fbpx
Wikipedia

Philosophy of mathematics

The philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the assumptions, foundations, and implications of mathematics. It aims to understand the nature and methods of mathematics, and find out the place of mathematics in people's lives. The logical and structural nature of mathematics makes this branch of philosophy broad and unique.

The philosophy of mathematics has two major themes: mathematical realism and mathematical anti-realism.

History Edit

 
Pythagoras is considered the father of mathematics and geometry as he set the foundation for Euclid and Euclidean Geometry. Pythagoras was the founder of Pythagoreanism: a mathematical and philosophical model to map the universe.

The origin of mathematics is of arguments and disagreements. Whether the birth of mathematics was by chance or induced by necessity during the development of similar subjects, such as physics, remains an area of contention.[1][2]

Many thinkers have contributed their ideas concerning the nature of mathematics. Today, some[who?] philosophers of mathematics aim to give accounts of this form of inquiry and its products as they stand, while others emphasize a role for themselves that goes beyond simple interpretation to critical analysis. There are traditions of mathematical philosophy in both Western philosophy and Eastern philosophy. Western philosophies of mathematics go as far back as Pythagoras, who described the theory "everything is mathematics" (mathematicism), Plato, who paraphrased Pythagoras, and studied the ontological status of mathematical objects, and Aristotle, who studied logic and issues related to infinity (actual versus potential).

Greek philosophy on mathematics was strongly influenced by their study of geometry. For example, at one time, the Greeks held the opinion that 1 (one) was not a number, but rather a unit of arbitrary length. A number was defined as a multitude. Therefore, 3, for example, represented a certain multitude of units, and was thus "truly" a number. At another point, a similar argument was made that 2 was not a number but a fundamental notion of a pair. These views come from the heavily geometric straight-edge-and-compass viewpoint of the Greeks: just as lines drawn in a geometric problem are measured in proportion to the first arbitrarily drawn line, so too are the numbers on a number line measured in proportion to the arbitrary first "number" or "one".[3]

These earlier Greek ideas of numbers were later upended by the discovery of the irrationality of the square root of two. Hippasus, a disciple of Pythagoras, showed that the diagonal of a unit square was incommensurable with its (unit-length) edge: in other words he proved there was no existing (rational) number that accurately depicts the proportion of the diagonal of the unit square to its edge. This caused a significant re-evaluation of Greek philosophy of mathematics. According to legend, fellow Pythagoreans were so traumatized by this discovery that they murdered Hippasus to stop him from spreading his heretical idea.[citation needed] Simon Stevin was one of the first in Europe to challenge Greek ideas in the 16th century. Beginning with Leibniz, the focus shifted strongly to the relationship between mathematics and logic. This perspective dominated the philosophy of mathematics through the time of Frege and of Russell, but was brought into question by developments in the late 19th and early 20th centuries.

Contemporary philosophy Edit

A perennial issue in the philosophy of mathematics concerns the relationship between logic and mathematics at their joint foundations. While 20th-century philosophers continued to ask the questions mentioned at the outset of this article, the philosophy of mathematics in the 20th century was characterized by a predominant interest in formal logic, set theory (both naive set theory and axiomatic set theory), and foundational issues.

It is a profound puzzle that on the one hand mathematical truths seem to have a compelling inevitability, but on the other hand the source of their "truthfulness" remains elusive. Investigations into this issue are known as the foundations of mathematics program.

At the start of the 20th century, philosophers of mathematics were already beginning to divide into various schools of thought about all these questions, broadly distinguished by their pictures of mathematical epistemology and ontology. Three schools, formalism, intuitionism, and logicism, emerged at this time, partly in response to the increasingly widespread worry that mathematics as it stood, and analysis in particular, did not live up to the standards of certainty and rigor that had been taken for granted. Each school addressed the issues that came to the fore at that time, either attempting to resolve them or claiming that mathematics is not entitled to its status as our most trusted knowledge.

Surprising and counter-intuitive developments in formal logic and set theory early in the 20th century led to new questions concerning what was traditionally called the foundations of mathematics. As the century unfolded, the initial focus of concern expanded to an open exploration of the fundamental axioms of mathematics, the axiomatic approach having been taken for granted since the time of Euclid around 300 BCE as the natural basis for mathematics. Notions of axiom, proposition and proof, as well as the notion of a proposition being true of a mathematical object (see Assignment), were formalized, allowing them to be treated mathematically. The Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms for set theory were formulated which provided a conceptual framework in which much mathematical discourse would be interpreted. In mathematics, as in physics, new and unexpected ideas had arisen and significant changes were coming. With Gödel numbering, propositions could be interpreted as referring to themselves or other propositions, enabling inquiry into the consistency of mathematical theories. This reflective critique in which the theory under review "becomes itself the object of a mathematical study" led Hilbert to call such study metamathematics or proof theory.[4]

At the middle of the century, a new mathematical theory was created by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane, known as category theory, and it became a new contender for the natural language of mathematical thinking.[5] As the 20th century progressed, however, philosophical opinions diverged as to just how well-founded were the questions about foundations that were raised at the century's beginning. Hilary Putnam summed up one common view of the situation in the last third of the century by saying:

When philosophy discovers something wrong with science, sometimes science has to be changed—Russell's paradox comes to mind, as does Berkeley's attack on the actual infinitesimal—but more often it is philosophy that has to be changed. I do not think that the difficulties that philosophy finds with classical mathematics today are genuine difficulties; and I think that the philosophical interpretations of mathematics that we are being offered on every hand are wrong, and that "philosophical interpretation" is just what mathematics doesn't need.[6]: 169–170 

Philosophy of mathematics today proceeds along several different lines of inquiry, by philosophers of mathematics, logicians, and mathematicians, and there are many schools of thought on the subject. The schools are addressed separately in the next section, and their assumptions explained.

Major themes Edit

Mathematical realism Edit

Mathematical realism, like realism in general, holds that mathematical entities exist independently of the human mind. Thus, humans do not invent mathematics, but rather discover it, and any other intelligent beings in the universe would presumably do the same. In this point of view, there is really one sort of mathematics that can be discovered; triangles, for example, are real entities, not the creations of the human mind.

Many working mathematicians have been mathematical realists; they see themselves as discoverers of naturally occurring objects. Examples include Paul Erdős and Kurt Gödel. Gödel believed in an objective mathematical reality that could be perceived in a manner analogous to sense perception. Certain principles (e.g., for any two objects, there is a collection of objects consisting of precisely those two objects) could be directly seen to be true, but the continuum hypothesis conjecture might prove undecidable just on the basis of such principles. Gödel suggested that quasi-empirical methodology could be used to provide sufficient evidence to be able to reasonably assume such a conjecture.

Within realism, there are distinctions depending on what sort of existence one takes mathematical entities to have, and how we know about them. Major forms of mathematical realism include Platonism and Aristotelianism.

Mathematical anti-realism Edit

Mathematical anti-realism generally holds that mathematical statements have truth-values, but that they do not do so by corresponding to a special realm of immaterial or non-empirical entities. Major forms of mathematical anti-realism include formalism and fictionalism.

Contemporary schools of thought Edit

Artistic Edit

The view that claims that mathematics is the aesthetic combination of assumptions, and then also claims that mathematics is an art. A famous mathematician who claims that is the British G. H. Hardy.[7] For Hardy, in his book, A Mathematician's Apology, the definition of mathematics was more like the aesthetic combination of concepts.[8]

Platonism Edit

Mathematical Platonism is the form of realism that suggests that mathematical entities are abstract, have no spatiotemporal or causal properties, and are eternal and unchanging. This is often claimed to be the view most people have of numbers. The term Platonism is used because such a view is seen to parallel Plato's Theory of Forms and a "World of Ideas" (Greek: eidos (εἶδος)) described in Plato's allegory of the cave: the everyday world can only imperfectly approximate an unchanging, ultimate reality. Both Plato's cave and Platonism have meaningful, not just superficial connections, because Plato's ideas were preceded and probably influenced by the hugely popular Pythagoreans of ancient Greece, who believed that the world was, quite literally, generated by numbers.

A major question considered in mathematical Platonism is: Precisely where and how do the mathematical entities exist, and how do we know about them? Is there a world, completely separate from our physical one, that is occupied by the mathematical entities? How can we gain access to this separate world and discover truths about the entities? One proposed answer is the Ultimate Ensemble, a theory that postulates that all structures that exist mathematically also exist physically in their own universe.

 
Kurt Gödel

Kurt Gödel's Platonism[9] postulates a special kind of mathematical intuition that lets us perceive mathematical objects directly. (This view bears resemblances to many things Husserl said about mathematics, and supports Kant's idea that mathematics is synthetic a priori.) Davis and Hersh have suggested in their 1999 book The Mathematical Experience that most mathematicians act as though they are Platonists, even though, if pressed to defend the position carefully, they may retreat to formalism.

Full-blooded Platonism is a modern variation of Platonism, which is in reaction to the fact that different sets of mathematical entities can be proven to exist depending on the axioms and inference rules employed (for instance, the law of the excluded middle, and the axiom of choice). It holds that all mathematical entities exist. They may be provable, even if they cannot all be derived from a single consistent set of axioms.[10]

Set-theoretic realism (also set-theoretic Platonism)[11] a position defended by Penelope Maddy, is the view that set theory is about a single universe of sets.[12] This position (which is also known as naturalized Platonism because it is a naturalized version of mathematical Platonism) has been criticized by Mark Balaguer on the basis of Paul Benacerraf's epistemological problem.[13] A similar view, termed Platonized naturalism, was later defended by the Stanford–Edmonton School: according to this view, a more traditional kind of Platonism is consistent with naturalism; the more traditional kind of Platonism they defend is distinguished by general principles that assert the existence of abstract objects.[14]

Mathematicism Edit

Max Tegmark's mathematical universe hypothesis (or mathematicism) goes further than Platonism in asserting that not only do all mathematical objects exist, but nothing else does. Tegmark's sole postulate is: All structures that exist mathematically also exist physically. That is, in the sense that "in those [worlds] complex enough to contain self-aware substructures [they] will subjectively perceive themselves as existing in a physically 'real' world".[15][16]

Logicism Edit

Logicism is the thesis that mathematics is reducible to logic, and hence nothing but a part of logic.[17]: 41  Logicists hold that mathematics can be known a priori, but suggest that our knowledge of mathematics is just part of our knowledge of logic in general, and is thus analytic, not requiring any special faculty of mathematical intuition. In this view, logic is the proper foundation of mathematics, and all mathematical statements are necessary logical truths.

Rudolf Carnap (1931) presents the logicist thesis in two parts:[17]

  1. The concepts of mathematics can be derived from logical concepts through explicit definitions.
  2. The theorems of mathematics can be derived from logical axioms through purely logical deduction.

Gottlob Frege was the founder of logicism. In his seminal Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Basic Laws of Arithmetic) he built up arithmetic from a system of logic with a general principle of comprehension, which he called "Basic Law V" (for concepts F and G, the extension of F equals the extension of G if and only if for all objects a, Fa equals Ga), a principle that he took to be acceptable as part of logic.

 
Bertrand Russell

Frege's construction was flawed. Bertrand Russell discovered that Basic Law V is inconsistent (this is Russell's paradox). Frege abandoned his logicist program soon after this, but it was continued by Russell and Whitehead. They attributed the paradox to "vicious circularity" and built up what they called ramified type theory to deal with it. In this system, they were eventually able to build up much of modern mathematics but in an altered, and excessively complex form (for example, there were different natural numbers in each type, and there were infinitely many types). They also had to make several compromises in order to develop much of mathematics, such as the "axiom of reducibility". Even Russell said that this axiom did not really belong to logic.

Modern logicists (like Bob Hale, Crispin Wright, and perhaps others) have returned to a program closer to Frege's. They have abandoned Basic Law V in favor of abstraction principles such as Hume's principle (the number of objects falling under the concept F equals the number of objects falling under the concept G if and only if the extension of F and the extension of G can be put into one-to-one correspondence). Frege required Basic Law V to be able to give an explicit definition of the numbers, but all the properties of numbers can be derived from Hume's principle. This would not have been enough for Frege because (to paraphrase him) it does not exclude the possibility that the number 3 is in fact Julius Caesar. In addition, many of the weakened principles that they have had to adopt to replace Basic Law V no longer seem so obviously analytic, and thus purely logical.

Formalism Edit

Formalism holds that mathematical statements may be thought of as statements about the consequences of certain string manipulation rules. For example, in the "game" of Euclidean geometry (which is seen as consisting of some strings called "axioms", and some "rules of inference" to generate new strings from given ones), one can prove that the Pythagorean theorem holds (that is, one can generate the string corresponding to the Pythagorean theorem). According to formalism, mathematical truths are not about numbers and sets and triangles and the like—in fact, they are not "about" anything at all.

