance. Nevertheless, mere modes can attain a lesser form of blessedness, namely, that of pure understanding of oneself as one really is, i.e., as a definite modification of Substance in a certain set of relationships with everything else in the universe. That this is what Spinoza has in mind can be seen at the end of the Ethics, in E5P24 and E5P25, wherein Spinoza makes two final key moves, unifying the metaphysical, epistemological, and ethical propositions he has developed over the course of the work. In E5P24, he links the understanding of particular things to the understanding of God, or Substance; in E5P25, the conatus of the mind is linked to the third kind of knowledge (Intuition). From here, it is a short step to the connection of Blessedness with the amor dei intellectualis ("intellectual love of God").

 
Engraving of Spinoza, captioned in Latin, "A Jew and an atheist"; he vehemently denied being an atheist.

Pantheism edit

Spinoza was considered to be an atheist because he used the word "God" [Deus] to signify a concept that was different from that of traditional Judeo–Christian monotheism. "Spinoza expressly denies personality and consciousness to God; he has neither intelligence, feeling, nor will; he does not act according to purpose, but everything follows necessarily from his nature, according to law...."[129] Thus, Spinoza's cool, indifferent God differs from the concept of an anthropomorphic, fatherly God who cares about humanity.[130]

In 1785, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi published a condemnation of Spinoza's pantheism, after Gotthold Lessing was thought to have confessed on his deathbed to being a "Spinozist", which was the equivalent in his time of being called an atheist. Jacobi claimed that Spinoza's doctrine was pure materialism, because all Nature and God are said to be nothing but extended substance. This, for Jacobi, was the result of Enlightenment rationalism and it would finally end in absolute atheism. Moses Mendelssohn disagreed with Jacobi, saying that there is no actual difference between theism and pantheism. The issue became a major intellectual and religious concern for European civilization at the time.

The attraction of Spinoza's philosophy to late 18th-century Europeans was that it provided an alternative to materialism, atheism, and deism. Three of Spinoza's ideas strongly appealed to them:

  • the unity of all that exists;
  • the regularity of all that happens;
  • the identity of spirit and nature.[131]

By 1879, Spinoza's pantheism was praised by many, but was considered by some to be alarming and dangerously inimical.[132]

Spinoza's "God or Nature" (Deus sive Natura) provided a living, natural God, in contrast to Isaac Newton's first cause argument and the dead mechanism of Julien Offray de La Mettrie's (1709–1751) work, Man a Machine (L'homme machine). Coleridge and Shelley saw in Spinoza's philosophy a religion of nature.[21] Novalis called him the "God-intoxicated man".[89][133] Spinoza inspired the poet Shelley to write his essay "The Necessity of Atheism".[89]

It is a widespread belief that Spinoza equated God with the material universe. He has therefore been called the "prophet"[134] and "prince"[135] and most eminent expounder of pantheism. More specifically, in a letter to Henry Oldenburg he states, "as to the view of certain people that I identify God with Nature (taken as a kind of mass or corporeal matter), they are quite mistaken".[136] For Spinoza, the universe (cosmos) is a mode under two attributes of Thought and Extension. God has infinitely many other attributes which are not present in the world.

According to German philosopher Karl Jaspers (1883–1969), when Spinoza wrote Deus sive Natura (Latin for 'God or Nature'), Spinoza meant God was natura naturans (nature doing what nature does; literally, 'nature naturing'), not natura naturata (nature already created; literally, 'nature natured'). Jaspers believed that Spinoza, in his philosophical system, did not mean to say that God and Nature are interchangeable terms, but rather that God's transcendence was attested by his infinitely many attributes, and that two attributes known by humans, namely Thought and Extension, signified God's immanence.[137] Even God under the attributes of thought and extension cannot be identified strictly with our world. That world is of course "divisible"; it has parts. But Spinoza said, "no attribute of a substance can be truly conceived from which it follows that the substance can be divided", meaning that one cannot conceive an attribute in a way that leads to division of substance. He also said, "a substance which is absolutely infinite is indivisible" (Ethics, Part I, Propositions 12 and 13).[138] Following this logic, our world should be considered as a mode under two attributes of thought and extension. Therefore, according to Jaspers, the pantheist formula "One and All" would apply to Spinoza only if the "One" preserves its transcendence and the "All" were not interpreted as the totality of finite things.[137]

Martial Guéroult (1891–1976) suggested the term "panentheism", rather than "pantheism" to describe Spinoza's view of the relation between God and the world. The world is not God, but it is, in a strong sense, "in" God. Not only do finite things have God as their cause; they cannot be conceived without God.[138] However, American panentheist philosopher Charles Hartshorne (1897–2000) insisted on the term Classical Pantheism to describe Spinoza's view.[113]

According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spinoza's God is an "infinite intellect" (Ethics 2p11c) — all knowing (2p3), and capable of loving both himself—and us, insofar as we are part of his perfection (5p35c). And if the mark of a personal being is that it is one towards which we can entertain personal attitudes, then we should note too that Spinoza recommends amor intellectualis dei (the intellectual love of God) as the supreme good for man (5p33). However, the matter is complex. Spinoza's God does not have free will (1p32c1), he does not have purposes or intentions (1 appendix), and Spinoza insists that "neither intellect nor will pertain to the nature of God" (1p17s1). Moreover, while we may love God, we need to remember that God is really not the kind of being who could ever love us back. "He who loves God cannot strive that God should love him in return", says Spinoza (5p19).[139]

Steven Nadler suggests that settling the question of Spinoza's atheism or pantheism depends on an analysis of attitudes. If pantheism is associated with religiosity, then Spinoza is not a pantheist, since Spinoza believes that the proper stance to take towards God is not one of reverence or religious awe, but instead one of objective study and reason, since taking the religious stance would leave one open to the possibility of error and superstition.[140]

Legacy edit

Spinoza's ideas have had a major impact on intellectual debates from the seventeenth century to the current era. His biographer Jonathan I. Israel contends that "No leading figure of the post-1750 later Enlightenment, for example, or the nineteenth century, was engaged with the philosophy of Descartes, Hobbes, Bayle, Locke, or Leibniz, to the degree leading figures such as Lessing, Goethe, Kant, Hegel, Fichte, Schelling, Heine, George Eliot, and Nietzsche, remained preoccupied throughout their creative lives with Spinoza."[141] On the so-called Jewish question, Spinoza influenced Moses Mendelsohn and Kant, as well as on subsequent thinkers, including Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud.[142] Hegel said, "The fact is that Spinoza is made a testing-point in modern philosophy, so that it may really be said: You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all."[143]

 
A Dutch commemorative coin issued on the 250th death anniversary of Spinoza, 1927.

Similarities between Spinoza's philosophy and Eastern philosophical traditions have been discussed by many authors. The 19th-century German Sanskritist Theodor Goldstücker was one of the early figures to notice the similarities between Spinoza's religious conceptions and the Vedanta tradition of India, writing that Spinoza's thought was "... so exact a representation of the ideas of the Vedanta, that we might have suspected its founder to have borrowed the fundamental principles of his system from the Hindus, did his biography not satisfy us that he was wholly unacquainted with their doctrines..."[144][145] Max Müller also noted the striking similarities between Vedanta and the system of Spinoza, equating the Brahman in Vedanta to Spinoza's 'Substantia.'[146]

When George Santayana graduated from college, he published an essay, "The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza", in The Harvard Monthly.[147] Later, he wrote an introduction to Spinoza's Ethics and "De Intellectus Emendatione".[148] In 1932, Santayana was invited to present an essay (published as "Ultimate Religion")[149] at a meeting at The Hague celebrating the tricentennial of Spinoza's birth. In Santayana's autobiography, he characterized Spinoza as his "master and model" in understanding the naturalistic basis of morality.[150]

Philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein evoked Spinoza with the title (suggested to him by G. E. Moore) of the English translation of his first definitive philosophical work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, an allusion to Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. Elsewhere, Wittgenstein deliberately borrowed the expression sub specie aeternitatis from Spinoza (Notebooks, 1914–16, p. 83). The structure of his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus does have some structural affinities with Spinoza's Ethics (though, admittedly, not with the Spinoza's Tractatus) in erecting complex philosophical arguments upon basic logical assertions and principles. Furthermore, in propositions 6.4311 and 6.45 he alludes to a Spinozian understanding of eternity and interpretation of the religious concept of eternal life, stating, "If by eternity is understood not eternal temporal duration, but timelessness, then he lives eternally who lives in the present." (6.4311) "The contemplation of the world sub specie aeterni is its contemplation as a limited whole." (6.45)

Spinoza's philosophy played an important role in the development of post-war French philosophy. Many of these philosophers "used Spinoza to erect a bulwark against the nominally irrationalist tendencies of phenomenology", which was associated with the dominance of Hegel, Martin Heidegger, and Edmund Husserl in France at that time.[151] Louis Althusser, as well as his colleagues such as Étienne Balibar, saw in Spinoza a philosophy which could lead Marxism out of what they considered to be flaws in its original formulation, particularly its reliance upon Hegel's conception of the dialectic, as well as Spinoza's concept of immanent causality. Antonio Negri, in exile in France for much of this period, also wrote a number of books on Spinoza, most notably The Savage Anomaly (1981) in his own reconfiguration of Italian Autonomia Operaia. Other notable French scholars of Spinoza in this period included Alexandre Matheron, Martial Gueroult, André Tosel, and Pierre Macherey, the last of whom published a widely read and influential five-volume commentary on Spinoza's Ethics, which has been described as "a monument of Spinoza commentary".[152] His philosophical accomplishments and moral character prompted Gilles Deleuze in his doctoral thesis (1968) to name him "the prince of philosophers".[153][154] Deleuze's interpretation of Spinoza's philosophy was highly influential among French philosophers, especially in restoring to prominence the political dimension of Spinoza's thought.[155] Deleuze published two books on Spinoza and gave numerous lectures on Spinoza in his capacity as a professor at the University of Paris VIII. His own work was deeply influenced by Spinoza's philosophy, particularly the concepts of immanence and univocity. Marilena de Souza Chaui described Deleuze's Expressionism in Philosophy (1968) as a "revolutionary work for its discovery of expression as a central concept in Spinoza's philosophy."[155]

Albert Einstein named Spinoza as the philosopher who exerted the most influence on his world view (Weltanschauung). Spinoza equated God (infinite substance) with Nature, consistent with Einstein's belief in an impersonal deity. In 1929, Einstein was asked in a telegram by Rabbi Herbert S. Goldstein whether he believed in God. Einstein responded by telegram: "I believe in Spinoza's God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists, not in a God who concerns himself with the fates and actions of human beings."[156][157]

Leo Strauss dedicated his first book, Spinoza's Critique of Religion, to an examination of the latter's ideas. In the book, Strauss identified Spinoza as part of the tradition of Enlightenment rationalism that eventually produced Modernity. Moreover, he identifies Spinoza and his works as the beginning of Jewish Modernity.[89] More recently Jonathan Israel argued that, from 1650 to 1750, Spinoza was "the chief challenger of the fundamentals of revealed religion, received ideas, tradition, morality, and what was everywhere regarded, in absolutist and non-absolutist states alike, as divinely constituted political authority."[158]

 
Statue (2008) of Spinoza by Nicolas Dings, Amsterdam, Zwanenburgwal, with inscription "The objective of the state is freedom" (translation, quote from Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, 1677)

Spinoza is an important historical figure in the Netherlands, where his portrait was featured prominently on the Dutch 1000-guilder banknote, legal tender until the euro was introduced in 2002. The highest and most prestigious scientific award of the Netherlands is named the Spinozaprijs (Spinoza prize). Spinoza was included in a 50 theme canon that attempts to summarise the history of the Netherlands.[159] In 2014 a copy of Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus was presented to the Chair of the Dutch Parliament, and shares a shelf with the Bible and the Quran.[160]

Modern era edit

Reconsideration of Enlightenment edit

There has been a renewed debate in modern times about Spinoza's excommunication among Israeli politicians, rabbis and Jewish press, with many calling for the cherem to be reversed.[161] Since such a cherem can only be rescinded by the congregation that issued it, and the chief rabbi of that community,[c] Haham Pinchas Toledano, declined to do so, citing Spinoza's "preposterous ideas, where he was tearing apart the very fundamentals of our religion",[162] the Amsterdam Jewish community organised a symposium in December 2015 to discuss lifting the cherem, inviting scholars from around the world to form an advisory committee at the meeting. However, the rabbi of the congregation ruled that it should hold, on the basis that he had no greater wisdom than his predecessors, and that Spinoza's views had not become less problematic over time.[161]

Memory and memorials edit

  • Spinoza Lyceum, a high school in Amsterdam South was named after Spinoza. There is also a 3 metre tall marble statute of him on the grounds of the school carved by Hildo Krop.[163]
  • The Spinoza Havurah (a Humanistic Jewish community) was named in Spinoza's honor.[164]
  • The Spinoza Foundation Monument has a statute of Spinoza located in front of the Amsterdam City Hall (at Zwanenburgwal) [165] It was created by Dutch sculptor Nicolas Dings and was erected in 2008.[166][167]

See also edit

References edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ However, Spinoza has also been interpreted as a defender of the coherence theory of truth.[3]
  2. ^ Baruch Spinoza is pronounced, in English, /bəˈrk spɪˈnzə/;[13] in Dutch, [baːˈrux spɪˈnoːzaː]; and, in Portuguese, [ðɨ ʃpiˈnɔzɐ]. He was born Bento (Portuguese) or Baruch (Hebrew) holding the family name Espinosa.[8] In most of the documents and records contemporary with Spinoza's years within the Jewish community, his name is given as the Portuguese Bento.[14][15][16] In Hebrew, without transliteration, his full name is written ברוך שפינוזה‎. His given name, Baruch/Bento, means "Blessed" in Hebrew and Portuguese respectively. Later, as an author and correspondent, he was known in Latin in which he wrote. Benedictus de Spinoza, was his preferred name also of his signature, with the first name sometimes anglicized as Benedict.
  3. ^ Portugees-Israëlietische Gemeente te Amsterdam (Portuguese-Israelite commune of Amsterdam)

