fbpx
Wikipedia

German idealism

German idealism is a philosophical movement that emerged in Germany in the late 18th and early 19th centuries. It developed out of the work of Immanuel Kant in the 1780s and 1790s,[1] and was closely linked both with Romanticism and the revolutionary politics of the Enlightenment. The period of German idealism after Kant is also known as post-Kantian idealism or simply post-Kantianism.[2] One scheme divides German idealists into transcendental idealists, associated with Kant and Fichte, and absolute idealists, associated with Schelling and Hegel.[3]

The four principal German idealists, clockwise from Immanuel Kant in the upper left: J.G. Fichte, G.W.F. Hegel, F.W.J. Schelling

Meaning of idealism edit

The philosophical meaning of idealism is that those properties we discover in objects are dependent on the way that those objects appear to us. These properties belong to the appearance of objects, and are not necessarily something they possess "in themselves".

History edit

Immanuel Kant's work purports to bridge the two dominant philosophical schools in the 18th century: rationalism, which holds that knowledge could be attained by reason alone a priori (prior to experience), and empiricism, which holds that knowledge could be arrived at only through the senses a posteriori (after experience), as expressed by philosopher David Hume, whose skepticism Kant sought to rebut.[4]

Kant's solution was to propose that, while we depend on objects of experience to know anything about the world, we can investigate a priori the form that our thoughts can take, determining the boundaries of possible experience. Kant calls this approach "critical philosophy". It is less concerned with setting out positive doctrine than with critiquing the limits to the theories we can set out.

There is, however, a positive doctrine: "transcendental idealism", which is distinct from classical idealism and subjective idealism. On this view, the world of appearances is "empirically real and transcendentally ideal." That is, the mind plays a central role in shaping our experience of the world: we perceive phenomena in time and space according to the categories of the understanding.

Theorists edit

The best-known German idealist thinkers, after Kant, are J. G. Fichte, F. W. J. Schelling, and G. W. F. Hegel. Critics of Kant's project such as F. H. Jacobi, Gottlob Ernst Schulze, and Salomon Maimon influenced the direction the movement would take in the philosophies of his would-be successors.

Kant edit

According to Immanuel Kant, the human mind is not capable of directly experiencing the external world as it is in itself. Instead, our experience of the world is mediated by the a priori categories and concepts that are inherent in the human mind. These categories and concepts, which Kant calls "transcendental" because they are necessary for any experience, structure and organize our experience of the world, but they do not provide us with direct access to the thing-in-itself, which is the ultimate reality.

Kant's transcendental idealism has two main components. The first is the idea that the human mind is not a passive recipient of sensory information, but is actively involved in shaping our experience of the world. The second is the idea that the nature of reality is ultimately unknowable to us, because our experience of the world is mediated by the structures of our own minds.

Kant restricted the domain of knowledge to objects of possible experience. His three most notable successors, however, would react against such stringent limits.[5]

Jacobi edit

In 1787, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi addressed, in his book On Faith, or Idealism and Realism, Kant's concept of "thing-in-itself". Jacobi agreed that the objective thing-in-itself cannot be directly known. However, he stated, it must be taken on belief. A subject must believe that there is a real object in the external world that is related to its subjective representation. This belief is a result of revelation or immediately known, but logically unproved, truth. The real existence of a thing-in-itself is revealed or disclosed to the observing subject. In this way, the subject directly knows the ideal, subjective representations that appear in the mind, and strongly believes in the real, objective thing-in-itself that exists outside the mind. By presenting the external world as an object of belief, Jacobi aimed to legitimize belief – or faith – in general.

Reinhold edit

Karl Leonhard Reinhold published two volumes of Letters Concerning the Kantian Philosophy in 1790 and 1792. He tried to prove Kant's assertion that humans and other animals can know only phenomena, never things-in-themselves. In order to establish his proof, Reinhold stated an axiom that could not possibly be doubted. From this axiom, all knowledge of consciousness could be deduced. His axiom was: "Representation is distinguished in consciousness by the subject from the subject and object, and is referred to both."

