fbpx
Wikipedia

Morality

Morality (from Latin moralitas 'manner, character, proper behavior') is the differentiation of intentions, decisions and actions between those that are distinguished as proper (right) and those that are improper (wrong).[1] Morality can be a body of standards or principles derived from a code of conduct from a particular philosophy, religion or culture, or it can derive from a standard that a person believes should be universal.[2] Morality may also be specifically synonymous with "goodness" or "rightness".

Allegory with a portrait of a Venetian senator (Allegory of the morality of earthly things), attributed to Tintoretto, 1585

Moral philosophy includes meta-ethics, which studies abstract issues such as moral ontology and moral epistemology, and normative ethics, which studies more concrete systems of moral decision-making such as deontological ethics and consequentialism. An example of normative ethical philosophy is the Golden Rule, which states: "One should treat others as one would like others to treat oneself."[3][4]

Immorality is the active opposition to morality (i.e. opposition to that which is good or right), while amorality is variously defined as an unawareness of, indifference toward, or disbelief in any particular set of moral standards or principles.[5][6][7]

History Edit

Ethics Edit

Ethics (also known as moral philosophy) is the branch of philosophy which addresses questions of morality. The word "ethics" is "commonly used interchangeably with 'morality' ... and sometimes it is used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group, or individual."[8] Likewise, certain types of ethical theories, especially deontological ethics, sometimes distinguish between ethics and morality.

 
Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative: "Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law."

Philosopher Simon Blackburn writes that "Although the morality of people and their ethics amounts to the same thing, there is a usage that restricts morality to systems such as that of Immanuel Kant, based on notions such as duty, obligation, and principles of conduct, reserving ethics for the more Aristotelian approach to practical reasoning, based on the notion of a virtue, and generally avoiding the separation of 'moral' considerations from other practical considerations."[9]

Descriptive and normative Edit

In its descriptive sense, "morality" refers to personal or cultural values, codes of conduct or social mores from a society that provides these codes of conduct in which it applies and is accepted by an individual. It does not connote objective claims of right or wrong, but only refers to that which is considered right or wrong. Descriptive ethics is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense.[10]

In its normative sense, "morality" refers to whatever (if anything) is actually right or wrong, which may be independent of the values or mores held by any particular peoples or cultures. Normative ethics is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense.[10]

Realism and anti-realism Edit

Philosophical theories on the nature and origins of morality (that is, theories of meta-ethics) are broadly divided into two classes:

  • Moral realism is the class of theories which hold that there are true moral statements that report objective moral facts. For example, while they might concede that forces of social conformity significantly shape individuals' "moral" decisions, they deny that those cultural norms and customs define morally right behavior. This may be the philosophical view propounded by ethical naturalists, but not all moral realists accept that position (e.g. ethical non-naturalists).[11]
  • Moral anti-realism, on the other hand, holds that moral statements either fail or do not even attempt to report objective moral facts. Instead, they hold that moral sentences are either categorically false claims of objective moral facts (error theory); claims about subjective attitudes rather than objective facts (ethical subjectivism); or else do not attempt to describe the world at all but rather something else, like an expression of an emotion or the issuance of a command (non-cognitivism).

Some forms of non-cognitivism and ethical subjectivism, while considered anti-realist in the robust sense used here, are considered realist in the sense synonymous with moral universalism. For example, universal prescriptivism is a universalist form of non-cognitivism which claims that morality is derived from reasoning about implied imperatives, and divine command theory and ideal observer theory are universalist forms of ethical subjectivism which claim that morality is derived from the edicts of a god or the hypothetical decrees of a perfectly rational being, respectively.

Anthropology Edit

Morality with practical reasoning Edit

Practical reason is necessary for the moral agency but it is not a sufficient condition for moral agency.[12] Real life issues that need solutions do need both rationality and emotion to be sufficiently moral. One uses rationality as a pathway to the ultimate decision, but the environment and emotions towards the environment at the moment must be a factor for the result to be truly moral, as morality is subject to culture. Something can only be morally acceptable if the culture as a whole has accepted this to be true. Both practical reason and relevant emotional factors are acknowledged as significant in determining the morality of a decision.[13][neutrality is disputed]

Tribal and territorial Edit

Celia Green made a distinction between tribal and territorial morality.[14] She characterizes the latter as predominantly negative and proscriptive: it defines a person's territory, including his or her property and dependents, which is not to be damaged or interfered with. Apart from these proscriptions, territorial morality is permissive, allowing the individual whatever behaviour does not interfere with the territory of another. By contrast, tribal morality is prescriptive, imposing the norms of the collective on the individual. These norms will be arbitrary, culturally dependent and 'flexible', whereas territorial morality aims at rules which are universal and absolute, such as Kant's 'categorical imperative' and Geisler's graded absolutism. Green relates the development of territorial morality to the rise of the concept of private property, and the ascendancy of contract over status.

In-group and out-group Edit

Some observers hold that individuals apply distinct sets of moral rules to people depending on their membership of an "in-group" (the individual and those they believe to be of the same group) or an "out-group" (people not entitled to be treated according to the same rules). Some biologists, anthropologists and evolutionary psychologists believe this in-group/out-group discrimination has evolved because it enhances group survival. This belief has been confirmed by simple computational models of evolution.[15] In simulations this discrimination can result in both unexpected cooperation towards the in-group and irrational hostility towards the out-group.[16] Gary R. Johnson and V.S. Falger have argued that nationalism and patriotism are forms of this in-group/out-group boundary. Jonathan Haidt has noted[17] that experimental observation indicating an in-group criterion provides one moral foundation substantially used by conservatives, but far less so by liberals.

In-group preference is also helpful at the individual level for the passing on of one's genes. For example, a mother who favors her own children more highly than the children of other people will give greater resources to her children than she will to strangers', thus heightening her children's chances of survival and her own gene's chances of being perpetuated. Due to this, within a population, there is substantial selection pressure exerted toward this kind of self-interest, such that eventually, all parents wind up favoring their own children (the in-group) over other children (the out-group).

Comparing cultures Edit

Peterson and Seligman[18] approach the anthropological view looking across cultures, geo-cultural areas and across millennia. They conclude that certain virtues have prevailed in all cultures they examined. The major virtues they identified include wisdom / knowledge; courage; humanity; justice; temperance; and transcendence. Each of these includes several divisions. For instance humanity includes love, kindness, and social intelligence.

Still, others theorize that morality is not always absolute, contending that moral issues often differ along cultural lines. A 2014 PEW research study among several nations illuminates significant cultural differences among issues commonly related to morality, including divorce, extramarital affairs, homosexuality, gambling, abortion, alcohol use, contraceptive use, and premarital sex. Each of the 40 countries in this study has a range of percentages according to what percentage of each country believes the common moral issues are acceptable, unacceptable, or not moral issues at all. Each percentage regarding the significance of the moral issue varies greatly on the culture in which the moral issue is presented.[19]

Advocates of a theory known as moral relativism subscribe to the notion that moral virtues are right or wrong only within the context of a certain standpoint (e.g., cultural community). In other words, what is morally acceptable in one culture may be taboo in another. They further contend that no moral virtue can objectively be proven right or wrong [20] Critics of moral relativism point to historical atrocities such as infanticide, slavery, or genocide as counter arguments, noting the difficulty in accepting these actions simply through cultural lenses.

Fons Trompenaars, author of Did the Pedestrian Die?, tested members of different cultures with various moral dilemmas. One of these was whether the driver of a car would have his friend, a passenger riding in the car, lie in order to protect the driver from the consequences of driving too fast and hitting a pedestrian. Trompenaars found that different cultures had quite different expectations, from none to definite.[21]

Anthropologists from Oxford’s Institute of Cognitive & Evolutionary Anthropology (part of the School of Anthropology & Museum Ethnography) analysed ethnographic accounts of ethics from 60 societies, comprising over 600,000 words from over 600 sources and discovered what they believe to be seven universal moral rules: help your family, help your group, return favours, be brave, defer to superiors, divide resources fairly, and respect others’ property.[22][23]

Evolution Edit

The development of modern morality is a process closely tied to sociocultural evolution. Some evolutionary biologists, particularly sociobiologists, believe that morality is a product of evolutionary forces acting at an individual level and also at the group level through group selection (although to what degree this actually occurs is a controversial topic in evolutionary theory). Some sociobiologists contend that the set of behaviors that constitute morality evolved largely because they provided possible survival or reproductive benefits (i.e. increased evolutionary success). Humans consequently evolved "pro-social" emotions, such as feelings of empathy or guilt, in response to these moral behaviors.

On this understanding, moralities are sets of self-perpetuating and biologically driven behaviors which encourage human cooperation. Biologists contend that all social animals, from ants to elephants, have modified their behaviors, by restraining immediate selfishness in order to improve their evolutionary fitness. Human morality, although sophisticated and complex relative to the moralities of other animals, is essentially a natural phenomenon that evolved to restrict excessive individualism that could undermine a group's cohesion and thereby reducing the individuals' fitness.[24]

On this view, moral codes are ultimately founded on emotional instincts and intuitions that were selected for in the past because they aided survival and reproduction (inclusive fitness). Examples: the maternal bond is selected for because it improves the survival of offspring; the Westermarck effect, where close proximity during early years reduces mutual sexual attraction, underpins taboos against incest because it decreases the likelihood of genetically risky behaviour such as inbreeding.

The phenomenon of reciprocity in nature is seen by evolutionary biologists as one way to begin to understand human morality. Its function is typically to ensure a reliable supply of essential resources, especially for animals living in a habitat where food quantity or quality fluctuates unpredictably. For example, some vampire bats fail to feed on prey some nights while others manage to consume a surplus. Bats that did eat will then regurgitate part of their blood meal to save a conspecific from starvation. Since these animals live in close-knit groups over many years, an individual can count on other group members to return the favor on nights when it goes hungry (Wilkinson, 1984)

Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce (2009) have argued that morality is a suite of behavioral capacities likely shared by all mammals living in complex social groups (e.g., wolves, coyotes, elephants, dolphins, rats, chimpanzees). They define morality as "a suite of interrelated other-regarding behaviors that cultivate and regulate complex interactions within social groups." This suite of behaviors includes empathy, reciprocity, altruism, cooperation, and a sense of fairness.[25] In related work, it has been convincingly demonstrated that chimpanzees show empathy for each other in a wide variety of contexts.[26] They also possess the ability to engage in deception, and a level of social politics[27] prototypical of our own tendencies for gossip and reputation management.

Christopher Boehm (1982)[28] has hypothesized that the incremental development of moral complexity throughout hominid evolution was due to the increasing need to avoid disputes and injuries in moving to open savanna and developing stone weapons. Other theories are that increasing complexity was simply a correlate of increasing group size and brain size, and in particular the development of theory of mind abilities.

Psychology Edit

 
Kohlberg's model of moral development

In modern moral psychology, morality is sometimes considered to change through personal development. Several psychologists have produced theories on the development of morals, usually going through stages of different morals. Lawrence Kohlberg, Jean Piaget, and Elliot Turiel have cognitive-developmental approaches to moral development; to these theorists morality forms in a series of constructive stages or domains. In the Ethics of care approach established by Carol Gilligan, moral development occurs in the context of caring, mutually responsive relationships which are based on interdependence, particularly in parenting but also in social relationships generally.[29] Social psychologists such as Martin Hoffman and Jonathan Haidt emphasize social and emotional development based on biology, such as empathy. Moral identity theorists, such as William Damon and Mordechai Nisan, see moral commitment as arising from the development of a self-identity that is defined by moral purposes: this moral self-identity leads to a sense of responsibility to pursue such purposes. Of historical interest in psychology are the theories of psychoanalysts such as Sigmund Freud, who believe that moral development is the product of aspects of the super-ego as guilt-shame avoidance. Theories of moral development therefore tend to regard it as positive moral development: the higher stages are morally higher, though this, naturally, involves a circular argument. The higher stages are better because they are higher, but the better higher because they are better.

