fbpx
Wikipedia

Good and evil

In religion, ethics, philosophy, and psychology "good and evil" is a very common dichotomy. In cultures with Manichaean and Abrahamic religious influence, evil is perceived as the dualistic antagonistic opposite of good, in which good should prevail and evil should be defeated.[1] In cultures with Buddhist spiritual influence, both good and evil are perceived as part of an antagonistic duality that itself must be overcome through achieving Śūnyatā meaning emptiness in the sense of recognition of good and evil being two opposing principles but not a reality, emptying the duality of them, and achieving a oneness.[1]

The devil, in opposition to the will of God, represents evil and tempts Christ, the personification of the character and will of God. Ary Scheffer, 1854.

Evil is often used to denote profound immorality.[2] Evil has also been described as a supernatural force.[2] Definitions of evil vary, as does the analysis of its motives.[3] However, elements that are commonly associated with evil involve unbalanced behavior involving expediency, selfishness, ignorance, or neglect.[4]

The modern philosophical questions regarding good and evil are subsumed into three major areas of study: meta-ethics concerning the nature of good and evil, normative ethics concerning how we ought to behave, and applied ethics concerning particular moral issues.[5]

One of the five paintings of Extermination of Evil portrays Sendan Kendatsuba, one of the eight guardians of Buddhist law, banishing evil.

History and etymology

Every language has a word expressing good in the sense of "having the right or desirable quality" (ἀρετή) and bad in the sense "undesirable". A sense of moral judgment and a distinction "right and wrong, good and bad" are cultural universals.[6]

Ancient world

The philosopher Zoroaster simplified the pantheon of early Iranian gods[7] into two opposing forces: Ahura Mazda (Illuminating Wisdom) and Angra Mainyu (Destructive Spirit) which were in conflict.

This idea developed into a religion which spawned many sects, some of which embraced an extreme dualistic belief that the material world should be shunned and the spiritual world should be embraced. Gnostic ideas influenced many ancient religions[8] which teach that gnosis (variously interpreted as enlightenment, salvation, emancipation or 'oneness with God') may be reached by practising philanthropy to the point of personal poverty, sexual abstinence (as far as possible for hearers, total for initiates) and diligently searching for wisdom by helping others.[9]

Similarly, in ancient Egypt, there were the concepts of Ma'at, the principle of justice, order, and cohesion, and Isfet, the principle of chaos, disorder, and decay, with the former being the power and principles which society sought to embody where the latter was such that undermined society.[10] This correspondence can also be seen reflected in ancient Mesopotamian religion as well in the conflict between Marduk and Tiamat.[11][12]

Classical world

In Western civilisation, the basic meanings of κακός and ἀγαθός are "bad, cowardly" and "good, brave, capable", and their absolute sense emerges only around 400 BC, with pre-Socratic philosophy, in particular Democritus.[13] Morality in this absolute sense solidifies in the dialogues of Plato, together with the emergence of monotheistic thought (notably in Euthyphro, which ponders the concept of piety (τὸ ὅσιον) as a moral absolute). The idea was further developed in Late Antiquity by Neoplatonists, Gnostics, and Church Fathers.[14]

This development from the relative or habitual to the absolute is also evident in the terms ethics and morality both being derived from terms for "regional custom", Greek ήθος and Latin mores, respectively (see also siðr).

Medieval period

According to the classical definition of Augustine of Hippo, sin is "a word, deed, or desire in opposition to the eternal law of God."[15]

Many medieval Christian theologians both broadened and narrowed the basic concept of Good and evil until it came to have several, sometimes complex definitions[16] such as:

Modern ideas

Today the basic dichotomy often breaks down along these lines:

  • Good is a broad concept often associated with life, charity, continuity, happiness, love, or justice.
  • Evil is often associated with conscious and deliberate wrongdoing, discrimination designed to harm others, humiliation of people designed to diminish their psychological needs and dignity, destructiveness, and acts of unnecessary or indiscriminate violence.[3]

The modern English word evil (Old English yfel) and its cognates such as the German Übel and Dutch euvel are widely considered to come from a Proto-Germanic reconstructed form of *ubilaz, comparable to the Hittite huwapp- ultimately from the Proto-Indo-European form *wap- and suffixed zero-grade form *up-elo-. Other later Germanic forms include Middle English evel, ifel, ufel, Old Frisian evel (adjective and noun), Old Saxon ubil, Old High German ubil, and Gothic ubils.

The nature of being good has been given many treatments; one is that the good is based on the natural love, bonding, and affection that begins at the earliest stages of personal development; another is that goodness is a product of knowing truth. Differing views also exist as to why evil might arise. Many religious and philosophical traditions claim that evil behavior is an aberration that results from the imperfect human condition (e.g. "The Fall of Man"). Sometimes, evil is attributed to the existence of free will and human agency. Some argue that evil itself is ultimately based in an ignorance of truth (i.e., human value, sanctity, divinity). A variety of thinkers have alleged the opposite, by suggesting that evil is learned as a consequence of tyrannical social structures.[citation needed]

Theories of moral goodness

Chinese moral philosophy

In Confucianism and Taoism, there is no direct analogue to the way good and evil are opposed, although references to demonic influence is common in Chinese folk religion. Confucianism's primary concern is with correct social relationships and the behavior appropriate to the learned or superior man. Evil would thus correspond to wrong behavior. Still less does it map into Taoism, in spite of the centrality of dualism in that system[citation needed], but the opposite of the basic virtues of Taoism (compassion, moderation, and humility) can be inferred to be the analogue of evil in it.[17][18]

Western philosophy

Pyrrhonism

Pyrrhonism holds that good and evil do not exist by nature, meaning that good and evil do not exist within the things themselves. All judgments of good and evil are relative to the one doing the judging.

Spinoza

Benedict de Spinoza states:

1. By good, I understand that which we certainly know is useful to us.
2. By evil, on the contrary I understand that which we certainly know hinders us from possessing anything that is good.[19]

Spinoza assumes a quasi-mathematical style and states these further propositions which he purports to prove or demonstrate from the above definitions in part IV of his Ethics :[19]

  • Proposition 8 "Knowledge of good or evil is nothing but affect of joy or sorrow in so far as we are conscious of it."
  • Proposition 30 "Nothing can be evil through that which it possesses in common with our nature, but in so far as a thing is evil to us it is contrary to us."
  • Proposition 64 "The knowledge of evil is inadequate knowledge."
    • Corollary "Hence it follows that if the human mind had none but adequate ideas, it would form no notion of evil."
  • Proposition 65 "According to the guidance of reason, of two things which are good, we shall follow the greater good, and of two evils, follow the less."
  • Proposition 68 "If men were born free, they would form no conception of good and evil so long as they were free."

Nietzsche

Friedrich Nietzsche, in a rejection of Judeo-Christian morality, addresses this in two books, Beyond Good and Evil and On the Genealogy of Morals. In these works, he states that the natural, functional, "non-good" has been socially transformed into the religious concept of evil by the "slave mentality" of the masses, who resent their "masters", the strong. He also critiques morality by saying that many who consider themselves to be moral are simply acting out of cowardice – wanting to do evil but afraid of the repercussions.

Psychology

Carl Jung

Carl Jung, in his book Answer to Job and elsewhere, depicted evil as the dark side of the Devil. People tend to believe evil is something external to them, because they project their shadow onto others. Jung interpreted the story of Jesus as an account of God facing his own shadow.[20]

Philip Zimbardo

In 2007, Philip Zimbardo suggested that people may act in evil ways as a result of a collective identity. This hypothesis, based on his previous experience from the Stanford prison experiment, was published in the book The Lucifer Effect: Understanding How Good People Turn Evil.[21]

Religion

Abrahamic religions

Baháʼí Faith

The Baháʼí Faith asserts that evil is non-existent and that it is a concept for the lacking of good, just as cold is the state of no heat, darkness is the state of no light, forgetfulness the lacking of memory, ignorance the lacking of knowledge. All of these are states of lacking and have no real existence.[22]

Thus, evil does not exist, and is relative to man. `Abdu'l-Bahá, son of the founder of the religion, in Some Answered Questions states:

"Nevertheless, a doubt occurs to the mind—that is, scorpions and serpents are poisonous. Are they good or evil, for they are existing beings? Yes, a scorpion is evil in relation to man; a serpent is evil in relation to man; but in relation to themselves they are not evil, for their poison is their weapon, and by their sting they defend themselves."[22]

Thus, evil is more of an intellectual concept than a true reality. Since God is good, and upon creating creation he confirmed it by saying it is Good (Genesis 1:31) evil cannot have a true reality.[22]

Christianity
 
In many religions, angels are considered good beings. In the Christian tradition, God—being the creator of all life—manifests himself through the son of God, Jesus Christ, who is the personification of goodness.
 
Satan, as seen in Codex Gigas. Demons are generally seen as evil beings, and Satan as the greatest of these (in the Christian tradition).

Christian theology draws its concept of evil from the Old and New Testaments. The Christian Bible exercises “the dominant influence upon ideas about God and evil in the Western world.”[23] In the Old Testament, evil is understood to be an opposition to God as well as something unsuitable or inferior such as the leader of the fallen angels Satan.[24] In the New Testament the Greek word poneros is used to indicate unsuitability, while kakos is used to refer to opposition to God in the human realm.[25] Officially, the Catholic Church extracts its understanding of evil from its canonical antiquity and the Dominican theologian, Thomas Aquinas, who in Summa Theologica defines evil as the absence or privation of good.[26] French-American theologian Henri Blocher describes evil, when viewed as a theological concept, as an "unjustifiable reality. In common parlance, evil is 'something' that occurs in experience that ought not to be."[27] According to 1 Timothy 6:10 "For the love of money is the root of all of evil"[28]

In Mormonism, mortal life is viewed as a test of faith, where one's choices are central to the Plan of Salvation. See Agency (LDS Church). Evil is that which keeps one from discovering the nature of God. It is believed that one must choose not to be evil to return to God.

Christian Science believes that evil arises from a misunderstanding of the goodness of nature, which is understood as being inherently perfect if viewed from the correct (spiritual) perspective. Misunderstanding God's reality leads to incorrect choices, which are termed evil. This has led to the rejection of any separate power being the source of evil, or of God as being the source of evil; instead, the appearance of evil is the result of a mistaken concept of good. Christian Scientists argue that even the most evil person does not pursue evil for its own sake, but from the mistaken viewpoint that he or she will achieve some kind of good thereby.

Islam

There is no concept of absolute evil in Islam, as a fundamental universal principle that is independent from and equal with good in a dualistic sense. Within Islam, it is considered essential to believe that all comes from God, whether it is perceived as good or bad by individuals; and things that are perceived as evil or bad are either natural events (natural disasters or illnesses) or caused by humanity's free will to disobey God's orders.

According to the Ahmadiyya understanding of Islam, evil does not have a positive existence in itself and is merely the lack of good, just as darkness is the result of lack of light.[29]

Judaism

In Judaism, yetzer hara is the congenital inclination to do evil, by violating the will of God. The term is drawn from the phrase "the imagination of the heart of man [is] evil" (יֵצֶר לֵב הָאָדָם רַע‎, yetzer lev-ha-adam ra), which occurs twice at the beginning of the Torah. Genesis 6:5 and 8:21. The Hebrew word "yetzer" having appeared twice in Genesis occurs again at the end of the Torah: "I knew their devisings that they do".[30] Thus from beginning to end the heart's "yetzer" is continually bent on evil, a profoundly pessimistic view of the human being. However, the Torah which began with blessing[31] anticipates future blessing[32] which will come as a result of God circumcising the heart in the latter days.[33]

In traditional Judaism, the yetzer hara is not a demonic force, but rather man's misuse of things the physical body needs to survive. Thus, the need for food becomes gluttony due to the yetzer hara. The need for procreation becomes promiscuity, and so on. The yetzer hara could thus be best described as one's baser instincts.