References edit

  1. ^ Melamed, Yitzhak Y., ed. (2015). . Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-997168-8. Archived from the original on 1 January 2023.Chapter 7
  2. ^ Stefano Di Bella, Tad M. Schmaltz (eds.), The Problem of Universals in Early Modern Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2017, p. 64 "there is a strong case to be made that Spinoza was a conceptualist about universals..."
  3. ^ "The Coherence Theory of Truth (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". from the original on 1 November 2019. Retrieved 1 November 2019.
  4. ^ David, Marian (28 May 2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Correspondence theory of truth – The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 May 2019 – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  5. ^ Michael Della Rocca (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza, Oxford University Press, 2017, p. 288.
  6. ^ James Kreines, Reason in the World: Hegel's Metaphysics and Its Philosophical Appeal, Oxford University Press, 2015, p. 25: "Spinoza's foundationalism (Hegel argues) threatens to eliminate all determinate reality, leaving only one indeterminate substance."
  7. ^ "Spinoza's Psychological Theory". Spinoza's Psychological Theory – The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2022.
  8. ^ a b c Nadler 1999, p. 45.
  9. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 119.
  10. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 64.
  11. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 65.
  12. ^ Steven Nadler, Spinoza and Medieval Jewish Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, 2014, p. 27: "Spinoza attended lectures and anatomical dissections at the University of Leiden..."
  13. ^ "Spinoza". Collins English Dictionary. HarperCollins. Retrieved 27 April 2019.
  14. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 42.
  15. ^ a b c d e Nadler 2001, p. 1.
  16. ^ Nadler, Steven (2022), "Baruch Spinoza", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 20 November 2022
  17. ^ Jonathan Israel in his various works on the Enlightenment, Spinoza, Life & Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2023
  18. ^ a b Richard H. Popkin, Benedict de Spinoza at the Encyclopædia Britannica
  19. ^ a b Dutton, Blake D. "Benedict De Spinoza (1632–1677)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 7 July 2019.
  20. ^ "Why Spinoza Was Excommunicated". The National Endowment for the Humanities. Retrieved 13 April 2023.
  21. ^ a b c d e f Gottlieb, Anthony (18 July 1999). "God Exists, Philosophically (review of Spinoza: A Life by Steven Nadler)". Books. The New York Times. Retrieved 7 September 2009.
  22. ^ Israel, Spinoza, Life and Legacy, 322, 327-51
  23. ^ Yovel, Yirmiyahu (1992). Spinoza and Other Heretics: The Adventures of Immanence. Princeton University Press. p. 3. ISBN 0691020795.
  24. ^ "Destroyer and Builder". The New Republic. 3 May 2012. Retrieved 7 March 2013.
  25. ^ Nadler, Steven (16 April 2020). "Baruch Spinoza". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  26. ^ Stewart 2007, p. 352.
  27. ^ Simkins, James (2014). "On the Development of Spinoza's Account of Human Religion". Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies. 5 (1).
  28. ^ Smith, Steven B. Spinoza, Liberalism, and the Question of Jewish Identity. New Haven: Yale University Press 1997, 2
  29. ^ Jonathan Israel, "The Banning of Spinoza's Works in the Dutch Republic (1670–1678)", in: Wiep van Bunge and Wim Klever (eds.) Disguised and Overt Spinozism around 1700 (Leiden, 1996), pp. 3–14 (online 28 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine).
  30. ^ P. TOTARO, "The Young Spinoza and the Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza's Ethics", in The Young Spinoza. A Metaphysician in the Making, ed. by Yitzhak Y. Melamed, New York, Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. 319–332 at 321–2.
  31. ^ Hübner, Karolina (2022), "Spinoza's Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 4 April 2023
  32. ^ Goldstein, Rebecca, Betraying Spinoza: The Renegade Jew who Gave Us Modernity. New York: Schocken 2009 ISBN 978-0805211597
  33. ^ Die Lebensgeschichte Spinozas. Zweite, stark erweiterte und vollständig neu kommentierte Auflage der Ausgabe von Jakob Freudenthal 1899. M. e. Bibliographie hg. v. Manfred Walther unter Mitarbeit v. Michael Czelinski. 2 Bde. Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt: frommann-holzboog, 2006. (Specula 4,1 – 4,2.) Erläuterungen. p. 98, 119.
  34. ^ Rowland, Robert, "New Christian, Marrano, Jew" in The Jews and the Expansion of Europe to the West, 1450-1800, Paolo Bernardini and Norman Fiering, eds. New York: Berghahn Books 2001, 131-37
  35. ^ Israel, Spinoza, “Spinoza family tree”, figure 4.1, p. 84
  36. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 23.
  37. ^ Israel, Spinoza 90
  38. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 47.
  39. ^ Nadler 1999, pp. 64–65.
  40. ^ a b c Scruton 2002, p. 21.
  41. ^ a b Nadler 2001, p. 25.
  42. ^ a b Nadler 2001, p. 27.
  43. ^ a b c Nadler 2001, p. 189.
  44. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 20.
  45. ^ Meinsma, K.O. Spinoza et son cercle: Étude critique historique sur les héterodoxes hollandais. 1896; expanded French edn. Paris 1983.
  46. ^ "Fonseca, da, Isaac Aboab - The Spinoza Web". spinozaweb.org. Retrieved 13 January 2024.
  47. ^ Curley, Edwin (31 March 2020). A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics and Other Works. Princeton University Press. p. xii. ISBN 978-0-691-20928-9.
  48. ^ Touber, Jetze (21 June 2018). Spinoza and Biblical Philology in the Dutch Republic, 1660–1710. Oxford University Press. p. 45. ISBN 978-0-19-252718-9.
  49. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 7.
  50. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 2.
  51. ^ Steven B. Smith, Spinoza's book of life: freedom and redemption in the Ethics, Yale University Press (2003), p. xx: "Introduction."
  52. ^ Nadler 2001b.
  53. ^ Nadler 2008, Biography.
  54. ^ Okhovat, Oren, "Cosmopolitan Empire: Portuguese Jewish Merchants and Iberian Imperialism in the seventeenth-century Atlantic". PhD dissertation. University of Florida 2023.
  55. ^ Nadler 2001, pp. 17–22.
  56. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 19.
  57. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 20.
  58. ^ Nadler 2001, pp. 19–21.
  59. ^ Nadler, Steven (Summer 2020). "Baruch Spinoza: God or Nature". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. OCLC 643092515. from the original on 17 April 2020. Retrieved 5 August 2021. In propositions one through fifteen of Part One, Spinoza presents the basic elements of his picture of God. God is the infinite, necessarily existing (that is, self-caused), unique substance of the universe. There is only one substance in the universe; it is God; and everything else that is, is in God. [...] As soon as this preliminary conclusion has been established, Spinoza immediately reveals the objective of his attack. His definition of God—condemned since his excommunication from the Jewish community as a "God existing in only a philosophical sense"—is meant to preclude any anthropomorphizing of the divine being. In the scholium to proposition fifteen, he writes against "those who feign a God, like man, consisting of a body and a mind, and subject to passions. But how far they wander from the true knowledge of God, is sufficiently established by what has already been demonstrated." Besides being false, such an anthropomorphic conception of God standing as judge over us can have only deleterious effects on human freedom and activity, insofar as it fosters a life enslaved to hope and fear and the superstitions to which such emotions give rise.
  60. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 28.
  61. ^ a b c d e Scruton 2002, p. 22.
  62. ^ Spinoza's Biography 26 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine in the Encyclopædia Britannica. 14 February 2018.
  63. ^ Kramer, Howard (17 July 2020). "HOME & GRAVESITE OF BARUCH SPINOZA – The Complete Pilgrim – Religious Travel Sites". The Complete Pilgrim. Retrieved 14 March 2022.
  64. ^ Nadler 2011, p. 167.
  65. ^ "Ralph Dumain: "The Autodidact Project": "Spinoza, the First Secular Jew?" by Yirmiyahu Yovel".
  66. ^ Steven Nadler, Spinoza and Medieval Jewish Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, 2014, p. 27: "Spinoza attended lectures and anatomical dissections at the University of Leiden..."
  67. ^ "he [Spinoza] told me [Leibniz] he had a strong desire, on the day of the massacre of Mess. De Witt, to sally forth at night, and put up somewhere, near the place of the massacre, a paper with the words Ultimi barbarorum [ultimate barbarians]. But his host had shut the house to prevent his going out, for he would have run the risk of being torn to pieces." (A Refutation Recently Discovered of Spinoza by Leibnitz, "Remarks on the Unpublished Refutation of Spinoza by Leibnitz", Edinburg: Thomas Constable and Company, 1855. p. 70.
  68. ^ Nadler, Steven, A Book Forged in Hell: Spinoza's Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the Secular Age. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2011.
  69. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 26.
  70. ^ Chauí 2001, pp. 30–31: "A commentary on Descartes' work, Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, only work published under his own name, brought him on an invitation to teach philosophy at the University of Heidelberg. Spinoza, however, refused, thinking that it might be demanded the renunciation of his freedom of thought, for the invite stipulated that all care should be taken to 'not insult the principles of the established religion'."
  71. ^ Popkin, Richard H., "Benedict de Spinoza" in The Columbia History of Western Philosophy (Columbia University Press, 1999), p. 381.
  72. ^ a b Lucas 1960.
  73. ^ Stewart 2007, p. [page needed].
  74. ^ Christiaan Huygens, Oeuvres complètes, Letter No. 1638, 11 May 1668
  75. ^ Christiaan Huygens, Oeuvres complètes, letter to his brother 23 September 1667
  76. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 215.
  77. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 183.
  78. ^ Christiaan Huygens, Oeuvres complètes, vol. XXII, p. 732, footnote
  79. ^ Theodore Kerckring, "Spicilegium Anatomicum" Observatio XCIII (1670)
  80. ^ Gullan-Whur, Within Reason: A Life of Spinoza 317-18
  81. ^ Israel, Spinoza (2023), 1150-51
  82. ^ Nadler, Spinoza, A Life (2018), 406
  83. ^ Israel, Spinoza, 1152-6, 1159
  84. ^ Colerus, Johannes, The Life of Benedict de Spinoza (London 1706)
  85. ^ Israel, Spinoza, 1154-55
  86. ^ Israel, Spinoza, 1158
  87. ^ Ven, Jeroen van de. Printing Spinoza: A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century. Leiden; Brill, 2022.
  88. ^ Stewart 2007, p. 106.
  89. ^ a b c d e f Bloom, Harold (16 June 2006). "Deciphering Spinoza, the Great Original – Book review of Betraying Spinoza. The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity by Rebecca Goldstein". The New York Times. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  90. ^ See G. Licata, "Spinoza e la cognitio universalis dell'ebraico. Demistificazione e speculazione grammaticale nel Compendio di grammatica ebraica", Giornale di Metafisica, 3 (2009), pp. 625–61.
  91. ^ see Refutation of Spinoza
  92. ^ a b Lisa Montanarelli (book reviewer) (8 January 2006). "Spinoza stymies 'God's attorney' – Stewart argues the secular world was at stake in Leibniz face off". San Francisco Chronicle. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  93. ^ "Spinoza on Islam". 13 February 2012.
  94. ^ Spinoza, Baruch (2003). Correspondence of Spinoza. Translated by A. Wolf. Kessinger Publishing, LLC. p. 354.
  95. ^ Coyle, Patrick A. (1938). Some aspects of the philosophy of Spinoza and his ontological proof of the existence of God (PDF). University of Western Ontario, CA. p. 2. OCLC 1067012129. Retrieved 9 June 2021 – via University of Windsor, Electronic Theses and Dissertations.
  96. ^ Soley, W.R. (1 July 1880). "Jewish Mediaeval Philosophy in Spinoza". Mind. Oxford University Press. os–V (19): 362–384. doi:10.1093/mind/os-V.19.362. ISSN 0026-4423. JSTOR 2246395. OCLC 5545819846. other hand, the discovery and publication in 1862 of a lost treatise of Spinoza's—the Tractatus brtvia de Deo et homine ejusque felicitate"
  97. ^ Nadler, Book Forged in Hell, xi
  98. ^ Israel, Spinoza, Life & Legacy, 776
  99. ^ Scruton 2002, pp. 31–32.
  100. ^ Della Rocca, Michael. (2008). Spinoza. Routledge., pg. 33.
  101. ^ Jaspers 1974, p. 9.
  102. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 41
  103. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 42
  104. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 43.
  105. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 44.
  106. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 45.
  107. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 38
  108. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 51.
  109. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 57.
  110. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 59.
  111. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 60.
  112. ^ Cannon, J. A. (2009, May 17). World in time of upheaval: Sources of enlightenment. Deseret News.
  113. ^ a b Charles Hartshorne and William Reese, "Philosophers Speak of God", Humanity Books, 1953 ch. 4
  114. ^ Baruch Spinoza. Ethics, in Spinoza: Complete Works, trans. by Samuel Shirley and ed. by Michael L. Morgan (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2002), see Part I, Proposition 33.
  115. ^ Ethics, Part III, Proposition 2.
  116. ^ Ethics, Pt. I, Prop. XXXVI, Appendix: "[M]en think themselves free inasmuch as they are conscious of their volitions and desires, and never even dream, in their ignorance, of the causes which have disposed of them so to wish and desire."
  117. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 86.
  118. ^ ""Spinoza and the Philosophy of Science: Mathematics, Motion, and Being"". 9 July 2012.
  119. ^ "Western philosophy - The rationalism of Spinoza and Leibniz | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 25 December 2022.
  120. ^ Della Rocca, Michael. (2008). Spinoza, Routledge.
  121. ^ a b Della Rocca, Spinoza, 2008.
  122. ^ a b Curley 1985
  123. ^ a b Konstan, David (2016). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 February 2017 – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  124. ^ Ethics, Part IV, preface: "Deus seu Natura".
  125. ^ "Baruch Spinoza, "Human Beings are Determined"". Lander.edu. Retrieved 21 February 2017.
  126. ^ Bennett 1984, p. 276.
  127. ^ Bennett 1984, p. 277.
  128. ^ Bennett 1984, p. 371.
  129. ^ Frank Thilly, A History of Philosophy, § 47, Holt & Co., New York, 1914
  130. ^ "I believe in Spinoza's God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists, not in a God who concerns himself with fates and actions of human beings." These words were spoken by Albert Einstein, upon being asked if he believed in God by Rabbi Herbert Goldstein of the Institutional Synagogue, New York, April 24, 1921, published in the New York Times, April 25, 1929; from Einstein: The Life and Times Ronald W. Clark, New York: World Publishing Co., 1971, p. 413; also cited as a telegram to a Jewish newspaper, 1929, Einstein Archive 33–272, from Alice Calaprice, ed., The Expanded Quotable Einstein, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
  131. ^ Lange, Frederick Albert (1880). History of Materialism and Criticism of its Present Importance, Vol. II. Boston: Houghton, Osgood, & Co. p. 147. Retrieved 11 November 2015.
  132. ^ "The Pantheism of Spinoza Dr. Smith regarded as the most dangerous enemy of Christianity, and as he announced his conviction that it had gained the control of the schools, press and pulpit of the Old World [Europe], and was rapidly gaining the same control of the New [United States], his alarm and indignation sometimes rose to the eloquence of genuine passion." Memorial of the Rev. Henry Smith, D.D., LL D., Professor of Sacred Rhetoric and Pastoral Theology in Lane Theological Seminary, Consisting of Addresses on Occasion of the Anniversary of the Seminary, 8 May 1879, Together with Commemorative Resolutions, p. 26.
  133. ^ Hutchison, Percy (20 November 1932). "Spinoza, "God-Intoxicated Man"; Three Books Which Mark the Three Hundredth Anniversary of the Philosopher's Birth". The New York Times. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  134. ^ Picton, J. Allanson, "Pantheism: Its Story and Significance", 1905.
  135. ^ Fraser, Alexander Campbell "Philosophy of Theism", William Blackwood and Sons, 1895, p. 163.
  136. ^ Correspondence of Benedict de Spinoza, Wilder Publications (26 March 2009), ISBN 978-1-60459-156-9, letter 73.
  137. ^ a b Jaspers 1974, pp. 14, 95
  138. ^ a b Genevieve Lloyd, Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to Spinoza and The Ethics (Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks), Routledge; 1 edition (2 October 1996), ISBN 978-0-415-10782-2, p. 40
  139. ^ "Pantheism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 3 October 2014.
  140. ^ Nadler 2008, God or Nature.
  141. ^ Israel, Spinoza, Life and Legacy, 1205
  142. ^ Smith, Spinoza, Liberalism, and the Question of Jewish Identity, 168-69
  143. ^ Hegel Society of America. Meeting (2003). Duquette, David A. (ed.). Hegel's History of Philosophy: New Interpretations. SUNY Series in Hegelian Studies. SUNY Press. ISBN 9780791455432. from the original on 13 May 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  144. ^ Literary Remains of the Late Professor Theodore Goldstucker, W. H. Allen, 1879. p. 32.
  145. ^ "The Religious Difficulties of India". The Westminster Review (American ed.). New York: Leonard Scott. 78: 256–257. October 1862. hdl:2027/mdp.39015013165819.
  146. ^ Three Lectures on the Vedanta Philosophy. F. Max Muller. Kessinger Publishing, 2003. p. 123
  147. ^ George Santayana, "The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza", The Harvard Monthly, 2 (June 1886: 144–52).
  148. ^ George Santayana, "Introduction", in Spinoza's Ethics and "De intellectus emendatione"(London: Dent, 1910, vii–xxii)
  149. ^ George Santayana, "Ultimate Religion", in Obiter Scripta, eds. Justus Buchler and Benjamin Schwartz (New York and London: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1936) 280–97.
  150. ^ George Santayana, Persons and Places (Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press, 1986), pp. 233–36.
  151. ^ Peden, Knox (2014). Spinoza contra phenomenology : French rationalism from Cavaillès to Deleuze. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press. ISBN 978-0-8047-9136-6. OCLC 880877889.
  152. ^ Baugh-Peden, Bruce (28 March 2015). "Spinoza Contra Phenomenology: French Rationalism from Cavaillès to Deleuze". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved 19 May 2022.
  153. ^ Deleuze, 1968.
  154. ^ Quoted in the translator's preface of Deleuze's Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (1990).
  155. ^ a b Rocha, Mauricio (2021), "Spinozist Moments in Deleuze: Materialism as Immanence", Materialism and Politics, Berlin: ICI Berlin Press, pp. 73–90, doi:10.37050/ci-20_04, S2CID 234131869, retrieved 19 May 2022.
  156. ^ "Einstein believes in "Spinoza's God"; Scientist Defines His Faith in Reply, to Cablegram From Rabbi Here. Sees a Divine Order But Says Its Ruler Is Not Concerned "Wit [sic] Fates and Actions of Human Beings."". The New York Times. 25 April 1929. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  157. ^ "Einstein's Third Paradise, by Gerald Holton". Aip.org. from the original on 22 May 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  158. ^ Israel, J. (2001) Radical Enlightenment; Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650–1750, Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 159.
  159. ^ "Entoen.nu". Entoen.nu. from the original on 13 May 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  160. ^ "Van der Ham biedt Verbeet Spinoza aan". RTL Nieuws. 5 July 2012. Retrieved 30 November 2014.
  161. ^ a b Rutledge, David (3 October 2020). "The Jewish philosopher Spinoza was one of the great Enlightenment thinkers. So why was he 'cancelled'?". ABC News. ABC Radio National (The Philosopher's Zone). Australian Broadcasting Corporation. Retrieved 7 October 2020.
  162. ^ Rocker, Simon (28 August 2014). "Why Baruch Spinoza is still excommunicated". The Jewish Chronicle Online.
  163. ^ "Mo 50 – Statue Spinoza – Amsterdam" (in Dutch). from the original on 22 January 2022. Retrieved 20 June 2023.
  164. ^ SpinozaHavurah.org 1 January 2023 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 202, 2022)
  165. ^ "Statute of Spinoza unveiled in Amsterdam centre" Simply Amsterdam (Nov. 25, 2008) 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 20, 2022)
  166. ^ "Who stands proud on a pedestal in Amsterdam" Unclogged in Amsterdam : An American Expat plumbs Holland (Aug. 22, 2020) 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 20, 2022)
  167. ^ "Spinoza Monument" CitySeeker.com 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 20, 2022)