As an alternative to viewing morality as an individual trait, some sociologists as well as social- and discursive psychologists have taken upon themselves to study the in-vivo aspects of morality by examining how persons conduct themselves in social interaction.[30][31][32][33]

A new study analyses the common perception of a decline in morality in societies worldwide and throughout history. Adam M. Mastroianni and Daniel T. Gilbert present a series of studies indicating that the perception of moral decline is an illusion and easily produced, with implications for misallocation of resources, underuse of social support, and social influence. To begin with, the authors demonstrate that people in no less than 60 nations hold the belief that morality is deteriorating continuously, and this conviction has been present for the last 70 years. Subsequently, they indicate that people ascribe this decay to the declining morality of individuals as they age and the succeeding generations. Thirdly, the authors demonstrate that people's evaluations of the morality of their peers have not decreased over time, indicating that the belief in moral decline is an illusion. Lastly, the authors explain a basic psychological mechanism that uses two well-established phenomena (distorted exposure to information and distorted memory of information) to cause the illusion of moral decline. The authors present studies that validate some of the predictions about the circumstances in which the perception of moral decline is attenuated, eliminated, or reversed (e.g., when participants are asked about the morality of people closest to them or people who lived before they were born).[34]

Moral cognition Edit

Moral cognition refers to cognitive processes implicated in moral judgment and decision making, and moral action. It consists of several domain-general cognitive processes, ranging from perception of a morally salient stimulus to reasoning when faced with a moral dilemma. While it's important to mention that there is not a single cognitive faculty dedicated exclusively to moral cognition,[35][36] characterizing the contributions of domain-general processes to moral behavior is a critical scientific endeavor to understand how morality works and how it can be improved.[37]

Cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists investigate the inputs to these cognitive processes and their interactions, as well as how these contribute to moral behavior by running controlled experiments.[38] In these experiments putatively moral versus nonmoral stimuli are compared to each other, while controlling for other variables such as content or working memory load. Often, the differential neural response to specifically moral statements or scenes, are examined using functional neuroimaging experiments.

Critically, the specific cognitive processes that are involved depend on the prototypical situation that a person encounters.[39] For instance, while situations that require an active decision on a moral dilemma may require active reasoning, an immediate reaction to a shocking moral violation may involve quick, affect-laden processes. Nonetheless, certain cognitive skills such as being able to attribute mental states—beliefs, intents, desires, emotions to oneself, and others is a common feature of a broad range of prototypical situations. In line with this, a meta-analysis found overlapping activity between moral emotion and moral reasoning tasks, suggesting a shared neural network for both tasks.[40] The results of this meta-analysis, however, also demonstrated that the processing of moral input is affected by task demands.

Regarding the issues of morality in video games, some scholars believe that because players appear in video games as actors, they maintain a distance between their sense of self and the role of the game in terms of imagination. Therefore, the decision-making and moral behavior of players in the game are not representing player's Moral dogma.[41]

It has been recently found that moral judgment consists in concurrent evaluations of three different components that align with precepts from three dominant moral theories (virtue ethics, deontology, and consequentialism): the character of a person (Agent-component, A); their actions (Deed-component, D); and the consequences brought about in the situation (Consequences-component, C).[42] This, implies that various inputs of the situation a person encounters affect moral cognition.

Neuroscience Edit

The brain areas that are consistently involved when humans reason about moral issues have been investigated by multiple quantitative large-scale meta-analyses of the brain activity changes reported in the moral neuroscience literature.[43][40][44][45] The neural network underlying moral decisions overlaps with the network pertaining to representing others' intentions (i.e., theory of mind) and the network pertaining to representing others' (vicariously experienced) emotional states (i.e., empathy). This supports the notion that moral reasoning is related to both seeing things from other persons' points of view and to grasping others' feelings. These results provide evidence that the neural network underlying moral decisions is probably domain-global (i.e., there might be no such things as a "moral module" in the human brain) and might be dissociable into cognitive and affective sub-systems.[43]

Cognitive neuroscientist Jean Decety thinks that the ability to recognize and vicariously experience what another individual is undergoing was a key step forward in the evolution of social behavior, and ultimately, morality.[46] The inability to feel empathy is one of the defining characteristics of psychopathy, and this would appear to lend support to Decety's view.[47][48]


Brain areas Edit

An essential, shared component of moral judgment involves the capacity to detect morally salient content within a given social context. Recent research implicated the salience network in this initial detection of moral content.[49] The salience network responds to behaviorally salient events [50] and may be critical to modulate downstream default and frontal control network interactions in the service of complex moral reasoning and decision-making processes.

The explicit making of moral right and wrong judgments coincides with activation in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPC), a region involved in valuation, while intuitive reactions to situations containing implicit moral issues activates the temporoparietal junction area, a region that plays a key role in understanding intentions and beliefs.[51][49]

Stimulation of the VMPC by transcranial magnetic stimulation, or neurological lesion, has been shown to inhibit the ability of human subjects to take into account intent when forming a moral judgment. According to such investigations, TMS did not disrupt participants' ability to make any moral judgment. On the contrary, moral judgments of intentional harms and non-harms were unaffected by TMS to either the RTPJ or the control site; presumably, however, people typically make moral judgments of intentional harms by considering not only the action's harmful outcome but the agent's intentions and beliefs. So why were moral judgments of intentional harms not affected by TMS to the RTPJ? One possibility is that moral judgments typically reflect a weighted function of any morally relevant information that is available at the time. Based on this view, when information concerning the agent's belief is unavailable or degraded, the resulting moral judgment simply reflects a higher weighting of other morally relevant factors (e.g., outcome). Alternatively, following TMS to the RTPJ, moral judgments might be made via an abnormal processing route that does not take belief into account. On either account, when belief information is degraded or unavailable, moral judgments are shifted toward other morally relevant factors (e.g., outcome). For intentional harms and non-harms, however, the outcome suggests the same moral judgment as to the intention. Thus, the researchers suggest that TMS to the RTPJ disrupted the processing of negative beliefs for both intentional harms and attempted harms, but the current design allowed the investigators to detect this effect only in the case of attempted harms, in which the neutral outcomes did not afford harsh moral judgments on their own.[52]

Similarly, individuals with a lesion of the VMPC judge an action purely on its outcome and are unable to take into account the intent of that action.[53]

Genetics Edit

Moral intuitions may have genetic bases. A 2022 study conducted by scholars Michael Zakharin and Timothy C. Bates, and published by the European Journal of Personality, found that moral foundations have significant genetic bases.[54] Another study, conducted by Smith and Hatemi, similarly found significant evidence in support of moral heritability by looking at and comparing the answers of moral dilemmas between twins.[55]

Genetics play a role in influencing prosocial behaviors and moral decision-making. Genetics contribute to the development and expression of certain traits and behaviors, including those related to morality. However, it is important to note that while genetics play a role in shaping certain aspects of moral behavior, morality itself is a multifaceted concept that encompasses cultural, societal, and personal influences as well.

Politics Edit

If morality is the answer to the question 'how ought we to live' at the individual level, politics can be seen as addressing the same question at the social level, though the political sphere raises additional problems and challenges.[56] It is therefore unsurprising that evidence has been found of a relationship between attitudes in morality and politics. Moral foundations theory, authored by Jonathan Haidt and colleagues,[57][58] has been used to study the differences between liberals and conservatives, in this regard.[17][59] Haidt found that Americans who identified as liberals tended to value care and fairness higher than loyalty, respect and purity. Self-identified conservative Americans valued care and fairness less and the remaining three values more. Both groups gave care the highest over-all weighting, but conservatives valued fairness the lowest, whereas liberals valued purity the lowest. Haidt also hypothesizes that the origin of this division in the United States can be traced to geo-historical factors, with conservatism strongest in closely knit, ethnically homogeneous communities, in contrast to port-cities, where the cultural mix is greater, thus requiring more liberalism.

Group morality develops from shared concepts and beliefs and is often codified to regulate behavior within a culture or community. Various defined actions come to be called moral or immoral. Individuals who choose moral action are popularly held to possess "moral fiber", whereas those who indulge in immoral behavior may be labeled as socially degenerate. The continued existence of a group may depend on widespread conformity to codes of morality; an inability to adjust moral codes in response to new challenges is sometimes credited with the demise of a community (a positive example would be the function of Cistercian reform in reviving monasticism; a negative example would be the role of the Dowager Empress in the subjugation of China to European interests). Within nationalist movements, there has been some tendency to feel that a nation will not survive or prosper without acknowledging one common morality, regardless of its content.

Political morality is also relevant to the behavior internationally of national governments, and to the support they receive from their host population. The Sentience Institute, co-founded by Jacy Reese Anthis, analyzes the trajectory of moral progress in society via the framework of an expanding moral circle.[60] Noam Chomsky states that

... if we adopt the principle of universality: if an action is right (or wrong) for others, it is right (or wrong) for us. Those who do not rise to the minimal moral level of applying to themselves the standards they apply to others—more stringent ones, in fact—plainly cannot be taken seriously when they speak of appropriateness of response; or of right and wrong, good and evil. In fact, one of them, maybe the most, elementary of moral principles is that of universality, that is, If something's right for me, it's right for you; if it's wrong for you, it's wrong for me. Any moral code that is even worth looking at has that at its core somehow.[61]

Religion Edit

Religion and morality are not synonymous. Morality does not depend upon religion although for some this is "an almost automatic assumption".[62] According to The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics, religion and morality "are to be defined differently and have no definitional connections with each other. Conceptually and in principle, morality and a religious value system are two distinct kinds of value systems or action guides."[63]

Positions Edit

Within the wide range of moral traditions, religious value systems co-exist with contemporary secular frameworks such as consequentialism, freethought, humanism, utilitarianism, and others. There are many types of religious value systems. Modern monotheistic religions, such as Islam, Judaism, Christianity, and to a certain degree others such as Sikhism and Zoroastrianism, define right and wrong by the laws and rules set forth by their respective scriptures and as interpreted by religious leaders within the respective faith. Other religions spanning pantheistic to nontheistic tend to be less absolute. For example, within Buddhism, the intention of the individual and the circumstances should be accounted for in the form of Merit, to determine if an action is right or wrong termed.[64] A further disparity between the values of religious traditions is pointed out by Barbara Stoler Miller, who states that, in Hinduism, "practically, right and wrong are decided according to the categories of social rank, kinship, and stages of life. For modern Westerners, who have been raised on ideals of universality and egalitarianism, this relativity of values and obligations is the aspect of Hinduism most difficult to understand".[65]

Religions provide different ways of dealing with moral dilemmas. For example, there is no absolute prohibition on killing in Hinduism, which recognizes that it "may be inevitable and indeed necessary" in certain circumstances.[66] In monotheistic traditions, certain acts are viewed in more absolute terms, such as abortion or divorce.[a] Religion is not always positively associated with morality. Philosopher David Hume stated that, "the greatest crimes have been found, in many instances, to be compatible with a superstitious piety and devotion; Hence it is justly regarded as unsafe to draw any inference in favor of a man's morals, from the fervor or strictness of his religious exercises, even though he himself believe them sincere."[67]

Religious value systems can also be used to justify acts that are contrary to contemporary morality, such as massacres, misogyny and slavery. For example, Simon Blackburn states that "apologists for Hinduism defend or explain away its involvement with the caste system, and apologists for Islam defend or explain away its harsh penal code or its attitude to women and infidels".[68] In regard to Christianity, he states that the "Bible can be read as giving us a carte blanche for harsh attitudes to children, the mentally handicapped, animals, the environment, the divorced, unbelievers, people with various sexual habits, and elderly women",[69] and notes morally suspect themes in the Bible's New Testament as well.[70][e] Elizabeth Anderson likewise holds that "the Bible contains both good and evil teachings", and it is "morally inconsistent".[71] Christian apologists address Blackburn's viewpoints[72] and construe that Jewish laws in the Hebrew Bible showed the evolution of moral standards towards protecting the vulnerable, imposing a death penalty on those pursuing slavery and treating slaves as persons and not property.[73] Humanists like Paul Kurtz believe that we can identify moral values across cultures, even if we do not appeal to a supernatural or universalist understanding of principles – values including integrity, trustworthiness, benevolence, and fairness. These values can be resources for finding common ground between believers and nonbelievers.[74]