Another version of formalism is often known as deductivism. In deductivism, the Pythagorean theorem is not an absolute truth, but a relative one: if one assigns meaning to the strings in such a way that the rules of the game become true (i.e., true statements are assigned to the axioms and the rules of inference are truth-preserving), then one must accept the theorem, or, rather, the interpretation one has given it must be a true statement. The same is held to be true for all other mathematical statements. Thus, formalism need not mean that mathematics is nothing more than a meaningless symbolic game. It is usually hoped that there exists some interpretation in which the rules of the game hold. (Compare this position to structuralism.) But it does allow the working mathematician to continue in his or her work and leave such problems to the philosopher or scientist. Many formalists would say that in practice, the axiom systems to be studied will be suggested by the demands of science or other areas of mathematics.

 
David Hilbert

A major early proponent of formalism was David Hilbert, whose program was intended to be a complete and consistent axiomatization of all of mathematics.[18] Hilbert aimed to show the consistency of mathematical systems from the assumption that the "finitary arithmetic" (a subsystem of the usual arithmetic of the positive integers, chosen to be philosophically uncontroversial) was consistent. Hilbert's goals of creating a system of mathematics that is both complete and consistent were seriously undermined by the second of Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which states that sufficiently expressive consistent axiom systems can never prove their own consistency. Since any such axiom system would contain the finitary arithmetic as a subsystem, Gödel's theorem implied that it would be impossible to prove the system's consistency relative to that (since it would then prove its own consistency, which Gödel had shown was impossible). Thus, in order to show that any axiomatic system of mathematics is in fact consistent, one needs to first assume the consistency of a system of mathematics that is in a sense stronger than the system to be proven consistent.

Hilbert was initially a deductivist, but, as may be clear from above, he considered certain metamathematical methods to yield intrinsically meaningful results and was a realist with respect to the finitary arithmetic. Later, he held the opinion that there was no other meaningful mathematics whatsoever, regardless of interpretation.

Other formalists, such as Rudolf Carnap, Alfred Tarski, and Haskell Curry, considered mathematics to be the investigation of formal axiom systems. Mathematical logicians study formal systems but are just as often realists as they are formalists.

Formalists are relatively tolerant and inviting to new approaches to logic, non-standard number systems, new set theories etc. The more games we study, the better. However, in all three of these examples, motivation is drawn from existing mathematical or philosophical concerns. The "games" are usually not arbitrary.

The main critique of formalism is that the actual mathematical ideas that occupy mathematicians are far removed from the string manipulation games mentioned above. Formalism is thus silent on the question of which axiom systems ought to be studied, as none is more meaningful than another from a formalistic point of view.

Recently, some[who?] formalist mathematicians have proposed that all of our formal mathematical knowledge should be systematically encoded in computer-readable formats, so as to facilitate automated proof checking of mathematical proofs and the use of interactive theorem proving in the development of mathematical theories and computer software. Because of their close connection with computer science, this idea is also advocated by mathematical intuitionists and constructivists in the "computability" tradition—see QED project for a general overview.

Conventionalism Edit

The French mathematician Henri Poincaré was among the first to articulate a conventionalist view. Poincaré's use of non-Euclidean geometries in his work on differential equations convinced him that Euclidean geometry should not be regarded as a priori truth. He held that axioms in geometry should be chosen for the results they produce, not for their apparent coherence with human intuitions about the physical world.

Intuitionism Edit

In mathematics, intuitionism is a program of methodological reform whose motto is that "there are no non-experienced mathematical truths" (L. E. J. Brouwer). From this springboard, intuitionists seek to reconstruct what they consider to be the corrigible portion of mathematics in accordance with Kantian concepts of being, becoming, intuition, and knowledge. Brouwer, the founder of the movement, held that mathematical objects arise from the a priori forms of the volitions that inform the perception of empirical objects.[19]

A major force behind intuitionism was L. E. J. Brouwer, who rejected the usefulness of formalized logic of any sort for mathematics. His student Arend Heyting postulated an intuitionistic logic, different from the classical Aristotelian logic; this logic does not contain the law of the excluded middle and therefore frowns upon proofs by contradiction. The axiom of choice is also rejected in most intuitionistic set theories, though in some versions it is accepted.

In intuitionism, the term "explicit construction" is not cleanly defined, and that has led to criticisms. Attempts have been made to use the concepts of Turing machine or computable function to fill this gap, leading to the claim that only questions regarding the behavior of finite algorithms are meaningful and should be investigated in mathematics. This has led to the study of the computable numbers, first introduced by Alan Turing. Not surprisingly, then, this approach to mathematics is sometimes associated with theoretical computer science.

Constructivism Edit

Like intuitionism, constructivism involves the regulative principle that only mathematical entities which can be explicitly constructed in a certain sense should be admitted to mathematical discourse. In this view, mathematics is an exercise of the human intuition, not a game played with meaningless symbols. Instead, it is about entities that we can create directly through mental activity. In addition, some adherents of these schools reject non-constructive proofs, such as using proof by contradiction when showing the existence of an object or when trying to establish the truth of some proposition. Important work was done by Errett Bishop, who managed to prove versions of the most important theorems in real analysis as constructive analysis in his 1967 Foundations of Constructive Analysis.[20]

Finitism Edit

 
Leopold Kronecker

Finitism is an extreme form of constructivism, according to which a mathematical object does not exist unless it can be constructed from natural numbers in a finite number of steps. In her book Philosophy of Set Theory, Mary Tiles characterized those who allow countably infinite objects as classical finitists, and those who deny even countably infinite objects as strict finitists.

The most famous proponent of finitism was Leopold Kronecker,[21] who said:

God created the natural numbers, all else is the work of man.

Ultrafinitism is an even more extreme version of finitism, which rejects not only infinities but finite quantities that cannot feasibly be constructed with available resources. Another variant of finitism is Euclidean arithmetic, a system developed by John Penn Mayberry in his book The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets.[22] Mayberry's system is Aristotelian in general inspiration and, despite his strong rejection of any role for operationalism or feasibility in the foundations of mathematics, comes to somewhat similar conclusions, such as, for instance, that super-exponentiation is not a legitimate finitary function.

Structuralism Edit

Structuralism is a position holding that mathematical theories describe structures, and that mathematical objects are exhaustively defined by their places in such structures, consequently having no intrinsic properties. For instance, it would maintain that all that needs to be known about the number 1 is that it is the first whole number after 0. Likewise all the other whole numbers are defined by their places in a structure, the number line. Other examples of mathematical objects might include lines and planes in geometry, or elements and operations in abstract algebra.

Structuralism is an epistemologically realistic view in that it holds that mathematical statements have an objective truth value. However, its central claim only relates to what kind of entity a mathematical object is, not to what kind of existence mathematical objects or structures have (not, in other words, to their ontology). The kind of existence mathematical objects have would clearly be dependent on that of the structures in which they are embedded; different sub-varieties of structuralism make different ontological claims in this regard.[23]

The ante rem structuralism ("before the thing") has a similar ontology to Platonism. Structures are held to have a real but abstract and immaterial existence. As such, it faces the standard epistemological problem of explaining the interaction between such abstract structures and flesh-and-blood mathematicians (see Benacerraf's identification problem).

The in re structuralism ("in the thing") is the equivalent of Aristotelian realism. Structures are held to exist inasmuch as some concrete system exemplifies them. This incurs the usual issues that some perfectly legitimate structures might accidentally happen not to exist, and that a finite physical world might not be "big" enough to accommodate some otherwise legitimate structures.

The post rem structuralism ("after the thing") is anti-realist about structures in a way that parallels nominalism. Like nominalism, the post rem approach denies the existence of abstract mathematical objects with properties other than their place in a relational structure. According to this view mathematical systems exist, and have structural features in common. If something is true of a structure, it will be true of all systems exemplifying the structure. However, it is merely instrumental to talk of structures being "held in common" between systems: they in fact have no independent existence.

Embodied mind theories Edit

Embodied mind theories hold that mathematical thought is a natural outgrowth of the human cognitive apparatus which finds itself in our physical universe. For example, the abstract concept of number springs from the experience of counting discrete objects (requiring the human senses such as sight for detecting the objects, touch; and signalling from the brain). It is held that mathematics is not universal and does not exist in any real sense, other than in human brains. Humans construct, but do not discover, mathematics.

The cognitive processes of pattern-finding and distinguishing objects are also subject to neuroscience; if mathematics is considered to be relevant to a natural world (such as from realism or a degree of it, as opposed to pure solipsism).

Its actual relevance to reality, while accepted to be a trustworthy approximation (it is also suggested the evolution of perceptions, the body, and the senses may have been necessary for survival) is not necessarily accurate to a full realism (and is still subject to flaws such as illusion, assumptions (consequently; the foundations and axioms in which mathematics have been formed by humans), generalisations, deception, and hallucinations). As such, this may also raise questions for the modern scientific method for its compatibility with general mathematics; as while relatively reliable, it is still limited by what can be measured by empiricism which may not be as reliable as previously assumed (see also: 'counterintuitive' concepts in such as quantum nonlocality, and action at a distance).

Another issue is that one numeral system may not necessarily be applicable to problem solving. Subjects such as complex numbers or imaginary numbers require specific changes to more commonly used axioms of mathematics; otherwise they cannot be adequately understood.

Alternatively, computer programmers may use hexadecimal for its 'human-friendly' representation of binary-coded values, rather than decimal (convenient for counting because humans have ten fingers). The axioms or logical rules behind mathematics also vary through time (such as the adaption and invention of zero).

As perceptions from the human brain are subject to illusions, assumptions, deceptions, (induced) hallucinations, cognitive errors or assumptions in a general context, it can be questioned whether they are accurate or strictly indicative of truth (see also: philosophy of being), and the nature of empiricism itself in relation to the universe and whether it is independent to the senses and the universe.

The human mind has no special claim on reality or approaches to it built out of math. If such constructs as Euler's identity are true then they are true as a map of the human mind and cognition.

Embodied mind theorists thus explain the effectiveness of mathematics—mathematics was constructed by the brain in order to be effective in this universe.

The most accessible, famous, and infamous treatment of this perspective is Where Mathematics Comes From, by George Lakoff and Rafael E. Núñez. In addition, mathematician Keith Devlin has investigated similar concepts with his book The Math Instinct, as has neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene with his book The Number Sense. For more on the philosophical ideas that inspired this perspective, see cognitive science of mathematics.

Aristotelian realism Edit

Aristotelian realism holds that mathematics studies properties such as symmetry, continuity and order that can be literally realized in the physical world (or in any other world there might be). It contrasts with Platonism in holding that the objects of mathematics, such as numbers, do not exist in an "abstract" world but can be physically realized. For example, the number 4 is realized in the relation between a heap of parrots and the universal "being a parrot" that divides the heap into so many parrots.[24][25] Aristotelian realism is defended by James Franklin and the Sydney School in the philosophy of mathematics and is close to the view of Penelope Maddy that when an egg carton is opened, a set of three eggs is perceived (that is, a mathematical entity realized in the physical world).[26] A problem for Aristotelian realism is what account to give of higher infinities, which may not be realizable in the physical world.

The Euclidean arithmetic developed by John Penn Mayberry in his book The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets[22] also falls into the Aristotelian realist tradition. Mayberry, following Euclid, considers numbers to be simply "definite multitudes of units" realized in nature—such as "the members of the London Symphony Orchestra" or "the trees in Birnam wood". Whether or not there are definite multitudes of units for which Euclid's Common Notion 5 (the whole is greater than the part) fails and which would consequently be reckoned as infinite is for Mayberry essentially a question about Nature and does not entail any transcendental suppositions.

Psychologism Edit

Psychologism in the philosophy of mathematics is the position that mathematical concepts and/or truths are grounded in, derived from or explained by psychological facts (or laws).

John Stuart Mill seems to have been an advocate of a type of logical psychologism, as were many 19th-century German logicians such as Sigwart and Erdmann as well as a number of psychologists, past and present: for example, Gustave Le Bon. Psychologism was famously criticized by Frege in his The Foundations of Arithmetic, and many of his works and essays, including his review of Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic. Edmund Husserl, in the first volume of his Logical Investigations, called "The Prolegomena of Pure Logic", criticized psychologism thoroughly and sought to distance himself from it. The "Prolegomena" is considered a more concise, fair, and thorough refutation of psychologism than the criticisms made by Frege, and also it is considered today by many as being a memorable refutation for its decisive blow to psychologism. Psychologism was also criticized by Charles Sanders Peirce and Maurice Merleau-Ponty.