According to the Talmudic tractate Avot de-Rabbi Natan, a boy's evil inclination is greater than his good inclination until he turns 13 (bar mitzvah), at which point the good inclination is "born" and able to control his behavior.[34] Moreover, the rabbis have stated: "The greater the man, the greater his [evil] inclination."[35]

Indian religions

Buddhism
 
Extermination of Evil. Late Heian period (12th century Japan)

Buddhist ethics are traditionally based on what Buddhists view as the enlightened perspective of the Buddha, or other enlightened beings such as Bodhisattvas. The Indian term for ethics or morality used in Buddhism is Śīla or sīla (Pāli). Śīla in Buddhism is one of three sections of the Noble Eightfold Path, and is a code of conduct that embraces a commitment to harmony and self-restraint with the principal motivation being nonviolence, or freedom from causing harm. It has been variously described as virtue,[36] moral discipline[37] and precept.

Sīla is an internal, aware, and intentional ethical behavior, according to one's commitment to the path of liberation. It is an ethical compass within self and relationships, rather than what is associated with the English word "morality" (i.e., obedience, a sense of obligation, and external constraint).

Sīla is one of the three practices foundational to Buddhism and the non-sectarian Vipassana movement; sīla, samādhi, and paññā as well as the Theravadin foundations of sīla, dāna, and bhavana. It is also the second pāramitā.[38] Sīla is also wholehearted commitment to what is wholesome. Two aspects of sīla are essential to the training: right "performance" (caritta), and right "avoidance" (varitta). Honoring the precepts of sīla is considered a "great gift" (mahadana) to others, because it creates an atmosphere of trust, respect, and security. It means the practitioner poses no threat to another person's life, property, family, rights, or well-being.[39]

Moral instructions are included in Buddhist scriptures or handed down through tradition. Most scholars of Buddhist ethics thus rely on the examination of Buddhist scriptures, and the use of anthropological evidence from traditional Buddhist societies, to justify claims about the nature of Buddhist ethics.[40]

Hinduism

In Hinduism the concept of dharma or righteousness clearly divides the world into good and evil, and clearly explains that wars have to be waged sometimes to establish and protect dharma, this war is called Dharmayuddha. This division of good and evil is of major importance in both the Hindu epics of Ramayana and Mahabharata. However, the main emphasis in Hinduism is on bad action, rather than bad people. The Hindu holy text, the Bhagavad Gita, speaks of the balance of good and evil. When this balance goes off, divine incarnations come to help to restore this balance.[41]

Sikhism

In adherence to the core principle of spiritual evolution, the Sikh idea of evil changes depending on one's position on the path to liberation. At the beginning stages of spiritual growth, good and evil may seem neatly separated. However, once one's spirit evolves to the point where it sees most clearly, the idea of evil vanishes and the truth is revealed. In his writings Guru Arjan explains that, because God is the source of all things, what we believe to be evil must too come from God. And because God is ultimately a source of absolute good, nothing truly evil can originate from God.[42]

Nevertheless, Sikhism, like many other religions, does incorporate a list of "vices" from which suffering, corruption, and abject negativity arise. These are known as the Five Thieves, called such due to their propensity to cloud the mind and lead one astray from the prosecution of righteous action.[43] These are:[44]

One who gives in to the temptations of the Five Thieves is known as "Manmukh", or someone who lives selfishly and without virtue. Inversely, the "Gurmukh, who thrive in their reverence toward divine knowledge, rise above vice via the practice of the high virtues of Sikhism. These are:[45]

  • Sewa, or selfless service to others.
  • Nam Simran, or meditation upon the divine name.

Zoroastrianism

In the originally Persian religion of Zoroastrianism, the world is a battle ground between the god Ahura Mazda (also called Ormazd) and the malignant spirit Angra Mainyu (also called Ahriman). The final resolution of the struggle between good and evil was supposed to occur on a day of Judgement, in which all beings that have lived will be led across a bridge of fire, and those who are evil will be cast down forever. In Afghan belief, angels and saints are beings sent to help us achieve the path towards goodness.[46]

Descriptive, meta-ethical, and normative fields

It is possible to treat the essential theories of value by the use of a philosophical and academic approach. In properly analyzing theories of value, everyday beliefs are not only carefully catalogued and described, but also rigorously analyzed and judged.

There are at least two basic ways of presenting a theory of value, based on two different kinds of questions:

  • What do people find good, and what do they despise?
  • What really is good, and what really is bad?

The two questions are subtly different. One may answer the first question by researching the world by use of social science, and examining the preferences that people assert. However, one may answer the second question by use of reasoning, introspection, prescription, and generalization. The former kind of method of analysis is called "descriptive", because it attempts to describe what people actually view as good or evil; while the latter is called "normative", because it tries to actively prohibit evils and cherish goods. These descriptive and normative approaches can be complementary. For example, tracking the decline of the popularity of slavery across cultures is the work of descriptive ethics, while advising that slavery be avoided is normative.

Meta-ethics is the study of the fundamental questions concerning the nature and origins of the good and the evil, including inquiry into the nature of good and evil, as well as the meaning of evaluative language. In this respect, meta-ethics is not necessarily tied to investigations into how others see the good, or of asserting what is good.

Theories of the intrinsically good

A satisfying formulation of goodness is valuable because it might allow one to construct a good life or society by reliable processes of deduction, elaboration, or prioritization. One could answer the ancient question, "How should we then live?" among many other important related questions. It has long been thought that this question can best be answered by examining what it is that necessarily makes a thing valuable, or in what the source of value consists.

Platonic idealism

One attempt to define goodness describes it as a property of the world with Platonic idealism. According to this claim, to talk about the good is to talk about something real that exists in the object itself, independent of the perception of it. Plato advocated this view, in his expression that there is such a thing as an eternal realm of forms or ideas, and that the greatest of the ideas and the essence of being was goodness, or The good. The good was defined by many ancient Greeks and other ancient philosophers as a perfect and eternal idea, or blueprint. The good is the right relation between all that exists, and this exists in the mind of the Divine, or some heavenly realm. The good is the harmony of a just political community, love, friendship, the ordered human soul of virtues, and the right relation to the Divine and to Nature. The characters in Plato's dialogues mention the many virtues of a philosopher, or a lover of wisdom.

A theist is a person who believes that the Supreme Being exists or gods exist (monotheism or polytheism). A theist may, therefore, claim that the universe has a purpose and value according to the will of such creator(s) that lies partially beyond human understanding. For instance, Thomas Aquinas—a proponent of this view—believed he had proven the existence of God, and the right relations that humans ought to have to the divine first cause.

Monotheists might also hope for infinite universal love. Such hope is often translated as "faith", and wisdom itself is largely defined within some religious doctrines as a knowledge and understanding of innate goodness. The concepts of innocence, spiritual purity, and salvation are likewise related to a concept of being in, or returning to, a state of goodness—one that, according to various teachings of "enlightenment", approaches a state of holiness (or Godliness).

Perfectionism

Aristotle believed that virtues consisted of realization of potentials unique to humanity, such as the use of reason. This type of view, called perfectionism, has been recently defended in modern form by Thomas Hurka.

An entirely different form of perfectionism has arisen in response to rapid technological change. Some techno-optimists, especially transhumanists, avow a form of perfectionism in which the capacity to determine good and trade off fundamental values, is expressed not by humans but by software, genetic engineering of humans, artificial intelligence. Skeptics assert that rather than perfect goodness, it would be only the appearance of perfect goodness, reinforced by persuasion technology and probably brute force of violent technological escalation, which would cause people to accept such rulers or rules authored by them.

Welfarist theories

Welfarist theories of value say things that are good are such because of their positive effects on human well-being.

Subjective theories of well-being

It is difficult to figure out where an immaterial trait such as "goodness" could reside in the world. A counterproposal is to locate values inside people. Some philosophers go so far as to say that if some state of affairs does not tend to arouse a desirable subjective state in self-aware beings, then it cannot be good.

Most philosophers that think goods have to create desirable mental states also say that goods are experiences of self-aware beings. These philosophers often distinguish the experience, which they call an intrinsic good, from the things that seem to cause the experience, which they call "inherent" goods.

Some theories describe no higher collective value than that of maximizing pleasure for individual(s). Some even define goodness and intrinsic value as the experience of pleasure, and bad as the experience of pain. This view is called hedonism, a monistic theory of value. It has two main varieties: simple, and Epicurean.

Simple hedonism is the view that physical pleasure is the ultimate good. However, the ancient philosopher Epicurus used the word 'pleasure' in a more general sense that encompassed a range of states from bliss to contentment to relief. Contrary to popular caricature, he valued pleasures of the mind to bodily pleasures, and advocated moderation as the surest path to happiness.

Jeremy Bentham's book The Principles of Morals and Legislation prioritized goods by considering pleasure, pain and consequences. This theory had a wide effect on public affairs, up to and including the present day. A similar system was later named Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill. More broadly, utilitarian theories are examples of Consequentialism. All utilitarian theories are based upon the maxim of utility, which states that good is whatever provides the greatest happiness for the greatest number. It follows from this principle that what brings happiness to the greatest number of people, is good.

A benefit of tracing good to pleasure and pain is that both are easily understandable, both in oneself and to an extent in others. For the hedonist, the explanation for helping behaviour may come in the form of empathy—the ability of a being to "feel" another's pain. People tend to value the lives of gorillas more than those of mosquitoes because the gorilla lives and feels, making it easier to empathize with them. This idea is carried forward in the ethical relationship view and has given rise to the animal rights movement and parts of the peace movement. The impact of sympathy on human behaviour is compatible with Enlightenment views, including David Hume's stances that the idea of a self with unique identity is illusory, and that morality ultimately comes down to sympathy and fellow feeling for others, or the exercise of approval underlying moral judgments.

A view adopted by James Griffin attempts to find a subjective alternative to hedonism as an intrinsic value. He argues that the satisfaction of one's informed desires constitutes well-being, whether or not these desires actually bring the agent happiness. Moreover, these preferences must be life-relevant, that is, contribute to the success of a person's life overall.

Desire satisfaction may occur without the agent's awareness of the satisfaction of the desire. For example, if a man wishes for his legal will to be enacted after his death, and it is, then his desire has been satisfied even though he will never experience or know of it.

Meher Baba proposed that it is not the satisfaction of desires that motivates the agent but rather "a desire to be free from the limitation of all desires. Those experiences and actions which increase the fetters of desire are bad, and those experiences and actions which tend to emancipate the mind from limiting desires are good."[47] It is through good actions, then, that the agent becomes free from selfish desires and achieves a state of well-being: "The good is the main link between selfishness thriving and dying. Selfishness, which in the beginning is the father of evil tendencies, becomes through good deeds the hero of its own defeat. When the evil tendencies are completely replaced by good tendencies, selfishness is transformed into selflessness, i.e., individual selfishness loses itself in universal interest."[47]

Objective theories of well-being

The idea that the ultimate good exists and is not orderable but is globally measurable is reflected in various ways in economic (classical economics, green economics, welfare economics, gross national happiness) and scientific (positive psychology, the science of morality) well-being measuring theories, all of which focus on various ways of assessing progress towards that goal, a so-called genuine progress indicator. Modern economics thus reflects very ancient philosophy, but a calculation or quantitative or other process based on cardinality and statistics replaces the simple ordering of values.

For example, in both economics and in folk wisdom, the value of something seems to rise so long as it is relatively scarce. However, if it becomes too scarce, it leads often to a conflict, and can reduce collective value.

In the classical political economy of Adam Smith and David Ricardo, and in its critique by Karl Marx, human labour is seen as the ultimate source of all new economic value. This is an objective theory of value, which attributes value to real production-costs, and ultimately expenditures of human labour-time (see law of value). It contrasts with marginal utility theory, which argues that the value of labour depends on subjective preferences by consumers, which may however also be objectively studied.

The economic value of labour may be assessed technically in terms of its use-value or utility or commercially in terms of its exchange-value, price or production cost (see labour power). But its value may also be socially assessed in terms of its contribution to the wealth and well-being of a society.

In non-market societies, labour may be valued primarily in terms of skill, time, and output, as well as moral or social criteria and legal obligations. In market societies, labour is valued economically primarily through the labour market. The price of labour may then be set by supply and demand, by strike action or legislation, or by legal or professional entry-requirements into occupations.

Mid-range theories

Conceptual metaphor theories argue against both subjective and objective conceptions of value and meaning, and focus on the relationships between body and other essential elements of human life. In effect, conceptual metaphor theories treat ethics as an ontology problem and the issue of how to work-out values as a negotiation of these metaphors, not the application of some abstraction or a strict standoff between parties who have no way to understand each other's views.