Empirical analyses Edit

Several studies have been conducted on the empirics of morality in various countries, and the overall relationship between faith and crime is unclear.[b] A 2001 review of studies on this topic found "The existing evidence surrounding the effect of religion on crime is varied, contested, and inconclusive, and currently, no persuasive answer exists as to the empirical relationship between religion and crime."[75] Phil Zuckerman's 2008 book, Society without God, based on studies conducted during 14 months in Scandinavia in 2005–2006, notes that Denmark and Sweden, "which are probably the least religious countries in the world, and possibly in the history of the world", enjoy "among the lowest violent crime rates in the world [and] the lowest levels of corruption in the world".[76][c]

Dozens of studies have been conducted on this topic since the twentieth century. A 2005 study by Gregory S. Paul published in the Journal of Religion and Society stated that, "In general, higher rates of belief in and worship of a creator correlate with higher rates of homicide, juvenile and early adult mortality, STD infection rates, teen pregnancy, and abortion in the prosperous democracies," and "In all secular developing democracies a centuries long-term trend has seen homicide rates drop to historical lows" with the exceptions being the United States (with a high religiosity level) and "theistic" Portugal.[77][d] In a response, Gary Jensen builds on and refines Paul's study.[78] he concludes that a "complex relationship" exists between religiosity and homicide "with some dimensions of religiosity encouraging homicide and other dimensions discouraging it". In April 2012, the results of a study which tested their subjects' pro-social sentiments were published in the Social Psychological and Personality Science journal in which non-religious people had higher scores showing that they were more motivated by their own compassion to perform pro-social behaviors. Religious people were found to be less motivated by compassion to be charitable than by an inner sense of moral obligation.[79][80]

See also Edit

Notes Edit

a.^ Studies on divorce in the United States done by the Barna Group suggested that atheists and agnostics have lower divorce rates than faith groups on average (though some faith groups had lower rates still).[81][82] The study notes that fewer atheists and agnostics enter into marriage relative to faith-based individuals.
b.^ Some studies appear to show positive links in the relationship between religiosity and moral behavior[83][84][85] Modern research in criminology also suggests an inverse relationship between religion and crime,[86] with some studies establishing this connection.[87] A meta-analysis of 60 studies on religion and crime concluded, "religious behaviors and beliefs exert a moderate deterrent effect on individuals' criminal behavior".[75]
c.^ Zuckerman identifies that Scandinavians have "relatively high rates of petty crime and burglary", but "their overall rates of violent crime—such as murder, aggravated assault, and rape—are among the lowest on earth" (Zuckerman 2008, pp. 5–6).
d.^ The authors also state that "A few hundred years ago rates of homicide were astronomical in Christian Europe and the American colonies,"[88] and "the least theistic secular developing democracies such as Japan, France, and Scandinavia have been most successful in these regards."[89] They argue for a positive correlation between the degree of public religiosity in a society and certain measures of dysfunction,[90] an analysis published later in the same journal argues that a number of methodological problems undermine any findings or conclusions in the research.[91]
e.^ Blackburn provides examples such as the phrase in Exodus 22:18 that has "helped to burn alive tens or hundreds of thousands of women in Europe and America": "Thou shalt not suffer a witch to live," and notes that the Old Testament God apparently has "no problems with a slave-owning society", considers birth control a crime punishable by death, and "is keen on child abuse".[92] Others interpret these passages differently, arguing for example that Jewish laws show the evolution of moral standards in society: that Jews actually threatened those who pursued forced slavery with the death penalty, held that slaves were persons instead of property, and protected them in several ways.[72][73][93]