Empiricism Edit

Mathematical empiricism is a form of realism that denies that mathematics can be known a priori at all. It says that we discover mathematical facts by empirical research, just like facts in any of the other sciences. It is not one of the classical three positions advocated in the early 20th century, but primarily arose in the middle of the century. However, an important early proponent of a view like this was John Stuart Mill. Mill's view was widely criticized, because, according to critics, such as A.J. Ayer,[27] it makes statements like "2 + 2 = 4" come out as uncertain, contingent truths, which we can only learn by observing instances of two pairs coming together and forming a quartet.

Karl Popper was another philosopher to point out empirical aspects of mathematics, observing that "most mathematical theories are, like those of physics and biology, hypothetico-deductive: pure mathematics therefore turns out to be much closer to the natural sciences whose hypotheses are conjectures, than it seemed even recently."[28] Popper also noted he would "admit a system as empirical or scientific only if it is capable of being tested by experience."[29]

Contemporary mathematical empiricism, formulated by W. V. O. Quine and Hilary Putnam, is primarily supported by the indispensability argument: mathematics is indispensable to all empirical sciences, and if we want to believe in the reality of the phenomena described by the sciences, we ought also believe in the reality of those entities required for this description. That is, since physics needs to talk about electrons to say why light bulbs behave as they do, then electrons must exist. Since physics needs to talk about numbers in offering any of its explanations, then numbers must exist. In keeping with Quine and Putnam's overall philosophies, this is a naturalistic argument. It argues for the existence of mathematical entities as the best explanation for experience, thus stripping mathematics of being distinct from the other sciences.

Putnam strongly rejected the term "Platonist" as implying an over-specific ontology that was not necessary to mathematical practice in any real sense. He advocated a form of "pure realism" that rejected mystical notions of truth and accepted much quasi-empiricism in mathematics. This grew from the increasingly popular assertion in the late 20th century that no one foundation of mathematics could be ever proven to exist. It is also sometimes called "postmodernism in mathematics" although that term is considered overloaded by some and insulting by others. Quasi-empiricism argues that in doing their research, mathematicians test hypotheses as well as prove theorems. A mathematical argument can transmit falsity from the conclusion to the premises just as well as it can transmit truth from the premises to the conclusion. Putnam has argued that any theory of mathematical realism would include quasi-empirical methods. He proposed that an alien species doing mathematics might well rely on quasi-empirical methods primarily, being willing often to forgo rigorous and axiomatic proofs, and still be doing mathematics—at perhaps a somewhat greater risk of failure of their calculations. He gave a detailed argument for this in New Directions.[30] Quasi-empiricism was also developed by Imre Lakatos.

The most important criticism of empirical views of mathematics is approximately the same as that raised against Mill. If mathematics is just as empirical as the other sciences, then this suggests that its results are just as fallible as theirs, and just as contingent. In Mill's case the empirical justification comes directly, while in Quine's case it comes indirectly, through the coherence of our scientific theory as a whole, i.e. consilience after E.O. Wilson. Quine suggests that mathematics seems completely certain because the role it plays in our web of belief is extraordinarily central, and that it would be extremely difficult for us to revise it, though not impossible.

For a philosophy of mathematics that attempts to overcome some of the shortcomings of Quine and Gödel's approaches by taking aspects of each see Penelope Maddy's Realism in Mathematics. Another example of a realist theory is the embodied mind theory.

For experimental evidence suggesting that human infants can do elementary arithmetic, see Brian Butterworth.

Fictionalism Edit

Mathematical fictionalism was brought to fame in 1980 when Hartry Field published Science Without Numbers,[31] which rejected and in fact reversed Quine's indispensability argument. Where Quine suggested that mathematics was indispensable for our best scientific theories, and therefore should be accepted as a body of truths talking about independently existing entities, Field suggested that mathematics was dispensable, and therefore should be considered as a body of falsehoods not talking about anything real. He did this by giving a complete axiomatization of Newtonian mechanics with no reference to numbers or functions at all. He started with the "betweenness" of Hilbert's axioms to characterize space without coordinatizing it, and then added extra relations between points to do the work formerly done by vector fields. Hilbert's geometry is mathematical, because it talks about abstract points, but in Field's theory, these points are the concrete points of physical space, so no special mathematical objects at all are needed.

Having shown how to do science without using numbers, Field proceeded to rehabilitate mathematics as a kind of useful fiction. He showed that mathematical physics is a conservative extension of his non-mathematical physics (that is, every physical fact provable in mathematical physics is already provable from Field's system), so that mathematics is a reliable process whose physical applications are all true, even though its own statements are false. Thus, when doing mathematics, we can see ourselves as telling a sort of story, talking as if numbers existed. For Field, a statement like "2 + 2 = 4" is just as fictitious as "Sherlock Holmes lived at 221B Baker Street"—but both are true according to the relevant fictions.

Another fictionalist, Mary Leng, expresses the perspective succinctly by dismissing any seeming connection between mathematics and the physical world as "a happy coincidence". This rejection separates fictionalism from other forms of anti-realism, which see mathematics itself as artificial but still bounded or fitted to reality in some way.[32]

By this account, there are no metaphysical or epistemological problems special to mathematics. The only worries left are the general worries about non-mathematical physics, and about fiction in general. Field's approach has been very influential, but is widely rejected. This is in part because of the requirement of strong fragments of second-order logic to carry out his reduction, and because the statement of conservativity seems to require quantification over abstract models or deductions.[citation needed]

Social constructivism Edit

Social constructivism sees mathematics primarily as a social construct, as a product of culture, subject to correction and change. Like the other sciences, mathematics is viewed as an empirical endeavor whose results are constantly evaluated and may be discarded. However, while on an empiricist view the evaluation is some sort of comparison with "reality", social constructivists emphasize that the direction of mathematical research is dictated by the fashions of the social group performing it or by the needs of the society financing it. However, although such external forces may change the direction of some mathematical research, there are strong internal constraints—the mathematical traditions, methods, problems, meanings and values into which mathematicians are enculturated—that work to conserve the historically-defined discipline.

This runs counter to the traditional beliefs of working mathematicians, that mathematics is somehow pure or objective. But social constructivists argue that mathematics is in fact grounded by much uncertainty: as mathematical practice evolves, the status of previous mathematics is cast into doubt, and is corrected to the degree it is required or desired by the current mathematical community. This can be seen in the development of analysis from reexamination of the calculus of Leibniz and Newton. They argue further that finished mathematics is often accorded too much status, and folk mathematics not enough, due to an overemphasis on axiomatic proof and peer review as practices.

The social nature of mathematics is highlighted in its subcultures. Major discoveries can be made in one branch of mathematics and be relevant to another, yet the relationship goes undiscovered for lack of social contact between mathematicians. Social constructivists argue each speciality forms its own epistemic community and often has great difficulty communicating, or motivating the investigation of unifying conjectures that might relate different areas of mathematics. Social constructivists see the process of "doing mathematics" as actually creating the meaning, while social realists see a deficiency either of human capacity to abstractify, or of human's cognitive bias, or of mathematicians' collective intelligence as preventing the comprehension of a real universe of mathematical objects. Social constructivists sometimes reject the search for foundations of mathematics as bound to fail, as pointless or even meaningless.

Contributions to this school have been made by Imre Lakatos and Thomas Tymoczko, although it is not clear that either would endorse the title.[clarification needed] More recently Paul Ernest has explicitly formulated a social constructivist philosophy of mathematics.[33] Some consider the work of Paul Erdős as a whole to have advanced this view (although he personally rejected it) because of his uniquely broad collaborations, which prompted others to see and study "mathematics as a social activity", e.g., via the Erdős number. Reuben Hersh has also promoted the social view of mathematics, calling it a "humanistic" approach,[34] similar to but not quite the same as that associated with Alvin White;[35] one of Hersh's co-authors, Philip J. Davis, has expressed sympathy for the social view as well.

Beyond the traditional schools Edit

Unreasonable effectiveness Edit

Rather than focus on narrow debates about the true nature of mathematical truth, or even on practices unique to mathematicians such as the proof, a growing movement from the 1960s to the 1990s began to question the idea of seeking foundations or finding any one right answer to why mathematics works. The starting point for this was Eugene Wigner's famous 1960 paper "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences", in which he argued that the happy coincidence of mathematics and physics being so well matched seemed to be unreasonable and hard to explain.

Popper's two senses of number statements Edit

Realist and constructivist theories are normally taken to be contraries. However, Karl Popper[36] argued that a number statement such as "2 apples + 2 apples = 4 apples" can be taken in two senses. In one sense it is irrefutable and logically true. In the second sense it is factually true and falsifiable. Another way of putting this is to say that a single number statement can express two propositions: one of which can be explained on constructivist lines; the other on realist lines.[37]

Philosophy of language Edit

Innovations in the philosophy of language during the 20th century renewed interest in whether mathematics is, as is often said,[citation needed] the language of science. Although some[who?] mathematicians and philosophers would accept the statement "mathematics is a language" (most consider that the language of mathematics is a part of mathematics to which mathematics cannot be reduced),[citation needed] linguists[who?] believe that the implications of such a statement must be considered. For example, the tools of linguistics are not generally applied to the symbol systems of mathematics, that is, mathematics is studied in a markedly different way from other languages. If mathematics is a language, it is a different type of language from natural languages. Indeed, because of the need for clarity and specificity, the language of mathematics is far more constrained than natural languages studied by linguists. However, the methods developed by Frege and Tarski for the study of mathematical language have been extended greatly by Tarski's student Richard Montague and other linguists working in formal semantics to show that the distinction between mathematical language and natural language may not be as great as it seems.

Mohan Ganesalingam has analysed mathematical language using tools from formal linguistics.[38] Ganesalingam notes that some features of natural language are not necessary when analysing mathematical language (such as tense), but many of the same analytical tools can be used (such as context-free grammars). One important difference is that mathematical objects have clearly defined types, which can be explicitly defined in a text: "Effectively, we are allowed to introduce a word in one part of a sentence, and declare its part of speech in another; and this operation has no analogue in natural language."[38]: 251 

Arguments Edit

Indispensability argument for realism Edit

This argument, associated with Willard Quine and Hilary Putnam, is considered by Stephen Yablo to be one of the most challenging arguments in favor of the acceptance of the existence of abstract mathematical entities, such as numbers and sets.[39] The form of the argument is as follows.

  1. One must have ontological commitments to all entities that are indispensable to the best scientific theories, and to those entities only (commonly referred to as "all and only").
  2. Mathematical entities are indispensable to the best scientific theories. Therefore,
  3. One must have ontological commitments to mathematical entities.[40]

The justification for the first premise is the most controversial. Both Putnam and Quine invoke naturalism to justify the exclusion of all non-scientific entities, and hence to defend the "only" part of "all and only". The assertion that "all" entities postulated in scientific theories, including numbers, should be accepted as real is justified by confirmation holism. Since theories are not confirmed in a piecemeal fashion, but as a whole, there is no justification for excluding any of the entities referred to in well-confirmed theories. This puts the nominalist who wishes to exclude the existence of sets and non-Euclidean geometry, but to include the existence of quarks and other undetectable entities of physics, for example, in a difficult position.[40]

Epistemic argument against realism Edit

The anti-realist "epistemic argument" against Platonism has been made by Paul Benacerraf and Hartry Field. Platonism posits that mathematical objects are abstract entities. By general agreement, abstract entities cannot interact causally with concrete, physical entities ("the truth-values of our mathematical assertions depend on facts involving Platonic entities that reside in a realm outside of space-time"[41]). Whilst our knowledge of concrete, physical objects is based on our ability to perceive them, and therefore to causally interact with them, there is no parallel account of how mathematicians come to have knowledge of abstract objects.[42][43][44] Another way of making the point is that if the Platonic world were to disappear, it would make no difference to the ability of mathematicians to generate proofs, etc., which is already fully accountable in terms of physical processes in their brains.

Field developed his views into fictionalism. Benacerraf also developed the philosophy of mathematical structuralism, according to which there are no mathematical objects. Nonetheless, some versions of structuralism are compatible with some versions of realism.

The argument hinges on the idea that a satisfactory naturalistic account of thought processes in terms of brain processes can be given for mathematical reasoning along with everything else. One line of defense is to maintain that this is false, so that mathematical reasoning uses some special intuition that involves contact with the Platonic realm. A modern form of this argument is given by Sir Roger Penrose.[45]

Another line of defense is to maintain that abstract objects are relevant to mathematical reasoning in a way that is non-causal, and not analogous to perception. This argument is developed by Jerrold Katz in his 2000 book Realistic Rationalism.