Philosophical questions

Universality

 
Adolf Hitler is sometimes used as a modern definition of evil.[48] Hitler's policies and orders resulted in the deaths of about 50 million people.[49]

A fundamental question is whether there is a universal, transcendent definition of evil, or whether evil is determined by one's social or cultural background. C. S. Lewis, in The Abolition of Man, maintained that there are certain acts that are universally considered evil, such as rape and murder. However, the numerous instances in which rape or murder is morally affected by social context call this into question. Up until the mid-19th century, many countries practiced forms of slavery. As is often the case, those transgressing moral boundaries stood to profit from that exercise. Arguably, slavery has always been the same and objectively evil, but individuals with a motivation to transgress will justify that action.

The Nazis, during World War II, considered genocide to be acceptable,[50] as did the Hutu Interahamwe in the Rwandan genocide.[51][52] One might point out, though, that the actual perpetrators of those atrocities probably avoided calling their actions genocide, since the objective meaning of any act accurately described by that word is to wrongfully kill a selected group of people, which is an action that at least their victims will understand to be evil. Universalists consider evil independent of culture, and wholly related to acts or intents.

Views on the nature of evil tend to fall into one of four opposed camps:

  • Moral absolutism holds that good and evil are fixed concepts established by a deity or deities, nature, morality, common sense, or some other source.
  • Amoralism claims that good and evil are meaningless, that there is no moral ingredient in nature.
  • Moral relativism holds that standards of good and evil are only products of local culture, custom, or prejudice.
  • Moral universalism is the attempt to find a compromise between the absolutist sense of morality, and the relativist view; universalism claims that morality is only flexible to a degree, and that what is truly good or evil can be determined by examining what is commonly considered to be evil amongst all humans.

Plato wrote that there are relatively few ways to do good, but there are countless ways to do evil, which can therefore have a much greater impact on our lives, and the lives of other beings capable of suffering.[53]

Usefulness as a term

Psychologist Albert Ellis, in his school of psychology called Rational Emotive Behavioral Therapy, says the root of anger and the desire to harm someone is almost always related to variations of implicit or explicit philosophical beliefs about other human beings. He further claims that without holding variants of those covert or overt belief and assumptions, the tendency to resort to violence in most cases is less likely.

American psychiatrist M. Scott Peck on the other hand, describes evil as militant ignorance.[54] The original Judeo-Christian concept of sin is as a process that leads one to miss the mark and not achieve perfection. Peck argues that while most people are conscious of this at least on some level, those that are evil actively and militantly refuse this consciousness. Peck describes evil as a malignant type of self-righteousness which results in a projection of evil onto selected specific innocent victims (often children or other people in relatively powerless positions). Peck considers those he calls evil to be attempting to escape and hide from their own conscience (through self-deception) and views this as being quite distinct from the apparent absence of conscience evident in sociopaths.

According to Peck, an evil person:[54][55]

  • Is consistently self-deceiving, with the intent of avoiding guilt and maintaining a self-image of perfection
  • Deceives others as a consequence of their own self-deception
  • Psychologically projects his or her evils and sins onto very specific targets, scapegoating those targets while treating everyone else normally ("their insensitivity toward him was selective")[56]
  • Commonly hates with the pretense of love, for the purposes of self-deception as much as the deception of others
  • Abuses political or emotional power ("the imposition of one's will upon others by overt or covert coercion")[57]
  • Maintains a high level of respectability and lies incessantly in order to do so
  • Is consistent in his or her sins. Evil people are defined not so much by the magnitude of their sins, but by their consistency (of destructiveness)
  • Is unable to think from the viewpoint of their victim
  • Has a covert intolerance to criticism and other forms of narcissistic injury

He also considers certain institutions may be evil, as his discussion of the My Lai Massacre and its attempted coverup illustrate. By this definition, acts of criminal and state terrorism would also be considered evil.

Necessary evil

 
Martin Luther believed that occasional minor evil could have a positive effect

Martin Luther argued that there are cases where a little evil is a positive good. He wrote, "Seek out the society of your boon companions, drink, play, talk bawdy, and amuse yourself. One must sometimes commit a sin out of hate and contempt for the Devil, so as not to give him the chance to make one scrupulous over mere nothings... ."[58]

The necessary evil approach to politics was put forth by Niccolò Machiavelli, a 16th-century Florentine writer who advised tyrants that "it is far safer to be feared than loved."[59] Treachery, deceit, eliminating political rivals, and the usage of fear are offered as methods of stabilizing the prince's security and power.[60]

The international relations theories of realism and neorealism, sometimes called realpolitik advise politicians to explicitly ban absolute moral and ethical considerations from international politics, and to focus on self-interest, political survival, and power politics, which they hold to be more accurate in explaining a world they view as explicitly amoral and dangerous. Political realists usually justify their perspectives by laying claim to a higher moral duty specific to political leaders, under which the greatest evil is seen to be the failure of the state to protect itself and its citizens. Machiavelli wrote: "...there will be traits considered good that, if followed, will lead to ruin, while other traits, considered vices which if practiced achieve security and well being for the Prince."[59]

Anton LaVey, founder of the Church of Satan, was a materialist and claimed that evil is actually good. He was responding to the common practice of describing sexuality or disbelief as evil, and his claim was that when the word evil is used to describe the natural pleasures and instincts of men and women, or the skepticism of an inquiring mind, the things called evil are really good.[61]

Goodness and agency

Goodwill

John Rawls' book A Theory of Justice prioritized social arrangements and goods based on their contribution to justice. Rawls defined justice as fairness, especially in distributing social goods, defined fairness in terms of procedures, and attempted to prove that just institutions and lives are good, if rational individuals' goods are considered fairly. Rawls's crucial invention was the original position, a procedure in which one tries to make objective moral decisions by refusing to let personal facts about oneself enter one's moral calculations. Immanuel Kant, a great influence for Rawls, similarly applies a lot of procedural practice within the practical application of The Categorical Imperative, however, this is indeed not based solely on 'fairness'.

Society, life and ecology

Many views value unity as a good: to go beyond eudaimonia by saying that an individual person's flourishing is valuable only as a means to the flourishing of society as a whole. In other words, a single person's life is, ultimately, not important or worthwhile in itself, but is good only as a means to the success of society as a whole. Some elements of Confucianism are an example of this, encouraging the view that people ought to conform as individuals to demands of a peaceful and ordered society.

According to the naturalistic view, the flourishing of society is not, or not the only, intrinsically good thing. Defenses of this notion are often formulated by reference to biology, and observations that living things compete more with their own kind than with other kinds. Rather, what is of intrinsic good is the flourishing of all sentient life, extending to those animals that have some level of similar sentience, such as Great Ape personhood. Others go farther, declaring that life itself is of intrinsic value.

By another approach, one achieves peace and agreement by focusing, not on one's peers (who may be rivals or competitors), but on the common environment. The reasoning: As living beings it is clearly and objectively good that we are surrounded by an ecosystem that supports life. Indeed, if we weren't, we could neither discuss that good nor even recognize it. The anthropic principle in cosmology recognizes this view.[citation needed]

Under materialism or even embodiment values, or in any system that recognizes the validity of ecology as a scientific study of limits and potentials, an ecosystem is a fundamental good. To all who investigate, it seems that goodness, or value, exists within an ecosystem, Earth. Creatures within that ecosystem and wholly dependent on it, evaluate good relative to what else could be achieved there. In other words, good is situated in a particular place and one does not dismiss everything that is not available there (such as very low gravity or absolutely abundant sugar candy) as "not good enough", one works within its constraints. Transcending them and learning to be satisfied with them, is thus another sort of value, perhaps called satisfaction.

Values and the people that hold them seem necessarily subordinate to the ecosystem. If this is so, then what kind of being could validly apply the word "good" to an ecosystem as a whole? Who would have the power to assess and judge an ecosystem as good or bad? By what criteria? And by what criteria would ecosystems be modified, especially larger ones such as the atmosphere (climate change) or oceans (extinction) or forests (deforestation)?[62]

"Remaining on Earth" as the most basic value. While green ethicists have been most forthright about it, and have developed theories of Gaia philosophy, biophilia, bioregionalism that reflect it, the questions are now universally recognized as central in determining value, e.g. the economic "value of Earth" to humans as a whole, or the "value of life" that is neither whole-Earth nor human. Many have come to the conclusion that without assuming ecosystem continuation as a universal good, with attendant virtues like biodiversity and ecological wisdom it is impossible to justify such operational requirements as sustainability of human activity on Earth.

One response is that humans are not necessarily confined to Earth, and could use it and move on. A counter-argument is that only a tiny fraction of humans could do this—and they would be self-selected by ability to do technological escalation on others (for instance, the ability to create large spacecraft to flee the planet in, and simultaneously fend off others who seek to prevent them). Another counter-argument is that extraterrestrial life would encounter the fleeing humans and destroy them as a locust species. A third is that if there are no other worlds fit to support life (and no extraterrestrials who compete with humans to occupy them) it is both futile to flee, and foolish to imagine that it would take less energy and skill to protect the Earth as a habitat than it would take to construct some new habitat.

Accordingly, remaining on Earth, as a living being surrounded by a working ecosystem, is a fair statement of the most basic values and goodness to any being we are able to communicate with. A moral system without this axiom seems simply not actionable.

However, most religious systems acknowledge an afterlife and improving this is seen as an even more basic good. In many other moral systems, also, remaining on Earth in a state that lacks honor or power over self is less desirable—consider seppuku in bushido, kamikazes or the role of suicide attacks in Jihadi rhetoric. In all these systems, remaining on Earth is perhaps no higher than a third-place value.

Radical values environmentalism can be seen as either a very old or a very new view: that the only intrinsically good thing is a flourishing ecosystem; individuals and societies are merely instrumentally valuable, good only as means to having a flourishing ecosystem. The Gaia philosophy is the most detailed expression of this overall thought but it strongly influenced deep ecology and the modern Green Parties.

It is often claimed that aboriginal peoples never lost this sort of view. Anthropological linguistics studies links between their languages and the ecosystems they lived in, which gave rise to their knowledge distinctions. Very often, environmental cognition and moral cognition were not distinguished in these languages. Offenses to nature were like those to other people, and Animism reinforced this by giving nature "personality" via myth. Anthropological theories of value explore these questions.

Most people in the world reject older situated ethics and localized religious views. However small-community-based and ecology-centric views have gained some popularity in recent years. In part, this has been attributed to the desire for ethical certainties. Such a deeply rooted definition of goodness would be valuable because it might allow one to construct a good life or society by reliable processes of deduction, elaboration or prioritisation. Ones that relied only on local referents one could verify for oneself, creating more certainty and therefore less investment in protection, hedging and insuring against consequences of loss of the value.

History and novelty

An event is often seen as being of value simply because of its novelty in fashion and art. By contrast, cultural history and other antiques are sometimes seen as of value in and of themselves due to their age. Philosopher-historians Will and Ariel Durant spoke as much with the quote, "As the sanity of the individual lies in the continuity of his memories, so the sanity of the group lies in the continuity of its traditions; in either case a break in the chain invites a neurotic reaction" (The Lessons of History, 72).

Assessment of the value of old or historical artifacts takes into consideration, especially but not exclusively: the value placed on having a detailed knowledge of the past, the desire to have tangible ties to ancestral history, or the increased market value scarce items traditionally hold.

Creativity and innovation and invention are sometimes upheld as fundamentally good especially in Western industrial society—all imply newness, and even opportunity to profit from novelty. Bertrand Russell was notably pessimistic about creativity and thought that knowledge expanding faster than wisdom necessarily was fatal.