References Edit

  1. ^ Long, A. A.; Sedley, D. N. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers: Translations of the Principal Sources with Philosophical Commentary. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 366–67. ISBN 978-0521275569.
  2. ^ Stanford University (2011). "The Definition of Morality". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 22 March 2014.
  3. ^ Antony Flew, ed. (1979). "golden rule". A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Pan Books in association with The MacMillan Press. p. 134. ISBN 978-0333262047. The maxim 'Treat others how you wish to be treated'. Various expressions of this fundamental moral rule are to be found in tenets of most religions and creeds through the ages, testifying to its universal applicability.
  4. ^ Walter Terence Stace argued that the Golden Rule is much more than simply an ethical code. He posits that it "express[es] the essence of a universal morality." The rationale for this distinction occupies much of his book The Concept of Morals (1937). Stace, Walter T. (1937). The Concept of Morals. New York: The MacMillan Company; reprinted by Peter Smith Publisher Inc, January 1990. p. 136. ISBN 978-0-8446-2990-2.
  5. ^ Johnstone, Megan-Jane (2008). Bioethics: A Nursing Perspective. pp. 102–03. ISBN 978-0-7295-3873-2. PMID 2129925. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  6. ^ Superson, Anita (2009). The Moral Skeptic. Oxford University Press. pp. 127–59. ISBN 978-0-19-537662-3.
  7. ^ "Amorality". Dictionary.com. Retrieved 2010-06-18. "having no moral standards, restraints, or principles; unaware of or indifferent to questions of right or wrong"
  8. ^ Deigh, John (2015). "ethics". In Audi, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (3rd ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 328. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139057509. ISBN 9781139057509.
  9. ^ Blackburn, Simon (2008). "morality". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 241. doi:10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001. ISBN 9780199541430.
  10. ^ a b Gert, Bernard; Gert, Joshua (2016). "The Definition of Morality". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  11. ^ Chapouthier, Georges, "To what extent is moral judgment natural?", European Review (GB), 2004, 12(2): 179–83
  12. ^ Ezedike, Edward Uzoma (2020-01-02). "Morality within the limits of practical reason: a critique of Kant's concept of moral virtue". International Journal of Ethics and Systems. 36 (2): 205–216. doi:10.1108/ijoes-11-2018-0171. ISSN 2514-9369. S2CID 214501283.
  13. ^ Richardson, Henry S. (2018), "Moral Reasoning", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-05-04
  14. ^ Green, Celia (2004). Letters from Exile: Observations on a Culture in Decline. Oxford: Oxford Forum. Chapters I–XX.
  15. ^ T.R. Shultz, M. Hartshorn, and A. Kaznatcheev. Why is ethnocentrism more common than humanitarianism? 2012-03-27 at the Wayback Machine Proceedings of the 31st annual conference of the cognitive science society, 2009.
  16. ^ Kaznatcheev, A. (2010, March). Robustness of ethnocentrism to changes in inter-personal interactions. In Complex Adaptive Systems – AAAI Fall Symposium. Butiz wintrades
  17. ^ a b Haidt, Jonathan; Graham, Jesse (2007). (PDF). Social Justice Research. 20: 98–116. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.385.3650. doi:10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z. S2CID 6824095. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-08-30. Retrieved 2014-09-26.
  18. ^ Peterson, Christopher, and Martin E. P. Seligman. Character Strengths and Virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
  19. ^ "Global Views on Morality". PewResearch.org. 15 April 2014.
  20. ^ (Westacott, https://www.iep.utm.edu/moral-re/#SH2g).
  21. ^ Trompenaars, Fons (2003). Did the Pedestrian Die: Insights from the World's Greatest Culture!. Wiley. ISBN 978-1841124360.
  22. ^ Curry, Oliver Scott; Mullins, Daniel Austin; Whitehouse, Harvey (2019). "Is It Good to Cooperate? Testing the Theory of Morality-as-Cooperation in 60 Societies". Current Anthropology. 60 (1): 47–69. doi:10.1086/701478.
  23. ^ "Seven moral rules found all around the world | University of Oxford". www.ox.ac.uk. 11 February 2019.
  24. ^ Shermer, Michael (2004). "Transcendent Morality". The Science of Good and Evil. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-8050-7520-5.
  25. ^ Bekoff, Marc and Jessica Pierce Wild Justice: The Moral Lives of Animals (Chicago, The University of Chicago Press 2009)
  26. ^ O'Connell, Sanjida (July 1995). "Empathy in chimpanzees: Evidence for theory of mind?". Primates. 36 (3): 397–410. doi:10.1007/BF02382862. ISSN 0032-8332. S2CID 41356986.
  27. ^ de Waal, Frans (1997). Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674356610.
  28. ^ Boehm, Christopher (1982). "The evolutionary development of morality as an effect of dominance behaviour and conflict interference". Journal of Social and Biological Sciences. 5 (4): 413–22. doi:10.1016/s0140-1750(82)92069-3.
  29. ^ Gilligan and Kohlberg: "Implications for Moral Theory" Author(s): Lawrence A. Blum Source: Ethics, Vol. 98, No. 3 (Apr., 1988), pp. 472–91
  30. ^ Bergmann Jörg (1998). "Introduction:Morality in discourse". Research on Language and Social Interaction. 31 (3/4): 279–74. doi:10.1080/08351813.1998.9683594.
  31. ^ Jörg Bergmann "Veiled morality: Notes on discretion in psychiatry." In Drew, Paul; Heritage, John, eds. (1992). Talk at work: Interaction in institutional settings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 137–62.
  32. ^ Lena Jayyusi "Values and moral judgment: Communicative praxis as moral order." In Button, Graham, ed. (1991). Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 227–51.
  33. ^ Cromdal Jakob; Michael Tholander (2014). "Morality in professional practice". Journal of Applied Linguistics and Professional Practice. 9 (2): 155–64. doi:10.1558/japl.v9i2.25734.
  34. ^ Mastroianni, Adam M.; Gilbert, Daniel T. (2023). "The illusion of moral decline". Nature. 618 (7966): 782–789. Bibcode:2023Natur.618..782M. doi:10.1038/s41586-023-06137-x. PMC 10284688. PMID 37286595.
  35. ^ Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Wheatley, Thalia (2012). "The Disunity of Morality and Why it Matters to Philosophy". Monist. 95 (3): 355–77. doi:10.5840/monist201295319.
  36. ^ Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Wheatley, Thalia (13 February 2013). "Are moral judgments unified?". Philosophical Psychology. 27 (4): 451–74. doi:10.1080/09515089.2012.736075. S2CID 143876741.
  37. ^ Young, Liane; Dungan, James (January 2012). "Where in the brain is morality? Everywhere and maybe nowhere". Social Neuroscience. 7 (1): 1–10. doi:10.1080/17470919.2011.569146. PMID 21590587. S2CID 14074566.
  38. ^ Yoder, Keith J.; Decety, Jean (12 December 2017). "The neuroscience of morality and social decision-making". Psychology, Crime & Law. 24 (3): 279–95. doi:10.1080/1068316X.2017.1414817. PMC 6372234. PMID 30766017.
  39. ^ Monin, Benoît; Pizarro, David A.; Beer, Jennifer S. (2007). "Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of moral judgment and the reason-affect debate". Review of General Psychology. 11 (2): 99–111. doi:10.1037/1089-2680.11.2.99. S2CID 144286153.
  40. ^ a b Sevinc, Gunes; Spreng, R. Nathan (4 February 2014). "Contextual and Perceptual Brain Processes Underlying Moral Cognition: A Quantitative Meta-Analysis of Moral Reasoning and Moral Emotions". PLOS ONE. 9 (2): e87427. Bibcode:2014PLoSO...987427S. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0087427. PMC 3913597. PMID 24503959.
  41. ^ Bartel, Christopher (2015). "Free will and moral responsibility in video games". Ethics and Information Technology. 17 (4): 285–293. doi:10.1007/s10676-015-9383-8. ISSN 1388-1957. S2CID 15800963.
  42. ^ Dubljević, Veljko; Sattler, Sebastian; Racine, Eric (2018). "Deciphering moral intuition: How agents, deeds, and consequences influence moral judgment". PLOS ONE. 13 (10): e0204631. Bibcode:2018PLoSO..1304631D. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0204631. PMC 6166963. PMID 30273370.
  43. ^ a b Bzdok, Danilo; Schilbach, Leonhard; Vogeley, Kai; Schneider, Karla; Laird, Angela R; Langner, Robert; Eickhoff, Simon B (2012-01-24). "Bzdok, D. et al. Parsing the neural correlates of moral cognition: ALE meta-analysis on morality, theory of mind, and empathy. Brain Struct Funct, 2011". Brain Structure and Function. 217 (4): 783–96. doi:10.1007/s00429-012-0380-y. PMC 3445793. PMID 22270812.
  44. ^ Boccia, M.; Dacquino, C.; Piccardi, L.; Cordellieri, P.; Guariglia, C.; Ferlazzo, F.; Ferracuti, S.; Giannini, A. M. (25 January 2016). . Brain Imaging and Behavior. 11 (1): 278–92. doi:10.1007/s11682-016-9505-x. PMID 26809288. S2CID 3984661. Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 September 2019. Retrieved 23 September 2019.
  45. ^ Eres, Robert; Louis, Winnifred R.; Molenberghs, Pascal (27 July 2017). "Common and distinct neural networks involved in fMRI studies investigating morality: an ALE meta-analysis". Social Neuroscience. 13 (4): 384–98. doi:10.1080/17470919.2017.1357657. PMID 28724332. S2CID 31749926.
  46. ^ Vedantam, Shankar. "If It Feels Good to Be Good, It Might Be Only Natural". The Washington Post. Retrieved 2010-05-13.
  47. ^ de Wied M, Goudena PP, Matthys W (2005). "Empathy in boys with disruptive behavior disorders". Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, and Allied Disciplines. 46 (8): 867–80. doi:10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00389.x. hdl:1874/11212. PMID 16033635. S2CID 45683502.
  48. ^ Fernandez YM, Marshall WL (2003). "Victim empathy, social self-esteem, and psychopathy in rapists". Sexual Abuse: A Journal of Research and Treatment. 15 (1): 11–26. doi:10.1023/A:1020611606754. PMID 12616926. S2CID 195293070.
  49. ^ a b Sevinc, Gunes; Gurvit, Hakan; Spreng, R. Nathan (July 2017). "Salience network engagement with the detection of morally laden information". Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience. 12 (7): 1118–27. doi:10.1093/scan/nsx035. PMC 5490682. PMID 28338944.
  50. ^ Seeley, W. W.; Menon, V.; Schatzberg, A. F.; Keller, J.; Glover, G. H.; Kenna, H.; Reiss, A. L.; Greicius, M. D. (28 February 2007). "Dissociable Intrinsic Connectivity Networks for Salience Processing and Executive Control". Journal of Neuroscience. 27 (9): 2349–56. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5587-06.2007. PMC 2680293. PMID 17329432.
  51. ^ Harenski, CL; Antonenko, O; Shane, MS; Kiehl, KA. (2010). "A functional imaging investigation of moral deliberation and moral intuition". NeuroImage. 49 (3): 2707–16. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.10.062. PMC 4270295. PMID 19878727.
  52. ^ Young, Liane; Camprodon, Joan Albert; Hauser, Marc; Pascual-Leone, Alvaro; Saxe, Rebecca (2010). "Disruption of the right temporoparietal junction with transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces the role of beliefs in moral judgments". PNAS. 107 (15): 6753–58. Bibcode:2010PNAS..107.6753Y. doi:10.1073/pnas.0914826107. PMC 2872442. PMID 20351278.
  53. ^ Young, Liane; Bechara, Antoine; Tranel, Daniel; Damasio, Hanna; Hauser, Marc; Damasio, Antonio (2010). "Damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex impairs judgment of harmful intent". Neuron. 65 (6): 845–51. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2010.03.003. PMC 3085837. PMID 20346759.
  54. ^ Zakharin, Michael; Bates, Timothy C (2022-05-26). "Testing heritability of moral foundations: Common pathway models support strong heritability for the five moral foundations". European Journal of Personality. 37 (4): 485–497. doi:10.1177/08902070221103957. ISSN 0890-2070. S2CID 249115484.
  55. ^ Smith, Kevin; Hatemi, Peter K. (December 2020). "Are Moral Intuitions Heritable?". Human Nature. 31 (4): 406–420. doi:10.1007/s12110-020-09380-7. ISSN 1045-6767. PMID 33420605. S2CID 231202698.
  56. ^ See Weber, Eric Thomas. 2011. Morality, Leadership, and Public Policy (London: Continuum).
  57. ^ Haidt, Jonathan; Joseph, Craig (September 2004). "Intuitive ethics: how innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues". Daedalus. 133 (4): 55–66. doi:10.1162/0011526042365555. S2CID 1574243.
  58. ^ Graham, J.; Haidt, J.; Koleva, S.; Motyl, M.; Iyer, R.; Wojcik, S.; Ditto, P.H. (2013). (PDF). pp. 55–130. doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-407236-7.00002-4. ISBN 978-0124072367. S2CID 2570757. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-07-31. Retrieved 2019-07-22. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  59. ^ "Morality: 2012: Online Only Video". The New Yorker. Retrieved 2012-05-06.
  60. ^ "Introducing Sentience Institute". Sentience Institute. 2 June 2017. Retrieved 2019-08-05.
  61. ^ Chomsky, Noam (2002-07-02). "Terror and Just Response". ZNet. Archived from the original on 2013-01-13.
  62. ^ Rachels, James; Rachels, Stuart, eds. (2011). The Elements of Moral Philosophy (7th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. p. [page needed]. ISBN 978-0-078-03824-2.
  63. ^ Childress, James F.; Macquarrie, John, eds. (1986). The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press. p. 401. ISBN 978-0-664-20940-7.
  64. ^ Peggy Morgan, "Buddhism." In Morgan, Peggy; Lawton, Clive A., eds. (2007). Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions (Second ed.). Columbia University Press. pp. 61, 88–89. ISBN 978-0-7486-2330-3.
  65. ^ Miller, Barbara Stoler (2004). The Bhagavad Gita: Krishna's Counsel in Time of War. New York: Random House. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-553-21365-2.
  66. ^ Werner Menski, "Hinduism." In Morgan, Peggy; Lawton, Clive A., eds. (2007). Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions (Second ed.). Columbia University Press. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-7486-2330-3.
  67. ^ David Hume, "The Natural History of Religion." In Hitchens, Christopher, ed. (2007). The Portable Atheist: Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever. Philadelphia: Da Capo Press. p. 30. ISBN 978-0-306-81608-6.
  68. ^ Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  69. ^ Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 12. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  70. ^ Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 11–12. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  71. ^ Elizabeth Anderson, "If God is Dead, Is Everything Permitted?" In Hitchens, Christopher, ed. (2007). The Portable Atheist: Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever. Philadelphia: Da Capo Press. p. 336. ISBN 978-0-306-81608-6.
  72. ^ a b Colley, Caleb. "Is Christianity a Threat to Ethics?". Apologetics Press. Retrieved 3 May 2012.
  73. ^ a b . Enrichmentjournal.ag.org. Archived from the original on 2018-10-05. Retrieved 2012-05-06.
  74. ^ See Weber, Eric Thomas. "Religion, Public Reason, and Humanism: Paul Kurtz on Fallibilism and Ethics 2013-10-14 at the Wayback Machine." Contemporary Pragmatism 5, Issue 2 (2008): 131–47.
  75. ^ a b Baier, C. J.; Wright, B. R. (2001). "If you love me, keep my commandments":A meta-analysis of the effect of religion on crime". Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency. 38: 3–21. doi:10.1177/0022427801038001001. S2CID 145779667.
  76. ^ Zuckerman, Phil (October 2008). Society Without God: What the Least Religious Nations Can Tell Us about Contentment. New York: New York University Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-8147-9714-3.
  77. ^ Paul, Gregory S. (2005). . Journal of Religion and Society. Baltimore, MD. 7: 4–5, 8, 10. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  78. ^ Gary F. Jensen (2006) Department of Sociology, Vanderbilt University "Religious Cosmologies and Homicide Rates among Nations: A Closer Look'", Journal of Religion and Society, Vol. 8, ISSN 1522-5658
  79. ^ "Highly Religious People Are Less Motivated by Compassion Than Are Non-Believers". Science Daily
  80. ^ Laura R. Saslow, Robb Willer, Matthew Feinberg, Paul K. Piff, Katharine Clark, Dacher Keltner and Sarina R. Saturn "My Brother's Keeper? Compassion Predicts Generosity More Among Less Religious Individuals"
  81. ^ Barna Group (31 March 2008). . Barna Group. Archived from the original on 19 December 2014. Retrieved 19 November 2011.
  82. ^ Wicker, Christine (2000). . www.adherents.com. Archived from the original on March 28, 2002. Retrieved 1 April 2012.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  83. ^ Kerley, Kent R.; Matthews; Blanchard, Troy C. (2005). "Religiosity, Religious Participation, and Negative Prison Behaviors". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 44 (4): 443–57. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00296.x.
  84. ^ Saroglou, Vassilis; Pichon; Dernelle, Rebecca (2005). "Prosocial Behavior and Religion: New Evidence Based on Projective Measures and Peer Ratings" (PDF). Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 44 (3): 323–48. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.503.7559. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00289.x.
  85. ^ e.g. a survey 2007-10-08 at the Wayback Machine by Robert Putnam showing that membership of religious groups was positively correlated with membership of voluntary organisations
  86. ^ As is stated in: Chu, Doris C. (2007). "Religiosity and Desistance From Drug Use". Criminal Justice and Behavior. 34 (5): 661–79. doi:10.1177/0093854806293485. S2CID 145491534.
  87. ^ For example:
    • Albrecht, S. I.; Chadwick, B. A.; Alcorn, D. S. (1977). "Religiosity and deviance:Application of an attitude-behavior contingent consistency model". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 16 (3): 263–74. doi:10.2307/1385697. JSTOR 1385697.
    • Burkett, S.; White, M. (1974). "Hellfire and delinquency:Another look". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 13 (4): 455–62. doi:10.2307/1384608. JSTOR 1384608.
    • Chard-Wierschem, D. (1998). In pursuit of the "true" relationship: A longitudinal study of the effects of religiosity on delinquency and substance abuse. Ann Arbor, MI: UMI Dissertation.
    • Cochran, J. K.; Akers, R. L. (1989). "Beyond Hellfire:An explanation of the variable effects of religiosity on adolescent marijuana and alcohol use". Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency. 26 (3): 198–225. doi:10.1177/0022427889026003002. S2CID 145479350.
    • Evans, T. D.; Cullen, F. T.; Burton, V. S. Jr.; Dunaway, R. G.; Payne, G. L.; Kethineni, S. R. (1996). "Religion, social bonds, and delinquency". Deviant Behavior. 17: 43–70. doi:10.1080/01639625.1996.9968014.
    • Grasmick, H. G.; Bursik, R. J.; Cochran, J. K. (1991). "Render unto Caesar what is Caesar's": Religiosity and taxpayer's inclinations to cheat". The Sociological Quarterly. 32 (2): 251–66. doi:10.1111/j.1533-8525.1991.tb00356.x.
    • Higgins, P. C.; Albrecht, G. L. (1977). "Hellfire and delinquency revisited". Social Forces. 55 (4): 952–58. doi:10.1093/sf/55.4.952.
    • Johnson, B. R.; Larson, D. B.; DeLi, S.; Jang, S. J. (2000). "Escaping from the crime of inner cities:Church attendance and religious salience among disadvantaged youth". Justice Quarterly. 17 (2): 377–91. doi:10.1080/07418820000096371. S2CID 144816590.
    • Johnson, R. E.; Marcos, A. C.; Bahr, S. J. (1987). "The role of peers in the complex etiology of adolescent drug use". Criminology. 25 (2): 323–40. doi:10.1111/j.1745-9125.1987.tb00800.x.
    • Powell, K. (1997). "Correlates of violent and nonviolent behavior among vulnerable inner-city youths". Family and Community Health. 20 (2): 38–47. doi:10.1097/00003727-199707000-00006.
  88. ^ Paul, Gregory S. (2005). . Journal of Religion and Society. Baltimore, MD. 7: 4–5, 8. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  89. ^ Paul, Gregory S. (2005). . Journal of Religion and Society. Baltimore, MD. 7: 11. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  90. ^ Paul, Gregory S. (2005). . Journal of Religion and Society. Baltimore, MD. 7. Archived from the original on 2011-12-14.
  91. ^ Gerson Moreno-Riaño; Mark Caleb Smith; Thomas Mach (2006). . Journal of Religion and Society. Cedarville University. 8. Archived from the original on 2011-10-28.
  92. ^ Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 10, 12. ISBN 978-0-19-280442-6.
  93. ^ Westacott, Emrys. "Moral Relativism". iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 12 May 2018.