A more radical defense is denial of physical reality, i.e. the mathematical universe hypothesis. In that case, a mathematician's knowledge of mathematics is one mathematical object making contact with another.

Aesthetics Edit

Many practicing mathematicians have been drawn to their subject because of a sense of beauty they perceive in it. One sometimes hears the sentiment that mathematicians would like to leave philosophy to the philosophers and get back to mathematics—where, presumably, the beauty lies.

In his work on the divine proportion, H.E. Huntley relates the feeling of reading and understanding someone else's proof of a theorem of mathematics to that of a viewer of a masterpiece of art—the reader of a proof has a similar sense of exhilaration at understanding as the original author of the proof, much as, he argues, the viewer of a masterpiece has a sense of exhilaration similar to the original painter or sculptor. Indeed, one can study mathematical and scientific writings as literature.

Philip J. Davis and Reuben Hersh have commented that the sense of mathematical beauty is universal amongst practicing mathematicians. By way of example, they provide two proofs of the irrationality of 2. The first is the traditional proof by contradiction, ascribed to Euclid; the second is a more direct proof involving the fundamental theorem of arithmetic that, they argue, gets to the heart of the issue. Davis and Hersh argue that mathematicians find the second proof more aesthetically appealing because it gets closer to the nature of the problem.

Paul Erdős was well known for his notion of a hypothetical "Book" containing the most elegant or beautiful mathematical proofs. There is not universal agreement that a result has one "most elegant" proof; Gregory Chaitin has argued against this idea.

Philosophers have sometimes criticized mathematicians' sense of beauty or elegance as being, at best, vaguely stated. By the same token, however, philosophers of mathematics have sought to characterize what makes one proof more desirable than another when both are logically sound.

Another aspect of aesthetics concerning mathematics is mathematicians' views towards the possible uses of mathematics for purposes deemed unethical or inappropriate. The best-known exposition of this view occurs in G. H. Hardy's book A Mathematician's Apology, in which Hardy argues that pure mathematics is superior in beauty to applied mathematics precisely because it cannot be used for war and similar ends.

Journals Edit

  • Philosophia Mathematica journal
  • The Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal homepage

See also Edit

Related works Edit

Historical topics Edit

Notes Edit

  1. ^ "Is mathematics discovered or invented?". University of Exeter. from the original on 27 July 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  2. ^ "Math: Discovered, Invented, or Both?". pbs.org. 13 April 2015. from the original on 28 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  3. ^ "Logical Combinators | Stanford University - KeepNotes". keepnotes.com. Retrieved 2023-10-18.
  4. ^ Kleene, Stephen (1971). Introduction to Metamathematics. Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland Publishing Company. p. 5.
  5. ^ Mac Lane, Saunders (1998), Categories for the Working Mathematician, 2nd edition, Springer-Verlag, New York, NY.
  6. ^ *Putnam, Hilary (1967), "Mathematics Without Foundations", Journal of Philosophy 64/1, 5-22. Reprinted, pp. 168–184 in W.D. Hart (ed., 1996).
  7. ^ "A Mathematician's Apology Quotes by G.H. Hardy". from the original on 2021-05-08. Retrieved 2020-07-20.
  8. ^ S, F. (January 1941). "A Mathematician's Apology". Nature. 147 (3714): 3–5. Bibcode:1941Natur.147....3S. doi:10.1038/147003a0. S2CID 4212863.
  9. ^ "Platonism in Metaphysics". Platonism in Metaphysics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2016. from the original on 2019-04-28. Retrieved 2018-08-24.
  10. ^ "Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics". "Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics", (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018. from the original on 2018-11-25. Retrieved 2018-08-17.
  11. ^ Ivor Grattan-Guinness (ed.), Companion Encyclopedia of the History and Philosophy of the Mathematical Sciences, Routledge, 2002, p. 681.
  12. ^ "Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics". Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2016. from the original on 2018-06-11. Retrieved 2018-08-18.
  13. ^ Balaguer, Mark (1994). "Against (Maddian) naturalized Platonism". Philosophia Mathematica. 2 (2): 97–108. doi:10.1093/philmat/2.2.97.
  14. ^ Linsky, B.; Zalta, E. (1995). "Naturalized Platonism vs. Platonized Naturalism". The Journal of Philosophy. 92 (10): 525–555. doi:10.2307/2940786. JSTOR 2940786.
  15. ^ Tegmark, Max (February 2008). "The Mathematical Universe". Foundations of Physics. 38 (2): 101–150. arXiv:0704.0646. Bibcode:2008FoPh...38..101T. doi:10.1007/s10701-007-9186-9. S2CID 9890455.
  16. ^ Tegmark (1998), p. 1.
  17. ^ a b Carnap, Rudolf (1931), "Die logizistische Grundlegung der Mathematik", Erkenntnis 2, 91-121. Republished, "The Logicist Foundations of Mathematics", E. Putnam and G.J. Massey (trans.), in Benacerraf and Putnam (1964). Reprinted, pp. 41–52 in Benacerraf and Putnam (1983).
  18. ^ Zach, Richard (2019), "Hilbert's Program", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, from the original on 2022-02-08, retrieved 2019-05-25
  19. ^ Audi, Robert (1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1995. 2nd edition. Page 542.
  20. ^ Bishop, Errett (2012) [1967], Foundations of Constructive Analysis (Paperback ed.), New York: Ishi Press, ISBN 978-4-87187-714-5
  21. ^ From an 1886 lecture at the 'Berliner Naturforscher-Versammlung', according to H. M. Weber's memorial article, as quoted and translated in Gonzalez Cabillon, Julio (2000-02-03). "FOM: What were Kronecker's f.o.m.?". from the original on 2007-10-09. Retrieved 2008-07-19. Gonzalez gives as the sources for the memorial article, the following: Weber, H: "Leopold Kronecker", Jahresberichte der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung, vol ii (1893), pp. 5-31. Cf. page 19. See also Mathematische Annalen vol. xliii (1893), pp. 1-25.
  22. ^ a b Mayberry, J.P. (2001). The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets. Cambridge University Press.
  23. ^ Brown, James (2008). Philosophy of Mathematics. New York: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-96047-2.
  24. ^ Franklin, James (2014). An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 9781137400727.
  25. ^ Franklin, James (2022). "Mathematics as a science of non-abstract reality: Aristotelian realist philosophies of mathematics". Foundations of Science. 27 (2): 327–344. doi:10.1007/s10699-021-09786-1. S2CID 233658181. Retrieved 30 June 2021.
  26. ^ Maddy, Penelope (1990), Realism in Mathematics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
  27. ^ Ayer, Alfred Jules (1952). Language, Truth, & Logic. New York: Dover Publications, Inc. p. 74 ff. ISBN 978-0-486-20010-1.
  28. ^ Popper, Karl R. (1995). "On knowledge". In Search of a Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years. New York: Routledge. p. 56. Bibcode:1992sbwl.book.....P. ISBN 978-0-415-13548-1.
  29. ^ Popper, Karl (2002) [1959]. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Abingdon-on-Thames: Routledge. p. 18. ISBN 978-0-415-27843-0.
  30. ^ Tymoczko, Thomas (1998), New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics. ISBN 978-0691034980.
  31. ^ Field, Hartry, Science Without Numbers, Blackwell, 1980.
  32. ^ Leng, Mary (2010). Mathematics and Reality. Oxford University Press. p. 239. ISBN 978-0199280797.
  33. ^ Ernest, Paul. "Is Mathematics Discovered or Invented?". University of Exeter. from the original on 2008-04-05. Retrieved 2008-12-26.
  34. ^ Hersh, Reuben (February 10, 1997). (Interview). Interviewed by John Brockman. Edge Foundation. Archived from the original on May 16, 2008. Retrieved 2008-12-26.
  35. ^ "Humanism and Mathematics Education". Math Forum. Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal. from the original on 2008-07-24. Retrieved 2008-12-26.
  36. ^ Popper, Karl Raimund (1946) Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume XX.
  37. ^ Gregory, Frank Hutson (1996) "Arithmetic and Reality: A Development of Popper's Ideas". City University of Hong Kong. Republished in Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal No. 26 (December 2011)
  38. ^ a b Ganesalingam, Mohan (2013). The Language of Mathematics: A Linguistic and Philosophical Investigation. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 7805. Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-37012-0. ISBN 978-3-642-37011-3. S2CID 14260721.
  39. ^ Yablo, S. (November 8, 1998). "A Paradox of Existence". from the original on January 7, 2020. Retrieved August 26, 2019.
  40. ^ a b Putnam, H. Mathematics, Matter and Method. Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975. 2nd. ed., 1985.
  41. ^ Field, Hartry, 1989, Realism, Mathematics, and Modality, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 68
  42. ^ "Since abstract objects are outside the nexus of causes and effects, and thus perceptually inaccessible, they cannot be known through their effects on us" — Katz, J. Realistic Rationalism, 2000, p. 15
  43. ^ . Archived from the original on February 7, 2011.
  44. ^ "Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics". Standard Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018. from the original on 2010-12-04. Retrieved 2011-02-13.
  45. ^ Review 2011-05-14 at the Wayback Machine of The Emperor's New Mind.

