fbpx
Wikipedia

Gilbert Ryle

Gilbert Ryle (19 August 1900 – 6 October 1976) was a British philosopher,[7] principally known for his critique of Cartesian dualism, for which he coined the phrase "ghost in the machine." He was a representative of the generation of British ordinary language philosophers who shared Ludwig Wittgenstein's approach to philosophical problems.[8]

Gilbert Ryle
Portrait by Rex Whistler
Born19 August 1900
Brighton, England
Died6 October 1976 (aged 76)
Whitby, England
Alma materThe Queen's College, Oxford
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Doctoral students
Other notable students
Main interests
Notable ideas

Some of Ryle's ideas in philosophy of mind have been called behaviourist. In his best-known book, The Concept of Mind (1949), he writes that the "general trend of this book will undoubtedly, and harmlessly, be stigmatised as 'behaviourist'."[9] Having studied the philosophers Bernard Bolzano, Franz Brentano, Alexius Meinong, Edmund Husserl, and Martin Heidegger, Ryle suggested that the book instead "could be described as a sustained essay in phenomenology, if you are at home with that label."[10]

Biography

Family tree

Gilbert Ryle's father, Reginald John Ryle, was a Brighton doctor, a generalist who had interests in philosophy and astronomy, passing on to his children a large library; he was a son of John Charles Ryle, the first Anglican Bishop of Liverpool.[11][12] The Ryles were Cheshire landed gentry; Gilbert's elder brother, John Alfred Ryle, of Barkhale, Sussex, became head of the family. Their ancestor John Ryle, a silk merchant, was a friend of theologian and evangelist John Wesley; members of this Ryle family include the silk manufacturer ("father of the United States silk industry") John Ryle, as well as his nephew and business partner, William.

Gilbert Ryle's mother, Catherine, was daughter of Samuel King Scott (younger brother of the architect Sir George Gilbert Scott) by his wife Georgina, daughter of William Hulme Bodley, M.D., and sister of architect George Frederick Bodley, himself a student of Sir George. Cousins of the Ryle family thus include the haematologist Ronald Bodley Scott, architect George Gilbert Scott Jr., founder of Watts & Co., and his son, Giles Gilbert Scott, designer of the Battersea Power Station.[13]

Early life and education

Gilbert Ryle was born in Brighton, England, on 19 August 1900, and grew up in an environment of learning.

He was educated at Brighton College and in 1919 went up to The Queen's College at Oxford to study classics, but was soon drawn to philosophy. He graduated with a "triple first": he received first-class honours in classical Honour Moderations (1921), literae humaniores (1923), and philosophy, politics, and economics (1924).

Career

In 1924, Ryle was appointed lecturer in philosophy at Christ Church, Oxford. A year later, he became a fellow and tutor at Christ Church, where he remained until 1940.[14]

In the Second World War, Ryle was commissioned in the Welsh Guards. A capable linguist, he was recruited into intelligence work and by the end of the war had been promoted to the rank of Major. After the war he returned to Oxford and was elected Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy and Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. He published The Concept of Mind in 1949. He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1945 to 1946, and editor of the philosophical journal Mind from 1947 to 1971. Ryle died on 6 October 1976 at Whitby, North Yorkshire.[14]

Ryle's brothers John Alfred (1889–1950) and George Bodley (1902–1978), both educated at Brighton College, also had eminent careers. John became Regius Professor of Physic at the University of Cambridge and physician to King George V. George, after serving as Director of Forestry first for Wales and then England, was Deputy-Director of the Forestry Commission and appointed a CBE.[15]

Ryle was the subject of a portrait by Rex Whistler, which he said made him look like "a drowned German General". He was a lifelong bachelor, and in retirement he lived with his twin sister Mary.[16]