Goodness and morality in biology

The issue of good and evil in the human visuality, often associated with morality, is regarded by some biologists (notably Edward O. Wilson, Jeremy Griffith, David Sloan Wilson and Frans de Waal) as an important question to be addressed by the field of biology.[63][64][65][66]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b Ingram, Paul O.; Streng, Frederick John (1986). Buddhist-Christian Dialogue: Mutual Renewal and Transformation. Honolulu, Hawaii: University of Hawaii Press. pp. 148–149.
  2. ^ a b . Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. 2012. Archived from the original on 2012-08-22.
  3. ^ a b Staub, Ervin (2011). Overcoming Evil: Genocide, Violent Conflict, and Terrorism. New York City: Oxford University Press. p. 32. ISBN 978-0195382044.
  4. ^ Matthews, Caitlin; Matthews, John (2004). Walkers Between the Worlds: The Western Mysteries from Shaman to Magus. Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions / Bear & Co. p. 173. ISBN 978-0892810918.
  5. ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy "Ethics"
  6. ^ Brown, Donald (1991). Human Universals. New York City: McGraw-Hill. ISBN 9780070082090.
  7. ^ Boyce 1979, pp. 6–12.
  8. ^ John Hinnel (1997). The Penguin Dictionary of Religion. Penguin Books UK.
  9. ^ Churton, Tobias (2005). Gnostic Philosophy: From Ancient Persia to Modern Times. Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions – Bear & Company. ISBN 978-1-59477-035-7.
  10. ^ Asante, Molefi Kete (2012). "Maat and Human Communication: Supporting Identity, Culture, and History Without Global Domination". Communicatio: South African Journal for Communication Theory and Research. London, England: Taylor & Francis. 38 (2).
  11. ^ Dalley, Stephanie (1987). Myths from Mesopotamia. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. p. 329. ISBN 978-0199538362.
  12. ^ Frymer-Kensky, Tikva (2005). "Marduk". In Jones, Lindsay (ed.). Encyclopedia of Religion. Vol. 8 (2nd ed.). New York: MacMillan Reference USA. pp. 5702–5703. ISBN 0-02-865741-1.
  13. ^ Kahn, Charles H. (Spring 1985). "Democritus and the Origins of Moral Psychology". The American Journal of Philology. Baltimore, Maryland: Johns Hopkins University. 106 (1): 1–31. doi:10.2307/295049. JSTOR 295049. PMID 16411324.
  14. ^ Kenney, John Peter (2018). On God, The Soul, Evil and the Rise of Christianity. New York City: Bloomsbury Publishing USA. p. 88. ISBN 9781501314018.
  15. ^ Augustine of Hippo, Against Two Letters of the Pelagians 1.31–32
  16. ^ Farley, Edward (1990). Good and Evil: Interpreting a Human Condition. Nasville, Tennessee: Fortress Press / Vanderbilt University. ISBN 978-0-8006-2447-7.
  17. ^ Good and Evil in Chinese Philosophy 2006-05-29 at the Wayback Machine C.W. Chan
  18. ^ History of Chinese Philosophy Feng Youlan, Volume II The Period of Classical Learning (from the Second Century B.C. to the Twentieth Century A.D). Trans. Derk Bodde. Ch. XIV Liu Chiu-Yuan, Wang Shou-jen, and Ming Idealism. part 6 § 6 Origin of Evil. Uses strikingly similar language to that in the etymology section of this article, in the context of Chinese Idealism.
  19. ^ a b Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics, Part IV Of Human Bondage or of the Strength of the Affects Definitions translated by W.H. White, Revised by A.H. Stirling, Great Books vol 31, Encyclopædia Britannica 1952 p. 424
  20. ^ Stephen Palmquist, Dreams of Wholeness 2008-09-06 at the Wayback Machine: A course of introductory lectures on religion, psychology and personal growth (Hong Kong: Philopsychy Press, 1997/2008), see especially Chapter XI.
  21. ^ Book website 2008-12-19 at the Wayback Machine
  22. ^ a b c 'Abdu'l-Bahá (1982). Some answered questions. Translated by Laura Clifford. Wilmette, Illinois: US Baháʼí Publishing Trust. ISBN 978-0-87743-162-6.
  23. ^ David Ray Griffin, God, Power, and Evil: a Process Theodicy (Westminster, 1976/2004), 31.
  24. ^ Hans Schwarz, Evil: A Historical and Theological Perspective (Lima, Ohio: Academic Renewal Press, 2001): 42–43.
  25. ^ Schwarz, Evil, 75.
  26. ^ Thomas Aquinas, SUMMA THEOLOGICA, translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1947) Volume 3, q. 72, a. 1, p. 902.
  27. ^ Henri Blocher, Evil and the Cross (Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 1994): 10.
  28. ^ 1 Timothy 6:10
  29. ^ Revelation, Rationality, Knowledge & Truth (PDF). p. 193. (PDF) from the original on March 3, 2016. Retrieved June 25, 2014.
  30. ^ Book of Deuteronomy 31:21
  31. ^ Genesis 1:1–2:3
  32. ^ Deuteronomy 33
  33. ^ Deuteronomy 30:6
  34. ^ Avot deRabbi Natan 16
  35. ^ Babylonian Talmud (Sukkah 52a)
  36. ^ Gethin (1998), p. 170; Harvey (2007), p. 199; Ñāamoli (1999), pp. 3 passim; Nyanatiloka (1988), entry for "sīla"; June 13, 2016, at the Wayback Machine Thanissaro (1999); , entry for "sīla"; and Saddhatissa (1987), pp. 54, 56.
  37. ^ Bodhi (2005), p. 153.
  38. ^ Horner, I.B. (trans.) (1975; reprinted 2000). The Minor Anthologies of the Pali Canon (Part III): 'Chronicle of Buddhas' (Buddhavamsa) and 'Basket of Conduct' (Cariyapitaka). Oxford: Pali Text Society. ISBN 0-86013-072-X
  39. ^ Living This Life Fully: Teachings of Anagarika Munindra, by Mirka Knaster Ph.D., Shambhala Publications, USA, 2010. Pg. 67
  40. ^ Damien Keown The Nature of Buddhist Ethics Macmillan 1992; Peter Harvey An Introduction to Buddhist Ethics Cambridge University Press 2000
  41. ^ Bhagavad Gita 4.07–08
  42. ^ Singh, Gopal (1967). Sri guru-granth sahib [english version]. New York: Taplinger Publishing Co.
  43. ^ Singh, Charan (2013-12-11). "Ethics and Business: Evidence from Sikh Religion". Social Science Research Network. Indian Institute of Management, Bangalore. SSRN 2366249. {{cite web}}: Missing or empty |url= (help)
  44. ^ Sandhu, Jaswinder (February 2004). "The Sikh Model of the Person, Suffering, and Healing: Implications for Counselors". International Journal for the Advancement of Counselling. 26 (1): 33–46. doi:10.1023/B:ADCO.0000021548.68706.18. S2CID 145256429.
  45. ^ Singh, Arjan (January 2000). "The universal ideal of sikhism". Global Dialogue. 2 (1).
  46. ^ Choksy, J.K. (1989). Purity and Pollution in Zoroastrianism: Triumph Over Evil. Austin: University of Texas Press. ISBN 0292798024.
  47. ^ a b Baba, Meher. Discourses. 1. 1967. Sufism Reoriented. p. 93. ISBN 1-880619-09-1.
  48. ^ Sanburn, Josh (February 4, 2011). . Time. Archived from the original on August 26, 2011. Retrieved August 27, 2011.
  49. ^ Del Testa, David W.; Lemoine, Florence; Strickland, John (2003). Government Leaders, Military Rulers, and Political Activists. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Publishing Group. p. 83. ISBN 978-1-57356-153-2.
  50. ^ Gaymon Bennett, Ted Peters, Martinez J. Hewlett, Robert John Russell (2008). The evolution of evil. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. p. 318. ISBN 3-525-56979-3
  51. ^ Gourevitch, Philip (1999). We Wish to Inform You That Tomorrow We Will be Killed With our Families. Picador. ISBN 978-0-312-24335-7.
  52. ^ "Frontline: the triumph of evil". PBS. from the original on 2007-04-19. Retrieved 2007-04-09.
  53. ^ Cherniss, Harold (1954). The Sources of Evil According to Plato. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. Vol. 98. Philadelphia, Pennsylvania: American Philosophical Society. pp. 23–30. ISBN 978-90-04-05235-2. JSTOR 3143666.
  54. ^ a b Peck, M. Scott. (1983; 1988). People of the Lie: The hope for healing human evil. Century Hutchinson.
  55. ^ Peck, M. Scott. (1978;1992), The Road Less Travelled. Arrow.
  56. ^ Peck, 1983/1988, p105
  57. ^ Peck, 1978/1992, p298
  58. ^ Martin Luther, Werke, XX, p58
  59. ^ a b Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince, Dante University of America Press, 2003, ISBN 0-937832-38-3, 978-0-937832-38-7
  60. ^ Strauss, Leo, Thoughts on Machiavelli
  61. ^ Anton LaVey, The Satanic Bible, Avon, 1969, ISBN 0-380-01539-0
  62. ^ For discussion, see debates on monoculture and permaculture.
  63. ^ Wilson, Edward Osborne (2012). The Social Conquest of Earth. ISBN 978-0-87140-413-8.
  64. ^ Griffith, Jeremy (2011). Good vs Evil. The Book of Real Answers to Everything!. ISBN 978-1-74129-007-3. from the original on 2012-11-22.
  65. ^ Wilson, Edward Osborne (2007). Evolution for Everyone: How Darwin's Theory Can Change the Way We Think About Our Lives. ISBN 978-0-385-34092-2.
  66. ^ de Waal, Frans (2012). Moral behavior in animals. from the original on 2012-04-17.

References

  • Anders, Timothy (1994). The evolution of evil. Chicago: Open Court. ISBN 9780812691757.
  • Atkinson, Philip. Recognising Good And Evil from ourcivilisation.com
  • Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". 1998. US: Oxford University Press. (1177a15)
  • Bentham, Jeremy. The Principles of Morals and Legislation. 1988. Prometheus Books.
  • Dewey, John. Theory of Valuation. 1948. University of Chicago Press.
  • Durant, Ariel and W. Durant. The Lessons of History. 1997. MJF Books. (p72)
  • Garcia, John David. The Moral Society — A Rational Alternative to Death. 2005. Whitmore Publishing.
  • Griffin, James. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance. 1986. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hume, David. A Treastise of Human Nature. 2000. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hurka, Thomas. Perfectionism. 1993. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. 1996. Cambridge University Press. Third section, [446]-[447].
  • Kierkegaard, Søren. Either/Or. 1992. Penguin Classics.
  • Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. 1999. Belknap Press.
  • Romero, Rhys. "Just Being a Student". 2009. Austin Student Press.

Further reading

  • Baumeister, Roy F. (1999) Evil: Inside Human Violence and Cruelty. New York: A.W.H. Freeman / Owl Book
  • Bennett, Gaymon, Hewlett, Martinez J, Peters, Ted, Russell, Robert John (2008). The Evolution of Evil. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. ISBN 978-3-525-56979-5
  • Katz, Fred Emil (1993) Ordinary People and Extraordinary Evil, [SUNY Press], ISBN 0-7914-1442-6
  • Katz, Fred Emil (2004) Confronting Evil, [SUNY Press], ISBN 0-7914-6030-4
  • Neiman, Susan. Evil in Modern Thought – An Alternative History of Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002.
  • Oppenheimer, Paul (1996). Evil and the Demonic: A New Theory of Monstrous Behavior. New York: New York University Press. ISBN 978-0-8147-6193-9.
  • Shermer, M. (2004). The Science of Good & Evil. New York: Time Books. ISBN 0-8050-7520-8
  • Steven Mintz; John Stauffer, eds. (2007). The Problem of Evil: Slavery, Freedom, and the Ambiguities of American Reform. University of Massachusetts Press. ISBN 978-1-55849-570-8.
  • Stapley, A.B. & Elder Delbert L., Using Our Free Agency. Ensign May 1975: 21
  • Stark, Ryan. Rhetoric, Science, and Magic in Seventeenth-Century England. (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2009), 115–45
  • Vetlesen, Arne Johan (2005) Evil and Human Agency – Understanding Collective Evildoing New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85694-2
  • Wilson, William McF., and Julian N. Hartt. Farrer's Theodicy. In David Hein and Edward Hugh Henderson (eds), Captured by the Crucified: The Practical Theology of Austin Farrer. New York and London: T & T Clark / Continuum, 2004. ISBN 0-567-02510-1