Further reading Edit

External links Edit

philosophy, mathematics, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, template, messages, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article. This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Philosophy of mathematics news newspapers books scholar JSTOR April 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message This article s lead section may be too short to adequately summarize the key points Please consider expanding the lead to provide an accessible overview of all important aspects of the article August 2021 The neutrality of this article is disputed Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page Please do not remove this message until conditions to do so are met November 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message This article is missing information about the point of view of notable mathematicians and many important philosophical problems such as the relationship between mathematics and other sciences Please expand the article to include this information Further details may exist on the talk page November 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message The philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the assumptions foundations and implications of mathematics It aims to understand the nature and methods of mathematics and find out the place of mathematics in people s lives The logical and structural nature of mathematics makes this branch of philosophy broad and unique The philosophy of mathematics has two major themes mathematical realism and mathematical anti realism Contents 1 History 1 1 Contemporary philosophy 2 Major themes 2 1 Mathematical realism 2 2 Mathematical anti realism 3 Contemporary schools of thought 3 1 Artistic 3 2 Platonism 3 3 Mathematicism 3 4 Logicism 3 5 Formalism 3 6 Conventionalism 3 7 Intuitionism 3 7 1 Constructivism 3 7 2 Finitism 3 8 Structuralism 3 9 Embodied mind theories 3 9 1 Aristotelian realism 3 9 2 Psychologism 3 9 3 Empiricism 3 10 Fictionalism 3 11 Social constructivism 3 12 Beyond the traditional schools 3 12 1 Unreasonable effectiveness 3 12 2 Popper s two senses of number statements 3 12 3 Philosophy of language 4 Arguments 4 1 Indispensability argument for realism 4 2 Epistemic argument against realism 5 Aesthetics 6 Journals 7 See also 7 1 Related works 7 2 Historical topics 8 Notes 9 Further reading 10 External linksHistory Edit nbsp Pythagoras is considered the father of mathematics and geometry as he set the foundation for Euclid and Euclidean Geometry Pythagoras was the founder of Pythagoreanism a mathematical and philosophical model to map the universe The origin of mathematics is of arguments and disagreements Whether the birth of mathematics was by chance or induced by necessity during the development of similar subjects such as physics remains an area of contention 1 2 Many thinkers have contributed their ideas concerning the nature of mathematics Today some who philosophers of mathematics aim to give accounts of this form of inquiry and its products as they stand while others emphasize a role for themselves that goes beyond simple interpretation to critical analysis There are traditions of mathematical philosophy in both Western philosophy and Eastern philosophy Western philosophies of mathematics go as far back as Pythagoras who described the theory everything is mathematics mathematicism Plato who paraphrased Pythagoras and studied the ontological status of mathematical objects and Aristotle who studied logic and issues related to infinity actual versus potential Greek philosophy on mathematics was strongly influenced by their study of geometry For example at one time the Greeks held the opinion that 1 one was not a number but rather a unit of arbitrary length A number was defined as a multitude Therefore 3 for example represented a certain multitude of units and was thus truly a number At another point a similar argument was made that 2 was not a number but a fundamental notion of a pair These views come from the heavily geometric straight edge and compass viewpoint of the Greeks just as lines drawn in a geometric problem are measured in proportion to the first arbitrarily drawn line so too are the numbers on a number line measured in proportion to the arbitrary first number or one 3 These earlier Greek ideas of numbers were later upended by the discovery of the irrationality of the square root of two Hippasus a disciple of Pythagoras showed that the diagonal of a unit square was incommensurable with its unit length edge in other words he proved there was no existing rational number that accurately depicts the proportion of the diagonal of the unit square to its edge This caused a significant re evaluation of Greek philosophy of mathematics According to legend fellow Pythagoreans were so traumatized by this discovery that they murdered Hippasus to stop him from spreading his heretical idea citation needed Simon Stevin was one of the first in Europe to challenge Greek ideas in the 16th century Beginning with Leibniz the focus shifted strongly to the relationship between mathematics and logic This perspective dominated the philosophy of mathematics through the time of Frege and of Russell but was brought into question by developments in the late 19th and early 20th centuries Contemporary philosophy Edit A perennial issue in the philosophy of mathematics concerns the relationship between logic and mathematics at their joint foundations While 20th century philosophers continued to ask the questions mentioned at the outset of this article the philosophy of mathematics in the 20th century was characterized by a predominant interest in formal logic set theory both naive set theory and axiomatic set theory and foundational issues It is a profound puzzle that on the one hand mathematical truths seem to have a compelling inevitability but on the other hand the source of their truthfulness remains elusive Investigations into this issue are known as the foundations of mathematics program At the start of the 20th century philosophers of mathematics were already beginning to divide into various schools of thought about all these questions broadly distinguished by their pictures of mathematical epistemology and ontology Three schools formalism intuitionism and logicism emerged at this time partly in response to the increasingly widespread worry that mathematics as it stood and analysis in particular did not live up to the standards of certainty and rigor that had been taken for granted Each school addressed the issues that came to the fore at that time either attempting to resolve them or claiming that mathematics is not entitled to its status as our most trusted knowledge Surprising and counter intuitive developments in formal logic and set theory early in the 20th century led to new questions concerning what was traditionally called the foundations of mathematics As the century unfolded the initial focus of concern expanded to an open exploration of the fundamental axioms of mathematics the axiomatic approach having been taken for granted since the time of Euclid around 300 BCE as the natural basis for mathematics Notions of axiom proposition and proof as well as the notion of a proposition being true of a mathematical object see Assignment were formalized allowing them to be treated mathematically The Zermelo Fraenkel axioms for set theory were formulated which provided a conceptual framework in which much mathematical discourse would be interpreted In mathematics as in physics new and unexpected ideas had arisen and significant changes were coming With Godel numbering propositions could be interpreted as referring to themselves or other propositions enabling inquiry into the consistency of mathematical theories This reflective critique in which the theory under review becomes itself the object of a mathematical study led Hilbert to call such study metamathematics or proof theory 4 At the middle of the century a new mathematical theory was created by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane known as category theory and it became a new contender for the natural language of mathematical thinking 5 As the 20th century progressed however philosophical opinions diverged as to just how well founded were the questions about foundations that were raised at the century s beginning Hilary Putnam summed up one common view of the situation in the last third of the century by saying When philosophy discovers something wrong with science sometimes science has to be changed Russell s paradox comes to mind as does Berkeley s attack on the actual infinitesimal but more often it is philosophy that has to be changed I do not think that the difficulties that philosophy finds with classical mathematics today are genuine difficulties and I think that the philosophical interpretations of mathematics that we are being offered on every hand are wrong and that philosophical interpretation is just what mathematics doesn t need 6 169 170 Philosophy of mathematics today proceeds along several different lines of inquiry by philosophers of mathematics logicians and mathematicians and there are many schools of thought on the subject The schools are addressed separately in the next section and their assumptions explained Major themes EditMathematical realism Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2007 Learn how and when to remove this template message Mathematical realism like realism in general holds that mathematical entities exist independently of the human mind Thus humans do not invent mathematics but rather discover it and any other intelligent beings in the universe would presumably do the same In this point of view there is really one sort of mathematics that can be discovered triangles for example are real entities not the creations of the human mind Many working mathematicians have been mathematical realists they see themselves as discoverers of naturally occurring objects Examples include Paul Erdos and Kurt Godel Godel believed in an objective mathematical reality that could be perceived in a manner analogous to sense perception Certain principles e g for any two objects there is a collection of objects consisting of precisely those two objects could be directly seen to be true but the continuum hypothesis conjecture might prove undecidable just on the basis of such principles Godel suggested that quasi empirical methodology could be used to provide sufficient evidence to be able to reasonably assume such a conjecture Within realism there are distinctions depending on what sort of existence one takes mathematical entities to have and how we know about them Major forms of mathematical realism include Platonism and Aristotelianism Mathematical anti realism Edit See also Post rem structuralism Mathematical anti realism generally holds that mathematical statements have truth values but that they do not do so by corresponding to a special realm of immaterial or non empirical entities Major forms of mathematical anti realism include formalism and fictionalism Contemporary schools of thought EditArtistic Edit The view that claims that mathematics is the aesthetic combination of assumptions and then also claims that mathematics is an art A famous mathematician who claims that is the British G H Hardy 7 For Hardy in his book A Mathematician s Apology the definition of mathematics was more like the aesthetic combination of concepts 8 Platonism Edit Main article Platonism See also Modern Platonism Mathematical Platonism is the form of realism that suggests that mathematical entities are abstract have no spatiotemporal or causal properties and are eternal and unchanging This is often claimed to be the view most people have of numbers The term Platonism is used because such a view is seen to parallel Plato s Theory of Forms and a World of Ideas Greek eidos eἶdos described in Plato s allegory of the cave the everyday world can only imperfectly approximate an unchanging ultimate reality Both Plato s cave and Platonism have meaningful not just superficial connections because Plato s ideas were preceded and probably influenced by the hugely popular Pythagoreans of ancient Greece who believed that the world was quite literally generated by numbers A major question considered in mathematical Platonism is Precisely where and how do the mathematical entities exist and how do we know about them Is there a world completely separate from our physical one that is occupied by the mathematical entities How can we gain access to this separate world and discover truths about the entities One proposed answer is the Ultimate Ensemble a theory that postulates that all structures that exist mathematically also exist physically in their own universe nbsp Kurt GodelKurt Godel s Platonism 9 postulates a special kind of mathematical intuition that lets us perceive mathematical objects directly This view bears resemblances to many things Husserl said about mathematics and supports Kant s idea that mathematics is synthetic a priori Davis and Hersh have suggested in their 1999 book The Mathematical Experience that most mathematicians act as though they are Platonists even though if pressed to defend the position carefully they may retreat to formalism Full blooded Platonism is a modern variation of Platonism which is in reaction to the fact that different sets of mathematical entities can be proven to exist depending on the axioms and inference rules employed for instance the law of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice It holds that all mathematical entities exist They may be provable even if they cannot all be derived from a single consistent set of axioms 10 Set theoretic realism also set theoretic Platonism 11 a position defended by Penelope Maddy is the view that set theory is about a single universe of sets 12 This position which is also known as naturalized Platonism because it is a naturalized version of mathematical Platonism has been criticized by Mark Balaguer on the basis of Paul Benacerraf s epistemological problem 13 A similar view termed Platonized naturalism was later defended by the Stanford Edmonton School according to this view a more traditional kind of Platonism is consistent with naturalism the more traditional kind of Platonism they defend is distinguished by general principles that assert the existence of abstract objects 14 Mathematicism Edit Main article Mathematicism Max Tegmark s mathematical universe hypothesis or mathematicism goes further than Platonism in asserting that not only do all mathematical objects exist but nothing else does Tegmark s sole postulate is All structures that exist mathematically also exist physically That is in the sense that in those worlds complex enough to contain self aware substructures they will subjectively perceive themselves as existing in a physically real world 15 16 Logicism Edit Main article Logicism Logicism is the thesis that mathematics is reducible to logic and hence nothing but a part of logic 17 41 Logicists hold that mathematics can be known a priori but suggest that our knowledge of mathematics is just part of our knowledge of logic in general and is thus analytic not requiring any special faculty of mathematical intuition In this view logic is the proper foundation of mathematics and all mathematical statements are necessary logical truths Rudolf Carnap 1931 presents the logicist thesis in two parts 17 The concepts of mathematics can be derived from logical concepts through explicit definitions The theorems of mathematics can be derived from logical axioms through purely logical deduction Gottlob Frege was the founder of logicism In his seminal Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik Basic Laws of Arithmetic he built up arithmetic from a system of logic with a general principle of comprehension which he called Basic Law V for concepts F and G the extension of F equals the extension of G if and only if for all objects a Fa equals Ga a principle that he took to be acceptable as part of logic nbsp Bertrand RussellFrege s construction was flawed Bertrand Russell discovered that Basic Law V is inconsistent this is Russell s paradox Frege abandoned his logicist program soon after this but it was continued by Russell and Whitehead They attributed the paradox to vicious circularity and built up what they called ramified type theory to deal with it In this system they were eventually able to build up much of modern mathematics but in an altered and excessively complex form for example there were different natural numbers in each type and there were infinitely many types They also had to make several compromises in order to develop much of mathematics such as the axiom of reducibility Even Russell said that this axiom did not really belong to logic Modern logicists like Bob Hale Crispin Wright and perhaps others have returned to a program closer to Frege s They have abandoned Basic Law V in favor of abstraction principles such as Hume s principle the number of objects falling under the concept F equals the number of objects falling under the concept G if and only if the extension of F and the extension of G can be put into one to one correspondence Frege required Basic Law V to be able to give an explicit definition of the numbers but all the properties of numbers can be derived from Hume s principle This would not have been enough for Frege because to paraphrase him it does not exclude the possibility that the number 3 is in fact Julius Caesar In addition many of the weakened principles that they have had to adopt to replace Basic Law V no longer seem so obviously analytic