Work

The Concept of Mind

In The Concept of Mind, Ryle argues that dualism involves category mistakes and philosophical nonsense, two philosophical topics that continued to inform Ryle's work. He rhetorically asked students in his 1967–68 Oxford audience what was wrong with saying that there are three things in a field: two cows and a pair of cows. They were also invited to ponder whether the bunghole of a beer barrel is part of the barrel or not.[17]

Knowing-how and knowing-that

A distinction deployed in The Concept of Mind, between 'knowing-how' and 'knowing-that', has attracted independent interest. This distinction is also the origin of procedural (knowing-how) and declarative (knowing-that) models of long-term memory.[18] This distinction is widely accepted in philosophy.[18]

Philosophers have not done justice to the distinction which is quite familiar to all of us between knowing that something is the case and knowing how to do things. In their theories of knowledge they concentrate on the discovery of truths or facts, and they either ignore the discovery of ways and methods of doing things or else they try to reduce it to the discovery of facts. They assume that intelligence equates with the contemplation of propositions and is exhausted in this contemplation.

— Gilbert Ryle, Aristotelian Society Presidential Address, 1945.

An example of the distinction can be knowing how to tie a reef knot and knowing that Queen Victoria died in 1901.

Philosophy as cartography

The philosophical arguments which constitute this book are intended not to increase what we know about minds but to rectify the logical geography of the knowledge we already possess.[19]

Ryle thought it no longer possible to believe that a philosopher's task is to study mental as opposed to physical objects. In its place, Ryle saw a tendency of philosophers to search for objects whose nature was neither physical nor mental. Ryle believed, instead, that "philosophical problems are problems of a certain sort; they are not problems of an ordinary sort about special entities."[14]

Ryle analogizes philosophy to cartography. Competent speakers of a language, Ryle believes, are to a philosopher what ordinary villagers are to a mapmaker: the ordinary villager has a competent grasp of his village, and is familiar with its inhabitants and geography. But when asked to interpret a map of that knowledge, the villager will have difficulty until he is able to translate his practical knowledge into universal cartographic terms. The villager thinks of the village in personal and practical terms, while the mapmaker thinks of the village in neutral, public, cartographic terms.[20]: 440–2 

By "mapping" the words and phrases of a particular statement, philosophers are able to generate what Ryle calls implication threads: each word or phrase of a statement contributes to the statement in that, if the words or phrases were changed, the statement would have a different implication. The philosopher must show the directions and limits of different implication threads that a "concept contributes to the statements in which it occurs." To show this, he must be "tugging" at neighbouring threads, which, in turn, must also be "tugging." Philosophy, then, searches for the meaning of these implication threads in the statements in which they are used.[20]: 444–5 

Thick description

In 1949 Ryle first introduced the notion of thick description in "The Thinking of Thoughts: What is 'Le Penseur' Doing?"[21][22] and "Thinking and Reflecting". According to Ryle, there are two types of descriptions:[21]

  1. thin description: surface-level observations of behaviour, e.g. 'His right hand rose to his forehead, palm out, when he was in the vicinity of and facing a certain other human.'
  2. thick description: adds context to such behaviour. Explaining this context necessitates an understanding of the motivations people have for their behaviours, as well as how observers in the community understand such behaviour: 'He saluted the General.'

Legacy

Ryle's notion of thick description[21] has been an important influence on cultural anthropologists such as Clifford Geertz.[23][24]

The Concept of Mind was recognised on its appearance as an important contribution to philosophical psychology, and an important work in the ordinary language philosophy movement. But in the 1960s and 1970s, the rising influence of the cognitivist theories of Noam Chomsky, Herbert A. Simon, Jerry Fodor, and others in the neo-Cartesian school became predominant. The two major postwar schools in the philosophy of mind, Fodor's representationalism and Wilfrid Sellars's functionalism, posited precisely the 'internal' cognitive states that Ryle had argued against. Philosopher Daniel Dennett, a student of Ryle's, has said that recent trends in psychology such as embodied cognition, discursive psychology, situated cognition, and others in the post-cognitivist tradition, have provoked a renewed interest in Ryle's work. Dennett provided a sympathetic foreword to the 2000 edition of The Concept of Mind.[25]