He thereby started, not from definitions, but, from a principle that referred to representations in a conscious mind. In this way, he analyzed knowledge into (1) the knowing subject, or observer, (2) the known object, and (3) the image or representation in the subject's mind.

Schulze edit

Gottlob Ernst Schulze objected to Kant's critical philosophy as self-contradictory. According to Kant himself, the law of cause and effect only applies to the phenomena, not between phenomena and things-in-themselves. Yet, Kant directly claims that the thing-in-itself is the cause of phenomena.

Fichte edit

After Schulze had seriously criticized the notion of a thing-in-itself, Johann Gottlieb Fichte produced a philosophy similar to Kant's, but without a thing-in-itself. Fichte asserted that our representations are the productions of the "transcendental ego", that is, the knowing subject. For him, there is no external thing-in-itself. On the contrary, the subject is the source of the external thing, object, or non-ego.

Fichte claimed that this truth was apparent by means of intellectual intuition. That is, the truth can be immediately seen by the use of reason.

Schelling edit

Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775–1854) claimed that the Fichte's "I" needs the Not-I, because there is no subject without object, and vice versa. So subjective representations are identical to the extended objects which are external to the mind. According to Schelling's "absolute identity" or "indifferentism", there is no difference between the subjective and the objective, that is, the ideal and the real.

Schleiermacher edit

Friedrich Schleiermacher was a theologian who asserted that the ideal and the real are united in God. He understood the ideal as the subjective mental activities of thought, intellect, and reason. The real was, for him, the objective area of nature and physical being. Schleiermacher declared that the unity of the ideal and the real is manifested in God. The two divisions do not have a productive or causal effect on each other. Rather, they are both equally existent in the absolute transcendental entity which is God.

Maimon edit

Salomon Maimon influenced German idealism by criticizing Kant's dichotomies, claiming that Kant did not explain how opposites such as sensibility and understanding could relate to each other. As he clearly saw, this presented a serious skeptical objection to the Kantian project:

By thus pointing out these problematic dualisms, Maimon and the neo-Humean critics left a foothold open for skepticism within the framework of Kant’s own philosophy. For now the question arose how two such heterogeneous realms as the intellectual and the sensible could be known to correspond with one another. The problem was no longer how we know that our representations correspond with things in themselves but how we know that a priori concepts apply to a posteriori intuitions.[6]

Maimon attempted to resolve this problem by introducing the concept of "infinite mind". For this reason, Maimon can be said to have returned to pre-Kantian transcendent speculation. In the words of Frederick C. Beiser, "by reviving metaphysical ideas from within the problematic of the critical philosophy, he gave them a new legitimacy and opened up the possibility for a critical resurrection of metaphysics.[7]

Hegel edit

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel responded to Kant's philosophy by suggesting that the unsolvable contradictions given by Kant in his Antinomies of Pure Reason applied more broadly to reality as such. Given that abstract thought is thus limited, he went on to consider how historical formations give rise to different philosophies and ways of thinking. In The Phenomenology of Spirit, he went on to trace formations of self-consciousness through history and the importance of other people in the awakening of self-consciousness. Thus Hegel introduced two important ideas to metaphysics and philosophy: the integral importance of history and intersubjectivity.

Hegel also claims to sublate the traditional concept of God with his concept of absolute spirit. Spinoza, who changed the anthropomorphic concept of God into that of an underlying substance, was praised by Hegel whose concept of absolute knowing fulfilled a similar function. Hegel claimed that "You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all".[8]

Responses edit

Neo-Kantianism edit

Neo-Kantianism emphasizes the critical dimension of Kant's philosophy as against the perceived excesses of German Idealism. It was the dominant philosophy in Germany during the late 19th and early 20th centuries. Although there was considerable disagreement among the neo-Kantians themselves, they shared a commitment to some version of the "transcendental method".[9]

British idealism edit

In England, during the nineteenth century, philosopher Thomas Hill Green embraced German Idealism in order to support Christian monotheism as a basis for morality. His philosophy attempted to account for an eternal consciousness or mind that was similar to Berkeley's concept of God. John Rodman, in the introduction to his book on Thomas Hill Green's political theory, wrote: "Green is best seen as an exponent of German idealism as an answer to the dilemma posed by the discrediting of Christianity...."[10]