and thus purely logical Formalism Edit Main article Formalism philosophy of mathematics Formalism holds that mathematical statements may be thought of as statements about the consequences of certain string manipulation rules For example in the game of Euclidean geometry which is seen as consisting of some strings called axioms and some rules of inference to generate new strings from given ones one can prove that the Pythagorean theorem holds that is one can generate the string corresponding to the Pythagorean theorem According to formalism mathematical truths are not about numbers and sets and triangles and the like in fact they are not about anything at all Another version of formalism is often known as deductivism In deductivism the Pythagorean theorem is not an absolute truth but a relative one if one assigns meaning to the strings in such a way that the rules of the game become true i e true statements are assigned to the axioms and the rules of inference are truth preserving then one must accept the theorem or rather the interpretation one has given it must be a true statement The same is held to be true for all other mathematical statements Thus formalism need not mean that mathematics is nothing more than a meaningless symbolic game It is usually hoped that there exists some interpretation in which the rules of the game hold Compare this position to structuralism But it does allow the working mathematician to continue in his or her work and leave such problems to the philosopher or scientist Many formalists would say that in practice the axiom systems to be studied will be suggested by the demands of science or other areas of mathematics nbsp David HilbertA major early proponent of formalism was David Hilbert whose program was intended to be a complete and consistent axiomatization of all of mathematics 18 Hilbert aimed to show the consistency of mathematical systems from the assumption that the finitary arithmetic a subsystem of the usual arithmetic of the positive integers chosen to be philosophically uncontroversial was consistent Hilbert s goals of creating a system of mathematics that is both complete and consistent were seriously undermined by the second of Godel s incompleteness theorems which states that sufficiently expressive consistent axiom systems can never prove their own consistency Since any such axiom system would contain the finitary arithmetic as a subsystem Godel s theorem implied that it would be impossible to prove the system s consistency relative to that since it would then prove its own consistency which Godel had shown was impossible Thus in order to show that any axiomatic system of mathematics is in fact consistent one needs to first assume the consistency of a system of mathematics that is in a sense stronger than the system to be proven consistent Hilbert was initially a deductivist but as may be clear from above he considered certain metamathematical methods to yield intrinsically meaningful results and was a realist with respect to the finitary arithmetic Later he held the opinion that there was no other meaningful mathematics whatsoever regardless of interpretation Other formalists such as Rudolf Carnap Alfred Tarski and Haskell Curry considered mathematics to be the investigation of formal axiom systems Mathematical logicians study formal systems but are just as often realists as they are formalists Formalists are relatively tolerant and inviting to new approaches to logic non standard number systems new set theories etc The more games we study the better However in all three of these examples motivation is drawn from existing mathematical or philosophical concerns The games are usually not arbitrary The main critique of formalism is that the actual mathematical ideas that occupy mathematicians are far removed from the string manipulation games mentioned above Formalism is thus silent on the question of which axiom systems ought to be studied as none is more meaningful than another from a formalistic point of view Recently some who formalist mathematicians have proposed that all of our formal mathematical knowledge should be systematically encoded in computer readable formats so as to facilitate automated proof checking of mathematical proofs and the use of interactive theorem proving in the development of mathematical theories and computer software Because of their close connection with computer science this idea is also advocated by mathematical intuitionists and constructivists in the computability tradition see QED project for a general overview Conventionalism Edit Main articles Conventionalism and Preintuitionism The French mathematician Henri Poincare was among the first to articulate a conventionalist view Poincare s use of non Euclidean geometries in his work on differential equations convinced him that Euclidean geometry should not be regarded as a priori truth He held that axioms in geometry should be chosen for the results they produce not for their apparent coherence with human intuitions about the physical world Intuitionism Edit Main article Mathematical intuitionism In mathematics intuitionism is a program of methodological reform whose motto is that there are no non experienced mathematical truths L E J Brouwer From this springboard intuitionists seek to reconstruct what they consider to be the corrigible portion of mathematics in accordance with Kantian concepts of being becoming intuition and knowledge Brouwer the founder of the movement held that mathematical objects arise from the a priori forms of the volitions that inform the perception of empirical objects 19 A major force behind intuitionism was L E J Brouwer who rejected the usefulness of formalized logic of any sort for mathematics His student Arend Heyting postulated an intuitionistic logic different from the classical Aristotelian logic this logic does not contain the law of the excluded middle and therefore frowns upon proofs by contradiction The axiom of choice is also rejected in most intuitionistic set theories though in some versions it is accepted In intuitionism the term explicit construction is not cleanly defined and that has led to criticisms Attempts have been made to use the concepts of Turing machine or computable function to fill this gap leading to the claim that only questions regarding the behavior of finite algorithms are meaningful and should be investigated in mathematics This has led to the study of the computable numbers first introduced by Alan Turing Not surprisingly then this approach to mathematics is sometimes associated with theoretical computer science Constructivism Edit Main article Constructivism philosophy of mathematics Like intuitionism constructivism involves the regulative principle that only mathematical entities which can be explicitly constructed in a certain sense should be admitted to mathematical discourse In this view mathematics is an exercise of the human intuition not a game played with meaningless symbols Instead it is about entities that we can create directly through mental activity In addition some adherents of these schools reject non constructive proofs such as using proof by contradiction when showing the existence of an object or when trying to establish the truth of some proposition Important work was done by Errett Bishop who managed to prove versions of the most important theorems in real analysis as constructive analysis in his 1967 Foundations of Constructive Analysis 20 Finitism Edit Main article Finitism nbsp Leopold KroneckerFinitism is an extreme form of constructivism according to which a mathematical object does not exist unless it can be constructed from natural numbers in a finite number of steps In her book Philosophy of Set Theory Mary Tiles characterized those who allow countably infinite objects as classical finitists and those who deny even countably infinite objects as strict finitists The most famous proponent of finitism was Leopold Kronecker 21 who said God created the natural numbers all else is the work of man Ultrafinitism is an even more extreme version of finitism which rejects not only infinities but finite quantities that cannot feasibly be constructed with available resources Another variant of finitism is Euclidean arithmetic a system developed by John Penn Mayberry in his book The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets 22 Mayberry s system is Aristotelian in general inspiration and despite his strong rejection of any role for operationalism or feasibility in the foundations of mathematics comes to somewhat similar conclusions such as for instance that super exponentiation is not a legitimate finitary function Structuralism Edit Main article Mathematical structuralism Structuralism is a position holding that mathematical theories describe structures and that mathematical objects are exhaustively defined by their places in such structures consequently having no intrinsic properties For instance it would maintain that all that needs to be known about the number 1 is that it is the first whole number after 0 Likewise all the other whole numbers are defined by their places in a structure the number line Other examples of mathematical objects might include lines and planes in geometry or elements and operations in abstract algebra Structuralism is an epistemologically realistic view in that it holds that mathematical statements have an objective truth value However its central claim only relates to what kind of entity a mathematical object is not to what kind of existence mathematical objects or structures have not in other words to their ontology The kind of existence mathematical objects have would clearly be dependent on that of the structures in which they are embedded different sub varieties of structuralism make different ontological claims in this regard 23 The ante rem structuralism before the thing has a similar ontology to Platonism Structures are held to have a real but abstract and immaterial existence As such it faces the standard epistemological problem of explaining the interaction between such abstract structures and flesh and blood mathematicians see Benacerraf s identification problem The in re structuralism in the thing is the equivalent of Aristotelian realism Structures are held to exist inasmuch as some concrete system exemplifies them This incurs the usual issues that some perfectly legitimate structures might accidentally happen not to exist and that a finite physical world might not be big enough to accommodate some otherwise legitimate structures The post rem structuralism after the thing is anti realist about structures in a way that parallels nominalism Like nominalism the post rem approach denies the existence of abstract mathematical objects with properties other than their place in a relational structure According to this view mathematical systems exist and have structural features in common If something is true of a structure it will be true of all systems exemplifying the structure However it is merely instrumental to talk of structures being held in common between systems they in fact have no independent existence Embodied mind theories Edit Embodied mind theories hold that mathematical thought is a natural outgrowth of the human cognitive apparatus which finds itself in our physical universe For example the abstract concept of number springs from the experience of counting discrete objects requiring the human senses such as sight for detecting the objects touch and signalling from the brain It is held that mathematics is not universal and does not exist in any real sense other than in human brains Humans construct but do not discover mathematics The cognitive processes of pattern finding and distinguishing objects are also subject to neuroscience if mathematics is considered to be relevant to a natural world such as from realism or a degree of it as opposed to pure solipsism Its actual relevance to reality while accepted to be a trustworthy approximation it is also suggested the evolution of perceptions the body and the senses may have been necessary for survival is not necessarily accurate to a full realism and is still subject to flaws such as illusion assumptions consequently the foundations and axioms in which mathematics have been formed by humans generalisations deception and hallucinations As such this may also raise questions for the modern scientific method for its compatibility with general mathematics as while relatively reliable it is still limited by what can be measured by empiricism which may not be as reliable as previously assumed see also counterintuitive concepts in such as quantum nonlocality and action at a distance Another issue is that one numeral system may not necessarily be applicable to problem solving Subjects such as complex numbers or imaginary numbers require specific changes to more commonly used axioms of mathematics otherwise they cannot be adequately understood Alternatively computer programmers may use hexadecimal for its human friendly representation of binary coded values rather than decimal convenient for counting because humans have ten fingers The axioms or logical rules behind mathematics also vary through time such as the adaption and invention of zero As perceptions from the human brain are subject to illusions assumptions deceptions induced hallucinations cognitive errors or assumptions in a general context it can be questioned whether they are accurate or strictly indicative of truth see also philosophy of being and the nature of empiricism itself in relation to the universe and whether it is independent to the senses and the universe The human mind has no special claim on reality or approaches to it built out of math If such constructs as Euler s identity are true then they are true as a map of the human mind and cognition Embodied mind theorists thus explain the effectiveness of mathematics mathematics was constructed by the brain in order to be effective in this universe The most accessible famous and infamous treatment of this perspective is Where Mathematics Comes From by George Lakoff and Rafael E Nunez In addition mathematician Keith Devlin has investigated similar concepts with his book The Math Instinct as has neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene with his book The Number Sense For more on the philosophical ideas that inspired this perspective see cognitive science of mathematics Aristotelian realism Edit Main article Aristotelian realist philosophy of mathematics See also In re structuralism and Immanent realism Aristotelian realism holds that mathematics studies properties such as symmetry continuity and order that can be literally realized in the physical world or in any other world there might be It contrasts with Platonism in holding that the objects of mathematics such as numbers do not exist in an abstract world but can be physically realized For example the number 4 is realized in the relation between a heap of parrots and the universal being a parrot that divides the heap into so many parrots 24 25 Aristotelian realism is defended by James Franklin and the Sydney School in the philosophy of mathematics and is close to the view of Penelope Maddy that when an egg carton is opened a set of three eggs is perceived that is a mathematical entity realized in the physical world 26 A problem for Aristotelian realism is what account to give of higher infinities which may not be realizable in the physical world The Euclidean arithmetic developed by John Penn Mayberry in his book The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets 22 also falls into the Aristotelian realist tradition Mayberry following Euclid considers numbers to be simply definite multitudes of units realized in nature such as the members of the London Symphony Orchestra or the trees in Birnam wood Whether or not there are definite multitudes of units for which Euclid s Common Notion 5 the whole is greater than the part fails and which would consequently be reckoned as infinite is for Mayberry essentially a question about Nature and does not entail any transcendental suppositions Psychologism Edit Main article Psychologism See also Anti psychologism Psychologism in the philosophy of mathematics is the position that mathematical concepts and or truths are grounded in derived from or explained by psychological facts or laws John Stuart Mill seems to have been an advocate of a type of logical psychologism as were many 19th century German logicians such as Sigwart and Erdmann as well as a number of psychologists past and present for example Gustave Le Bon Psychologism was famously criticized by Frege in his The Foundations of Arithmetic and many of his works and essays including his review of Husserl s Philosophy of Arithmetic Edmund Husserl in the first volume of his Logical Investigations called The Prolegomena of Pure Logic criticized psychologism thoroughly and sought to distance himself from it The Prolegomena is considered a more concise fair and thorough refutation of psychologism than the criticisms made by Frege and also it is considered today by many as being a memorable refutation for its decisive blow to psychologism Psychologism was also criticized by Charles Sanders Peirce and Maurice Merleau Ponty Empiricism Edit Main articles Quasi empiricism in mathematics and Postmodern mathematics Mathematical empiricism is a form of realism that denies that mathematics can be known a priori at all It says that we discover mathematical facts by empirical research just like facts in any of the other sciences It is not one of the classical three positions advocated in the early 20th century but primarily arose in the middle