Author Richard Webster endorsed Ryle's arguments against mentalist philosophies, suggesting in Why Freud Was Wrong (1995) that they implied that "theories of human nature which repudiate the evidence of behaviour and refer solely or primarily to invisible mental events will never in themselves be able to unlock the most significant mysteries of human nature."[26]

Books

  • 1949. The Concept of Mind
  • 1954. Dilemmas: The Tarner Lectures 1953, a collection of shorter pieces
  • 1966. Plato's Progress
  • 1971. Collected Essays 1929 - 1968, in two volumes, 57 essays
  • 1977. Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy, editor
  • 1979. On Thinking[27]

References

  1. ^ Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Behaviorism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  2. ^ Neil Tennant, Introducing Philosophy: God, Mind, World, and Logic, Routledge, 2015, p. 299.
  3. ^ Logical Constants (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
  4. ^ Stuart Brown, Diane Collinson, Robert Wilkinson (eds), Biographical Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Philosophers, Routledge, 2012: "Paton, Herbert James."
  5. ^ Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations, Volume 1, Routledge & Keegan Paul, 2001: Introduction by Dermot Moran, p. lxiv: "Husserl... visited England in 1922 intent on establishing relations with English philosopherss.... He delivered a number of lectures which were attended by Gilbert Ryle...."
  6. ^ Michael Dummett, Origins of Analytical Philosophy, Bloomsbury Publishing, 2014, p. xiii; Anat Biletzki, Anat Matarp (eds.), The Story of Analytic Philosophy: Plot and Heroes, Routledge, 2002, p. 57: "It was Gilbert Ryle who, [Dummett] says, opened his eyes to this fact in his lectures on Bolzano, Brentano, Meinong, and Husserl."
  7. ^ "Gilbert Ryle | British philosopher". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 3 September 2018.
  8. ^ A. C. Grayling (Wittgenstein: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1988, p.114) is certain that, despite the fact that Wittgenstein's work might have possibly played some "second or third-hand [part in the promotion of] the philosophical concern for language which was dominant in the mid-century", neither Gilbert Ryle nor any of those in the so-called "ordinary language philosophy" school that is chiefly associated with J. L. Austin (and, according to Grayling, G. E. Moore, C. D. Broad, Bertrand Russell and A. J. Ayer) were Wittgensteinians. Grayling asserts that "most of them were largely unaffected by Wittgenstein's later ideas, and some were actively hostile to them"
  9. ^ Ryle, Gilbert. [1949] 2002. The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 327.
  10. ^ Ryle, Gilbert. 1971. "Phenomenology versus 'The Concept of Mind'." In Collected Papers. London: Hutchinson. p. 188.
  11. ^ Ryle ('Modern Studies in Philosophy' series), ed. Oscar P. Wood and George Pitcher, Doubleday & Co. Ltd, 1970, p. 1
  12. ^ Faith in the Age of Science: Atheism, Religion, and the Big Yellow Crane, Mark Silversides, Sacristy Press, 2012, p. 157
  13. ^ Burke's Landed Gentry, 18th edition, vol. 1, 1965, ed. Peter Townend, p. 615, 'Ryle formerly of Barkhale' pedigree
  14. ^ a b c Tanney, Julia (Winter 2003). "Gilbert Ryle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved 5 March 2008.
  15. ^ "George Bodley Ryle C.b.e". Forestry: An International Journal of Forest Research. 51 (2): 187–188. 1 January 1978. doi:10.1093/forestry/51.2.187. ISSN 0015-752X.
  16. ^ "Gilbert Ryle". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  17. ^ "Ryle: The concept of mind (Summary)". www.the-philosophy.com. 3 June 2012. Retrieved 3 September 2018.
  18. ^ a b Jason Stanley and Timothy Williamson, "Knowing How", Journal of Philosophy, 98(8): 411–444, 2001.
  19. ^ Concept of Mind p 1
  20. ^ a b Ryle, Gilbert. 1971. "Abstractions." In Collected Papers 2. London: Hutchinson.
  21. ^ a b c Ryle, Gilbert. [1968] 1996. "" Studies in Anthropology 11:11. ISSN 1363-1098. Archived from the original on 10 April 2008. Retrieved 25 June 2008.
  22. ^ Ryle, Gilbert. [1968] 1971. "The Thinking of Thoughts: What is 'Le Penseur' Doing?" Pp. 480–96 in Collected Papers 2. London: Hutchinson.
  23. ^ Geertz, Clifford (1973). "Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture". The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays. New-York: Basic Books. pp. 3–30. Retrieved 25 June 2008.
  24. ^ "Gilbert Ryle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2021.
  25. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (2002). "Re-Introducing The Concept of Mind". Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy (7). Retrieved 20 December 2007.
  26. ^ Webster, Richard (2005). Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin, Science and Psychoanalysis. Oxford: The Orwell Press. pp. vii, 483. ISBN 0951592254.
  27. ^ "Gilbert Ryle Collection | Linacre College". www.linacre.ox.ac.uk. Retrieved 3 September 2018.

