fbpx
Wikipedia

Pre-Socratic philosophy

Pre-Socratic philosophy, also known as early Greek philosophy, is ancient Greek philosophy before Socrates. Pre-Socratic philosophers were mostly interested in cosmology, the beginning and the substance of the universe, but the inquiries of these early philosophers spanned the workings of the natural world as well as human society, ethics, and religion. They sought explanations based on natural law rather than the actions of gods. Their work and writing has been almost entirely lost. Knowledge of their views comes from testimonia, i.e. later authors' discussions of the work of pre-Socratics. Philosophy found fertile ground in the ancient Greek world because of the close ties with neighboring civilizations and the rise of autonomous civil entities, poleis.

Pre-Socratic philosophy began in the 6th century BCE with the three Milesians: Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes. They all attributed the arche (a word that could take the meaning of "origin," "substance" or "principle") of the world to, respectively, water, apeiron (the unlimited), and air governed by nous (mind or intelligence). Another three pre-Socratic philosophers came from nearby Ionian towns: Xenophanes, Heraclitus, and Pythagoras. Xenophanes is known for his critique of the anthropomorphism of gods. Heraclitus, who was notoriously difficult to understand, is known for his maxim on impermanence, ta panta rhei, and for attributing fire to be the arche of the world. Pythagoras created a cult-like following that advocated that the universe was made up of numbers. The Eleatic school (Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, and Melissus) followed in the 5th century BCE. Parmenides claimed that only one thing exists and nothing can change. Zeno and Melissus mainly defended Parmenides' opinion. Anaxagoras and Empedocles offered a pluralistic account of how the universe was created. Leucippus and Democritus are known for their atomism, and their views that only void and matter exist. The Sophists advanced critical thinking and philosophical relativism.

The impact of the pre-Socratics has been enormous. The pre-Socratics invented some of the central concepts of Western civilization, such as naturalism and rationalism, and paved the way for scientific methodology.

Terminology

Pre-Socratic is a term adopted in the 19th century to refer to this group of philosophers. It was first used by the German philosopher J.A. Eberhard as "vorsokratische Philosophie' in the late 18th century.[1] In earlier literature they were referred to as physikoi ("physicists", after physis, "nature"), and their activity, as physiologoi (physical or natural philosophers), with this usage arising with Aristotle to differentiate them from theologoi (theologians) and mythologoi (storytellers and bards who conveyed Greek mythology), who attributed natural phenomena to the gods.[2]

The term was coined to highlight a fundamental change in philosophical inquiries between the philosophers who lived before Socrates, who were interested in the structure of nature and cosmos (i.e., the universe, with the implication that the universe had order to it), and Socrates and his successors, who were mostly interested in ethics and politics. The term comes with drawbacks, as several of the pre-Socratics were highly interested in ethics and how to live the best life. Further, the term implies that the pre-Socratics are less significant than Socrates, or even that they were merely a stage (implying teleology) to classical era philosophy.[3] The term is also chronologically inaccurate, as the last of the pre-Socratics were contemporaries of Socrates.[4]

According to James Warren, the distinction between the pre-Socratic philosophers and philosophers of the classical era is demarcated not so much by Socrates, but by geography and what texts survived. The shift from the pre-Socratic to the classical periods involves a shift from philosophers being dispersed throughout the Greek-speaking world to their being concentrated in Athens. Further, starting in the classical period we have complete surviving texts, whereas in the pre-Socratic era we have only fragments.[5] Scholar André Laks distinguishes two traditions of separating pre-Socratics from Socratics, dating back to the classical era and running through current times. The first tradition is the Socratic-Ciceronian, which uses the content of their philosophical inquires to divide the two groups: the pre-Socratics were interested in nature whereas Socrates focused on human affairs. The other tradition, the Platonic-Aristotelian, emphasizes method as the distinction between the two groups, as Socrates moved to a more epistemological approach of studying various concepts.[6] Because of the drawbacks of the term pre-Socratic, early Greek philosophy is also used, most commonly in Anglo-Saxon literature.[7]

Sources

Very few fragments of the works of the pre-Socratic philosophers have survived. The knowledge we have of the pre-Socratics derives from the accounts of later writers such as Plato, Aristotle, Plutarch, Diogenes Laërtius, Stobaeus, and Simplicius, and some early Christian theologians, especially Clement of Alexandria and Hippolytus of Rome. Many of the works are titled Peri Physeos, or On Nature, a title probably attributed later by other authors.[8] These accounts, known as testimonia (testimonies), often come from biased writers. Consequently, it is sometimes difficult to determine the actual line of argument some pre-Socratics used in supporting their views.[9] Adding more difficulty to their interpretation is the obscure language they used.[10] Plato paraphrased the pre-Socratics and showed no interest in accurately representing their views. Aristotle was more accurate, but saw them under the scope of his philosophy. Theophrastus, Aristotle's successor, wrote an encyclopedic book Opinion of the Physicists that was the standard work about the pre-Socratics in ancient times. It is now lost, but Simplicius relied on it heavily in his accounts.[11]

In 1903, the German professors H. Diels and W. Kranz published Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (The Fragments of the pre-Socratics), which collected all of the known fragments. Scholars now use this book to reference the fragments using a coding scheme called Diels–Kranz numbering. The first two characters of the scheme are "DK" for Diels and Kranz. Next is a number representing a specific philosopher. After that is a code regarding whether the fragment is a testimonia, coded as "A", or "B" if is a direct quote from the philosopher. Last is a number assigned to the fragment, which may include a decimal to reflect specific lines of a fragment. For example, "DK59B12.3" identifies line 3 of Anaxagoras fragment 12. A similar way of referring to quotes is the system prefixed with "LM" by André Laks and Glenn W. Most who edited Early Greek Philosophy in 2016.[12]

Collectively, these fragments are called doxography (derived from the latin doxographus; derived from the Greek word for "opinion" doxa).[13]

Historical background

 
Map of Greek territories and colonies during the Archaic period (800–480 BCE)

Philosophy emerged in ancient Greece in the 6th century BCE. The pre-Socratic era lasted about two centuries, during which the expanding Persian Achaemenid Empire was stretching to the west, while the Greeks were advancing in trade and sea routes, reaching Cyprus and Syria.[14] The first pre-Socratics lived in Ionia, on the western coast of Anatolia. Persians conquered the towns of Ionia c. 540 BCE and Persian tyrants then ruled them. The Greeks revolted in 499 BCE, but ultimately were defeated in 494 BCE.[15] Slowly but steadily Athens became the philosophical center of Greece by the middle of the fifth century.[16] Athens was entering its Classical Era, with philosophers such as Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, but the impact of the pre-Socratics continued.[17]

Several factors contributed to the birth of pre-Socratic philosophy in Ancient Greece. Ionian towns, especially Miletus, had close trade relations with Egypt and Mesopotamia, cultures with observations about the natural world that differed from those of the Greeks.[18] Apart from technical skills and cultural influences, of paramount significance was that the Greeks acquired the alphabet c. 800 BCE.[19]

Another factor was the ease and frequency of intra-Greek travel, which led to the blending and comparison of ideas. During the sixth century BCE, various philosophers and other thinkers moved easily around Greece, especially visiting pan-Hellenic festivals. While long-distance communication was difficult during ancient times, persons, philosophers, and books moved through other parts of the Greek peninsula, the Aegean islands, and Magna Graecia, a coastal area in Southern Italy.[20]

The democratic political system of independent poleis also contributed to the rise of philosophy. Most Greek towns were not ruled by autocrats or priests, allowing citizens to question freely a wide range of issues.[21] Various poleis flourished and became wealthy, especially Miletus. which was a centre of trade and production during the early phases of pre-Socratic philosophy. Trade of grain, oil, wine, and other commodities among each polis and colonies meant these towns were not isolated but embedded – and economically dependent – on a complex and changeable web of trade routes.[22]

Greek mythology also influenced the birth of philosophy. The philosophers' ideas, were, to a certain extent, answers to questions that were subtly present in the work of Homer and Hesiod.[23] The pre-Socratics arose from a world dominated by myths, sacred places, and local deities. The work of epic poets such as Homer, Hesiod and others reflected this environment. They are considered predecessors of the pre-Socratics since they seek to address the origin of the world and to organize traditional folklore and legends systematically. However, their answers were rather simplistic and resisted naturalistic explanations, hence they were far from being named as philosophers. Greek popular religion contained many features of the religions of neighboring civilizations, such as the Egyptians, Mesopotamians, and Hittites. The first pre-Socratic philosophers also traveled extensively to other lands, meaning that pre-Socratic thought had roots abroad as well as domestically.[24]

Homer, in his two epic poems, not only personifies gods and other natural phenomena, such as the Night, but he hints at some views on the origin and the nature of the world that came under scrutiny by the pre-Socratics.[25] In his epic poem Theogony (literally meaning the birth of gods) Hesiod (c. 700 BCE) describes the origin of gods, and apart from the solid mythical structure, one can notice an attempt towards organizing beliefs using some form of rationalization; an example would be that Night gives birth to Death, Sleep and Dreams. [26] Transmigration of life, a belief of the Orphics, a religious cult originating from Thrace, had affected the thought of the 5th century BCE but the overall influence of their cosmology on philosophy is disputed.[27] Pherecydes, a poet, magician, and contemporary of Thales, in his book describes a particular cosmogony, asserting that three gods pre-existed – a step towards rationality.[28]

General features

List of major pre-Socratic philosophers and when they flourished (according to Catherine Osborne)[29]
Philosophers Flourished (year BCE)
Thales 585
Anaximander 550
Anaximenes 545
Pythagoras 530
Xenophanes 530
Heraclitus 500
Parmenides 500
Zenon 450
Anaxagoras 450
Empedocles 445
Melissus 440
Protagoras 440
Leukippus 435
Gorgias 430
Antiphon 430
Democritus 420
Philolaus 420
Socrates 420
Plato 380
Aristotle 350

The most important feature of pre-Socratic philosophy was the use of reason to explain the universe. The pre-Socratic philosophers shared the intuition that there was a single explanation that could explain both the plurality and the singularity of the whole – and that explanation would not be direct actions of the gods.[30] The pre-Socratic philosophers rejected traditional mythological explanations of the phenomena they saw around them in favor of more rational explanations, initiating analytic and critical thought. Their efforts were directed at the investigation of the ultimate basis and essential nature of the external world. Many sought the material principle (arche) of things, and the method of their origin and disappearance.[31] They emphasized the rational unity of things and rejected supernatural explanations, seeking natural principles at work in the world and human society. The pre-Socratics saw the world as a cosmos, an ordered arrangement that could be understood via rational inquiry.[32] In their effort to make sense of the cosmos they coined new terms and concepts such as rhythm, symmetry, analogy, deductionism, reductionism, mathematicazion of nature and others.[33]

An important term that is met in the thought of several pre-Socratic philosophers is arche. Depending on the context, it can take various related meanings. It could mean the beginning or origin with the undertone that there is an effect on the things to follow. Also, it might mean a principle or a cause (especially in Aristotelian tradition).[34]

A common feature of the pre-Socratics is the absence of empiricism and experimentation in order to prove their theories. This may have been because of a lack of instruments, or because of a tendency to view the world as a unity, undeconstructable, so it would be impossible for an external eye to observe tiny fractions of nature under experimental control.[35]

According to Jonathan Barnes, a professor of ancient philosophy, pre-Socratic philosophy exhibits three significant features: they were internal, systematic and economical. Internal meaning they tried to explain the world with characteristics found within this world. Systematic because they tried to universalize their findings. Economical because they tried to invoke only a few new terms. Based on these features, they reached their most significant achievement, they changed the course of human thought from myth to philosophy and science.[36]

The pre-Socratics were not atheists; however, they minimized the extent of the gods' involvement in natural phenomena such as thunder or totally eliminated the gods from the natural world.[37]

Pre-Socratic philosophy encompasses the first of the three phases of ancient Greek philosophy, which spanned around a thousand years. The pre-Socratic phase itself is divided into three phases. The first phase of pre-Socratic philosophy, mainly the Milesians, Xenophanes, and Heraclitus, consisted of rejecting traditional cosmogony and attempting to explain nature based on empirical observations and interpretations.[38] A second phase – that of the Eleatics – resisted the idea that change or motion can happen. Based on their radical monism, they believed that only one substance exists and forms Kosmos.[39] The Eleatics were also monists (believing that only one thing exists and everything else is just a transformation of it).[39] In the third phase, the post-Eleatics (mainly Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus) opposed most Eleatic teaching and returned to the naturalism of the Milesians.[40]

The pre-Socratics were succeeded by the second phase of ancient philosophy, where the philosophical movements of Platonism, Cynicism, Cyrenaicism, Aristotelianism, Pyrrhonism, Epicureanism, Academic skepticism, and Stoicism rose to prominence until 100 BCE. In the third phase, philosophers studied their predecessors.[41]

Pre-Socratic philosophers

Milesian beginning: Thales, Anaximander and Anaximenes

The Milesian school was located in Miletus, Ionia, in the 6th century BCE. It consisted of Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, who most probably had a teacher-pupil relationship. They were mainly occupied with the origin and substance of the world; each of them attributed the Whole to a single arche (beginning or principle), starting the tradition of naturalistic monism.[42]

Thales

 
Thales's theorem: if AC is a diameter and B is a point on the diameter's circle, the angle ABC is a right angle.