of the century However an important early proponent of a view like this was John Stuart Mill Mill s view was widely criticized because according to critics such as A J Ayer 27 it makes statements like 2 2 4 come out as uncertain contingent truths which we can only learn by observing instances of two pairs coming together and forming a quartet Karl Popper was another philosopher to point out empirical aspects of mathematics observing that most mathematical theories are like those of physics and biology hypothetico deductive pure mathematics therefore turns out to be much closer to the natural sciences whose hypotheses are conjectures than it seemed even recently 28 Popper also noted he would admit a system as empirical or scientific only if it is capable of being tested by experience 29 Contemporary mathematical empiricism formulated by W V O Quine and Hilary Putnam is primarily supported by the indispensability argument mathematics is indispensable to all empirical sciences and if we want to believe in the reality of the phenomena described by the sciences we ought also believe in the reality of those entities required for this description That is since physics needs to talk about electrons to say why light bulbs behave as they do then electrons must exist Since physics needs to talk about numbers in offering any of its explanations then numbers must exist In keeping with Quine and Putnam s overall philosophies this is a naturalistic argument It argues for the existence of mathematical entities as the best explanation for experience thus stripping mathematics of being distinct from the other sciences Putnam strongly rejected the term Platonist as implying an over specific ontology that was not necessary to mathematical practice in any real sense He advocated a form of pure realism that rejected mystical notions of truth and accepted much quasi empiricism in mathematics This grew from the increasingly popular assertion in the late 20th century that no one foundation of mathematics could be ever proven to exist It is also sometimes called postmodernism in mathematics although that term is considered overloaded by some and insulting by others Quasi empiricism argues that in doing their research mathematicians test hypotheses as well as prove theorems A mathematical argument can transmit falsity from the conclusion to the premises just as well as it can transmit truth from the premises to the conclusion Putnam has argued that any theory of mathematical realism would include quasi empirical methods He proposed that an alien species doing mathematics might well rely on quasi empirical methods primarily being willing often to forgo rigorous and axiomatic proofs and still be doing mathematics at perhaps a somewhat greater risk of failure of their calculations He gave a detailed argument for this in New Directions 30 Quasi empiricism was also developed by Imre Lakatos The most important criticism of empirical views of mathematics is approximately the same as that raised against Mill If mathematics is just as empirical as the other sciences then this suggests that its results are just as fallible as theirs and just as contingent In Mill s case the empirical justification comes directly while in Quine s case it comes indirectly through the coherence of our scientific theory as a whole i e consilience after E O Wilson Quine suggests that mathematics seems completely certain because the role it plays in our web of belief is extraordinarily central and that it would be extremely difficult for us to revise it though not impossible For a philosophy of mathematics that attempts to overcome some of the shortcomings of Quine and Godel s approaches by taking aspects of each see Penelope Maddy s Realism in Mathematics Another example of a realist theory is the embodied mind theory For experimental evidence suggesting that human infants can do elementary arithmetic see Brian Butterworth Fictionalism Edit See also Fictionalism Mathematical fictionalism was brought to fame in 1980 when Hartry Field published Science Without Numbers 31 which rejected and in fact reversed Quine s indispensability argument Where Quine suggested that mathematics was indispensable for our best scientific theories and therefore should be accepted as a body of truths talking about independently existing entities Field suggested that mathematics was dispensable and therefore should be considered as a body of falsehoods not talking about anything real He did this by giving a complete axiomatization of Newtonian mechanics with no reference to numbers or functions at all He started with the betweenness of Hilbert s axioms to characterize space without coordinatizing it and then added extra relations between points to do the work formerly done by vector fields Hilbert s geometry is mathematical because it talks about abstract points but in Field s theory these points are the concrete points of physical space so no special mathematical objects at all are needed Having shown how to do science without using numbers Field proceeded to rehabilitate mathematics as a kind of useful fiction He showed that mathematical physics is a conservative extension of his non mathematical physics that is every physical fact provable in mathematical physics is already provable from Field s system so that mathematics is a reliable process whose physical applications are all true even though its own statements are false Thus when doing mathematics we can see ourselves as telling a sort of story talking as if numbers existed For Field a statement like 2 2 4 is just as fictitious as Sherlock Holmes lived at 221B Baker Street but both are true according to the relevant fictions Another fictionalist Mary Leng expresses the perspective succinctly by dismissing any seeming connection between mathematics and the physical world as a happy coincidence This rejection separates fictionalism from other forms of anti realism which see mathematics itself as artificial but still bounded or fitted to reality in some way 32 By this account there are no metaphysical or epistemological problems special to mathematics The only worries left are the general worries about non mathematical physics and about fiction in general Field s approach has been very influential but is widely rejected This is in part because of the requirement of strong fragments of second order logic to carry out his reduction and because the statement of conservativity seems to require quantification over abstract models or deductions citation needed Social constructivism Edit Main article Social constructivism Social constructivism sees mathematics primarily as a social construct as a product of culture subject to correction and change Like the other sciences mathematics is viewed as an empirical endeavor whose results are constantly evaluated and may be discarded However while on an empiricist view the evaluation is some sort of comparison with reality social constructivists emphasize that the direction of mathematical research is dictated by the fashions of the social group performing it or by the needs of the society financing it However although such external forces may change the direction of some mathematical research there are strong internal constraints the mathematical traditions methods problems meanings and values into which mathematicians are enculturated that work to conserve the historically defined discipline This runs counter to the traditional beliefs of working mathematicians that mathematics is somehow pure or objective But social constructivists argue that mathematics is in fact grounded by much uncertainty as mathematical practice evolves the status of previous mathematics is cast into doubt and is corrected to the degree it is required or desired by the current mathematical community This can be seen in the development of analysis from reexamination of the calculus of Leibniz and Newton They argue further that finished mathematics is often accorded too much status and folk mathematics not enough due to an overemphasis on axiomatic proof and peer review as practices The social nature of mathematics is highlighted in its subcultures Major discoveries can be made in one branch of mathematics and be relevant to another yet the relationship goes undiscovered for lack of social contact between mathematicians Social constructivists argue each speciality forms its own epistemic community and often has great difficulty communicating or motivating the investigation of unifying conjectures that might relate different areas of mathematics Social constructivists see the process of doing mathematics as actually creating the meaning while social realists see a deficiency either of human capacity to abstractify or of human s cognitive bias or of mathematicians collective intelligence as preventing the comprehension of a real universe of mathematical objects Social constructivists sometimes reject the search for foundations of mathematics as bound to fail as pointless or even meaningless Contributions to this school have been made by Imre Lakatos and Thomas Tymoczko although it is not clear that either would endorse the title clarification needed More recently Paul Ernest has explicitly formulated a social constructivist philosophy of mathematics 33 Some consider the work of Paul Erdos as a whole to have advanced this view although he personally rejected it because of his uniquely broad collaborations which prompted others to see and study mathematics as a social activity e g via the Erdos number Reuben Hersh has also promoted the social view of mathematics calling it a humanistic approach 34 similar to but not quite the same as that associated with Alvin White 35 one of Hersh s co authors Philip J Davis has expressed sympathy for the social view as well Beyond the traditional schools Edit Unreasonable effectiveness Edit Rather than focus on narrow debates about the true nature of mathematical truth or even on practices unique to mathematicians such as the proof a growing movement from the 1960s to the 1990s began to question the idea of seeking foundations or finding any one right answer to why mathematics works The starting point for this was Eugene Wigner s famous 1960 paper The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences in which he argued that the happy coincidence of mathematics and physics being so well matched seemed to be unreasonable and hard to explain Popper s two senses of number statements Edit Realist and constructivist theories are normally taken to be contraries However Karl Popper 36 argued that a number statement such as 2 apples 2 apples 4 apples can be taken in two senses In one sense it is irrefutable and logically true In the second sense it is factually true and falsifiable Another way of putting this is to say that a single number statement can express two propositions one of which can be explained on constructivist lines the other on realist lines 37 Philosophy of language Edit This section possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Innovations in the philosophy of language during the 20th century renewed interest in whether mathematics is as is often said citation needed the language of science Although some who mathematicians and philosophers would accept the statement mathematics is a language most consider that the language of mathematics is a part of mathematics to which mathematics cannot be reduced citation needed linguists who believe that the implications of such a statement must be considered For example the tools of linguistics are not generally applied to the symbol systems of mathematics that is mathematics is studied in a markedly different way from other languages If mathematics is a language it is a different type of language from natural languages Indeed because of the need for clarity and specificity the language of mathematics is far more constrained than natural languages studied by linguists However the methods developed by Frege and Tarski for the study of mathematical language have been extended greatly by Tarski s student Richard Montague and other linguists working in formal semantics to show that the distinction between mathematical language and natural language may not be as great as it seems Mohan Ganesalingam has analysed mathematical language using tools from formal linguistics 38 Ganesalingam notes that some features of natural language are not necessary when analysing mathematical language such as tense but many of the same analytical tools can be used such as context free grammars One important difference is that mathematical objects have clearly defined types which can be explicitly defined in a text Effectively we are allowed to introduce a word in one part of a sentence and declare its part of speech in another and this operation has no analogue in natural language 38 251 Arguments EditIndispensability argument for realism Edit Main article Quine Putnam indispensability argument This argument associated with Willard Quine and Hilary Putnam is considered by Stephen Yablo to be one of the most challenging arguments in favor of the acceptance of the existence of abstract mathematical entities such as numbers and sets 39 The form of the argument is as follows One must have ontological commitments to all entities that are indispensable to the best scientific theories and to those entities only commonly referred to as all and only Mathematical entities are indispensable to the best scientific theories Therefore One must have ontological commitments to mathematical entities 40 The justification for the first premise is the most controversial Both Putnam and Quine invoke naturalism to justify the exclusion of all non scientific entities and hence to defend the only part of all and only The assertion that all entities postulated in scientific theories including numbers should be accepted as real is justified by confirmation holism Since theories are not confirmed in a piecemeal fashion but as a whole there is no justification for excluding any of the entities referred to in well confirmed theories This puts the nominalist who wishes to exclude the existence of sets and non Euclidean geometry but to include the existence of quarks and other undetectable entities of physics for example in a difficult position 40 Epistemic argument against realism Edit The anti realist epistemic argument against Platonism has been made by Paul Benacerraf and Hartry Field Platonism posits that mathematical objects are abstract entities By general agreement abstract entities cannot interact causally with concrete physical entities the truth values of our mathematical assertions depend on facts involving Platonic entities that reside in a realm outside of space time 41 Whilst our knowledge of concrete physical objects is based on our ability to perceive them and therefore to causally interact with them there is no parallel account of how mathematicians come to have knowledge of abstract objects 42 43 44 Another way of making the point is that if the Platonic world were to disappear it would make no difference to the ability of mathematicians to generate proofs etc which is already fully accountable in terms of physical processes in their brains Field developed his views into fictionalism Benacerraf also developed the philosophy of mathematical structuralism according to which there are no mathematical objects Nonetheless some versions of structuralism are compatible with some versions of realism The argument hinges on the idea that a satisfactory naturalistic account of thought processes in terms of brain processes can be given for mathematical reasoning along with everything else One line of defense is to maintain that this is false so that mathematical reasoning uses some special intuition that involves contact with the Platonic realm A modern form of this argument is given by Sir Roger Penrose 45 Another line of defense is to maintain that abstract objects are relevant to mathematical reasoning in a way that is non causal and not analogous to perception This argument is developed by Jerrold Katz in his 2000 book Realistic Rationalism A more radical defense is denial of physical reality i e the mathematical universe hypothesis In that case a mathematician s knowledge of mathematics is one mathematical object making contact with another Aesthetics EditThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed November 2015 Learn how and when to remove this template message Many practicing mathematicians have been drawn to their subject because of a sense of beauty they perceive in it One sometimes hears the sentiment that mathematicians would like to leave philosophy to the philosophers and get back to mathematics where presumably the beauty lies In his work on the divine proportion H E Huntley relates the feeling of reading and understanding someone else s proof of a theorem of mathematics to that of a viewer of a masterpiece of art the reader of a proof has a similar sense of exhilaration at understanding as the original author of the proof much as he argues the viewer of a masterpiece has a sense of exhilaration similar to the original painter or sculptor Indeed one can study mathematical and scientific writings as literature Philip J Davis and Reuben Hersh have commented that the sense of mathematical beauty is universal amongst practicing mathematicians By way of example they provide two proofs of the irrationality of 2 The first is the traditional proof by contradiction ascribed to Euclid the second is a more direct proof involving the fundamental theorem of arithmetic that they argue gets to the heart of the issue Davis and Hersh argue that mathematicians find the