External links

  • Gilbert Ryle in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • "Ordinary Language", Gilbert Ryle, The Philosophical Review LXII (1953)
  • "Symposium: Use, Usage and Meaning". Gilbert Ryle; J. N. Findlay, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 35 (1961): 223–242.
  • The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy – Issue 7, 2002 (Issue dedicated to Ryle)
  • The Gilbert Ryle Collection at Linacre College, Oxford. Linacre College houses Gilbert Ryle's library along with a collection of his papers
  • "Gilbert Ryle, British ‘Philosopher Of Mind,’ Dead in Yorkshire at 76" The New York Times, 20 October 1976 (obituary)

gilbert, ryle, august, 1900, october, 1976, british, philosopher, principally, known, critique, cartesian, dualism, which, coined, phrase, ghost, machine, representative, generation, british, ordinary, language, philosophers, shared, ludwig, wittgenstein, appr. Gilbert Ryle 19 August 1900 6 October 1976 was a British philosopher 7 principally known for his critique of Cartesian dualism for which he coined the phrase ghost in the machine He was a representative of the generation of British ordinary language philosophers who shared Ludwig Wittgenstein s approach to philosophical problems 8 Gilbert RylePortrait by Rex WhistlerBorn19 August 1900Brighton EnglandDied6 October 1976 aged 76 Whitby EnglandAlma materThe Queen s College OxfordEra20th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolAnalytic philosophylogical behaviourism 1 2 Doctoral studentsDaniel Dennett Colin RadfordOther notable studentsA J Ayer G A Cohen Antony Flew THorsteinn Gylfason Bernard WilliamsMain interestsPhilosophy of languageordinary language philosophyphilosophy of mindbehaviourismmeaningcognitionNotable ideasCategory mistakeRyle s regressordinary language philosophyghost in the machinethick description vs thin descriptionknowing how vs knowing thattopic neutrality 3 Influences Rene Descartes Ludwig Wittgenstein Herbert James Paton 4 Edmund Husserl 5 Influenced J L Austin A J Ayer John Searle R M Hare Wilfrid Sellars Daniel Dennett Richard Webster Ullin Place Clifford Geertz G A Cohen P F Strawson Michael Dummett 6 THorsteinn Gylfason J J C Smart Alan R WhiteSome of Ryle s ideas in philosophy of mind have been called behaviourist In his best known book The Concept of Mind 1949 he writes that the general trend of this book will undoubtedly and harmlessly be stigmatised as behaviourist 9 Having studied the philosophers Bernard Bolzano Franz Brentano Alexius Meinong Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger Ryle suggested that the book instead could be described as a sustained essay in phenomenology if you are at home with that label 10 Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Family tree 1 2 Early life and education 1 3 Career 2 Work 2 1 The Concept of Mind 2 1 1 Knowing how and knowing that 2 2 Philosophy as cartography 2 3 Thick description 3 Legacy 4 Books 5 References 6 External linksBiography EditFamily tree Edit Gilbert Ryle s father Reginald John Ryle was a Brighton doctor a generalist who had interests in philosophy and astronomy passing on to his children a large library he was a son of John Charles Ryle the first Anglican Bishop of Liverpool 11 12 The Ryles were Cheshire landed gentry Gilbert s elder brother John Alfred Ryle of Barkhale Sussex became head of the family Their ancestor John Ryle a silk merchant was a friend of theologian and evangelist John Wesley members of this Ryle family include the silk manufacturer father of the United States silk industry John Ryle as well as his nephew and business partner William Gilbert Ryle s mother Catherine was daughter of Samuel King Scott younger brother of the architect Sir George Gilbert Scott by his wife Georgina daughter of William Hulme Bodley M D and sister of architect George Frederick Bodley himself a student of Sir George Cousins of the Ryle family thus include the haematologist Ronald Bodley Scott architect George Gilbert Scott Jr founder of Watts amp Co and his