Thales (c. 624–546 BCE) is considered to be the father of philosophy.[43] None of his writings have survived. He is considered the first western philosopher since he was the first to use reason, to use proof, and to generalize. He created the word cosmos, the first word to describe the universe. He contributed to geometry and predicted the eclipse of 585 BCE.[44] Thales may have been of Phoenician ancestry.[45] Miletus was a meeting point and trade centre of the then great civilizations, and Thales visited the neighbouring civilizations, Egypt, Mesopotamia, Crete, and Phoenicia.[46] In Egypt, geometry was advanced as a means of separating agricultural fields. Thales, though, advanced geometry with his abstract deductive reasoning reaching universal generalizations. Proclus, a later Athenian philosopher, attributed the theorem now known as Thales's theorem to Thales. He is also known for being the first to claim that the base angles of isosceles triangles are equal, and that a diameter bisects the circle.[47] Thales visited Sardis, as many Greeks then, where astronomical records were kept and used astronomical observations for practical matters (oil harvesting).[48] Thales was widely considered a genius in ancient times[49] and was revered as one of the Seven Sages of Greece.[50]

Most importantly, what marks Thales as the first philosopher is the posing of the fundamental philosophical question about the origin and the substance of the world, while providing an answer based on empirical evidence and reasoning. He attributed the origin of the world to an element instead of a divine being.[51] Our knowledge of Thales' claim derives from Aristotle. Aristotle, while discussing opinions of previous philosophers, tells us that "Thales, the founder of this type of philosophy, says the principle (arche) is water." What he meant by arche, is a matter of interpretation (might be the origin, the element, or an ontological matrix), but regardless of the various interpretations, he conceived the world as One thing instead of a collection of various items and speculated on the binding/original elements.[52]

Another important aspect of Thales' philosophy is his claim that everything is full of gods. What he meant by that is again a matter of interpretation, that could be from a theistic view to an atheist one.[53] But the most plausible explanation, suggested by Aristotle, is that Thales is advocating a theory of hylozoism, that the universe, the sum of all things that exist, is divine and alive.[54] Lastly, another notable claim by Thales is that earth "rests on water"- maybe that was a conclusion after observing fish fossils on land.[55]

Anaximander

That from which all things are born
the beginning of all things
the first foundation of things is the Unlimited (apeiron);
The source from which coming-to-be is, for things that are, and for
their passing away in accordance with necessity.
For they give justice and pay retribution to each other for their mutual
injustice according to the ordered process of time.

Anaximander, DK 12 B 1, preserved fragment of On Nature[56]

Anaximander (610–546 BCE), also from Miletus, was 25 years younger than Thales. He was a member of the elite of Miletus, wealthy and a statesman. He showed interest in many fields, including mathematics and geography. He drew the first map of the world, was the first to conclude that the earth is spherical, and made instruments to mark time, something like a clock.[57] In response to Thales, he postulated as the first principle an undefined, unlimited substance without qualities (apeiron), out of which the primary opposites, hot and cold, moist and dry, became differentiated. His answer was an attempt to explain observable changes by attributing them to a single source that transforms to various elements. Like Thales, he provided a naturalistic explanation for phenomena previously given supernatural explanations. He is also known for speculating on the origin of mankind. He proclaimed that the earth is not situated in another structure but lies unsupported in the middle of the universe. Further, he developed a rudimentary evolutionary explanation for biodiversity in which constant universal powers affected the lives of animals.[58] According to Giorgio de Santillana, a philosophy professor at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Anaximander's conception of a universe governed by laws shaped the philosophical thinking of centuries to come and was as important as the discovery of fire or Einstein's breakthroughs in science.[59]

Anaximenes

Little is known of Anaximenes' (585–525 BCE) life. He was a younger contemporary and friend of Anaximander, and the two worked together on various intellectual projects. He also wrote a book on nature in prose. Anaximenes took for his principle aēr (air), conceiving it as being modified, via thickening and thinning, into the other classical elements: fire, wind, clouds, water, and earth. While his theory resembled that of Anaximander, as they both claimed a single source of the universe, Anaximenes suggested sophisticated mechanisms in which air is transformed to other elements, mainly because of changes of density. Since the classical era, he was considered the father of naturalistic explanations. Anaximenes expanded Anaximander's attempt to find a unitary cause explaining natural phenomena both living and nonliving, without, according to James Warren, having to "reduce living things in some way to mere locations of material change".[60]

Xenophanes

 
St. Elmo's fire (luminous plasma created by a corona discharge from a rod-like object) in a ship. Xenophanes' contemporaries attributed this phenomenon to the deity Dioscuri. Xenophanes argued that the observed illumination is due to small clouds influenced by special circumstances relating to stars—an example of naturalism and reductionism.[61]

Xenophanes was born in Colophon, an Ionian town near Miletus. He was a well-traveled poet whose primary interests were theology and epistemology. Concerning theology, he pointed out that we did not know whether there was one god or many gods, or in such case whether there was a hierarchy among them. To critique the anthropomorphic representation of the gods by his contemporary Greeks, he pointed out that different nations depicted their gods as looking like themselves. He famously said that if oxen, horses, or lions could draw, they would draw their gods as oxen, horses, or lions. This critique was not limited to the looks of gods but also their behaviour. Greek mythology, mostly shaped by the poets Homer and Hesiod, attributed moral failures such as jealously and adultery to the gods. Xenophanes opposed this. He thought gods must be morally superior to humans. Xenophanes, however, never claimed the gods were omnipotent, omnibenevolent, or omniscient.[62] Xenophanes also offered naturalistic explanations for phenomena such as the sun, the rainbow and St. Elmo's fire. Traditionally these were attributed to divine intervention but according to Xenophanes they were actually effects of clouds. These explanations of Xenophanes indicate empiricism in his thought and might constitute a kind of proto-scientism. Scholars have overlooked his cosmology and naturalism since Aristotle (maybe due to Xenophanes' lack of teleology) until recently but current literature suggests otherwise.[63] Concerning epistemology, Xenophanes questioned the validity of human knowledge. Humans usually tend to assert their beliefs are real and represent truth. While Xenophanes was a pessimist about the capability of humans to reach knowledge, he also believed in gradual progress through critical thinking. Xenophanes tried to find naturalistic explanations for meteorological and cosmological phenomena.[64]

Ancient philosophy historian Alexander Mourelatos notes Xenophanes used a pattern of thought that is still in use by modern metaphysics. Xenophanes, by reducing meteorological phenomena to clouds, created an argument that "X in reality is Y", for example B32, "What they call Iris [the rainbow] that too is in reality a cloud: one that appears to the eye as purple, red, and green. This is still use[d] today 'lightning is massive electrical discharge' or 'items such as tables are a cloud of micro-particles'." Mourelatos comments that the type of analogy that the cloud analogy is remains present in scientific language and "...is the modern philosopher's favourite subject for illustrations of inter-theoretic identity".[65]

According to Aristotle and Diogenes Laertius, Xenophanes was Parmenides' teacher; but is a matter of debate in current literature whether Xenophanes should also be considered an Eleatic.[39]

Heraclitus

The hallmark of Heraclitus' philosophy is flux. In fragment DK B30, Heraclitus writes: This world-order [Kosmos], the same of all, no god nor man did create, but it ever was and is and will be: everliving fire, kindling in measures and being quenched in measures. Heraclitus posited that all things in nature are in a state of perpetual flux. Like previous monist philosophers, Heraclitus claimed that the arche of the world was fire, which was subject to change – that makes him a materialist monist.[66] From fire all things originate and all things return to it again in a process of eternal cycles. Fire becomes water and earth and vice versa. These everlasting modifications explain his view that the cosmos was and is and will be.[66] The idea of continual flux is also met in the "river fragments". There, Heraclitus claims we can not step into the same river twice, a position summarized with the slogan ta panta rhei (everything flows). One fragment reads: "Into the same rivers we both step and do not step; we both are and are not" (DK 22 B49a). Heraclitus is seemingly suggesting that not only the river is constantly changing, but we do as well, even hinting at existential questions about humankind.[67]

Another key concept of Heraclitus is that opposites somehow mirror each other, a doctrine called unity of opposites. Two fragments relating to this concept state, "As the same thing in us is living and dead, waking and sleeping, young and old. For these things having changed around are those, and those in turn having changed around are these" (B88) and "Cold things warm up, the hot cools off, wet becomes dry, dry becomes wet" (B126). [68] Heraclitus' doctrine on the unity of opposites suggests that unity of the world and its various parts is kept through the tension produced by the opposites. Furthermore, each polar substance contains its opposite, in a continual circular exchange and motion that results in the stability of the cosmos.[69] Another of Heraclitus' famous axioms highlights this doctrine (B53): "War is father of all and king of all; and some he manifested as gods, some as men; some he made slaves, some free", where war means the creative tension that brings things into existence.[70]

A fundamental idea in Heraclitus is logos, an ancient Greek word with a variety of meanings; Heraclitus might have used a different meaning of the word with each usage in his book. Logos seems like a universal law that unites the cosmos, according to a fragment: "Listening not to me but to the logos, it is wise to agree (homologein) that all things are one" (DK 22 B50). While logos is everywhere, very few people are familiar with it. B 19 reads: [hoi polloi] "...do not know how to listen [to Logos] or how to speak [the truth]" [71] Heraclitus' thought on logos influenced the Stoics, who referred to him to support their belief that rational law governs the universe.[72]

Pythagoreanism

Pythagoras (582–496 BCE) was born on Samos, a small island near Miletus. He moved to Croton at about age 30, where he established his school and acquired political influence. Some decades later he had to flee Croton and relocate to Metapontum.[73]

Pythagoras was famous for studying numbers and the geometrical relations of numbers. A large following of Pythagoreans adopted and extended his doctrine. They advanced his ideas, reaching the claim that everything consists of numbers, the universe is made by numbers and everything is a reflection of analogies and geometrical relations.[74] Numbers, music and philosophy, all interlinked, could comfort the beauty-seeking human soul and hence Pythagoreans espoused the study of mathematics.[75]

Pythagorianism perceived the world as perfect harmony, dependent on number, and aimed at inducing humankind likewise to lead a harmonious life, including ritual and dietary recommendations.[76] Their way of life was ascetic, restraining themselves from various pleasures and food. They were vegetarians and placed enormous value on friendship.[77] Pythagoras politically was an advocate of a form of aristocracy, a position which later Pythagoreans rejected, but generally, they were reactionary and notably repressed women.[78] Other pre-Socratic philosophers mocked Pythagoras for his belief in reincarnation.[79]

Notable Pythagorians included Philolaus (470-380 BCE), Alcmaeon of Croton, Archytas (428-347 BCE) and Echphantus.[80] The most notable was Alcmaeon, a medical and philosophical writer. Alcmaeon noticed that most organs in the body come in pairs and suggested that human health depends on harmony between opposites (hot/cold, dry/wet), and illness is due to an imbalance of them. He was the first to think of the brain as the center of senses and thinking. Philolaus advanced cosmology through his discovery of heliocentricism – the idea that the Sun lies in the middle of the earth's orbit and other planets.[81]

Pythagoreanism influenced later Christian currents as Neoplatonism, and its pedagogical methods were adapted by Plato.[82] Furthermore, there seems to be a continuity in some aspects of Plato's philosophy. As Prof. Carl Huffman notes, Plato had a tendency to invoke mathematics in explaining natural phenomena, and he also believed in the immortality, even divinity of the human soul.[83]