United States edit

"German idealism was initially introduced to the broader community of American literati through a Vermont intellectual, James Marsh. Studying theology with Moses Stuart at Andover Seminary in the early 1820s, Marsh sought a Christian theology that would 'keep alive the heart in the head.' "[11] Some American theologians and churchmen found value in German Idealism's theological concept of the infinite Absolute Ideal or Geist [Spirit]. It provided a religious alternative to the traditional Christian concept of the Deity.[12] The Absolute Ideal Weltgeist [World Spirit] was invoked by American ministers as they "turned to German idealism in the hope of finding comfort against English positivism and empiricism."[13] German idealism was a substitute for religion after the Civil War when "Americans were drawn to German idealism because of a 'loss of faith in traditional cosmic explanations.' "[14] "By the early 1870s, the infiltration of German idealism was so pronounced that Walt Whitman declared in his personal notes that 'Only Hegel is fit for America — is large enough and free enough.' "[15]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Beiser, Frederick C. (2002). German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781–1801. Vol. Part I. Harvard University Press.
  2. ^ Pinkard, Terry (2002). German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism. Cambridge University Press. p. 217.
  3. ^ Dunham, Jeremy; Grant, Iain Hamilton; Watson, Sean (2011). Idealism: A History of a Philosophy. Durham: McGill-Queen's University Press. p. 303 n. 4.
  4. ^ Dudley, Will. Understanding German Idealism. pp. 3–6. ISBN 9781844653935.
  5. ^ "Fichte: Kantian or Spinozian? Three Interpretations of the Absolute I" by Alexandre Guilherme, South African Journal of Philosophy, (2010), Volume 29, Number 1, p. 14.
  6. ^ Beiser, Frederick C. (2000). "Chapter I: The Enlightenment and idealism Section V: The meta-critical campaign". In Ameriks, Karl (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge University Press. p. 28.
  7. ^ Beiser, Frederick C. (1987). "10: Maimon's Critical Philosophy". The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Harvard University Press. p. 287.
  8. ^ Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Section 2, Chapter 1, A2. Spinoza. General Criticism of Spinoza's Philosophy, Second Point of View (cf. paragraph beginning with "The second point to be considered...")
  9. ^ Heis, Jeremy, "Neo-Kantianism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/neo-kantianism/>.
  10. ^ John Rodman, The Political Theory of T. H. Green, New York: Appleton Century–Crofts, 1964, "Introduction"
  11. ^ James Marsh, as quoted by James A. Good (2002) in volume 2 of his The early American reception of German idealism, p. 43.
  12. ^ “The Absolute or World Spirit was easily identified with the God of Christianity....”, (Morton White (Ed.) The Mentor Philosophers: The Age of Analysis: twentieth century philosophers, Houghton Mifflin, 1955, Chapter 1, “The Decline and Fall of the Absolute”)
  13. ^ Schneider, Herbert (1963). History of American philosophy (2nd ed.). New York: Columbia University Press. p. 376.
  14. ^ Dowler, Lawrence (1974). The New Idealism (Ph.D.). University of Maryland. p. 13. as quoted in Good, James Allan. A search for unity in diversity. p. 83.
  15. ^ Walt Whitman, The complete writings, vol. 9, p. 170, as quoted in James A. Good (2005), A search for unity in diversity, ch. 2, p. 57.

Bibliography edit

  • Karl Ameriks (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. ISBN 978-0-521-65695-5.
  • Frederick C. Beiser, German Idealism. The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781-1801. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002.
  • Pinkard, Terry (2002). German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521663816.
  • Josiah Royce, Lectures on Modern Idealism. New Haven: Yale University Press 1967.
  • Solomon, R., and K. Higgins, (eds). 1993. Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. VI: The Age of German Idealism. New York: Routledge.