son Giles Gilbert Scott designer of the Battersea Power Station 13 Early life and education Edit Gilbert Ryle was born in Brighton England on 19 August 1900 and grew up in an environment of learning He was educated at Brighton College and in 1919 went up to The Queen s College at Oxford to study classics but was soon drawn to philosophy He graduated with a triple first he received first class honours in classical Honour Moderations 1921 literae humaniores 1923 and philosophy politics and economics 1924 Career Edit In 1924 Ryle was appointed lecturer in philosophy at Christ Church Oxford A year later he became a fellow and tutor at Christ Church where he remained until 1940 14 In the Second World War Ryle was commissioned in the Welsh Guards A capable linguist he was recruited into intelligence work and by the end of the war had been promoted to the rank of Major After the war he returned to Oxford and was elected Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy and Fellow of Magdalen College Oxford He published The Concept of Mind in 1949 He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1945 to 1946 and editor of the philosophical journal Mind from 1947 to 1971 Ryle died on 6 October 1976 at Whitby North Yorkshire 14 Ryle s brothers John Alfred 1889 1950 and George Bodley 1902 1978 both educated at Brighton College also had eminent careers John became Regius Professor of Physic at the University of Cambridge and physician to King George V George after serving as Director of Forestry first for Wales and then England was Deputy Director of the Forestry Commission and appointed a CBE 15 Ryle was the subject of a portrait by Rex Whistler which he said made him look like a drowned German General He was a lifelong bachelor and in retirement he lived with his twin sister Mary 16 Work EditThe Concept of Mind Edit Main article The Concept of Mind In The Concept of Mind Ryle argues that dualism involves category mistakes and philosophical nonsense two philosophical topics that continued to inform Ryle s work He rhetorically asked students in his 1967 68 Oxford audience what was wrong with saying that there are three things in a field two cows and a pair of cows They were also invited to ponder whether the bunghole of a beer barrel is part of the barrel or not 17 Knowing how and knowing that Edit Main articles Descriptive knowledge and Procedural knowledge A distinction deployed in The Concept of Mind between knowing how and knowing that has attracted independent interest This distinction is also the origin of procedural knowing how and declarative knowing that models of long term memory 18 This distinction is widely accepted in philosophy 18 Philosophers have not done justice to the distinction which is quite familiar to all of us between knowing that something is the case and knowing how to do things In their theories of knowledge they concentrate on the discovery of truths or facts and they either ignore the discovery of ways and methods of doing things or else they try to reduce it to the discovery of facts They assume that intelligence equates with the contemplation of propositions and is exhausted in this contemplation Gilbert Ryle Aristotelian Society Presidential Address 1945 An example of the distinction can be knowing how to tie a reef knot and knowing that Queen Victoria died in 1901 Philosophy as cartography Edit The philosophical arguments which constitute this book are intended not to increase what we know about minds but to rectify the logical geography of the knowledge we already possess 19 Ryle thought it no longer possible to believe that a philosopher s task is to study mental as opposed to physical objects In its place Ryle saw a tendency of philosophers to search for objects whose nature was neither physical nor mental Ryle believed instead that philosophical problems are problems of a certain sort they are not problems of an ordinary sort about special entities 14 Ryle analogizes philosophy to cartography Competent speakers of a language Ryle believes are to a philosopher