fbpx
Wikipedia

Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant (UK: /kænt/,[1][2] US: /kɑːnt/,[3][4] German: [ɪˈmaːnu̯eːl ˈkant];[5][6] 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher (a native of the Kingdom of Prussia) and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western philosophy.

Immanuel Kant
Portrait by Johann Gottlieb Becker, 1768
Born(1724-04-22)22 April 1724
Died12 February 1804(1804-02-12) (aged 79)
Königsberg, East Prussia, Kingdom of Prussia
EducationCollegium Fridericianum
University of Königsberg
(BA; MA, April 1755; PhD, September 1755; PhD, August 1770)
EraAge of Enlightenment
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Other schools
InstitutionsUniversity of Königsberg
Theses
  • Principiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio (September 1755)
  • De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis (August 1770)
Academic advisorsMartin Knutzen, Johann Gottfried Teske (M.A. advisor), Konrad Gottlieb Marquardt
Notable studentsJakob Sigismund Beck, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Johann Gottfried Herder, Karl Leonhard Reinhold (epistolary correspondent)
Main interests
Aesthetics, cosmogony, epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, systematic philosophy
Notable ideas
Influences
Influenced
Signature

In his doctrine of transcendental idealism, Kant argued space and time are mere "forms of intuition" that structure all experience and that the objects of experience are mere "appearances". The nature of things as they are in themselves is unknowable to us. In an attempt to counter the philosophical doctrine of skepticism, he wrote the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), his most well-known work. Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal to think of the objects of experience as conforming to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition and the categories of our understanding, so that we have a priori cognition of those objects.

Kant believed that reason is the source of morality, and that aesthetics arises from a faculty of disinterested judgment. Kant's religious views were deeply connected to his moral theory. Their exact nature, however, remains in dispute. He hoped that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation. His cosmopolitan reputation, however, is called into question by his promulgation of scientific racism for much of his career, even though he changed those views in the last decade of his life.

Biography

Immanuel Kant was born on 22 April 1724 into a Prussian German family of Lutheran Protestant faith in Königsberg, East Prussia (since 1946 the Russian city of Kaliningrad). His mother, Anna Regina Reuter (1697–1737), was born in Königsberg to a father from Nuremberg.[7] Her surname is sometimes erroneously given as Porter. Kant's father, Johann Georg Kant (1682–1746), was a German harness-maker from Memel, at the time Prussia's most northeastern city (now Klaipėda, Lithuania). It is possible that Kants got their name from the village of Kantvainiai (German: Kantwaggen – today part of Priekulė) and were of Kursenieki origin.[8][9]

Baptized Emanuel, Kant later changed the spelling of his name to Immanuel after learning Hebrew.[10] He was the fourth of nine children (six of whom reached adulthood).[11]

The Kant household stressed the pietist values of religious devotion, humility, and a literal interpretation of the Bible.[12] The young Immanuel's education was strict, punitive and disciplinary, and focused on Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science.[13]

In his later years, Kant lived a strictly ordered life. It was said that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks. He never married but seems to have had a rewarding social life; he was a popular teacher as well as a modestly successful author, even before starting on his major philosophical works.[14]

Young scholar

Kant showed a great aptitude for study at an early age. He first attended the Collegium Fridericianum from which he graduated at the end of the summer of 1740. In 1740, aged 16, he enrolled at the University of Königsberg, where he spent his whole career.[15] He studied the philosophy of Gottfried Leibniz and Christian Wolff under Martin Knutzen (Associate Professor of Logic and Metaphysics from 1734 until his death in 1751), a rationalist who was also familiar with developments in British philosophy and science and introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of Isaac Newton. Knutzen dissuaded Kant from the theory of pre-established harmony, which he regarded as "the pillow for the lazy mind".[16] He also dissuaded Kant from idealism, the idea that reality is purely mental, which most philosophers in the 18th century regarded in a negative light. The theory of transcendental idealism that Kant later included in the Critique of Pure Reason was developed partially in opposition to traditional idealism.

Kant had contacts with students, colleagues, friends and diners who frequented the local Masonic lodge.[17]

His father's stroke and subsequent death in 1746 interrupted his studies. Kant left Königsberg shortly after August 1748;[18] he would return there in August 1754.[19] He became a private tutor in the towns surrounding Königsberg, but continued his scholarly research. In 1749, he published his first philosophical work, Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces (written in 1745–1747).[20]

Early work

Kant is best known for his work in the philosophy of ethics and metaphysics, but he made significant contributions to other disciplines. In 1754, while contemplating on a prize question by the Berlin Academy about the problem of Earth's rotation, he argued that the Moon's gravity would slow down Earth's spin and he also put forth the argument that gravity would eventually cause the Moon's tidal locking to coincide with the Earth's rotation.[a][22] The next year, he expanded this reasoning to the formation and evolution of the Solar System in his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens.[22] In 1755, Kant received a license to lecture in the University of Königsberg and began lecturing on a variety of topics including mathematics, physics, logic, and metaphysics. In his 1756 essay on the theory of winds, Kant laid out an original insight into the Coriolis force.

In 1756, Kant also published three papers on the 1755 Lisbon earthquake.[23] Kant's theory, which involved shifts in huge caverns filled with hot gases, though inaccurate, was one of the first systematic attempts to explain earthquakes in natural rather than supernatural terms. In 1757, Kant began lecturing on geography making him one of the first lecturers to explicitly teach geography as its own subject.[24][25] Geography was one of Kant's most popular lecturing topics and, in 1802, a compilation by Friedrich Theodor Rink of Kant's lecturing notes, Physical Geography, was released. After Kant became a professor in 1770, he expanded the topics of his lectures to include lectures on natural law, ethics, and anthropology, along with other topics.[24]

 
Kant's house in Königsberg

In the Universal Natural History, Kant laid out the Nebular hypothesis, in which he deduced that the Solar System had formed from a large cloud of gas, a nebula. Kant also correctly deduced that the Milky Way was a large disk of stars, which he theorized formed from a much larger spinning gas cloud. He further suggested that other distant "nebulae" might be other galaxies. These postulations opened new horizons for astronomy, for the first time extending it beyond the solar system to galactic and intergalactic realms.[26]

From then on, Kant turned increasingly to philosophical issues, although he continued to write on the sciences throughout his life. In the early 1760s, Kant produced a series of important works in philosophy. The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures, a work in logic, was published in 1762. Two more works appeared the following year: Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy and The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God. By 1764, Kant had become a notable popular author, and wrote Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime; he was second to Moses Mendelssohn in a Berlin Academy prize competition with his Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality (often referred to as "The Prize Essay"). In 1766 Kant wrote a critical piece on Emanuel Swedenborg's Dreams of a Spirit-Seer.

On 31 March 1770, aged 45, Kant was finally appointed Full Professor of Logic and Metaphysics (Professor Ordinarius der Logic und Metaphysic) at the University of Königsberg. In defense of this appointment, Kant wrote his inaugural dissertation (Inaugural-Dissertation) De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis (On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World).[b] This work saw the emergence of several central themes of his mature work, including the distinction between the faculties of intellectual thought and sensible receptivity. To miss this distinction would mean to commit the error of subreption, and, as he says in the last chapter of the dissertation, only in avoiding this error does metaphysics flourish.

It is often claimed that Kant was a late developer, that he only became an important philosopher in his mid-50's after rejecting his earlier views. While it is true that Kant wrote his greatest works relatively late in life, there is a tendency to underestimate the value of his earlier works. Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these "pre-critical" writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work.[27]

Publication of The Critique of Pure Reason

At age 46, Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher, and much was expected of him. In correspondence with his ex-student and friend Markus Herz, Kant admitted that, in the inaugural dissertation, he had failed to account for the relation between our sensible and intellectual faculties.[28] He needed to explain how we combine what is known as sensory knowledge with the other type of knowledge – that is, reasoned knowledge – these two being related, but having very different processes.

 
Portrait of philosopher David Hume

Kant also credited David Hume with awakening him from a "dogmatic slumber" in which he had unquestioningly accepted the tenets of both religion and natural philosophy.[29][30] Hume, in his 1739 Treatise on Human Nature, had argued that we only know the mind through a subjective, essentially illusory series of perceptions. Ideas such as causality, morality, and objects are not evident in experience, so their reality may be questioned. Kant felt that reason could remove this skepticism, and he set himself to solving these problems. Although fond of company and conversation with others, Kant isolated himself, and resisted friends' attempts to bring him out of his isolation.[c] When Kant emerged from his silence in 1781, the result was the Critique of Pure Reason. Kant countered Hume's empiricism by claiming that some knowledge exists inherently in the mind, independent of experience.[29] He drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal that worldly objects can be intuited a priori, and that intuition is consequently distinct from objective reality. He acquiesced to Hume somewhat by defining causality as a "regular, constant sequence of events in time, and nothing more".[32]

Although now uniformly recognized as one of the greatest works in the history of philosophy, this Critique disappointed Kant's readers upon its initial publication.[33] The book was long, over 800 pages in the original German edition, and written in a convoluted style. Kant was quite upset with its reception.[34] His former student, Johann Gottfried Herder criticized it for placing reason as an entity worthy of criticism instead of considering the process of reasoning within the context of language and one's entire personality.[35] Similar to Christian Garve and Johann Georg Heinrich Feder, he rejected Kant's position that space and time possessed a form that could be analyzed. Additionally, Garve and Feder also faulted Kant's Critique for not explaining differences in perception of sensations.[36] Its density made it, as Herder said in a letter to Johann Georg Hamann, a "tough nut to crack", obscured by "all this heavy gossamer".[37] Its reception stood in stark contrast to the praise Kant had received for earlier works, such as his Prize Essay and shorter works that preceded the first Critique. Recognizing the need to clarify the original treatise, Kant wrote the Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics in 1783 as a summary of its main views. Shortly thereafter, Kant's friend Johann Friedrich Schultz (1739–1805), a professor of mathematics, published Explanations of Professor Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (Königsberg, 1784), which was a brief but very accurate commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.[38]

 
Engraving of Immanuel Kant

Kant's reputation gradually rose through the latter portion of the 1780s, sparked by a series of important works: the 1784 essay, "Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?"; 1785's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (his first work on moral philosophy); and, from 1786, Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. But Kant's fame ultimately arrived from an unexpected source. In 1786, Karl Leonhard Reinhold published a series of public letters on Kantian philosophy.[39] In these letters, Reinhold framed Kant's philosophy as a response to the central intellectual controversy of the era: the pantheism controversy. Friedrich Jacobi had accused the recently deceased Gotthold Ephraim Lessing (a distinguished dramatist and philosophical essayist) of Spinozism. Such a charge, tantamount to atheism, was vigorously denied by Lessing's friend Moses Mendelssohn, leading to a bitter public dispute among partisans. The controversy gradually escalated into a debate about the values of the Enlightenment and the value of reason.

Reinhold maintained in his letters that Kant's Critique of Pure Reason could settle this dispute by defending the authority and bounds of reason. Reinhold's letters were widely read and made Kant the most famous philosopher of his era.

Later work

Kant published a second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787, heavily revising the first parts of the book. Most of his subsequent work focused on other areas of philosophy. He continued to develop his moral philosophy, notably in 1788's Critique of Practical Reason (known as the second Critique), and 1797's Metaphysics of Morals. The 1790 Critique of the Power of Judgment (the third Critique) applied the Kantian system to aesthetics and teleology.

In 1792, Kant's attempt to publish the Second of the four Pieces of Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason,[40] in the journal Berlinische Monatsschrift, met with opposition from the King's censorship commission, which had been established that same year in the context of the French Revolution.[41] Kant then arranged to have all four pieces published as a book, routing it through the philosophy department at the University of Jena to avoid the need for theological censorship.[41] This insubordination earned him a now-famous reprimand from the King.[41] When he nevertheless published a second edition in 1794, the censor was so irate that he arranged for a royal order that required Kant never to publish or even speak publicly about religion.[41] Kant then published his response to the King's reprimand and explained himself in the preface of The Conflict of the Faculties.[41]

He also wrote a number of semi-popular essays on history, religion, politics, and other topics. These works were-well received by Kant's contemporaries and confirmed his preeminent status in eighteenth-century philosophy. There were several journals devoted solely to defending and criticizing Kantian philosophy. Despite his success, philosophical trends were moving in another direction. Many of Kant's most important disciples and followers (including Reinhold, Beck, and Fichte) transformed the Kantian position. The progressive stages of revision of Kant's teachings marked the emergence of German idealism. Kant opposed these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in 1799.[42] It was one of his final acts expounding a stance on philosophical questions.

In 1800, a student of Kant named Gottlob Benjamin Jäsche (1762–1842) published a manual of logic for teachers called Logik, which he had prepared at Kant's request. Jäsche prepared the Logik using a copy of a textbook in logic by Georg Friedrich Meier entitled Excerpt from the Doctrine of Reason, in which Kant had written copious notes and annotations. The Logik has been considered of fundamental importance to Kant's philosophy, and the understanding of it. The great 19th-century logician Charles Sanders Peirce remarked, in an incomplete review of Thomas Kingsmill Abbott's English translation of the introduction to Logik, that "Kant's whole philosophy turns upon his logic."[43] Also, Robert Schirokauer Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz wrote in the translators' introduction to their English translation of the Logik, "Its importance lies not only in its significance for the Critique of Pure Reason, the second part of which is a restatement of fundamental tenets of the Logic, but in its position within the whole of Kant's work."[44]

Death and burial

Kant's health, long poor, worsened. He died at Königsberg on 12 February 1804, uttering "Es ist gut" (It is good) before expiring.[45] His unfinished final work was published as Opus Postumum. Kant always cut a curious figure in his lifetime for his modest, rigorously scheduled habits, which have been referred to as clocklike. However, Heinrich Heine noted the magnitude of "his destructive, world-crushing thoughts" and considered him a sort of philosophical "executioner", comparing him to Robespierre with the observation that both men "represented in the highest the type of provincial bourgeois. Nature had destined them to weigh coffee and sugar, but Fate determined that they should weigh other things and placed on the scales of the one a king, on the scales of the other a god."[46]

When his body was transferred to a new burial spot, his skull was measured during the exhumation and found to be larger than the average German male's with a "high and broad" forehead.[47] His forehead has been an object of interest ever since it became well known through his portraits: "In Döbler's portrait and in Kiefer's faithful if expressionistic reproduction of it – as well as in many of the other late eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century portraits of Kant – the forehead is remarkably large and decidedly retreating."[48]

 
Kant's tomb in Kaliningrad, Russia

Kant's mausoleum adjoins the northeast corner of Königsberg Cathedral in Kaliningrad, Russia. The mausoleum was constructed by the architect Friedrich Lahrs and was finished in 1924, in time for the bicentenary of Kant's birth. Originally, Kant was buried inside the cathedral, but in 1880 his remains were moved to a neo-Gothic chapel adjoining the northeast corner of the cathedral. Over the years, the chapel became dilapidated and was demolished to make way for the mausoleum, which was built on the same location.

The tomb and its mausoleum are among the few artifacts of German times preserved by the Soviets after they captured the city.[49] Today, many newlyweds bring flowers to the mausoleum. Artifacts previously owned by Kant, known as Kantiana, were included in the Königsberg City Museum. However, the museum was destroyed during World War II. A replica of the statue of Kant that in German times stood in front of the main University of Königsberg building was donated by a German entity in the early 1990s and placed in the same grounds.

After the expulsion of Königsberg's German population at the end of World War II, the University of Königsberg where Kant taught was replaced by the Russian-language Kaliningrad State University, which appropriated the campus and surviving buildings. In 2005, the university was renamed Immanuel Kant State University of Russia. The name change was announced at a ceremony attended by President Vladimir Putin of Russia and Chancellor Gerhard Schröder of Germany, and the university formed a Kant Society, dedicated to the study of Kantianism. The university was again renamed in the 2010s, to Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University.[50]

Philosophy

Like many of his contemporaries, Kant was greatly impressed with the scientific advances made by Newton and others. This new evidence of the power of human reason, however, called into question the traditional authority of politics and religion. Although this was in some respects liberatory, it was in other respects threatening. In particular, the modern mechanistic view of the world called into question the very possibility of morality; for, if there is no agency, there cannot be any responsibility.[51][52]

The aim of Kant's critical project is to secure human autonomy, the basis of religion and morality, from this threat of mechanism—and to do so in a way that preserves the advances of modern science.[53]

In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant summarizes his philosophical concerns in the following three questions:

 
Bust of Immanuel Kant by Emanuel Bardou, 1798
  1. What can I know?
  2. What should I do?
  3. What may I hope?[54]

The Critique of Pure Reason focuses upon the first question and opens a conceptual space for an answer to the second question. It argues that even though we cannot, strictly know that we are free, we can – and for practical purposes, must – think of ourselves as free. In Kant's own words, "I had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith."[55] Our rational faith in morality is further developed in The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and The Critique of Practical Reason.[56][57]

The Critique of the Power of Judgment argues we may rationally hope for the harmonious unity of the theoretical and practical domains treated in the first two Critiques on the basis, not only of its conceptual possibility, but also on the basis of our affective experience of natural beauty and, more generally, the organization of the natural world.[58] In Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason, Kant endeavors to complete his answer to this third question.[59]

These works all place the active, rational human subject at the center of the cognitive and moral worlds. In brief, Kant argues that the mind itself necessarily makes a constitutive contribution to knowledge, that this contribution is transcendental rather than psychological, and that to act autonomously is to act according to rational moral principles.[60]

Kant's critical project

 
Immanuel Kant by Carle Vernet (1758–1836)

Kant's 1781 (revised 1787) book the Critique of Pure Reason has often been cited as the most significant volume of metaphysics and epistemology in modern philosophy.[61]

In the first Critique, and later on in other works as well, Kant frames the "general" and "real problem of pure reason" in terms of the following question: "How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?"[62][63]

To parse this claim, it is necessary to define some terms. First, Kant makes a distinction in terms of the source of the content of knowledge:

  1. Cognitions a priori: "cognition independent of all experience and even of all the impressions of the senses".
  2. Cognitions a posteriori: cognitions that have their sources in experience—that is, which are empirical.[64]

Second, he makes a distinction in terms of the form of knowledge:

  1. Analytic proposition: a proposition whose predicate concept is contained in its subject concept; e.g., "All bachelors are unmarried", or "All bodies take up space". These can also be called "judgments of clarification".
  2. Synthetic proposition: a proposition whose predicate concept is not contained in its subject concept; e.g., "All bachelors are alone", or "All bodies have weight". These can also be called "judgments of amplification".[65]

An analytic proposition is true by nature of strictly conceptual relations. All analytic propositions are a priori (it is analytically true that no analytic proposition could be a posteriori). By contrast, a synthetic proposition is one the content of which includes something new. The truth or falsehood of a synthetic statement depends upon something more than what is contained in its concepts. The most obvious form of synthetic proposition is a simple empirical observation.[66]

Philosophers such as David Hume believed that these were the only possible kinds of human reason and investigation, which he called "relations of ideas" and "matters of fact".[67] Establishing the synthetic a priori as a third mode of knowledge would allow Kant to push back against Hume's skepticism about such matters as causation and metaphysical knowledge more generally. This is because, unlike a posteriori cognition, a priori cognition has "true or strict...universality" and includes a claim of "necessity".[68][66]

Kant himself regards it as uncontroversial that we do have synthetic a priori knowledge—most obviously, that of mathematics. That 7 + 5 = 12, he claims, is a result not contained in the concepts of seven, five, and the addition operation.[69] Yet, although he considers the possibility of such knowledge to be obvious, Kant nevertheless assumes the burden of providing a philosophical proof that we have a priori knowledge in mathematics, the natural sciences, and metaphysics. It is the twofold aim of the Critique both to prove and to explain the possibility of this knowledge.[70]

 
Christian Wolff (1679–1754), whose methodical principles of logical exposition are responsible for many of the formal qualities of Kant's works.

Before turning to Kant's arguments in the body of the Critique, there are two more distinctions from its introductory sections that must be introduced.

"There are", Kant says, "two stems of human cognition, which may perhaps arise from a common but to us unknown root, namely sensibility and understanding, through the first of which objects are given to us, but through the second of which they are thought."[71]

Kant's term for the object of sensibility is intuition, and his term for the object of the understanding is concept. In general terms, the former is a non-discursive representation of a particular object, and the latter is a discursive (or mediate) representation of a general type of object.[72] The conditions of possible experience require both intuitions and concepts, that is, the affection of the receptive sensibility and the actively synthesizing power of the understanding.[73][d] Thus the statement: "Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind."[75]

Kant's basic strategy in the first half of his book will be to argue that some intuitions and concepts are pure—that is, are contributed entirely by the mind, independent of anything empirical. Knowledge generated on this basis, under certain conditions, can be synthetic a priori. This insight is known as Kant's "Copernican revolution", because, just as Copernicus advanced astronomy by way of a radical shift in perspective, so Kant here claims do the same for metaphysics.[76][77]

The second half of the Critique is the explicitly critical part. In this "transcendental dialectic", Kant argues that many of the claims of traditional rationalist metaphysics violate the criteria he claims to establishing the first, "constructive" part of his book.[78][79] As Kant observes, "human reason, without being moved by the mere vanity of knowing it all, inexorably pushes on, driven by its own need to such questions that cannot be answered by any experiential use of reason".[80] It is the project of "the critique of pure reason" to establish the limits as to just how far reason may legitimately so proceed.[81]

The doctrine of transcendental idealism

The section of the Critique entitled "The transcendental aesthetic" advances Kant's famous thesis of transcendental idealism. Something is "transcendental" if it is a necessary condition for the possibility of experience, and "idealism" denotes some form of mind-dependence that must be further specified. (The correct interpretation of Kant's own specification remains controversial.)[82]

The thesis, then, states that human beings only experience and know appearances, not things-in-themselves, because space and time are nothing but the subjective forms of intuition that we ourselves contribute to experience.[83][84]

Nevertheless, although Kant says that space and time are "transcendentally ideal" – the pure forms of human sensibility, rather than part of nature or reality as it exists in-itself – he also claims that they are "empirically real", by which he means "that 'everything that can come before us externally as an object' is in both space and time, and that our internal intuitions of ourselves are in time".[85][83] However we may interpret Kant's doctrine, he clearly wishes to distinguish his position from the subjective idealism of Berkeley.[86]

Paul Guyer, although critical of many of Kant's arguments in this section, nevertheless writes of the "Transcendental Aesthetic" that it "not only lays the first stone in Kant's constructive theory of knowledge; it also lays the foundation for both his critique and his reconstruction of traditional metaphysics. It argues that all genuine knowledge requires a sensory component, and thus that metaphysical claims that transcend the possibility of sensory confirmation can never amount to knowledge."[87]

Interpretive disagreements

One interpretation, known as the "two-world" interpretation, regards Kant's position as a statement of epistemological limitation, that we are not able to transcend the bounds of our own mind, meaning that we cannot access the "thing-in-itself". However, Kant also speaks of the thing in itself or transcendent object as a product of the (human) understanding as it attempts to conceive of objects in abstraction from the conditions of sensibility. Following this line of thought, some interpreters have argued that the thing in itself does not represent a separate ontological domain but simply a way of considering objects by means of the understanding alone; this is known as the "two-aspect" view.[88][89]

Kant's theory of judgment

 
Kant statue in the School of Philosophy and Human Sciences (FAFICH) in the Federal University of Minas Gerais (UFMG), Belo Horizonte, Brazil

Following the "Transcendental Analytic" is the "Transcendental Logic". Whereas the former was concerned with the contributions of the sensibility, the latter is concerned, first, with the contributions of the understanding ("Transcendental Analytic") and, second, with the faculty of reason as the source of both metaphysical errors and genuine regulatory principles ("Transcendental Dialectic").