Sources edit

  • Bennett, Jonathan (July 1984). A Study of Spinoza's 'Ethics'. CUP Archive. ISBN 978-0-521-27742-6.
  • Chauí, Marilena (2001) [1995]. Espinosa: uma filosofia da liberdade. São Paulo: Editora Moderna.
  • Curley, Edwin M., ed. (1985). The Collected Works of Spinoza, Volume 1. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-07222-7.
  • Jaspers, Karl (23 October 1974). Spinoza. Great Philosophers. Harvest Books. ISBN 978-0-15-684730-8.
  • Lucas, P. G. (1960). "Some Speculative and Critical Philosophers". In I. Levine (ed.). Philosophy. London: Odhams.
  • Nadler, Steven M. (1999). Spinoza: A Life. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55210-3. Second edition 2018.
  • Nadler, Steven M. (2001). Spinoza's Heresy: Immortality and the Jewish Mind. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926887-0.
  • Nadler, Steven (2001b). "The Excommunication of Spinoza: Trouble and Toleration in the "Dutch Jerusalem"". Shofar. 19 (4): 40–52. ISSN 0882-8539. JSTOR 42943396.
  • Nadler, Steven (1 December 2008) [2001]. "Baruch Spinoza". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (substantive revised ed.).
  • Nadler, Steven (2011). . Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-13989-0. Archived from the original on 29 November 2019. Retrieved 12 October 2011.
  • Scruton, Roger (2002). Spinoza: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-280316-0.
  • Stewart, Matthew (2007). The Courtier and the Heretic: Leibniz, Spinoza, and the Fate of God in the Modern World. W. W. Norton. ISBN 978-0393071047.

Further reading edit

Biographies and reference works edit

  • Brenner-Golomb, Nancy. 2010. The Importance of Spinoza for the Modern Philosophy of Science. Frankfurt.
  • Carlisle, Clare. 2021. "Spinoza's Religion", Princeton University Press.
  • Della Rocca, Michael. 2008. Spinoza, New York: Routledge.
  • _____, (ed.), 2018. The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza. Oxford University Press.
  • Garrett, Don, ed., 1995. The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza. Cambridge Uni. Press.
  • Gullan-Whur, Margaret. 2000. Within Reason: A Life of Spinoza. New York:St. Martin's Press.
  • Israel, Jonathan. 2023. Spinoza: Life and Legacy. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198857488
  • Koistinen, Olli, (ed.). 2009. The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza's Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Popkin, R. H., 2004. Spinoza (Oxford: One World Publications)
  • Yovel, Yirmiyahu, Spinoza and Other Heretics, Vol. 1: The Marrano of Reason. Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1989.
  • Yovel, Yirmiyahu, Spinoza and Other Heretics, Vol. 2: The Adventures of Immanence. Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1989.

Other works edit

  • Damásio, António, 2003. Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain, Harvest Books, ISBN 978-0-15-602871-4
  • Deleuze, Gilles, 1968. Spinoza et le problème de l'expression. Trans. "Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza" Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books).
  • _____, 1970. Spinoza: Philosophie pratique. Transl. "Spinoza: Practical Philosophy".
  • _____, 1990. Negotiations trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press).
  • Della Rocca, Michael. 1996. Representation and the Mind-Body Problem in Spinoza. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509562-3
  • Gatens, Moira, and Lloyd, Genevieve, 1999. Collective imaginings: Spinoza, past and present. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-16570-9, 978-0-415-16571-6
  • Goldstein, Rebecca, 2006. Betraying Spinoza: The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity. Schocken. ISBN 978-0-8052-1159-7
  • Goode, Francis, 2012. Life of Spinoza. Smashwords edition. ISBN 978-1-4661-3399-0
  • Gullan-Whur, Margaret, 1998. Within Reason: A Life of Spinoza. Jonathan Cape. ISBN 978-0-224-05046-3
  • Hampshire, Stuart, 1951. Spinoza and Spinozism, OUP, 2005 ISBN 978-0-19-927954-8
  • Hardt, Michael, trans., University of Minnesota Press. Preface, in French, by Gilles Deleuze, available here: . Multitudes.samizdat.net. Archived from the original on 11 June 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  • Israel, Jonathan, 2001. The Radical Enlightenment, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • _____, 2006. Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752, (ISBN 978-0-19-927922-7)
  • _____. 2002. “Philosophy, Commerce and the Synagogue: Spinoza’s Expulsion from the Amsterdam Portuguese Jewish Community in 1656.” In Dutch Jewry: Its History and Secular Culture (1500-2000). Edited by Jonathan Israel and Reinier Salverda, pp. 125-140. Leiden: Brill.
  • Ives, David (2009). New Jerusalem; The Interrogation of Baruch de Spinoza at Talmud Torah Congregation: Amsterdam, 27 July 1656. New York: Dramatists Play Service. ISBN 978-0-8222-2385-6.)
  • Kayser, Rudolf, 1946, with an introduction by Albert Einstein. Spinoza: Portrait of a Spiritual Hero. New York: The Philosophical Library.
  • Lloyd, Genevieve, 2018. Reclaiming wonder. After the sublime. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-1-4744-3311-2
  • LeBuffe, Michael. 2010. Spinoza and Human Freedom. Oxford University Press.
  • Lovejoy, Arthur O., 1936. "Plenitude and Sufficient Reason in Leibniz and Spinoza" in his The Great Chain of Being. Harvard University Press: 144–82 (ISBN 978-0-674-36153-9). Reprinted in Frankfurt, H. G., ed., 1972. Leibniz: A Collection of Critical Essays. Anchor Books.
  • Macherey, Pierre, 1977. Hegel ou Spinoza, Maspéro (2nd ed. La Découverte, 2004).
  • _____, 1994–98. Introduction à l'Ethique de Spinoza. Paris: PUF.
  • Magnusson 1990: Magnusson, M (ed.), Spinoza, Baruch, Chambers Biographical Dictionary, Chambers 1990, ISBN 978-0-550-16041-6.
  • Matheron, Alexandre, 1969. Individu et communauté chez Spinoza, Paris: Minuit.
  • Melamed, Yitzhak Y., Spinoza's Metaphysics: Substance and Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013). xxii+232 pp.
  • Melamed, Yitzhak Y. (ed.), The Young Spinoza: A Metaphysician in the Making (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).
  • Millner, Simon L., The Face of Benedictus Spinoza (New York: Machmadim Art Editions, Inc., 1946).
  • Montag, Warren, Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and his Contemporaries. (London: Verso, 2002).
  • Moreau, Pierre-François, 2003, Spinoza et le spinozisme, PUF (Presses Universitaires de France)
  • Nadler, Steven, Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die, 2020 (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, ISBN 978-0691183848).
  • Negri, Antonio, 1991. The Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza's Metaphysics and Politics.
  • _____, 2004. Subversive Spinoza: (Un)Contemporary Variations.
  • Prokhovnik, Raia (2004). Spinoza and republicanism. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire New York: Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-0333733905.
  • Ratner, Joseph, 1927. The Philosophy of Spinoza (The Modern Library: Random House)
  • Stolze, Ted and Warren Montag (eds.), The New Spinoza, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.
  • Strauss, Leo. Persecution and the Art of Writing. Glencoe, Illinois: Free Press, 1952. Reprint. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.
  • _____ch. 5, "How to Study Spinoza's Tractus Theologico-Politicus;" reprinted in Strauss, Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, ed. Kenneth Hart Green (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1997), 181–233.
  • ____Spinoza's Critique of Religion. New York: Schocken Books, 1965. Reprint. University of Chicago Press, 1996.
  • _____ "Preface to the English Translation" reprinted as "Preface to Spinoza's Critique of Religion", in Strauss, Liberalism Ancient and Modern (New York: Basic Books, 1968, 224–59; also in Strauss, Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, 137–77).
  • Valentiner, W.R., 1957. Rembrandt and Spinoza: A Study of the Spiritual Conflicts in Seventeenth-Century Holland, London: Phaidon Press.
  • Spinoza in French Philosophy Today. Philosophy Today 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine, Vol. 53, No. 4, Winter 2009 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Van den Ven, Jeroen. Printing Spinoza: A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century. Leiden 2022.
  • _____. Documenting Spinoza: A Biographical History of his Life and Time. (forthcoming)
  • Williams, David Lay. 2010. "Spinoza and the General Will", The Journal of Politics, vol. 72 (April): 341–356.
  • Wolfson, Henry A. "The Philosophy of Spinoza". 2 vols. Harvard University Press.