The Eleatics: Parmenides, Zeno and Melissus

The Eleatic school is named after Elea, an ancient Greek town on the southern Italian Peninsula. Parmenides is considered the founder of the school. Other eminent Eleatics include Zeno of Elea and Melissus of Samos. According to Aristotle and Diogenes Laertius, Xenophanes was Parmenides' teacher, and it is debated whether Xenophanes should also be considered an Eleatic. [39] Parmenides was born in Elea to a wealthy family around 515 BCE.[84] Parmenides of Elea was interested in many fields, such as biology and astronomy. He was the first to deduce that the earth is spherical.[85] He was also involved in his town's political life.[86]

 
According to Parmenides, Being, what exists, is like the mass of a perfect sphere: undifferentiated, indivisible, and unchangeable.[87]

Parmenides' contributions were paramount not only to ancient philosophy but to all of western metaphysics and ontology.[86] Parmenides wrote a hard to interpret poem, named On Nature or On What-is, that substantially influenced later Greek philosophy.[88] Only 150 fragments of this poem survive.[89] It tells a story of a young man (kouros in ancient Greek) dedicated to finding the truth carried by a goddess on a long journey to the heavens. The poem consists of three parts, the proem (i.e., preface), the Way of Truth and the Way of Opinion. Very few pieces from the Way of Opinion survive. In that part, Parmenides must have been dealing with cosmology, judging from other authors' references.[90] The Way of Truth was then, and is still today, considered of much more importance. In the Way of Truth, the goddess criticizes the logic of people who do not distinguish the real from the non-existent ("What-is" and "What-is-Not"). In this poem Parmenides unfolds his philosophy: that all things are One, and therefore nothing can be changed or altered. Hence, all the things that we think to be true, even ourselves, are false representations.[91] What-is, according to Parmenides, is a physical sphere that is unborn, unchanged, and infinite.[92] This is a monist vision of the world, far more radical than that of Heraclitus.[93] The goddess teaches Kouros to use his reasoning to understand whether various claims are true or false, discarding senses as fallacious.[94] Other fundamental issues raised by Parmenides' poem are the doctrine that nothing comes from nothing[95] and the unity of being and thinking. As quoted by DK fragment 3: To gar auto noein estin te kai einai (For to think and to be is one and the same).[96]

Zeno and Melissus continued Parmenides' thought on cosmology.[97] Zeno is mostly known for his paradoxes, i.e., self-contradictory statements which served as proofs that Parmenides' monism was valid, and that pluralism was invalid. The most common theme of those paradoxes involved traveling a distance, but since that distance comprises infinite points, the traveler could never accomplish it. His most famous is the Achilles paradox, which is mentioned by Aristotelis: "The second is called the 'Achilles' and says that the slowest runner will never be caught by the fastest, because it is necessary for the pursuer first to arrive at the point from which the pursued set off, so it is necessary that the slower will always be a little ahead." (Aristotle Phys. 239b14–18 [DK 29 A26])[98] Melissus defended and advanced Parmenides' theory using prose, without invoking divinity or mythical figures. He tried to explain why we think various non-existent objects exist.[99]

The Eleatics' focus on Being through means of logic initiated the philosophical discipline of ontology. Other philosophers influenced by the Eleatics (such as the Sophists, Plato, and Aristotle) further advanced logic, argumentation, mathematics and especially elenchos (proof). The Sophists even placed Being under the scrutiny of elenchos. Because of the Eleatics reasoning was acquiring a formal method.[100]

The Pluralists: Anaxagoras and Empedocles

 
The Death of Empedocles by Salvator Rosa. Legend holds that Empedocles committed suicide by falling into Mount Etna's volcano.[101]

The Pluralist school marked a return to Milesian natural philosophy, though much more refined because of Eleatic criticism.[102]

Anaxagoras was born in Ionia, but was the first major philosopher to emigrate to Athens. He was soon associated with the Athenian statesman Pericles and, probably due to this association, was accused by a political opponent of Pericles for impiety as Anaxagoras held that the sun was not associated with divinity; it was merely a huge burning stone. Pericles helped Anaxagoras flee Athens and return to Ionia.[103] Anaxagoras was also a major influence on Socrates.[104]

Anaxagoras is known for his "theory of everything".[105] He claimed that "in everything there is a share of everything." Interpretations differ as to what he meant. Anaxagoras was trying to stay true to the Eleatic principle of the everlasting (What-is) while also explaining the diversity of the natural world.[106] Anaxagoras accepted Parmenides' doctrine that everything that exists (What-is) has existed forever, but contrary to the Eleatics, he added the ideas of panspermia and nous. All objects were mixtures of various elements, such as air, water, and others. One special element was nous, i.e., mind, which is present in living things and causes motion. According to Anaxagoras, Nous was one of the elements that make up the cosmos. Things that had nous were alive. According to Anaxagoras, all things are composites of some basic elements; although it is not clear what these elements are.[107] All objects are a mixture of these building blocks and have a portion of each element, except nous. Nous was also considered a building block of the cosmos, but it exists only in living objects. Anaxagoras writes: "In everything there is a portion (moira) of everything except mind (nous), but there are some things in which mind too is present."[108] Nous was not just an element of things, somehow it was the cause of setting the universe into motion. Anaxagoras advanced Milesian thought on epistemology, striving to establish an explanation that could be valid for all natural phenomena. Influenced by the Eleatics, he also furthered the exploration of metatheoretical questions such as the nature of knowledge.[106]

Empedocles was born in Akragas, a town in the southern Italian peninsula. According to Diogenes Laertius, Empedocles wrote two books in the form of poems: Peri Physeos (On nature) and the Katharmoi (Purifications). Some contemporary scholars argue these books might be one; all agree that interpreting Empedocles is difficult.[109]

On cosmological issues, Empedocles takes from the Eleatic school the idea that the universe is unborn, has always been and always will be. He also continues Anaxagoras' thought on the four "roots" (i.e., classical elements), that by intermixing, they create all things around us. These roots are fire, air, earth, and water. Crucially, he adds two more components, the immaterial forces of love and strife. These two forces are opposite and by acting upon the material of the four roots unite in harmony or tear apart the four roots, with the resulting mixture being all things that exist. Empedocles uses an analogy of how this is possible: as a painter uses a few basic colors to create a painting, the same happens with the four roots. It is not quite clear if love and strife co-operate or have a greater plan, but love and strife are in a continual cycle that generates life and the earth we live in.[110] Other beings, apart from the four roots and love and strife, according to Empedocles' Purifications are mortals, gods, and daemons.[111] Like Pythagoras, Empedocles believed in the soul's transmigration and was vegetarian.[112]

Atomists: Leucippus and Democritus

 
Democritus by Hendrick ter Brugghen, 1628. Democritus was known as the "laughing philosopher"[113]

Leucippus and Democritus both lived in Abdera, in Thrace. They are most famous for their atomic cosmology even though their thought included many other fields of philosophy, such as ethics, mathematics, aesthetics, politics, and even embryology. [114]

The atomic theory of Leucippus and Democritus was a response to the Eleatic school, who held that motion is not possible because everything is occupied with What-is. Democritus and Leucippus reverted the Eleatic axiom, claiming that since motions exist, What-is-not must also exist; hence void exists. Democritus and Leucippus were skeptics regarding the reliability of our senses, but they were confident that motion exists.[115] Atoms, according to Democritus and Leucippus, had some characteristics of the Eleatic What-is: they were homogeneous and indivisible. These characteristics allowed answers to Zeno's paradoxes.[116] Atoms move within the void, interact with each other, and form the plurality of the world we live in, in a purely mechanical manner.[117]

One conclusion of the Atomists was determinism - the philosophical view that all events are determined completely by previously existing causes. As Leucippus said, (DK 67 B2) "Nothing comes to be random but everything is by reason and out of necessity."[118] Democritus concluded that since everything is atoms and void, several of our senses are not real but conventional. Color, for example, is not a property of atoms; hence our perception of color is a convention. As Democritus said, (DK 68 B9) "By convention sweet, by convention bitter, by convention hot, by convention cold, by convention colour; in reality atoms and void."[119] This can be interpreted in two ways. According to James Warren there is an eliminativist interpretation, such that Democritus means that color is not real, and there is a relativist interpretation, such that Democritus means that color and taste are not real but are perceived as such by our senses through sensory interaction.[120]

Sophists

The sophists were a philosophical and educational movement that flourished in ancient Greece before Socrates. They attacked traditional thinking, from gods to morality, paving the way for further advances of philosophy and other disciplines such as drama, social sciences, mathematics, and history.[121]

Plato disparaged the sophists, causing long-lasting harm to their reputation. Plato thought philosophy should be reserved for those who had the appropriate intellect to understand it; whereas the sophists would teach anyone who would pay tuition.[122] The sophists taught rhetoric and how to address issues from multiple viewpoints. Since the sophists and their pupils were persuasive speakers at court or in public, they were accused of moral and epistemological relativism,[123] which indeed some sophists appeared to advocate. Prominent sophists include Protagoras, Gorgias, Hippias, Thrasymachus, Prodicus, Callicles, Antiphon, and Critias.[124]

Protagoras is mostly known for two of his quotes. One is that "[humans are..] the measure of all things, of things that are that they are, of things that are not that they are not" which is commonly interpreted as affirming philosophical relativism, but it can also be interpreted as claiming that knowledge is only relevant to humankind, that moral rightness and other forms of knowledge are relevant to and limited to human mind and perception. The other quote is, "Concerning the gods, I cannot ascertain whether they exist or whether they do not, or what form they have; for there are many obstacles to knowing, including the obscurity of the question and the brevity of human life."[125]

Gorgias wrote a book named On Nature, in which he attacked the Eleatics' concepts of What-is and What-is-not. He claimed it is absurd to hold that nonexistence exists, and that What-is was impossible since it had to either be generated or be unlimited and neither is sufficient. There is an ongoing debate among modern scholars whether he was a serious thinker, a precursor of extreme relativism and skepticism, or merely a charlatan.[126]

Antiphon placed natural law against the law of the city. One need not obey the city's laws as long as one will not get caught. One could argue that Antiphon was a careful hedonist—rejecting dangerous pleasures.[127]

Philolaous of Croton and Diogenes of Apollonia

Philolaus of Croton and Diogenes of Apollonia from Thrace (born c. 460 BCE) are considered the last generation of pre-Socratics. Rather than advancing a cosmological perspective on how our universe is constructed, they are mostly noted for advancing abstract thinking and argumentation.[128]
Pythagorianism, Anaxagoras and Empedocles influenced Philolaus. He attempted to explain both the variety and unity of the cosmos. He addressed the need to explain how the various masses of the universe interact among them and coined the term Harmonia, a binding force that allows mass to take shape. The structure of the cosmos consisted of apeira (unlimiteds) and perainonta (limiters).[129] Diogenes of Apollonia returned to Milesian monism, but with a rather more elegant thought. As he says in DK64 B2 "It seems to me, overall, that all things are alterations of the same things and are the same thing". He explains that things, even when changing shapes, remain ontologically the same.[130]

Topics

Knowledge

The mythologoi, Homer and Hesiod, along with other poets, centuries before the pre-Socratics, thought that true knowledge was exclusive to the divine. But starting with Xenophanes, the pre-Socratics moved towards a more secular approach to knowledge.[131] The pre-Socratics sought a method to understand the cosmos, while being aware that there is a limit to human knowledge.[132]

While Pythagoras and Empedocles linked their self-proclaimed wisdom to their divinely inspired status, they tried to teach or urge mortals to seek the truth about the natural realm—Pythagoras by means of mathematics and geometry and Empedocles by exposure to experiences.[133] Xenophanes thought that human knowledge was merely an opinion that cannot be validated or proven to be true. According to Jonathan Warren, Xenophanes set the outline of the nature of knowledge.[134] Later, Heraclitus and Parmenides stressed the capability of humans to understand how things stand in nature through direct observation, inquiry, and reflection.[132]

Theology

Pre-Socratic thought contributed to the demythologization of the Greek popular religion. The narrative of their thought contributed to shifting the course of ancient Greek philosophy and religion away from the realm of divinity and even paved the way for teleological explanations.[135] They attacked the traditional representations of gods that Homer and Hesiod had established and put Greek popular religion under scrutiny, initiating the schism between natural philosophy and theology.[136] Pre-Socratic philosophers did not have atheistic beliefs, but it should be kept in mind that being an atheist those days was not without social or legal dangers. Despite that, arguments rejecting deities were not barred from the public sphere which can be seen in Protagoras's quotation on the gods: "About the gods I am able to know neither that they exist nor that they do not exist."[137]