The "Transcendental Analytic" is further divided into two sections. The first, "Analytic of Concepts", is concerned with establishing the universality and necessity of the pure concepts of the understanding (i.e., the categories). This section contains Kant's famous "transcendental deduction". The second, "Analytic of Principles", is concerned with the application of those pure concepts in empirical judgments. This second section is longer than the first and is further divided into many sub-sections.[90]

Transcendental deduction of the categories of the understanding

The "Analytic of Concepts" argues for the universal and necessary validity of the pure concepts of the understanding, or the categories, e.g., the concepts of substance and causation. These twelve basic categories define what it is to be a thing in general, that is, they articulate the necessary conditions according to which something is a possible object of experience. These, in conjunction with the a priori forms of intuition, are the basis of all synthetic a priori cognition.

According to Guyer and Wood, "Kant's idea is that just as there are certain essential features of all judgments, so there must be certain corresponding ways in which we form the concepts of objects so that judgments may be about objects."[91]

Kant provides two central lines of argumentation in support of his claims about the categories. The first, known as the "metaphysical deduction", proceeds analytically from a table of the Aristotelian logical functions of judgment. As Kant was aware, however, this assumes precisely what the skeptic rejects, namely, the existence of synthetic a priori cognition. For this reason, Kant also supplies a synthetic argument that does not depend upon the assumption in dispute.[92]

This argument, provided under the heading "Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding", is widely considered to be both the most important and the most difficult of Kant's arguments in the Critique. Kant himself said that it is the one that cost him the most labor.[93] Frustrated by its confused reception in the first edition of his book, he rewrote it entirely for the second edition.[94][95]

The "Transcendental Deduction" gives Kant's argument that these pure concepts apply universally and necessarily to the objects that are given in experience. According to Guyer and Wood, "He centers his argument on the premise that our experience can be ascribed to a single identical subject, via what he calls the 'transcendental unity of apperception,' only if the elements of experience given in intuition are synthetically combined so as to present us with objects that are thought through the categories."[96]

Kant's principle of apperception is that "The I think must be able to accompany all my representations; for otherwise something would be represented in me that could not be thought at all, which is as much as to say that the representation would either be impossible or else at least would be nothing for me."[97] The necessary possibility of the self-ascription of the representations of self-consciousness, identical to itself through time, is an a priori conceptual truth that cannot be based on experience.[98]

This, however, is only a bare sketch of one of the arguments that Kant presents.

Principles of pure understanding

Kant's deduction of the categories in the "Analytic of Concepts", if successful, demonstrates its claims about the categories only in an abstract way. The task of the "Analytic of Principles" is to show both, that they must universally apply to objects given in actual experience (i.e., manifolds of intuition), and how it is they do so.[99]

In the first book of this section on the "schematism", Kant connects each of the purely logical categories of the understanding to the temporality of intuition to show that, although non-empirical, they do have purchase upon the objects of experience. The second book continues this line of argument in four chapters, each associated with one of the category groupings. In some cases, it adds a connection to the spatial dimension of intuition to the categories it analyzes.[100]

The fourth chapter of this section, "The Analogies of Experience", marks a shift from "mathematical" to "dynamical" principles, that is, to those that deal with relations among objects. Some commentators consider this the most significant section of the Critique.[101] The analogies are three in number:

  1. Principle of persistence of substance: Kant is here concerned with the general conditions of determining time-relations among the objects of experience. He argues that the unity of time implies that "all change must consist in the alteration of states in an underlying substance, whose existence and quantity must be unchangeable or conserved."[102]
  2. Principle of temporal succession according to the law of causality: Here Kant argues that "we can make determinate judgments about the objective succession of events, as contrasted to merely subjective successions of representations, only if every objective alteration follows a necessary rule of succession, or a causal law." This is Kant's most direct rejoinder to Hume's skepticism about causality.[103]
  3. Principle of simultaneity according to the law of reciprocity or community: The final analogy argues that "determinate judgments that objects (or states of substance) in different regions of space exists simultaneously are possible only if such objects stand in mutual causal relation of community or reciprocal interaction." (This is Kant's rejoinder to Leibniz's thesis in the Monadology.)[104][105]

The fourth section of this chapter, which is not an analogy, deals with the empirical use of the modal categories. That was the end of the chapter in the A edition of the Critique.

The B addition, however, includes one more short section, "The Refutation of Idealism". In this section, by analysis of the concept of self-consciousness, Kant argues that his transcendental idealism is a "critical" or "formal" idealism that does not deny the existence of reality apart from our subjective representations.[106]

The final chapter of "The Analytic of Principles" distinguishes phenomena, of which we have can have genuine knowledge, from noumena, a term which refers to objects of pure thought that we cannot know, but to which we may still refer "in a negative sense".[107]

An Appendix to the section further develops Kant's criticism of Leibnizian-Wolffian rationalism by arguing that its "dogmatic" metaphysics confuses the "mere features of concepts through which we think things...[with] features of the objects themselves". Against this, Kant reasserts his own insistence upon the necessity of a sensible component in all genuine knowledge.[108]

Critique of metaphysics

The second of the two Divisions of "The Transcendental Logic", "The Transcendental Dialectic", contains the "negative" portion of Kant's Critique, which builds upon the "positive" arguments of the preceding "Transcendental Analytic" to expose the limits of metaphysical speculation. In particular, it is concerned to demonstrate as spurious the efforts of reason to arrive at knowledge independent of sensibility. This endeavor, Kant argues, is doomed to failure, which he claims to demonstrate by showing that reason, unbounded by sense, is always capable of generating opposing or otherwise incompatible conclusions.

Like "the light dove, in free flight cutting through the air, the resistance of which it feels", reason "could get the idea that it could do even better in airless space".[109] Against this, Kant claims that, absent epistemic friction, there can be no knowledge.

Nevertheless, Kant's critique is not entirely destructive. He presents the speculative excesses of traditional metaphysics as inherent in our very capacity of reason. Moreover, he argues that its products are not without some (carefully qualified) regulative value.

On the concepts of pure reason

Kant calls the basic concepts of metaphysics "ideas". They are different from the concepts of understanding in that they are not limited by the stricture[clarification needed] of possible experience. "Transcendental illusion" is Kant's term for the tendency of reason to produce such ideas.[110]

Although reason has a "logical use" of simply drawing inferences from principles, in "The Transcendental Dialectic", Kant is concerned with its purportedly "real use" to arrive at conclusions by way of unchecked regressive syllogistic ratiocination.[111]

The three categories of relation, pursued without regard to the limits of possible experience, yield the three central ideas of traditional metaphysics:

  1. The soul: the concept of substance as the ultimate subject;
  2. The world in its entirety: the concept of causation as a completed series; and
  3. God: the concept of community as the common ground of all possibilities.[111]

Although Kant denies that these ideas can be objects of genuine cognition, he argues that they are the result of reason's inherent drive to unify cognition into a systematic whole.[110]

Leibnizian-Wolffian metaphysics was divided into four parts: ontology, psychology, cosmology, and theology. Kant replaces the first with the positive results of the first part of the Critique. He proposes to replace the following three with his later doctrines of anthropology, the metaphysical foundations of natural science, and the critical postulation of human freedom and morality.[112]

The dialectical inferences of pure reason

In the second of the two Books of "The Transcendental Dialectic", Kant undertakes to demonstrate the contradictory nature of unbounded reason. He does this by developing contradictions in each of the three metaphysical disciplines that he contends are, in fact, pseudo-sciences. This section of the Critique is long and Kant's arguments are extremely detailed. In this context, it not possible to do much more than enumerate the topics of discussion.

The first chapter addresses what Kant terms the paralogisms, i.e., false inferences, that pure reason makes in the metaphysical discipline of rational psychology. He argues that one cannot take the mere thought of "I" in the proposition "I think" as the proper cognition of "I" as an object. In this way, he claims to debunk various metaphysical theses about the substantiality, unity, and self-identity of the soul.[113]

The second chapter, which is the longest, takes up the topic Kant calls the antinomies of pure reason – that is, the contradictions of reason with itself – in the metaphysical discipline of rational cosmology. (Originally, Kant thought that all transcendental illusion could be analyzed in antinomic terms.[114]) He presents four cases in which he claims reason is able to prove opposing theses with equal plausibility:

  1. That "reason seems to be able to prove that the universe is both finite and infinite in space and time";
  2. that "reason seems to be able to prove that matter both is and is not infinitely divisible into ever smaller parts";
  3. that "reason seems to be able to prove that free will cannot be a causally efficacious part of the world (because all of nature is deterministic) and yet that it must be such a cause"; and,
  4. that "reason seems to be able to prove that there is and there is not a necessary being (which some would identify with God)."[115][116]

Kant further argues in each case that his doctrine of transcendental idealism is able to resolve the antinomy.[115]

The third chapter examines fallacious arguments about God in rational theology under the heading of the "Ideal of Pure Reason". (Whereas an idea is a pure concept generated by reason, an ideal is the concept of an idea as an individual thing.[117]) Here Kant addresses and claims to refute three traditional arguments for the existence of God: the ontological argument, the cosmological argument, and the physio-theological argument (i.e., the argument from design).[118]

The results of the transcendental dialectic so far appear to be entirely negative. In an Appendix to this section, however, Kant rejects such a conclusion. The ideas of pure reason, he argues, have an important regulatory function in directing and organizing our theoretical and practical inquiry. Kant's later works elaborate upon this function at length and in detail.[119]

Moral thought

Kant developed his ethics, or moral philosophy, in three works: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), Critique of Practical Reason (1788), and Metaphysics of Morals (1797). With regard to morality, Kant argued that the source of the good lies not in anything outside the human subject, either in nature or given by God, but rather is only the good will itself. A good will is one that acts from duty in accordance with the universal moral law that the autonomous human being freely gives itself. This law obliges one to treat humanity – understood as rational agency, and represented through oneself as well as others – as an end in itself rather than (merely) as means to other ends the individual might hold.

Kant is known for his theory that all moral obligation is grounded in what he calls the "categorical imperative", which is derived from the concept of duty. He argues that the moral law is a principle of reason itself, not based on contingent facts about the world, such as what would make us happy; to act on the moral law has no other motive than "worthiness to be happy".[120]

The idea of freedom

In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant distinguishes between the transcendental idea of freedom, which as a psychological concept is "mainly empirical" and refers to "whether a faculty of beginning a series of successive things or states from itself is to be assumed"[121] and the practical concept of freedom as the independence of our will from the "coercion" or "necessitation through sensuous impulses". Kant finds it a source of difficulty that the practical idea of freedom is founded on the transcendental idea of freedom,[122] but for the sake of practical interests uses the practical meaning, taking "no account of ... its transcendental meaning", which he feels was properly "disposed of" in the Third Antinomy, and as an element in the question of the freedom of the will is for philosophy "a real stumbling block" that has embarrassed speculative reason.[121]

Kant calls practical "everything that is possible through freedom"; he calls the pure practical laws that are never given through sensuous conditions, but are held analogously with the universal law of causality, moral laws. Reason can give us only the "pragmatic laws of free action through the senses", but pure practical laws given by reason a priori[121] dictate "what is to be done.[123]

Kant's categories of freedom function primarily as conditions for the possibility for actions (i) to be free, (ii) to be understood as free, and (iii) to be morally evaluated. For Kant, although actions as theoretical objects are constituted by means of the theoretical categories, actions as practical objects (objects of practical use of reason, and which can be good or bad) are constituted by means of the categories of freedom. Only in this way can actions, as phenomena, be a consequence of freedom, and be understood and evaluated as such.[124]

The categorical imperative

 
In his Groundwork, Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative: "Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you at the same time can will that it become a universal law."

Kant makes a distinction between categorical and hypothetical imperatives. A hypothetical imperative is one that we must obey to satisfy contingent desires. A categorical imperative binds us regardless of our desires: everyone has a duty to not lie, regardless of circumstances, even though it is sometimes in our narrowly selfish interest to do so. These imperatives are morally binding because they are based on reason, rather than contingent facts about an agent.[125] Unlike hypothetical imperatives, which bind us insofar as we are part of a group or society which we owe duties to, we cannot opt out of the categorical imperative because we cannot opt out of being rational agents. We owe a duty to rationality by virtue of being rational agents; therefore, rational moral principles apply to all rational agents at all times.[126] Stated in other terms, with all forms of instrumental rationality excluded from morality, "the moral law itself, Kant holds, can only be the form of lawfulness itself, because nothing else is left once all content has been rejected."[127]

Kant provides three formulations for the categorical imperative. He claims these are necessarily equivalent as all being expressions of the pure universality of the law as such.[128] Many scholars, however, are not convinced.[129]

The formulas are as follows:

  • Formula of Universal Law:
"Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you at the same time can will that it become a universal law";[130] alternatively,
Formula of the Law of Nature: "So act, as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature."[130]
  • Formula of Humanity as End in Itself:
"So act that you use humanity, as much in your own person as in the person of every other, always at the same time as an end and never merely as a means".[131]
  • Formula of Autonomy:
"the idea of the will of every rational being as a will giving universal law",[132] or "Not to choose otherwise than so that the maxims of one's choice are at the same time comprehended with it in the same volition as universal law";[133] alternatively,
Formula of the Realm of Ends: "Act in accordance with maxims of a universally legislative member for a merely possible realm of ends."[134][135]

Kant defines maxim as a "subjective principle of volition", which is distinguished from an "objective principle or 'practical law.'" While "the latter is valid for every rational being and is a 'principle according to which they ought to act[,]' a maxim 'contains the practical rule which reason determines in accordance with the conditions of the subject (often their ignorance or inclinations) and is thus the principle according to which the subject does act.'"[136]

Maxims fail to qualify as practical laws if they produce a contradiction in conception or a contradiction in the will when universalized. A contradiction in conception happens when, if a maxim were to be universalized, it ceases to make sense, because the "maxim would necessarily destroy itself as soon as it was made a universal law".[137] For example, if the maxim 'It is permissible to break promises' was universalized, no one would trust any promises made, so the idea of a promise would become meaningless; the maxim would be self-contradictory because, when universalized, promises cease to be meaningful. The maxim is not moral because it is logically impossible to universalize—we could not conceive of a world where this maxim was universalized.[138] A maxim can also be immoral if it creates a contradiction in the will when universalized. This does not mean a logical contradiction, but that universalizing the maxim leads to a state of affairs that no rational being would desire.

"The Doctrine of Virtue"

As Kant explains in the 1785 Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (and as its title directly indicates), that text is "nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality".[139] His promised Metaphysics of Morals, however, was much delayed and did not appear until its two parts, "The Doctrine of Right" and "The Doctrine of Virtue", were published separately in 1797 and 1798.[140] The first deals with political philosophy, the second with ethics.

"The Doctrine of Virtue" provides "a very different account of ordinary moral reasoning" than the one suggested by the Groundwork.[141] It is concerned with duties of virtue or "ends that are at the same time duties".[142] It is here, in the domain of ethics, that The Metaphysics of Morals's greatest innovation is to be found. According to Kant's account, "ordinary moral reasoning is fundamentally teleological – it is reasoning about what ends we are constrained by morality to pursue, and the priorities among these ends we are required to observe."[143] More specifically,

There are two sorts of ends that it is our duty to have: our own perfection and the happiness of others (MS 6:385). "Perfection" includes both our natural perfection (the development of our talents, skills, and capacities of understanding) and moral perfection (our virtuous disposition) (MS 6:387). A person's "happiness" is the greatest rational whole of the ends the person set for the sake of her own satisfaction (MS 6:387–8).[144]

Kant's elaboration of this teleological doctrine offers up a very different moral theory than the one typically attributed to him on the basis of his foundational works alone.

Political philosophy

In Towards Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Project, Kant listed several conditions that he thought necessary for ending wars and creating a lasting peace. They included a world of constitutional republics.[145] His classical republican theory was extended in the Doctrine of Right, the first part of the Metaphysics of Morals (1797).[146] Kant believed that universal history leads to the ultimate world of republican states at peace, but his theory was not pragmatic. The process was described in Perpetual Peace as natural rather than rational:

What affords this guarantee (surety) is nothing less than the great artist nature (natura daedala rerum) from whose mechanical course purposiveness shines forth visibly, letting concord arise by means of the discord between human beings even against their will; and for this reason nature, regarded as necessitation by a cause the laws of whose operation are unknown to us, is called fate, but if we consider its purposiveness in the course of the world as the profound wisdom of a higher cause directed to the objective final end of the human race and predetermining this course of the world, it is called providence.[147]

Kant's political thought can be summarized as republican government and international organization: "In more characteristically Kantian terms, it is doctrine of the state based upon the law (Rechtsstaat) and of eternal peace. Indeed, in each of these formulations, both terms express the same idea: that of legal constitution or of 'peace through law.'"[148] "Kant's political philosophy, being essentially a legal doctrine, rejects by definition the opposition between moral education and the play of passions as alternate foundations for social life. The state is defined as the union of men under law. The state rightly so called is constituted by laws which are necessary a priori because they flow from the very concept of law. A regime can be judged by no other criteria nor be assigned any other functions, than those proper to the lawful order as such."[149]

He opposed "democracy", which at his time meant direct democracy, believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty. He stated, "democracy in the strict sense of the word is necessarily a despotism because it establishes an executive power in which all decide for and, if need be, against one (who thus does not agree), so that all, who are nevertheless not all, decide; and this is a contradiction of the general will with itself and with freedom."[150] As with most writers at the time, he distinguished three forms of government – namely, democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy – with mixed government as the most ideal form of it.

Although Kant published this as a "popular piece", Mary J. Gregor points out that two years later, in The Metaphysics of Morals, Kant claims to demonstrate systematically that "establishing universal and lasting peace constitutes not merely a part of the doctrine of right, but rather the entire final end of the doctrine of right within the limits of mere reason."[151][152]

"The Doctrine of Right", published in 1797, contains Kant's most mature and systematic contribution to political philosophy. It addresses juridical duties, which are "concerned only with protecting the external freedom of individuals" and indifferent to incentives. (Although we do have a moral duty "to limit ourselves to actions that are right, that duty is not part of [right] itself".)[141] Its basic political idea is that "each person's entitlement to be his or her own master is only consistent with the entitlements of others if public legal institutions are in place."[153]

Religious writings

Commentators, starting in the twentieth century, have tended to see Kant as having a strained relationship with religion, though this was not the prevalent view in the nineteenth century. Karl Leonhard Reinhold, whose letters helped make Kant famous, wrote, "I believe that I may infer without reservation that the interest of religion, and of Christianity in particular, accords completely with the result of the Critique of Reason."[154] According to Johann Schultz, who wrote one of the first commentaries on Kant, "And does not this system itself cohere most splendidly with the Christian religion? Do not the divinity and beneficence of the latter become all the more evident?"[155] The reason for these views was Kant's moral theology and the widespread belief that his philosophy was the great antithesis to Spinozism, which was widely seen as a form of sophisticated pantheism or even atheism. As Kant's philosophy disregarded the possibility of arguing for God through pure reason alone, for the same reasons it also disregarded the possibility of arguing against God through pure reason alone.

Kant articulates his strongest criticisms of the organization and practices of religious organizations to those that encourage what he sees as a religion of counterfeit service to God.[156] Among the major targets of his criticism are external ritual, superstition, and a hierarchical church order. He sees these as efforts to make oneself pleasing to God in ways other than conscientious adherence to the principle of moral rightness in choosing and acting upon one's maxims. Kant's criticisms on these matters, along with his rejection of certain theoretical proofs grounded in pure reason (particularly the ontological argument) for the existence of God and his philosophical commentary on some Christian doctrines, have resulted in interpretations that see Kant as hostile to religion in general and Christianity in particular.[157] Nevertheless, other interpreters consider that Kant was trying to mark off defensible from indefensible Christian belief.[158]

Regarding Kant's conception of religion, some critics have argued that he was sympathetic to deism.[159] Other critics have argued that Kant's moral conception moves from deism to theism (as moral theism), for example, Allen W. Wood[160] and Merold Westphal.[161] As for Kant's book Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason, it was emphasized that Kant reduced religiosity to rationality, religion to morality, and Christianity to ethics.[162] However, many interpreters, including Allen W. Wood[163] and Lawrence Pasternack,[164] now agree with Stephen Palmquist's claim that a better way of reading Kant's Religion is to see him as raising morality to the status of religion.[165]

Aesthetics

 
Immanuel Kant

Kant discusses the subjective nature of aesthetic qualities and experiences in Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime (1764). Kant's contribution to aesthetic theory is developed in the Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790), where he investigates the possibility and logical status of "judgments of taste". In the "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment", the first major division of the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant used the term "aesthetic" in a manner that differs from its modern sense.[166] In the Critique of Pure Reason, to note essential differences between judgments of taste, moral judgments, and scientific judgments, Kant abandoned the term "aesthetic" as "designating the critique of taste", noting that judgments of taste could never be "directed" by "laws a priori".[167]

After A. G. Baumgarten, who wrote Aesthetica (1750–58),[e] Kant was one of the first philosophers to develop and integrate aesthetic theory into a unified and comprehensive philosophical system, utilizing ideas that played an integral role throughout his philosophy.[168]

In the chapter "Analytic of the Beautiful" in the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant states that beauty is not a property of an artwork or natural phenomenon, but is instead consciousness of the pleasure that attends the 'free play' of the imagination and the understanding. Even though it appears that we are using reason to decide what is beautiful, the judgment is not a cognitive judgment,[f] "and is consequently not logical, but aesthetical".[169]

A pure judgement of taste is subjective since it refers to the emotional response of the subject and is based upon nothing but esteem for an object itself: it is a disinterested pleasure, and we feel that pure judgements of taste (i.e., judgements of beauty), lay claim to universal validity.[170] It is important to note that this universal validity is not derived from a determinate concept of beauty but from common sense.[171] Kant also believed that a judgement of taste shares characteristics engaged in a moral judgement: both are disinterested, and we hold them to be universal.

In the chapter "Analytic of the Sublime" Kant identifies the sublime as an aesthetic quality that, like beauty, is subjective, but unlike beauty refers to an indeterminate relationship between the faculties of the imagination and of reason, and shares the character of moral judgments in the use of reason. The feeling of the sublime, divided into two distinct modes (the mathematical and the dynamical sublime), describes two subjective moments that concern the relationship of the faculty of the imagination to reason.

Some commentators[172] argue that Kant's critical philosophy contains a third kind of the sublime, the moral sublime, which is the aesthetic response to the moral law or a representation, and a development of the "noble" sublime in Kant's theory of 1764.

The mathematical sublime results from the failure of the imagination to comprehend natural objects that appear boundless and formless, or appear "absolutely great".[173] This imaginative failure is then recuperated through the pleasure taken in reason's assertion of the concept of infinity. In this move the faculty of reason proves itself superior to our fallible sensible self.[174] In the dynamical sublime, there is the sense of annihilation of the sensible self as the imagination tries to comprehend a vast might. This power of nature threatens us but through the resistance of reason to such sensible annihilation, the subject feels a pleasure and a sense of the human moral vocation. This appreciation of moral feeling through exposure to the sublime helps to develop moral character.

Kant developed a theory of humor[175] that has been interpreted as an "incongruity" theory. He illustrated his theory of humor by telling three narrative jokes in the Critique of Judgment. He thought that the physiological impact of humor is akin to that of music.[176]

Kant developed a distinction between an object of art as a material value subject to the conventions of society and the transcendental condition of the judgment of taste as a "refined" value in his Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim (1784). In the Fourth and Fifth Theses of that work he identified all art as the "fruits of unsociableness" due to men's "antagonism in society"[177] and, in the Seventh Thesis, asserted that while such material property is indicative of a civilized state, only the ideal of morality and the universalization of refined value through the improvement of the mind "belongs to culture".[178]

Anthropology

 
5 DM 1974 D silver coin commemorating the 250th birthday of Immanuel Kant in Königsberg

Kant lectured on anthropology, the study of human nature, for twenty-three years.[179] His Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View was published in 1798. Transcripts of Kant's lectures on anthropology were published for the first time in 1997 in German.[180]

Kant was among the first people of his time to introduce anthropology as an intellectual area of study, long before the field gained popularity, and his texts are considered to have advanced the field. His point of view was to influence the works of later philosophers such as Martin Heidegger and Paul Ricoeur.[citation needed]

Kant was also the first to suggest using a dimensionality approach to human diversity. He analyzed the nature of the Hippocrates-Galen four temperaments and plotted in two dimensions "what belongs to a human being's faculty of desire": "his natural aptitude or natural predisposition" and "his temperament or sensibility".[181] Cholerics were described as emotional and energetic; phlegmatics as balanced and weak; sanguines as balanced and energetic, and melancholics as emotional and weak. These two dimensions reappeared in all subsequent models of temperament and personality traits.