External links edit

Articles

  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • "Benedict de Spinoza"
    • "Spinoza: Epistemology
    • "Spinoza: Metaphysics
    • "Spinoza: Moral Philosophy
    • "Spinoza: Political Philosophy
    • "Spinoza: Free Will and Determinism"
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • "Spinoza" by Steven Nadler.
    • "Spinoza's Psychological Theory" by Michael LeBuffe.
    • "Spinoza's Physical Theory" by Richard Manning.
    • "Spinoza's Political Philosophy" by Justin Steinberg.
  • Spinoza, Baruch (Bento, Benedictus) De in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2005) by Edwin Curley
  • of the journal Archives de philosophie
  • Susan James on Spinoza on the Passions, Philosophy Bites podcast
  • Spinoza, the Moral Heretic by Matthew J. Kisner
  • BBC Radio 4 In Our Time programme on Spinoza
  • Spinoza in the Jewish Encyclopedia
  • Spinoza in the Encyclopaedia Judaica
  • by Henry Abramson

Works

  • Spinoza Opera 27 July 2017 at the Wayback Machine Carl Gebhardt's 1925 four volume edition of Spinoza's Works.
  • Works by Benedictus de Spinoza at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by or about Baruch Spinoza at Internet Archive
  • Works by Baruch Spinoza at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  
  • Works by Baruch Spinoza at Open Library
  • Refutation of Spinoza by Leibniz In full via Google Books
  • More easily readable versions of the Correspondence, Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order and Treatise on Theology and Politics
  • EthicaDB 30 October 2012 at the Wayback Machine Hypertextual and multilingual publication of Ethics
  • – English Translation
  • A Theologico-Political Treatise – English Translation (at sacred-texts.com)
  • Opera posthuma – Amsterdam 1677. Complete photographic reproduction, ed. by F. Mignini (Quodlibet publishing house website)
  • Spinoza Archive on the Digital collections of Younes and Soraya Nazarian Library, University of Haifa