what ordinary villagers are to a mapmaker the ordinary villager has a competent grasp of his village and is familiar with its inhabitants and geography But when asked to interpret a map of that knowledge the villager will have difficulty until he is able to translate his practical knowledge into universal cartographic terms The villager thinks of the village in personal and practical terms while the mapmaker thinks of the village in neutral public cartographic terms 20 440 2 By mapping the words and phrases of a particular statement philosophers are able to generate what Ryle calls implication threads each word or phrase of a statement contributes to the statement in that if the words or phrases were changed the statement would have a different implication The philosopher must show the directions and limits of different implication threads that a concept contributes to the statements in which it occurs To show this he must be tugging at neighbouring threads which in turn must also be tugging Philosophy then searches for the meaning of these implication threads in the statements in which they are used 20 444 5 Thick description Edit Main article Thick description In 1949 Ryle first introduced the notion of thick description in The Thinking of Thoughts What is Le Penseur Doing 21 22 and Thinking and Reflecting According to Ryle there are two types of descriptions 21 thin description surface level observations of behaviour e g His right hand rose to his forehead palm out when he was in the vicinity of and facing a certain other human thick description adds context to such behaviour Explaining this context necessitates an understanding of the motivations people have for their behaviours as well as how observers in the community understand such behaviour He saluted the General Legacy EditRyle s notion of thick description 21 has been an important influence on cultural anthropologists such as Clifford Geertz 23 24 The Concept of Mind was recognised on its appearance as an important contribution to philosophical psychology and an important work in the ordinary language philosophy movement But in the 1960s and 1970s the rising influence of the cognitivist theories of Noam Chomsky Herbert A Simon Jerry Fodor and others in the neo Cartesian school became predominant The two major postwar schools in the philosophy of mind Fodor s representationalism and Wilfrid Sellars s functionalism posited precisely the internal cognitive states that Ryle had argued against Philosopher Daniel Dennett a student of Ryle s has said that recent trends in psychology such as embodied cognition discursive psychology situated cognition and others in the post cognitivist tradition have provoked a renewed interest in Ryle s work Dennett provided a sympathetic foreword to the 2000 edition of The Concept of Mind 25 Author Richard Webster endorsed Ryle s arguments against mentalist philosophies suggesting in Why Freud Was Wrong 1995 that they implied that theories of human nature which repudiate the evidence of behaviour and refer solely or primarily to invisible mental events will never in themselves be able to unlock the most significant mysteries of human nature 26 Books Edit1949 The Concept of Mind 1954 Dilemmas The Tarner Lectures 1953 a collection of shorter pieces 1966 Plato s Progress 1971 Collected Essays 1929 1968 in two volumes 57 essays 1977 Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy editor 1979 On Thinking 27 References Edit Zalta Edward N ed Behaviorism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Neil Tennant Introducing Philosophy God Mind World and Logic Routledge 2015 p 299 Logical Constants Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stuart Brown Diane Collinson Robert Wilkinson eds Biographical Dictionary of Twentieth Century Philosophers Routledge 2012 Paton Herbert James Edmund Husserl Logical Investigations Volume 1 Routledge amp Keegan Paul 2001 Introduction by Dermot Moran p lxiv Husserl visited England in 1922 intent on establishing relations with English philosopherss He