Kant viewed anthropology in two broad categories: (1) the physiological approach, which he referred to as "what nature makes of the human being"; and (2) the pragmatic approach, which explores the things that a human "can and should make of himself".[182]

Racism

 
Kant mixing mustard, drawn by Carl Friedrich Hagemann [de], 1801.

Kant's theory of race and his prejudicial beliefs are among the most contentious areas of recent Kant scholarship.[183][184][185] While few, if any, dispute the overt racism and chauvinism present in his work, a more contested question is the degree to which it degrades or invalidates his other contributions. His most severe critics assert that Kant intentionally manipulated science to support chattel slavery and discrimination.[186][187][183] Others acknowledge that he lived in an era of immature science, with many erroneous beliefs, some racist, all appearing decades before evolution, molecular genetics, and other sciences that today are taken for granted.[183][184][188][189]

Kant was one of the most notable Enlightenment thinkers to defend racism. Although many of these views were common at the time, some have claimed that he was one of the central figures in the birth of the since-discredited pseudoscience known as scientific racism.[190] Where figures such as Carl Linnaeus and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach had supposed only "empirical" observation for racism, Kant produced a fully developed theory of race. Using the four temperaments of ancient Greece, he proposed a hierarchy of four racial categories: white Europeans, yellow Asians, black Africans, and red Americans.[191][192][193][194] Although he was a proponent of scientific racism for much of his career, Kant's views on race changed significantly in the last decade of his life, and he ultimately rejected racial hierarchies and European colonialism in Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795).[185][195][196][g]

Kant was an opponent of miscegenation, believing that whites would be "degraded" and that "fusing of races" is undesirable, for "not every race adopts the morals and customs of the Europeans." He states that "instead of assimilation, which was intended by the melting together of the various races, nature has here made a law of just the opposite."[198] He believed that in the future all races would be extinguished, except that of the whites.[196]

Kant was also an anti-Semite, believing that Jews were incapable of transcending material forces, which a moral order required. In this way, Jews are presented as the opposite of autonomous, rational Christians, and therefore incapable of being incorporated into an ethical Christian society. In his "Anthropology", Kant called the Jews "a nation of cheaters" and portrayed them as "a group that has followed not the path of transcendental freedom but that of enslavement to the material world".[199]

Charles W. Mills wrote that Kant has been "sanitized for public consumption", his racist works conveniently ignored.[196] Robert Bernasconi stated that Kant "supplied the first scientific definition of race". Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze is credited with bringing Kant's contributions to racism to light in the 1990s among Western philosophers, who he believed often glossed over this part of his life and works.[193]

Pauline Kleingeld argues that, while Kant "did defend a racial hierarchy until at least the end of the 1780s", his views on race changed significantly in works published in the last decade of his life. In particular, she argues that Kant rejected past views related to racial hierarchies and the diminished rights or moral status of non-whites in Perpetual Peace (1795). This work also saw him providing extended arguments against European colonialism, which he claimed was morally unjust and incompatible with the equal rights held by indigenous populations. Kleingeld argues that this shift in Kant's views later in life has often been forgotten or ignored in the literature on Kant's racist anthropology, and that the shift suggests a belated recognition of the fact that racial hierarchy was incompatible with a universalized moral framework.[185]

While Kant's racist rhetoric is indicative of the state of scholarship and science during the 18th century, German philosopher Daniel-Pascal Zorn explains the risk of taking period quotations out of context. Many of Kant's most outrageous quotations are from a series of articles from 1777–1788, a public exchange among Kant, Herder, natural scientist Georg Forster, and other scholars prominent in that period.[200][201][202] Kant asserts that all races of humankind are of the same species, challenging the position of Forster and others that the races were distinct species. While his commentary is clearly biased at times, certain extreme statements were patterned specifically to paraphrase or counter Forster and other authors.[183][184] By considering the full arc of Kant's scholarship, Zorn notes the progression in both his philosophical and his anthropological works, "with which he argues, against the zeitgeist, for the unity of humanity".[184]

Influence and legacy

 
Poster celebrating the 300 years of the University of Königsberg, 1844. Among others, Kant and Herbart are honored.

Kant's influence on Western thought has been profound.[h] Although the basic tenets of Kant's transcendental idealism (i.e., that space and time are a priori forms of human perception rather than real properties and the claim that formal logic and transcendental logic coincide) have been claimed to be falsified by modern science and logic,[203][204][205] and no longer set the intellectual agenda of contemporary philosophers, Kant is credited with having innovated the way philosophical inquiry has been carried at least up to the early nineteenth century. This shift consisted in several closely related innovations that, although highly contentious in themselves, have become important in subsequent philosophy and in the social sciences broadly construed:

  • The human subject seen as the center of inquiry into human knowledge, such that it is impossible to philosophize about things as they exist independently of human perception or of how they are "for us";[206]
  • the notion that is possible to discover and systematically explore the inherent limits to our ability to know entirely a priori;
  • the notion of the "categorical imperative", an assertion that people are naturally endowed with the ability and obligation toward right reason and acting. Perhaps his most famous quote is drawn from the Critique of Practical Reason: "Two things fill my mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence...: the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me";[207]
  • the concept of "conditions of possibility", as in his notion of "the conditions of possible experience"; that is, that things, knowledge, and forms of consciousness rest on prior conditions that make them possible, so that, to understand or to know them, we must first understand these conditions;
  • the claim that objective experience is actively constituted or constructed by the functioning of the human mind;
  • the concept of moral autonomy as central to humanity; and
  • the assertion of the principle that human beings should be treated as ends rather than as mere means.

Kant's ideas have been incorporated into a variety of schools of thought. These include German idealism, Marxism, positivism, phenomenology, existentialism, critical theory, linguistic philosophy, structuralism, post-structuralism, and deconstruction.[citation needed]

Historical influence

During his own life, much critical attention was paid to Kant's thought. He influenced Reinhold, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and Novalis during the 1780s and 1790s.

 
Statue of Immanuel Kant in Kaliningrad (Königsberg), Russia. Replica by Harald Haacke [de] of the original by Christian Daniel Rauch lost in 1945.

Samuel Taylor Coleridge was greatly influenced by Kant and helped to spread awareness of him, and of German Idealism generally, in the UK and the USA. In his Biographia Literaria (1817), he credits Kant's ideas in coming to believe that the mind is not a passive, but an active agent in the apprehension of reality.

Hegel was one of Kant's first major critics. In Hegel's view the entire project of setting a "transcendental subject" (i.e., human consciousness) apart from nature, history, and society was fundamentally flawed,[208] although parts of that very project could be put to good use in a new direction. Similar concerns motivated Hegel's criticisms to Kant's concept of moral autonomy, to which Hegel opposed an ethic focused on the "ethical life" of the community.[i] In a sense, Hegel's notion of "ethical life" is meant to subsume, rather than replace, Kantian ethics. And Hegel can be seen as trying to defend Kant's idea of freedom as going beyond finite "desires", by means of reason. Thus, in contrast to later critics like Nietzsche or Russell, Hegel shares some of Kant's concerns.[j]

Kant's thinking on religion was used in Britain to challenge the decline in religious faith in the nineteenth century. British Catholic writers, notably G. K. Chesterton and Hilaire Belloc, followed this approach. Criticisms of Kant were common in the realist views of the new positivism at that time.

Arthur Schopenhauer was strongly influenced by Kant's transcendental idealism. He, like G. E. Schulze, Jacobi, and Fichte before him, was critical of Kant's theory of the thing-in-itself. Things-in-themselves, they argued, are neither the cause of what we observe, nor are they completely beyond our access. Ever since the Critique of Pure Reason philosophers have been critical of Kant's theory of the thing-in-itself. Many have argued, if such a thing exists beyond experience, then one cannot posit that it affects us causally, since that would entail stretching the category "causality" beyond the realm of experience.[k]

With the success and wide influence of Hegel's writings, Kant's influence began to wane, though there was in Germany a movement that hailed a return to Kant in the 1860s, beginning with the publication of Kant und die Epigonen in 1865 by Otto Liebmann. His motto was "Back to Kant", and a re-examination of his ideas began. During the turn of the twentieth century there was an important revival of Kant's theoretical philosophy, known as the Marburg School, represented in the work of Hermann Cohen, Paul Natorp, Ernst Cassirer,[209] and anti-Neo-Kantian Nicolai Hartmann.[l]

 
Weimar Republic stamp honoring Kant, 1926.

Kant's notion of "critique" has been quite influential. The early German Romantics, especially Friedrich Schlegel in his "Athenaeum Fragments", used Kant's reflexive conception of criticism in their Romantic theory of poetry.[210] Also in aesthetics, Clement Greenberg, in his classic essay "Modernist Painting", uses Kantian criticism, what Greenberg refers to as "immanent criticism", to justify the aims of abstract painting, a movement Greenberg saw as aware of the key limitation – flatness – that makes up the medium of painting.[211]

French philosopher Michel Foucault was also greatly influenced by Kant's notion of "critique" and wrote several pieces on Kant for a re-thinking of the Enlightenment as a form of "critical thought". He went so far as to classify his own philosophy as a "critical history of modernity, rooted in Kant".[212]

Kant believed that mathematical truths were forms of synthetic a priori knowledge, which means they are necessary and universal, yet known through the a priori intuition of space and time, as transcendental preconditions of experience.[213] Kant's often brief remarks about mathematics influenced the mathematical school known as intuitionism, a movement in philosophy of mathematics opposed to Hilbert's formalism, and Frege and Bertrand Russell's logicism.[m]

Influence on modern thinkers

 
West German postage stamp, 1974, commemorating the 250th anniversary of Kant's birth

With his Perpetual Peace, Kant is considered to have foreshadowed many of the ideas that have come to form the democratic peace theory, one of the main controversies in political science.[214]

Prominent recent Kantians include the British philosophers P. F. Strawson,[n] Onora O'Neill,[215] and Quassim Cassam,[216] and the American philosophers Wilfrid Sellars[217] and Christine Korsgaard.[o] Due to the influence of Strawson and Sellars, among others, there has been a renewed interest in Kant's view of the mind. Central to many debates in philosophy of psychology and cognitive science is Kant's conception of the unity of consciousness.[p]

Jürgen Habermas and John Rawls are two significant political and moral philosophers whose work is strongly influenced by Kant's moral philosophy.[q] They argued against relativism,[218] supporting the Kantian view that universality is essential to any viable moral philosophy.

Mou Zongsan's study of Kant has been cited as a highly crucial part in the development of Mou's personal philosophy, namely New Confucianism. Widely regarded as the most influential Kant scholar in China, Mou's rigorous critique of Kant's philosophy – having translated all three of Kant's critiques – served as an ardent attempt to reconcile Chinese and Western philosophy whilst increasing pressure to westernize in China.[219][220]

 
East German commemorative coin honoring Kant, 1974

Kant's influence also has extended to the social, behavioral, and physical sciences, as in the sociology of Max Weber, the psychology of Jean Piaget, and Carl Gustav Jung,[221][222] and the linguistics of Noam Chomsky. Kant's work on mathematics and synthetic a priori knowledge is also cited by theoretical physicist Albert Einstein as an early influence on his intellectual development, though one which he later criticized and rejected.[223] In recent years, there has also been renewed interest in Kant's theory of mind from the point of view of formal logic and computer science.[224]

Because of the thoroughness of Kant's paradigm shift, his influence extends well beyond this to thinkers who neither specifically refer to his work nor use his terminology.

Bibliography

Unless otherwise noted, all citations are to The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in English Translation, 16 vols., ed. Guyer, Paul, and Wood, Allen W. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. Citations in the article are to individual works per abbreviations in List of Major works below.

  • Lectures on Logic. Ed. and trans. J. Michael Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
  • Opus postumum. Ed. Eckart Förster, trans. Eckart Förster and Michael Rosen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993
  • Practical Philosophy. Ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
  • Religion and Rational Theology. Ed. and trans.Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996
  • Lectures on Metaphysics. Ed. and trans. Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • Lectures on Ethics. Ed. Peter Heath and J.B. Schneewind, trans. Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • Correspondence. Ed. and trans. Arnulf Zweig. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
  • Critique of the Power of Judgment. Ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
  • Theoretical Philosophy after 1781. Ed. Henry Allison and Peter Heath, trans. Gary Hatfield, Michael Friedman, Henry Allison, and Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
  • Notes and Fragments. Ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Curtis Bowman, Paul Guyer, and Frederick Rauscher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.
  • Anthropology, History, and Education, Ed. Günter Zöller and Robert B. Louden (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
  • Lectures on Anthropology, Ed. Allen W. Wood and Robert B. Louden (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
  • Natural Science, Ed. by Eric Watkins (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).

List of major works

Abbreviations used in body of article are boldface in brackets. Unless otherwise noted, pagination is to the critical Akademie edition, which can be found in the margins of the Cambridge translations.

Collected works in German

Wilhelm Dilthey inaugurated the Academy edition (the Akademie-Ausgabe abbreviated as AA or Ak) of Kant's writings (Gesammelte Schriften, Königlich-Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin, 1902–38) in 1895,[249] and served as its first editor. The volumes are grouped into four sections:

  • I. Kant's published writings (vols. 1–9),
  • II. Kant's correspondence (vols. 10–13),
  • III. Kant's literary remains, or Nachlass (vols. 14–23), and
  • IV. Student notes from Kant's lectures (vols. 24–29).

An electronic version is also available: (vols. 1–23).

Notes

  1. ^ Kant himself seems to have found his contribution not significant enough that he published his arguments in a newspaper commentary on the prize question and did not submit them to the Academy: "Whether the Earth has Undergone an Alteration of its Axial Rotation". Kant's Cosmogony. Translated by Hastie, William. Glasgow: James Maclehose. 1900 [1754]. pp. 1–11. Retrieved 29 March 2022.. The prize was instead awarded in 1756 to P. Frisi, who incorrectly argued against the slowing down of the spin.[21]
  2. ^ Since he had written his last habilitation thesis 14 years earlier, a new habilitation thesis was required (see S.J. McGrath, Joseph Carew (eds.), Rethinking German Idealism, Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, p. 24).
  3. ^ It has been noted that in 1778, in response to one of these offers by a former pupil, Kant wrote, "Any change makes me apprehensive, even if it offers the greatest promise of improving my condition, and I am persuaded by this natural instinct of mine that I must take heed if I wish that the threads which the Fates spin so thin and weak in my case to be spun to any length. My great thanks, to my well-wishers and friends, who think so kindly of me as to undertake my welfare, but at the same time a most humble request to protect me in my current condition from any disturbance."[31]
  4. ^ More technically, Kant puts his general point that all genuine knowledge requires both sensory input and intellectual organization by saying that all knowledge requires both "intuitions" and "concepts" (e.g., A 50 / B 74). Intuitions and concepts are two different species of the genus "representation" (Vorstellung), Kant's most general term for any cognitive state (see A 320 / B 376–7). At the outset of the "Transcendental Aesthetic", Kant states that an "intuition" is our most direct or "immediate" kind of representation of objects, in contrast to a "concept" which always represents an object "through a detour (indirecte)"—that is, merely by some "mark" or property that the object has (A 19 / B 33). In his logic textbook, Kant defines an intuition as a "singular representation"—that is, one that represents a particular object—while a concept is always a "universal (repraesentation per notas communes)", which represents properties common to many objects (Logic, §1, 9:91).[74]
  5. ^ Beardsley, Monroe. "History of Aesthetics". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 1, section on "Toward a unified aesthetics", p. 25, Macmillan 1973. Baumgarten coined the term "aesthetics" and expanded, clarified, and unified Wolffian aesthetic theory, but had left the Aesthetica unfinished (See also: Tonelli, Giorgio. "Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 1, Macmillan 1973). In Bernard's translation of the Critique of Judgment he indicates in the notes that Kant's reference in § 15 in regard to the identification of perfection and beauty is probably a reference to Baumgarten.
  6. ^ Kant's general discussions of the distinction between "cognition" and "conscious of" are also given in the Critique of Pure Reason (notably A320/B376), and section V and the conclusion of section VIII of his Introduction in Logic.
  7. ^ Kant wrote that "[Whites] contain all the impulses of nature in affects and passions, all talents, all dispositions to culture and civilization and can as readily obey as govern. They are the only ones who always advance to perfection." He describes South Asians as "educated to the highest degree but only in the arts and not in the sciences". He goes on that Hindustanis can never reach the level of abstract concepts and that a "great hindustani man" is one who has "gone far in the art of deception and has much money". He states that the Hindus always stay the way they are and can never advance. About black Africans, Kant wrote that "they can be educated but only as servants, that is they allow themselves to be trained". To Kant, "the Negro can be disciplined and cultivated, but is never genuinely civilized. He falls of his own accord into savagery." Native Americans, Kant opined, "cannot be educated". He calls them unmotivated, lacking affect, passion and love, and describes them as too weak for labor, unfit for any culture, and too phlegmatic for diligence. He said that Native Americans are "far below the Negro, who undoubtedly holds the lowest of all remaining levels by which we designate the different races". Kant stated that "Americans and Blacks cannot govern themselves. They thus serve only for slaves."[196][197]
  8. ^ Prof. Oliver A. Johnson claims, "With the possible exception of Plato's Republic, (Critique of Pure Reason) is the most important philosophical book ever written." Article on Kant within the collection Great thinkers of the Western World, Ian P. McGreal, Ed., HarperCollins, 1992.
  9. ^ Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Natural Law: The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, Its Place in Moral Philosophy, and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences. trans. T. M. Knox. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1975. Hegel's mature view and his concept of "ethical life" is elaborated in his Philosophy of Right. Hegel, Philosophy of Right. trans. T. M. Knox. Oxford University Press, 1967.
  10. ^ Robert Pippin's Hegel's Idealism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) emphasizes the continuity of Hegel's concerns with Kant's. Robert Wallace, Hegel's Philosophy of Reality, Freedom, and God (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) explains how Hegel's Science of Logic defends Kant's idea of freedom as going beyond finite "inclinations", contra skeptics such as David Hume.
  11. ^ For a review of this problem and the relevant literature see The Thing in Itself and the Problem of Affection in the revised edition of Henry Allison's Kant's Transcendental Idealism.
  12. ^ Cerf, Walter. "Nicolai Hartmann". In Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 3–4. Macmillan, 1973. Nicolai was a realist who later rejected the idealism of Neo-Kantianism, his anti-Neo-Kantian views emerging with the publication of the second volume of Hegel (1929).
  13. ^ Körner, Stephan, The Philosophy of Mathematics, Dover, 1986. For an analysis of Kant's writings on mathematics see, Friedman, Michael, Kant and the Exact Sciences, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1992.
  14. ^ Strawson, P. F., The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Routledge: 2004. When first published in 1966, this book forced many Anglo-American philosophers to reconsider Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.
  15. ^ Korsgaard, Christine. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996.ISBN 978-0-521-49644-5 Not a commentary, but a defense of a broadly Kantian approach to ethics.
  16. ^ Brook, Andrew. Kant and the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. See also, Meerbote, R. "Kant's Functionalism". In: J. C. Smith, ed. Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel, 1991. Brook has an article on Kant's View of the Mind in the Stanford Encyclopedia 9 July 2010 at the Wayback Machine
  17. ^ See Habermas, J. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1996. For Rawls see, Rawls, John. Theory of Justice Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1971. Rawls has a well-known essay on Kant's concept of good. See, Rawls, "Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy" in Kant's Transcendental Deductions. Ed. Eckart Förster. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989.
  18. ^ vailable online at Bonner Kant-Korpus 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  19. ^ As noted by Allen W. Wood in his Introduction, p. 12. Wood further speculates that the lectures themselves were delivered in the Winter of 1783–84.