External links edit

german, idealism, philosophical, movement, that, emerged, germany, late, 18th, early, 19th, centuries, developed, work, immanuel, kant, 1780s, 1790s, closely, linked, both, with, romanticism, revolutionary, politics, enlightenment, period, after, kant, also, k. German idealism is a philosophical movement that emerged in Germany in the late 18th and early 19th centuries It developed out of the work of Immanuel Kant in the 1780s and 1790s 1 and was closely linked both with Romanticism and the revolutionary politics of the Enlightenment The period of German idealism after Kant is also known as post Kantian idealism or simply post Kantianism 2 One scheme divides German idealists into transcendental idealists associated with Kant and Fichte and absolute idealists associated with Schelling and Hegel 3 The four principal German idealists clockwise from Immanuel Kant in the upper left J G Fichte G W F Hegel F W J Schelling Contents 1 Meaning of idealism 2 History 3 Theorists 3 1 Kant 3 2 Jacobi 3 3 Reinhold 3 4 Schulze 3 5 Fichte 3 6 Schelling 3 7 Schleiermacher 3 8 Maimon 3 9 Hegel 4 Responses 4 1 Neo Kantianism 4 2 British idealism 4 3 United States 5 See also 6 References 7 Bibliography 8 External linksMeaning of idealism editMain article Idealism The philosophical meaning of idealism is that those properties we discover in objects are dependent on the way that those objects appear to us These properties belong to the appearance of objects and are not necessarily something they possess in themselves History editSee also Timeline of German idealism Immanuel Kant s work purports to bridge the two dominant philosophical schools in the 18th century rationalism which holds that knowledge could be attained by reason alone a priori prior to experience and empiricism which holds that knowledge could be arrived at only through the senses a posteriori after experience as expressed by philosopher David Hume whose skepticism Kant sought to rebut 4 Kant s solution was to propose that while we depend on objects of experience to know anything about the world we can investigate a priori the form that our thoughts can take determining the boundaries of possible experience Kant calls this approach critical philosophy It is less concerned with setting out positive doctrine than with critiquing the limits to the theories we can set out There is however a positive doctrine transcendental idealism which is distinct from classical idealism and subjective idealism On this view the world of appearances is empirically real and transcendentally ideal That is the mind plays a central role in shaping our experience of the world we perceive phenomena in time and space according to the categories of the understanding Theorists editThis article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations September 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message The best known German idealist thinkers after Kant are J G Fichte F W J Schelling and G W F Hegel Critics of Kant s project such as F H Jacobi Gottlob Ernst Schulze and Salomon Maimon influenced the direction the movement would take in the philosophies of his would be successors Kant edit According to Immanuel Kant the human mind is not capable of directly experiencing the external world as it is in itself Instead our experience of the world is mediated by the a priori categories and concepts that are inherent in the human mind These categories and concepts which Kant calls transcendental because they are necessary for any experience structure and organize our experience of the world but they do not provide us with direct access to the thing in itself which is the ultimate reality Kant s transcendental idealism has two main components The first is the idea that the human mind is not a passive recipient of sensory information but is actively involved in shaping our experience of the world The second is the idea that the nature of reality is ultimately unknowable to us because our experience of the world is mediated by the structures of our own minds Kant restricted the domain of knowledge to objects of possible experience His three most notable successors however would react against such stringent limits 5 Jacobi edit See also Leap of faith In 1787 Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi addressed in his book On Faith or Idealism and Realism Kant s concept of thing in itself Jacobi agreed that the objective thing in itself cannot be directly known However he stated it must be taken on belief A subject must believe that there is a real object in the external world that is related to its subjective representation This belief is a result of revelation or immediately known but logically unproved truth The real existence of a thing in itself is revealed or disclosed to the observing subject In this way the subject directly knows the ideal subjective representations that appear in the mind and strongly believes in the real objective thing in itself that exists outside the mind By presenting the external world as an object of belief Jacobi aimed to legitimize belief or faith in general Reinhold edit Karl Leonhard