The theological thought starts with the Milesian philosophers. It is evident in Anaximander's idea of the apeiron steering everything, which had other abilities usually attributed to Zeus.[138] Later, Xenophanes developed a critique of the anthropomorphism of the gods. Xenophanes set three preconditions for God: he had to be all good, immortal and not resembling humans in appearance, which had a major impact on western religious thought.[139]

The theological thought of Heraclitus and Parmenides is not entirely certain, but it is generally accepted that they believed in some kind of divinity. The Pythagoreans and Empedocles believed in the transmigration of souls. Anaxagoras asserted that cosmic intelligence (nous) gives life to things. Diogenes of Appollonia expanded this line of thinking and might have constructed the first teleological argument "it would not be possible without Intellection for it so to be divided up that it has the measures of all things — of winter and summer and night and day and rains and winds and fair weather. The other things, too, if one wishes to consider them, one would find disposed of in the best possible way."[140] While some pre-Socratics were trying to find alternatives to divinity, others were setting the foundation of explaining the universe in terms of teleology and intelligent design by a divine force.[141]

Medicine

Prior to the pre-Socratics, health and illness were thought to be governed by gods.[142] Pre-Socratic philosophy and medicine advanced in parallel, with medicine as a part of philosophy and vice versa.[143] It was Hippocrates (often hailed as the father of medicine) who separated – but not completely – the two domains.[144] Physicians incorporated pre-Socratic philosophical ideas about the nature of the world in their theoretical framework, blurring the border between the two domains. An example is the study of epilepsy, which in popular religion was thought to be a divine intervention to human life, but Hippocrates' school attributed it to nature, just as Milesian rationalism demythologized other natural phenomena such as earthquakes.[145] The systematic study of anatomy, physiology, and illnesses led to the discovery of cause-effect relations and a more sophisticated terminology and understanding of the diseases that ultimately yielded rational science.[146]

Cosmology

The pre-Socratics were the first to attempt to provide reductive explanations for a plethora of natural phenomena.[147]

Firstly, they were preoccupied with the mystery of the cosmic matter—what was the basic substance of the universe? Anaximander suggested apeiron (limitless), which hints, as Aristotle analyzed, there is no beginning and no end to it, both chronologically and within the space.[148] Anaximenes placed aêr (air) as the primary principle, probably after realizing the importance of air to life and/or the need to explain various observable changes.[149] Heraclitus, also seeking to address the issue of the ever changing world, placed fire as the primary principle of the universe, that transforms to water and earth to produce the universe. Ever-transforming nature is summarized by Heraclitus' axiom panta rhei (everything is in a state of flux).[150] Parmenides suggested two ever-lasting primary building blocs, night and day, which together form the universe.[151] Empedocles increased the building blocks to four and named them roots, while also adding Love and Strife, to serve as the driving force for the roots to mingle.[152] Anaxagoras extended even more the plurality of Empedocles, claiming everything is in everything, myriads of substances were mixing among each other except one, Nous (mind) that orchestrates everything—but did not attribute divine characteristics to Nous.[153] Leucippus and Democritus asserted the universe consists of atoms and void, while the motion of atoms is responsible for the changes we observe.[154]

Rationalism, observation and the beginning of scientific thought

The pre-Socratic intellectual revolution is widely considered to have been the first step towards liberation of the human mind from the mythical world and initiated a march towards reason and scientific thought that yielded modern western philosophy and science.[155] The pre-Socratics sought to understand the various aspects of nature by means of rationalism, observations, and offering explanations that could be deemed as scientific, giving birth to what became Western rationalism.[156] Thales was the first to seek for a unitary arche of the world. Whether arche meant the beginning, the origin, the main principle or the basic element is unclear, but was the first attempt to reduce the explanations of the universe to a single cause, based on reason and not guided by any sort of divinity. [157] Anaximander offered the principle of sufficient reason,[158] a revolutionary argument that would also yield the principle that nothing comes out of nothing.[159] Most of pre-Socratics seemed indifferent to the concept of teleology, especially the Atomists who fiercely rejected the idea.[160] According to them, the various phenomena were the consequence of the motion of atoms without any purpose.[161] Xenophanes also advanced a critique of anthropomorphic religion by highlighting in a rational way the inconsistency of depictions of the gods in Greek popular religion.[162]

Undoubtedly, pre-Socratics paved the way towards science, but whether what they did could constitute science is a matter of debate.[163] Thales had offered the first account of a reduction and a generalization, a significant milestone towards scientific thought. Other pre-Socratics also sought to answer the question of arche, offering various answers, but the first step towards scientific thought was already taken.[157] Philosopher Karl Popper, in his seminal work Back to Presocratics (1958) traces the roots of modern science (and the West) to the early Greek philosophers. He writes: "There can be little doubt that the Greek tradition of philosophical criticism had its main source in Ionia ... It thus leads the tradition which created the rational or scientific attitude, and with it our Western civilization, the only civilization, which is based upon science (though, of course, not upon science alone)." Elsewhere in the same study Popper diminishes the significance of the label they should carry as purely semantics. "There is the most perfect possible continuity of thought between [the Presocratics'] theories and the later developments in physics. Whether they are called philosophers, or pre-scientists, or scientists, matters very little."[164] Other scholars did not share the same view. F. M. Cornford considered the Ionanians as dogmatic speculators, due to their lack of empiricism.[165]

Reception and legacy

Antiquity

The pre-Socratics had a direct influence on classical antiquity in many ways. The philosophic thought produced by the pre-Socratics heavily influenced later philosophers, historians and playwrights.[166] One line of influence was the Socrato-Ciceronian tradition, while the other was the Platonic-Aristotelian.[1]

Socrates, Xenophon and Cicero were highly influenced by the physiologoi (naturalists) as they were named in ancient times. The naturalists impressed young Socrates and he was interested in the quest for the substance of the cosmos, but his interest waned as he became steadily more focused on epistemology, virtue, and ethics rather than the natural world. According to Xenophon, the reason was that Socrates believed humans incapable of comprehending the cosmos.[167] Plato, in the Phaedo, claims that Socrates was uneasy with the materialistic approach of the pre-Socratics, particularly Anaxagoras.[168] Cicero analyzed his views on the pre-Socratics in his Tusculanae Disputationes, as he distinguished the theoretical nature of pre-Socratic thought from previous "sages" who were interested in more practical issues. Xenophon, like Cicero, saw the difference between pre-Socratics and Socrates being his interest in human affairs (ta anthropina).[169]

The pre-Socratics deeply influenced both Plato and Aristotle.[170] Aristotle discussed the pre-Socratics in the first book of Metaphysics, as an introduction to his own philosophy and the quest for arche.[171] He was the first to state that philosophy starts with Thales.[172] It is not clear whether Thales talked of water as arche, or that was a retrospective interpretation by Aristotle, who was examining his predecessors under the scope of his views.[173] More crucially, Aristotle criticized the pre-Socratics for not identifying a purpose as a final cause, a fundamental idea in Aristotelian metaphysics.[174] Plato also attacked pre-Socratic materialism.[175]

Later, during the Hellenistic era, philosophers of various currents focused on the study of nature and advanced pre-Socratic ideas.[176] The Stoics incorporated features from Anaxagoras and Heraclitus, such as nous and fire respectively.[177] The Epicureans saw Democritus' atomism as their predecessor while the Sceptics were linked to Xenophanes.[178]

Modern era

The pre-Socratics, along with the rest of ancient Greece, invented the central concepts of Western civilization: freedom, democracy, individual autonomy and rationalism.[179] Francis Bacon, a 16th-century philosopher known for advancing the scientific method, was probably the first philosopher of the modern era to use pre-Socratic axioms extensively in his texts. He criticized the pre-Socratic theory of knowledge by Xenophanes and others, claiming that their deductive reasoning could not yield meaningful results—an opinion contemporary philosophy of science rejects.[180] Bacon's fondness for the pre-Socratics, especially Democritus' atomist theory, might have been because of his anti-Aristotelianism.[181]

Friedrich Nietzsche admired the pre-Socratics deeply, calling them "tyrants of the spirit" to mark their antithesis and his preference against Socrates and his successors.[182] Nietzsche also weaponized pre-Socratic antiteleology, coupled with the materialism exemplified by Democritus, for his attack on Christianity and its morals. Nietzsche saw the pre-Socratics as the first ancestors of contemporary science—linking Empedocles to Darwinism and Heraclitus to physicist Helmholtz.[183] According to his narrative, limned in many of his books, the pre-Socratic era was the glorious era of Greece, while the so-called Golden Age that followed was an age of decay, according to Nietzsche. Nietzsche incorporated the pre-Socratics in his Apollonian and Dionysian dialectics, with them representing the creative Dionysian aspect of the duo.[184]

Martin Heidegger found the roots of his phenomenology and later thinking of Things and the Fourfold[185] in the pre-Socratics,[186] considering Anaximander, Parmenides, and Heraclitus as the original thinkers on being, which he identified in their work as physis [φύσις] (emergence, contrasted against κρύπτεσθαι, kryptesthai, in Heraclitus’ Fragment 123)[187] or aletheia [αλήθεια] (truth as unconcealment).[188]