References

Citations

  1. ^ "Kant" 27 September 2019 at the Wayback Machine. Collins English Dictionary.
  2. ^ "Kant" 23 October 2014 at the Wayback Machine. Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary.
  3. ^ Wells, John C. (2008). Longman Pronunciation Dictionary (3rd ed.). Longman. ISBN 978-1-4058-8118-0.
  4. ^ Jones, Daniel (2011). Roach, Peter; Setter, Jane; Esling, John (eds.). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (18th ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-15255-6.
  5. ^ "Immanuel". Duden (in German). from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 20 October 2018.
  6. ^ "Kant". Duden (in German). from the original on 20 October 2018. Retrieved 20 October 2018.
  7. ^ "Cosmopolis". Koenigsberg-is-dead.de. 23 April 2001. from the original on 22 March 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  8. ^ R.K. Murray, "The Origin of Immanuel Kant's Family Name", Kantian Review 13(1), March 2008, pp. 190–93.
  9. ^ Rosa Kohlheim, Volker Kohlheim, Duden – Familiennamen: Herkunft und Bedeutung von 20.000 Nachnamen, Bibliographisches Institut & F.A. Brockhaus AG, Mannheim 2005, p. 365.
  10. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 26.
  11. ^ Haupt, Viktor. (PDF). freunde-kants.com (in German). p. 7. Archived from the original on 25 September 2015.
  12. ^ Pasternack, Lawrence; Fugate, Courtney (2020). "Kant's Philosophy of Religion". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 25 February 2021.
  13. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 47.
  14. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 169.
  15. ^ The American International Encyclopedia (New York: J.J. Little & Ives, 1954), Vol. IX.
  16. ^ Porter, Burton (2010). What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. p. 133.
  17. ^ "Die Freimaurer im Alten Preußen 1738–1806" (PDF) (in German). (PDF) from the original on 19 November 2020.
  18. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 94.
  19. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 98.
  20. ^ Eric Watkins (ed.), Immanuel Kant: Natural Science, Cambridge University Press, 2012: "Thoughts on the true estimation..." 7 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  21. ^ Schönfeld, Martin (2000). The Philosophy of the Young Kant: The Precritical Project. Oxford University Press. p. 84. ISBN 978-0-19-513218-2.
  22. ^ a b Brush, Stephen G. (2014). A History of Modern Planetary Physics: Nebulous Earth. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-521-44171-1.
  23. ^ See:
    • Kant, I. (1756a) "Von den Ursachen der Erderschütterungen bei Gelegenheit des Unglücks, welches die westliche Länder von Europa gegen das Ende des vorigen Jahres betroffen hat" [On the causes of the earthquakes on the occasion of the disaster which affected the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year] In: Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences), ed.s (1902) Kant's gesammelte Schriften [Kant's collected writings] (in German) Berlin, Germany: G. Reimer. vol. 1, pp. 417–427.
    • Kant, I. (1756b) "Geschichte und Naturbeschreibung der merkwürdigsten Vorfälle des Erdbebens, welches an dem Ende des 1755sten Jahres einen großen Theil der Erde erschüttert hat" [History and description of the nature of the most remarkable events of the earthquake which shook a large part of the Earth at the end of the year 1755], ibid. pp. 429–461.
    • Kant, I. (1756c) "Immanuel Kants fortgesetzte Betrachtung der seit einiger Zeit wahrgenommenen Erderschütterungen" [Immanuel Kant's continued consideration of the earthquakes that were felt some time ago], ibid. pp. 463–472.
    • Amador, Filomena (2004) "The causes of 1755 Lisbon earthquake on Kant" In: Escribano Benito, J.J.; Español González, L.; Martínez García, M.A., ed.s. Actas VIII Congreso de la Sociedad Española de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Técnicas [Proceedings of the Eighth Congress of the Spanish Society of the History of the Sciences and Technology] (in English) Logroño, Spain: Sociedad Española de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Técnicas (Universidad de la Rioja), vol. 2, pp. 485–495.
  24. ^ a b Richards, Paul (1974). "Kant's Geography and Mental Maps". Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers (61): 1–16. doi:10.2307/621596. JSTOR 621596.
  25. ^ Elden, Stuart (2009). "Reassessing Kant's geography" (PDF). Journal of Historical Geography. 35 (1): 3–25. doi:10.1016/j.jhg.2008.06.001. (PDF) from the original on 1 August 2020. Retrieved 27 September 2019.
  26. ^ Gamow, George (1947). One Two Three... Infinity. New York: Viking P. pp. 300ff.
  27. ^ Cf., for example, Susan Shell, The Embodiment of Reason (Chicago, 1996)
  28. ^ Kuehn, Manfred (2009). Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Background Source Materials. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. p. 276. ISBN 978-0-521-78162-6.
  29. ^ a b Smith, Homer W. (1952). Man and His Gods. New York: Grosset & Dunlap. p. 404.
  30. ^ Kant, PFM 4:260
  31. ^ Christopher Kul-Want and Andrzej Klimowski, Introducing Kant (Cambridge: Icon Books, 2005).[page needed] ISBN 978-1-84046-664-5
  32. ^ Smith, Homer W. (1952). Man and His Gods. New York: Grosset & Dunlap. p. 416.
  33. ^ Dorrien, Gary (2012). Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit: The Idealistic Logic of Modern Theology. Malden, MA: John Wiley & Sons. p. 37. ISBN 978-0-470-67331-7.
  34. ^ Kuehn 2001, pp. 250–54.
  35. ^ Copleston, Frederick Charles (2003). The Enlightenment: Voltaire to Kant. p. 146.
  36. ^ Sassen, Brigitte. Kant's Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy. 2000.
  37. ^ Ein Jahrhundert deutscher Literaturkritik, vol. III, Der Aufstieg zur Klassik in der Kritik der Zeit (Berlin, 1959), p. 315; as quoted in Gulyga, Arsenij. Immanuel Kant: His Life and Thought. Trans., Marijan Despaltović. Boston: Birkhäuser, 1987.
  38. ^ Kuehn 2001, pp. 268–69.
  39. ^ Guyer, Paul (2006). The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. p. 631. ISBN 978-0-521-82303-6.
  40. ^ a b Werner S. Pluhar, Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 4 March 2020 at the Wayback Machine. 2009. Description 1 February 2020 at the Wayback Machine & Contents. With an Introduction 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine by Stephen Palmquist. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,
  41. ^ a b c d e Derrida, Vacant Chair p. 44.
  42. ^ "Open letter by Kant denouncing Fichte's Philosophy". Korpora.org (in German). from the original on 19 July 2011. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  43. ^ Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 1, (HUP, 1960), 'Kant and his Refutation of Idealism' p. 15
  44. ^ Kant, Immanuel, Logic, G.B. Jäsche (ed), R.S. Hartman, W. Schwarz (translators), Indianapolis, 1984, p. xv.
  45. ^ Karl Vorländer, Immanuel Kant: Der Mann und das Werk, Hamburg: Meiner, 1992, p. II 332.
  46. ^ "Heine on Immanuel Kant" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 23 November 2015. Retrieved 10 July 2015.
  47. ^ Examined Lives, From Socrates to Nietzsche, James Miller p. 284
  48. ^ Immanuel Kant and the Bo(a)rders of Art History Mark Cheetham, in The Subjects of Art History: Historical Objects in Contemporary Perspectives, p. 16
  49. ^ Beyer, Susanne (25 July 2014). "Resurrecting Königsberg: Russian City Looks to German Roots". Spiegel Online. from the original on 4 February 2018. Retrieved 3 February 2018.
  50. ^ "Executive order on establishing Immanuel Kant University".
  51. ^ Kant CPuR Bxxviii–Bxxx
  52. ^ di Giovanni 2005.
  53. ^ Rohlf 2020, §2.1.
  54. ^ Kant, CPuR A804–05/B833
  55. ^ Kant, CPuR Bxxx
  56. ^ Guyer 2014, pp. 7–8.
  57. ^ Jankowiak 2023.
  58. ^ Guyer 2014, pp. 6–8.
  59. ^ di Giovanni, George. (1996) "Translator's Introduction", In Religion and Rational Theology. Cambridge University Press. p.49, citing Kant in correspondence with Stäudlin.
  60. ^ Rohlf 2020.
  61. ^ "Immanuel Kant (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". from the original on 14 November 2019. Retrieved 29 May 2019.
  62. ^ Kant, CPuR B135
  63. ^ Guyer 2014, p. 51.
  64. ^ Kant, CPuR B1–3
  65. ^ Kant, CPuR A6–8/B10–12
  66. ^ a b Guyer 2014, pp. 52–54.
  67. ^ Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Section 4; Part 1.
  68. ^ Kant, CPuR B3–4
  69. ^ Kant, CPuR B14–17
  70. ^ Guyer 2014, p. 55.
  71. ^ Kant, CPuR A15/B29, emphases added
  72. ^ Guyer 2014, pp. 32, 61.
  73. ^ Rohlf 2020, §2.12.
  74. ^ Guyer 2014, pp. 60–61.
  75. ^ Kant, CPuR A51/B75
  76. ^ Kant, CPuR Bxvi–xviii
  77. ^ Rohlf 2020, §2.2.
  78. ^ Jankowiak 2023, 2(g).
  79. ^ Guyer 2014, ch. 4.
  80. ^ Kant, CPuR B21
  81. ^ Kant, CPuR Axi–xii
  82. ^ Jankowiak 2023, §2(d).
  83. ^ a b Rohlf 2020, §3.
  84. ^ Kant CPuR A43/B59–60, A369
  85. ^ Kant CPuR A28/B44, A34–35/B51–51
  86. ^ Stang 2022, §2.3.
  87. ^ Guyer 2014, p. 60.
  88. ^ Rohlf 2020, §§3.1–3.2.
  89. ^ Stang 2022, §§4–5.
  90. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, pp. 4–13.
  91. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 8.
  92. ^ Guyer 2014, pp. 89–90.
  93. ^ Kant, CPuR Axi
  94. ^ Jankowiak 2023, §2(e).
  95. ^ Rohlf 2020, §4.
  96. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 9.
  97. ^ Kant, CPuR B131-32
  98. ^ Rohlf 2020, §4.1.
  99. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, pp. 9–10.
  100. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, pp. 10–11.
  101. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 11.
  102. ^ see Kant, CPuR A182–26/B224–36
  103. ^ see Kant, CPuR A186–211/B232–56
  104. ^ see Kant, CPuR A211-15/B256-62
  105. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, pp. 11–12.
  106. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 12.
  107. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, pp. 12–13.
  108. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 13.
  109. ^ Kant, CPuR A5/B8
  110. ^ a b Jankowiak 2023, §2(g).
  111. ^ a b Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 15.
  112. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 14.
  113. ^ Jankowiak 2023, §2(g.i).
  114. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 16.
  115. ^ a b Jankowiak 2023, §2(g.ii).
  116. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, pp. 16–17.
  117. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 17.
  118. ^ Jankowiak 2023, §2(g.iii).
  119. ^ Guyer & Wood 1998, p. 18.
  120. ^ Kant, CPuR A806/B834
  121. ^ a b c Kant, CPuR A448/B467
  122. ^ Kant, CPuR A533–34/B561–62
  123. ^ Kant, CPuR A800–02/B 828–30
  124. ^ Susanne Bobzien, 'Die Kategorien der Freiheit bei Kant', in Kant: Analysen, Probleme, Kritik Vol. 1, 1988, 193–220.
  125. ^ Driver 2007, p. 83.
  126. ^ Johnson 2008.
  127. ^ Schneewind 2010, p. 261.
  128. ^ Kant, G. 4:420–21, 436.
  129. ^ Wood, Allen. (2017) Formulas of the Moral Law. Cambridge University Press, pp.74–78
  130. ^ a b Kant, G 4:421
  131. ^ Kant, G 4:429
  132. ^ Kant, G 4:431; cf. 4:432
  133. ^ Kant, G 4:440; cf. 4:432, 434, 438
  134. ^ Kant, G 4:439; cf. 4:433, 437–39
  135. ^ Wood, Allen. (2017) Formulas of the Moral Law. Cambridge University Press, p.6
  136. ^ Caygill, Howard. (1995) A Kant Dictionary. Blackwell Publishing, p. 289, citing GMM.
  137. ^ Kant, G 4:403.
  138. ^ Driver 2007, p. 88.
  139. ^ Kant, GMM 4:392.
  140. ^ Gregor, Mary J. (1996) "Translator's note on the text of The metaphysics of morals". In Practical Philosophy. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, p. 355.
  141. ^ a b Wood 2006, p. 68.
  142. ^ Kant, MM. 6:382–91.
  143. ^ Wood 2006, p. 69.
  144. ^ Wood 2006, p. 70.
  145. ^ Kant, PP 8:349–53
  146. ^ Manfred Riedel, Between Tradition and Revolution: The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy, Cambridge 1984
  147. ^ Kant, PP 8:360–62
  148. ^ Hassner, Pierre. "Immanuel Kant", in History of Political Philosophy, edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, The University of Chicago Press, 1987, pp. 581–582
  149. ^ Hassner, Pierre. "Immanuel Kant", in History of Political Philosophy, edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, The University of Chicago Press, 1987, p. 603
  150. ^ Kant, PP 8:352
  151. ^ Kant, MM 6:355
  152. ^ Gregor, Mary J. "Introduction", in Practical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, p. 313
  153. ^ Ripstein, Arthur. (2009) Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy. Harvard University Press, pp. 9.
  154. ^ Karl Leonhard Reinhold, Letters on the Kantian Philosophy (1786), 3rd Letter
  155. ^ Johann Schultz, Exposition of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1784), 141.
  156. ^ Kant, RBMR Part IV, First part, First section [6:157–63]
  157. ^ E.g., Walsh, W. H., 1967, "Kant, Immanuel: Philosophy of Religion", The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume Four, Paul Edwards (ed.), New York: Macmillan Publishing Co. Inc. & The Free Press, 322.
  158. ^ Pasternack, Lawrence; Rossi, Philip. "Kant's Philosophy of Religion". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 9 July 2010. Retrieved 18 October 2019.
  159. ^ For example Peter Byrne, who wrote about Kant's relationship with deism. Byrne, Peter (2007), Kant on God, London: Ashgate, p. 159.
  160. ^ Wood, Allen W. (1970), Kant's moral religion, London and Ithaca: Cornell University Press, p. 16.
  161. ^ Westphal, Merold (2010), The Emerge of Modern Philosophy of Religion, in Taliaferro, Charles, Draper, Paul and Quinn, Philip (editors), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 135.
  162. ^ Iţu, Mircia (2004), Dumnezeu şi religia în concepţia lui Immanuel Kant din Religia în limitele raţiunii, in Boboc, Alexandru and Mariş, N.I. (editors), Studii de istoria filosofiei universale, volume 12, Bucharest: Romanian Academy.
  163. ^ Wood, Allen W. (2020), Kant and Religion, Cambridge University Press, p.2.
  164. ^ See e.g., Lawrence Pasternack, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason (New York, Routledge, 2014), pp.239–240.
  165. ^ Palmquist, Stephen (1992), "Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality?", Kant-Studien 83.2, pp. 129–148.
  166. ^ Critique of Judgment in "Kant, Immanuel" Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol 4. Macmillan, 1973.
  167. ^ Kant, CPuR A22/B36
  168. ^ German Idealism in "History of Aesthetics" Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol 1. Macmillan, 1973.
  169. ^ Kant, CPJ §1
  170. ^ Kant, CPJ §§ 20–22
  171. ^ Kant, CPJ §40
  172. ^ Clewis, Robert (2009). "The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom". Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. from the original on 20 October 2012. Retrieved 8 December 2011.
  173. ^ Kant, CPJ §§23–25
  174. ^ Kant, CPJ §§25–26
  175. ^ Kant, CPJ §54
  176. ^ Jakobidze-Gitman, Alexander (2020). "Kant's Situated Approach to Musicking and Joking". Journal of Interdisciplinary Music Studies. 10: 17–33. doi:10.25364/24.10:2020.2.
  177. ^ Kant, UH 8:20–22
  178. ^ Kant, UH 8:24–26.
  179. ^ Wilson, Holly (2006). Kant's Pragmatic Anthropology. Albany: State University of New York Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-7914-6849-4.
  180. ^ Thomas Sturm, Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen (Paderborn: Mentis Verlag, 2009).
  181. ^ Kant APPV 7:285
  182. ^ Kant APPV 7:119
  183. ^ a b c d Mikkelsen, Jon M., ed. (2013). Kant and the Concept of Race. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press. pp. 12–30. ISBN 9781438443614.
  184. ^ a b c d Zorn, Daniel-Pascal (2020). "Kant—a Racist?". Public History Weekly. 2020 (8). doi:10.1515/phw-2020-17156. ISSN 2197-6376.
  185. ^ a b c Kleingeld 2007, pp. 573–92.
  186. ^ Eze, Emmanuel (1997). "The Color of Reason: The Idea of 'Race' in Kant's Anthropology". In Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (ed.). Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader. Blackwell. pp. 103–140. Retrieved 20 April 2023.
  187. ^ Serequeberhan, T. (1996). "Eurocentrism in philosophy : The case of Immanuel Kant". The Philosophical Forum.
  188. ^ "The Philosophy Junkie: Immanuel Kant's Racism and Sexism with Professors Lucy Allais and Helga Varden on Apple Podcasts". Apple Podcasts. Retrieved 20 April 2023.
  189. ^ Geismann, Georg (1 January 2022). "Why Kant Was Not a 'Racist'". Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik / Annual Review of Law and Ethics. 30 (1): 263–357. doi:10.3790/jre.30.1.263. ISSN 0944-4610.
  190. ^ Bernasconi, Robert (1 January 2002). "Kant as an Unfamiliar Source of Racism". In Ward, Julie K.; Lott, Tommy L. (eds.). Philosophers on Race: Critical Essays. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers Ltd. pp. 145–166. doi:10.1002/9780470753514.ch8. ISBN 978-0-470-75351-4. Retrieved 21 April 2023.
  191. ^ Eze 1997a, pp. 103–31.
  192. ^ Eze 1997b, pp. 39–48.
  193. ^ a b Bouie 2018.
  194. ^ Bernasconi 2010, pp. 141–48.
  195. ^ Kant 2010.
  196. ^ a b c d Mills 2017, pp. 169–93.
  197. ^ Bowersox 2016.
  198. ^ Kant APPV 7:320
  199. ^ Shrage 2019.
  200. ^ Mikkelsen, Jon M., ed. (2013). Kant and the Concept of Race: late eighteenth-century writings. Jon M. Mikkelsen. Albany. ISBN 978-1-4619-4312-9. OCLC 861693001.
  201. ^ Kuehn 2001, pp. 298–301, 343–45.
  202. ^ cf. Kant, DCHR 8:91-106
  203. ^ Strawson, Peter. Bounds of Sense: Essay on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason". ASIN 0415040302.
  204. ^ "Einstein on Kant". University of Pittsburgh. from the original on 9 August 2020. Retrieved 2 September 2020.
  205. ^ Perrick, Michael (1985). "Kant and Kripke on Necessary Empirical Truths". Mind. 94 (376): 596–598. doi:10.1093/mind/XCIV.376.596. ISSN 0026-4423. JSTOR 2254731.
  206. ^ Stephen Palmquist, "The Architectonic Form of Kant's Copernican Logic", Metaphilosophy 17:4 (October 1986), pp. 266–288; revised and reprinted as Chapter III of Kant's System of Perspectives 14 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine: An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  207. ^ Kant, CPracR 5:161
  208. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1827). Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline. Heidelberg. pp. 14–15.
  209. ^ Beck, Lewis White. "Neo-Kantianism". In Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 5–6. Macmillan, 1973. Article on Neo-Kantianism by a translator and scholar of Kant.
  210. ^ Schlegel, Friedrich. "Athenaeum Fragments", in Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Peter Firchow. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1991. See especially fragments Nos. 1, 43, 44.
  211. ^ Greenberg, Clement. "Modernist Painting", in The Philosophy of Art, ed. Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley, McGraw-Hill, 1995.
  212. ^ See "Essential Works of Foucault: 1954–1984 vol. 2: Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology". Ed. by James Faubion, Trans. Robert Hurley et al. New York City: The New Press, 1998 (2010 reprint). See "Foucault, Michel, 1926 –" entry by Maurice Florence.
  213. ^ For a discussion and qualified defense of this position, see Stephen Palmquist, "A Priori Knowledge in Perspective: (I) Mathematics, Method and Pure Intuition", The Review of Metaphysics 41:1 (September 1987), pp. 3–22.
  214. ^ Ray, James Lee (1998). . Annual Review of Political Science. 1: 27–46. doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.1.1.27. Archived from the original on 17 February 2008.
  215. ^ Aridi, Sara (14 March 2017). "Onora O'Neill Wins Holberg Prize for Academic Research". The New York Times. from the original on 9 January 2019. Retrieved 9 January 2019.
  216. ^ Cassam, Q. The Possibility of Knowledge Oxford: 2009
  217. ^ Sellars, Wilfrid, Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes. Ridgeview Publishing Company, 1967
  218. ^ Habermas, J. (1994): The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of Its Voices. In: Habermas, J. (Eds.): Postmetaphysical Thinking. Political Essays, Cambridge, Massachusetts: 115–148.
  219. ^ Palmquist, Stephen (19 November 2010). Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy (1st ed.). Hong Kong: De Gruyter, Inc. pp. 25. ISBN 978-3-11-022624-9.
  220. ^ Wing‐Cheuk, Chan (21 February 2006). "Mou Zongsan's Transformation of Kant's Philosophy". Journal of Chinese Philosophy. 33 (1): 1. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.2006.00340.x.
  221. ^ Balanovskiy, Valentin (2016). "Whether jung was a kantian?". Con-Textos Kantianos (4): 118–126. doi:10.5281/zenodo.2550828. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 29 May 2020.
  222. ^ Balanovskiy, Valentin (2017). "Kant and Jung on the prospects of Scientific Psychology". Estudos Kantianos. 5 (1): 357–390. doi:10.36311/2318-0501.2017.v5n1.26.p375. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 29 May 2020.
  223. ^ Issacson, Walter. "Einstein: His Life and Universe". p. 20.
  224. ^ Theodora Achourioti & Michiel van Lambalgen, 'A Formalization of Kant's Transcendental Logic', The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4 (2011), 254–289.
  225. ^ The thesis was submitted on 17 April 1755. "The public examination was held four weeks later on 13 May, and the degree was formally awarded on 12 June" (Eric Watkins, Kant: Natural Science, Cambridge University Press, 2012, p. 309).
  226. ^ Eric Watkins (ed.), Kant and the Sciences, Oxford University Press, 2001, p. 27.
  227. ^ Martin Schonfeld, The Philosophy of the Young Kant: The Precritical Project, Oxford University Press, 2000, p. 74.
  228. ^ Available online at Bonner Kant-Korpus 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  229. ^ The thesis was publicly disputed on 27 September 1755 (Kuehn 2001, p. 100).
  230. ^ Kant's application for the position was unsuccessful. He defended it on 10 April 1756 (Kuehn 2001, p. 102).
  231. ^ Available online at Archive.org.
  232. ^ Immanuel Kant, "Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space" 16 July 2018 at the Wayback Machine.
  233. ^ The thesis was publicly disputed on 21 August 1770 (Kuehn 2001, p. 189).
  234. ^ Available online at Google Books 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine.
  235. ^ English translation available online at Wikisource.
  236. ^ Immanuel Kant. . Etext.library.adelaide.edu.au. Archived from the original on 2 December 2008. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  237. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft – 1. Auflage – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. from the original on 9 June 2007. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  238. ^ Frank-Christian Lilienweihs (10 June 1999). "Immanuel Kant: Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklaerung?". Prometheusonline.de. from the original on 1 August 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  239. ^ "Critique of Pure Reason". Hkbu.edu.hk. 31 October 2003. from the original on 27 April 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  240. ^ "Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft – 2. Auflage – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. 20 July 2009. from the original on 26 December 2005. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  241. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Immanuel Kant: Kritik der praktischen Vernunft – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. from the original on 9 June 2007. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  242. ^ s:The Critique of Judgment
  243. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone by Immanuel Kant 1793". Marxists.org. from the original on 1 June 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  244. ^ "Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace"". Mountr Holyoke. from the original on 6 April 2019. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  245. ^ "Immanuel Kant: Zum ewigen Frieden, 12.02.2004 (Friedensratschlag)". Uni-kassel.de. from the original on 23 September 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  246. ^ "Kant, The Contest of Faculties". Chnm.gmu.edu. 1798. from the original on 4 August 2011. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  247. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Immanuel Kant: Der Streit der Facultäten – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. from the original on 9 June 2007. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  248. ^ Available online at DeutschesTextArchiv.de 10 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  249. ^ Immanuel Kant, Notes and Fragments, Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. xvi.

Works cited

  • Bernasconi, Robert (2010). "Defining Race Scientifically: A response to Michael Banton". Ethnicities. 10 (1): 141–148. doi:10.1177/14687968100100010802. ISSN 1468-7968. JSTOR 23890861. S2CID 143925406.
  • Bouie, Jamelle (5 June 2018). "How the Enlightenment Created Modern Race Thinking and Why We Should Confront It". Slate. from the original on 15 June 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  • Bowersox, Jeff (4 February 2016). "Kant on the different human races (1777)". Black Central Europe. from the original on 16 June 2020. Retrieved 16 June 2020.
  • Caygill, Howard (1995). A Kant Dictionary. Blackwell Publishing.
  • Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (1997a). Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader. Wiley. pp. 103–131. ISBN 978-0-631-20339-1. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  • Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (1997b). Race and the Enlightenment: A Reader. Wiley. pp. 39–48. ISBN 978-0-631-20136-6. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  • Driver, Julia (2007). Ethics: The Fundamentals. Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4051-1154-6.
  • di Giovanni, George (2005). Freedom and Religion in Kant and His Immediate Successors. Cambridge University Press.
  • Guyer, Paul (2014). Kant. Routledge.
  • Guyer, Paul; Wood, Alan W. (1998). "Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason [Editors' Introduction]". The Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press.
  • Jankowiak, Tim (2023). Immanuel Kant. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 4 March 2023.
  • Johnson, Robert (2008). "Kant's Moral Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 11 September 2013.
  • Kant, Immanuel (2010). Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (ed.). "Kant on the Different Races of Man" (PDF). UMass Amherst. (PDF) from the original on 1 August 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  • Kleingeld, Pauline (October 2007). "Kant's Second Thoughts on Race" (PDF). The Philosophical Quarterly. 57 (229): 573–592. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.498.x. hdl:11370/e15b6815-5eab-42d6-a789-24a2f6ecb946. S2CID 55185762. (PDF) from the original on 16 February 2019. Retrieved 14 December 2020.
  • Kuehn, Manfred (2001). Kant: a Biography. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-49704-6.
  • Mills, Charles W. (2017). Black Rights/White Wrongs: The Critique of Racial Liberalism. Oxford University Press. pp. 169–193. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190245412.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-024545-0. from the original on 16 June 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  • Rohlf, Michael (2020). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Immanuel Kant. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition).
  • Schneewind, J. B. (2010). "Autonomy, Obligation, and Virtue: An Overview of Kant's Moral Philosophy". Essays on the History of Moral Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  • Shrage, Laurie (18 March 2019). "Should we continue to teach thinkers like Kant, Voltaire and Hume without mention of the harmful prejudices they helped legitimize?". The New York Times. Retrieved 10 November 2022.
  • Stang, Nicholas F. (2022). Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (ed.). Kant's Transcendental Idealism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 Edition).
  • Wood, Allen (1999). Kant's Ethical Thought. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521648363.
  • Wood, Allen (2006). "Kant's Practical Philosophy". In Karl Ameriks (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780801486043.
  • Wood, Allen (2008). Kantian Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521671149.