Further reading Edit

External links Edit

morality, capacity, group, members, maintain, belief, face, opposition, hardship, morale, novella, novella, morals, redirects, here, film, morals, film, immoralist, redirects, here, novel, immoralist, from, latin, moralitas, manner, character, proper, behavior. For the capacity of a group s members to maintain belief in the face of opposition or hardship see Morale For the novella see Morality novella Morals redirects here For the film see Morals film Immoralist redirects here For the novel see The Immoralist Morality from Latin moralitas manner character proper behavior is the differentiation of intentions decisions and actions between those that are distinguished as proper right and those that are improper wrong 1 Morality can be a body of standards or principles derived from a code of conduct from a particular philosophy religion or culture or it can derive from a standard that a person believes should be universal 2 Morality may also be specifically synonymous with goodness or rightness Allegory with a portrait of a Venetian senator Allegory of the morality of earthly things attributed to Tintoretto 1585Moral philosophy includes meta ethics which studies abstract issues such as moral ontology and moral epistemology and normative ethics which studies more concrete systems of moral decision making such as deontological ethics and consequentialism An example of normative ethical philosophy is the Golden Rule which states One should treat others as one would like others to treat oneself 3 4 Immorality is the active opposition to morality i e opposition to that which is good or right while amorality is variously defined as an unawareness of indifference toward or disbelief in any particular set of moral standards or principles 5 6 7 Contents 1 History 2 Ethics 3 Descriptive and normative 4 Realism and anti realism 5 Anthropology 5 1 Morality with practical reasoning 5 2 Tribal and territorial 5 3 In group and out group 5 4 Comparing cultures 6 Evolution 7 Psychology 7 1 Moral cognition 8 Neuroscience 8 1 Brain areas 9 Genetics 10 Politics 11 Religion 11 1 Positions 11 2 Empirical analyses 12 See also 13 Notes 14 References 15 Further reading 16 External linksHistory EditSee also Evolution of morality and History of ethicsEthics EditSee also Sittlichkeit Confucius Laozi and Tao Te Ching Ethics also known as moral philosophy is the branch of philosophy which addresses questions of morality The word ethics is commonly used interchangeably with morality and sometimes it is used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition group or individual 8 Likewise certain types of ethical theories especially deontological ethics sometimes distinguish between ethics and morality nbsp Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law Philosopher Simon Blackburn writes that Although the morality of people and their ethics amounts to the same thing there is a usage that restricts morality to systems such as that of Immanuel Kant based on notions such as duty obligation and principles of conduct reserving ethics for the more Aristotelian approach to practical reasoning based on the notion of a virtue and generally avoiding the separation of moral considerations from other practical considerations 9 Descriptive and normative EditIn its descriptive sense morality refers to personal or cultural values codes of conduct or social mores from a society that provides these codes of conduct in which it applies and is accepted by an individual It does not connote objective claims of right or wrong but only refers to that which is considered right or wrong Descriptive ethics is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense 10 In its normative sense morality refers to whatever if anything is actually right or wrong which may be independent of the values or mores held by any particular peoples or cultures Normative ethics is the branch of philosophy which studies morality in this sense 10 Realism and anti realism EditPhilosophical theories on the nature and origins of morality that is theories of meta ethics are broadly divided into two classes Moral realism is the class of theories which hold that there are true moral statements that report objective moral facts For example while they might concede that forces of social conformity significantly shape individuals moral decisions they deny that those cultural norms and customs define morally right behavior This may be the philosophical view propounded by ethical naturalists but not all moral realists accept that position e g ethical non naturalists 11 Moral anti realism on the other hand holds that moral statements either fail or do not even attempt to report objective moral facts Instead they hold that moral sentences are either categorically false claims of objective moral facts error theory claims about subjective attitudes rather than objective facts ethical subjectivism or else do not attempt to describe the world at all but rather something else like an expression of an emotion or the issuance of a command non cognitivism Some forms of non cognitivism and ethical subjectivism while considered anti realist in the robust sense used here are considered realist in the sense synonymous with moral universalism For example universal prescriptivism is a universalist form of non cognitivism which claims that morality is derived from reasoning about implied imperatives and divine command theory and ideal observer theory are universalist forms of ethical subjectivism which claim that morality is derived from the edicts of a god or the hypothetical decrees of a perfectly rational being respectively Anthropology EditMorality with practical reasoning Edit Practical reason is necessary for the moral agency but it is not a sufficient condition for moral agency 12 Real life issues that need solutions do need both rationality and emotion to be sufficiently moral One uses rationality as a pathway to the ultimate decision but the environment and emotions towards the environment at the moment must be a factor for the result to be truly moral as morality is subject to culture Something can only be morally acceptable if the culture as a whole has accepted this to be true Both practical reason and relevant emotional factors are acknowledged as significant in determining the morality of a decision 13 neutrality is disputed Tribal and territorial Edit Celia Green made a distinction between tribal and territorial morality 14 She characterizes the latter as predominantly negative and proscriptive it defines a person s territory including his or her property and dependents which is not to be damaged or interfered with Apart from these proscriptions territorial morality is permissive allowing the individual whatever behaviour does not interfere with the territory of another By contrast tribal morality is prescriptive imposing the norms of the collective on the individual These norms will be arbitrary culturally dependent and flexible whereas territorial morality aims at rules which are universal and absolute such as Kant s categorical imperative and Geisler s graded absolutism Green relates the development of territorial morality to the rise of the concept of private property and the ascendancy of contract over status In group and out group Edit Main article In group and out group Some observers hold that individuals apply distinct sets of moral rules to people depending on their membership of an in group the individual and those they believe to be of the same group or an out group people not entitled to be treated according to the same rules Some biologists anthropologists and evolutionary psychologists believe this in group out group discrimination has evolved because it enhances group survival This belief has been confirmed by simple computational models of evolution 15 In simulations this discrimination can result in both unexpected cooperation towards the in group and irrational hostility towards the out group 16 Gary R Johnson and V S Falger have argued that nationalism and patriotism are forms of this in group out group boundary Jonathan Haidt has noted 17 that experimental observation indicating an in group criterion provides one moral foundation substantially used by conservatives but far less so by liberals In group preference is also helpful at the individual level for the passing on of one s genes For example a mother who favors her own children more highly than the children of other people will give greater resources to her children than she will to strangers thus heightening her children s chances of survival and her own gene s chances of being perpetuated Due to this within a population there is substantial selection pressure exerted toward this kind of self interest such that eventually all parents wind up favoring their own children the in group over other children the out group Comparing cultures Edit Peterson and Seligman 18 approach the anthropological view looking across cultures geo cultural areas and across millennia They conclude that certain virtues have prevailed in all cultures they examined The major virtues they identified include wisdom knowledge courage humanity justice temperance and transcendence Each of these includes several divisions For instance humanity includes love kindness and social intelligence Still others theorize that morality is not always absolute contending that moral issues often differ along cultural lines A 2014 PEW research study among several nations illuminates significant cultural differences among issues commonly related to morality including divorce extramarital affairs homosexuality gambling abortion alcohol use contraceptive use and premarital sex Each of the 40 countries in this study has a range of percentages according to what percentage of each country believes the common moral issues are acceptable unacceptable or not moral issues at all Each percentage regarding the significance of the moral issue varies greatly on the culture in which the moral issue is presented 19 Advocates of a theory known as moral relativism subscribe to the notion that moral virtues are right or wrong only within the context of a certain standpoint e g cultural community In other words what is morally acceptable in one culture may be taboo in another They further contend that no moral virtue can objectively be proven right or wrong 20 Critics of moral relativism point to historical atrocities such as infanticide slavery or genocide as counter arguments noting the difficulty in accepting these actions simply through cultural lenses Fons Trompenaars author of Did the Pedestrian Die tested members of different cultures with various moral dilemmas One of these was whether the driver of a car would have his friend a passenger riding in the car lie in order to protect the driver from the consequences of driving too fast and hitting a pedestrian Trompenaars found that different cultures had quite different expectations from none to definite 21 Anthropologists from Oxford s Institute of Cognitive amp Evolutionary Anthropology part of the School of Anthropology amp Museum Ethnography analysed ethnographic accounts of ethics from 60 societies comprising over 600 000 words from over 600 sources and discovered what they believe to be seven universal moral rules help your family help your group return favours be brave defer to superiors divide resources fairly and respect others property 22 23 Evolution EditSee also Altruism Evolutionary explanations Evolution of morality and Evolutionary ethics The development of modern morality is a process closely tied to sociocultural evolution Some evolutionary biologists particularly sociobiologists believe that morality is a product of evolutionary forces acting at an individual level and also at the group level through group selection although to what degree this actually occurs is a controversial topic in evolutionary theory Some sociobiologists contend that the set of behaviors that constitute morality evolved largely because they provided possible survival or reproductive benefits i e increased evolutionary success Humans consequently evolved pro social emotions such as feelings of empathy or guilt in response to these moral behaviors On this understanding moralities are sets of self perpetuating and biologically driven behaviors which encourage human cooperation Biologists contend that all social animals from ants to elephants have modified their behaviors by restraining immediate selfishness in order to improve their evolutionary fitness Human morality although sophisticated and complex relative to the moralities of other animals is essentially a natural phenomenon that evolved to restrict excessive individualism that could undermine a group s cohesion and thereby reducing the individuals fitness 24 On this view moral codes are ultimately founded on emotional instincts and intuitions that were selected for in the past because they aided survival and reproduction inclusive fitness Examples the maternal bond is selected for because it improves the survival of offspring the Westermarck effect where close proximity during early years reduces mutual sexual attraction underpins taboos against incest because it decreases the likelihood of genetically risky behaviour such as inbreeding The phenomenon of reciprocity in nature is seen by evolutionary biologists as one way to begin to understand human morality Its function is typically to ensure a reliable supply of essential resources especially for animals living in a habitat where food quantity or quality fluctuates unpredictably For example some vampire bats fail to feed on prey some nights while others manage to consume a surplus Bats that did eat will then regurgitate part of their blood meal to save a conspecific from starvation Since these animals live in close knit groups over many years an individual can count on other group members to return the favor on nights when it goes hungry Wilkinson 1984 Marc Bekoff and Jessica Pierce 2009 have argued that morality is a suite of behavioral capacities likely shared by all mammals living in complex social groups e g wolves coyotes elephants dolphins rats chimpanzees They define morality as a suite of interrelated other regarding behaviors that cultivate and regulate complex interactions within social groups This suite of behaviors includes empathy reciprocity altruism cooperation and a sense of fairness 25 In related work it has been convincingly demonstrated that chimpanzees show empathy for each other in a wide variety of contexts 26 They also possess the ability to engage in deception and a level of social politics 