delivered a number of lectures which were attended by Gilbert Ryle Michael Dummett Origins of Analytical Philosophy Bloomsbury Publishing 2014 p xiii Anat Biletzki Anat Matarp eds The Story of Analytic Philosophy Plot and Heroes Routledge 2002 p 57 It was Gilbert Ryle who Dummett says opened his eyes to this fact in his lectures on Bolzano Brentano Meinong and Husserl Gilbert Ryle British philosopher Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 3 September 2018 A C Grayling Wittgenstein A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press Oxford 1988 p 114 is certain that despite the fact that Wittgenstein s work might have possibly played some second or third hand part in the promotion of the philosophical concern for language which was dominant in the mid century neither Gilbert Ryle nor any of those in the so called ordinary language philosophy school that is chiefly associated with J L Austin and according to Grayling G E Moore C D Broad Bertrand Russell and A J Ayer were Wittgensteinians Grayling asserts that most of them were largely unaffected by Wittgenstein s later ideas and some were actively hostile to them Ryle Gilbert 1949 2002 The Concept of Mind Chicago University of Chicago Press p 327 Ryle Gilbert 1971 Phenomenology versus The Concept of Mind In Collected Papers London Hutchinson p 188 Ryle Modern Studies in Philosophy series ed Oscar P Wood and George Pitcher Doubleday amp Co Ltd 1970 p 1 Faith in the Age of Science Atheism Religion and the Big Yellow Crane Mark Silversides Sacristy Press 2012 p 157 Burke s Landed Gentry 18th edition vol 1 1965 ed Peter Townend p 615 Ryle formerly of Barkhale pedigree a b c Tanney Julia Winter 2003 Gilbert Ryle Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford CA The Metaphysics Research Lab Retrieved 5 March 2008 George Bodley Ryle C b e Forestry An International Journal of Forest Research 51 2 187 188 1 January 1978 doi 10 1093 forestry 51 2 187 ISSN 0015 752X Gilbert Ryle The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2021 Ryle The concept of mind Summary www the philosophy com 3 June 2012 Retrieved 3 September 2018 a b Jason Stanley and Timothy Williamson Knowing How Journal of Philosophy 98 8 411 444 2001 Concept of Mind p 1 a b Ryle Gilbert 1971 Abstractions In Collected Papers 2 London Hutchinson a b c Ryle Gilbert 1968 1996 The Thinking of Thoughts What is Le Penseur Doing Studies in Anthropology 11 11 ISSN 1363 1098 Archived from the original on 10 April 2008 Retrieved 25 June 2008 Ryle Gilbert 1968 1971 The Thinking of Thoughts What is Le Penseur Doing Pp 480 96 in Collected Papers 2 London Hutchinson Geertz Clifford 1973 Thick Description Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture The Interpretation of Cultures Selected Essays New York Basic Books pp 3 30 Retrieved 25 June 2008 Gilbert Ryle Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2021 Dennett Daniel C 2002 Re Introducing The Concept of Mind Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 7 Retrieved 20 December 2007 Webster Richard 2005 Why Freud Was Wrong Sin Science and Psychoanalysis Oxford The Orwell Press pp vii 483 ISBN 0951592254 Gilbert Ryle Collection Linacre College www linacre ox ac uk Retrieved 3 September 2018 External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Gilbert Ryle Gilbert Ryle in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ordinary Language Gilbert Ryle The Philosophical Review LXII 1953 Symposium Use Usage and Meaning Gilbert Ryle J N Findlay Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 35 1961 223 242 The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy Issue 7 2002 Issue dedicated to Ryle The Gilbert Ryle Collection at Linacre College Oxford Linacre College houses Gilbert Ryle s library along with a collection of his papers Gilbert Ryle British Philosopher Of Mind Dead in Yorkshire at 76 The New York Times 20 October 1976 obituary Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Gilbert Ryle amp oldid 1147299707, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.