External links

  • Evil on In Our Time at the BBC
  • Good and Evil in (Ultra Orthodox) Judaism
  • ABC News: Looking for Evil in Everyday Life
  • Booknotes interview with Lance Morrow on Evil: An Investigation, October 19, 2003.
  • Chattopadhyay, Subhasis. The Discussion of Evil in Christianity in Prabuddha Bharata or Awakened India 118 (9):540–542 (2013). ISSN 0032-6178
  • Chattopadhyay, Subhasis. Prolegomenon to the Study of Evil. in Prabuddha Bharata or Awakened India 118 (4):278–281 (2013). ISSN 0032-6178
  • Contestabile, Bruno (2016). "The Denial of the World from an Impartial View". Contemporary Buddhism. 17: 49–61. doi:10.1080/14639947.2015.1104003. S2CID 148168698.

good, evil, other, uses, disambiguation, good, disambiguation, evil, disambiguation, good, redirects, here, other, uses, disambiguation, good, against, evil, redirects, here, other, uses, conflict, between, good, evil, this, article, multiple, issues, please, . For other uses see Good and evil disambiguation Good disambiguation and Evil disambiguation Good and bad redirects here For other uses see Bad disambiguation Good against evil redirects here For other uses see Conflict between good and evil This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed April 2019 Learn how and when to remove this template message The examples and perspective in this article deal primarily with part of the world with dualistic world view of distinct good and evil concept and do not represent a worldwide view of the subject You may improve this article discuss the issue on the talk page or create a new article as appropriate March 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Learn how and when to remove this template message In religion ethics philosophy and psychology good and evil is a very common dichotomy In cultures with Manichaean and Abrahamic religious influence evil is perceived as the dualistic antagonistic opposite of good in which good should prevail and evil should be defeated 1 In cultures with Buddhist spiritual influence both good and evil are perceived as part of an antagonistic duality that itself must be overcome through achieving Sunyata meaning emptiness in the sense of recognition of good and evil being two opposing principles but not a reality emptying the duality of them and achieving a oneness 1 The devil in opposition to the will of God represents evil and tempts Christ the personification of the character and will of God Ary Scheffer 1854 Evil is often used to denote profound immorality 2 Evil has also been described as a supernatural force 2 Definitions of evil vary as does the analysis of its motives 3 However elements that are commonly associated with evil involve unbalanced behavior involving expediency selfishness ignorance or neglect 4 The modern philosophical questions regarding good and evil are subsumed into three major areas of study meta ethics concerning the nature of good and evil normative ethics concerning how we ought to behave and applied ethics concerning particular moral issues 5 One of the five paintings of Extermination of Evil portrays Sendan Kendatsuba one of the eight guardians of Buddhist law banishing evil Contents 1 History and etymology 1 1 Ancient world 1 2 Classical world 1 3 Medieval period 1 4 Modern ideas 2 Theories of moral goodness 2 1 Chinese moral philosophy 2 2 Western philosophy 2 2 1 Pyrrhonism 2 2 2 Spinoza 2 2 3 Nietzsche 2 3 Psychology 2 3 1 Carl Jung 2 3 2 Philip Zimbardo 2 4 Religion 2 4 1 Abrahamic religions 2 4 1 1 Bahaʼi Faith 2 4 1 2 Christianity 2 4 1 3 Islam 2 4 1 4 Judaism 2 4 2 Indian religions 2 4 2 1 Buddhism 2 4 2 2 Hinduism 2 4 2 3 Sikhism 2 4 3 Zoroastrianism 3 Descriptive meta ethical and normative fields 4 Theories of the intrinsically good 4 1 Platonic idealism 4 2 Perfectionism 4 3 Welfarist theories 4 3 1 Subjective theories of well being 4 3 2 Objective theories of well being 4 3 3 Mid range theories 5 Philosophical questions 5 1 Universality 5 2 Usefulness as a term 5 3 Necessary evil 6 Goodness and agency 6 1 Goodwill 6 2 Society life and ecology 6 3 History and novelty 7 Goodness and morality in biology 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Further reading 12 External linksHistory and etymology EditEvery language has a word expressing good in the sense of having the right or desirable quality ἀreth and bad in the sense undesirable A sense of moral judgment and a distinction right and wrong good and bad are cultural universals 6 Ancient world Edit Further information Zoroastrianism and Gnosticism The philosopher Zoroaster simplified the pantheon of early Iranian gods 7 into two opposing forces Ahura Mazda Illuminating Wisdom and Angra Mainyu Destructive Spirit which were in conflict This idea developed into a religion which spawned many sects some of which embraced an extreme dualistic belief that the material world should be shunned and the spiritual world should be embraced Gnostic ideas influenced many ancient religions 8 which teach that gnosis variously interpreted as enlightenment salvation emancipation or oneness with God may be reached by practising philanthropy to the point of personal poverty sexual abstinence as far as possible for hearers total for initiates and diligently searching for wisdom by helping others 9 Similarly in ancient Egypt there were the concepts of Ma at the principle of justice order and cohesion and Isfet the principle of chaos disorder and decay with the former being the power and principles which society sought to embody where the latter was such that undermined society 10 This correspondence can also be seen reflected in ancient Mesopotamian religion as well in the conflict between Marduk and Tiamat 11 12 Classical world Edit In Western civilisation the basic meanings of kakos and ἀga8os are bad cowardly and good brave capable and their absolute sense emerges only around 400 BC with pre Socratic philosophy in particular Democritus 13 Morality in this absolute sense solidifies in the dialogues of Plato together with the emergence of monotheistic thought notably in Euthyphro which ponders the concept of piety tὸ ὅsion as a moral absolute The idea was further developed in Late Antiquity by Neoplatonists Gnostics and Church Fathers 14 This development from the relative or habitual to the absolute is also evident in the terms ethics and morality both being derived from terms for regional custom Greek h8os and Latin mores respectively see also sidr Medieval period Edit According to the classical definition of Augustine of Hippo sin is a word deed or desire in opposition to the eternal law of God 15 Many medieval Christian theologians both broadened and narrowed the basic concept of Good and evil until it came to have several sometimes complex definitions 16 such as a personal preference or subjective judgment regarding any issue which might be earn praise or punishment from the religious authorities religious obligation arising from Divine law leading to sainthood or damnation a generally accepted cultural standard of behaviour which might enhance group survival or wealth natural law or behaviour which induces strong emotional reaction statute law imposing a legal dutyModern ideas Edit Today the basic dichotomy often breaks down along these lines Good is a broad concept often associated with life charity continuity happiness love or justice Evil is often associated with conscious and deliberate wrongdoing discrimination designed to harm others humiliation of people designed to diminish their psychological needs and dignity destructiveness and acts of unnecessary or indiscriminate violence 3 The modern English word evil Old English yfel and its cognates such as the German Ubel and Dutch euvel are widely considered to come from a Proto Germanic reconstructed form of ubilaz comparable to the Hittite huwapp ultimately from the Proto Indo European form wap and suffixed zero grade form up elo Other later Germanic forms include Middle English evel ifel ufel Old Frisian evel adjective and noun Old Saxon ubil Old High German ubil and Gothic ubils The nature of being good has been given many treatments one is that the good is based on the natural love bonding and affection that begins at the earliest stages of personal development another is that goodness is a product of knowing truth Differing views also exist as to why evil might arise Many religious and philosophical traditions claim that evil behavior is an aberration that results from the imperfect human condition e g The Fall of Man Sometimes evil is attributed to the existence of free will and human agency Some argue that evil itself is ultimately based in an ignorance of truth i e human value sanctity divinity A variety of thinkers have alleged the opposite by suggesting that evil is learned as a consequence of tyrannical social structures citation needed Theories of moral goodness EditFor other uses of good see Good disambiguation Chinese moral philosophy Edit Main articles Confucius Ethics and Taoism Ethics In Confucianism and Taoism there is no direct analogue to the way good and evil are opposed although references to demonic influence is common in Chinese folk religion Confucianism s primary concern is with correct social relationships and the behavior appropriate to the learned or superior man Evil would thus correspond to wrong behavior Still less does it map into Taoism in spite of the centrality of dualism in that system citation needed but the opposite of the basic virtues of Taoism compassion moderation and humility can be inferred to be the analogue of evil in it 17 18 Western philosophy Edit Pyrrhonism Edit Pyrrhonism holds that good and evil do not exist by nature meaning that good and evil do not exist within the things themselves All judgments of good and evil are relative to the one doing the judging Spinoza Edit Benedict de Spinoza states 1 By good I understand that which we certainly know is useful to us 2 By evil on the contrary I understand that which we certainly know hinders us from possessing anything that is good 19 Spinoza assumes a quasi mathematical style and states these further propositions which he purports to prove or demonstrate from the above definitions in part IV of his Ethics 19 Proposition 8 Knowledge of good or evil is nothing but affect of joy or sorrow in so far as we are conscious of it Proposition 30 Nothing can be evil through that which it possesses in common with our nature but in so far as a thing is evil to us it is contrary to us Proposition 64 The knowledge of evil is inadequate knowledge Corollary Hence it follows that if the human mind had none but adequate ideas it would form no notion of evil Proposition 65 According to the guidance of reason of two things which are good we shall follow the greater good and of two evils follow the less Proposition 68 If men were born free they would form no conception of good and evil so long as they were free Nietzsche Edit Friedrich Nietzsche in a rejection of Judeo Christian morality addresses this in two books Beyond Good and Evil and On the Genealogy of Morals In these works he states that the natural functional non good has been socially transformed into the religious concept of evil by the slave mentality of the masses who resent their masters the strong He also critiques morality by saying that many who consider themselves to be moral are simply acting out of cowardice wanting to do evil but afraid of the repercussions Psychology Edit See also Moral psychology Carl Jung Edit Carl Jung in his book Answer to Job and elsewhere depicted evil as the dark side of the Devil People tend to believe evil is something external to them because they project their shadow onto others Jung interpreted the story of Jesus as an account of God facing his own shadow 20 Philip Zimbardo Edit In 2007 Philip Zimbardo suggested that people may act in evil ways as a result of a collective identity This hypothesis based on his previous experience from the Stanford prison experiment was published in the book The Lucifer Effect Understanding How Good People Turn Evil 21 Religion Edit Main article Problem of evil Abrahamic religions Edit Bahaʼi Faith Edit The Bahaʼi Faith asserts that evil is non existent and that it is a concept for the lacking of good just as cold is the state of no heat darkness is the state of no light forgetfulness the lacking of memory ignorance the lacking of knowledge All of these are states of lacking and have no real existence 22 Thus evil does not exist and is relative to man Abdu l Baha son of the founder of the religion in Some Answered Questions states Nevertheless a doubt occurs to the mind that is scorpions and serpents are poisonous Are they good or evil for they are existing beings Yes a scorpion is evil in relation to man a serpent is evil in relation to man but in relation to themselves they are not evil for their poison is their weapon and by their sting they defend themselves 22 Thus evil is more of an intellectual concept than a true reality Since God is good and upon creating creation he confirmed it by saying it is Good Genesis 1 31 evil cannot have a true reality 22 Christianity Edit See also Devil Christianity In many religions angels are considered good beings In the Christian tradition God being the creator of all life manifests himself through the son of God Jesus Christ who is the personification of goodness Satan as seen in Codex Gigas Demons are generally seen as evil beings and Satan as the greatest of these in the Christian tradition Christian theology draws its concept of evil from the Old and New Testaments The Christian Bible exercises the dominant influence upon ideas about God and evil in the Western world 23 In the Old Testament evil is understood to be an opposition to God as well as something unsuitable or inferior such as the leader of the fallen angels Satan 24 In the New Testament the Greek word poneros is used to indicate unsuitability while kakos is used to refer to opposition to God in the human realm 25 Officially the Catholic Church extracts its understanding of evil from its canonical antiquity and the Dominican theologian Thomas Aquinas who in Summa Theologica defines evil as the absence or privation of good 26 French American theologian Henri Blocher describes evil when viewed as a theological concept as an unjustifiable reality In common parlance evil is something that occurs in experience that ought not to be 27 According to 1 Timothy 6 10 For the love of money is the root of all of evil 28 In Mormonism mortal life is viewed as a test of faith where one s choices are central to the Plan of Salvation See Agency LDS Church Evil is that which keeps one from discovering the nature of God It is believed that one must choose not to be evil to return to God Christian Science believes that evil arises from a misunderstanding of the goodness of nature which is understood as being inherently perfect if viewed from the correct spiritual perspective Misunderstanding God s reality leads to incorrect choices which are termed evil This has led to the rejection of any separate power being the source of evil or of