baruch, spinoza, spinoza, redirects, here, other, uses, spinoza, disambiguation, this, article, lead, section, long, please, read, length, guidelines, help, move, details, into, article, body, january, 2024, baruch, spinoza, november, 1632, february, 1677, mos. Spinoza redirects here For other uses see Spinoza disambiguation This article s lead section may be too long Please read the length guidelines and help move details into the article s body January 2024 Baruch de Spinoza b 24 November 1632 21 February 1677 17 18 19 mostly known under his Latinized pen name Benedictus de Spinoza 20 was a leading seventeenth century philosopher of Portuguese Jewish origin 21 resident in the Dutch Republic and as young man permanently expelled from the Jewish community After his expulsion Spinoza lived an outwardly simple life without religious affiliation the center of his life was philosophy He had a dedicated clandestine circle of supporters a philosophical sect who met to discuss the writings he shared with them 22 Baruch SpinozaBornBaruch Espinosa 8 Bento de Spinosa 9 1632 11 24 24 November 1632Amsterdam Dutch RepublicDied21 February 1677 1677 02 21 aged 44 The Hague Dutch RepublicOther namesBenedictus de SpinozaEducationTalmud Torah of Amsterdam 10 withdrew 11 University of Leiden no degree 12 Era17th century philosophyAge of EnlightenmentRegionWestern philosophySchoolCartesianism 1 Conceptualism 2 Correspondence theory of truth a 4 Direct realism 5 Foundationalism according to Hegel 6 RationalismPsychological Egoism 7 SpinozismMain interestsEpistemologyethicsHebrew BiblemetaphysicsSignatureOne of the foremost thinkers of the Age of Reason 18 modern biblical criticism 23 and 17th century Rationalism including modern conceptions of the self and the universe 24 Spinoza came to be considered one of the most important philosophers and certainly the most radical of the early modern period 25 He was influenced by Stoicism Maimonides Machiavelli Descartes Hobbes and a variety of heterodox Christian thinkers of his day 19 He challenged the divine origin of the Hebrew Bible the nature of God and the earthly power wielded by religious authorities Jewish and Christian alike He was frequently called an atheist by contemporaries although nowhere in his work does Spinoza argue against the existence of god 26 27 His theological studies were inseparable from his thinking on politics he is grouped with Hobbes Locke Leibniz and Kant who helped establish the genre of political writing called secular theology 28 He died unexpectedly at age 44 in 1677 Supporters swiftly removed unpublished manuscripts from his lodgings to prevent their destruction by authorities they prepared his works with speed and secrecy for posthumous publication in both their original Latin and Dutch His works were banned by Dutch authorities and later the Roman Catholic Church 29 30 Spinoza s philosophy encompasses nearly every area of philosophical discourse 31 including metaphysics epistemology political philosophy ethics philosophy of mind and philosophy of science It earned Spinoza an enduring reputation as one of the most important and original thinkers of the seventeenth century influencing philosophers ever since He has been called the renegade Jew who gave us modernity 32 Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Family background 1 2 School days 1 3 The family business and intellectual explorations 1 4 Expulsion from the Jewish community 1 5 Career as a philosopher 1 5 1 Lens grinding and optics 1 5 2 Death and burial 2 Writings 2 1 Major publications 2 2 Correspondence 3 Philosophy 3 1 Tractatus Theologico Politicus 3 2 Ethics 3 2 1 Metaphysics 3 2 1 1 Substance attributes and modes 3 2 1 2 Causality 3 2 1 3 The emotions 3 2 2 Ethical philosophy 4 Pantheism 5 Legacy 6 Modern era 6 1 Reconsideration of Enlightenment 6 2 Memory and memorials 7 See also 8 References 8 1 Notes 8 2 References 9 Sources 10 Further reading 10 1 Biographies and reference works 10 2 Other works 11 External linksBiography edit nbsp Spinoza lived where the Moses and Aaron Church is located now and there is strong evidence that he may have been born there 33 Family background edit Both sides of Spinoza s family were originally Sephardic Jews from Iberia His immediate family migrated to Amsterdam arriving in the early seventeenth century as Sephardic Jews in the Netherlands were openly establishing a community and could practice their religion without persecution by the Inquisition The family in Portugal were New Christians forced converts conversos to Catholicism In Portugal in the early sixteenth century the crown initially looked the other way as outwardly Catholic New Christians practiced Judaism in private The Portuguese Inquisition was not even established until 1536 As the Inquisition increasingly cracked down more New Christians continued practicing Judaism in secrecy 34 A legacy of the era was that many in Spinoza s family had both Christian and Jewish names Spinoza s father Michael married his cousin Rachael d Espinosa daughter of his uncle Abraham d Espinosa Such a pattern of intermarriage was fairly common in the Jewish merchant community keeping commercial and religious ties strong and secrets safe Marrying his cousin Rachel gave Michael access to his uncle father in law s commercial network and capital When Michael s wife died in 1627 he married again to Hannah Deborah His second wife brought a dowry to the marriage which should not have been absorbed into the capital of the family business This marriage proved fruitful with five children who survived to adulthood Michael was a successful although not enormously wealthy merchant in Amsterdam prominent in the community 15 The first born of his second marriage was Miriam followed by Isaac 1631 49 Isaac d Espinosa was expected to take over as head of family and its commercial enterprise Baruch Espinosa 8 the third child and second son was born on 24 November 1632 in the Jodenbuurt in Amsterdam Netherlands He was named as per tradition for his maternal grandfather Spinoza s younger brother Gabriel Abraham was born in 1634 followed by another sister Rebecca Ribca Spinoza s sister Miriam married Samuel de Caceres but Miriam died shortly after giving birth Following Jewish tradition the widower Samuel married his former sister in law Rebecca Spinoza s sisters marriages to Caceres and his honored place in the Spinoza family as a scholar meant that Spinoza s own ambitions as a scholar were shunted aside There was discord between Spinoza and his sister and brother in law over inheritance which played out later when Spinoza broke with rabbinic authorities and the Jewish community 35 His mother Hannah Deborah Michael s second wife died when Baruch was only six years old Michael remarried to give his five children a mother figure The third marriage was childless so that Spinoza and his siblings had no half or step siblings 36 Spinoza was related in a complicated way with the highly controversial figure in the Amsterdam Portuguese Jewish community Uriel da Costa 1585 1640 through his mother s family in Porto DaCosta was twice sanctioned by rabbinic authorities and committed suicide in 1640 when Spinoza was eight years old He might not have known of the scandalous family connection until he was an adolescent 37 School days edit Baruch s family spoke Portuguese as did other Sephardim He studied Hebrew at school and heard it Jewish liturgy he knew Dutch which he likely learned informally He learned Latin only later as a young man 38 His name in contemporary documents before his 1656 expulsion from the Jewish community is given as the Portuguese Bento his Hebrew name Baruch was used in the religious context Following his expulsion at age 23 he used the Latinized version of his name Benedictus de Spinoza Spinoza had a traditional upbringing for a Jewish boy attending a local religious school the Keter Torah yeshiva of the Amsterdam Talmud Torah congregation headed by the learned and traditional senior Rabbi Saul Levi Morteira 39 Teachers also included the less traditional Rabbi Manasseh ben Israel Since Spinoza never reached the level of advanced study of the Torah 15 the senior rabbis were unlikely to have had Spinoza as their pupil Spinoza s end of schooling was due the unexpected death of his elder brother Isaac who had been actively involved in the family business 15 The family business and intellectual explorations edit When Spinoza s father Michael died in 1654 Spinoza had been actively involved in the running of the family business Although Spinoza duly recited Kaddish the Jewish prayer of mourning for eleven months as required by Jewish law 15 there is evidence that his relations with his father had been chilly citation needed As with other merchants in Amsterdam the Spinozas business was affected by the First Anglo Dutch War in the years of 1652 1654 as well as by some commercial deals that soured and found itself in severe difficulty In addition Michael had absorbed the dowry of Spinoza s mother as regular capital for his business rather than keeping it separate for her children after her death As such the money was at risk for collection by Michael s many creditors Spinoza was just 21 when his father died in Dutch law a legal minor until age 25 Nonetheless he and his younger brother Gabriel Abraham formed a business partnership attempting to continue the family business including collecting unpaid debts owed by merchants to their father s estate Spinoza had continued to support the synagogue financially and attend services When his sister Rebekah disputed his inheritance seeking it for herself he sued her to seek a court judgment won the case but then renounced his claim to the court s judgment in his favor and assigned his inheritance to her 40 In March 1656 Spinoza filed suit with the Amsterdam municipal authorities to be declared an orphan since he was still a legal minor He sought relief through Dutch law not through judgment by Jewish authorities from whom he had become increasingly estranged but not openly as yet He won the civil lawsuit which allowed him to inherit his mother s estate without it being subject to his father s creditors and devote himself chiefly to the study of philosophy especially the system expounded by Descartes and to optics 41 At some point between 1654 and 1658 Spinoza began to study Latin with Franciscus van den Enden Van den Enden was a former Jesuit who was a political radical and likely introduced Spinoza to scholastic and modern philosophy including that of Descartes 42 43 Spinoza adopted the Latin name Benedictus de Spinoza began boarding with Van den Enden and began teaching in his school 42 43 During this period Spinoza also became acquainted with the Collegiants an anti clerical sect of Remonstrants with tendencies towards rationalism and with the liberal faction among the Mennonites who had existed for a century but were close to the Remonstrants 44 Many of his friends belonged to dissident Christian groups which met regularly as discussion groups and which typically rejected the authority of established churches as well as traditional dogmas 21 In the second half of the 1650s and the first half of the 1660s Spinoza became acquainted with several persons who would themselves emerge as unorthodox thinkers this group known as the Spinoza Circle 45 included Pieter Balling Wikidata Jarig Jelles Wikidata Lodewijk Meyer Johannes Bouwmeester and Adriaen Koerbagh Expulsion from the Jewish community edit nbsp Spinoza and the Rabbis by Samuel Hirszenberg 1907 nbsp Spinoza s name crossed out on the list of pupils of Ets Haim nbsp Seal with Spinoza s initials and the Latin word meaning caution Spinoza did not openly break with Jewish authorities until after his father s death in 1654 He challenged the prevailing dogmas of Judaism and particularly the insistence on non Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch His break was not sudden rather it appears to have been the result of a lengthy internal struggle as well as a degree of filial piety Nevertheless after he was branded as a heretic Spinoza s clashes with authority became more pronounced He was later attacked on the steps of the synagogue by a knife wielding assailant shouting Heretic He was apparently quite shaken by this attack and for years kept and wore his torn cloak unmended as a reminder 40 On 27 July 1656 the Sepharadi Talmud Torah congregation of Amsterdam which included Aboab de Fonseca 46 issued a writ of herem Hebrew חרם a kind of ban shunning ostracism expulsion or excommunication against the 23 year old Spinoza 40 47 48 The Talmud Torah congregation issued censures routinely on matters great and small so such an edict was not unusual 49 The language of Spinoza s censure is unusually harsh however and does not appear in any other censure known to have been issued by the Portuguese Jewish community in Amsterdam 50 The exact reason for expelling Spinoza is not stated 51 The censure refers only to the abominable heresies horrendas heregias that he practised and taught to his monstrous deeds and to the testimony of witnesses in the presence of the said Espinoza There is no record of such testimony but there appear to have been several likely reasons for the issuance of the censure 52 Spinoza began publicly expressing radical religious views that were highly controversial Spinoza biographer Steven Nadler wrote No doubt he was giving utterance to just those ideas that would soon appear in his philosophical treatises In those works Spinoza denies the immortality of the soul strongly rejects the notion of a providential god the god of Abraham Isaac and Jacob and claims that the Mosiac Law was neither literally given by God nor any longer binding on Jews 53 The Amsterdam Jewish community was largely composed of Spanish and Portuguese conversos New Christians who had respectively migrated from Spain via Portugal to escape the Spanish Inquisition and Portuguese conversos following the establishment of the Portuguese Inquisition with their children and grandchildren Amsterdam was tolerant of religious diversity so long as it was practiced discreetly Jews were not legally confined to a ghetto and the city presented economic opportunities for those willing to move 54 This community must have been concerned to protect its reputation from any association with Spinoza lest his controversial views provide the basis for their own possible persecution or expulsion 55 There is little evidence that the Amsterdam municipal authorities were directly involved in Spinoza s censure itself But in 1619 the town council expressly ordered the Portuguese Jewish community to regulate their conduct and ensure that the members of the community kept to a strict observance of Jewish law 56 Other evidence makes it clear that the danger of upsetting the civil authorities was never far from mind such as bans adopted by the synagogue on public wedding or funeral processions and on discussing religious matters with Christians lest such activity might disturb the liberty we enjoy 57 Thus the issuance of Spinoza s censure was almost certainly in part an exercise in self censorship by the Portuguese Jewish community in Amsterdam 58 nbsp Ban in Portuguese of Baruch Spinoza by his Portuguese Jewish synagogue community of Amsterdam Amsterdam 6 Av 5416 27 July 1656 It appears likely that Spinoza had already taken the initiative to separate himself from the Talmud Torah congregation and was vocally expressing his hostility to Judaism itself also through his philosophical works such as the Part I of Ethics 59 He had probably stopped attending services at the synagogue either after the lawsuit with his sister or after the knife attack on its steps He might already have been voicing the view expressed later in his Theological Political Treatise that the civil authorities should suppress Judaism as harmful to the Jews themselves Either for financial or other reasons 60 43 he had in any case effectively stopped contributing to the synagogue by March 1656 He had also committed the monstrous deed contrary to the regulations of the synagogue and the views of some rabbinical authorities including Maimonides of filing suit in a civil court rather than with the synagogue authorities 41 to renounce his father s heritage no less Upon being notified of the issuance of the censure he is reported to have said Very well this does not force me to do anything that I would not have done of my own accord had I not been afraid of a scandal 61 Thus unlike most of the censure issued routinely by the Amsterdam congregation to discipline its members the censure issued against Spinoza did not lead to repentance and so was never withdrawn After the censure Spinoza is said to have addressed an Apologia defense written in Spanish to the elders of the synagogue in which he defended his views as orthodox and condemned the rabbis for accusing him of horrible practices and other enormities merely because he had neglected ceremonial observances 61 This apologia does not survive but some of its contents may later have been included in his Theological Political Treatise 61 Spinoza s expulsion from the Jewish community did not lead to his conversion to Christianity Spinoza used the Latinized name Benedictus de Spinoza and maintained a close association with the Collegiants a liberal Protestant sect of Remonstrants and Quakers 62 even moved to a town near the Collegiants headquarters and was buried at the Protestant Church Nieuwe Kerk The Hague since burial was a sectarian matter and he was ineligible to be buried in the Jewish cemetery 63 There is no evidence he maintained any sense of Jewish identity Spinoza did not envision secular Judaism To be a secular and assimilated Jew is in his view nonsense 64 Spinoza scholar Yirmiyahu Yovel raises the question of whether or not Spinoza could be categorized as the first secular Jew since he was still regarded as a Jew although he did not adhere to Jewish law or belong to the Jewish community Yovel writes that Spinoza exemplifies the situation of the modern Jew secular assimilationist or national without himself falling neatly into any of these categories Countless Jews in the coming centuries were to find themselves in a similar predicament 65 Career as a philosopher edit nbsp Study room of Spinoza in RijnsburgSpinoza spent his remaining 22 years writing and studying as a private scholar 21 initially teaching in the school of his Latin tutor Franciscus Van den Enden with whom he boarded for a time and later upon leaving Amsterdam earning a living as a lens grinder He also received some financial assistance from supporters of his intellectual stance After the herem the Amsterdam municipal authorities expelled Spinoza from Amsterdam responding to the appeals of the rabbis and also of the Calvinist clergy who had been vicariously offended by the existence of a free thinker in the synagogue He spent a brief time in or near the village of Ouderkerk aan de Amstel but returned soon afterwards to Amsterdam and lived there quietly for several years giving private philosophy lessons and grinding lenses before leaving the city in 1660 or 1661 61 During this time in Amsterdam Spinoza wrote his Short Treatise on God Man and His Well Being which he never published in his lifetime assuming with good reason that it might get suppressed Two Dutch translations of it survive discovered about 1810 61 In 1660 or 1661 Spinoza moved from Amsterdam to Rijnsburg near Leiden the center of Dutch Remonstrants known as the Collegiants 66 In Rijnsburg he began work on his Descartes Principles of Philosophy as well as on his masterpiece the Ethics In 1663 he returned briefly to Amsterdam where he finished and published Descartes Principles of Philosophy the only work published in his lifetime under his own name and then moved the same year to Voorburg In Voorburg Spinoza continued work on his magnum opus eventually entitled Ethics and corresponded with scientists philosophers and theologians throughout Europe He published in Latin anonymously and with false printer information Theological Political Treatise TTP in 1670 in defense of secular and constitutional government and in support of Jan de Witt the Grand Pensionary of Holland against the Stadtholder the Prince of Orange Leibniz visited Spinoza and claimed that Spinoza s life was in danger when supporters of the Prince of Orange murdered de Witt in 1672 67 While the TTP was published anonymously the work did not long remain so and de Witt s enemies characterized it as forged in Hell by a renegade Jew and the Devil and issued with the knowledge of Jan de Witt It was condemned in 1673 by the Synod of the Dutch Reformed Church and