External links

  • Works by Immanuel Kant at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by or about Immanuel Kant at Internet Archive
  • Works by Immanuel Kant at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  
  • KantPapers, authors and papers database powered by PhilPapers, focused on Kant, and located at Cornell University
  • Stephen Palmquist's Glossary of Kantian Terminology
  • At the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • Immanuel Kant: An Overview
    • Aesthetics
    • Logic
    • Metaphysics
    • Philosophy of Mind
    • Philosophy of Religion
    • Radical Evil
    • Transcendental Idealism
  • At the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • Immanuel Kant
    • Kant and Hume on Causality
    • Kant and Hume on Morality
    • Kant's Account of Reason
    • Kant's Aesthetics and Teleology
    • Kant's Critique of Metaphysics
    • Kant's Moral Philosophy
    • Kant's Philosophical Development
    • Kant's Philosophy of Mathematics
    • Kant's Philosophy of Religion
    • Kant's Philosophy of Science
    • Kant's Social and Political Philosophy
    • Kant's Theory of Judgment
    • Kant's Transcendental Arguments
    • Kant's View of the Mind and Consciousness of Self
    • Kant's Views on Space and Time
    • Kantian Conceptualism/Nonconceptualism
    • Leibniz's Influence on Kant

immanuel, kant, kant, redirects, here, other, uses, kant, disambiguation, ɑː, german, ɪˈmaːnu, eːl, ˈkant, april, 1724, february, 1804, german, philosopher, native, kingdom, prussia, central, enlightenment, thinkers, born, königsberg, kant, comprehensive, syst. Kant redirects here For other uses see Kant disambiguation Immanuel Kant UK k ae n t 1 2 US k ɑː n t 3 4 German ɪˈmaːnu eːl ˈkant 5 6 22 April 1724 12 February 1804 was a German philosopher a native of the Kingdom of Prussia and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers Born in Konigsberg Kant s comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology metaphysics ethics and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western philosophy Immanuel KantPortrait by Johann Gottlieb Becker 1768Born 1724 04 22 22 April 1724Konigsberg Kingdom of Prussia present day Kaliningrad Russia Died12 February 1804 1804 02 12 aged 79 Konigsberg East Prussia Kingdom of PrussiaEducationCollegium FridericianumUniversity of Konigsberg BA MA April 1755 PhD September 1755 PhD August 1770 EraAge of EnlightenmentRegionWestern philosophySchoolEnlightenment philosophy Kantianism Other schools Classical liberalismEmpirical realismGerman idealismLiberal naturalismTranscendental idealismInstitutionsUniversity of KonigsbergThesesPrincipiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio September 1755 De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis August 1770 Academic advisorsMartin Knutzen Johann Gottfried Teske M A advisor Konrad Gottlieb MarquardtNotable studentsJakob Sigismund Beck Johann Gottlieb Fichte Johann Gottfried Herder Karl Leonhard Reinhold epistolary correspondent Main interestsAesthetics cosmogony epistemology ethics metaphysics systematic philosophyNotable ideas Aesthetic teleological judgmentsAnalytic synthetic distinctionCategorical and hypothetical imperativeCategoriesCritical philosophyCopernican revolution in philosophyDisinterested delightEmpirical realismKant s antinomiesKant s pitchforkKantian ethicsKingdom of EndsNebular hypothesisTranscendental schemaTheoretical vs practical philosophyTranscendental idealismTranscendental subjectUnderstanding reason distinctionInfluences AristotleBaumgartenEmilie du ChateletCrusiusDescartesEmpiricusHamannHumeLeibnizLockeLucretiusNewtonPlatoRousseauSmithWolffInfluenced Virtually all subsequent Western philosophySignatureIn his doctrine of transcendental idealism Kant argued space and time are mere forms of intuition that structure all experience and that the objects of experience are mere appearances The nature of things as they are in themselves is unknowable to us In an attempt to counter the philosophical doctrine of skepticism he wrote the Critique of Pure Reason 1781 1787 his most well known work Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal to think of the objects of experience as conforming to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition and the categories of our understanding so that we have a priori cognition of those objects Kant believed that reason is the source of morality and that aesthetics arises from a faculty of disinterested judgment Kant s religious views were deeply connected to his moral theory Their exact nature however remains in dispute He hoped that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation His cosmopolitan reputation however is called into question by his promulgation of scientific racism for much of his career even though he changed those views in the last decade of his life Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Young scholar 1 2 Early work 1 3 Publication of The Critique of Pure Reason 1 4 Later work 1 5 Death and burial 2 Philosophy 2 1 Kant s critical project 2 2 The doctrine of transcendental idealism 2 2 1 Interpretive disagreements 2 3 Kant s theory of judgment 2 3 1 Transcendental deduction of the categories of the understanding 2 3 2 Principles of pure understanding 2 4 Critique of metaphysics 2 4 1 On the concepts of pure reason 2 4 2 The dialectical inferences of pure reason 2 5 Moral thought 2 5 1 The idea of freedom 2 5 2 The categorical imperative 2 5 3 The Doctrine of Virtue 2 6 Political philosophy 2 7 Religious writings 2 8 Aesthetics 2 9 Anthropology 2 9 1 Racism 3 Influence and legacy 3 1 Historical influence 3 2 Influence on modern thinkers 4 Bibliography 4 1 List of major works 4 2 Collected works in German 5 Notes 6 References 6 1 Citations 6 2 Works cited 7 External linksBiography EditImmanuel Kant was born on 22 April 1724 into a Prussian German family of Lutheran Protestant faith in Konigsberg East Prussia since 1946 the Russian city of Kaliningrad His mother Anna Regina Reuter 1697 1737 was born in Konigsberg to a father from Nuremberg 7 Her surname is sometimes erroneously given as Porter Kant s father Johann Georg Kant 1682 1746 was a German harness maker from Memel at the time Prussia s most northeastern city now Klaipeda Lithuania It is possible that Kants got their name from the village of Kantvainiai German Kantwaggen today part of Priekule and were of Kursenieki origin 8 9 Baptized Emanuel Kant later changed the spelling of his name to Immanuel after learning Hebrew 10 He was the fourth of nine children six of whom reached adulthood 11 The Kant household stressed the pietist values of religious devotion humility and a literal interpretation of the Bible 12 The young Immanuel s education was strict punitive and disciplinary and focused on Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science 13 In his later years Kant lived a strictly ordered life It was said that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks He never married but seems to have had a rewarding social life he was a popular teacher as well as a modestly successful author even before starting on his major philosophical works 14 Young scholar Edit Kant showed a great aptitude for study at an early age He first attended the Collegium Fridericianum from which he graduated at the end of the summer of 1740 In 1740 aged 16 he enrolled at the University of Konigsberg where he spent his whole career 15 He studied the philosophy of Gottfried Leibniz and Christian Wolff under Martin Knutzen Associate Professor of Logic and Metaphysics from 1734 until his death in 1751 a rationalist who was also familiar with developments in British philosophy and science and introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of Isaac Newton Knutzen dissuaded Kant from the theory of pre established harmony which he regarded as the pillow for the lazy mind 16 He also dissuaded Kant from idealism the idea that reality is purely mental which most philosophers in the 18th century regarded in a negative light The theory of transcendental idealism that Kant later included in the Critique of Pure Reason was developed partially in opposition to traditional idealism Kant had contacts with students colleagues friends and diners who frequented the local Masonic lodge 17 His father s stroke and subsequent death in 1746 interrupted his studies Kant left Konigsberg shortly after August 1748 18 he would return there in August 1754 19 He became a private tutor in the towns surrounding Konigsberg but continued his scholarly research In 1749 he published his first philosophical work Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces written in 1745 1747 20 Early work Edit Kant is best known for his work in the philosophy of ethics and metaphysics but he made significant contributions to other disciplines In 1754 while contemplating on a prize question by the Berlin Academy about the problem of Earth s rotation he argued that the Moon s gravity would slow down Earth s spin and he also put forth the argument that gravity would eventually cause the Moon s tidal locking to coincide with the Earth s rotation a 22 The next year he expanded this reasoning to the formation and evolution of the Solar System in his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens 22 In 1755 Kant received a license to lecture in the University of Konigsberg and began lecturing on a variety of topics including mathematics physics logic and metaphysics In his 1756 essay on the theory of winds Kant laid out an original insight into the Coriolis force In 1756 Kant also published three papers on the 1755 Lisbon earthquake 23 Kant s theory which involved shifts in huge caverns filled with hot gases though inaccurate was one of the first systematic attempts to explain earthquakes in natural rather than supernatural terms In 1757 Kant began lecturing on geography making him one of the first lecturers to explicitly teach geography as its own subject 24 25 Geography was one of Kant s most popular lecturing topics and in 1802 a compilation by Friedrich Theodor Rink of Kant s lecturing notes Physical Geography was released After Kant became a professor in 1770 he expanded the topics of his lectures to include lectures on natural law ethics and anthropology along with other topics 24 Kant s house in Konigsberg In the Universal Natural History Kant laid out the Nebular hypothesis in which he deduced that the Solar System had formed from a large cloud of gas a nebula Kant also correctly deduced that the Milky Way was a large disk of stars which he theorized formed from a much larger spinning gas cloud He further suggested that other distant nebulae might be other galaxies These postulations opened new horizons for astronomy for the first time extending it beyond the solar system to galactic and intergalactic realms 26 From then on Kant turned increasingly to philosophical issues although he continued to write on the sciences throughout his life In the early 1760s Kant produced a series of important works in philosophy The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures a work in logic was published in 1762 Two more works appeared the following year Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy and The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God By 1764 Kant had become a notable popular author and wrote Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime he was second to Moses Mendelssohn in a Berlin Academy prize competition with his Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality often referred to as The Prize Essay In 1766 Kant wrote a critical piece on Emanuel Swedenborg s Dreams of a Spirit Seer On 31 March 1770 aged 45 Kant was finally appointed Full Professor of Logic and Metaphysics Professor Ordinarius der Logic und Metaphysic at the University of Konigsberg In defense of this appointment Kant wrote his inaugural dissertation Inaugural Dissertation De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World b This work saw the emergence of several central themes of his mature work including the distinction between the faculties of intellectual thought and sensible receptivity To miss this distinction would mean to commit the error of subreption and as he says in the last chapter of the dissertation only in avoiding this error does metaphysics flourish It is often claimed that Kant was a late developer that he only became an important philosopher in his mid 50 s after rejecting his earlier views While it is true that Kant wrote his greatest works relatively late in life there is a tendency to underestimate the value of his earlier works Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these pre critical writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work 27 Publication of The Critique of Pure Reason Edit Main article Critique of Pure Reason At age 46 Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher and much was expected of him In correspondence with his ex student and friend Markus Herz Kant admitted that in the inaugural dissertation he had failed to account for the relation between our sensible and intellectual faculties 28 He needed to explain how we combine what is known as sensory knowledge with the other type of knowledge that is reasoned knowledge these two being related but having very different processes Portrait of philosopher David Hume Kant also credited David Hume with awakening him from a dogmatic slumber in which he had unquestioningly accepted the tenets of both religion and natural philosophy 29 30 Hume in his 1739 Treatise on Human Nature had argued that we only know the mind through a subjective essentially illusory series of perceptions Ideas such as causality morality and objects are not evident in experience so their reality may be questioned Kant felt that reason could remove this skepticism and he set himself to solving these problems Although fond of company and conversation with others Kant isolated himself and resisted friends attempts to bring him out of his isolation c When Kant emerged from his silence in 1781 the result was the Critique of Pure Reason Kant countered Hume s empiricism by claiming that some knowledge exists inherently in the mind independent of experience 29 He drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal that worldly objects can be intuited a priori and that intuition is consequently distinct from objective reality He acquiesced to Hume somewhat by defining causality as a regular constant sequence of events in time and nothing more 32 Although now uniformly recognized as one of the greatest works in the history of philosophy this Critique disappointed Kant s readers upon its initial publication 33 The book was long over 800 pages in the original German edition and written in a convoluted style Kant was quite upset with its reception 34 His former student Johann Gottfried Herder criticized it for placing reason as an entity worthy of criticism instead of considering the process of reasoning within the context of language and one s entire personality 35 Similar to Christian Garve and Johann Georg Heinrich Feder he rejected Kant s position that space and time possessed a form that could be analyzed Additionally Garve and Feder also faulted Kant s Critique for not explaining differences in perception of sensations 36 Its density made it as Herder said in a letter to Johann Georg Hamann a tough nut to crack obscured by all this heavy gossamer 37 Its reception stood in stark contrast to the praise Kant had received for earlier works such as his Prize Essay and shorter works that preceded the first Critique Recognizing the need to clarify the original treatise Kant wrote the Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics in 1783 as a summary of its main views Shortly thereafter Kant s friend Johann Friedrich Schultz 1739 1805 a professor of mathematics published Explanations of Professor Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Konigsberg 1784 which was a brief but very accurate commentary on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason 38 Engraving of Immanuel Kant Kant s reputation gradually rose through the latter portion of the 1780s sparked by a series of important works the 1784 essay Answer to the Question What is Enlightenment 1785 s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals his first work on moral philosophy and from 1786 Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science But Kant s fame ultimately arrived from an unexpected source In 1786 Karl Leonhard Reinhold published a series of public letters on Kantian philosophy 39 In these letters Reinhold framed Kant s philosophy as a response to the central intellectual controversy of the era the pantheism controversy Friedrich Jacobi had accused the recently deceased Gotthold Ephraim Lessing a distinguished dramatist and philosophical essayist of Spinozism Such a charge tantamount to atheism was vigorously denied by Lessing s friend Moses Mendelssohn leading to a bitter public dispute among partisans The controversy gradually escalated into a debate about the values of the Enlightenment and the value of reason Reinhold maintained in his letters that Kant s Critique of Pure Reason could settle this dispute by defending the authority and bounds of reason Reinhold s letters were widely read and made Kant the most famous philosopher of his era Later work Edit Kant published a second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787 heavily revising the first parts of the book Most of his subsequent work focused on other areas of philosophy He continued to develop his moral philosophy notably in 1788 s Critique of Practical Reason known as the second Critique and 1797 s Metaphysics of Morals The 1790 Critique of the Power of Judgment the third Critique applied the Kantian system to aesthetics and teleology In 1792 Kant s attempt to publish the Second of the four Pieces of Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 40 in the journal Berlinische Monatsschrift met with opposition from the King s censorship commission which had been established that same year in the context of the French Revolution 41 Kant then arranged to have all four pieces published as a book routing it through the philosophy department at the University of Jena to avoid the need for theological censorship 41 This insubordination earned him a now famous reprimand from the King 41 When he nevertheless published a second edition in 1794 the censor was so irate that he arranged for a royal order that required Kant never to publish or even speak publicly about religion 41 Kant then published his response to the King s reprimand and explained himself in the preface of The Conflict of the Faculties 41 Kant with friends including Christian Jakob Kraus Johann Georg Hamann Theodor Gottlieb von Hippel and Karl Gottfried Hagen He also wrote a number of semi popular essays on history religion politics and other topics These works were well received by Kant s contemporaries and confirmed his preeminent status in eighteenth century philosophy There were several journals devoted solely to defending and criticizing Kantian philosophy Despite his success philosophical trends were moving in another direction Many of Kant s most important disciples and followers including Reinhold Beck and Fichte transformed the Kantian position The progressive stages of revision of Kant s teachings marked the emergence of German idealism Kant opposed these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in 1799 42 It was one of his final acts expounding a stance on philosophical questions In 1800 a student of Kant named Gottlob Benjamin Jasche 1762 1842 published a manual of logic for teachers called Logik which he had prepared at Kant s request Jasche prepared the Logik using a copy of a textbook in logic by Georg Friedrich Meier entitled Excerpt from the Doctrine of Reason in which Kant had written copious notes and annotations The Logik has been considered of fundamental importance to Kant s philosophy and the understanding of it The great 19th century logician Charles Sanders Peirce remarked in an incomplete review of Thomas Kingsmill Abbott s English translation of the introduction to Logik that Kant s whole philosophy turns upon his logic 43 Also Robert Schirokauer Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz wrote in the translators introduction to their English translation of the Logik Its importance lies not only in its significance for the Critique of Pure Reason the second part of which is a restatement of fundamental tenets of the Logic but in its position within the whole of Kant s work 44 Death and burial Edit Kant s health long poor worsened He died at Konigsberg on 12 February 1804 uttering Es ist gut It is good before expiring 45 His unfinished final work was published as Opus Postumum Kant always cut a curious figure in his lifetime for his modest rigorously scheduled habits which have been referred to as clocklike However Heinrich Heine noted the magnitude of his destructive world crushing thoughts and considered him a sort of philosophical executioner comparing him to Robespierre with the observation that both men represented in the highest the type of provincial bourgeois Nature had destined them to weigh coffee and sugar but Fate determined that they should weigh other things and placed on the scales of the one a king on the scales of the other a god 46 When his body was transferred to a new burial spot his skull was measured during the exhumation and found to be larger than the average German male s with a high and broad forehead 47 His forehead has been an object of interest ever since it became well known through his portraits In Dobler s portrait and in Kiefer s faithful if expressionistic reproduction of it as well as in many of the other late eighteenth and early nineteenth century portraits of Kant the forehead is remarkably large and decidedly retreating 48 Kant s tomb in Kaliningrad Russia Kant s mausoleum adjoins the northeast corner of Konigsberg Cathedral in Kaliningrad Russia The mausoleum was constructed by the architect Friedrich Lahrs and was finished in 1924 in time for the bicentenary of Kant s birth Originally Kant was buried inside the cathedral but in 1880 his remains were moved to a neo Gothic chapel adjoining the northeast corner of the cathedral Over the years the chapel became dilapidated and was demolished to make way for the mausoleum which was built on the same location The tomb and its mausoleum are among the few artifacts of German times preserved by the Soviets after they captured the city 49 Today many newlyweds bring flowers to the mausoleum Artifacts previously owned by Kant known as Kantiana were included in the Konigsberg City Museum However the museum was destroyed during World War II A replica of the statue of Kant that in German times stood in front of the main University of Konigsberg building was donated by a German entity in the early 1990s and placed in the same grounds After the expulsion of Konigsberg s German population at the end of World War II the University of Konigsberg where Kant taught was replaced by the Russian language Kaliningrad State University which appropriated the campus and surviving buildings In 2005 the university was renamed Immanuel Kant State University of Russia The name change was announced at a ceremony attended by President Vladimir Putin of Russia and Chancellor Gerhard Schroder of Germany and the university formed a Kant Society dedicated to the study of Kantianism The university was again renamed in the 2010s to Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University 50 Philosophy EditLike many of his contemporaries Kant was greatly impressed with the scientific advances made by Newton and others This new evidence of the power of human reason however called into question the traditional authority of politics and religion Although this was in some respects liberatory it was in other respects threatening In particular the modern mechanistic view of the world called into question the very possibility of morality for if there is no agency there cannot be any responsibility 51 52 The aim of Kant s critical project is to secure human autonomy the basis of religion and morality from this threat of mechanism and to do so in a way that preserves the advances of modern science 53 In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant summarizes his philosophical concerns in the following three questions Bust of Immanuel Kant by Emanuel Bardou 1798 What can I know What should I do What may I hope 54 The Critique of Pure Reason focuses upon the first question and opens a conceptual space for an answer to the second question It argues that even though we cannot strictly know that we are free we can and for practical purposes must think of ourselves as free In Kant s own words I had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith 55 Our rational faith in morality is further developed in The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and The Critique of Practical Reason 56 57 The Critique of the Power of Judgment argues we may rationally hope for the harmonious unity of the theoretical and practical domains treated in the first two Critiques on the basis not only of its conceptual possibility but also on the basis of our affective experience of natural beauty and more generally the organization of the natural world 58 In Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason Kant endeavors to complete his answer to this third question 59 These works all place the active rational human subject at the center of the cognitive and moral worlds In brief Kant argues that the mind itself necessarily makes a constitutive contribution to knowledge that this contribution is transcendental rather than psychological and that to act autonomously is to act according to rational moral principles 60 Kant s critical project Edit See also Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant by Carle Vernet 1758 1836 Kant s 1781 revised 1787 book the Critique of Pure Reason has often been cited as the most significant volume of metaphysics and epistemology in modern philosophy 61 In the first Critique and later on in other works as well Kant frames the general and real problem of pure reason in terms of the following question How are synthetic judgments a priori possible 62 63 To parse this claim it is necessary to define some terms First Kant makes a distinction in terms of the source of the content of knowledge Cognitions a priori cognition independent of all experience and even of all the impressions of the senses Cognitions a posteriori cognitions that have their sources in experience that is which are empirical 64 Second he makes a distinction in terms of the form of knowledge Analytic proposition a proposition whose predicate concept is contained in its subject concept e g All bachelors are unmarried or All bodies take up space These can also be called judgments of clarification Synthetic proposition a proposition whose predicate concept is not contained in its subject concept e g All bachelors are alone or All bodies have weight These can also be called judgments of amplification 65 An analytic proposition is true by nature of strictly conceptual relations All analytic propositions are a priori it is analytically true that no analytic proposition could be a posteriori By contrast a synthetic proposition is one the content of which includes something new The truth or falsehood of a synthetic statement depends upon something more than what is contained in its concepts The most obvious form of synthetic proposition is a simple empirical observation 66 Philosophers such as David Hume believed that these were the only possible kinds of human reason and investigation which he called relations of ideas and matters of fact 67 Establishing the synthetic a priori as a third mode of knowledge would allow Kant to push back against Hume s skepticism about such matters as causation and metaphysical knowledge more generally This is because unlike a posteriori cognition a priori cognition has true or strict universality and includes a claim of necessity 68 66 Kant himself regards it as uncontroversial that we do have synthetic a priori knowledge most obviously that of mathematics That 7 5 12 he claims is a result not contained in the concepts of seven five and the addition operation 69 Yet although he considers the possibility of such knowledge to be obvious Kant nevertheless assumes the burden of providing a philosophical proof that we have a priori knowledge in mathematics the natural sciences and metaphysics It is the twofold aim of the Critique both to prove and to explain the possibility of this knowledge 70 Christian Wolff 1679 1754 whose methodical principles of logical exposition are responsible for many of the formal qualities of Kant s works Before turning to Kant s arguments in the body of the Critique there are two more distinctions from its introductory sections that must be introduced There are Kant says two stems of human cognition which may perhaps arise from a common but to us unknown root namely sensibility and understanding through the first of which objects are given to us but through the second of which they are thought 71 Kant s term for the object of sensibility is intuition and his term for the object of the understanding is concept In general terms the former is a non discursive representation of a particular object and the latter is a discursive or mediate representation of a general type of object 72 The conditions of possible experience require both intuitions and concepts that is the affection of the receptive sensibility and the actively synthesizing power of the understanding 73 d Thus the statement Thoughts without content are empty intuitions without concepts are blind 75 Kant s basic strategy in the first half of his book will be to argue that some intuitions and concepts are pure that is are contributed entirely by the mind independent of anything empirical Knowledge generated on this basis under certain conditions can be synthetic a priori This insight is known as Kant s Copernican revolution because just