References

  1. ^ a b Laks & Most 2018, p. 1.
  2. ^ Most 1999, pp. 332–362.
  3. ^ Curd 2020, section 1. Who Were the Presocratic Philosophers?.
  4. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 10; Warren 2014, pp. 1–2.
  5. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 180–181.
  6. ^ Laks & Most 2018, pp. 1–2, 12–13.
  7. ^ Laks & Most 2018, pp. 29–31; Runia 2008, p. 28.
  8. ^ Irwin 1999, p. 6; Barnes 1987, pp. 24–35; Warren 2014, pp. 7–9.
  9. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 24–25.
  10. ^ Waterfield 2000, p. ix.
  11. ^ Kirk & Raven 1977, pp. 3.
  12. ^ Warren 2014, p. 3; Curd 2020, Introduction.
  13. ^ Runia 2008, p. 35.
  14. ^ Curd 2008, p. 3; Burkert 2008, pp. 55–56.
  15. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 82–83.
  16. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 18–21.
  17. ^ Warren 2014, p. 181.
  18. ^ Evans 2019, pp. 12–14; Barnes 1987, p. 14; Laks & Most 2018, p. 53.
  19. ^ Burkert 2008, p. 55-57.
  20. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 10–12.
  21. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 14; Laks & Most 2018, p. 53.
  22. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 79–80.
  23. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 16.
  24. ^ Kirk & Raven 1977, pp. 8–9, 71–72; Barnes 1987, pp. 55–59; Waterfield 2000, pp. xx–xxiv.
  25. ^ Kirk & Raven 1977, pp. 10, 19; Barnes 1987, p. 55.
  26. ^ Waterfield 2000, p. xxii; Barnes 1987, pp. 56–67.
  27. ^ Kirk & Raven 1977, p. 37-39.
  28. ^ Kirk & Raven 1977, pp. 70–71.
  29. ^ Osborne 2004, p. 13.
  30. ^ Vamvacas 2009, pp. 19–20.
  31. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 16–24; Vamvacas 2009, p. 27.
  32. ^ Curd 2020, Introduction.
  33. ^ Vamvacas 2009, p. 27.
  34. ^ Warren 2014, p. 25; Sandywell 1996, p. 38.
  35. ^ Vamvacas 2009, p. 20-21.
  36. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 16–22.
  37. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 16–17.
  38. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 36–39.
  39. ^ a b c d Warren 2014, p. 3.
  40. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 39–42; Warren 2014, p. 3.
  41. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 9.
  42. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 75–78; Kirk & Raven 1977, p. 73.
  43. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 36; Warren 2014, p. 23.
  44. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 86.
  45. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 89; Kirk & Raven 1977, pp. 74–75.
  46. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 89.
  47. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 87.
  48. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 86, 90.
  49. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 90.
  50. ^ Warren 2014, p. 28.
  51. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 93.
  52. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 90-94.
  53. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 94-96.
  54. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 97.
  55. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 97–98; Warren 2014, p. 27.
  56. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 139.
  57. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 136–138.
  58. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 36–37; Warren 2014, pp. 28–33.
  59. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 141.
  60. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 33–37; Sandywell 1996, pp. 172–173.
  61. ^ Mourelatos 2008, pp. 134–135.
  62. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 41–50.
  63. ^ Mourelatos 2008, pp. 134–139.
  64. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 50–56.
  65. ^ Mourelatos 2008; Curd 2020, Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus.
  66. ^ a b Graham 2008, pp. 170–172.
  67. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 72–74.
  68. ^ Graham 2008, p. 175.
  69. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 263–265; Graham 2008, pp. 175–177.
  70. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 263–265; Curd 2020, Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus.
  71. ^ Warren 2014, p. 63; Sandywell 1996, p. 237.
  72. ^ Warren 2014, p. 63.
  73. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 81; Sandywell 1996, p. 189.
  74. ^ Warren 2014, p. 39; Sandywell 1996, p. 197.
  75. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 199.
  76. ^ Curd 2020, The Pythagorean Tradition.
  77. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 192.
  78. ^ Curd 2020, The Pythagorean Tradition; Sandywell 1996, pp. 192–194.
  79. ^ Warren 2014, p. 38.
  80. ^ Curd 2020, The Pythagorean Tradition; Sandywell 1996, p. 195.
  81. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 196–197.
  82. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 191–192.
  83. ^ Huffman 2008, pp. 284–285.
  84. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 129; Sandywell 1996, p. 295.
  85. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 40.
  86. ^ a b Sandywell 1996, p. 295.
  87. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 309–310.
  88. ^ Warren 2014, p. 77; Barnes 1987, pp. 40–41.
  89. ^ Warren 2014, p. 79.
  90. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 79–80.
  91. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 77–80; Sandywell 1996, p. 300.
  92. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 98.
  93. ^ Warren 2014, p. 80.
  94. ^ Curd 2020, Parmenides of Elea.
  95. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 312.
  96. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 298.
  97. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 103–104.
  98. ^ Warren 2014, p. 108.
  99. ^ Barnes 1987, pp. 148–149; Warren 2014, pp. 103–104.
  100. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 349–350.
  101. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 356.
  102. ^ Warren 2014, p. 3:Warren also adds Democritus as a pluralist.
  103. ^ Warren 2014, p. 119.
  104. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 132–133.
  105. ^ Curd 2008, p. 230.
  106. ^ a b Curd 2008, p. 231.
  107. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 121–122.
  108. ^ Warren 2014, p. 125 DK 59 B11:6.
  109. ^ Primavesi 2008, pp. 250; Warren 2014, pp. 135–137.
  110. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 137–141; Vamvacas 2009, pp. 169–172.
  111. ^ Warren 2014, p. 146.
  112. ^ Primavesi 2008, p. 251.
  113. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 380.
  114. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 153–154.
  115. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 155–157.
  116. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 157–161.
  117. ^ Warren 2014, p. 163.
  118. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 164–165.
  119. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 166–167.
  120. ^ Warren 2014, p. 169.
  121. ^ Gagarin & Woodruff 2008, p. 367.
  122. ^ Gagarin & Woodruff 2008, pp. 365–367.
  123. ^ Graham 2021, The Sophists and Anonymous Sophistic Texts.
  124. ^ Gagarin & Woodruff 2008, pp. 366–368.
  125. ^ Graham 2021, Protagoras.
  126. ^ Graham 2021, Gorgias.
  127. ^ Graham 2021, Antiphon.
  128. ^ Warren 2014, p. 179.
  129. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 175–177.
  130. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 178–179.
  131. ^ Lesher 2008, pp. 458–459.
  132. ^ a b Lesher 2008, p. 476.
  133. ^ Lesher 2008, pp. 466–468.
  134. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 51.
  135. ^ Robinson 2008, pp. 496–497.
  136. ^ Robinson 2008, p. 497.
  137. ^ Sedley 2013, p. 140.
  138. ^ Robinson 2008, pp. 485–487.
  139. ^ Robinson 2008, pp. 487–488.
  140. ^ Robinson 2008, pp. 490–492.
  141. ^ Robinson 2008, p. 496.
  142. ^ Longrigg 1989, p. 1-2.
  143. ^ Van der Eijk 2008, p. 385.
  144. ^ Van der Eijk 2008, pp. 385–386.
  145. ^ Van der Eijk 2008, p. 387; Longrigg 2013, pp. 1–2.
  146. ^ Van der Eijk 2008, pp. 387, 395–399; Longrigg 2013, pp. 1–2.
  147. ^ Wright 2008, p. 414.
  148. ^ Wright 2008, p. 415.
  149. ^ Wright 2008, p. 416.
  150. ^ Wright 2008, pp. 416–417.
  151. ^ Wright 2008, p. 417.
  152. ^ Wright 2008, p. 418.
  153. ^ Wright 2008, p. 419 & 425.
  154. ^ Wright 2008, pp. 419–420.
  155. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 17; Hankinson 2008, pp. 453–455.
  156. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 16; Laks & Most 2018, p. 36.
  157. ^ a b Hankinson 2008, pp. 435–437.
  158. ^ Hankinson 2008, pp. 445.
  159. ^ Hankinson 2008, pp. 446.
  160. ^ Hankinson 2008, pp. 449.
  161. ^ Hankinson 2008, pp. 449–450.
  162. ^ Hankinson 2008, p. 453.
  163. ^ Taub 2020, pp. 7–9.
  164. ^ Vamvacas 2009, pp. 19, 23.
  165. ^ Curd 2008, p. 18-19.
  166. ^ Barnes 1987, p. 14.
  167. ^ Palmer 2008, p. 534.
  168. ^ Laks & Most 2018, pp. 1–8; Palmer 2008, pp. 534–554.
  169. ^ Laks & Most 2018, pp. 9–11.
  170. ^ Palmer 2008, p. 548.
  171. ^ Frede 2008, p. 503; Palmer 2008, p. 536.
  172. ^ Frede 2008, p. 503.
  173. ^ Frede 2008, pp. 505, 522.
  174. ^ Laks & Most 2018, pp. 16.
  175. ^ Palmer 2008, p. 536.
  176. ^ Curd 2008, p. 40.
  177. ^ Palmer 2008, pp. 547–548.
  178. ^ Curd 2008, p. 11.
  179. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 6-7.
  180. ^ Vamvacas 2009, pp. 20–23.
  181. ^ McCarthy 1999, pp. 183–187.
  182. ^ Laks & Most 2018, pp. 21–22.
  183. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 7; Laks & Most 2018, pp. 21–22.
  184. ^ Sandywell 1996, p. 7.
  185. ^ Mitchell, Andrew (2015). The Fourfold: Reading the Late Heidegger. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 9780810130760.
  186. ^ Curd 2008, pp. 19–20.
  187. ^ Heidegger, Martin (1991). The Principle of Reason. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. ISBN 9780253210661.
  188. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 69–71; Laks & Most 2018, p. 73.

Cited sources

  • Barnes, Jonathan (1987). Early Greek Philosophy. Penguin Books. ISBN 978-0-14-044461-2.
  • Burkert, Walter (27 October 2008). "Prehistory of Presocratic Philosophy in an Orientalizing Context". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 55–88. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Curd, Patricia (27 October 2008). "Anaxagoras and the Theory of Everything". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Curd, Patricia (2020). "Presocratic Philosophy". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  • Evans, C. Stephen (2019). A History of Western Philosophy: From the Pre-Socratics to Postmodernism. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-7369-2.
  • Frede, Michael (27 October 2008). "Aristotle's Account of the Origins of Philosophy". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 501–529. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Graham, Daniel W. (27 October 2008). "Heraclitus: Flux, Order, and Knowledge". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 169–187. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Graham, Jacob N (2021). Pre-Socratic philosophy. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Gagarin, Michael; Woodruff, Paul (27 October 2008). "The Sophists". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Hankinson, R.J. (27 October 2008). "Reason, Cause, and Explanation in Presocratic Philosophy". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 434–457. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Huffman, Carl (27 October 2008). "Two Problems in Pythagoreanism". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 284–304. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Kirk, Geoffrey; Raven, J. E. (1977). The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-27455-5.
  • Lesher, J.H. (27 October 2008). "The humanizing of knowledge in presocratic thought". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 458–484. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Mourelatos, Alexander P. D. (27 October 2008). "The Cloud-Astrophysics of Xenophanes and Ionian Material Monism". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 134–168. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Irwin, Terence (1999). Classical Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-289253-9.
  • Laks, André; Most, Glenn (1 January 2018). The Concept of Presocratic Philosophy: Its Origin, Development, and Significance. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-8791-0.
  • Longrigg, James (1989). "Presocratic Philosophy and Hippocratic Medicine". History of Science. SAGE Publications. 27 (1): 1–39. Bibcode:1989HisSc..27....1L. doi:10.1177/007327538902700101. ISSN 0073-2753. PMID 11621888. S2CID 742356.
  • Longrigg, James (7 March 2013). Greek Rational Medicine: Philosophy and Medicine from Alcmaeon to the Alexandrians. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-97366-8.
  • McCarthy, John C. (1999). "Bacon's Third Sailing: The 'Pre–Socratic' Origins of Modern Philosophy". In McCoy, Joe (ed.). Early Greek Philosophy:Reason at the Beginning of Philosophy. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press. pp. 157–188. ISBN 978-0-19-964465-0.
  • Most, Glenn W. (28 June 1999). "16 - The poetics of early Greek philosophy". In A. A. Long (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
  • Osborne, Catherine (22 April 2004). Presocratic Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-284094-3.
  • Palmer, John (27 October 2008). "Classical Representations and Uses of the Presocratics". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 530–554. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Primavesi, Oliver (27 October 2008). "Empedocles: Physical and Mythical Divinity". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Robinson, T.M. (27 October 2008). "Presocratic Theology". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 485–499. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Runia, David T. (27 October 2008). "The sources of pre-Socratic philosophy". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 27–54. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Sandywell, Barry (1996). Presocratic Reflexivity: The Construction of Philosophical Discourse c. 600-450 B.C.: Logological Investigations: Volume Three. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-85347-2.
  • Sedley, David (November 2013). "The Pre-Socratics to the Hellenistic Age". In Bullivant, Stephen (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Atheism. Michael Ruse. OUP Oxford. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199644650.013.002. ISBN 978-0-19-964465-0.
  • Taub, Liba (30 January 2020). The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Greek and Roman Science. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-09248-8.
  • Vamvacas, Constantine J. (28 May 2009). The Founders of Western Thought – The Presocratics: A diachronic parallelism between Presocratic Thought and Philosophy and the Natural Sciences. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 20–. ISBN 978-1-4020-9791-1.
  • Van der Eijk, Philip (27 October 2008). "The Role of Medicine in the Formation of Early Greek Thought". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 385–412. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Warren, James (5 December 2014). Presocratics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-49337-2.
  • Waterfield, Robin (7 September 2000). The First Philosophers: The Presocratics and Sophists. Oxford University Press, UK. ISBN 978-0-19-282454-7.
  • Wright, M.R. (27 October 2008). "Presocratic cosmologies". In Curd, Patricia (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Daniel W Graham. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 413–432. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.

Further reading

  • Cornford, F. M. 1991. From Religion to Philosophy: A Study in the Origins of Western Speculation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Graham, D. W. 2010. The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics. 2 vols. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Furley, D. J., and R. E. Allen, eds. 1970. Studies in Presocratic Philosophy. Vol. 1, The Beginnings of Philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Jaeger, W. 1947. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
  • Lloyd, G. E. R., Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle. New York: Norton, 1970.
  • Luchte, James. 2011. Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn. New York:Continuum International Publishing Group
  • McKirahan, R. D. 2011. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.
  • Robb, K., ed. 1983. Language and Thought in Early Greek Philosophy. La Salle, IL: Hegeler Institute.
  • Stamatellos, G. 2012, Introduction to Presocratics: A Thematic Approach to Early Greek Philosophy with Key Readings, Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Vlastos, G. 1995. Studies in Greek Philosophy. Vol. 1, The Presocratics. Edited by D. W. Graham. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press.
  • Vassallo, Ch. 2021 The Presocratics at Herculaneum: A Study of Early Greek Philosophy in the Epicurean Tradition. Berlin-Boston: De Gruyter.