Reinhold published two volumes of Letters Concerning the Kantian Philosophy in 1790 and 1792 He tried to prove Kant s assertion that humans and other animals can know only phenomena never things in themselves In order to establish his proof Reinhold stated an axiom that could not possibly be doubted From this axiom all knowledge of consciousness could be deduced His axiom was Representation is distinguished in consciousness by the subject from the subject and object and is referred to both He thereby started not from definitions but from a principle that referred to representations in a conscious mind In this way he analyzed knowledge into 1 the knowing subject or observer 2 the known object and 3 the image or representation in the subject s mind Schulze edit Gottlob Ernst Schulze objected to Kant s critical philosophy as self contradictory According to Kant himself the law of cause and effect only applies to the phenomena not between phenomena and things in themselves Yet Kant directly claims that the thing in itself is the cause of phenomena Fichte edit After Schulze had seriously criticized the notion of a thing in itself Johann Gottlieb Fichte produced a philosophy similar to Kant s but without a thing in itself Fichte asserted that our representations are the productions of the transcendental ego that is the knowing subject For him there is no external thing in itself On the contrary the subject is the source of the external thing object or non ego Fichte claimed that this truth was apparent by means of intellectual intuition That is the truth can be immediately seen by the use of reason Schelling edit Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling 1775 1854 claimed that the Fichte s I needs the Not I because there is no subject without object and vice versa So subjective representations are identical to the extended objects which are external to the mind According to Schelling s absolute identity or indifferentism there is no difference between the subjective and the objective that is the ideal and the real Schleiermacher edit Friedrich Schleiermacher was a theologian who asserted that the ideal and the real are united in God He understood the ideal as the subjective mental activities of thought intellect and reason The real was for him the objective area of nature and physical being Schleiermacher declared that the unity of the ideal and the real is manifested in God The two divisions do not have a productive or causal effect on each other Rather they are both equally existent in the absolute transcendental entity which is God Maimon edit Salomon Maimon influenced German idealism by criticizing Kant s dichotomies claiming that Kant did not explain how opposites such as sensibility and understanding could relate to each other As he clearly saw this presented a serious skeptical objection to the Kantian project By thus pointing out these problematic dualisms Maimon and the neo Humean critics left a foothold open for skepticism within the framework of Kant s own philosophy For now the question arose how two such heterogeneous realms as the intellectual and the sensible could be known to correspond with one another The problem was no longer how we know that our representations correspond with things in themselves but how we know that a priori concepts apply to a posteriori intuitions 6 Maimon attempted to resolve this problem by introducing the concept of infinite mind For this reason Maimon can be said to have returned to pre Kantian transcendent speculation In the words of Frederick C Beiser by reviving metaphysical ideas from within the problematic of the critical philosophy he gave them a new legitimacy and opened up the possibility for a critical resurrection of metaphysics 7 Hegel edit Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel responded to Kant s philosophy by suggesting that the unsolvable contradictions given by Kant in his Antinomies of Pure Reason applied more broadly to reality as such Given that abstract thought is thus limited he went on to consider how historical formations give rise to different philosophies and ways of thinking In The Phenomenology of Spirit he went on to trace formations of self consciousness through history and the importance of other people in the awakening of self consciousness Thus Hegel introduced two important ideas to metaphysics and philosophy the integral importance of history and intersubjectivity Hegel also claims to sublate the traditional concept of God with his concept of absolute spirit Spinoza who changed the anthropomorphic concept of God into that of an underlying substance was praised by Hegel whose concept of absolute knowing fulfilled a similar function Hegel claimed that You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all 8 Responses editNeo Kantianism edit Main article Neo Kantianism Neo Kantianism emphasizes the critical dimension of Kant s philosophy as against the perceived excesses of German Idealism It was the dominant philosophy in Germany during the late 19th and early 20th centuries Although there was considerable disagreement among the neo Kantians themselves they shared a commitment