God as being the source of evil instead the appearance of evil is the result of a mistaken concept of good Christian Scientists argue that even the most evil person does not pursue evil for its own sake but from the mistaken viewpoint that he or she will achieve some kind of good thereby Islam Edit See also Islamic ethics Morality in Islam Emphasis on good character and Devil Islam There is no concept of absolute evil in Islam as a fundamental universal principle that is independent from and equal with good in a dualistic sense Within Islam it is considered essential to believe that all comes from God whether it is perceived as good or bad by individuals and things that are perceived as evil or bad are either natural events natural disasters or illnesses or caused by humanity s free will to disobey God s orders According to the Ahmadiyya understanding of Islam evil does not have a positive existence in itself and is merely the lack of good just as darkness is the result of lack of light 29 Judaism Edit See also Yetzer hara In Judaism yetzer hara is the congenital inclination to do evil by violating the will of God The term is drawn from the phrase the imagination of the heart of man is evil י צ ר ל ב ה א ד ם ר ע yetzer lev ha adam ra which occurs twice at the beginning of the Torah Genesis 6 5 and 8 21 The Hebrew word yetzer having appeared twice in Genesis occurs again at the end of the Torah I knew their devisings that they do 30 Thus from beginning to end the heart s yetzer is continually bent on evil a profoundly pessimistic view of the human being However the Torah which began with blessing 31 anticipates future blessing 32 which will come as a result of God circumcising the heart in the latter days 33 In traditional Judaism the yetzer hara is not a demonic force but rather man s misuse of things the physical body needs to survive Thus the need for food becomes gluttony due to the yetzer hara The need for procreation becomes promiscuity and so on The yetzer hara could thus be best described as one s baser instincts According to the Talmudic tractate Avot de Rabbi Natan a boy s evil inclination is greater than his good inclination until he turns 13 bar mitzvah at which point the good inclination is born and able to control his behavior 34 Moreover the rabbis have stated The greater the man the greater his evil inclination 35 Indian religions Edit Buddhism Edit Extermination of Evil Late Heian period 12th century Japan Main article Buddhist ethics Buddhist ethics are traditionally based on what Buddhists view as the enlightened perspective of the Buddha or other enlightened beings such as Bodhisattvas The Indian term for ethics or morality used in Buddhism is Sila or sila Pali Sila in Buddhism is one of three sections of the Noble Eightfold Path and is a code of conduct that embraces a commitment to harmony and self restraint with the principal motivation being nonviolence or freedom from causing harm It has been variously described as virtue 36 moral discipline 37 and precept Sila is an internal aware and intentional ethical behavior according to one s commitment to the path of liberation It is an ethical compass within self and relationships rather than what is associated with the English word morality i e obedience a sense of obligation and external constraint Sila is one of the three practices foundational to Buddhism and the non sectarian Vipassana movement sila samadhi and panna as well as the Theravadin foundations of sila dana and bhavana It is also the second paramita 38 Sila is also wholehearted commitment to what is wholesome Two aspects of sila are essential to the training right performance caritta and right avoidance varitta Honoring the precepts of sila is considered a great gift mahadana to others because it creates an atmosphere of trust respect and security It means the practitioner poses no threat to another person s life property family rights or well being 39 Moral instructions are included in Buddhist scriptures or handed down through tradition Most scholars of Buddhist ethics thus rely on the examination of Buddhist scriptures and the use of anthropological evidence from traditional Buddhist societies to justify claims about the nature of Buddhist ethics 40 Hinduism Edit In Hinduism the concept of dharma or righteousness clearly divides the world into good and evil and clearly explains that wars have to be waged sometimes to establish and protect dharma this war is called Dharmayuddha This division of good and evil is of major importance in both the Hindu epics of Ramayana and Mahabharata However the main emphasis in Hinduism is on bad action rather than bad people The Hindu holy text the Bhagavad Gita speaks of the balance of good and evil When this balance goes off divine incarnations come to help to restore this balance 41 Sikhism Edit In adherence to the core principle of spiritual evolution the Sikh idea of evil changes depending on one s position on the path to liberation At the beginning stages of spiritual growth good and evil may seem neatly separated However once one s spirit evolves to the point where it sees most clearly the idea of evil vanishes and the truth is revealed In his writings Guru Arjan explains that because God is the source of all things what we believe to be evil must too come from God And because God is ultimately a source of absolute good nothing truly evil can originate from God 42 Nevertheless Sikhism like many other religions does incorporate a list of vices from which suffering corruption and abject negativity arise These are known as the Five Thieves called such due to their propensity to cloud the mind and lead one astray from the prosecution of righteous action 43 These are 44 Moh or Attachment Lobh or Greed Karodh or Wrath Kaam or Lust Ahankar or EgotismOne who gives in to the temptations of the Five Thieves is known as Manmukh or someone who lives selfishly and without virtue Inversely the Gurmukh who thrive in their reverence toward divine knowledge rise above vice via the practice of the high virtues of Sikhism These are 45 Sewa or selfless service to others Nam Simran or meditation upon the divine name Zoroastrianism Edit In the originally Persian religion of Zoroastrianism the world is a battle ground between the god Ahura Mazda also called Ormazd and the malignant spirit Angra Mainyu also called Ahriman The final resolution of the struggle between good and evil was supposed to occur on a day of Judgement in which all beings that have lived will be led across a bridge of fire and those who are evil will be cast down forever In Afghan belief angels and saints are beings sent to help us achieve the path towards goodness 46 Descriptive meta ethical and normative fields EditThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed November 2012 Learn how and when to remove this template message It is possible to treat the essential theories of value by the use of a philosophical and academic approach In properly analyzing theories of value everyday beliefs are not only carefully catalogued and described but also rigorously analyzed and judged There are at least two basic ways of presenting a theory of value based on two different kinds of questions What do people find good and what do they despise What really is good and what really is bad The two questions are subtly different One may answer the first question by researching the world by use of social science and examining the preferences that people assert However one may answer the second question by use of reasoning introspection prescription and generalization The former kind of method of analysis is called descriptive because it attempts to describe what people actually view as good or evil while the latter is called normative because it tries to actively prohibit evils and cherish goods These descriptive and normative approaches can be complementary For example tracking the decline of the popularity of slavery across cultures is the work of descriptive ethics while advising that slavery be avoided is normative Meta ethics is the study of the fundamental questions concerning the nature and origins of the good and the evil including inquiry into the nature of good and evil as well as the meaning of evaluative language In this respect meta ethics is not necessarily tied to investigations into how others see the good or of asserting what is good Theories of the intrinsically good EditThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed April 2010 Learn how and when to remove this template message A satisfying formulation of goodness is valuable because it might allow one to construct a good life or society by reliable processes of deduction elaboration or prioritization One could answer the ancient question How should we then live among many other important related questions It has long been thought that this question can best be answered by examining what it is that necessarily makes a thing valuable or in what the source of value consists Platonic idealism Edit One attempt to define goodness describes it as a property of the world with Platonic idealism According to this claim to talk about the good is to talk about something real that exists in the object itself independent of the perception of it Plato advocated this view in his expression that there is such a thing as an eternal realm of forms or ideas and that the greatest of the ideas and the essence of being was goodness or The good The good was defined by many ancient Greeks and other ancient philosophers as a perfect and eternal idea or blueprint The good is the right relation between all that exists and this exists in the mind of the Divine or some heavenly realm The good is the harmony of a just political community love friendship the ordered human soul of virtues and the right relation to the Divine and to Nature The characters in Plato s dialogues mention the many virtues of a philosopher or a lover of wisdom A theist is a person who believes that the Supreme Being exists or gods exist monotheism or polytheism A theist may therefore claim that the universe has a purpose and value according to the will of such creator s that lies partially beyond human understanding For instance Thomas Aquinas a proponent of this view believed he had proven the existence of God and the right relations that humans ought to have to the divine first cause Monotheists might also hope for infinite universal love Such hope is often translated as faith and wisdom itself is largely defined within some religious doctrines as a knowledge and understanding of innate goodness The concepts of innocence spiritual purity and salvation are likewise related to a concept of being in or returning to a state of goodness one that according to various teachings of enlightenment approaches a state of holiness or Godliness Perfectionism Edit Aristotle believed that virtues consisted of realization of potentials unique to humanity such as the use of reason This type of view called perfectionism has been recently defended in modern form by Thomas Hurka An entirely different form of perfectionism has arisen in response to rapid technological change Some techno optimists especially transhumanists avow a form of perfectionism in which the capacity to determine good and trade off fundamental values is expressed not by humans but by software genetic engineering of humans artificial intelligence Skeptics assert that rather than perfect goodness it would be only the appearance of perfect goodness reinforced by persuasion technology and probably brute force of violent technological escalation which would cause people to accept such rulers or rules authored by them Welfarist theories Edit Welfarist theories of value say things that are good are such because of their positive effects on human well being Subjective theories of well being Edit It is difficult to figure out where an immaterial trait such as goodness could reside in the world A counterproposal is to locate values inside people Some philosophers go so far as to say that if some state of affairs does not tend to arouse a desirable subjective state in self aware beings then it cannot be good Most philosophers that think goods have to create desirable mental states also say that goods are experiences of self aware beings These philosophers often distinguish the experience which they call an intrinsic good from the things that seem to cause the experience which they call inherent goods Some theories describe no higher collective value than that of maximizing pleasure for individual s Some even define goodness and intrinsic value as the experience of pleasure and bad as the experience of pain This view is called hedonism a monistic theory of value It has two main varieties simple and Epicurean Simple hedonism is the view that physical pleasure is the ultimate good However the ancient philosopher Epicurus used the word pleasure in a more general sense that encompassed a range of states from bliss to contentment to relief Contrary to popular caricature he valued pleasures of the mind to bodily pleasures and advocated moderation as the surest path to happiness Jeremy Bentham s book The Principles of Morals and Legislation prioritized goods by considering pleasure pain and consequences This theory had a wide effect on public affairs up to and including the present day A similar system was later named Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill More broadly utilitarian theories are examples of Consequentialism All utilitarian theories are based upon the maxim of utility which states that good is whatever provides the greatest happiness for the greatest number It follows from this principle that what brings happiness to the greatest number of people is good A benefit of tracing good to pleasure and pain is that both are easily understandable both in oneself and to an extent in others For the hedonist the explanation for helping behaviour may come in the form of empathy the ability of a being to feel another s pain People tend to value the lives of gorillas more than those of mosquitoes because the gorilla lives and feels making it easier to empathize with them This idea is carried forward in the ethical relationship view and has given rise to the animal rights movement and parts of the peace movement The impact of sympathy on human behaviour is compatible with Enlightenment views including David Hume s stances that the idea of a self with unique identity is illusory and that morality ultimately comes down to sympathy and fellow feeling for others or the exercise of approval underlying moral judgments A view adopted by James Griffin attempts to find a subjective alternative to hedonism as an intrinsic value He argues that the satisfaction of one s informed desires constitutes well being whether or not these desires actually bring the agent happiness Moreover these preferences must be life relevant that is contribute to the success of a person s life overall Desire satisfaction may occur without the agent s awareness of the satisfaction of the desire For example if a man wishes for his legal