External links

  • Collections Containing Articles on Presocratic Philosophy
  • Pre-Socratic philosophy at PhilPapers

socratic, philosophy, presocratics, redirects, here, band, presocratics, band, also, known, early, greek, philosophy, ancient, greek, philosophy, before, socrates, socratic, philosophers, were, mostly, interested, cosmology, beginning, substance, universe, inq. Presocratics redirects here For the band see Presocratics band Pre Socratic philosophy also known as early Greek philosophy is ancient Greek philosophy before Socrates Pre Socratic philosophers were mostly interested in cosmology the beginning and the substance of the universe but the inquiries of these early philosophers spanned the workings of the natural world as well as human society ethics and religion They sought explanations based on natural law rather than the actions of gods Their work and writing has been almost entirely lost Knowledge of their views comes from testimonia i e later authors discussions of the work of pre Socratics Philosophy found fertile ground in the ancient Greek world because of the close ties with neighboring civilizations and the rise of autonomous civil entities poleis PythagorasParmenidesHeraclitusPre Socratic philosophy began in the 6th century BCE with the three Milesians Thales Anaximander and Anaximenes They all attributed the arche a word that could take the meaning of origin substance or principle of the world to respectively water apeiron the unlimited and air governed by nous mind or intelligence Another three pre Socratic philosophers came from nearby Ionian towns Xenophanes Heraclitus and Pythagoras Xenophanes is known for his critique of the anthropomorphism of gods Heraclitus who was notoriously difficult to understand is known for his maxim on impermanence ta panta rhei and for attributing fire to be the arche of the world Pythagoras created a cult like following that advocated that the universe was made up of numbers The Eleatic school Parmenides Zeno of Elea and Melissus followed in the 5th century BCE Parmenides claimed that only one thing exists and nothing can change Zeno and Melissus mainly defended Parmenides opinion Anaxagoras and Empedocles offered a pluralistic account of how the universe was created Leucippus and Democritus are known for their atomism and their views that only void and matter exist The Sophists advanced critical thinking and philosophical relativism The impact of the pre Socratics has been enormous The pre Socratics invented some of the central concepts of Western civilization such as naturalism and rationalism and paved the way for scientific methodology Contents 1 Terminology 2 Sources 3 Historical background 4 General features 5 Pre Socratic philosophers 5 1 Milesian beginning Thales Anaximander and Anaximenes 5 1 1 Thales 5 1 2 Anaximander 5 1 3 Anaximenes 5 2 Xenophanes 5 3 Heraclitus 5 4 Pythagoreanism 5 5 The Eleatics Parmenides Zeno and Melissus 5 6 The Pluralists Anaxagoras and Empedocles 5 7 Atomists Leucippus and Democritus 5 8 Sophists 5 9 Philolaous of Croton and Diogenes of Apollonia 6 Topics 6 1 Knowledge 6 2 Theology 6 3 Medicine 6 4 Cosmology 6 5 Rationalism observation and the beginning of scientific thought 7 Reception and legacy 7 1 Antiquity 7 2 Modern era 8 References 9 Cited sources 10 Further reading 11 External linksTerminology EditPre Socratic is a term adopted in the 19th century to refer to this group of philosophers It was first used by the German philosopher J A Eberhard as vorsokratische Philosophie in the late 18th century 1 In earlier literature they were referred to as physikoi physicists after physis nature and their activity as physiologoi physical or natural philosophers with this usage arising with Aristotle to differentiate them from theologoi theologians and mythologoi storytellers and bards who conveyed Greek mythology who attributed natural phenomena to the gods 2 The term was coined to highlight a fundamental change in philosophical inquiries between the philosophers who lived before Socrates who were interested in the structure of nature and cosmos i e the universe with the implication that the universe had order to it and Socrates and his successors who were mostly interested in ethics and politics The term comes with drawbacks as several of the pre Socratics were highly interested in ethics and how to live the best life Further the term implies that the pre Socratics are less significant than Socrates or even that they were merely a stage implying teleology to classical era philosophy 3 The term is also chronologically inaccurate as the last of the pre Socratics were contemporaries of Socrates 4 According to James Warren the distinction between the pre Socratic philosophers and philosophers of the classical era is demarcated not so much by Socrates but by geography and what texts survived The shift from the pre Socratic to the classical periods involves a shift from philosophers being dispersed throughout the Greek speaking world to their being concentrated in Athens Further starting in the classical period we have complete surviving texts whereas in the pre Socratic era we have only fragments 5 Scholar Andre Laks distinguishes two traditions of separating pre Socratics from Socratics dating back to the classical era and running through current times The first tradition is the Socratic Ciceronian which uses the content of their philosophical inquires to divide the two groups the pre Socratics were interested in nature whereas Socrates focused on human affairs The other tradition the Platonic Aristotelian emphasizes method as the distinction between the two groups as Socrates moved to a more epistemological approach of studying various concepts 6 Because of the drawbacks of the term pre Socratic early Greek philosophy is also used most commonly in Anglo Saxon literature 7 Sources EditVery few fragments of the works of the pre Socratic philosophers have survived The knowledge we have of the pre Socratics derives from the accounts of later writers such as Plato Aristotle Plutarch Diogenes Laertius Stobaeus and Simplicius and some early Christian theologians especially Clement of Alexandria and Hippolytus of Rome Many of the works are titled Peri Physeos or On Nature a title probably attributed later by other authors 8 These accounts known as testimonia testimonies often come from biased writers Consequently it is sometimes difficult to determine the actual line of argument some pre Socratics used in supporting their views 9 Adding more difficulty to their interpretation is the obscure language they used 10 Plato paraphrased the pre Socratics and showed no interest in accurately representing their views Aristotle was more accurate but saw them under the scope of his philosophy Theophrastus Aristotle s successor wrote an encyclopedic book Opinion of the Physicists that was the standard work about the pre Socratics in ancient times It is now lost but Simplicius relied on it heavily in his accounts 11 In 1903 the German professors H Diels and W Kranz published Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker The Fragments of the pre Socratics which collected all of the known fragments Scholars now use this book to reference the fragments using a coding scheme called Diels Kranz numbering The first two characters of the scheme are DK for Diels and Kranz Next is a number representing a specific philosopher After that is a code regarding whether the fragment is a testimonia coded as A or B if is a direct quote from the philosopher Last is a number assigned to the fragment which may include a decimal to reflect specific lines of a fragment For example DK59B12 3 identifies line 3 of Anaxagoras fragment 12 A similar way of referring to quotes is the system prefixed with LM by Andre Laks and Glenn W Most who edited Early Greek Philosophy in 2016 12 Collectively these fragments are called doxography derived from the latin doxographus derived from the Greek word for opinion doxa 13 Historical background Edit Map of Greek territories and colonies during the Archaic period 800 480 BCE Philosophy emerged in ancient Greece in the 6th century BCE The pre Socratic era lasted about two centuries during which the expanding Persian Achaemenid Empire was stretching to the west while the Greeks were advancing in trade and sea routes reaching Cyprus and Syria 14 The first pre Socratics lived in Ionia on the western coast of Anatolia Persians conquered the towns of Ionia c 540 BCE and Persian tyrants then ruled them The Greeks revolted in 499 BCE but ultimately were defeated in 494 BCE 15 Slowly but steadily Athens became the philosophical center of Greece by the middle of the fifth century 16 Athens was entering its Classical Era with philosophers such as Socrates Plato and Aristotle but the impact of the pre Socratics continued 17 Several factors contributed to the birth of pre Socratic philosophy in Ancient Greece Ionian towns especially Miletus had close trade relations with Egypt and Mesopotamia cultures with observations about the natural world that differed from those of the Greeks 18 Apart from technical skills and cultural influences of paramount significance was that the Greeks acquired the alphabet c 800 BCE 19 Another factor was the ease and frequency of intra Greek travel which led to the blending and comparison of ideas During the sixth century BCE various philosophers and other thinkers moved easily around Greece especially visiting pan Hellenic festivals While long distance communication was difficult during ancient times persons philosophers and books moved through other parts of the Greek peninsula the Aegean islands and Magna Graecia a coastal area in Southern Italy 20 The democratic political system of independent poleis also contributed to the rise of philosophy Most Greek towns were not ruled by autocrats or priests allowing citizens to question freely a wide range of issues 21 Various poleis flourished and became wealthy especially Miletus which was a centre of trade and production during the early phases of pre Socratic philosophy Trade of grain oil wine and other commodities among each polis and colonies meant these towns were not isolated but embedded and economically dependent on a complex and changeable web of trade routes 22 Greek mythology also influenced the birth of philosophy The philosophers ideas were to a certain extent answers to questions that were subtly present in the work of Homer and Hesiod 23 The pre Socratics arose from a world dominated by myths sacred places and local deities The work of epic poets such as Homer Hesiod and others reflected this environment They are considered predecessors of the pre Socratics since they seek to address the origin of the world and to organize traditional folklore and legends systematically However their answers were rather simplistic and resisted naturalistic explanations hence they were far from being named as philosophers Greek popular religion contained many features of the religions of neighboring civilizations such as the Egyptians Mesopotamians and Hittites The first pre Socratic philosophers also traveled extensively to other lands meaning that pre Socratic thought had roots abroad as well as domestically 24 Homer in his two epic poems not only personifies gods and other natural phenomena such as the Night but he hints at some views on the origin and the nature of the world that came under scrutiny by the pre Socratics 25 In his epic poem Theogony literally meaning the birth of gods Hesiod c 700 BCE describes the origin of gods and apart from the solid mythical structure one can notice an attempt towards organizing beliefs using some form of rationalization an example would be that Night gives birth to Death Sleep and Dreams 26 Transmigration of life a belief of the Orphics a religious cult originating from Thrace had affected the thought of the 5th century BCE but the overall influence of their cosmology on philosophy is disputed 27 Pherecydes a poet magician and contemporary of Thales in his book describes a particular cosmogony asserting that three gods pre existed a step towards rationality 28 General features EditList of major pre Socratic philosophers and when they flourished according to Catherine Osborne 29 Philosophers Flourished year BCE Thales 585Anaximander 550Anaximenes 545Pythagoras 530Xenophanes 530Heraclitus 500Parmenides 500Zenon 450Anaxagoras 450Empedocles 445Melissus 440Protagoras 440Leukippus 435Gorgias 430Antiphon 430Democritus 420Philolaus 420Socrates 420Plato 380Aristotle 350The most important feature of pre Socratic philosophy was the use of reason to explain the universe The pre Socratic philosophers shared the intuition that there was a single explanation that could explain both the plurality and the singularity of the whole and that explanation would not be direct actions of the gods 30 The pre Socratic philosophers rejected traditional mythological explanations of the phenomena they saw around them in favor of more rational explanations initiating analytic and critical thought Their efforts were directed at the investigation of the ultimate basis and essential nature of the external world Many sought the material principle arche of things and the method of their origin and disappearance 31 They emphasized the rational unity of things and rejected supernatural explanations seeking natural principles at work in the world and human society The pre Socratics saw the world as a cosmos an ordered arrangement that could be understood via rational inquiry 32 In their effort to make sense of the cosmos they coined new terms and concepts such as rhythm symmetry analogy deductionism reductionism mathematicazion of nature and others 33 An important term that is met in the thought of several pre Socratic philosophers is arche Depending on the context it can take various related meanings It could mean the beginning or origin with the undertone that there is an effect on the things to follow Also it might mean a principle or a cause especially in Aristotelian tradition 34 A common feature of the pre Socratics is the absence of empiricism and experimentation in order to prove their theories This may have been because of a lack of instruments or because of a tendency to view the world as a unity undeconstructable so it would be impossible for an external eye to observe tiny fractions of nature under experimental control 35 According to Jonathan Barnes a professor of ancient philosophy pre Socratic philosophy exhibits three significant features they were internal systematic and economical Internal meaning they tried to explain the world with characteristics found within this world Systematic because they tried to universalize their findings Economical because they tried to invoke only a few new terms Based on these features they reached their most significant achievement they changed the course of human thought from myth to philosophy and science 36 The pre Socratics were not atheists however they minimized the extent of the gods involvement in natural phenomena such as thunder or totally eliminated the gods from the natural world 37 Pre Socratic philosophy encompasses the first of the three phases of ancient Greek philosophy which spanned around a thousand years The pre Socratic phase itself is divided into three phases The first phase of pre Socratic philosophy mainly the Milesians Xenophanes and Heraclitus consisted of rejecting traditional cosmogony and attempting to explain nature based on empirical observations and interpretations 38 A second phase that of the Eleatics resisted the idea that change or motion can happen Based on their radical monism they believed that only one substance exists and forms Kosmos 39 The Eleatics were also monists believing that only one thing exists and everything else is just a transformation of it 39 In the third phase the