as Copernicus advanced astronomy by way of a radical shift in perspective so Kant here claims do the same for metaphysics 76 77 The second half of the Critique is the explicitly critical part In this transcendental dialectic Kant argues that many of the claims of traditional rationalist metaphysics violate the criteria he claims to establishing the first constructive part of his book 78 79 As Kant observes human reason without being moved by the mere vanity of knowing it all inexorably pushes on driven by its own need to such questions that cannot be answered by any experiential use of reason 80 It is the project of the critique of pure reason to establish the limits as to just how far reason may legitimately so proceed 81 The doctrine of transcendental idealism Edit See also Transcendental idealism The section of the Critique entitled The transcendental aesthetic advances Kant s famous thesis of transcendental idealism Something is transcendental if it is a necessary condition for the possibility of experience and idealism denotes some form of mind dependence that must be further specified The correct interpretation of Kant s own specification remains controversial 82 The thesis then states that human beings only experience and know appearances not things in themselves because space and time are nothing but the subjective forms of intuition that we ourselves contribute to experience 83 84 Nevertheless although Kant says that space and time are transcendentally ideal the pure forms of human sensibility rather than part of nature or reality as it exists in itself he also claims that they are empirically real by which he means that everything that can come before us externally as an object is in both space and time and that our internal intuitions of ourselves are in time 85 83 However we may interpret Kant s doctrine he clearly wishes to distinguish his position from the subjective idealism of Berkeley 86 Paul Guyer although critical of many of Kant s arguments in this section nevertheless writes of the Transcendental Aesthetic that it not only lays the first stone in Kant s constructive theory of knowledge it also lays the foundation for both his critique and his reconstruction of traditional metaphysics It argues that all genuine knowledge requires a sensory component and thus that metaphysical claims that transcend the possibility of sensory confirmation can never amount to knowledge 87 Interpretive disagreements Edit One interpretation known as the two world interpretation regards Kant s position as a statement of epistemological limitation that we are not able to transcend the bounds of our own mind meaning that we cannot access the thing in itself However Kant also speaks of the thing in itself or transcendent object as a product of the human understanding as it attempts to conceive of objects in abstraction from the conditions of sensibility Following this line of thought some interpreters have argued that the thing in itself does not represent a separate ontological domain but simply a way of considering objects by means of the understanding alone this is known as the two aspect view 88 89 Kant s theory of judgment Edit See also Category Kant Kant statue in the School of Philosophy and Human Sciences FAFICH in the Federal University of Minas Gerais UFMG Belo Horizonte Brazil Following the Transcendental Analytic is the Transcendental Logic Whereas the former was concerned with the contributions of the sensibility the latter is concerned first with the contributions of the understanding Transcendental Analytic and second with the faculty of reason as the source of both metaphysical errors and genuine regulatory principles Transcendental Dialectic The Transcendental Analytic is further divided into two sections The first Analytic of Concepts is concerned with establishing the universality and necessity of the pure concepts of the understanding i e the categories This section contains Kant s famous transcendental deduction The second Analytic of Principles is concerned with the application of those pure concepts in empirical judgments This second section is longer than the first and is further divided into many sub sections 90 Transcendental deduction of the categories of the understanding Edit The Analytic of Concepts argues for the universal and necessary validity of the pure concepts of the understanding or the categories e g the concepts of substance and causation These twelve basic categories define what it is to be a thing in general that is they articulate the necessary conditions according to which something is a possible object of experience These in conjunction with the a priori forms of intuition are the basis of all synthetic a priori cognition According to Guyer and Wood Kant s idea is that just as there are certain essential features of all judgments so there must be certain corresponding ways in which we form the concepts of objects so that judgments may be about objects 91 Kant provides two central lines of argumentation in support of his claims about the categories The first known as the metaphysical deduction proceeds analytically from a table of the Aristotelian logical functions of judgment As Kant was aware however this assumes precisely what the skeptic rejects namely the existence of synthetic a priori cognition For this reason Kant also supplies a synthetic argument that does not depend upon the assumption in dispute 92 This argument provided under the heading Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding is widely considered to be both the most important and the most difficult of Kant s arguments in the Critique Kant himself said that it is the one that cost him the most labor 93 Frustrated by its confused reception in the first edition of his book he rewrote it entirely for the second edition 94 95 The Transcendental Deduction gives Kant s argument that these pure concepts apply universally and necessarily to the objects that are given in experience According to Guyer and Wood He centers his argument on the premise that our experience can be ascribed to a single identical subject via what he calls the transcendental unity of apperception only if the elements of experience given in intuition are synthetically combined so as to present us with objects that are thought through the categories 96 Kant s principle of apperception is that The I think must be able to accompany all my representations for otherwise something would be represented in me that could not be thought at all which is as much as to say that the representation would either be impossible or else at least would be nothing for me 97 The necessary possibility of the self ascription of the representations of self consciousness identical to itself through time is an a priori conceptual truth that cannot be based on experience 98 This however is only a bare sketch of one of the arguments that Kant presents Principles of pure understanding Edit Kant s deduction of the categories in the Analytic of Concepts if successful demonstrates its claims about the categories only in an abstract way The task of the Analytic of Principles is to show both that they must universally apply to objects given in actual experience i e manifolds of intuition and how it is they do so 99 In the first book of this section on the schematism Kant connects each of the purely logical categories of the understanding to the temporality of intuition to show that although non empirical they do have purchase upon the objects of experience The second book continues this line of argument in four chapters each associated with one of the category groupings In some cases it adds a connection to the spatial dimension of intuition to the categories it analyzes 100 The fourth chapter of this section The Analogies of Experience marks a shift from mathematical to dynamical principles that is to those that deal with relations among objects Some commentators consider this the most significant section of the Critique 101 The analogies are three in number Principle of persistence of substance Kant is here concerned with the general conditions of determining time relations among the objects of experience He argues that the unity of time implies that all change must consist in the alteration of states in an underlying substance whose existence and quantity must be unchangeable or conserved 102 Principle of temporal succession according to the law of causality Here Kant argues that we can make determinate judgments about the objective succession of events as contrasted to merely subjective successions of representations only if every objective alteration follows a necessary rule of succession or a causal law This is Kant s most direct rejoinder to Hume s skepticism about causality 103 Principle of simultaneity according to the law of reciprocity or community The final analogy argues that determinate judgments that objects or states of substance in different regions of space exists simultaneously are possible only if such objects stand in mutual causal relation of community or reciprocal interaction This is Kant s rejoinder to Leibniz s thesis in the Monadology 104 105 The fourth section of this chapter which is not an analogy deals with the empirical use of the modal categories That was the end of the chapter in the A edition of the Critique The B addition however includes one more short section The Refutation of Idealism In this section by analysis of the concept of self consciousness Kant argues that his transcendental idealism is a critical or formal idealism that does not deny the existence of reality apart from our subjective representations 106 The final chapter of The Analytic of Principles distinguishes phenomena of which we have can have genuine knowledge from noumena a term which refers to objects of pure thought that we cannot know but to which we may still refer in a negative sense 107 An Appendix to the section further develops Kant s criticism of Leibnizian Wolffian rationalism by arguing that its dogmatic metaphysics confuses the mere features of concepts through which we think things with features of the objects themselves Against this Kant reasserts his own insistence upon the necessity of a sensible component in all genuine knowledge 108 Critique of metaphysics Edit The second of the two Divisions of The Transcendental Logic The Transcendental Dialectic contains the negative portion of Kant s Critique which builds upon the positive arguments of the preceding Transcendental Analytic to expose the limits of metaphysical speculation In particular it is concerned to demonstrate as spurious the efforts of reason to arrive at knowledge independent of sensibility This endeavor Kant argues is doomed to failure which he claims to demonstrate by showing that reason unbounded by sense is always capable of generating opposing or otherwise incompatible conclusions Like the light dove in free flight cutting through the air the resistance of which it feels reason could get the idea that it could do even better in airless space 109 Against this Kant claims that absent epistemic friction there can be no knowledge Nevertheless Kant s critique is not entirely destructive He presents the speculative excesses of traditional metaphysics as inherent in our very capacity of reason Moreover he argues that its products are not without some carefully qualified regulative value On the concepts of pure reason Edit Kant calls the basic concepts of metaphysics ideas They are different from the concepts of understanding in that they are not limited by the stricture clarification needed of possible experience Transcendental illusion is Kant s term for the tendency of reason to produce such ideas 110 Although reason has a logical use of simply drawing inferences from principles in The Transcendental Dialectic Kant is concerned with its purportedly real use to arrive at conclusions by way of unchecked regressive syllogistic ratiocination 111 The three categories of relation pursued without regard to the limits of possible experience yield the three central ideas of traditional metaphysics The soul the concept of substance as the ultimate subject The world in its entirety the concept of causation as a completed series and God the concept of community as the common ground of all possibilities 111 Although Kant denies that these ideas can be objects of genuine cognition he argues that they are the result of reason s inherent drive to unify cognition into a systematic whole 110 Leibnizian Wolffian metaphysics was divided into four parts ontology psychology cosmology and theology Kant replaces the first with the positive results of the first part of the Critique He proposes to replace the following three with his later doctrines of anthropology the metaphysical foundations of natural science and the critical postulation of human freedom and morality 112 The dialectical inferences of pure reason Edit In the second of the two Books of The Transcendental Dialectic Kant undertakes to demonstrate the contradictory nature of unbounded reason He does this by developing contradictions in each of the three metaphysical disciplines that he contends are in fact pseudo sciences This section of the Critique is long and Kant s arguments are extremely detailed In this context it not possible to do much more than enumerate the topics of discussion The first chapter addresses what Kant terms the paralogisms i e false inferences that pure reason makes in the metaphysical discipline of rational psychology He argues that one cannot take the mere thought of I in the proposition I think as the proper cognition of I as an object In this way he claims to debunk various metaphysical theses about the substantiality unity and self identity of the soul 113 The second chapter which is the longest takes up the topic Kant calls the antinomies of pure reason that is the contradictions of reason with itself in the metaphysical discipline of rational cosmology Originally Kant thought that all transcendental illusion could be analyzed in antinomic terms 114 He presents four cases in which he claims reason is able to prove opposing theses with equal plausibility That reason seems to be able to prove that the universe is both finite and infinite in space and time that reason seems to be able to prove that matter both is and is not infinitely divisible into ever smaller parts that reason seems to be able to prove that free will cannot be a causally efficacious part of the world because all of nature is deterministic and yet that it must be such a cause and that reason seems to be able to prove that there is and there is not a necessary being which some would identify with God 115 116 Kant further argues in each case that his doctrine of transcendental idealism is able to resolve the antinomy 115 The third chapter examines fallacious arguments about God in rational theology under the heading of the Ideal of Pure Reason Whereas an idea is a pure concept generated by reason an ideal is the concept of an idea as an individual thing 117 Here Kant addresses and claims to refute three traditional arguments for the existence of God the ontological argument the cosmological argument and the physio theological argument i e the argument from design 118 The results of the transcendental dialectic so far appear to be entirely negative In an Appendix to this section however Kant rejects such a conclusion The ideas of pure reason he argues have an important regulatory function in directing and organizing our theoretical and practical inquiry Kant s later works elaborate upon this function at length and in detail 119 Moral thought Edit Main article Kantian ethics Kant developed his ethics or moral philosophy in three works Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 1785 Critique of Practical Reason 1788 and Metaphysics of Morals 1797 With regard to morality Kant argued that the source of the good lies not in anything outside the human subject either in nature or given by God but rather is only the good will itself A good will is one that acts from duty in accordance with the universal moral law that the autonomous human being freely gives itself This law obliges one to treat humanity understood as rational agency and represented through oneself as well as others as an end in itself rather than merely as means to other ends the individual might hold Kant is known for his theory that all moral obligation is grounded in what he calls the categorical imperative which is derived from the concept of duty He argues that the moral law is a principle of reason itself not based on contingent facts about the world such as what would make us happy to act on the moral law has no other motive than worthiness to be happy 120 The idea of freedom Edit In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant distinguishes between the transcendental idea of freedom which as a psychological concept is mainly empirical and refers to whether a faculty of beginning a series of successive things or states from itself is to be assumed 121 and the practical concept of freedom as the independence of our will from the coercion or necessitation through sensuous impulses Kant finds it a source of difficulty that the practical idea of freedom is founded on the transcendental idea of freedom 122 but for the sake of practical interests uses the practical meaning taking no account of its transcendental meaning which he feels was properly disposed of in the Third Antinomy and as an element in the question of the freedom of the will is for philosophy a real stumbling block that has embarrassed speculative reason 121 Kant calls practical everything that is possible through freedom he calls the pure practical laws that are never given through sensuous conditions but are held analogously with the universal law of causality moral laws Reason can give us only the pragmatic laws of free action through the senses but pure practical laws given by reason a priori 121 dictate what is to be done 123 Kant s categories of freedom function primarily as conditions for the possibility for actions i to be free ii to be understood as free and iii to be morally evaluated For Kant although actions as theoretical objects are constituted by means of the theoretical categories actions as practical objects objects of practical use of reason and which can be good or bad are constituted by means of the categories of freedom Only in this way can actions as phenomena be a consequence of freedom and be understood and evaluated as such 124 The categorical imperative Edit In his Groundwork Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you at the same time can will that it become a universal law Kant makes a distinction between categorical and hypothetical imperatives A hypothetical imperative is one that we must obey to satisfy contingent desires A categorical imperative binds us regardless of our desires everyone has a duty to not lie regardless of circumstances even though it is sometimes in our narrowly selfish interest to do so These imperatives are morally binding because they are based on reason rather than contingent facts about an agent 125 Unlike hypothetical imperatives which bind us insofar as we are part of a group or society which we owe duties to we cannot opt out of the categorical imperative because we cannot opt out of being rational agents We owe a duty to rationality by virtue of being rational agents therefore rational moral principles apply to all rational agents at all times 126 Stated in other terms with all forms of instrumental rationality excluded from morality the moral law itself Kant holds can only be the form of lawfulness itself because nothing else is left once all content has been rejected 127 Kant provides three formulations for the categorical imperative He claims these are necessarily equivalent as all being expressions of the pure universality of the law as such 128 Many scholars however are not convinced 129 The formulas are as follows Formula of Universal Law Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you at the same time can will that it become a universal law 130 alternatively Formula of the Law of Nature So act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature 130 dd dd Formula of Humanity as End in Itself So act that you use humanity as much in your own person as in the person of every other always at the same time as an end and never merely as a means 131 dd Formula of Autonomy the idea of the will of every rational being as a will giving universal law 132 or Not to choose otherwise than so that the maxims of one s choice are at the same time comprehended with it in the same volition as universal law 133 alternatively Formula of the Realm of Ends Act in accordance with maxims of a universally legislative member for a merely possible realm of ends 134 135 dd dd Kant defines maxim as a subjective principle of volition which is distinguished from an objective principle or practical law While the latter is valid for every rational being and is a principle according to which they ought to act a maxim contains the practical rule which reason determines in accordance with the conditions of the subject often their ignorance or inclinations and is thus the principle according to which the subject does act 136 Maxims fail to qualify as practical laws if they produce a contradiction in conception or a contradiction in the will when universalized A contradiction in conception happens when if a maxim were to be universalized it ceases to make sense because the maxim would necessarily destroy itself as soon as it was made a universal law 137 For example if the maxim It is permissible to break promises was universalized no one would trust any promises made so the idea of a promise would become meaningless the maxim would be self contradictory because when universalized promises cease to be meaningful The maxim is not moral because it is logically impossible to universalize we could not conceive of a world where this maxim was universalized 138 A maxim can also be immoral if it creates a contradiction in the will when universalized This does not mean a logical contradiction but that universalizing the maxim leads to a state of affairs that no rational being would desire The Doctrine of Virtue Edit As Kant explains in the 1785 Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and as its title directly indicates that text is nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality 139 His promised Metaphysics of Morals however was much delayed and did not appear until its two parts The Doctrine of Right and The Doctrine of Virtue were published separately in 1797 and 1798 140 The first deals with political philosophy the second with ethics The Doctrine of Virtue provides a very different account of ordinary moral reasoning than the one suggested by the Groundwork 141 It is concerned with duties of virtue or ends that are at the same time duties 142 It is here in the domain of ethics that The Metaphysics of Morals s greatest innovation is to be found According to Kant s account ordinary moral reasoning is fundamentally teleological it is reasoning about what ends we are constrained by morality to pursue and the priorities among these ends we are required to observe 143 More specifically There are two sorts of ends that it is our duty to have our own perfection and the happiness of others MS 6 385 Perfection includes both our natural perfection the development of our talents skills and capacities of understanding and moral perfection our virtuous disposition MS 6 387 A person s happiness is the greatest rational whole of the ends the person set for the sake of her own satisfaction MS 6 387 8 144 Kant s elaboration of this teleological doctrine offers up a very different moral theory than the one typically attributed to him on the basis of his foundational works alone Political philosophy Edit Main article Political philosophy of Immanuel Kant In Towards Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Project Kant listed several conditions that he thought necessary for ending wars and creating a lasting peace They included a world of constitutional republics 145 His classical republican theory was extended in the Doctrine of Right the first part of the Metaphysics of Morals 1797 146 Kant believed that universal history leads to the ultimate world of republican states at peace but his theory was not pragmatic The process was described in Perpetual Peace as natural rather than rational What affords this guarantee surety is nothing less than the great artist nature natura daedala rerum from whose mechanical course purposiveness shines forth visibly letting concord arise by means of the discord between human beings even against their will and for this reason nature regarded as necessitation by a cause the laws of whose operation are unknown to us is called fate but if we consider its purposiveness in the course of the world as the profound wisdom of a higher cause directed to the objective final end of the human race and predetermining this course of the world it is called providence 147 Kant s political thought can be summarized as republican government and international organization In more characteristically Kantian terms it is doctrine of the state based upon the law Rechtsstaat and of eternal peace Indeed in each of these formulations both terms express the same idea that of legal constitution or of peace through law 148 Kant s political philosophy being essentially a legal doctrine rejects by definition the opposition between moral education and the play of passions as alternate foundations for social life The state is defined as the union of men under law The state rightly so called is constituted by laws which are necessary a priori because they flow from the very concept of law A regime can be judged by no other criteria nor be assigned any other functions than those proper to the lawful order as such 149 He opposed democracy which at his time meant direct democracy believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty He stated democracy in the strict sense of the word is necessarily a despotism because it establishes an executive power in which all decide for and if need be against one who thus does not agree so that all who are nevertheless not all decide and this is a contradiction of the general will with itself and with freedom 150 As with most writers at the time he distinguished three forms of government namely democracy aristocracy and monarchy with mixed government as the most ideal form of it Although Kant published this as a popular piece Mary J Gregor points out that two years later in The Metaphysics of Morals Kant claims to demonstrate systematically that establishing universal and lasting peace constitutes not merely a part of the doctrine of right but rather the entire final end of the doctrine of right within the limits of mere reason 151 152 The Doctrine of Right published in 1797 contains Kant s most mature and systematic contribution to political philosophy It addresses juridical duties which are concerned only with protecting the external freedom of individuals and indifferent to incentives Although we do have a moral duty to limit ourselves to actions that are right that duty is not part of right itself 141 Its basic political idea is that each person s entitlement to be his or her own master is only consistent with the entitlements of others if public legal institutions are in place 153 Religious writings Edit Main article Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason Commentators starting in the twentieth century have tended to see Kant as having a strained relationship with religion though this was not the prevalent view in the nineteenth century Karl Leonhard Reinhold whose letters helped make Kant famous wrote I believe that I may infer without reservation that the interest of religion and of Christianity in particular accords completely with the result of the Critique of Reason 154 According to Johann Schultz who wrote one of the first commentaries on Kant And does not this system itself cohere most splendidly with the Christian religion Do not the divinity and beneficence of the latter become all the more evident 155 The reason for these views was Kant s moral theology and the widespread belief that his philosophy was the great antithesis to Spinozism which was widely seen as a form of sophisticated pantheism or even atheism As Kant s philosophy disregarded the possibility of arguing for God through pure reason alone for the same reasons it also disregarded the possibility of arguing against God through pure reason alone Kant articulates his strongest criticisms of the organization and practices of religious organizations to those that encourage what he sees as a religion of counterfeit service to God 156 Among the major targets of his criticism are external ritual superstition and a hierarchical church order He sees these as efforts to make oneself pleasing to God in ways other than conscientious adherence to the principle of moral rightness in choosing and acting upon one s maxims Kant s criticisms on these matters along with his rejection of certain theoretical proofs grounded in pure reason particularly the ontological argument for the existence of God and his philosophical commentary on some Christian doctrines have resulted in interpretations that see Kant as hostile to religion in general and Christianity in particular 157 Nevertheless other interpreters consider that Kant was trying to mark off defensible from indefensible Christian belief 158 Regarding Kant s conception of religion some critics have argued that he was sympathetic to deism 159 Other critics have argued that Kant s moral conception moves from deism to theism as moral theism for example Allen W Wood 160 and Merold Westphal 161 As for Kant s book Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason it was emphasized that Kant reduced religiosity to rationality religion to morality and Christianity to ethics 162 However many interpreters including Allen W Wood 163 and Lawrence Pasternack 164 now agree with Stephen Palmquist s claim that a better way of reading Kant s Religion is to see him