27 prototypical of our own tendencies for gossip and reputation management Christopher Boehm 1982 28 has hypothesized that the incremental development of moral complexity throughout hominid evolution was due to the increasing need to avoid disputes and injuries in moving to open savanna and developing stone weapons Other theories are that increasing complexity was simply a correlate of increasing group size and brain size and in particular the development of theory of mind abilities Psychology EditMain article Moral psychology See also Kohlberg s stages of moral development and Jean Piaget Education and development of morality nbsp Kohlberg s model of moral developmentIn modern moral psychology morality is sometimes considered to change through personal development Several psychologists have produced theories on the development of morals usually going through stages of different morals Lawrence Kohlberg Jean Piaget and Elliot Turiel have cognitive developmental approaches to moral development to these theorists morality forms in a series of constructive stages or domains In the Ethics of care approach established by Carol Gilligan moral development occurs in the context of caring mutually responsive relationships which are based on interdependence particularly in parenting but also in social relationships generally 29 Social psychologists such as Martin Hoffman and Jonathan Haidt emphasize social and emotional development based on biology such as empathy Moral identity theorists such as William Damon and Mordechai Nisan see moral commitment as arising from the development of a self identity that is defined by moral purposes this moral self identity leads to a sense of responsibility to pursue such purposes Of historical interest in psychology are the theories of psychoanalysts such as Sigmund Freud who believe that moral development is the product of aspects of the super ego as guilt shame avoidance Theories of moral development therefore tend to regard it as positive moral development the higher stages are morally higher though this naturally involves a circular argument The higher stages are better because they are higher but the better higher because they are better As an alternative to viewing morality as an individual trait some sociologists as well as social and discursive psychologists have taken upon themselves to study the in vivo aspects of morality by examining how persons conduct themselves in social interaction 30 31 32 33 A new study analyses the common perception of a decline in morality in societies worldwide and throughout history Adam M Mastroianni and Daniel T Gilbert present a series of studies indicating that the perception of moral decline is an illusion and easily produced with implications for misallocation of resources underuse of social support and social influence To begin with the authors demonstrate that people in no less than 60 nations hold the belief that morality is deteriorating continuously and this conviction has been present for the last 70 years Subsequently they indicate that people ascribe this decay to the declining morality of individuals as they age and the succeeding generations Thirdly the authors demonstrate that people s evaluations of the morality of their peers have not decreased over time indicating that the belief in moral decline is an illusion Lastly the authors explain a basic psychological mechanism that uses two well established phenomena distorted exposure to information and distorted memory of information to cause the illusion of moral decline The authors present studies that validate some of the predictions about the circumstances in which the perception of moral decline is attenuated eliminated or reversed e g when participants are asked about the morality of people closest to them or people who lived before they were born 34 Moral cognition Edit Moral cognition refers to cognitive processes implicated in moral judgment and decision making and moral action It consists of several domain general cognitive processes ranging from perception of a morally salient stimulus to reasoning when faced with a moral dilemma While it s important to mention that there is not a single cognitive faculty dedicated exclusively to moral cognition 35 36 characterizing the contributions of domain general processes to moral behavior is a critical scientific endeavor to understand how morality works and how it can be improved 37 Cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists investigate the inputs to these cognitive processes and their interactions as well as how these contribute to moral behavior by running controlled experiments 38 In these experiments putatively moral versus nonmoral stimuli are compared to each other while controlling for other variables such as content or working memory load Often the differential neural response to specifically moral statements or scenes are examined using functional neuroimaging experiments Critically the specific cognitive processes that are involved depend on the prototypical situation that a person encounters 39 For instance while situations that require an active decision on a moral dilemma may require active reasoning an immediate reaction to a shocking moral violation may involve quick affect laden processes Nonetheless certain cognitive skills such as being able to attribute mental states beliefs intents desires emotions to oneself and others is a common feature of a broad range of prototypical situations In line with this a meta analysis found overlapping activity between moral emotion and moral reasoning tasks suggesting a shared neural network for both tasks 40 The results of this meta analysis however also demonstrated that the processing of moral input is affected by task demands Regarding the issues of morality in video games some scholars believe that because players appear in video games as actors they maintain a distance between their sense of self and the role of the game in terms of imagination Therefore the decision making and moral behavior of players in the game are not representing player s Moral dogma 41 It has been recently found that moral judgment consists in concurrent evaluations of three different components that align with precepts from three dominant moral theories virtue ethics deontology and consequentialism the character of a person Agent component A their actions Deed component D and the consequences brought about in the situation Consequences component C 42 This implies that various inputs of the situation a person encounters affect moral cognition Neuroscience EditSee also Science of morality and Neuromorality The brain areas that are consistently involved when humans reason about moral issues have been investigated by multiple quantitative large scale meta analyses of the brain activity changes reported in the moral neuroscience literature 43 40 44 45 The neural network underlying moral decisions overlaps with the network pertaining to representing others intentions i e theory of mind and the network pertaining to representing others vicariously experienced emotional states i e empathy This supports the notion that moral reasoning is related to both seeing things from other persons points of view and to grasping others feelings These results provide evidence that the neural network underlying moral decisions is probably domain global i e there might be no such things as a moral module in the human brain and might be dissociable into cognitive and affective sub systems 43 Cognitive neuroscientist Jean Decety thinks that the ability to recognize and vicariously experience what another individual is undergoing was a key step forward in the evolution of social behavior and ultimately morality 46 The inability to feel empathy is one of the defining characteristics of psychopathy and this would appear to lend support to Decety s view 47 48 Brain areas Edit An essential shared component of moral judgment involves the capacity to detect morally salient content within a given social context Recent research implicated the salience network in this initial detection of moral content 49 The salience network responds to behaviorally salient events 50 and may be critical to modulate downstream default and frontal control network interactions in the service of complex moral reasoning and decision making processes The explicit making of moral right and wrong judgments coincides with activation in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex VMPC a region involved in valuation while intuitive reactions to situations containing implicit moral issues activates the temporoparietal junction area a region that plays a key role in understanding intentions and beliefs 51 49 Stimulation of the VMPC by transcranial magnetic stimulation or neurological lesion has been shown to inhibit the ability of human subjects to take into account intent when forming a moral judgment According to such investigations TMS did not disrupt participants ability to make any moral judgment On the contrary moral judgments of intentional harms and non harms were unaffected by TMS to either the RTPJ or the control site presumably however people typically make moral judgments of intentional harms by considering not only the action s harmful outcome but the agent s intentions and beliefs So why were moral judgments of intentional harms not affected by TMS to the RTPJ One possibility is that moral judgments typically reflect a weighted function of any morally relevant information that is available at the time Based on this view when information concerning the agent s belief is unavailable or degraded the resulting moral judgment simply reflects a higher weighting of other morally relevant factors e g outcome Alternatively following TMS to the RTPJ moral judgments might be made via an abnormal processing route that does not take belief into account On either account when belief information is degraded or unavailable moral judgments are shifted toward other morally relevant factors e g outcome For intentional harms and non harms however the outcome suggests the same moral judgment as to the intention Thus the researchers suggest that TMS to the RTPJ disrupted the processing of negative beliefs for both intentional harms and attempted harms but the current design allowed the investigators to detect this effect only in the case of attempted harms in which the neutral outcomes did not afford harsh moral judgments on their own 52 Similarly individuals with a lesion of the VMPC judge an action purely on its outcome and are unable to take into account the intent of that action 53 Genetics EditThis section needs expansion You can help by adding to it May 2022 Moral intuitions may have genetic bases A 2022 study conducted by scholars Michael Zakharin and Timothy C Bates and published by the European Journal of Personality found that moral foundations have significant genetic bases 54 Another study conducted by Smith and Hatemi similarly found significant evidence in support of moral heritability by looking at and comparing the answers of moral dilemmas between twins 55 Genetics play a role in influencing prosocial behaviors and moral decision making Genetics contribute to the development and expression of certain traits and behaviors including those related to morality However it is important to note that while genetics play a role in shaping certain aspects of moral behavior morality itself is a multifaceted concept that encompasses cultural societal and personal influences as well Politics EditIf morality is the answer to the question how ought we to live at the individual level politics can be seen as addressing the same question at the social level though the political sphere raises additional problems and challenges 56 It is therefore unsurprising that evidence has been found of a relationship between attitudes in morality and politics Moral foundations theory authored by Jonathan Haidt and colleagues 57 58 has been used to study the differences between liberals and conservatives in this regard 17 59 Haidt found that Americans who identified as liberals tended to value care and fairness higher than loyalty respect and purity Self identified conservative Americans valued care and fairness less and the remaining three values more Both groups gave care the highest over all weighting but conservatives valued fairness the lowest whereas liberals valued purity the lowest Haidt also hypothesizes that the origin of this division in the United States can be traced to geo historical factors with conservatism strongest in closely knit ethnically homogeneous communities in contrast to port cities where the cultural mix is greater thus requiring more liberalism Group morality develops from shared concepts and beliefs and is often codified to regulate behavior within a culture or community Various defined actions come to be called moral or immoral Individuals who choose moral action are popularly held to possess moral fiber whereas those who indulge in immoral behavior may be labeled as socially degenerate The continued existence of a group may depend on widespread conformity to codes of morality an inability to adjust moral codes in response to new challenges is sometimes credited with the demise of a community a positive example would be the function of Cistercian reform in reviving monasticism a negative example would be the role of the Dowager Empress in the subjugation of China to European interests Within nationalist movements there has been some tendency to feel that a nation will not survive or prosper without acknowledging one common morality regardless of its content Political morality is also relevant to the behavior internationally of national governments and to the support they receive from their host population The Sentience Institute co founded by Jacy Reese Anthis analyzes the trajectory of moral progress in society via the framework of an expanding moral circle 60 Noam Chomsky states that if we adopt the principle of universality if an action is right or wrong for others it is right or wrong for us Those who do not rise to the minimal moral level of applying to themselves the standards they apply to others more stringent ones in fact plainly cannot be taken seriously when they speak of appropriateness of response or of right and wrong good and evil In fact one of them maybe the most elementary of moral principles is that of universality that is If something s right for me it s right for you if it s wrong for you it s wrong for me Any moral code that is even worth looking at has that at its core somehow 61 Religion EditMain articles Ethics in religion and Morality and