formally banned in 1674 68 In 1670 Spinoza moved to The Hague where he lived on a small pension from Jan de Witt and a small annuity from the brother of his dead friend Simon de Vries 69 He worked on the Ethics wrote an unfinished Hebrew grammar began his Political Treatise TP left unfinished at his death wrote two scientific essays On the Rainbow and On the Calculation of Chances and began a Dutch translation of the Bible which he later destroyed 69 Spinoza was offered the chair of philosophy at the University of Heidelberg but he refused it perhaps because of the possibility that it might in some way curb his freedom of thought 70 Spinoza also corresponded with Peter Serrarius a radical Protestant and millenarian merchant Serrarius was a patron to Spinoza after Spinoza was expelled from the Jewish community He acted as an intermediary for Spinoza s correspondence sending and receiving letters of the philosopher to and from third parties Spinoza and Serrarius maintained their relationship until Serrarius death in 1669 71 By the beginning of the 1660s Spinoza s name became more widely known The Secretary of the British Royal Society Henry Oldenburg paid him visits and became a correspondent with Spinoza for the rest of his life 72 In 1676 Leibniz came to the Hague to discuss the unpublished Ethics Spinoza s principal philosophical work parts of which apparently had circulated in manuscript form 73 Lens grinding and optics edit Spinoza earned a modest living from lens grinding and instrument making yet he was involved in important optical investigations of the day while living in Voorburg through correspondence and friendships with scientist Christiaan Huygens and mathematician Johannes Hudde including debate over microscope design with Huygens favouring small objectives 74 and collaborating on calculations for a prospective 40 foot 12 m focal length telescope which would have been one of the largest in Europe at the time 75 He was known for making not just lenses but also telescopes and microscopes 76 The quality of Spinoza s lenses was much praised by Christiaan Huygens among others 77 In fact his technique and instruments were so esteemed that Constantijn Huygens ground a clear and bright telescope lens with focal length of 42 feet 13 m in 1687 from one of Spinoza s grinding dishes ten years after his death 78 He was said by anatomist Theodor Kerckring to have produced an excellent microscope the quality of which was the foundation of Kerckring s anatomy claims 79 During his time as a lens and instrument maker he was also supported by small but regular donations from close friends 21 Death and burial edit nbsp Burial monument of Spinoza at the churchyard of the Nieuwe Kerk The Hague Spinoza s health began to fail in 1676 dying in The Hague on 21 February 1677 at the age of 44 attended by a physician friend Georg Herman Schuller Although he had been ill with some form of lung affliction described as ex phthisi from consumption perhaps complicated by silicosis brought on by grinding glass lenses 80 his death on that particular day was unexpected by himself or his landlord and landlady with whom he lived and he died without leaving a will 81 82 His personal belongings and papers most importantly his unpublished manuscripts were stored in a cabinet attached to his writing desk and were taken away for safekeeping from seizure by those wishing to suppress his writings They do not appear in the inventory of his possessions at death There were assertions that he had repented his philosophical stances on his deathbed but all credible evidence points to his dying unrepentant and in tranquility 83 The first biography of Spinoza 84 by Lutheran preacher Johannes Colerus 1647 1707 was prompted to investigate Spinoza s last days 85 Spinoza was buried in the Nieuwe Kerk New Church on the Spui four days after his death on 25 February inside the church with six others in the same vault At the time there was no memorial plaque for Spinoza In the 18th century the vault was emptied and the remains disposed of with the remnants scattered over the earth of the churchyard The memorial plaque visitors now see is outside where some of his remains are part of the churchyard s soil 86 Writings editSpinoza published little in his lifetime and most of his formal writings were in Latin which would have reached only a small number of readers His supporters published his works posthumously in Latin and in Dutch with other translations to European languages following A descriptive bibliography has been published that contextualizes all aspects of the publication history of Spinoza s writings from manuscript to print 87 The reaction to the anonymously published work Theologico Political Treatise TTP 1670 was extremely unfavorable Spinoza abstained from publishing further but his writings circulated among his supporters during his lifetime Wary and independent he wore a signet ring which he used to mark his letters and which was engraved with the word caute Latin for cautiously underneath a rose itself a symbol of secrecy 88 The Ethics and all other works apart from the Descartes Principles of Philosophy and the Theologico Political Treatise were published after his 1677 death The Opera Posthuma was edited by his friends in secrecy to prevent confiscation and destruction of manuscripts The Ethics contains many still unresolved obscurities and is written with a forbidding mathematical structure modeled on Euclid s geometry 21 and has been described as a superbly cryptic masterwork 89 Major publications edit c 1660 Korte Verhandeling van God de mensch en deszelvs welstand A Short Treatise on God Man and His Well Being 1662 Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione On the Improvement of the Understanding unfinished 1663 Principia philosophiae cartesianae The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy translated by Samuel Shirley with an Introduction and Notes by Steven Barbone and Lee Rice Indianapolis 1998 Gallica in Latin 1670 Tractatus Theologico Politicus A Theologico Political Treatise 1675 76 Tractatus Politicus unfinished PDF version 1677 Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata The Ethics finished 1674 but published posthumously 1677 Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae Hebrew Grammar 90 Morgan Michael L ed 2002 Spinoza Complete Works with the Translation of Samuel Shirley Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 87220 620 5 Edwin Curley ed 1985 2016 The Collected Works of Spinoza two volumes Princeton Princeton University Press Not including the Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae Spruit Leen and Pina Totaro 2011 The Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza s Ethica Leiden Brill Correspondence edit See also Epistolae Spinoza and List of Epistolae Letters of Spinoza nbsp Letter from Spinoza to Leibniz with his BdS sealFew letters are extant for such an important intellectual figure and none before 1661 Spinoza engaged in correspondence from December 1664 to June 1665 with Willem van Blijenbergh an amateur Calvinist theologian who questioned Spinoza on the definition of evil Later in 1665 Spinoza notified Oldenburg that he had started to work on a new book the Theologico Political Treatise published in 1670 Leibniz disagreed harshly with Spinoza in his own manuscript Refutation of Spinoza 91 but he is also known to have met with Spinoza on at least one occasion 72 92 as mentioned above and his own work bears some striking resemblances to specific important parts of Spinoza s philosophy see Monadology In a letter written in December 1675 and sent to Albert Burgh who wanted to defend Catholicism Spinoza clearly explained his view of both Catholicism and Islam He stated that both religions are made to deceive the people and to constrain the minds of men He also states that Islam far surpasses Catholicism in doing so 93 94 The Tractatus de Deo Homine ejusque Felicitate Treatise on God man and his happiness was one of the last Spinoza s works to be published between 1851 95 and 1862 96 Philosophy editSpinoza s philosophy is explicated in his two major publications originally written in Latin the Tratacus Theologico Politicus TTP 1670 and the Ethics published posthumously in Latin and Dutch Tractatus Theologico Politicus edit Main article Tractatus Theologico PoliticusSee also Thomas Hobbes Despite its being published in Latin rather than a vernacular language this 1670 treatise published in Spinoza s lifetime caused a huge reaction described as one of the most significant events in European intellectual history 97 with a prolonged furore that has no parallel in early modern intellectual history 98 Ethics edit The Ethics has been associated with that of Leibniz and Rene Descartes as part of the rationalist school of thought 92 which includes the assumption that ideas correspond to reality perfectly in the same way that mathematics is supposed to be an exact representation of the world The writings of Rene Descartes have been described as Spinoza s starting point 89 Spinoza s first publication was his 1663 geometric exposition of proofs using Euclid s model with definitions and axioms of Descartes Principles of Philosophy Following Descartes Spinoza aimed to understand truth through logical deductions from clear and distinct ideas a process which always begins from the self evident truths of axioms 99 Metaphysics edit Spinoza s metaphysics consists of one thing substance and its modifications modes Early in The Ethics Spinoza argues that there is only one substance which is absolutely infinite self caused and eternal He calls this substance God or Nature In fact he takes these two terms to be synonymous in the Latin the phrase he uses is Deus sive Natura For Spinoza the whole of the natural universe is made of one substance God or what is the same Nature and its modifications modes It cannot be overemphasized how the rest of Spinoza s philosophy his philosophy of mind his epistemology his psychology his moral philosophy his political philosophy and his philosophy of religion flows more or less directly from the metaphysical underpinnings in Part I of the Ethics 100 Substance attributes and modes edit These are the fundamental concepts with which Spinoza sets forth a vision of Being illuminated by his awareness of God They may seem strange at first sight To the question What is he replies Substance its attributes and modes Karl Jaspers 101 Following Maimonides Spinoza defined substance as that which is in itself and is conceived through itself meaning that it can be understood without any reference to anything external 102 Being conceptually independent also means that the same thing is ontologically independent depending on nothing else for its existence and being the cause of itself causa sui 102 A mode is something which cannot exist independently but rather must do so as part of something else on which it depends including properties for example colour relations such as size and individual things 103 Modes can be further divided into finite and infinite ones with the latter being evident in every finite mode he gives the examples of motion and rest 104 The traditional understanding of an attribute in philosophy is similar to Spinoza s modes though he uses that word differently 103 To him an attribute is that which the intellect perceives as constituting the essence of substance and there are possibly an infinite number of them 105 It is the essential nature which is attributed to reality by intellect 106 nbsp Probable portrait of Spinoza by Barend Graat 1666 Spinoza defined God as a substance consisting of infinite attributes each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence and since no cause or reason can prevent such a being from existing it therefore must exist 106 This is a form of the ontological argument which is claimed to prove the existence of God but Spinoza went further in stating that it showed that only God exists 107 Accordingly he stated that Whatever is is in God and nothing can exist or be conceived without God 107 This means that God is identical with the universe an idea which he encapsulated in the phrase Deus sive Natura God or Nature which has been interpreted by some as atheism or pantheism 108 God can be known either through the attribute of extension or the attribute of thought 109 Thought and extension represent giving complete accounts of the world in mental or physical terms 110 To this end he says that the mind and the body are one and the same thing which is conceived now under the attribute of thought now under the attribute of extension 111 After stating his proof for God s existence Spinoza addresses who God is Spinoza believed that God is the sum of the natural and physical laws of the universe and certainly not an individual entity or creator 112 Spinoza attempts to prove that God is just the substance of the universe by first stating that substances do not share attributes or essences and then demonstrating that God is a substance with an infinite number of attributes thus the attributes possessed by any other substances must also be possessed by God Therefore God is just the sum of all the substances of the universe God is the only substance in the universe and everything is a part of God This view was described by Charles Hartshorne as Classical Pantheism 113 Spinoza argues that things could not have been produced by God in any other way or in any other order than is the case 114 Therefore concepts such as freedom and chance have little meaning 108 This picture of Spinoza s determinism is illuminated in Ethics the infant believes that it is by free will that it seeks the breast the angry boy believes that by free will he wishes vengeance the timid man thinks it is with free will he seeks flight the drunkard believes that by a free command of his mind he speaks the things which when sober he wishes he had left unsaid All believe that they speak by a free command of the mind whilst in truth they have no power to restrain the impulse which they have to speak 115 In his letter to G H Schuller Letter 58 he wrote men are conscious of their desire and unaware of the causes by which their desires are determined 116 He also held that knowledge of true causes of passive emotion can transform it into an active emotion thus anticipating one of the key ideas of Sigmund Freud s psychoanalysis 117 According to Professor Eric Schliesser Spinoza was skeptical regarding the possibility of knowledge of nature and as a consequence at odds with scientists like Galileo and Huygens 118 Causality edit Though the principle of sufficient reason is most commonly associated with Gottfried Leibniz 119 it is arguably found in its strongest form in Spinoza s philosophy 120 Within the context of Spinoza s philosophical system the principle can be understood to unify causation and explanation 121 What this means is that for Spinoza questions regarding the reason why a given phenomenon is the way it is or exists are always answerable and are always answerable in terms of the relevant cause s This constitutes a rejection of teleological or final causation except possibly in a more restricted sense for human beings 122 page needed 121 Given this Spinoza s views regarding causality and modality begin to make much more sense Spinoza has also been described as an Epicurean materialist 89 specifically in reference to his opposition to Cartesian mind body dualism This view was held by Epicureans before him as they believed that atoms with their probabilistic paths were the only substance that existed fundamentally 123 124 Spinoza however deviated significantly from Epicureans by adhering to strict determinism much like the Stoics before him in contrast to the Epicurean belief in the probabilistic path of atoms which is more in line with contemporary thought on quantum mechanics 123 125 The emotions edit One thing which seems on the surface to distinguish Spinoza s view of the emotions from both Descartes and Hume s pictures of them is that he takes the emotions to be cognitive in some important respect Jonathan Bennett claims that Spinoza mainly saw emotions as caused by cognitions However he did not say this clearly enough and sometimes lost sight of it entirely 126 Spinoza provides several demonstrations which purport to show truths about how human emotions work The picture presented is according to Bennett unflattering coloured as it is by universal egoism 127 Ethical philosophy edit Spinoza s notion of blessedness figures centrally in his ethical philosophy Blessedness or salvation or freedom Spinoza thinks consists in a constant and eternal love of God or in God s love for men E5P36s 122 page needed And this means as Jonathan Bennett explains that Spinoza wants blessedness to stand for the most elevated and desirable state one could possibly be in 128 Here understanding what is meant by most elevated and desirable state requires understanding Spinoza s notion of conatus read striving but not necessarily with any teleological baggage and that perfection refers not to moral value but to completeness Given that individuals are identified as mere modifications of the infinite Substance it follows that no individual can ever be fully complete i e perfect or blessed Absolute perfection is as noted above reserved solely for Substance Nevertheless mere modes can attain a lesser form of blessedness namely that of pure understanding of oneself as one really is i e as a definite modification of Substance in a certain set of relationships with everything else in the universe That this is what Spinoza has in mind can be seen at the end of the Ethics in E5P24 and E5P25 wherein Spinoza makes two final key moves unifying the metaphysical epistemological and ethical propositions he has developed over the course of the work In E5P24 he links the understanding of particular things to the understanding of God or Substance in E5P25 the conatus of the mind is linked to the third kind of knowledge Intuition From here it is a short step to the connection of Blessedness with the amor dei intellectualis intellectual love of God nbsp Engraving of Spinoza captioned in Latin A Jew and an atheist he vehemently denied being an atheist Pantheism editSee also Pantheism controversy Spinoza was considered to be an atheist because he used the word God Deus to signify a concept that was different from that of traditional Judeo Christian monotheism Spinoza expressly denies personality and consciousness to God he has neither intelligence feeling nor will he does not act according to purpose but everything follows necessarily from his nature according to law 129 Thus Spinoza s cool indifferent God differs from the concept of an anthropomorphic fatherly God who cares about humanity 130 In 1785 Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi published a condemnation of Spinoza s pantheism after Gotthold Lessing was thought to have confessed on his deathbed to being a Spinozist which was the equivalent in his time of being called an atheist Jacobi claimed that Spinoza s doctrine was pure materialism because all Nature and God are said to be nothing but extended substance This for Jacobi was the result of Enlightenment rationalism and it would finally end in absolute atheism Moses Mendelssohn disagreed with Jacobi saying that there is no actual difference between theism and pantheism The issue became a major intellectual and religious concern for European civilization at the time The attraction of Spinoza s philosophy to late 18th century Europeans was that it provided an alternative to materialism atheism and deism Three of Spinoza s ideas strongly appealed to them the unity of all that exists the regularity of all that happens the identity of spirit and nature 131 By 1879 Spinoza s pantheism was praised by many but was considered by some to be alarming and dangerously inimical 132 Spinoza s God or Nature Deus sive Natura provided a living natural God in contrast to Isaac Newton s first cause argument and the dead mechanism of Julien Offray de La Mettrie s 1709 1751 work Man a Machine L homme machine Coleridge and Shelley saw in Spinoza s philosophy a religion of nature 21 Novalis called him the God intoxicated man 89 133 Spinoza inspired the poet Shelley to write his essay The Necessity of Atheism 89 It is a widespread belief that Spinoza equated God with the material universe He has therefore been called the prophet 134 and prince 135 and most eminent expounder of pantheism More specifically in a letter to Henry Oldenburg he states as to the view of certain people that I identify God with Nature taken as a kind of mass or corporeal matter they are quite