second proof more aesthetically appealing because it gets closer to the nature of the problem Paul Erdos was well known for his notion of a hypothetical Book containing the most elegant or beautiful mathematical proofs There is not universal agreement that a result has one most elegant proof Gregory Chaitin has argued against this idea Philosophers have sometimes criticized mathematicians sense of beauty or elegance as being at best vaguely stated By the same token however philosophers of mathematics have sought to characterize what makes one proof more desirable than another when both are logically sound Another aspect of aesthetics concerning mathematics is mathematicians views towards the possible uses of mathematics for purposes deemed unethical or inappropriate The best known exposition of this view occurs in G H Hardy s book A Mathematician s Apology in which Hardy argues that pure mathematics is superior in beauty to applied mathematics precisely because it cannot be used for war and similar ends Journals EditPhilosophia Mathematica journal The Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal homepageSee also Edit nbsp Mathematics portal nbsp Philosophy portalDefinitions of mathematics Formal language Foundations of mathematics Golden ratio Model theory Non standard analysis Philosophy of language Philosophy of logic Philosophy of science Philosophy of physics Philosophy of probability Rule of inference Science studies Scientific method Related works Edit The Analyst Euclid s Elements On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems On Computable Numbers with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy New Foundations for Mathematical Logic Principia Mathematica The Simplest Mathematics Historical topics Edit History and philosophy of science History of mathematics History of philosophyNotes Edit Is mathematics discovered or invented University of Exeter Archived from the original on 27 July 2018 Retrieved 28 March 2018 Math Discovered Invented or Both pbs org 13 April 2015 Archived from the original on 28 March 2018 Retrieved 28 March 2018 Logical Combinators Stanford University KeepNotes keepnotes com Retrieved 2023 10 18 Kleene Stephen 1971 Introduction to Metamathematics Amsterdam Netherlands North Holland Publishing Company p 5 Mac Lane Saunders 1998 Categories for the Working Mathematician 2nd edition Springer Verlag New York NY Putnam Hilary 1967 Mathematics Without Foundations Journal of Philosophy 64 1 5 22 Reprinted pp 168 184 in W D Hart ed 1996 A Mathematician s Apology Quotes by G H Hardy Archived from the original on 2021 05 08 Retrieved 2020 07 20 S F January 1941 A Mathematician s Apology Nature 147 3714 3 5 Bibcode 1941Natur 147 3S doi 10 1038 147003a0 S2CID 4212863 Platonism in Metaphysics Platonism in Metaphysics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2016 Archived from the original on 2019 04 28 Retrieved 2018 08 24 Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2018 Archived from the original on 2018 11 25 Retrieved 2018 08 17 Ivor Grattan Guinness ed Companion Encyclopedia of the History and Philosophy of the Mathematical Sciences Routledge 2002 p 681 Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2016 Archived from the original on 2018 06 11 Retrieved 2018 08 18 Balaguer Mark 1994 Against Maddian naturalized Platonism Philosophia Mathematica 2 2 97 108 doi 10 1093 philmat 2 2 97 Linsky B Zalta E 1995 Naturalized Platonism vs Platonized Naturalism The Journal of Philosophy 92 10 525 555 doi 10 2307 2940786 JSTOR 2940786 Tegmark Max February 2008 The Mathematical Universe Foundations of Physics 38 2 101 150 arXiv 0704 0646 Bibcode 2008FoPh 38 101T doi 10 1007 s10701 007 9186 9 S2CID 9890455 Tegmark 1998 p 1 a b Carnap Rudolf 1931 Die logizistische Grundlegung der Mathematik Erkenntnis 2 91 121 Republished The Logicist Foundations of Mathematics E Putnam and G J Massey trans in Benacerraf and Putnam 1964 Reprinted pp 41 52 in Benacerraf and Putnam 1983 Zach Richard 2019 Hilbert s Program in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University archived from the original on 2022 02 08 retrieved 2019 05 25 Audi Robert 1999 The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Cambridge University Press Cambridge UK 1995 2nd edition Page 542 Bishop Errett 2012 1967 Foundations of Constructive Analysis Paperback ed New York Ishi Press ISBN 978 4 87187 714 5 From an 1886 lecture at the Berliner Naturforscher Versammlung according to H M Weber s memorial article as quoted and translated in Gonzalez Cabillon Julio 2000 02 03 FOM What were Kronecker s f o m Archived from the original on 2007 10 09 Retrieved 2008 07 19 Gonzalez gives as the sources for the memorial article the following Weber H Leopold Kronecker Jahresberichte der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung vol ii 1893 pp 5 31 Cf page 19 See also Mathematische Annalen vol xliii 1893 pp 1 25 a b Mayberry J P 2001 The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets Cambridge University Press Brown James 2008 Philosophy of Mathematics New York Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 96047 2 Franklin James 2014 An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 9781137400727 Franklin James 2022 Mathematics as a science of non abstract reality Aristotelian realist philosophies of mathematics Foundations of Science 27 2 327 344 doi 10 1007 s10699 021 09786 1 S2CID 233658181 Retrieved 30 June 2021 Maddy Penelope 1990 Realism in Mathematics Oxford University Press Oxford UK Ayer Alfred Jules 1952 Language Truth amp Logic New York Dover Publications Inc p 74 ff ISBN 978 0 486 20010 1 Popper Karl R 1995 On knowledge In Search of a Better World Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years New York Routledge p 56 Bibcode 1992sbwl book P ISBN 978 0 415 13548 1 Popper Karl 2002 1959 The Logic of Scientific Discovery Abingdon on Thames Routledge p 18 ISBN 978 0 415 27843 0 Tymoczko Thomas 1998 New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics ISBN 978 0691034980 Field Hartry Science Without Numbers Blackwell 1980 Leng Mary 2010 Mathematics and Reality Oxford University Press p 239 ISBN 978 0199280797 Ernest Paul Is Mathematics Discovered or Invented University of Exeter Archived from the original on 2008 04 05 Retrieved 2008 12 26 Hersh Reuben February 10 1997 What Kind of a Thing is a Number Interview Interviewed by John Brockman Edge Foundation Archived from the original on May 16 2008 Retrieved 2008 12 26 Humanism and Mathematics Education Math Forum Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal Archived from the original on 2008 07 24 Retrieved 2008 12 26 Popper Karl Raimund 1946 Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume XX Gregory Frank Hutson 1996 Arithmetic and Reality A Development of Popper s Ideas City University of Hong Kong Republished in Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal No 26 December 2011 a b Ganesalingam Mohan 2013 The Language of Mathematics A Linguistic and Philosophical Investigation Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 7805 Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 642 37012 0 ISBN 978 3 642 37011 3 S2CID 14260721 Yablo S November 8 1998 A Paradox of Existence Archived from the original on January 7 2020 Retrieved August 26 2019 a b Putnam H Mathematics Matter and Method Philosophical Papers vol 1 Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1975 2nd ed 1985 Field Hartry 1989 Realism Mathematics and Modality Oxford Blackwell p 68 Since abstract objects are outside the nexus of causes and effects and thus perceptually inaccessible they cannot be known through their effects on us Katz J Realistic Rationalism 2000 p 15 Philosophy Now Mathematical Knowledge A dilemma Archived from the original on February 7 2011 Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics Standard Encyclopaedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2018 Archived from the original on 2010 12 04 Retrieved 2011 02 13 Review Archived 2011 05 14 at the Wayback Machine of The Emperor s New Mind Further reading EditThis further reading section may contain inappropriate or excessive suggestions that may not follow Wikipedia s guidelines Please ensure that only a reasonable number of balanced topical reliable and notable further reading suggestions are given removing less relevant or redundant publications with the same point of view where appropriate Consider utilising appropriate texts as inline sources or creating a separate bibliography article August 2010 Learn how and when to remove this template message Aristotle Prior Analytics Hugh Tredennick trans pp 181 531 in Aristotle Volume 1 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London UK 1938 Benacerraf Paul Putnam Hilary eds 1983 Philosophy of Mathematics Selected Readings 2nd ed Cambridge University Press ISBN 9781107268135 Berkeley George 1734 The Analyst or a Discourse Addressed to an Infidel Mathematician Wherein It is examined whether the Object Principles and Inferences of the modern Analysis are more distinctly conceived or more evidently deduced than Religious Mysteries and Points of Faith London amp Dublin Online text David R Wilkins ed Eprint Bourbaki N 2013 1994 Elements of the History of Mathematics Translated by Meldrum John Springer ISBN 9783642616938 OCLC 1076247011 Chandrasekhar Subrahmanyan 1987 Truth and Beauty Aesthetics and Motivations in Science University of Chicago Press ISBN 9780226100876 OCLC 1023891429 Colyvan Mark 2004 Indispensability Arguments in the Philosophy of Mathematics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Edward N Zalta ed Eprint Davis Philip J Hersh Reuben 1981 The Mathematical Experience Mariner Books Devlin Keith 2005 The Math Instinct Why You re a Mathematical Genius Along with Lobsters Birds Cats and Dogs Thunder s Mouth Press ISBN 9781560256724 OCLC 636363534 Dummett Michael 1991 Frege Philosophy of Mathematics Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674319356 Dummett Michael 1991 Frege and Other Philosophers Oxford University Press ISBN 9780191520051 Dummett Michael 1993 Origins of Analytical Philosophy Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674644724 Ernest Paul 1998 Social Constructivism as a Philosophy of Mathematics State University of New York Press ISBN 9780791435885 George Alexandre ed 1994 Mathematics and Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195079296 Hadamard Jacques 1954 The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field 2nd ed Dover ISBN 9780486201078 Hardy G H 1992 1940 A Mathematician s Apology Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521427067 Hart W D 1996 Wilbur Dyre Hart ed The Philosophy of Mathematics Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198751199 Hendricks Vincent F Leitgeb Hannes eds 2006 Philosophy of Mathematics 5 Questions Automatic Press ISBN 9788799101351 VIP キャッシング対策局 審査 在籍確認 増額 おまとめ 借り換え Huntley H E 1970 The Divine Proportion A Study in Mathematical Beauty Dover ISBN 9780486222547 Irvine A ed 2009 The Philosophy of Mathematics Handbook of the Philosophy of Science North Holland Elsevier ISBN 9780080930589 Klein Jacob 2013 1968 Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra Translated by Brann Eva Dover ISBN 9780486319810 OCLC 841505651 Kline Morris 2012 1959 Mathematics and the Physical World Dover ISBN 9780486136318 OCLC 868272162 Kline Morris 1990 1972 Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195061352 Konig Julius Gyula 1905 Uber die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre und das Kontinuumproblem Mathematische Annalen 61 156 160 doi 10 1007 BF01457735 S2CID 123696953 Reprinted On the Foundations of Set Theory and the Continuum Problem Stefan Bauer Mengelberg trans pp 145 149 in Jean van Heijenoort ed 1967 Korner Stephan 1960 The Philosophy of Mathematics An Introduction Harper Books OCLC 1054045322 Lakoff George Nunez Rafael E 2000 Where Mathematics Comes From How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being Basic Books ISBN 9780465037704 Lakatos Imre 1976 Worrall J Zahar E eds Proofs and Refutations The Logic of Mathematical Discovery Cambridge University Press Lakatos Imre 1978 Worrall J Currie G eds Mathematics Science and Epistemology Philosophical Papers Vol 2 Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521280303 Lakatos Imre 1968 Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics North Holland OCLC 254371777 Leibniz G W 1966 Parkinson G H R ed Logical Papers 1666 1690 Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198243069 Maddy Penelope 1997 Naturalism in Mathematics Oxford University Press ISBN 9780191518973 OCLC 1200106111 Maziarz Edward A Greenwood Thomas 1995 Greek Mathematical Philosophy Barnes and Noble Books ISBN 9781566199544 Mount Matthew Classical Greek Mathematical Philosophy citation needed Parsons Charles 2014 Philosophy of Mathematics in the Twentieth Century Selected Essays Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 72806 6 Peirce Benjamin 1870 Linear Associative Algebra 1 See Peirce B 1881 Linear Associative Algebra American Journal of Mathematics 4 1 97 229 doi 10 2307 2369153 JSTOR 2369153 Peirce C S Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce vols 1 6 Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds vols 7 8 Arthur W Burks ed Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1931 1935 1958 Cited as CP volume paragraph Peirce C S various pieces on mathematics and logic many readable online through links at the Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography especially under Books authored or edited by Peirce published in his lifetime and the two sections following it Plato The Republic Volume 1 Paul Shorey trans pp 1 535 in Plato Volume 5 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London UK 1930 Plato The Republic Volume 2 Paul Shorey trans pp 1 521 in Plato Volume 6 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London UK 1935 Resnik Michael D 1980 Frege and the Philosophy of Mathematics Cornell University ISBN 9780801412936 Resnik Michael 1997 Mathematics as a Science of Patterns Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 825014 2 Robinson Gilbert de B 1959 The Foundations of Geometry 4th ed University of Toronto Press ISBN 9780802011039 Raymond Eric S 1993 The Utility of Mathematics Smullyan Raymond M 1993 Recursion Theory for Metamathematics Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195082326 Russell Bertrand 1993 1919 Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy Routledge ISBN 9780486277240 OCLC 1097317975 Shapiro Stewart 2000 Thinking About Mathematics The Philosophy of Mathematics Oxford University Press ISBN 9780192893062 Strohmeier John Westbrook Peter 1999 Divine Harmony The Life and Teachings of Pythagoras Berkeley Hills Books ISBN 9780985424114 Styazhkin N I 1975 1969 History of Mathematical Logic from Leibniz to Peano MIT Press ISBN 9780262690492 Tait William W 1986 Truth and Proof The Platonism of Mathematics Synthese 69 3 341 370 doi 10 1007 BF00413978 JSTOR 20116347 S2CID 10240391 Reprinted in Hart 1996 pp 142 167 Tarski A 1983 Logic Semantics Metamathematics Papers from 1923 to 1938 2nd ed Hackett ISBN 0 915144 76 X Ulam S M 2022 1990 Bednarek A R Ulam Francoise eds Analogies Between Analogies The Mathematical Reports of S M Ulam and His Los Alamos Collaborators University of California Press ISBN 9780520302303 van Heijenoort Jean ed 2002 1967 From Frege To Godel A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674324497 Wigner E P 1960 The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences Richard Courant lecture in mathematical sciences delivered at New York University May 11 1959 Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13 1 1 14 Bibcode 1960CPAM 13 1W doi 10 1002 cpa 3160130102 S2CID 6112252 Wilder Raymond L 1980 Mathematics as a Cultural System Pergamon ISBN 9780080257969 Witzany Guenther 2011 Can mathematics explain the evolution of human language Communicative and Integrative Biology 4 5 516 520 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 1043 1595 doi 10 4161 cib 16426 PMC 3204117 PMID 22046452 External links Edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Philosophy of mathematics Philosophy of mathematics at PhilPapers Philosophy of mathematics at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Horsten Leon Philosophy of Mathematics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Philosophy of mathematics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Mathematical Structuralism Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy Abstractionism Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy Ludwig Wittgenstein Later Philosophy of Mathematics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The London Philosophy Study Guide Archived 2009 09 23 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read depending on the student s familiarity with the subject Philosophy of Mathematics Archived 2009 06 20 at the Wayback Machine Mathematical Logic Archived 2009 01 25 at the Wayback Machine Set Theory amp Further Logic Archived 2009 02 27 at the Wayback Machine R B Jones philosophy of mathematics page Philosophy of mathematics at Curlie Corfield David The Philosophy of Real Mathematics Blog Peirce C S 1998 22 New Elements Kaina Stoixeia In Peirce Edition Project ed The Essential Peirce Selected Philosophical Writings Vol 2 1893 1913 Indiana University Press pp 300 324 ISBN 9780253007810 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Philosophy of mathematics amp oldid 1180776384 Mathematical realism, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.