religion See also Divine command theory Divine law Religious law Secular ethics and Secular morality Religion and morality are not synonymous Morality does not depend upon religion although for some this is an almost automatic assumption 62 According to The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics religion and morality are to be defined differently and have no definitional connections with each other Conceptually and in principle morality and a religious value system are two distinct kinds of value systems or action guides 63 Positions Edit Within the wide range of moral traditions religious value systems co exist with contemporary secular frameworks such as consequentialism freethought humanism utilitarianism and others There are many types of religious value systems Modern monotheistic religions such as Islam Judaism Christianity and to a certain degree others such as Sikhism and Zoroastrianism define right and wrong by the laws and rules set forth by their respective scriptures and as interpreted by religious leaders within the respective faith Other religions spanning pantheistic to nontheistic tend to be less absolute For example within Buddhism the intention of the individual and the circumstances should be accounted for in the form of Merit to determine if an action is right or wrong termed 64 A further disparity between the values of religious traditions is pointed out by Barbara Stoler Miller who states that in Hinduism practically right and wrong are decided according to the categories of social rank kinship and stages of life For modern Westerners who have been raised on ideals of universality and egalitarianism this relativity of values and obligations is the aspect of Hinduism most difficult to understand 65 Religions provide different ways of dealing with moral dilemmas For example there is no absolute prohibition on killing in Hinduism which recognizes that it may be inevitable and indeed necessary in certain circumstances 66 In monotheistic traditions certain acts are viewed in more absolute terms such as abortion or divorce a Religion is not always positively associated with morality Philosopher David Hume stated that the greatest crimes have been found in many instances to be compatible with a superstitious piety and devotion Hence it is justly regarded as unsafe to draw any inference in favor of a man s morals from the fervor or strictness of his religious exercises even though he himself believe them sincere 67 Religious value systems can also be used to justify acts that are contrary to contemporary morality such as massacres misogyny and slavery For example Simon Blackburn states that apologists for Hinduism defend or explain away its involvement with the caste system and apologists for Islam defend or explain away its harsh penal code or its attitude to women and infidels 68 In regard to Christianity he states that the Bible can be read as giving us a carte blanche for harsh attitudes to children the mentally handicapped animals the environment the divorced unbelievers people with various sexual habits and elderly women 69 and notes morally suspect themes in the Bible s New Testament as well 70 e Elizabeth Anderson likewise holds that the Bible contains both good and evil teachings and it is morally inconsistent 71 Christian apologists address Blackburn s viewpoints 72 and construe that Jewish laws in the Hebrew Bible showed the evolution of moral standards towards protecting the vulnerable imposing a death penalty on those pursuing slavery and treating slaves as persons and not property 73 Humanists like Paul Kurtz believe that we can identify moral values across cultures even if we do not appeal to a supernatural or universalist understanding of principles values including integrity trustworthiness benevolence and fairness These values can be resources for finding common ground between believers and nonbelievers 74 Empirical analyses Edit Several studies have been conducted on the empirics of morality in various countries and the overall relationship between faith and crime is unclear b A 2001 review of studies on this topic found The existing evidence surrounding the effect of religion on crime is varied contested and inconclusive and currently no persuasive answer exists as to the empirical relationship between religion and crime 75 Phil Zuckerman s 2008 book Society without God based on studies conducted during 14 months in Scandinavia in 2005 2006 notes that Denmark and Sweden which are probably the least religious countries in the world and possibly in the history of the world enjoy among the lowest violent crime rates in the world and the lowest levels of corruption in the world 76 c Dozens of studies have been conducted on this topic since the twentieth century A 2005 study by Gregory S Paul published in the Journal of Religion and Society stated that In general higher rates of belief in and worship of a creator correlate with higher rates of homicide juvenile and early adult mortality STD infection rates teen pregnancy and abortion in the prosperous democracies and In all secular developing democracies a centuries long term trend has seen homicide rates drop to historical lows with the exceptions being the United States with a high religiosity level and theistic Portugal 77 d In a response Gary Jensen builds on and refines Paul s study 78 he concludes that a complex relationship exists between religiosity and homicide with some dimensions of religiosity encouraging homicide and other dimensions discouraging it In April 2012 the results of a study which tested their subjects pro social sentiments were published in the Social Psychological and Personality Science journal in which non religious people had higher scores showing that they were more motivated by their own compassion to perform pro social behaviors Religious people were found to be less motivated by compassion to be charitable than by an inner sense of moral obligation 79 80 See also EditEthics Integrity Applied ethics Appeal to tradition Buddhist ethics Christian ethics Emotional intelligence Ethical dilemma Good and evil Ideology Index of ethics articles Islamic ethics Moral agency Moral character Moral conviction Moral intelligence Moral panic Moral skepticism Outline of ethics Value theory WorldviewNotes Edita Studies on divorce in the United States done by the Barna Group suggested that atheists and agnostics have lower divorce rates than faith groups on average though some faith groups had lower rates still 81 82 The study notes that fewer atheists and agnostics enter into marriage relative to faith based individuals b Some studies appear to show positive links in the relationship between religiosity and moral behavior 83 84 85 Modern research in criminology also suggests an inverse relationship between religion and crime 86 with some studies establishing this connection 87 A meta analysis of 60 studies on religion and crime concluded religious behaviors and beliefs exert a moderate deterrent effect on individuals criminal behavior 75 c Zuckerman identifies that Scandinavians have relatively high rates of petty crime and burglary but their overall rates of violent crime such as murder aggravated assault and rape are among the lowest on earth Zuckerman 2008 pp 5 6 d The authors also state that A few hundred years ago rates of homicide were astronomical in Christian Europe and the American colonies 88 and the least theistic secular developing democracies such as Japan France and Scandinavia have been most successful in these regards 89 They argue for a positive correlation between the degree of public religiosity in a society and certain measures of dysfunction 90 an analysis published later in the same journal argues that a number of methodological problems undermine any findings or conclusions in the research 91 e Blackburn provides examples such as the phrase in Exodus 22 18 that has helped to burn alive tens or hundreds of thousands of women in Europe and America Thou shalt not suffer a witch to live and notes that the Old Testament God apparently has no problems with a slave owning society considers birth control a crime punishable by death and is keen on child abuse 92 Others interpret these passages differently arguing for example that Jewish laws show the evolution of moral standards in society that Jews actually threatened those who pursued forced slavery with the death penalty held that slaves were persons instead of property and protected them in several ways 72 73 93 References Edit Long A A Sedley D N 1987 The Hellenistic Philosophers Translations of the Principal Sources with Philosophical Commentary Vol 1 Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 366 67 ISBN 978 0521275569 Stanford University 2011 The Definition of Morality Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Retrieved 22 March 2014 Antony Flew ed 1979 golden rule A Dictionary of Philosophy London Pan Books in association with The MacMillan Press p 134 ISBN 978 0333262047 The maxim Treat others how you wish to be treated Various expressions of this fundamental moral rule are to be found in tenets of most religions and creeds through the ages testifying to its universal applicability Walter Terence Stace argued that the Golden Rule is much more than simply an ethical code He posits that it express es the essence of a universal morality The rationale for this distinction occupies much of his book The Concept of Morals 1937 Stace Walter T 1937 The Concept of Morals New York The MacMillan Company reprinted by Peter Smith Publisher Inc January 1990 p 136 ISBN 978 0 8446 2990 2 Johnstone Megan Jane 2008 Bioethics A Nursing Perspective pp 102 03 ISBN 978 0 7295 3873 2 PMID 2129925 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help Superson Anita 2009 The Moral Skeptic Oxford University Press pp 127 59 ISBN 978 0 19 537662 3 Amorality Dictionary com Retrieved 2010 06 18 having no moral standards restraints or principles unaware of or indifferent to questions of right or wrong Deigh John 2015 ethics In Audi Robert ed The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy 3rd ed Cambridge University Press p 328 doi 10 1017 CBO9781139057509 ISBN 9781139057509 Blackburn Simon 2008 morality The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy 2nd ed Oxford University Press p 241 doi 10 1093 acref 9780199541430 001 0001 ISBN 9780199541430 a b Gert Bernard Gert Joshua 2016 The Definition of Morality In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Chapouthier Georges To what extent is moral judgment natural European Review GB 2004 12 2 179 83 Ezedike Edward Uzoma 2020 01 02 Morality within the limits of practical reason a critique of Kant s concept of moral virtue International Journal of Ethics and Systems 36 2 205 216 doi 10 1108 ijoes 11 2018 0171 ISSN 2514 9369 S2CID 214501283 Richardson Henry S 2018 Moral Reasoning in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2022 05 04 Green Celia 2004 Letters from Exile Observations on a Culture in Decline Oxford Oxford Forum Chapters I XX T R Shultz M Hartshorn and A Kaznatcheev Why is ethnocentrism more common than humanitarianism Archived 2012 03 27 at the Wayback Machine Proceedings of the 31st annual conference of the cognitive science society 2009 Kaznatcheev A 2010 March Robustness of ethnocentrism to changes in inter personal interactions In Complex Adaptive Systems AAAI Fall Symposium Butiz wintrades a b Haidt Jonathan Graham Jesse 2007 When Morality Opposes Justice Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize PDF Social Justice Research 20 98 116 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 385 3650 doi 10 1007 s11211 007 0034 z S2CID 6824095 Archived from the original PDF on 2014 08 30 Retrieved 2014 09 26 Peterson Christopher and Martin E P Seligman Character Strengths and Virtues Oxford Oxford University Press 2004 Global Views on Morality PewResearch org 15 April 2014 Westacott https www iep utm edu moral re SH2g Trompenaars Fons 2003 Did the Pedestrian Die Insights from the World s Greatest Culture Wiley ISBN 978 1841124360 Curry Oliver Scott Mullins Daniel Austin Whitehouse Harvey 2019 Is It Good to Cooperate Testing the Theory of Morality as Cooperation in 60 Societies Current Anthropology 60 1 47 69 doi 10 1086 701478 Seven moral rules found all around the world University of Oxford www ox ac uk 11 February 2019 Shermer Michael 2004 Transcendent Morality The Science of Good and Evil Macmillan ISBN 978 0 8050 7520 5 Bekoff Marc and Jessica Pierce Wild Justice The Moral Lives of Animals Chicago The University of Chicago Press 2009 O Connell Sanjida July 1995 Empathy in chimpanzees Evidence for theory of mind Primates 36 3 397 410 doi 10 1007 BF02382862 ISSN 0032 8332 S2CID 41356986 de Waal Frans 1997 Good Natured The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674356610 Boehm Christopher 1982 The evolutionary development of morality as an effect of dominance behaviour and conflict interference Journal of Social and Biological Sciences 5 4 413 22 doi 10 1016 s0140 1750 82 92069 3 Gilligan and Kohlberg Implications for Moral Theory Author s Lawrence A Blum Source Ethics Vol 98 No 3 Apr 1988 pp 472 91 Bergmann Jorg 1998 Introduction Morality in discourse Research on Language and Social Interaction 31 3 4 279 74 doi 10 1080 08351813 1998 9683594 Jorg Bergmann Veiled morality Notes on discretion in psychiatry In Drew Paul Heritage John eds 1992 Talk at work Interaction in institutional settings Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 137 62 Lena Jayyusi Values and moral judgment Communicative praxis as moral order In Button Graham ed 1991 Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 227 51 Cromdal Jakob Michael Tholander 2014 Morality in professional practice Journal of Applied Linguistics and Professional Practice 9 2 155 64 doi 10 1558 japl v9i2 25734 Mastroianni Adam M Gilbert Daniel T 2023 The illusion of moral decline Nature 618 7966 782 789 Bibcode 2023Natur 618 782M doi 10 1038 s41586 023 06137 x PMC 10284688 PMID 37286595 Sinnott Armstrong Walter Wheatley Thalia 2012 The Disunity of Morality and Why it Matters to Philosophy Monist 95 3 355 77 doi 10 5840 monist201295319 Sinnott Armstrong Walter Wheatley Thalia 13 February 2013 Are moral judgments unified Philosophical Psychology 27 4 451 74 doi 10 1080 09515089 2012 736075 S2CID 143876741 Young Liane Dungan James January 2012 Where in the brain is morality Everywhere and maybe nowhere Social Neuroscience 7 1 1 10 doi 10 1080 17470919 2011 569146 PMID 21590587 S2CID 14074566 Yoder Keith J Decety Jean 12 December 2017 The neuroscience of morality and social decision