as raising morality to the status of religion 165 Aesthetics Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed April 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message See also Kant s teleology Immanuel Kant Kant discusses the subjective nature of aesthetic qualities and experiences in Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime 1764 Kant s contribution to aesthetic theory is developed in the Critique of the Power of Judgment 1790 where he investigates the possibility and logical status of judgments of taste In the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment the first major division of the Critique of the Power of Judgment Kant used the term aesthetic in a manner that differs from its modern sense 166 In the Critique of Pure Reason to note essential differences between judgments of taste moral judgments and scientific judgments Kant abandoned the term aesthetic as designating the critique of taste noting that judgments of taste could never be directed by laws a priori 167 After A G Baumgarten who wrote Aesthetica 1750 58 e Kant was one of the first philosophers to develop and integrate aesthetic theory into a unified and comprehensive philosophical system utilizing ideas that played an integral role throughout his philosophy 168 In the chapter Analytic of the Beautiful in the Critique of the Power of Judgment Kant states that beauty is not a property of an artwork or natural phenomenon but is instead consciousness of the pleasure that attends the free play of the imagination and the understanding Even though it appears that we are using reason to decide what is beautiful the judgment is not a cognitive judgment f and is consequently not logical but aesthetical 169 A pure judgement of taste is subjective since it refers to the emotional response of the subject and is based upon nothing but esteem for an object itself it is a disinterested pleasure and we feel that pure judgements of taste i e judgements of beauty lay claim to universal validity 170 It is important to note that this universal validity is not derived from a determinate concept of beauty but from common sense 171 Kant also believed that a judgement of taste shares characteristics engaged in a moral judgement both are disinterested and we hold them to be universal In the chapter Analytic of the Sublime Kant identifies the sublime as an aesthetic quality that like beauty is subjective but unlike beauty refers to an indeterminate relationship between the faculties of the imagination and of reason and shares the character of moral judgments in the use of reason The feeling of the sublime divided into two distinct modes the mathematical and the dynamical sublime describes two subjective moments that concern the relationship of the faculty of the imagination to reason Some commentators 172 argue that Kant s critical philosophy contains a third kind of the sublime the moral sublime which is the aesthetic response to the moral law or a representation and a development of the noble sublime in Kant s theory of 1764 The mathematical sublime results from the failure of the imagination to comprehend natural objects that appear boundless and formless or appear absolutely great 173 This imaginative failure is then recuperated through the pleasure taken in reason s assertion of the concept of infinity In this move the faculty of reason proves itself superior to our fallible sensible self 174 In the dynamical sublime there is the sense of annihilation of the sensible self as the imagination tries to comprehend a vast might This power of nature threatens us but through the resistance of reason to such sensible annihilation the subject feels a pleasure and a sense of the human moral vocation This appreciation of moral feeling through exposure to the sublime helps to develop moral character Kant developed a theory of humor 175 that has been interpreted as an incongruity theory He illustrated his theory of humor by telling three narrative jokes in the Critique of Judgment He thought that the physiological impact of humor is akin to that of music 176 Kant developed a distinction between an object of art as a material value subject to the conventions of society and the transcendental condition of the judgment of taste as a refined value in his Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim 1784 In the Fourth and Fifth Theses of that work he identified all art as the fruits of unsociableness due to men s antagonism in society 177 and in the Seventh Thesis asserted that while such material property is indicative of a civilized state only the ideal of morality and the universalization of refined value through the improvement of the mind belongs to culture 178 Anthropology Edit 5 DM 1974 D silver coin commemorating the 250th birthday of Immanuel Kant in Konigsberg Kant lectured on anthropology the study of human nature for twenty three years 179 His Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View was published in 1798 Transcripts of Kant s lectures on anthropology were published for the first time in 1997 in German 180 Kant was among the first people of his time to introduce anthropology as an intellectual area of study long before the field gained popularity and his texts are considered to have advanced the field His point of view was to influence the works of later philosophers such as Martin Heidegger and Paul Ricoeur citation needed Kant was also the first to suggest using a dimensionality approach to human diversity He analyzed the nature of the Hippocrates Galen four temperaments and plotted in two dimensions what belongs to a human being s faculty of desire his natural aptitude or natural predisposition and his temperament or sensibility 181 Cholerics were described as emotional and energetic phlegmatics as balanced and weak sanguines as balanced and energetic and melancholics as emotional and weak These two dimensions reappeared in all subsequent models of temperament and personality traits Kant viewed anthropology in two broad categories 1 the physiological approach which he referred to as what nature makes of the human being and 2 the pragmatic approach which explores the things that a human can and should make of himself 182 Racism Edit Kant mixing mustard drawn by Carl Friedrich Hagemann de 1801 Kant s theory of race and his prejudicial beliefs are among the most contentious areas of recent Kant scholarship 183 184 185 While few if any dispute the overt racism and chauvinism present in his work a more contested question is the degree to which it degrades or invalidates his other contributions His most severe critics assert that Kant intentionally manipulated science to support chattel slavery and discrimination 186 187 183 Others acknowledge that he lived in an era of immature science with many erroneous beliefs some racist all appearing decades before evolution molecular genetics and other sciences that today are taken for granted 183 184 188 189 Kant was one of the most notable Enlightenment thinkers to defend racism Although many of these views were common at the time some have claimed that he was one of the central figures in the birth of the since discredited pseudoscience known as scientific racism 190 Where figures such as Carl Linnaeus and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach had supposed only empirical observation for racism Kant produced a fully developed theory of race Using the four temperaments of ancient Greece he proposed a hierarchy of four racial categories white Europeans yellow Asians black Africans and red Americans 191 192 193 194 Although he was a proponent of scientific racism for much of his career Kant s views on race changed significantly in the last decade of his life and he ultimately rejected racial hierarchies and European colonialism in Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 1795 185 195 196 g Kant was an opponent of miscegenation believing that whites would be degraded and that fusing of races is undesirable for not every race adopts the morals and customs of the Europeans He states that instead of assimilation which was intended by the melting together of the various races nature has here made a law of just the opposite 198 He believed that in the future all races would be extinguished except that of the whites 196 Kant was also an anti Semite believing that Jews were incapable of transcending material forces which a moral order required In this way Jews are presented as the opposite of autonomous rational Christians and therefore incapable of being incorporated into an ethical Christian society In his Anthropology Kant called the Jews a nation of cheaters and portrayed them as a group that has followed not the path of transcendental freedom but that of enslavement to the material world 199 Charles W Mills wrote that Kant has been sanitized for public consumption his racist works conveniently ignored 196 Robert Bernasconi stated that Kant supplied the first scientific definition of race Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze is credited with bringing Kant s contributions to racism to light in the 1990s among Western philosophers who he believed often glossed over this part of his life and works 193 Pauline Kleingeld argues that while Kant did defend a racial hierarchy until at least the end of the 1780s his views on race changed significantly in works published in the last decade of his life In particular she argues that Kant rejected past views related to racial hierarchies and the diminished rights or moral status of non whites in Perpetual Peace 1795 This work also saw him providing extended arguments against European colonialism which he claimed was morally unjust and incompatible with the equal rights held by indigenous populations Kleingeld argues that this shift in Kant s views later in life has often been forgotten or ignored in the literature on Kant s racist anthropology and that the shift suggests a belated recognition of the fact that racial hierarchy was incompatible with a universalized moral framework 185 While Kant s racist rhetoric is indicative of the state of scholarship and science during the 18th century German philosopher Daniel Pascal Zorn explains the risk of taking period quotations out of context Many of Kant s most outrageous quotations are from a series of articles from 1777 1788 a public exchange among Kant Herder natural scientist Georg Forster and other scholars prominent in that period 200 201 202 Kant asserts that all races of humankind are of the same species challenging the position of Forster and others that the races were distinct species While his commentary is clearly biased at times certain extreme statements were patterned specifically to paraphrase or counter Forster and other authors 183 184 By considering the full arc of Kant s scholarship Zorn notes the progression in both his philosophical and his anthropological works with which he argues against the zeitgeist for the unity of humanity 184 Influence and legacy EditThis article contains embedded lists that may be poorly defined unverified or indiscriminate Please help to clean it up to meet Wikipedia s quality standards Where appropriate incorporate items into the main body of the article April 2023 Poster celebrating the 300 years of the University of Konigsberg 1844 Among others Kant and Herbart are honored Kant s influence on Western thought has been profound h Although the basic tenets of Kant s transcendental idealism i e that space and time are a priori forms of human perception rather than real properties and the claim that formal logic and transcendental logic coincide have been claimed to be falsified by modern science and logic 203 204 205 and no longer set the intellectual agenda of contemporary philosophers Kant is credited with having innovated the way philosophical inquiry has been carried at least up to the early nineteenth century This shift consisted in several closely related innovations that although highly contentious in themselves have become important in subsequent philosophy and in the social sciences broadly construed The human subject seen as the center of inquiry into human knowledge such that it is impossible to philosophize about things as they exist independently of human perception or of how they are for us 206 the notion that is possible to discover and systematically explore the inherent limits to our ability to know entirely a priori the notion of the categorical imperative an assertion that people are naturally endowed with the ability and obligation toward right reason and acting Perhaps his most famous quote is drawn from the Critique of Practical Reason Two things fill my mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me 207 the concept of conditions of possibility as in his notion of the conditions of possible experience that is that things knowledge and forms of consciousness rest on prior conditions that make them possible so that to understand or to know them we must first understand these conditions the claim that objective experience is actively constituted or constructed by the functioning of the human mind the concept of moral autonomy as central to humanity and the assertion of the principle that human beings should be treated as ends rather than as mere means Kant s ideas have been incorporated into a variety of schools of thought These include German idealism Marxism positivism phenomenology existentialism critical theory linguistic philosophy structuralism post structuralism and deconstruction citation needed Historical influence Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed July 2016 Learn how and when to remove this template message During his own life much critical attention was paid to Kant s thought He influenced Reinhold Fichte Schelling Hegel and Novalis during the 1780s and 1790s Statue of Immanuel Kant in Kaliningrad Konigsberg Russia Replica by Harald Haacke de of the original by Christian Daniel Rauch lost in 1945 Samuel Taylor Coleridge was greatly influenced by Kant and helped to spread awareness of him and of German Idealism generally in the UK and the USA In his Biographia Literaria 1817 he credits Kant s ideas in coming to believe that the mind is not a passive but an active agent in the apprehension of reality Hegel was one of Kant s first major critics In Hegel s view the entire project of setting a transcendental subject i e human consciousness apart from nature history and society was fundamentally flawed 208 although parts of that very project could be put to good use in a new direction Similar concerns motivated Hegel s criticisms to Kant s concept of moral autonomy to which Hegel opposed an ethic focused on the ethical life of the community i In a sense Hegel s notion of ethical life is meant to subsume rather than replace Kantian ethics And Hegel can be seen as trying to defend Kant s idea of freedom as going beyond finite desires by means of reason Thus in contrast to later critics like Nietzsche or Russell Hegel shares some of Kant s concerns j Kant s thinking on religion was used in Britain to challenge the decline in religious faith in the nineteenth century British Catholic writers notably G K Chesterton and Hilaire Belloc followed this approach Criticisms of Kant were common in the realist views of the new positivism at that time Arthur Schopenhauer was strongly influenced by Kant s transcendental idealism He like G E Schulze Jacobi and Fichte before him was critical of Kant s theory of the thing in itself Things in themselves they argued are neither the cause of what we observe nor are they completely beyond our access Ever since the Critique of Pure Reason philosophers have been critical of Kant s theory of the thing in itself Many have argued if such a thing exists beyond experience then one cannot posit that it affects us causally since that would entail stretching the category causality beyond the realm of experience k With the success and wide influence of Hegel s writings Kant s influence began to wane though there was in Germany a movement that hailed a return to Kant in the 1860s beginning with the publication of Kant und die Epigonen in 1865 by Otto Liebmann His motto was Back to Kant and a re examination of his ideas began During the turn of the twentieth century there was an important revival of Kant s theoretical philosophy known as the Marburg School represented in the work of Hermann Cohen Paul Natorp Ernst Cassirer 209 and anti Neo Kantian Nicolai Hartmann l Weimar Republic stamp honoring Kant 1926 Kant s notion of critique has been quite influential The early German Romantics especially Friedrich Schlegel in his Athenaeum Fragments used Kant s reflexive conception of criticism in their Romantic theory of poetry 210 Also in aesthetics Clement Greenberg in his classic essay Modernist Painting uses Kantian criticism what Greenberg refers to as immanent criticism to justify the aims of abstract painting a movement Greenberg saw as aware of the key limitation flatness that makes up the medium of painting 211 French philosopher Michel Foucault was also greatly influenced by Kant s notion of critique and wrote several pieces on Kant for a re thinking of the Enlightenment as a form of critical thought He went so far as to classify his own philosophy as a critical history of modernity rooted in Kant 212 Kant believed that mathematical truths were forms of synthetic a priori knowledge which means they are necessary and universal yet known through the a priori intuition of space and time as transcendental preconditions of experience 213 Kant s often brief remarks about mathematics influenced the mathematical school known as intuitionism a movement in philosophy of mathematics opposed to Hilbert s formalism and Frege and Bertrand Russell s logicism m Influence on modern thinkers Edit West German postage stamp 1974 commemorating the 250th anniversary of Kant s birth With his Perpetual Peace Kant is considered to have foreshadowed many of the ideas that have come to form the democratic peace theory one of the main controversies in political science 214 Prominent recent Kantians include the British philosophers P F Strawson n Onora O Neill 215 and Quassim Cassam 216 and the American philosophers Wilfrid Sellars 217 and Christine Korsgaard o Due to the influence of Strawson and Sellars among others there has been a renewed interest in Kant s view of the mind Central to many debates in philosophy of psychology and cognitive science is Kant s conception of the unity of consciousness p Jurgen Habermas and John Rawls are two significant political and moral philosophers whose work is strongly influenced by Kant s moral philosophy q They argued against relativism 218 supporting the Kantian view that universality is essential to any viable moral philosophy Mou Zongsan s study of Kant has been cited as a highly crucial part in the development of Mou s personal philosophy namely New Confucianism Widely regarded as the most influential Kant scholar in China Mou s rigorous critique of Kant s philosophy having translated all three of Kant s critiques served as an ardent attempt to reconcile Chinese and Western philosophy whilst increasing pressure to westernize in China 219 220 East German commemorative coin honoring Kant 1974 Kant s influence also has extended to the social behavioral and physical sciences as in the sociology of Max Weber the psychology of Jean Piaget and Carl Gustav Jung 221 222 and the linguistics of Noam Chomsky Kant s work on mathematics and synthetic a priori knowledge is also cited by theoretical physicist Albert Einstein as an early influence on his intellectual development though one which he later criticized and rejected 223 In recent years there has also been renewed interest in Kant s theory of mind from the point of view of formal logic and computer science 224 Because of the thoroughness of Kant s paradigm shift his influence extends well beyond this to thinkers who neither specifically refer to his work nor use his terminology Bibliography EditUnless otherwise noted all citations are to The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in English Translation 16 vols ed Guyer Paul and Wood Allen W Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1992 Citations in the article are to individual works per abbreviations in List of Major works below Lectures on Logic Ed and trans J Michael Young Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1992 Opus postumum Ed Eckart Forster trans Eckart Forster and Michael Rosen Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1993 Practical Philosophy Ed and trans Mary J Gregor Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1996 Religion and Rational Theology Ed and trans Allen W Wood and George di Giovanni Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1996 Lectures on Metaphysics Ed and trans Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1997 Lectures on Ethics Ed Peter Heath and J B Schneewind trans Peter Heath Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1997 Critique of Pure Reason Ed and trans Paul Guyer and Allen W Wood Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1998 Correspondence Ed and trans Arnulf Zweig Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1999 Critique of the Power of Judgment Ed Paul Guyer trans Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2000 Theoretical Philosophy after 1781 Ed Henry Allison and Peter Heath trans Gary Hatfield Michael Friedman Henry Allison and Peter Heath Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2002 Notes and Fragments Ed Paul Guyer trans Curtis Bowman Paul Guyer and Frederick Rauscher Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2005 Anthropology History and Education Ed Gunter Zoller and Robert B Louden Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2007 Lectures on Anthropology Ed Allen W Wood and Robert B Louden Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2012 Natural Science Ed by Eric Watkins Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2012 List of major works Edit Abbreviations used in body of article are boldface in brackets Unless otherwise noted pagination is to the critical Akademie edition which can be found in the margins of the Cambridge translations 1749 Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces Gedanken von der wahren Schatzung der lebendigen Krafte 1755 Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens UNH Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels 1755 Brief Outline of Certain Meditations on Fire Meditationum quarundam de igne succinta delineatio master s thesis under Johann Gottfried Teske 225 226 227 228 1755 A New Elucidation of the First Principles of Metaphysical Cognition Principiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio doctoral thesis 229 r 1756 The Use in Natural Philosophy of Metaphysics Combined with Geometry Part I Physical Monadology PM Metaphysicae cum geometrica iunctae usus in philosophia naturali cuius specimen I continet monadologiam physicam abbreviated as Monadologia Physica thesis as a prerequisite of associate professorship 230 1762 The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figuren 1763 The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God Der einzig mogliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes 1763 Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy NQ Versuch den Begriff der negativen Grossen in die Weltweisheit einzufuhren 1764 Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime OFBS Beobachtungen uber das Gefuhl des Schonen und Erhabenen 1764 Essay on the Illness of the Head Uber die Krankheit des Kopfes 1764 Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality the Prize Essay PNTM Untersuchungen uber die Deutlichkeit der Grundsatze der naturlichen Theologie und der Moral 1766 Dreams of a Spirit Seer DSS Traume eines Geistersehers 231 1768 On the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Regions in Space 1768 Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiedes der Gegenden im Raume 232 1770 Dissertation on the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World ID De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis doctoral thesis 233 234 235 1775 On the Different Races of Man Uber die verschiedenen Rassen der Menschen 1781 First edition of the Critique of Pure Reason CPuR A 236 Kritik der reinen Vernunft 237 1783 Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics PFM Prolegomena zu einer jeden kunftigen Metaphysik 1784 An Answer to the Question What Is Enlightenment WE Beantwortung der Frage Was ist Aufklarung 238 1784 Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose UH Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltburgerlicher Absicht 1785 Determination of the Concept of a Human Race DCHR Bestimmung des Begriffs einer Menschenrace 1785 Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals G Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten 1786 Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science MFNS Metaphysische Anfangsgrunde der Naturwissenschaft 1786 What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking OT Was heisst sich im Denken orientieren 1786 Conjectural Beginning of Human History CB Mutmasslicher Anfang der Menschengeschichte 1787 Second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason CPuR B 239 Kritik der reinen Vernunft 240 1788 Critique of Practical Reason CPracR Kritik der praktischen Vernunft 241 1790 Critique of Judgment CPJ Kritik der Urteilskraft 242 1793 Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason RBMR Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft 40 243 1793 On the Old Saw That May be Right in Theory But It Won t Work in Practice TP Uber den Gemeinspruch Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein taugt aber nicht fur die Praxis 1795 Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 244 PP Zum ewigen Frieden 245 1797 Metaphysics of Morals MM Metaphysik der Sitten First part is The Doctrine of Right which has often been published separately as The Science of Right 1798 Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View APPV Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht 1798 Conflict of Faculties CF 246 Der Streit der Fakultaten 247 1800 Logic Logik 1803 On Pedagogy Uber Padagogik 248 1804 Opus Postumum OP 1817 Lectures on Philosophical Theology Immanuel Kants Vorlesungen uber die philosophische Religionslehre edited by K H L Politz The English edition of A W Wood amp G M Clark Cornell 1978 is based on Politz second edition 1830 of these lectures s Collected works in German Edit Wilhelm Dilthey inaugurated the Academy edition the Akademie Ausgabe abbreviated as AA or Ak of Kant s writings Gesammelte Schriften Koniglich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin 1902 38 in 1895 249 and served as its first editor The volumes are grouped into four sections I Kant s published writings vols 1 9 II Kant s correspondence vols 10 13 III Kant s literary remains or Nachlass vols 14 23 and IV Student notes from Kant s lectures vols 24 29 An electronic version is also available Elektronische Edition der Gesammelten Werke Immanuel Kants vols 1 23 Notes Edit Kant himself seems to have found his contribution not significant enough that he published his arguments in a newspaper commentary on the prize question and did not submit them to the Academy Whether the Earth has Undergone an Alteration of its Axial Rotation Kant s Cosmogony Translated by Hastie William Glasgow James Maclehose 1900 1754 pp 1 11 Retrieved 29 March 2022 The prize was instead awarded in 1756 to P Frisi who incorrectly argued against the slowing down of the spin 21 Since he had written his last habilitation thesis 14 years earlier a new habilitation thesis was required see S J McGrath Joseph Carew eds Rethinking German Idealism Palgrave Macmillan 2016 p 24 It has been noted that in 1778 in response to one of these offers by a former pupil Kant wrote Any change makes me apprehensive even if it offers the greatest promise of improving my condition and I am persuaded by this natural instinct of mine that I must take heed if I wish that the threads which the Fates spin so thin and weak in my case to be spun to any length My great thanks to my well wishers and friends who think so kindly of me as to undertake my welfare but at the same time a most humble request to protect me in my current condition from any disturbance 31 More technically Kant puts his general point that all genuine knowledge requires both sensory input and intellectual organization by saying that all knowledge requires both intuitions and concepts e g A 50 B 74 Intuitions and concepts are two different species of the genus representation Vorstellung Kant s most general term for any cognitive state see A 320 B 376 7 At the outset of the Transcendental Aesthetic Kant states that an intuition is our most direct or immediate kind of representation of objects in contrast to a concept which always represents an object through a detour indirecte that is merely by some mark or property that the object has A 19 B 33 In his logic textbook Kant defines an intuition as a singular representation that is one that represents a particular object while a concept is always a universal repraesentation per notas communes which represents properties common to many objects Logic 1 9 91 74 Beardsley Monroe History of Aesthetics Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 1 section on Toward a unified aesthetics p 25 Macmillan 1973 Baumgarten coined the term aesthetics and expanded clarified and unified Wolffian aesthetic theory but had left the Aesthetica unfinished See also Tonelli Giorgio Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 1 Macmillan 1973 In Bernard s translation of the Critique of Judgment he indicates in the notes that Kant s reference in 15 in regard to the identification of perfection and beauty is probably a reference to Baumgarten Kant s general discussions of the distinction between cognition and conscious of are also given in the Critique of Pure Reason notably A320 B376 and section V and the conclusion of section VIII of his Introduction in Logic Kant wrote that Whites contain