mistaken 136 For Spinoza the universe cosmos is a mode under two attributes of Thought and Extension God has infinitely many other attributes which are not present in the world According to German philosopher Karl Jaspers 1883 1969 when Spinoza wrote Deus sive Natura Latin for God or Nature Spinoza meant God was natura naturans nature doing what nature does literally nature naturing not natura naturata nature already created literally nature natured Jaspers believed that Spinoza in his philosophical system did not mean to say that God and Nature are interchangeable terms but rather that God s transcendence was attested by his infinitely many attributes and that two attributes known by humans namely Thought and Extension signified God s immanence 137 Even God under the attributes of thought and extension cannot be identified strictly with our world That world is of course divisible it has parts But Spinoza said no attribute of a substance can be truly conceived from which it follows that the substance can be divided meaning that one cannot conceive an attribute in a way that leads to division of substance He also said a substance which is absolutely infinite is indivisible Ethics Part I Propositions 12 and 13 138 Following this logic our world should be considered as a mode under two attributes of thought and extension Therefore according to Jaspers the pantheist formula One and All would apply to Spinoza only if the One preserves its transcendence and the All were not interpreted as the totality of finite things 137 Martial Gueroult 1891 1976 suggested the term panentheism rather than pantheism to describe Spinoza s view of the relation between God and the world The world is not God but it is in a strong sense in God Not only do finite things have God as their cause they cannot be conceived without God 138 However American panentheist philosopher Charles Hartshorne 1897 2000 insisted on the term Classical Pantheism to describe Spinoza s view 113 According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spinoza s God is an infinite intellect Ethics 2p11c all knowing 2p3 and capable of loving both himself and us insofar as we are part of his perfection 5p35c And if the mark of a personal being is that it is one towards which we can entertain personal attitudes then we should note too that Spinoza recommends amor intellectualis dei the intellectual love of God as the supreme good for man 5p33 However the matter is complex Spinoza s God does not have free will 1p32c1 he does not have purposes or intentions 1 appendix and Spinoza insists that neither intellect nor will pertain to the nature of God 1p17s1 Moreover while we may love God we need to remember that God is really not the kind of being who could ever love us back He who loves God cannot strive that God should love him in return says Spinoza 5p19 139 Steven Nadler suggests that settling the question of Spinoza s atheism or pantheism depends on an analysis of attitudes If pantheism is associated with religiosity then Spinoza is not a pantheist since Spinoza believes that the proper stance to take towards God is not one of reverence or religious awe but instead one of objective study and reason since taking the religious stance would leave one open to the possibility of error and superstition 140 Legacy editSpinoza s ideas have had a major impact on intellectual debates from the seventeenth century to the current era His biographer Jonathan I Israel contends that No leading figure of the post 1750 later Enlightenment for example or the nineteenth century was engaged with the philosophy of Descartes Hobbes Bayle Locke or Leibniz to the degree leading figures such as Lessing Goethe Kant Hegel Fichte Schelling Heine George Eliot and Nietzsche remained preoccupied throughout their creative lives with Spinoza 141 On the so called Jewish question Spinoza influenced Moses Mendelsohn and Kant as well as on subsequent thinkers including Marx Nietzsche and Freud 142 Hegel said The fact is that Spinoza is made a testing point in modern philosophy so that it may really be said You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all 143 nbsp A Dutch commemorative coin issued on the 250th death anniversary of Spinoza 1927 Similarities between Spinoza s philosophy and Eastern philosophical traditions have been discussed by many authors The 19th century German Sanskritist Theodor Goldstucker was one of the early figures to notice the similarities between Spinoza s religious conceptions and the Vedanta tradition of India writing that Spinoza s thought was so exact a representation of the ideas of the Vedanta that we might have suspected its founder to have borrowed the fundamental principles of his system from the Hindus did his biography not satisfy us that he was wholly unacquainted with their doctrines 144 145 Max Muller also noted the striking similarities between Vedanta and the system of Spinoza equating the Brahman in Vedanta to Spinoza s Substantia 146 When George Santayana graduated from college he published an essay The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza in The Harvard Monthly 147 Later he wrote an introduction to Spinoza s Ethics and De Intellectus Emendatione 148 In 1932 Santayana was invited to present an essay published as Ultimate Religion 149 at a meeting at The Hague celebrating the tricentennial of Spinoza s birth In Santayana s autobiography he characterized Spinoza as his master and model in understanding the naturalistic basis of morality 150 Philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein evoked Spinoza with the title suggested to him by G E Moore of the English translation of his first definitive philosophical work Tractatus Logico Philosophicus an allusion to Spinoza s Tractatus Theologico Politicus Elsewhere Wittgenstein deliberately borrowed the expression sub specie aeternitatis from Spinoza Notebooks 1914 16 p 83 The structure of his Tractatus Logico Philosophicus does have some structural affinities with Spinoza s Ethics though admittedly not with the Spinoza s Tractatus in erecting complex philosophical arguments upon basic logical assertions and principles Furthermore in propositions 6 4311 and 6 45 he alludes to a Spinozian understanding of eternity and interpretation of the religious concept of eternal life stating If by eternity is understood not eternal temporal duration but timelessness then he lives eternally who lives in the present 6 4311 The contemplation of the world sub specie aeterni is its contemplation as a limited whole 6 45 Spinoza s philosophy played an important role in the development of post war French philosophy Many of these philosophers used Spinoza to erect a bulwark against the nominally irrationalist tendencies of phenomenology which was associated with the dominance of Hegel Martin Heidegger and Edmund Husserl in France at that time 151 Louis Althusser as well as his colleagues such as Etienne Balibar saw in Spinoza a philosophy which could lead Marxism out of what they considered to be flaws in its original formulation particularly its reliance upon Hegel s conception of the dialectic as well as Spinoza s concept of immanent causality Antonio Negri in exile in France for much of this period also wrote a number of books on Spinoza most notably The Savage Anomaly 1981 in his own reconfiguration of Italian Autonomia Operaia Other notable French scholars of Spinoza in this period included Alexandre Matheron Martial Gueroult Andre Tosel and Pierre Macherey the last of whom published a widely read and influential five volume commentary on Spinoza s Ethics which has been described as a monument of Spinoza commentary 152 His philosophical accomplishments and moral character prompted Gilles Deleuze in his doctoral thesis 1968 to name him the prince of philosophers 153 154 Deleuze s interpretation of Spinoza s philosophy was highly influential among French philosophers especially in restoring to prominence the political dimension of Spinoza s thought 155 Deleuze published two books on Spinoza and gave numerous lectures on Spinoza in his capacity as a professor at the University of Paris VIII His own work was deeply influenced by Spinoza s philosophy particularly the concepts of immanence and univocity Marilena de Souza Chaui described Deleuze s Expressionism in Philosophy 1968 as a revolutionary work for its discovery of expression as a central concept in Spinoza s philosophy 155 Albert Einstein named Spinoza as the philosopher who exerted the most influence on his world view Weltanschauung Spinoza equated God infinite substance with Nature consistent with Einstein s belief in an impersonal deity In 1929 Einstein was asked in a telegram by Rabbi Herbert S Goldstein whether he believed in God Einstein responded by telegram I believe in Spinoza s God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists not in a God who concerns himself with the fates and actions of human beings 156 157 Leo Strauss dedicated his first book Spinoza s Critique of Religion to an examination of the latter s ideas In the book Strauss identified Spinoza as part of the tradition of Enlightenment rationalism that eventually produced Modernity Moreover he identifies Spinoza and his works as the beginning of Jewish Modernity 89 More recently Jonathan Israel argued that from 1650 to 1750 Spinoza was the chief challenger of the fundamentals of revealed religion received ideas tradition morality and what was everywhere regarded in absolutist and non absolutist states alike as divinely constituted political authority 158 nbsp Statue 2008 of Spinoza by Nicolas Dings Amsterdam Zwanenburgwal with inscription The objective of the state is freedom translation quote from Tractatus Theologico Politicus 1677 Spinoza is an important historical figure in the Netherlands where his portrait was featured prominently on the Dutch 1000 guilder banknote legal tender until the euro was introduced in 2002 The highest and most prestigious scientific award of the Netherlands is named the Spinozaprijs Spinoza prize Spinoza was included in a 50 theme canon that attempts to summarise the history of the Netherlands 159 In 2014 a copy of Spinoza s Tractatus Theologico Politicus was presented to the Chair of the Dutch Parliament and shares a shelf with the Bible and the Quran 160 Modern era editReconsideration of Enlightenment edit There has been a renewed debate in modern times about Spinoza s excommunication among Israeli politicians rabbis and Jewish press with many calling for the cherem to be reversed 161 Since such a cherem can only be rescinded by the congregation that issued it and the chief rabbi of that community c Haham Pinchas Toledano declined to do so citing Spinoza s preposterous ideas where he was tearing apart the very fundamentals of our religion 162 the Amsterdam Jewish community organised a symposium in December 2015 to discuss lifting the cherem inviting scholars from around the world to form an advisory committee at the meeting However the rabbi of the congregation ruled that it should hold on the basis that he had no greater wisdom than his predecessors and that Spinoza s views had not become less problematic over time 161 Memory and memorials edit Spinoza Lyceum a high school in Amsterdam South was named after Spinoza There is also a 3 metre tall marble statute of him on the grounds of the school carved by Hildo Krop 163 The Spinoza Havurah a Humanistic Jewish community was named in Spinoza s honor 164 The Spinoza Foundation Monument has a statute of Spinoza located in front of the Amsterdam City Hall at Zwanenburgwal 165 It was created by Dutch sculptor Nicolas Dings and was erected in 2008 166 167 See also editBiblical criticism History of the Jews in Amsterdam History of the Jews in the Netherlands Uriel da CostaReferences editNotes edit However Spinoza has also been interpreted as a defender of the coherence theory of truth 3 Baruch Spinoza is pronounced in English b e ˈ r uː k s p ɪ ˈ n oʊ z e 13 in Dutch baːˈrux spɪˈnoːzaː and in Portuguese dɨ ʃpiˈnɔzɐ He was born Bento Portuguese or Baruch Hebrew holding the family name Espinosa 8 In most of the documents and records contemporary with Spinoza s years within the Jewish community his name is given as the Portuguese Bento 14 15 16 In Hebrew without transliteration his full name is written ברוך שפינוזה His given name Baruch Bento means Blessed in Hebrew and Portuguese respectively Later as an author and correspondent he was known in Latin in which he wrote Benedictus de Spinoza was his preferred name also of his signature with the first name sometimes anglicized as Benedict Portugees Israelietische Gemeente te Amsterdam Portuguese Israelite commune of Amsterdam References edit Melamed Yitzhak Y ed 2015 The Young Spinoza A Metaphysician in the Making Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 997168 8 Archived from the original on 1 January 2023 Chapter 7 Stefano Di Bella Tad M Schmaltz eds The Problem of Universals in Early Modern Philosophy Oxford University Press 2017 p 64 there is a strong case to be made that Spinoza was a conceptualist about universals The Coherence Theory of Truth Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 1 November 2019 Retrieved 1 November 2019 David Marian 28 May 2015 Zalta Edward N ed Correspondence theory of truth The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 May 2019 via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Michael Della Rocca ed The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza Oxford University Press 2017 p 288 James Kreines Reason in the World Hegel s Metaphysics and Its Philosophical Appeal Oxford University Press 2015 p 25 Spinoza s foundationalism Hegel argues threatens to eliminate all determinate reality leaving only one indeterminate substance Spinoza s Psychological Theory Spinoza s Psychological Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2022 a b c Nadler 1999 p 45 Nadler 1999 p 119 Nadler 1999 p 64 Nadler 1999 p 65 Steven Nadler Spinoza and Medieval Jewish Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2014 p 27 Spinoza attended lectures and anatomical dissections at the University of Leiden Spinoza Collins English Dictionary HarperCollins Retrieved 27 April 2019 Nadler 1999 p 42 a b c d e Nadler 2001 p 1 Nadler Steven 2022 Baruch Spinoza in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2022 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 20 November 2022 Jonathan Israel in his various works on the Enlightenment Spinoza Life amp Legacy Oxford Oxford University Press 2023 a b Richard H Popkin Benedict de Spinoza at the Encyclopaedia Britannica a b Dutton Blake D Benedict De Spinoza 1632 1677 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 7 July 2019 Why Spinoza Was Excommunicated The National Endowment for the Humanities Retrieved 13 April 2023 a b c d e f Gottlieb Anthony 18 July 1999 God Exists Philosophically review of Spinoza A Life by Steven Nadler Books The New York Times Retrieved 7 September 2009 Israel Spinoza Life and Legacy 322 327 51 Yovel Yirmiyahu 1992 Spinoza and Other Heretics The Adventures of Immanence Princeton University Press p 3 ISBN 0691020795 Destroyer and Builder The New Republic 3 May 2012 Retrieved 7 March 2013 Nadler Steven 16 April 2020 Baruch Spinoza In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stewart 2007 p 352 Simkins James 2014 On the Development of Spinoza s Account of Human Religion Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies 5 1 Smith Steven B Spinoza Liberalism and the Question of Jewish Identity New Haven Yale University Press 1997 2 Jonathan Israel The Banning of Spinoza s Works in the Dutch Republic 1670 1678 in Wiep van Bunge and Wim Klever eds Disguised and Overt Spinozism around 1700 Leiden 1996 pp 3 14 online Archived 28 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine P TOTARO The Young Spinoza and the Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza s Ethics in The Young Spinoza A Metaphysician in the Making ed by Yitzhak Y Melamed New York Oxford University Press 2015 pp 319 332 at 321 2 Hubner Karolina 2022 Spinoza s Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2022 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 4 April 2023 Goldstein Rebecca Betraying Spinoza The Renegade Jew who Gave Us Modernity New York Schocken 2009 ISBN 978 0805211597 Die Lebensgeschichte Spinozas Zweite stark erweiterte und vollstandig neu kommentierte Auflage der Ausgabe von Jakob Freudenthal 1899 M e Bibliographie hg v Manfred Walther unter Mitarbeit v Michael Czelinski 2 Bde Stuttgart Bad Canstatt frommann holzboog 2006 Specula 4 1 4 2 Erlauterungen p 98 119 Rowland Robert New Christian Marrano Jew in The Jews and the Expansion of Europe to the West 1450 1800 Paolo Bernardini and Norman Fiering eds New York Berghahn Books 2001 131 37 Israel Spinoza Spinoza family tree figure 4 1 p 84 Nadler 2001 p 23 Israel Spinoza 90 Nadler 1999 p 47 Nadler 1999 pp 64 65 a b c Scruton 2002 p 21 a b Nadler 2001 p 25 a b Nadler 2001 p 27 a b c Nadler 2001 p 189 Scruton 2002 p 20 Meinsma K O Spinoza et son cercle Etude critique historique sur les heterodoxes hollandais 1896 expanded French edn Paris 1983 Fonseca da Isaac Aboab The Spinoza Web spinozaweb org Retrieved 13 January 2024 Curley Edwin 31 March 2020 A Spinoza Reader The Ethics and Other Works Princeton University Press p xii ISBN 978 0 691 20928 9 Touber Jetze 21 June 2018 Spinoza and Biblical Philology in the Dutch Republic 1660 1710 Oxford University Press p 45 ISBN 978 0 19 252718 9 Nadler 2001 p 7 Nadler 2001 p 2 Steven B Smith Spinoza s book of life freedom and redemption in the Ethics Yale University Press 2003 p xx Introduction Nadler 2001b Nadler 2008 Biography Okhovat Oren Cosmopolitan Empire Portuguese Jewish Merchants and Iberian Imperialism in the seventeenth century Atlantic PhD dissertation University of Florida 2023 Nadler 2001 pp 17 22 Nadler 2001 p 19 Nadler 2001 p 20 Nadler 2001 pp 19 21 Nadler Steven Summer 2020 Baruch Spinoza God or Nature In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University ISSN 1095 5054 OCLC 643092515 Archived from the original on 17 April 2020 Retrieved 5 August 2021 In propositions one through fifteen of Part One Spinoza presents the basic elements of his picture of God God is the infinite necessarily existing that is self caused unique substance of the universe There is only one substance in the universe it is God and everything else that is is in God As soon as this preliminary conclusion has been established Spinoza immediately reveals the objective of his attack His definition of God condemned since his excommunication from the Jewish community as a God existing in only a philosophical sense is meant to preclude any anthropomorphizing of the divine being In the scholium to proposition fifteen he writes against those who feign a God like man consisting of a body and a mind and subject to passions But how far they wander from the true knowledge of God is sufficiently established by what has already been demonstrated Besides being false such an anthropomorphic conception of God standing as judge over us can have only deleterious effects on human freedom and activity insofar as it fosters a life enslaved to hope and fear and the superstitions to which such emotions give rise Nadler 2001 p 28 a b c d e Scruton 2002 p 22 Spinoza s Biography Archived 26 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine in the Encyclopaedia Britannica 14 February 2018 Kramer Howard 17 July 2020 HOME amp GRAVESITE OF BARUCH SPINOZA The Complete Pilgrim Religious Travel Sites The Complete Pilgrim Retrieved 14 March 2022 Nadler 2011 p 167 Ralph Dumain The Autodidact Project Spinoza the First Secular Jew by Yirmiyahu Yovel Steven Nadler Spinoza and Medieval Jewish Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2014 p 27 Spinoza attended lectures and anatomical dissections at the University of Leiden he Spinoza told me Leibniz he had a strong desire on the day of the massacre of Mess De Witt to sally forth at night and put up somewhere near the place of the massacre a paper with the words Ultimi barbarorum ultimate barbarians But his host had shut the house to prevent his going out for he would have run the risk of being torn to pieces A Refutation Recently Discovered of Spinoza by Leibnitz Remarks on the Unpublished Refutation of Spinoza by Leibnitz Edinburg Thomas Constable and Company 1855 p 70 Nadler Steven A Book Forged in Hell Spinoza s Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the Secular Age Princeton Princeton University Press 2011 a b Scruton 2002 p 26 Chaui 2001 pp 30 31 A commentary on Descartes work Principles of Cartesian Philosophy only work published under his