to some version of the transcendental method 9 British idealism edit Main article British idealism In England during the nineteenth century philosopher Thomas Hill Green embraced German Idealism in order to support Christian monotheism as a basis for morality His philosophy attempted to account for an eternal consciousness or mind that was similar to Berkeley s concept of God John Rodman in the introduction to his book on Thomas Hill Green s political theory wrote Green is best seen as an exponent of German idealism as an answer to the dilemma posed by the discrediting of Christianity 10 United States edit Main articles Transcendentalism and St Louis Hegelians German idealism was initially introduced to the broader community of American literati through a Vermont intellectual James Marsh Studying theology with Moses Stuart at Andover Seminary in the early 1820s Marsh sought a Christian theology that would keep alive the heart in the head 11 Some American theologians and churchmen found value in German Idealism s theological concept of the infinite Absolute Ideal or Geist Spirit It provided a religious alternative to the traditional Christian concept of the Deity 12 The Absolute Ideal Weltgeist World Spirit was invoked by American ministers as they turned to German idealism in the hope of finding comfort against English positivism and empiricism 13 German idealism was a substitute for religion after the Civil War when Americans were drawn to German idealism because of a loss of faith in traditional cosmic explanations 14 By the early 1870s the infiltration of German idealism was so pronounced that Walt Whitman declared in his personal notes that Only Hegel is fit for America is large enough and free enough 15 See also editGeisteswissenschaft Naturphilosophie Speculative materialism Teleological idealismReferences edit Beiser Frederick C 2002 German Idealism The Struggle Against Subjectivism 1781 1801 Vol Part I Harvard University Press Pinkard Terry 2002 German Philosophy 1760 1860 The Legacy of Idealism Cambridge University Press p 217 Dunham Jeremy Grant Iain Hamilton Watson Sean 2011 Idealism A History of a Philosophy Durham McGill Queen s University Press p 303 n 4 Dudley Will Understanding German Idealism pp 3 6 ISBN 9781844653935 Fichte Kantian or Spinozian Three Interpretations of the Absolute I by Alexandre Guilherme South African Journal of Philosophy 2010 Volume 29 Number 1 p 14 Beiser Frederick C 2000 Chapter I The Enlightenment and idealism Section V The meta critical campaign In Ameriks Karl ed The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism Cambridge University Press p 28 Beiser Frederick C 1987 10 Maimon s Critical Philosophy The Fate of Reason German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte Harvard University Press p 287 Hegel s Lectures on the History of Philosophy Section 2 Chapter 1 A2 Spinoza General Criticism of Spinoza s Philosophy Second Point of View cf paragraph beginning with The second point to be considered Heis Jeremy Neo Kantianism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Edward N Zalta ed URL lt https plato stanford edu archives sum2018 entries neo kantianism gt John Rodman The Political Theory of T H Green New York Appleton Century Crofts 1964 Introduction James Marsh as quoted by James A Good 2002 in volume 2 of his The early American reception of German idealism p 43 The Absolute or World Spirit was easily identified with the God of Christianity Morton White Ed The Mentor Philosophers The Age of Analysis twentieth century philosophers Houghton Mifflin 1955 Chapter 1 The Decline and Fall of the Absolute Schneider Herbert 1963 History of American philosophy 2nd ed New York Columbia University Press p 376 Dowler Lawrence 1974 The New Idealism Ph D University of Maryland p 13 as quoted in Good James Allan A search for unity in diversity p 83 Walt Whitman The complete writings vol 9 p 170 as quoted in James A Good 2005 A search for unity in diversity ch 2 p 57 Bibliography editKarl Ameriks ed The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2000 ISBN 978 0 521 65695 5 Frederick C Beiser German Idealism The Struggle Against Subjectivism 1781 1801 Cambridge Harvard University Press 2002 Pinkard Terry 2002 German Philosophy 1760 1860 The Legacy of Idealism Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521663816 Josiah Royce Lectures on Modern Idealism New Haven Yale University Press 1967 Solomon R and K Higgins eds 1993 Routledge History of Philosophy Vol VI The Age of German Idealism New York Routledge External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Idealism in Germany The London Philosophy Study Guide Archived 2009 09 23 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read depending on the student s familiarity with the subject Nineteenth Century German Philosophy Archived 2007 11 20 at the Wayback Machine Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy articles on Fichte Hegel Kant Reinhold Schelling German Idealism from the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title German idealism amp oldid 1204687811, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.