all the impulses of nature in affects and passions all talents all dispositions to culture and civilization and can as readily obey as govern They are the only ones who always advance to perfection He describes South Asians as educated to the highest degree but only in the arts and not in the sciences He goes on that Hindustanis can never reach the level of abstract concepts and that a great hindustani man is one who has gone far in the art of deception and has much money He states that the Hindus always stay the way they are and can never advance About black Africans Kant wrote that they can be educated but only as servants that is they allow themselves to be trained To Kant the Negro can be disciplined and cultivated but is never genuinely civilized He falls of his own accord into savagery Native Americans Kant opined cannot be educated He calls them unmotivated lacking affect passion and love and describes them as too weak for labor unfit for any culture and too phlegmatic for diligence He said that Native Americans are far below the Negro who undoubtedly holds the lowest of all remaining levels by which we designate the different races Kant stated that Americans and Blacks cannot govern themselves They thus serve only for slaves 196 197 Prof Oliver A Johnson claims With the possible exception of Plato s Republic Critique of Pure Reason is the most important philosophical book ever written Article on Kant within the collection Great thinkers of the Western World Ian P McGreal Ed HarperCollins 1992 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Natural Law The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law Its Place in Moral Philosophy and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences trans T M Knox Philadelphia PA University of Pennsylvania Press 1975 Hegel s mature view and his concept of ethical life is elaborated in his Philosophy of Right Hegel Philosophy of Right trans T M Knox Oxford University Press 1967 Robert Pippin s Hegel s Idealism Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1989 emphasizes the continuity of Hegel s concerns with Kant s Robert Wallace Hegel s Philosophy of Reality Freedom and God Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2005 explains how Hegel s Science of Logic defends Kant s idea of freedom as going beyond finite inclinations contra skeptics such as David Hume For a review of this problem and the relevant literature see The Thing in Itself and the Problem of Affection in the revised edition of Henry Allison s Kant s Transcendental Idealism Cerf Walter Nicolai Hartmann In Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3 4 Macmillan 1973 Nicolai was a realist who later rejected the idealism of Neo Kantianism his anti Neo Kantian views emerging with the publication of the second volume of Hegel 1929 Korner Stephan The Philosophy of Mathematics Dover 1986 For an analysis of Kant s writings on mathematics see Friedman Michael Kant and the Exact Sciences Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1992 Strawson P F The Bounds of Sense An Essay on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Routledge 2004 When first published in 1966 this book forced many Anglo American philosophers to reconsider Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Korsgaard Christine Creating the Kingdom of Ends Cambridge New York Cambridge University Press 1996 ISBN 978 0 521 49644 5 Not a commentary but a defense of a broadly Kantian approach to ethics Brook Andrew Kant and the Mind Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1994 See also Meerbote R Kant s Functionalism In J C Smith ed Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science Dordrecht Holland Reidel 1991 Brook has an article on Kant s View of the Mind in the Stanford Encyclopedia Archived 9 July 2010 at the Wayback Machine See Habermas J Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action Trans Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen Cambridge Massachusetts MIT Press 1996 For Rawls see Rawls John Theory of Justice Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1971 Rawls has a well known essay on Kant s concept of good See Rawls Themes in Kant s Moral Philosophy in Kant s Transcendental Deductions Ed Eckart Forster Stanford CA Stanford University Press 1989 vailable online at Bonner Kant Korpus Archived 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine As noted by Allen W Wood in his Introduction p 12 Wood further speculates that the lectures themselves were delivered in the Winter of 1783 84 References EditCitations Edit Kant Archived 27 September 2019 at the Wayback Machine Collins English Dictionary Kant Archived 23 October 2014 at the Wayback Machine Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary Wells John C 2008 Longman Pronunciation Dictionary 3rd ed Longman ISBN 978 1 4058 8118 0 Jones Daniel 2011 Roach Peter Setter Jane Esling John eds Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary 18th ed Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 15255 6 Immanuel Duden in German Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 20 October 2018 Kant Duden in German Archived from the original on 20 October 2018 Retrieved 20 October 2018 Cosmopolis Koenigsberg is dead de 23 April 2001 Archived from the original on 22 March 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 R K Murray The Origin of Immanuel Kant s Family Name Kantian Review 13 1 March 2008 pp 190 93 Rosa Kohlheim Volker Kohlheim Duden Familiennamen Herkunft und Bedeutung von 20 000 Nachnamen Bibliographisches Institut amp F A Brockhaus AG Mannheim 2005 p 365 Kuehn 2001 p 26 Haupt Viktor Rede des Bohnenkonigs Von Petersburg bis Panama Die Genealogie der Familie Kant PDF freunde kants com in German p 7 Archived from the original on 25 September 2015 Pasternack Lawrence Fugate Courtney 2020 Kant s Philosophy of Religion In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 25 February 2021 Kuehn 2001 p 47 Kuehn 2001 p 169 The American International Encyclopedia New York J J Little amp Ives 1954 Vol IX Porter Burton 2010 What the Tortoise Taught Us The Story of Philosophy Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers p 133 Die Freimaurer im Alten Preussen 1738 1806 PDF in German Archived PDF from the original on 19 November 2020 Kuehn 2001 p 94 Kuehn 2001 p 98 Eric Watkins ed Immanuel Kant Natural Science Cambridge University Press 2012 Thoughts on the true estimation Archived 7 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine Schonfeld Martin 2000 The Philosophy of the Young Kant The Precritical Project Oxford University Press p 84 ISBN 978 0 19 513218 2 a b Brush Stephen G 2014 A History of Modern Planetary Physics Nebulous Earth p 7 ISBN 978 0 521 44171 1 See Kant I 1756a Von den Ursachen der Erderschutterungen bei Gelegenheit des Unglucks welches die westliche Lander von Europa gegen das Ende des vorigen Jahres betroffen hat On the causes of the earthquakes on the occasion of the disaster which affected the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year In Koniglich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences ed s 1902 Kant s gesammelte Schriften Kant s collected writings in German Berlin Germany G Reimer vol 1 pp 417 427 Kant I 1756b Geschichte und Naturbeschreibung der merkwurdigsten Vorfalle des Erdbebens welches an dem Ende des 1755sten Jahres einen grossen Theil der Erde erschuttert hat History and description of the nature of the most remarkable events of the earthquake which shook a large part of the Earth at the end of the year 1755 ibid pp 429 461 Kant I 1756c Immanuel Kants fortgesetzte Betrachtung der seit einiger Zeit wahrgenommenen Erderschutterungen Immanuel Kant s continued consideration of the earthquakes that were felt some time ago ibid pp 463 472 Amador Filomena 2004 The causes of 1755 Lisbon earthquake on Kant In Escribano Benito J J Espanol Gonzalez L Martinez Garcia M A ed s Actas VIII Congreso de la Sociedad Espanola de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Tecnicas Proceedings of the Eighth Congress of the Spanish Society of the History of the Sciences and Technology in English Logrono Spain Sociedad Espanola de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Tecnicas Universidad de la Rioja vol 2 pp 485 495 a b Richards Paul 1974 Kant s Geography and Mental Maps Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 61 1 16 doi 10 2307 621596 JSTOR 621596 Elden Stuart 2009 Reassessing Kant s geography PDF Journal of Historical Geography 35 1 3 25 doi 10 1016 j jhg 2008 06 001 Archived PDF from the original on 1 August 2020 Retrieved 27 September 2019 Gamow George 1947 One Two Three Infinity New York Viking P pp 300ff Cf for example Susan Shell The Embodiment of Reason Chicago 1996 Kuehn Manfred 2009 Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Background Source Materials Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press p 276 ISBN 978 0 521 78162 6 a b Smith Homer W 1952 Man and His Gods New York Grosset amp Dunlap p 404 Kant PFM 4 260 Christopher Kul Want and Andrzej Klimowski Introducing Kant Cambridge Icon Books 2005 page needed ISBN 978 1 84046 664 5 Smith Homer W 1952 Man and His Gods New York Grosset amp Dunlap p 416 Dorrien Gary 2012 Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit The Idealistic Logic of Modern Theology Malden MA John Wiley amp Sons p 37 ISBN 978 0 470 67331 7 Kuehn 2001 pp 250 54 Copleston Frederick Charles 2003 The Enlightenment Voltaire to Kant p 146 Sassen Brigitte Kant s Early Critics The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy 2000 Ein Jahrhundert deutscher Literaturkritik vol III Der Aufstieg zur Klassik in der Kritik der Zeit Berlin 1959 p 315 as quoted in Gulyga Arsenij Immanuel Kant His Life and Thought Trans Marijan Despaltovic Boston Birkhauser 1987 Kuehn 2001 pp 268 69 Guyer Paul 2006 The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press p 631 ISBN 978 0 521 82303 6 a b Werner S Pluhar Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason Archived 4 March 2020 at the Wayback Machine 2009 Description Archived 1 February 2020 at the Wayback Machine amp Contents With an Introduction Archived 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine by Stephen Palmquist Indianapolis Hackett Publishing Company a b c d e Derrida Vacant Chair p 44 Open letter by Kant denouncing Fichte s Philosophy Korpora org in German Archived from the original on 19 July 2011 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Peirce C S Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 1 HUP 1960 Kant and his Refutation of Idealism p 15 Kant Immanuel Logic G B Jasche ed R S Hartman W Schwarz translators Indianapolis 1984 p xv Karl Vorlander Immanuel Kant Der Mann und das Werk Hamburg Meiner 1992 p II 332 Heine on Immanuel Kant PDF Archived PDF from the original on 23 November 2015 Retrieved 10 July 2015 Examined Lives From Socrates to Nietzsche James Miller p 284 Immanuel Kant and the Bo a rders of Art History Mark Cheetham in The Subjects of Art History Historical Objects in Contemporary Perspectives p 16 Beyer Susanne 25 July 2014 Resurrecting Konigsberg Russian City Looks to German Roots Spiegel Online Archived from the original on 4 February 2018 Retrieved 3 February 2018 Executive order on establishing Immanuel Kant University Kant CPuR Bxxviii Bxxx di Giovanni 2005 Rohlf 2020 2 1 Kant CPuR A804 05 B833 Kant CPuR Bxxx Guyer 2014 pp 7 8 Jankowiak 2023 Guyer 2014 pp 6 8 di Giovanni George 1996 Translator s Introduction In Religion and Rational Theology Cambridge University Press p 49 citing Kant in correspondence with Staudlin Rohlf 2020 Immanuel Kant Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 14 November 2019 Retrieved 29 May 2019 Kant CPuR B135 Guyer 2014 p 51 Kant CPuR B1 3 Kant CPuR A6 8 B10 12 a b Guyer 2014 pp 52 54 Hume David An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Section 4 Part 1 Kant CPuR B3 4 Kant CPuR B14 17 Guyer 2014 p 55 Kant CPuR A15 B29 emphases added Guyer 2014 pp 32 61 Rohlf 2020 2 12 Guyer 2014 pp 60 61 Kant CPuR A51 B75 Kant CPuR Bxvi xviii Rohlf 2020 2 2 Jankowiak 2023 2 g Guyer 2014 ch 4 Kant CPuR B21 Kant CPuR Axi xii Jankowiak 2023 2 d a b Rohlf 2020 3 Kant CPuR A43 B59 60 A369 Kant CPuR A28 B44 A34 35 B51 51 Stang 2022 2 3 Guyer 2014 p 60 Rohlf 2020 3 1 3 2 Stang 2022 4 5 Guyer amp Wood 1998 pp 4 13 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 8 Guyer 2014 pp 89 90 Kant CPuR Axi Jankowiak 2023 2 e Rohlf 2020 4 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 9 Kant CPuR B131 32 Rohlf 2020 4 1 Guyer amp Wood 1998 pp 9 10 Guyer amp Wood 1998 pp 10 11 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 11 see Kant CPuR A182 26 B224 36 see Kant CPuR A186 211 B232 56 see Kant CPuR A211 15 B256 62 Guyer amp Wood 1998 pp 11 12 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 12 Guyer amp Wood 1998 pp 12 13 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 13 Kant CPuR A5 B8 a b Jankowiak 2023 2 g a b Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 15 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 14 Jankowiak 2023 2 g i Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 16 a b Jankowiak 2023 2 g ii Guyer amp Wood 1998 pp 16 17 Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 17 Jankowiak 2023 2 g iii Guyer amp Wood 1998 p 18 Kant CPuR A806 B834 a b c Kant CPuR A448 B467 Kant CPuR A533 34 B561 62 Kant CPuR A800 02 B 828 30 Susanne Bobzien Die Kategorien der Freiheit bei Kant in Kant Analysen Probleme Kritik Vol 1 1988 193 220 Driver 2007 p 83 Johnson 2008 sfn error no target CITEREFJohnson2008 help Schneewind 2010 p 261 Kant G 4 420 21 436 Wood Allen 2017 Formulas of the Moral Law Cambridge University Press pp 74 78 a b Kant G 4 421 Kant G 4 429 Kant G 4 431 cf 4 432 Kant G 4 440 cf 4 432 434 438 Kant G 4 439 cf 4 433 437 39 Wood Allen 2017 Formulas of the Moral Law Cambridge University Press p 6 Caygill Howard 1995 A Kant Dictionary Blackwell Publishing p 289 citing GMM Kant G 4 403 Driver 2007 p 88 Kant GMM 4 392 Gregor Mary J 1996 Translator s note on the text of The metaphysics of morals In Practical Philosophy The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant p 355 a b Wood 2006 p 68 Kant MM 6 382 91 Wood 2006 p 69 Wood 2006 p 70 Kant PP 8 349 53 Manfred Riedel Between Tradition and Revolution The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy Cambridge 1984 Kant PP 8 360 62 Hassner Pierre Immanuel Kant in History of Political Philosophy edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey The University of Chicago Press 1987 pp 581 582 Hassner Pierre Immanuel Kant in History of Political Philosophy edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey The University of Chicago Press 1987 p 603 Kant PP 8 352 Kant MM 6 355 Gregor Mary J Introduction in Practical Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 313 Ripstein Arthur 2009 Force and Freedom Kant s Legal and Political Philosophy Harvard University Press pp 9 Karl Leonhard Reinhold Letters on the Kantian Philosophy 1786 3rd Letter Johann Schultz Exposition of Kant s Critique of Pure Reason 1784 141 Kant RBMR Part IV First part First section 6 157 63 E g Walsh W H 1967 Kant Immanuel Philosophy of Religion The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Volume Four Paul Edwards ed New York Macmillan Publishing Co Inc amp The Free Press 322 Pasternack Lawrence Rossi Philip Kant s Philosophy of Religion In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2014 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 9 July 2010 Retrieved 18 October 2019 For example Peter Byrne who wrote about Kant s relationship with deism Byrne Peter 2007 Kant on God London Ashgate p 159 Wood Allen W 1970 Kant s moral religion London and Ithaca Cornell University Press p 16 Westphal Merold 2010 The Emerge of Modern Philosophy of Religion in Taliaferro Charles Draper Paul and Quinn Philip editors A Companion to Philosophy of Religion Oxford Blackwell p 135 Iţu Mircia 2004 Dumnezeu si religia in concepţia lui Immanuel Kant din Religia in limitele raţiunii in Boboc Alexandru and Maris N I editors Studii de istoria filosofiei universale volume 12 Bucharest Romanian Academy Wood Allen W 2020 Kant and Religion Cambridge University Press p 2 See e g Lawrence Pasternack Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason New York Routledge 2014 pp 239 240 Palmquist Stephen 1992 Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality Kant Studien 83 2 pp 129 148 Critique of Judgment in Kant Immanuel Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 4 Macmillan 1973 Kant CPuR A22 B36 German Idealism in History of Aesthetics Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 1 Macmillan 1973 Kant CPJ 1 Kant CPJ 20 22 Kant CPJ 40 Clewis Robert 2009 The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom Cambridge Cambridge University Press Archived from the original on 20 October 2012 Retrieved 8 December 2011 Kant CPJ 23 25 Kant CPJ 25 26 Kant CPJ 54 Jakobidze Gitman Alexander 2020 Kant s Situated Approach to Musicking and Joking Journal of Interdisciplinary Music Studies 10 17 33 doi 10 25364 24 10 2020 2 Kant UH 8 20 22 Kant UH 8 24 26 Wilson Holly 2006 Kant s Pragmatic Anthropology Albany State University of New York Press p 7 ISBN 978 0 7914 6849 4 Thomas Sturm Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen Paderborn Mentis Verlag 2009 Kant APPV 7 285 Kant APPV 7 119 a b c d Mikkelsen Jon M ed 2013 Kant and the Concept of Race Albany New York State University of New York Press pp 12 30 ISBN 9781438443614 a b c d Zorn Daniel Pascal 2020 Kant a Racist Public History Weekly 2020 8 doi 10 1515 phw 2020 17156 ISSN 2197 6376 a b c Kleingeld 2007 pp 573 92 Eze Emmanuel 1997 The Color of Reason The Idea of Race in Kant s Anthropology In Eze Emmanuel Chukwudi ed Postcolonial African Philosophy A Critical Reader Blackwell pp 103 140 Retrieved 20 April 2023 Serequeberhan T 1996 Eurocentrism in philosophy The case of Immanuel Kant The Philosophical Forum The Philosophy Junkie Immanuel Kant s Racism and Sexism with Professors Lucy Allais and Helga Varden on Apple Podcasts Apple Podcasts Retrieved 20 April 2023 Geismann Georg 1 January 2022 Why Kant Was Not a Racist Jahrbuch fur Recht und Ethik Annual Review of Law and Ethics 30 1 263 357 doi 10 3790 jre 30 1 263 ISSN 0944 4610 Bernasconi Robert 1 January 2002 Kant as an Unfamiliar Source of Racism In Ward Julie K Lott Tommy L eds Philosophers on Race Critical Essays Oxford UK Blackwell Publishers Ltd pp 145 166 doi 10 1002 9780470753514 ch8 ISBN 978 0 470 75351 4 Retrieved 21 April 2023 Eze 1997a pp 103 31 Eze 1997b pp 39 48 a b Bouie 2018 Bernasconi 2010 pp 141 48 Kant 2010 a b c d Mills 2017 pp 169 93 Bowersox 2016 Kant APPV 7 320 Shrage 2019 Mikkelsen Jon M ed 2013 Kant and the Concept of Race late eighteenth century writings Jon M Mikkelsen Albany ISBN 978 1 4619 4312 9 OCLC 861693001 Kuehn 2001 pp 298 301 343 45 cf Kant DCHR 8 91 106 Strawson Peter Bounds of Sense Essay on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason ASIN 0415040302 Einstein on Kant University of Pittsburgh Archived from the original on 9 August 2020 Retrieved 2 September 2020 Perrick Michael 1985 Kant and Kripke on Necessary Empirical Truths Mind 94 376 596 598 doi 10 1093 mind XCIV 376 596 ISSN 0026 4423 JSTOR 2254731 Stephen Palmquist The Architectonic Form of Kant s Copernican Logic Metaphilosophy 17 4 October 1986 pp 266 288 revised and reprinted as Chapter III of Kant s System of Perspectives Archived 14 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy Lanham University Press of America 1993 Kant CPracR 5 161 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1827 Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline Heidelberg pp 14 15 Beck Lewis White Neo Kantianism In Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 5 6 Macmillan 1973 Article on Neo Kantianism by a translator and scholar of Kant Schlegel Friedrich Athenaeum Fragments in Philosophical Fragments Trans Peter Firchow Minneapolis MN University of Minnesota Press 1991 See especially fragments Nos 1 43 44 Greenberg Clement Modernist Painting in The Philosophy of Art ed Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley McGraw Hill 1995 See Essential Works of Foucault 1954 1984 vol 2 Aesthetics Method and Epistemology Ed by James Faubion Trans Robert Hurley et al New York City The New Press 1998 2010 reprint See Foucault Michel 1926 entry by Maurice Florence For a discussion and qualified defense of this position see Stephen Palmquist A Priori Knowledge in Perspective I Mathematics Method and Pure Intuition The Review of Metaphysics 41 1 September 1987 pp 3 22 Ray James Lee 1998 Does Democracy Cause Peace Annual Review of Political Science 1 27 46 doi 10 1146 annurev polisci 1 1 27 Archived from the original on 17 February 2008 Aridi Sara 14 March 2017 Onora O Neill Wins Holberg Prize for Academic Research The New York Times Archived from the original on 9 January 2019 Retrieved 9 January 2019 Cassam Q The Possibility of Knowledge Oxford 2009 Sellars Wilfrid Science and Metaphysics Variations on Kantian Themes Ridgeview Publishing Company 1967 Habermas J 1994 The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of Its Voices In Habermas J Eds Postmetaphysical Thinking Political Essays Cambridge Massachusetts 115 148 Palmquist Stephen 19 November 2010 Cultivating Personhood Kant and Asian Philosophy 1st ed Hong Kong De Gruyter Inc pp 25 ISBN 978 3 11 022624 9 Wing Cheuk Chan 21 February 2006 Mou Zongsan s Transformation of Kant s Philosophy Journal of Chinese Philosophy 33 1 1 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6253 2006 00340 x Balanovskiy Valentin 2016 Whether jung was a kantian Con Textos Kantianos 4 118 126 doi 10 5281 zenodo 2550828 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 29 May 2020 Balanovskiy Valentin 2017 Kant and Jung on the prospects of Scientific Psychology Estudos Kantianos 5 1 357 390 doi 10 36311 2318 0501 2017 v5n1 26 p375 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 29 May 2020 Issacson Walter Einstein His Life and Universe p 20 Theodora Achourioti amp Michiel van Lambalgen A Formalization of Kant s Transcendental Logic The Review of Symbolic Logic 4 2011 254 289 The thesis was submitted on 17 April 1755 The public examination was held four weeks later on 13 May and the degree was formally awarded on 12 June Eric Watkins Kant Natural Science Cambridge University Press 2012 p 309 Eric Watkins ed Kant and the Sciences Oxford University Press 2001 p 27 Martin Schonfeld The Philosophy of the Young Kant The Precritical Project Oxford University Press 2000 p 74 Available online at Bonner Kant Korpus Archived 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine The thesis was publicly disputed on 27 September 1755 Kuehn 2001 p 100 Kant s application for the position was unsuccessful He defended it on 10 April 1756 Kuehn 2001 p 102 Available online at Archive org Immanuel Kant Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space Archived 16 July 2018 at the Wayback Machine The thesis was publicly disputed on 21 August 1770 Kuehn 2001 p 189 Available online at Google Books Archived 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine English translation available online at Wikisource Immanuel Kant The Critique of Pure Reason Etext library adelaide edu au Archived from the original on 2 December 2008 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Kritik der reinen Vernunft 1 Auflage Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE Archived from the original on 9 June 2007 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Frank Christian Lilienweihs 10 June 1999 Immanuel Kant Beantwortung der Frage Was ist Aufklaerung Prometheusonline de Archived from the original on 1 August 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Critique of Pure Reason Hkbu edu hk 31 October 2003 Archived from the original on 27 April 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Kritik der reinen Vernunft 2 Auflage Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE 20 July 2009 Archived from the original on 26 December 2005 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Kritik der praktischen Vernunft Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE Archived from the original on 9 June 2007 Retrieved 24 July 2009 s The Critique of Judgment Immanuel Kant Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone by Immanuel Kant 1793 Marxists org Archived from the original on 1 June 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Perpetual Peace Mountr Holyoke Archived from the original on 6 April 2019 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Zum ewigen Frieden 12 02 2004 Friedensratschlag Uni kassel de Archived from the original on 23 September 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Kant The Contest of Faculties Chnm gmu edu 1798 Archived from the original on 4 August 2011 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Der Streit der Facultaten Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE Archived from the original on 9 June 2007 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Available online at DeutschesTextArchiv de Archived 10 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine Immanuel Kant Notes and Fragments Cambridge University Press 2005 p xvi Works cited Edit Bernasconi Robert 2010 Defining Race Scientifically A response to Michael Banton Ethnicities 10 1 141 148 doi 10 1177 14687968100100010802 ISSN 1468 7968 JSTOR 23890861 S2CID 143925406 Bouie Jamelle 5 June 2018 How the Enlightenment Created Modern Race Thinking and Why We Should Confront It Slate Archived from the original on 15 June 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 Bowersox Jeff 4 February 2016 Kant on the different human races 1777 Black Central Europe Archived from the original on 16 June 2020 Retrieved 16 June 2020 Caygill Howard 1995 A Kant Dictionary Blackwell Publishing Eze Emmanuel Chukwudi 1997a Postcolonial African Philosophy A Critical Reader Wiley pp 103 131 ISBN 978 0 631 20339 1 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 Eze Emmanuel Chukwudi 1997b Race and the Enlightenment A Reader Wiley pp 39 48 ISBN 978 0 631 20136 6 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 Driver Julia 2007 Ethics The Fundamentals Blackwell ISBN 978 1 4051 1154 6 di Giovanni George 2005 Freedom and Religion in Kant and His Immediate Successors Cambridge University Press Guyer Paul 2014 Kant Routledge Guyer Paul Wood Alan W 1998 Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason Editors Introduction The Critique of Pure Reason Cambridge University Press Jankowiak Tim 2023 Immanuel Kant The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 4 March 2023 Johnson Robert 2008 Kant s Moral Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 11 September 2013 Kant Immanuel 2010 Eze Emmanuel Chukwudi ed Kant on the Different Races of Man PDF UMass Amherst Archived PDF from the original on 1 August 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 Kleingeld Pauline October 2007 Kant s Second Thoughts on Race PDF The Philosophical Quarterly 57 229 573 592 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9213 2007 498 x hdl 11370 e15b6815 5eab 42d6 a789 24a2f6ecb946 S2CID 55185762 Archived PDF from the original on 16 February 2019 Retrieved 14 December 2020 Kuehn Manfred 2001 Kant a Biography Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 49704 6 Mills Charles W 2017 Black Rights White Wrongs The Critique of Racial Liberalism Oxford University Press pp 169 193 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780190245412 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 024545 0 Archived from the original on 16 June 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 Rohlf Michael 2020 Edward N Zalta ed Immanuel Kant The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2020 Edition Schneewind J B 2010 Autonomy Obligation and Virtue An Overview of Kant s Moral Philosophy Essays on the History of Moral Philosophy Oxford University Press Shrage Laurie 18 March 2019 Should we continue to teach thinkers like Kant Voltaire and Hume without mention of the harmful prejudices they helped legitimize The New York Times Retrieved 10 November 2022 Stang Nicholas F 2022 Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman ed Kant s Transcendental Idealism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2022 Edition Wood Allen 1999 Kant s Ethical Thought Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521648363 Wood Allen 2006 Kant s Practical Philosophy In Karl Ameriks ed The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780801486043 Wood Allen 2008 Kantian Ethics Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521671149 External links EditImmanuel Kant at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Media from Commons Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Data from Wikidata Works by Immanuel Kant at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Immanuel Kant at Internet Archive Works by Immanuel Kant at LibriVox public domain audiobooks KantPapers authors and papers database powered by PhilPapers focused on Kant and located at Cornell University Stephen Palmquist s Glossary of Kantian Terminology At the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant An OverviewAestheticsLogicMetaphysicsPhilosophy of MindPhilosophy of ReligionRadical EvilTranscendental Idealism At the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel KantKant and Hume on CausalityKant and Hume on MoralityKant s Account of ReasonKant s Aesthetics and TeleologyKant s Critique of MetaphysicsKant s Moral PhilosophyKant s Philosophical DevelopmentKant s Philosophy of MathematicsKant s Philosophy of ReligionKant s Philosophy of ScienceKant s Social and Political PhilosophyKant s Theory of JudgmentKant s Transcendental ArgumentsKant s View of the Mind and Consciousness of SelfKant s Views on Space and TimeKantian Conceptualism NonconceptualismLeibniz s Influence on Kant Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Immanuel Kant amp oldid 1151771384, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.