post Eleatics mainly Empedocles Anaxagoras and Democritus opposed most Eleatic teaching and returned to the naturalism of the Milesians 40 The pre Socratics were succeeded by the second phase of ancient philosophy where the philosophical movements of Platonism Cynicism Cyrenaicism Aristotelianism Pyrrhonism Epicureanism Academic skepticism and Stoicism rose to prominence until 100 BCE In the third phase philosophers studied their predecessors 41 Pre Socratic philosophers EditMilesian beginning Thales Anaximander and Anaximenes Edit The Milesian school was located in Miletus Ionia in the 6th century BCE It consisted of Thales Anaximander and Anaximenes who most probably had a teacher pupil relationship They were mainly occupied with the origin and substance of the world each of them attributed the Whole to a single arche beginning or principle starting the tradition of naturalistic monism 42 Thales Edit Main article Thales Thales s theorem if AC is a diameter and B is a point on the diameter s circle the angle ABC is a right angle Thales c 624 546 BCE is considered to be the father of philosophy 43 None of his writings have survived He is considered the first western philosopher since he was the first to use reason to use proof and to generalize He created the word cosmos the first word to describe the universe He contributed to geometry and predicted the eclipse of 585 BCE 44 Thales may have been of Phoenician ancestry 45 Miletus was a meeting point and trade centre of the then great civilizations and Thales visited the neighbouring civilizations Egypt Mesopotamia Crete and Phoenicia 46 In Egypt geometry was advanced as a means of separating agricultural fields Thales though advanced geometry with his abstract deductive reasoning reaching universal generalizations Proclus a later Athenian philosopher attributed the theorem now known as Thales s theorem to Thales He is also known for being the first to claim that the base angles of isosceles triangles are equal and that a diameter bisects the circle 47 Thales visited Sardis as many Greeks then where astronomical records were kept and used astronomical observations for practical matters oil harvesting 48 Thales was widely considered a genius in ancient times 49 and was revered as one of the Seven Sages of Greece 50 Most importantly what marks Thales as the first philosopher is the posing of the fundamental philosophical question about the origin and the substance of the world while providing an answer based on empirical evidence and reasoning He attributed the origin of the world to an element instead of a divine being 51 Our knowledge of Thales claim derives from Aristotle Aristotle while discussing opinions of previous philosophers tells us that Thales the founder of this type of philosophy says the principle arche is water What he meant by arche is a matter of interpretation might be the origin the element or an ontological matrix but regardless of the various interpretations he conceived the world as One thing instead of a collection of various items and speculated on the binding original elements 52 Another important aspect of Thales philosophy is his claim that everything is full of gods What he meant by that is again a matter of interpretation that could be from a theistic view to an atheist one 53 But the most plausible explanation suggested by Aristotle is that Thales is advocating a theory of hylozoism that the universe the sum of all things that exist is divine and alive 54 Lastly another notable claim by Thales is that earth rests on water maybe that was a conclusion after observing fish fossils on land 55 Anaximander Edit Main article Anaximander That from which all things are born the beginning of all things the first foundation of things is the Unlimited apeiron The source from which coming to be is for things that are and for their passing away in accordance with necessity For they give justice and pay retribution to each other for their mutual injustice according to the ordered process of time Anaximander DK 12 B 1 preserved fragment of On Nature 56 Anaximander 610 546 BCE also from Miletus was 25 years younger than Thales He was a member of the elite of Miletus wealthy and a statesman He showed interest in many fields including mathematics and geography He drew the first map of the world was the first to conclude that the earth is spherical and made instruments to mark time something like a clock 57 In response to Thales he postulated as the first principle an undefined unlimited substance without qualities apeiron out of which the primary opposites hot and cold moist and dry became differentiated His answer was an attempt to explain observable changes by attributing them to a single source that transforms to various elements Like Thales he provided a naturalistic explanation for phenomena previously given supernatural explanations He is also known for speculating on the origin of mankind He proclaimed that the earth is not situated in another structure but lies unsupported in the middle of the universe Further he developed a rudimentary evolutionary explanation for biodiversity in which constant universal powers affected the lives of animals 58 According to Giorgio de Santillana a philosophy professor at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology Anaximander s conception of a universe governed by laws shaped the philosophical thinking of centuries to come and was as important as the discovery of fire or Einstein s breakthroughs in science 59 Anaximenes Edit Main article Anaximenes of Miletus Little is known of Anaximenes 585 525 BCE life He was a younger contemporary and friend of Anaximander and the two worked together on various intellectual projects He also wrote a book on nature in prose Anaximenes took for his principle aer air conceiving it as being modified via thickening and thinning into the other classical elements fire wind clouds water and earth While his theory resembled that of Anaximander as they both claimed a single source of the universe Anaximenes suggested sophisticated mechanisms in which air is transformed to other elements mainly because of changes of density Since the classical era he was considered the father of naturalistic explanations Anaximenes expanded Anaximander s attempt to find a unitary cause explaining natural phenomena both living and nonliving without according to James Warren having to reduce living things in some way to mere locations of material change 60 Xenophanes Edit Main article Xenophanes St Elmo s fire luminous plasma created by a corona discharge from a rod like object in a ship Xenophanes contemporaries attributed this phenomenon to the deity Dioscuri Xenophanes argued that the observed illumination is due to small clouds influenced by special circumstances relating to stars an example of naturalism and reductionism 61 Xenophanes was born in Colophon an Ionian town near Miletus He was a well traveled poet whose primary interests were theology and epistemology Concerning theology he pointed out that we did not know whether there was one god or many gods or in such case whether there was a hierarchy among them To critique the anthropomorphic representation of the gods by his contemporary Greeks he pointed out that different nations depicted their gods as looking like themselves He famously said that if oxen horses or lions could draw they would draw their gods as oxen horses or lions This critique was not limited to the looks of gods but also their behaviour Greek mythology mostly shaped by the poets Homer and Hesiod attributed moral failures such as jealously and adultery to the gods Xenophanes opposed this He thought gods must be morally superior to humans Xenophanes however never claimed the gods were omnipotent omnibenevolent or omniscient 62 Xenophanes also offered naturalistic explanations for phenomena such as the sun the rainbow and St Elmo s fire Traditionally these were attributed to divine intervention but according to Xenophanes they were actually effects of clouds These explanations of Xenophanes indicate empiricism in his thought and might constitute a kind of proto scientism Scholars have overlooked his cosmology and naturalism since Aristotle maybe due to Xenophanes lack of teleology until recently but current literature suggests otherwise 63 Concerning epistemology Xenophanes questioned the validity of human knowledge Humans usually tend to assert their beliefs are real and represent truth While Xenophanes was a pessimist about the capability of humans to reach knowledge he also believed in gradual progress through critical thinking Xenophanes tried to find naturalistic explanations for meteorological and cosmological phenomena 64 Ancient philosophy historian Alexander Mourelatos notes Xenophanes used a pattern of thought that is still in use by modern metaphysics Xenophanes by reducing meteorological phenomena to clouds created an argument that X in reality is Y for example B32 What they call Iris the rainbow that too is in reality a cloud one that appears to the eye as purple red and green This is still use d today lightning is massive electrical discharge or items such as tables are a cloud of micro particles Mourelatos comments that the type of analogy that the cloud analogy is remains present in scientific language and is the modern philosopher s favourite subject for illustrations of inter theoretic identity 65 According to Aristotle and Diogenes Laertius Xenophanes was Parmenides teacher but is a matter of debate in current literature whether Xenophanes should also be considered an Eleatic 39 Heraclitus Edit Main article Heraclitus The hallmark of Heraclitus philosophy is flux In fragment DK B30 Heraclitus writes This world order Kosmos the same of all no god nor man did create but it ever was and is and will be everliving fire kindling in measures and being quenched in measures Heraclitus posited that all things in nature are in a state of perpetual flux Like previous monist philosophers Heraclitus claimed that the arche of the world was fire which was subject to change that makes him a materialist monist 66 From fire all things originate and all things return to it again in a process of eternal cycles Fire becomes water and earth and vice versa These everlasting modifications explain his view that the cosmos was and is and will be 66 The idea of continual flux is also met in the river fragments There Heraclitus claims we can not step into the same river twice a position summarized with the slogan ta panta rhei everything flows One fragment reads Into the same rivers we both step and do not step we both are and are not DK 22 B49a Heraclitus is seemingly suggesting that not only the river is constantly changing but we do as well even hinting at existential questions about humankind 67 Another key concept of Heraclitus is that opposites somehow mirror each other a doctrine called unity of opposites Two fragments relating to this concept state As the same thing in us is living and dead waking and sleeping young and old For these things having changed around are those and those in turn having changed around are these B88 and Cold things warm up the hot cools off wet becomes dry dry becomes wet B126 68 Heraclitus doctrine on the unity of opposites suggests that unity of the world and its various parts is kept through the tension produced by the opposites Furthermore each polar substance contains its opposite in a continual circular exchange and motion that results in the stability of the cosmos 69 Another of Heraclitus famous axioms highlights this doctrine B53 War is father of all and king of all and some he manifested as gods some as men some he made slaves some free where war means the creative tension that brings things into existence 70 A fundamental idea in Heraclitus is logos an ancient Greek word with a variety of meanings Heraclitus might have used a different meaning of the word with each usage in his book Logos seems like a universal law that unites the cosmos according to a fragment Listening not to me but to the logos it is wise to agree homologein that all things are one DK 22 B50 While logos is everywhere very few people are familiar with it B 19 reads hoi polloi do not know how to listen to Logos or how to speak the truth 71 Heraclitus thought on logos influenced the Stoics who referred to him to support their belief that rational law governs the universe 72 Pythagoreanism Edit Main article Pythagoras See also Pythagoreanism Pythagoras Pythagoras 582 496 BCE was born on Samos a small island near Miletus He moved to Croton at about age 30 where he established his school and acquired political influence Some decades later he had to flee Croton and relocate to Metapontum 73 Pythagoras was famous for studying numbers and the geometrical relations of numbers A large following of Pythagoreans adopted and extended his doctrine They advanced his ideas reaching the claim that everything consists of numbers the universe is made by numbers and everything is a reflection of analogies and geometrical relations 74 Numbers music and philosophy all interlinked could comfort the beauty seeking human soul and hence Pythagoreans espoused the study of mathematics 75 Pythagorianism perceived the world as perfect harmony dependent on number and aimed at inducing humankind likewise to lead a harmonious life including ritual and dietary recommendations 76 Their way of life was ascetic restraining themselves from various pleasures and food They were vegetarians and placed enormous value on friendship 77 Pythagoras politically was an advocate of a form of aristocracy a position which later Pythagoreans rejected but generally they were reactionary and notably repressed women 78 Other pre Socratic philosophers mocked Pythagoras for his belief in reincarnation 79 Notable Pythagorians included Philolaus 470 380 BCE Alcmaeon of Croton Archytas 428 347 BCE and Echphantus 80 The most notable was Alcmaeon a medical and philosophical writer Alcmaeon noticed that most organs in the body come in pairs and suggested that human health depends on harmony between opposites hot cold dry wet and illness is due to an imbalance of them He was the first to think of the brain as the center of senses and thinking Philolaus advanced cosmology through his discovery of heliocentricism the idea that the Sun lies in the middle of the earth s orbit and other planets 81 Pythagoreanism influenced later Christian currents as Neoplatonism and its pedagogical methods were adapted by Plato 82 Furthermore there seems to be a continuity in some aspects of Plato s philosophy As Prof Carl Huffman notes Plato had a tendency to invoke mathematics in explaining natural phenomena and he also believed in the immortality even divinity of the human soul 83 The Eleatics Parmenides Zeno and Melissus Edit Main article Eleatic school The Eleatic school is named after Elea an ancient Greek town on the southern Italian Peninsula Parmenides is considered the founder of the school Other eminent Eleatics include Zeno of Elea and Melissus of Samos According to Aristotle and Diogenes Laertius Xenophanes was Parmenides teacher and it is debated whether Xenophanes should also be considered an Eleatic 39 Parmenides was born in Elea to a wealthy family around 515 BCE 84 Parmenides of Elea was interested in many fields such as biology and astronomy He was the first to deduce that the earth is spherical 85 He was also involved in his town s political life 86 According to Parmenides Being what exists is like the mass of a perfect sphere undifferentiated indivisible and unchangeable 87 Parmenides contributions were paramount not only to ancient philosophy but to all of western metaphysics and ontology 86 Parmenides wrote a hard to interpret poem named On Nature or On What is that substantially influenced later Greek philosophy 88 Only 150 fragments of