making Psychology Crime amp Law 24 3 279 95 doi 10 1080 1068316X 2017 1414817 PMC 6372234 PMID 30766017 Monin Benoit Pizarro David A Beer Jennifer S 2007 Deciding versus reacting Conceptions of moral judgment and the reason affect debate Review of General Psychology 11 2 99 111 doi 10 1037 1089 2680 11 2 99 S2CID 144286153 a b Sevinc Gunes Spreng R Nathan 4 February 2014 Contextual and Perceptual Brain Processes Underlying Moral Cognition A Quantitative Meta Analysis of Moral Reasoning and Moral Emotions PLOS ONE 9 2 e87427 Bibcode 2014PLoSO 987427S doi 10 1371 journal pone 0087427 PMC 3913597 PMID 24503959 Bartel Christopher 2015 Free will and moral responsibility in video games Ethics and Information Technology 17 4 285 293 doi 10 1007 s10676 015 9383 8 ISSN 1388 1957 S2CID 15800963 Dubljevic Veljko Sattler Sebastian Racine Eric 2018 Deciphering moral intuition How agents deeds and consequences influence moral judgment PLOS ONE 13 10 e0204631 Bibcode 2018PLoSO 1304631D doi 10 1371 journal pone 0204631 PMC 6166963 PMID 30273370 a b Bzdok Danilo Schilbach Leonhard Vogeley Kai Schneider Karla Laird Angela R Langner Robert Eickhoff Simon B 2012 01 24 Bzdok D et al Parsing the neural correlates of moral cognition ALE meta analysis on morality theory of mind and empathy Brain Struct Funct 2011 Brain Structure and Function 217 4 783 96 doi 10 1007 s00429 012 0380 y PMC 3445793 PMID 22270812 Boccia M Dacquino C Piccardi L Cordellieri P Guariglia C Ferlazzo F Ferracuti S Giannini A M 25 January 2016 Neural foundation of human moral reasoning an ALE meta analysis about the role of personal perspective Brain Imaging and Behavior 11 1 278 92 doi 10 1007 s11682 016 9505 x PMID 26809288 S2CID 3984661 Archived from the original PDF on 23 September 2019 Retrieved 23 September 2019 Eres Robert Louis Winnifred R Molenberghs Pascal 27 July 2017 Common and distinct neural networks involved in fMRI studies investigating morality an ALE meta analysis Social Neuroscience 13 4 384 98 doi 10 1080 17470919 2017 1357657 PMID 28724332 S2CID 31749926 Vedantam Shankar If It Feels Good to Be Good It Might Be Only Natural The Washington Post Retrieved 2010 05 13 de Wied M Goudena PP Matthys W 2005 Empathy in boys with disruptive behavior disorders Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry and Allied Disciplines 46 8 867 80 doi 10 1111 j 1469 7610 2004 00389 x hdl 1874 11212 PMID 16033635 S2CID 45683502 Fernandez YM Marshall WL 2003 Victim empathy social self esteem and psychopathy in rapists Sexual Abuse A Journal of Research and Treatment 15 1 11 26 doi 10 1023 A 1020611606754 PMID 12616926 S2CID 195293070 a b Sevinc Gunes Gurvit Hakan Spreng R Nathan July 2017 Salience network engagement with the detection of morally laden information Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 12 7 1118 27 doi 10 1093 scan nsx035 PMC 5490682 PMID 28338944 Seeley W W Menon V Schatzberg A F Keller J Glover G H Kenna H Reiss A L Greicius M D 28 February 2007 Dissociable Intrinsic Connectivity Networks for Salience Processing and Executive Control Journal of Neuroscience 27 9 2349 56 doi 10 1523 JNEUROSCI 5587 06 2007 PMC 2680293 PMID 17329432 Harenski CL Antonenko O Shane MS Kiehl KA 2010 A functional imaging investigation of moral deliberation and moral intuition NeuroImage 49 3 2707 16 doi 10 1016 j neuroimage 2009 10 062 PMC 4270295 PMID 19878727 Young Liane Camprodon Joan Albert Hauser Marc Pascual Leone Alvaro Saxe Rebecca 2010 Disruption of the right temporoparietal junction with transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces the role of beliefs in moral judgments PNAS 107 15 6753 58 Bibcode 2010PNAS 107 6753Y doi 10 1073 pnas 0914826107 PMC 2872442 PMID 20351278 Young Liane Bechara Antoine Tranel Daniel Damasio Hanna Hauser Marc Damasio Antonio 2010 Damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex impairs judgment of harmful intent Neuron 65 6 845 51 doi 10 1016 j neuron 2010 03 003 PMC 3085837 PMID 20346759 Zakharin Michael Bates Timothy C 2022 05 26 Testing heritability of moral foundations Common pathway models support strong heritability for the five moral foundations European Journal of Personality 37 4 485 497 doi 10 1177 08902070221103957 ISSN 0890 2070 S2CID 249115484 Smith Kevin Hatemi Peter K December 2020 Are Moral Intuitions Heritable Human Nature 31 4 406 420 doi 10 1007 s12110 020 09380 7 ISSN 1045 6767 PMID 33420605 S2CID 231202698 See Weber Eric Thomas 2011 Morality Leadership and Public Policy London Continuum Haidt Jonathan Joseph Craig September 2004 Intuitive ethics how innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues Daedalus 133 4 55 66 doi 10 1162 0011526042365555 S2CID 1574243 Graham J Haidt J Koleva S Motyl M Iyer R Wojcik S Ditto P H 2013 Moral Foundations Theory The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism PDF pp 55 130 doi 10 1016 b978 0 12 407236 7 00002 4 ISBN 978 0124072367 S2CID 2570757 Archived from the original PDF on 2017 07 31 Retrieved 2019 07 22 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help Morality 2012 Online Only Video The New Yorker Retrieved 2012 05 06 Introducing Sentience Institute Sentience Institute 2 June 2017 Retrieved 2019 08 05 Chomsky Noam 2002 07 02 Terror and Just Response ZNet Archived from the original on 2013 01 13 Rachels James Rachels Stuart eds 2011 The Elements of Moral Philosophy 7th ed New York McGraw Hill p page needed ISBN 978 0 078 03824 2 Childress James F Macquarrie John eds 1986 The Westminster Dictionary of Christian Ethics Philadelphia The Westminster Press p 401 ISBN 978 0 664 20940 7 Peggy Morgan Buddhism In Morgan Peggy Lawton Clive A eds 2007 Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions Second ed Columbia University Press pp 61 88 89 ISBN 978 0 7486 2330 3 Miller Barbara Stoler 2004 The Bhagavad Gita Krishna s Counsel in Time of War New York Random House p 3 ISBN 978 0 553 21365 2 Werner Menski Hinduism In Morgan Peggy Lawton Clive A eds 2007 Ethical Issues in Six Religious Traditions Second ed Columbia University Press p 5 ISBN 978 0 7486 2330 3 David Hume The Natural History of Religion In Hitchens Christopher ed 2007 The Portable Atheist Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever Philadelphia Da Capo Press p 30 ISBN 978 0 306 81608 6 Blackburn Simon 2001 Ethics A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press p 13 ISBN 978 0 19 280442 6 Blackburn Simon 2001 Ethics A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press p 12 ISBN 978 0 19 280442 6 Blackburn Simon 2001 Ethics A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press pp 11 12 ISBN 978 0 19 280442 6 Elizabeth Anderson If God is Dead Is Everything Permitted In Hitchens Christopher ed 2007 The Portable Atheist Essential Readings for the Nonbeliever Philadelphia Da Capo Press p 336 ISBN 978 0 306 81608 6 a b Colley Caleb Is Christianity a Threat to Ethics Apologetics Press Retrieved 3 May 2012 a b Does the Old Testament Endorse Slavery An Overview Enrichmentjournal ag org Archived from the original on 2018 10 05 Retrieved 2012 05 06 See Weber Eric Thomas Religion Public Reason and Humanism Paul Kurtz on Fallibilism and Ethics Archived 2013 10 14 at the Wayback Machine Contemporary Pragmatism 5 Issue 2 2008 131 47 a b Baier C J Wright B R 2001 If you love me keep my commandments A meta analysis of the effect of religion on crime Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 38 3 21 doi 10 1177 0022427801038001001 S2CID 145779667 Zuckerman Phil October 2008 Society Without God What the Least Religious Nations Can Tell Us about Contentment New York New York University Press p 2 ISBN 978 0 8147 9714 3 Paul Gregory S 2005 Cross National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies A First Look Journal of Religion and Society Baltimore MD 7 4 5 8 10 Archived from the original on 2011 12 14 Gary F Jensen 2006 Department of Sociology Vanderbilt University Religious Cosmologies and Homicide Rates among Nations A Closer Look Journal of Religion and Society Vol 8 ISSN 1522 5658 Highly Religious People Are Less Motivated by Compassion Than Are Non Believers Science Daily Laura R Saslow Robb Willer Matthew Feinberg Paul K Piff Katharine Clark Dacher Keltner and Sarina R Saturn My Brother s Keeper Compassion Predicts Generosity More Among Less Religious Individuals Barna Group 31 March 2008 New Marriage and Divorce Statistics Released Barna Group Archived from the original on 19 December 2014 Retrieved 19 November 2011 Wicker Christine 2000 Survey Inspires Debate Over Why Faith Isn t a Bigger Factor in Marriage www adherents com Archived from the original on March 28 2002 Retrieved 1 April 2012 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint unfit URL link Kerley Kent R Matthews Blanchard Troy C 2005 Religiosity Religious Participation and Negative Prison Behaviors Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 44 4 443 57 doi 10 1111 j 1468 5906 2005 00296 x Saroglou Vassilis Pichon Dernelle Rebecca 2005 Prosocial Behavior and Religion New Evidence Based on Projective Measures and Peer Ratings PDF Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 44 3 323 48 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 503 7559 doi 10 1111 j 1468 5906 2005 00289 x e g a survey Archived 2007 10 08 at the Wayback Machine by Robert Putnam showing that membership of religious groups was positively correlated with membership of voluntary organisations As is stated in Chu Doris C 2007 Religiosity and Desistance From Drug Use Criminal Justice and Behavior 34 5 661 79 doi 10 1177 0093854806293485 S2CID 145491534 For example Albrecht S I Chadwick B A Alcorn D S 1977 Religiosity and deviance Application of an attitude behavior contingent consistency model Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 16 3 263 74 doi 10 2307 1385697 JSTOR 1385697 Burkett S White M 1974 Hellfire and delinquency Another look Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 13 4 455 62 doi 10 2307 1384608 JSTOR 1384608 Chard Wierschem D 1998 In pursuit of the true relationship A longitudinal study of the effects of religiosity on delinquency and substance abuse Ann Arbor MI UMI Dissertation Cochran J K Akers R L 1989 Beyond Hellfire An explanation of the variable effects of religiosity on adolescent marijuana and alcohol use Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 26 3 198 225 doi 10 1177 0022427889026003002 S2CID 145479350 Evans T D Cullen F T Burton V S Jr Dunaway R G Payne G L Kethineni S R 1996 Religion social bonds and delinquency Deviant Behavior 17 43 70 doi 10 1080 01639625 1996 9968014 Grasmick H G Bursik R J Cochran J K 1991 Render unto Caesar what is Caesar s Religiosity and taxpayer s inclinations to cheat The Sociological Quarterly 32 2 251 66 doi 10 1111 j 1533 8525 1991 tb00356 x Higgins P C Albrecht G L 1977 Hellfire and delinquency revisited Social Forces 55 4 952 58 doi 10 1093 sf 55 4 952 Johnson B R Larson D B DeLi S Jang S J 2000 Escaping from the crime of inner cities Church attendance and religious salience among disadvantaged youth Justice Quarterly 17 2 377 91 doi 10 1080 07418820000096371 S2CID 144816590 Johnson R E Marcos A C Bahr S J 1987 The role of peers in the complex etiology of adolescent drug use Criminology 25 2 323 40 doi 10 1111 j 1745 9125 1987 tb00800 x Powell K 1997 Correlates of violent and nonviolent behavior among vulnerable inner city youths Family and Community Health 20 2 38 47 doi 10 1097 00003727 199707000 00006 Paul Gregory S 2005 Cross National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies A First Look Journal of Religion and Society Baltimore MD 7 4 5 8 Archived from the original on 2011 12 14 Paul Gregory S 2005 Cross National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies A First Look Journal of Religion and Society Baltimore MD 7 11 Archived from the original on 2011 12 14 Paul Gregory S 2005 Cross National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies A First Look Journal of Religion and Society Baltimore MD 7 Archived from the original on 2011 12 14 Gerson Moreno Riano Mark Caleb Smith Thomas Mach 2006 Religiosity Secularism and Social Health Journal of Religion and Society Cedarville University 8 Archived from the original on 2011 10 28 Blackburn Simon 2001 Ethics A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press pp 10 12 ISBN 978 0 19 280442 6 Westacott Emrys Moral Relativism iep utm edu Retrieved 12 May 2018 Further reading EditChurchland Patricia Smith 2011 Braintrust What Neuroscience Tells Us about Morality Princeton NJ Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 13703 2 Reviewed in The Montreal Review Richard Dawkins The roots of morality why are we good in The God Delusion Black Swan 2007 ISBN 978 0 552 77429 1 Harris Sam 2010 The Moral Landscape How Science Can Determine Human Values New York Free Press ISBN 978 1 4391 7121 9 Lunn Arnold and Garth Lean 1964 The New Morality London Blandford Press John Newton Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century 2000 ISBN 0967370574 Prinz Jesse Jan Feb 2013 Morality is a Culturally Conditioned Response Philosophy Now Slater S J Thomas 1925 Book I Morality A manual of moral theology for English speaking countries Burns Oates amp Washbourne Ltd Stace Walter Terence 1937 The Concept of Morals New York The MacMillan Company Reprinted 1975 by permission of Macmillan Publishing Co Inc and also reprinted by Peter Smith Publisher Inc January 1990 ISBN 978 0 8446 2990 2 Trompenaars Fons 2003 Did the Pedestrian Die Insights from the World s Greatest Culture Guru Oxford Capstone ISBN 978 1 84112 436 0 Yandell Keith E 1973 God man and religion readings in the philosophy of religion McGraw Hill containing articles by Paterson Brown Religious Morality from Mind 1963 Religious Morality a Reply to Flew and Campbell from Mind 1964 God and the Good from Religious Studies 1967 Ashley Welch Virtuous behaviors sanction later sins people are quick to treat themselves after a good deed or healthy act March 4 2012 Roberto Andorno Do our moral judgements need to be guided by principles Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2012 21 4 457 65 External links Edit nbsp Look up morality in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Morality nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Morality The Definition of Morality Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Boston College s Morality Lab Morality and Judaism chabad org The Moral Instinct by Steven Pinker The New York Times 13 January 2008 Portal nbsp Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Morality amp oldid 1178037547, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.