will to be enacted after his death and it is then his desire has been satisfied even though he will never experience or know of it Meher Baba proposed that it is not the satisfaction of desires that motivates the agent but rather a desire to be free from the limitation of all desires Those experiences and actions which increase the fetters of desire are bad and those experiences and actions which tend to emancipate the mind from limiting desires are good 47 It is through good actions then that the agent becomes free from selfish desires and achieves a state of well being The good is the main link between selfishness thriving and dying Selfishness which in the beginning is the father of evil tendencies becomes through good deeds the hero of its own defeat When the evil tendencies are completely replaced by good tendencies selfishness is transformed into selflessness i e individual selfishness loses itself in universal interest 47 Objective theories of well being Edit See also Wealth separate analysis The idea that the ultimate good exists and is not orderable but is globally measurable is reflected in various ways in economic classical economics green economics welfare economics gross national happiness and scientific positive psychology the science of morality well being measuring theories all of which focus on various ways of assessing progress towards that goal a so called genuine progress indicator Modern economics thus reflects very ancient philosophy but a calculation or quantitative or other process based on cardinality and statistics replaces the simple ordering of values For example in both economics and in folk wisdom the value of something seems to rise so long as it is relatively scarce However if it becomes too scarce it leads often to a conflict and can reduce collective value In the classical political economy of Adam Smith and David Ricardo and in its critique by Karl Marx human labour is seen as the ultimate source of all new economic value This is an objective theory of value which attributes value to real production costs and ultimately expenditures of human labour time see law of value It contrasts with marginal utility theory which argues that the value of labour depends on subjective preferences by consumers which may however also be objectively studied The economic value of labour may be assessed technically in terms of its use value or utility or commercially in terms of its exchange value price or production cost see labour power But its value may also be socially assessed in terms of its contribution to the wealth and well being of a society In non market societies labour may be valued primarily in terms of skill time and output as well as moral or social criteria and legal obligations In market societies labour is valued economically primarily through the labour market The price of labour may then be set by supply and demand by strike action or legislation or by legal or professional entry requirements into occupations Mid range theories Edit Conceptual metaphor theories argue against both subjective and objective conceptions of value and meaning and focus on the relationships between body and other essential elements of human life In effect conceptual metaphor theories treat ethics as an ontology problem and the issue of how to work out values as a negotiation of these metaphors not the application of some abstraction or a strict standoff between parties who have no way to understand each other s views Philosophical questions EditUniversality Edit Adolf Hitler is sometimes used as a modern definition of evil 48 Hitler s policies and orders resulted in the deaths of about 50 million people 49 A fundamental question is whether there is a universal transcendent definition of evil or whether evil is determined by one s social or cultural background C S Lewis in The Abolition of Man maintained that there are certain acts that are universally considered evil such as rape and murder However the numerous instances in which rape or murder is morally affected by social context call this into question Up until the mid 19th century many countries practiced forms of slavery As is often the case those transgressing moral boundaries stood to profit from that exercise Arguably slavery has always been the same and objectively evil but individuals with a motivation to transgress will justify that action The Nazis during World War II considered genocide to be acceptable 50 as did the Hutu Interahamwe in the Rwandan genocide 51 52 One might point out though that the actual perpetrators of those atrocities probably avoided calling their actions genocide since the objective meaning of any act accurately described by that word is to wrongfully kill a selected group of people which is an action that at least their victims will understand to be evil Universalists consider evil independent of culture and wholly related to acts or intents Views on the nature of evil tend to fall into one of four opposed camps Moral absolutism holds that good and evil are fixed concepts established by a deity or deities nature morality common sense or some other source Amoralism claims that good and evil are meaningless that there is no moral ingredient in nature Moral relativism holds that standards of good and evil are only products of local culture custom or prejudice Moral universalism is the attempt to find a compromise between the absolutist sense of morality and the relativist view universalism claims that morality is only flexible to a degree and that what is truly good or evil can be determined by examining what is commonly considered to be evil amongst all humans Plato wrote that there are relatively few ways to do good but there are countless ways to do evil which can therefore have a much greater impact on our lives and the lives of other beings capable of suffering 53 Usefulness as a term Edit Psychologist Albert Ellis in his school of psychology called Rational Emotive Behavioral Therapy says the root of anger and the desire to harm someone is almost always related to variations of implicit or explicit philosophical beliefs about other human beings He further claims that without holding variants of those covert or overt belief and assumptions the tendency to resort to violence in most cases is less likely American psychiatrist M Scott Peck on the other hand describes evil as militant ignorance 54 The original Judeo Christian concept of sin is as a process that leads one to miss the mark and not achieve perfection Peck argues that while most people are conscious of this at least on some level those that are evil actively and militantly refuse this consciousness Peck describes evil as a malignant type of self righteousness which results in a projection of evil onto selected specific innocent victims often children or other people in relatively powerless positions Peck considers those he calls evil to be attempting to escape and hide from their own conscience through self deception and views this as being quite distinct from the apparent absence of conscience evident in sociopaths According to Peck an evil person 54 55 Is consistently self deceiving with the intent of avoiding guilt and maintaining a self image of perfection Deceives others as a consequence of their own self deception Psychologically projects his or her evils and sins onto very specific targets scapegoating those targets while treating everyone else normally their insensitivity toward him was selective 56 Commonly hates with the pretense of love for the purposes of self deception as much as the deception of others Abuses political or emotional power the imposition of one s will upon others by overt or covert coercion 57 Maintains a high level of respectability and lies incessantly in order to do so Is consistent in his or her sins Evil people are defined not so much by the magnitude of their sins but by their consistency of destructiveness Is unable to think from the viewpoint of their victim Has a covert intolerance to criticism and other forms of narcissistic injuryHe also considers certain institutions may be evil as his discussion of the My Lai Massacre and its attempted coverup illustrate By this definition acts of criminal and state terrorism would also be considered evil Necessary evil Edit Martin Luther believed that occasional minor evil could have a positive effect Martin Luther argued that there are cases where a little evil is a positive good He wrote Seek out the society of your boon companions drink play talk bawdy and amuse yourself One must sometimes commit a sin out of hate and contempt for the Devil so as not to give him the chance to make one scrupulous over mere nothings 58 The necessary evil approach to politics was put forth by Niccolo Machiavelli a 16th century Florentine writer who advised tyrants that it is far safer to be feared than loved 59 Treachery deceit eliminating political rivals and the usage of fear are offered as methods of stabilizing the prince s security and power 60 The international relations theories of realism and neorealism sometimes called realpolitik advise politicians to explicitly ban absolute moral and ethical considerations from international politics and to focus on self interest political survival and power politics which they hold to be more accurate in explaining a world they view as explicitly amoral and dangerous Political realists usually justify their perspectives by laying claim to a higher moral duty specific to political leaders under which the greatest evil is seen to be the failure of the state to protect itself and its citizens Machiavelli wrote there will be traits considered good that if followed will lead to ruin while other traits considered vices which if practiced achieve security and well being for the Prince 59 Anton LaVey founder of the Church of Satan was a materialist and claimed that evil is actually good He was responding to the common practice of describing sexuality or disbelief as evil and his claim was that when the word evil is used to describe the natural pleasures and instincts of men and women or the skepticism of an inquiring mind the things called evil are really good 61 Goodness and agency EditGoodwill Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed August 2009 Learn how and when to remove this template message John Rawls book A Theory of Justice prioritized social arrangements and goods based on their contribution to justice Rawls defined justice as fairness especially in distributing social goods defined fairness in terms of procedures and attempted to prove that just institutions and lives are good if rational individuals goods are considered fairly Rawls s crucial invention was the original position a procedure in which one tries to make objective moral decisions by refusing to let personal facts about oneself enter one s moral calculations Immanuel Kant a great influence for Rawls similarly applies a lot of procedural practice within the practical application of The Categorical Imperative however this is indeed not based solely on fairness Society life and ecology Edit This section is written like a personal reflection personal essay or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor s personal feelings or presents an original argument about a topic Please help improve it by rewriting it in an encyclopedic style September 2012 Learn how and when to remove this template message Many views value unity as a good to go beyond eudaimonia by saying that an individual person s flourishing is valuable only as a means to the flourishing of society as a whole In other words a single person s life is ultimately not important or worthwhile in itself but is good only as a means to the success of society as a whole Some elements of Confucianism are an example of this encouraging the view that people ought to conform as individuals to demands of a peaceful and ordered society According to the naturalistic view the flourishing of society is not or not the only intrinsically good thing Defenses of this notion are often formulated by reference to biology and observations that living things compete more with their own kind than with other kinds Rather what is of intrinsic good is the flourishing of all sentient life extending to those animals that have some level of similar sentience such as Great Ape personhood Others go farther declaring that life itself is of intrinsic value By another approach one achieves peace and agreement by focusing not on one s peers who may be rivals or competitors but on the common environment The reasoning As living beings it is clearly and objectively good that we are surrounded by an ecosystem that supports life Indeed if we weren t we could neither discuss that good nor even recognize it The anthropic principle in cosmology recognizes this view citation needed Under materialism or even embodiment values or in any system that recognizes the validity of ecology as a scientific study of limits and potentials an ecosystem is a fundamental good To all who investigate it seems that goodness or value exists within an ecosystem Earth Creatures within that ecosystem and wholly dependent on it evaluate good relative to what else could be achieved there In other words good is situated in a particular place and one does not dismiss everything that is not available there such as very low gravity or absolutely abundant sugar candy as not good enough one works within its constraints Transcending them and learning to be satisfied with them is thus another sort of value perhaps called satisfaction Values and the people that hold them seem necessarily subordinate to the ecosystem If this is so then what kind of being could validly apply the word good to an ecosystem as a whole Who would have the power to assess and judge an ecosystem as good or bad By what criteria And by what criteria would ecosystems be modified especially larger ones such as the atmosphere climate change or oceans extinction or forests deforestation 62 Remaining on Earth as the most basic value While green ethicists have been most forthright about it and have developed theories of Gaia philosophy biophilia bioregionalism that reflect it the questions are now universally recognized as central in determining value e g the economic value of Earth to humans as a whole or the value of life that is neither whole Earth nor human Many have come to the conclusion that without assuming ecosystem continuation as a universal good with attendant virtues like biodiversity and ecological wisdom it is impossible to justify such operational requirements as sustainability of human activity on Earth One response is that humans are not necessarily confined to Earth and could use it and move on A counter argument is that only a tiny fraction of humans could do this and they would be self selected by ability to do technological escalation on others for instance the ability to create large spacecraft to flee the planet in and simultaneously fend off others who seek to prevent them Another counter argument is that extraterrestrial life would encounter the fleeing humans and