own name brought him on an invitation to teach philosophy at the University of Heidelberg Spinoza however refused thinking that it might be demanded the renunciation of his freedom of thought for the invite stipulated that all care should be taken to not insult the principles of the established religion Popkin Richard H Benedict de Spinoza in The Columbia History of Western Philosophy Columbia University Press 1999 p 381 a b Lucas 1960 Stewart 2007 p page needed Christiaan Huygens Oeuvres completes Letter No 1638 11 May 1668 Christiaan Huygens Oeuvres completes letter to his brother 23 September 1667 Nadler 1999 p 215 Nadler 2001 p 183 Christiaan Huygens Oeuvres completes vol XXII p 732 footnote Theodore Kerckring Spicilegium Anatomicum Observatio XCIII 1670 Gullan Whur Within Reason A Life of Spinoza 317 18 Israel Spinoza 2023 1150 51 Nadler Spinoza A Life 2018 406 Israel Spinoza 1152 6 1159 Colerus Johannes The Life of Benedict de Spinoza London 1706 Israel Spinoza 1154 55 Israel Spinoza 1158 Ven Jeroen van de Printing Spinoza A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century Leiden Brill 2022 Stewart 2007 p 106 a b c d e f Bloom Harold 16 June 2006 Deciphering Spinoza the Great Original Book review of Betraying Spinoza The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity by Rebecca Goldstein The New York Times Retrieved 8 September 2009 See G Licata Spinoza e la cognitio universalis dell ebraico Demistificazione e speculazione grammaticale nel Compendio di grammatica ebraica Giornale di Metafisica 3 2009 pp 625 61 see Refutation of Spinoza a b Lisa Montanarelli book reviewer 8 January 2006 Spinoza stymies God s attorney Stewart argues the secular world was at stake in Leibniz face off San Francisco Chronicle Retrieved 8 September 2009 Spinoza on Islam 13 February 2012 Spinoza Baruch 2003 Correspondence of Spinoza Translated by A Wolf Kessinger Publishing LLC p 354 Coyle Patrick A 1938 Some aspects of the philosophy of Spinoza and his ontological proof of the existence of God PDF University of Western Ontario CA p 2 OCLC 1067012129 Retrieved 9 June 2021 via University of Windsor Electronic Theses and Dissertations Soley W R 1 July 1880 Jewish Mediaeval Philosophy in Spinoza Mind Oxford University Press os V 19 362 384 doi 10 1093 mind os V 19 362 ISSN 0026 4423 JSTOR 2246395 OCLC 5545819846 other hand the discovery and publication in 1862 of a lost treatise of Spinoza s the Tractatus brtvia de Deo et homine ejusque felicitate Nadler Book Forged in Hell xi Israel Spinoza Life amp Legacy 776 Scruton 2002 pp 31 32 Della Rocca Michael 2008 Spinoza Routledge pg 33 Jaspers 1974 p 9 a b Scruton 2002 p 41 a b Scruton 2002 p 42 Scruton 2002 p 43 Scruton 2002 p 44 a b Scruton 2002 p 45 a b Scruton 2002 p 38 a b Scruton 2002 p 51 Scruton 2002 p 57 Scruton 2002 p 59 Scruton 2002 p 60 Cannon J A 2009 May 17 World in time of upheaval Sources of enlightenment Deseret News a b Charles Hartshorne and William Reese Philosophers Speak of God Humanity Books 1953 ch 4 Baruch Spinoza Ethics inSpinoza Complete Works trans by Samuel Shirley and ed by Michael L Morgan Indianapolis Hackett Publishing 2002 see Part I Proposition 33 Ethics Part III Proposition 2 Ethics Pt I Prop XXXVI Appendix M en think themselves free inasmuch as they are conscious of their volitions and desires and never even dream in their ignorance of the causes which have disposed of them so to wish and desire Scruton 2002 p 86 Spinoza and the Philosophy of Science Mathematics Motion and Being 9 July 2012 Western philosophy The rationalism of Spinoza and Leibniz Britannica www britannica com Retrieved 25 December 2022 Della Rocca Michael 2008 Spinoza Routledge a b Della Rocca Spinoza 2008 a b Curley 1985 a b Konstan David 2016 Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 21 February 2017 via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ethics Part IV preface Deus seu Natura Baruch Spinoza Human Beings are Determined Lander edu Retrieved 21 February 2017 Bennett 1984 p 276 Bennett 1984 p 277 Bennett 1984 p 371 Frank Thilly A History of Philosophy 47 Holt amp Co New York 1914 I believe in Spinoza s God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists not in a God who concerns himself with fates and actions of human beings These words were spoken by Albert Einstein upon being asked if he believed in God by Rabbi Herbert Goldstein of the Institutional Synagogue New York April 24 1921 published in the New York Times April 25 1929 from Einstein The Life and Times Ronald W Clark New York World Publishing Co 1971 p 413 also cited as a telegram to a Jewish newspaper 1929 Einstein Archive 33 272 from Alice Calaprice ed The Expanded Quotable Einstein Princeton NJ Princeton University Lange Frederick Albert 1880 History of Materialism and Criticism of its Present Importance Vol II Boston Houghton Osgood amp Co p 147 Retrieved 11 November 2015 The Pantheism of Spinoza Dr Smith regarded as the most dangerous enemy of Christianity and as he announced his conviction that it had gained the control of the schools press and pulpit of the Old World Europe and was rapidly gaining the same control of the New United States his alarm and indignation sometimes rose to the eloquence of genuine passion Memorial of the Rev Henry Smith D D LL D Professor of Sacred Rhetoric and Pastoral Theology in Lane Theological Seminary Consisting of Addresses on Occasion of the Anniversary of the Seminary 8 May 1879 Together with Commemorative Resolutions p 26 Hutchison Percy 20 November 1932 Spinoza God Intoxicated Man Three Books Which Mark the Three Hundredth Anniversary of the Philosopher s Birth The New York Times Retrieved 8 September 2009 Picton J Allanson Pantheism Its Story and Significance 1905 Fraser Alexander Campbell Philosophy of Theism William Blackwood and Sons 1895 p 163 Correspondence of Benedict de Spinoza Wilder Publications 26 March 2009 ISBN 978 1 60459 156 9 letter 73 a b Jaspers 1974 pp 14 95 a b Genevieve Lloyd Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to Spinoza and The Ethics Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks Routledge 1 edition 2 October 1996 ISBN 978 0 415 10782 2 p 40 Pantheism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 3 October 2014 Nadler 2008 God or Nature Israel Spinoza Life and Legacy 1205 Smith Spinoza Liberalism and the Question of Jewish Identity 168 69 Hegel Society of America Meeting 2003 Duquette David A ed Hegel s History of Philosophy New Interpretations SUNY Series in Hegelian Studies SUNY Press ISBN 9780791455432 Archived from the original on 13 May 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Literary Remains of the Late Professor Theodore Goldstucker W H Allen 1879 p 32 The Religious Difficulties of India The Westminster Review American ed New York Leonard Scott 78 256 257 October 1862 hdl 2027 mdp 39015013165819 Three Lectures on the Vedanta Philosophy F Max Muller Kessinger Publishing 2003 p 123 George Santayana The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza The Harvard Monthly 2 June 1886 144 52 George Santayana Introduction in Spinoza s Ethics and De intellectus emendatione London Dent 1910 vii xxii George Santayana Ultimate Religion in Obiter Scripta eds Justus Buchler and Benjamin Schwartz New York and London Charles Scribner s Sons 1936 280 97 George Santayana Persons and Places Cambridge MA and London MIT Press 1986 pp 233 36 Peden Knox 2014 Spinoza contra phenomenology French rationalism from Cavailles to Deleuze Stanford California Stanford University Press ISBN 978 0 8047 9136 6 OCLC 880877889 Baugh Peden Bruce 28 March 2015 Spinoza Contra Phenomenology French Rationalism from Cavailles to Deleuze Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews Retrieved 19 May 2022 Deleuze 1968 Quoted in the translator s preface of Deleuze s Expressionism in Philosophy Spinoza 1990 a b Rocha Mauricio 2021 Spinozist Moments in Deleuze Materialism as Immanence Materialism and Politics Berlin ICI Berlin Press pp 73 90 doi 10 37050 ci 20 04 S2CID 234131869 retrieved 19 May 2022 Einstein believes in Spinoza s God Scientist Defines His Faith in Reply to Cablegram From Rabbi Here Sees a Divine Order But Says Its Ruler Is Not Concerned Wit sic Fates and Actions of Human Beings The New York Times 25 April 1929 Retrieved 8 September 2009 Einstein s Third Paradise by Gerald Holton Aip org Archived from the original on 22 May 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Israel J 2001 Radical Enlightenment Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650 1750 Oxford Oxford University Press p 159 Entoen nu Entoen nu Archived from the original on 13 May 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Van der Ham biedt Verbeet Spinoza aan RTL Nieuws 5 July 2012 Retrieved 30 November 2014 a b Rutledge David 3 October 2020 The Jewish philosopher Spinoza was one of the great Enlightenment thinkers So why was he cancelled ABC News ABC Radio National The Philosopher s Zone Australian Broadcasting Corporation Retrieved 7 October 2020 Rocker Simon 28 August 2014 Why Baruch Spinoza is still excommunicated The Jewish Chronicle Online Mo 50 Statue Spinoza Amsterdam in Dutch Archived from the original on 22 January 2022 Retrieved 20 June 2023 SpinozaHavurah org Archived 1 January 2023 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 202 2022 Statute of Spinoza unveiled in Amsterdam centre Simply Amsterdam Nov 25 2008 Archived 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 20 2022 Who stands proud on a pedestal in Amsterdam Unclogged in Amsterdam An American Expat plumbs Holland Aug 22 2020 Archived 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 20 2022 Spinoza Monument CitySeeker com Archived 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 20 2022 Sources editBennett Jonathan July 1984 A Study of Spinoza s Ethics CUP Archive ISBN 978 0 521 27742 6 Chaui Marilena 2001 1995 Espinosa uma filosofia da liberdade Sao Paulo Editora Moderna Curley Edwin M ed 1985 The Collected Works of Spinoza Volume 1 Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 07222 7 Jaspers Karl 23 October 1974 Spinoza Great Philosophers Harvest Books ISBN 978 0 15 684730 8 Lucas P G 1960 Some Speculative and Critical Philosophers In I Levine ed Philosophy London Odhams Nadler Steven M 1999 Spinoza A Life Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 55210 3 Second edition 2018 Nadler Steven M 2001 Spinoza s Heresy Immortality and the Jewish Mind New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926887 0 Nadler Steven 2001b The Excommunication of Spinoza Trouble and Toleration in the Dutch Jerusalem Shofar 19 4 40 52 ISSN 0882 8539 JSTOR 42943396 Nadler Steven 1 December 2008 2001 Baruch Spinoza Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy substantive revised ed Nadler Steven 2011 A Book Forged in Hell Spinoza s Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the Secular Age Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 13989 0 Archived from the original on 29 November 2019 Retrieved 12 October 2011 Scruton Roger 2002 Spinoza A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 280316 0 Stewart Matthew 2007 The Courtier and the Heretic Leibniz Spinoza and the Fate of God in the Modern World W W Norton ISBN 978 0393071047 Further reading editSee also List of works about Baruch Spinoza This further reading section may need cleanup Please read the editing guide and help improve the section October 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Biographies and reference works edit Brenner Golomb Nancy 2010 The Importance of Spinoza for the Modern Philosophy of Science Frankfurt Carlisle Clare 2021 Spinoza s Religion Princeton University Press Della Rocca Michael 2008 Spinoza New York Routledge ed 2018 The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza Oxford University Press Garrett Don ed 1995 The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza Cambridge Uni Press Gullan Whur Margaret 2000 Within Reason A Life of Spinoza New York St Martin s Press Israel Jonathan 2023 Spinoza Life and Legacy New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198857488 Koistinen Olli ed 2009 The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza s Ethics Cambridge Cambridge University Press Popkin R H 2004 Spinoza Oxford One World Publications Yovel Yirmiyahu Spinoza and Other Heretics Vol 1 The Marrano of Reason Princeton Princeton University Press 1989 Yovel Yirmiyahu Spinoza and Other Heretics Vol 2 The Adventures of Immanence Princeton Princeton University Press 1989 Other works edit Damasio Antonio 2003 Looking for Spinoza Joy Sorrow and the Feeling Brain Harvest Books ISBN 978 0 15 602871 4 Deleuze Gilles 1968 Spinoza et le probleme de l expression Trans Expressionism in Philosophy Spinoza Martin Joughin New York Zone Books 1970 Spinoza Philosophie pratique Transl Spinoza Practical Philosophy 1990 Negotiations trans Martin Joughin New York Columbia University Press Della Rocca Michael 1996 Representation and the Mind Body Problem in Spinoza Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 509562 3 Gatens Moira and Lloyd Genevieve 1999 Collective imaginings Spinoza past and present Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 16570 9 978 0 415 16571 6 Goldstein Rebecca 2006 Betraying Spinoza The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity Schocken ISBN 978 0 8052 1159 7 Goode Francis 2012 Life of Spinoza Smashwords edition ISBN 978 1 4661 3399 0 Gullan Whur Margaret 1998 Within Reason A Life of Spinoza Jonathan Cape ISBN 978 0 224 05046 3 Hampshire Stuart 1951 Spinoza and Spinozism OUP 2005 ISBN 978 0 19 927954 8 Hardt Michael trans University of Minnesota Press Preface in French by Gilles Deleuze available here 01 Preface a L Anomalie sauvage de Negri Multitudes samizdat net Archived from the original on 11 June 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Israel Jonathan 2001 The Radical Enlightenment Oxford Oxford University Press 2006 Enlightenment Contested Philosophy Modernity and the Emancipation of Man 1670 1752 ISBN 978 0 19 927922 7 2002 Philosophy Commerce and the Synagogue Spinoza s Expulsion from the Amsterdam Portuguese Jewish Community in 1656 In Dutch Jewry Its History and Secular Culture 1500 2000 Edited by Jonathan Israel and Reinier Salverda pp 125 140 Leiden Brill Ives David 2009 New Jerusalem The Interrogation of Baruch de Spinoza at Talmud Torah Congregation Amsterdam 27 July 1656 New York Dramatists Play Service ISBN 978 0 8222 2385 6 Kayser Rudolf 1946 with an introduction by Albert Einstein Spinoza Portrait of a Spiritual Hero New York The Philosophical Library Lloyd Genevieve 2018 Reclaiming wonder After the sublime Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 1 4744 3311 2 LeBuffe Michael 2010 Spinoza and Human Freedom Oxford University Press Lovejoy Arthur O 1936 Plenitude and Sufficient Reason in Leibniz and Spinoza in his The Great Chain of Being Harvard University Press 144 82 ISBN 978 0 674 36153 9 Reprinted in Frankfurt H G ed 1972 Leibniz A Collection of Critical Essays Anchor Books Macherey Pierre 1977 Hegel ou Spinoza Maspero 2nd ed La Decouverte 2004 1994 98 Introduction a l Ethique de Spinoza Paris PUF Magnusson 1990 Magnusson M ed Spinoza Baruch Chambers Biographical Dictionary Chambers 1990 ISBN 978 0 550 16041 6 Matheron Alexandre 1969 Individu et communaute chez Spinoza Paris Minuit Melamed Yitzhak Y Spinoza s Metaphysics Substance and Thought Oxford Oxford University Press 2013 xxii 232 pp Melamed Yitzhak Y ed The Young Spinoza A Metaphysician in the Making Oxford Oxford University Press 2015 Millner Simon L The Face of Benedictus Spinoza New York Machmadim Art Editions Inc 1946 Montag Warren Bodies Masses Power Spinoza and his Contemporaries London Verso 2002 Moreau Pierre Francois 2003 Spinoza et le spinozisme PUF Presses Universitaires de France Nadler Steven Think Least of Death Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die 2020 Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0691183848 Negri Antonio 1991 The Savage Anomaly The Power of Spinoza s Metaphysics and Politics 2004 Subversive Spinoza Un Contemporary Variations Prokhovnik Raia 2004 Spinoza and republicanism Houndmills Basingstoke Hampshire New York Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 0333733905 Ratner Joseph 1927 The Philosophy of Spinoza The Modern Library Random House Stolze Ted and Warren Montag eds The New Spinoza Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press 1997 Strauss Leo Persecution and the Art of Writing Glencoe Illinois Free Press 1952 Reprint Chicago University of Chicago Press 1988 ch 5 How to Study Spinoza s Tractus Theologico Politicus reprinted in Strauss Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity ed Kenneth Hart Green Albany NY SUNY Press 1997 181 233 Spinoza s Critique of Religion New York Schocken Books 1965 Reprint University of Chicago Press 1996 Preface to the English Translation reprinted as Preface to Spinoza s Critique of Religion in Strauss Liberalism Ancient and Modern New York Basic Books 1968 224 59 also in Strauss Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity 137 77 Valentiner W R 1957 Rembrandt and Spinoza A Study of the Spiritual Conflicts in Seventeenth Century Holland London Phaidon Press Vinciguerra Lorenzo Spinoza in French Philosophy Today Philosophy Today Archived 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine Vol 53 No 4 Winter 2009 Archived 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine Van den Ven Jeroen Printing Spinoza A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century Leiden 2022 Documenting Spinoza A Biographical History of his Life and Time forthcoming Williams David Lay 2010 Spinoza and the General Will The Journal of Politics vol 72 April 341 356 Wolfson Henry A The Philosophy of Spinoza 2 vols Harvard University Press External links editThis article s use of external links may not follow Wikipedia s policies or guidelines Please improve this article by removing excessive or inappropriate external links and converting useful links where appropriate into footnote references October 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Baruch de Spinoza nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Baruch Spinoza nbsp Wikisource has original works by or about Benedictus de Spinoza Articles Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Benedict de Spinoza Spinoza Epistemology Spinoza Metaphysics Spinoza Moral Philosophy Spinoza Political Philosophy Spinoza Free Will and Determinism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spinoza by Steven Nadler Spinoza s Psychological Theory by Michael LeBuffe Spinoza s Physical Theory by Richard Manning Spinoza s Political Philosophy by Justin Steinberg Spinoza Baruch Bento Benedictus De in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2005 by Edwin Curley Bulletin Spinoza of the journal Archives de philosophie Susan James on Spinoza on the Passions Philosophy Bites podcast Spinoza the Moral Heretic by Matthew J Kisner BBC Radio 4 In Our Time programme on Spinoza The Escamoth stating Spinoza s excommunication Gilles Deleuze s lectures about Spinoza 1978 1981 Spinoza in the Jewish Encyclopedia Spinoza in the Encyclopaedia Judaica Video lecture on Baruch Spinoza by Henry AbramsonWorks Spinoza Opera Archived 27 July 2017 at the Wayback Machine Carl Gebhardt s 1925 four volume edition of Spinoza s Works Works by Benedictus de Spinoza at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Baruch Spinoza at Internet Archive Works by Baruch Spinoza at LibriVox public domain audiobooks nbsp Works by Baruch Spinoza at Open Library Refutation of Spinoza by Leibniz In full via Google Books More easily readable versions of the Correspondence Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order and Treatise on Theology and Politics EthicaDB Archived 30 October 2012 at the Wayback Machine Hypertextual and multilingual publication of Ethics A Theologico Political Treatise English Translation A Theologico Political Treatise English Translation at sacred texts com A letter from Spinoza to Albert Burgh Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata et in quinque partes distincta in quibus agetur Opera posthuma Amsterdam 1677 Complete photographic reproduction ed by F Mignini Quodlibet publishing house website The Ethics of Benedict de Spinoza translated by George Eliot transcribed by Thomas Deegan Spinoza Archive on the Digital collections of Younes and Soraya Nazarian Library University of Haifa Portals nbsp Biography nbsp Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Baruch Spinoza amp oldid 1197033406, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.