destroy them as a locust species A third is that if there are no other worlds fit to support life and no extraterrestrials who compete with humans to occupy them it is both futile to flee and foolish to imagine that it would take less energy and skill to protect the Earth as a habitat than it would take to construct some new habitat Accordingly remaining on Earth as a living being surrounded by a working ecosystem is a fair statement of the most basic values and goodness to any being we are able to communicate with A moral system without this axiom seems simply not actionable However most religious systems acknowledge an afterlife and improving this is seen as an even more basic good In many other moral systems also remaining on Earth in a state that lacks honor or power over self is less desirable consider seppuku in bushido kamikazes or the role of suicide attacks in Jihadi rhetoric In all these systems remaining on Earth is perhaps no higher than a third place value Radical values environmentalism can be seen as either a very old or a very new view that the only intrinsically good thing is a flourishing ecosystem individuals and societies are merely instrumentally valuable good only as means to having a flourishing ecosystem The Gaia philosophy is the most detailed expression of this overall thought but it strongly influenced deep ecology and the modern Green Parties It is often claimed that aboriginal peoples never lost this sort of view Anthropological linguistics studies links between their languages and the ecosystems they lived in which gave rise to their knowledge distinctions Very often environmental cognition and moral cognition were not distinguished in these languages Offenses to nature were like those to other people and Animism reinforced this by giving nature personality via myth Anthropological theories of value explore these questions Most people in the world reject older situated ethics and localized religious views However small community based and ecology centric views have gained some popularity in recent years In part this has been attributed to the desire for ethical certainties Such a deeply rooted definition of goodness would be valuable because it might allow one to construct a good life or society by reliable processes of deduction elaboration or prioritisation Ones that relied only on local referents one could verify for oneself creating more certainty and therefore less investment in protection hedging and insuring against consequences of loss of the value History and novelty Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to goodness Wikiquote has quotations related to evil An event is often seen as being of value simply because of its novelty in fashion and art By contrast cultural history and other antiques are sometimes seen as of value in and of themselves due to their age Philosopher historians Will and Ariel Durant spoke as much with the quote As the sanity of the individual lies in the continuity of his memories so the sanity of the group lies in the continuity of its traditions in either case a break in the chain invites a neurotic reaction The Lessons of History 72 Assessment of the value of old or historical artifacts takes into consideration especially but not exclusively the value placed on having a detailed knowledge of the past the desire to have tangible ties to ancestral history or the increased market value scarce items traditionally hold Creativity and innovation and invention are sometimes upheld as fundamentally good especially in Western industrial society all imply newness and even opportunity to profit from novelty Bertrand Russell was notably pessimistic about creativity and thought that knowledge expanding faster than wisdom necessarily was fatal Goodness and morality in biology EditThe issue of good and evil in the human visuality often associated with morality is regarded by some biologists notably Edward O Wilson Jeremy Griffith David Sloan Wilson and Frans de Waal as an important question to be addressed by the field of biology 63 64 65 66 See also Edit Philosophy portal Psychology portalAkrasia Axiology Banality of evil Common good Form of the Good Plato Graded absolutism Inductive reasoning Moral dilemma Moral evil Moral realism Natural evil Non physical entity Objectivist theory of good and evil Ponerology Psychopathy Supreme good Theodicy Tree of the knowledge of good and evil WelfarismNotes Edit a b Ingram Paul O Streng Frederick John 1986 Buddhist Christian Dialogue Mutual Renewal and Transformation Honolulu Hawaii University of Hawaii Press pp 148 149 a b Evil Oxford England Oxford University Press 2012 Archived from the original on 2012 08 22 a b Staub Ervin 2011 Overcoming Evil Genocide Violent Conflict and Terrorism New York City Oxford University Press p 32 ISBN 978 0195382044 Matthews Caitlin Matthews John 2004 Walkers Between the Worlds The Western Mysteries from Shaman to Magus Rochester Vermont Inner Traditions Bear amp Co p 173 ISBN 978 0892810918 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ethics Brown Donald 1991 Human Universals New York City McGraw Hill ISBN 9780070082090 Boyce 1979 pp 6 12harvnb error no target CITEREFBoyce1979 help John Hinnel 1997 The Penguin Dictionary of Religion Penguin Books UK Churton Tobias 2005 Gnostic Philosophy From Ancient Persia to Modern Times Rochester Vermont Inner Traditions Bear amp Company ISBN 978 1 59477 035 7 Asante Molefi Kete 2012 Maat and Human Communication Supporting Identity Culture and History Without Global Domination Communicatio South African Journal for Communication Theory and Research London England Taylor amp Francis 38 2 Dalley Stephanie 1987 Myths from Mesopotamia Oxford England Oxford University Press p 329 ISBN 978 0199538362 Frymer Kensky Tikva 2005 Marduk In Jones Lindsay ed Encyclopedia of Religion Vol 8 2nd ed New York MacMillan Reference USA pp 5702 5703 ISBN 0 02 865741 1 Kahn Charles H Spring 1985 Democritus and the Origins of Moral Psychology The American Journal of Philology Baltimore Maryland Johns Hopkins University 106 1 1 31 doi 10 2307 295049 JSTOR 295049 PMID 16411324 Kenney John Peter 2018 On God The Soul Evil and the Rise of Christianity New York City Bloomsbury Publishing USA p 88 ISBN 9781501314018 Augustine of Hippo Against Two Letters of the Pelagians 1 31 32 Farley Edward 1990 Good and Evil Interpreting a Human Condition Nasville Tennessee Fortress Press Vanderbilt University ISBN 978 0 8006 2447 7 Good and Evil in Chinese Philosophy Archived 2006 05 29 at the Wayback Machine C W Chan History of Chinese Philosophy Feng Youlan Volume II The Period of Classical Learning from the Second Century B C to the Twentieth Century A D Trans Derk Bodde Ch XIV Liu Chiu Yuan Wang Shou jen and Ming Idealism part 6 6 Origin of Evil Uses strikingly similar language to that in the etymology section of this article in the context of Chinese Idealism a b Benedict de Spinoza Ethics Part IV Of Human Bondage or of the Strength of the Affects Definitions translated by W H White Revised by A H Stirling Great Books vol 31 Encyclopaedia Britannica 1952 p 424 Stephen Palmquist Dreams of Wholeness Archived 2008 09 06 at the Wayback Machine A course of introductory lectures on religion psychology and personal growth Hong Kong Philopsychy Press 1997 2008 see especially Chapter XI Book website Archived 2008 12 19 at the Wayback Machine a b c Abdu l Baha 1982 Some answered questions Translated by Laura Clifford Wilmette Illinois US Bahaʼi Publishing Trust ISBN 978 0 87743 162 6 David Ray Griffin God Power and Evil a Process Theodicy Westminster 1976 2004 31 Hans Schwarz Evil A Historical and Theological Perspective Lima Ohio Academic Renewal Press 2001 42 43 Schwarz Evil 75 Thomas Aquinas SUMMA THEOLOGICA translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province New York Benziger Brothers 1947 Volume 3 q 72 a 1 p 902 Henri Blocher Evil and the Cross Downers Grove InterVarsity Press 1994 10 1 Timothy 6 10 Revelation Rationality Knowledge amp Truth PDF p 193 Archived PDF from the original on March 3 2016 Retrieved June 25 2014 Book of Deuteronomy 31 21 Genesis 1 1 2 3 Deuteronomy 33 Deuteronomy 30 6 Avot deRabbi Natan 16 Babylonian Talmud Sukkah 52a Gethin 1998 p 170 Harvey 2007 p 199 Naṇ amoli 1999 pp 3 passim Nyanatiloka 1988 entry for sila Archived June 13 2016 at the Wayback Machine Thanissaro 1999 June 1389 Nyanatiloka 1988 entry for sila and Saddhatissa 1987 pp 54 56 Bodhi 2005 p 153 Horner I B trans 1975 reprinted 2000 The Minor Anthologies of the Pali Canon Part III Chronicle of Buddhas Buddhavamsa and Basket of Conduct Cariyapitaka Oxford Pali Text Society ISBN 0 86013 072 X Living This Life Fully Teachings of Anagarika Munindra by Mirka Knaster Ph D Shambhala Publications USA 2010 Pg 67 Damien Keown The Nature of Buddhist Ethics Macmillan 1992 Peter Harvey An Introduction to Buddhist Ethics Cambridge University Press 2000 Bhagavad Gita 4 07 08 Singh Gopal 1967 Sri guru granth sahib english version New York Taplinger Publishing Co Singh Charan 2013 12 11 Ethics and Business Evidence from Sikh Religion Social Science Research Network Indian Institute of Management Bangalore SSRN 2366249 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a Missing or empty url help Sandhu Jaswinder February 2004 The Sikh Model of the Person Suffering and Healing Implications for Counselors International Journal for the Advancement of Counselling 26 1 33 46 doi 10 1023 B ADCO 0000021548 68706 18 S2CID 145256429 Singh Arjan January 2000 The universal ideal of sikhism Global Dialogue 2 1 Choksy J K 1989 Purity and Pollution in Zoroastrianism Triumph Over Evil Austin University of Texas Press ISBN 0292798024 a b Baba Meher Discourses 1 1967 Sufism Reoriented p 93 ISBN 1 880619 09 1 Sanburn Josh February 4 2011 Top 25 Political Icons Adolf Hitler Time Archived from the original on August 26 2011 Retrieved August 27 2011 Del Testa David W Lemoine Florence Strickland John 2003 Government Leaders Military Rulers and Political Activists Westport Connecticut Greenwood Publishing Group p 83 ISBN 978 1 57356 153 2 Gaymon Bennett Ted Peters Martinez J Hewlett Robert John Russell 2008 The evolution of evil Vandenhoeck amp Ruprecht p 318 ISBN 3 525 56979 3 Gourevitch Philip 1999 We Wish to Inform You That Tomorrow We Will be Killed With our Families Picador ISBN 978 0 312 24335 7 Frontline the triumph of evil PBS Archived from the original on 2007 04 19 Retrieved 2007 04 09 Cherniss Harold 1954 The Sources of Evil According to Plato Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society Vol 98 Philadelphia Pennsylvania American Philosophical Society pp 23 30 ISBN 978 90 04 05235 2 JSTOR 3143666 a b Peck M Scott 1983 1988 People of the Lie The hope for healing human evil Century Hutchinson Peck M Scott 1978 1992 The Road Less Travelled Arrow Peck 1983 1988 p105 Peck 1978 1992 p298 Martin Luther Werke XX p58 a b Niccolo Machiavelli The Prince Dante University of America Press 2003 ISBN 0 937832 38 3 978 0 937832 38 7 Strauss Leo Thoughts on Machiavelli Anton LaVey The Satanic Bible Avon 1969 ISBN 0 380 01539 0 For discussion see debates on monoculture and permaculture Wilson Edward Osborne 2012 The Social Conquest of Earth ISBN 978 0 87140 413 8 Griffith Jeremy 2011 Good vs Evil The Book of Real Answers to Everything ISBN 978 1 74129 007 3 Archived from the original on 2012 11 22 Wilson Edward Osborne 2007 Evolution for Everyone How Darwin s Theory Can Change the Way We Think About Our Lives ISBN 978 0 385 34092 2 de Waal Frans 2012 Moral behavior in animals Archived from the original on 2012 04 17 References EditAnders Timothy 1994 The evolution of evil Chicago Open Court ISBN 9780812691757 Atkinson Philip Recognising Good And Evil from ourcivilisation com Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 1998 US Oxford University Press 1177a15 Bentham Jeremy The Principles of Morals and Legislation 1988 Prometheus Books Dewey John Theory of Valuation 1948 University of Chicago Press Durant Ariel and W Durant The Lessons of History 1997 MJF Books p72 Garcia John David The Moral Society A Rational Alternative to Death 2005 Whitmore Publishing Griffin James Well Being Its Meaning Measurement and Moral Importance 1986 Oxford Oxford University Press Hume David A Treastise of Human Nature 2000 Oxford Oxford University Press Hurka Thomas Perfectionism 1993 Oxford Oxford University Press Kant Immanuel Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals 1996 Cambridge University Press Third section 446 447 Kierkegaard Soren Either Or 1992 Penguin Classics Rawls John A Theory of Justice 1999 Belknap Press Romero Rhys Just Being a Student 2009 Austin Student Press Further reading EditBaumeister Roy F 1999 Evil Inside Human Violence and Cruelty New York A W H Freeman Owl Book Bennett Gaymon Hewlett Martinez J Peters Ted Russell Robert John 2008 The Evolution of Evil Gottingen Vandenhoeck amp Ruprecht ISBN 978 3 525 56979 5 Katz Fred Emil 1993 Ordinary People and Extraordinary Evil SUNY Press ISBN 0 7914 1442 6 Katz Fred Emil 2004 Confronting Evil SUNY Press ISBN 0 7914 6030 4 Neiman Susan Evil in Modern Thought An Alternative History of Philosophy Princeton Princeton University Press 2002 Oppenheimer Paul 1996 Evil and the Demonic A New Theory of Monstrous Behavior New York New York University Press ISBN 978 0 8147 6193 9 Shermer M 2004 The Science of Good amp Evil New York Time Books ISBN 0 8050 7520 8 Steven Mintz John Stauffer eds 2007 The Problem of Evil Slavery Freedom and the Ambiguities of American Reform University of Massachusetts Press ISBN 978 1 55849 570 8 Stapley A B amp Elder Delbert L Using Our Free Agency Ensign May 1975 21 Stark Ryan Rhetoric Science and Magic in Seventeenth Century England Washington DC The Catholic University of America Press 2009 115 45 Vetlesen Arne Johan 2005 Evil and Human Agency Understanding Collective Evildoing New York Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 85694 2 Wilson William McF and Julian N Hartt Farrer s Theodicy In David Hein and Edward Hugh Henderson eds Captured by the Crucified The Practical Theology of Austin Farrer New York and London T amp T Clark Continuum 2004 ISBN 0 567 02510 1External links Edit Look up goodness or evil in Wiktionary the free dictionary Wikiquote has quotations related to Good and evil Wikimedia Commons has media related to Good and evil Evil on In Our Time at the BBC Good and Evil in Ultra Orthodox Judaism ABC News Looking for Evil in Everyday Life Booknotes interview with Lance Morrow on Evil An Investigation October 19 2003 Chattopadhyay Subhasis The Discussion of Evil in Christianity in Prabuddha Bharata or Awakened India 118 9 540 542 2013 ISSN 0032 6178 Chattopadhyay Subhasis Prolegomenon to the Study of Evil in Prabuddha Bharata or Awakened India 118 4 278 281 2013 ISSN 0032 6178 Contestabile Bruno 2016 The Denial of the World from an Impartial View Contemporary Buddhism 17 49 61 doi 10 1080 14639947 2015 1104003 S2CID 148168698 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Good and evil amp oldid 1134032884, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.