this poem survive 89 It tells a story of a young man kouros in ancient Greek dedicated to finding the truth carried by a goddess on a long journey to the heavens The poem consists of three parts the proem i e preface the Way of Truth and the Way of Opinion Very few pieces from the Way of Opinion survive In that part Parmenides must have been dealing with cosmology judging from other authors references 90 The Way of Truth was then and is still today considered of much more importance In the Way of Truth the goddess criticizes the logic of people who do not distinguish the real from the non existent What is and What is Not In this poem Parmenides unfolds his philosophy that all things are One and therefore nothing can be changed or altered Hence all the things that we think to be true even ourselves are false representations 91 What is according to Parmenides is a physical sphere that is unborn unchanged and infinite 92 This is a monist vision of the world far more radical than that of Heraclitus 93 The goddess teaches Kouros to use his reasoning to understand whether various claims are true or false discarding senses as fallacious 94 Other fundamental issues raised by Parmenides poem are the doctrine that nothing comes from nothing 95 and the unity of being and thinking As quoted by DK fragment 3 To gar auto noein estin te kai einai For to think and to be is one and the same 96 Zeno and Melissus continued Parmenides thought on cosmology 97 Zeno is mostly known for his paradoxes i e self contradictory statements which served as proofs that Parmenides monism was valid and that pluralism was invalid The most common theme of those paradoxes involved traveling a distance but since that distance comprises infinite points the traveler could never accomplish it His most famous is the Achilles paradox which is mentioned by Aristotelis The second is called the Achilles and says that the slowest runner will never be caught by the fastest because it is necessary for the pursuer first to arrive at the point from which the pursued set off so it is necessary that the slower will always be a little ahead Aristotle Phys 239b14 18 DK 29 A26 98 Melissus defended and advanced Parmenides theory using prose without invoking divinity or mythical figures He tried to explain why we think various non existent objects exist 99 The Eleatics focus on Being through means of logic initiated the philosophical discipline of ontology Other philosophers influenced by the Eleatics such as the Sophists Plato and Aristotle further advanced logic argumentation mathematics and especially elenchos proof The Sophists even placed Being under the scrutiny of elenchos Because of the Eleatics reasoning was acquiring a formal method 100 The Pluralists Anaxagoras and Empedocles Edit The Death of Empedocles by Salvator Rosa Legend holds that Empedocles committed suicide by falling into Mount Etna s volcano 101 The Pluralist school marked a return to Milesian natural philosophy though much more refined because of Eleatic criticism 102 Anaxagoras was born in Ionia but was the first major philosopher to emigrate to Athens He was soon associated with the Athenian statesman Pericles and probably due to this association was accused by a political opponent of Pericles for impiety as Anaxagoras held that the sun was not associated with divinity it was merely a huge burning stone Pericles helped Anaxagoras flee Athens and return to Ionia 103 Anaxagoras was also a major influence on Socrates 104 Anaxagoras is known for his theory of everything 105 He claimed that in everything there is a share of everything Interpretations differ as to what he meant Anaxagoras was trying to stay true to the Eleatic principle of the everlasting What is while also explaining the diversity of the natural world 106 Anaxagoras accepted Parmenides doctrine that everything that exists What is has existed forever but contrary to the Eleatics he added the ideas of panspermia and nous All objects were mixtures of various elements such as air water and others One special element was nous i e mind which is present in living things and causes motion According to Anaxagoras Nous was one of the elements that make up the cosmos Things that had nous were alive According to Anaxagoras all things are composites of some basic elements although it is not clear what these elements are 107 All objects are a mixture of these building blocks and have a portion of each element except nous Nous was also considered a building block of the cosmos but it exists only in living objects Anaxagoras writes In everything there is a portion moira of everything except mind nous but there are some things in which mind too is present 108 Nous was not just an element of things somehow it was the cause of setting the universe into motion Anaxagoras advanced Milesian thought on epistemology striving to establish an explanation that could be valid for all natural phenomena Influenced by the Eleatics he also furthered the exploration of metatheoretical questions such as the nature of knowledge 106 Empedocles was born in Akragas a town in the southern Italian peninsula According to Diogenes Laertius Empedocles wrote two books in the form of poems Peri Physeos On nature and the Katharmoi Purifications Some contemporary scholars argue these books might be one all agree that interpreting Empedocles is difficult 109 On cosmological issues Empedocles takes from the Eleatic school the idea that the universe is unborn has always been and always will be He also continues Anaxagoras thought on the four roots i e classical elements that by intermixing they create all things around us These roots are fire air earth and water Crucially he adds two more components the immaterial forces of love and strife These two forces are opposite and by acting upon the material of the four roots unite in harmony or tear apart the four roots with the resulting mixture being all things that exist Empedocles uses an analogy of how this is possible as a painter uses a few basic colors to create a painting the same happens with the four roots It is not quite clear if love and strife co operate or have a greater plan but love and strife are in a continual cycle that generates life and the earth we live in 110 Other beings apart from the four roots and love and strife according to Empedocles Purifications are mortals gods and daemons 111 Like Pythagoras Empedocles believed in the soul s transmigration and was vegetarian 112 Atomists Leucippus and Democritus Edit Main article Atomism Democritus by Hendrick ter Brugghen 1628 Democritus was known as the laughing philosopher 113 Leucippus and Democritus both lived in Abdera in Thrace They are most famous for their atomic cosmology even though their thought included many other fields of philosophy such as ethics mathematics aesthetics politics and even embryology 114 The atomic theory of Leucippus and Democritus was a response to the Eleatic school who held that motion is not possible because everything is occupied with What is Democritus and Leucippus reverted the Eleatic axiom claiming that since motions exist What is not must also exist hence void exists Democritus and Leucippus were skeptics regarding the reliability of our senses but they were confident that motion exists 115 Atoms according to Democritus and Leucippus had some characteristics of the Eleatic What is they were homogeneous and indivisible These characteristics allowed answers to Zeno s paradoxes 116 Atoms move within the void interact with each other and form the plurality of the world we live in in a purely mechanical manner 117 One conclusion of the Atomists was determinism the philosophical view that all events are determined completely by previously existing causes As Leucippus said DK 67 B2 Nothing comes to be random but everything is by reason and out of necessity 118 Democritus concluded that since everything is atoms and void several of our senses are not real but conventional Color for example is not a property of atoms hence our perception of color is a convention As Democritus said DK 68 B9 By convention sweet by convention bitter by convention hot by convention cold by convention colour in reality atoms and void 119 This can be interpreted in two ways According to James Warren there is an eliminativist interpretation such that Democritus means that color is not real and there is a relativist interpretation such that Democritus means that color and taste are not real but are perceived as such by our senses through sensory interaction 120 Sophists Edit Main article Sophism The sophists were a philosophical and educational movement that flourished in ancient Greece before Socrates They attacked traditional thinking from gods to morality paving the way for further advances of philosophy and other disciplines such as drama social sciences mathematics and history 121 Plato disparaged the sophists causing long lasting harm to their reputation Plato thought philosophy should be reserved for those who had the appropriate intellect to understand it whereas the sophists would teach anyone who would pay tuition 122 The sophists taught rhetoric and how to address issues from multiple viewpoints Since the sophists and their pupils were persuasive speakers at court or in public they were accused of moral and epistemological relativism 123 which indeed some sophists appeared to advocate Prominent sophists include Protagoras Gorgias Hippias Thrasymachus Prodicus Callicles Antiphon and Critias 124 Protagoras is mostly known for two of his quotes One is that humans are the measure of all things of things that are that they are of things that are not that they are not which is commonly interpreted as affirming philosophical relativism but it can also be interpreted as claiming that knowledge is only relevant to humankind that moral rightness and other forms of knowledge are relevant to and limited to human mind and perception The other quote is Concerning the gods I cannot ascertain whether they exist or whether they do not or what form they have for there are many obstacles to knowing including the obscurity of the question and the brevity of human life 125 Gorgias wrote a book named On Nature in which he attacked the Eleatics concepts of What is and What is not He claimed it is absurd to hold that nonexistence exists and that What is was impossible since it had to either be generated or be unlimited and neither is sufficient There is an ongoing debate among modern scholars whether he was a serious thinker a precursor of extreme relativism and skepticism or merely a charlatan 126 Antiphon placed natural law against the law of the city One need not obey the city s laws as long as one will not get caught One could argue that Antiphon was a careful hedonist rejecting dangerous pleasures 127 Philolaous of Croton and Diogenes of Apollonia Edit Philolaus of Croton and Diogenes of Apollonia from Thrace born c 460 BCE are considered the last generation of pre Socratics Rather than advancing a cosmological perspective on how our universe is constructed they are mostly noted for advancing abstract thinking and argumentation 128 Pythagorianism Anaxagoras and Empedocles influenced Philolaus He attempted to explain both the variety and unity of the cosmos He addressed the need to explain how the various masses of the universe interact among them and coined the term Harmonia a binding force that allows mass to take shape The structure of the cosmos consisted of apeira unlimiteds and perainonta limiters 129 Diogenes of Apollonia returned to Milesian monism but with a rather more elegant thought As he says in DK64 B2 It seems to me overall that all things are alterations of the same things and are the same thing He explains that things even when changing shapes remain ontologically the same 130 Topics EditKnowledge Edit The mythologoi Homer and Hesiod along with other poets centuries before the pre Socratics thought that true knowledge was exclusive to the divine But starting with Xenophanes the pre Socratics moved towards a more secular approach to knowledge 131 The pre Socratics sought a method to understand the cosmos while being aware that there is a limit to human knowledge 132 While Pythagoras and Empedocles linked their self proclaimed wisdom to their divinely inspired status they tried to teach or urge mortals to seek the truth about the natural realm Pythagoras by means of mathematics and geometry and Empedocles by exposure to experiences 133 Xenophanes thought that human knowledge was merely an opinion that cannot be validated or proven to be true According to Jonathan Warren Xenophanes set the outline of the nature of knowledge 134 Later Heraclitus and Parmenides stressed the capability of humans to understand how things stand in nature through direct observation inquiry and reflection 132 Theology Edit Pre Socratic thought contributed to the demythologization of the Greek popular religion The narrative of their thought contributed to shifting the course of ancient Greek philosophy and religion away from the realm of divinity and even paved the way for teleological explanations 135 They attacked the traditional representations of gods that Homer and Hesiod had established and put Greek popular religion under scrutiny initiating the schism between natural philosophy and theology 136 Pre Socratic philosophers did not have atheistic beliefs but it should be kept in mind that being an atheist those days was not without social or legal dangers Despite that arguments rejecting deities were not barred from the public sphere which can be seen in Protagoras s quotation on the gods About the gods I am able to know neither that they exist nor that they do not exist 137 The theological thought starts with the Milesian philosophers It is evident in Anaximander s idea of the apeiron steering everything which had other abilities usually attributed to Zeus 138 Later Xenophanes developed a critique of the anthropomorphism of the gods Xenophanes set three preconditions for God he had to be all good immortal and not resembling humans in appearance which had a major impact on western religious thought 139 The theological thought of Heraclitus and Parmenides is not entirely certain but it is generally accepted that they believed in some kind of divinity The Pythagoreans and Empedocles believed in the transmigration of souls Anaxagoras asserted that cosmic intelligence nous gives life to things Diogenes of Appollonia expanded this line of thinking and might have constructed the first teleological argument it would not be possible without Intellection for it so to be divided up that it has the measures of all things of winter and summer and night and day and rains and winds and fair weather The other things too if one wishes to consider them one would find disposed of in the best possible way 140 While some pre Socratics were trying to find alternatives to divinity others were setting the foundation of explaining the universe in terms of teleology and intelligent design by a divine force 141 Medicine Edit Prior to the pre Socratics health and illness were thought to be governed by gods 142 Pre Socratic philosophy and medicine advanced in parallel with medicine as a part of philosophy and vice versa 143 It was Hippocrates often hailed as the father of medicine who separated but not completely the two domains 144 Physicians incorporated pre Socratic philosophical ideas about the nature of the world in their theoretical framework blurring the border between the two domains An example is the study of epilepsy which in popular religion was thought to be a divine intervention to human life but Hippocrates school attributed it to nature just as Milesian rationalism demythologized other natural phenomena such as earthquakes 145 The systematic study of anatomy physiology and illnesses led to the discovery of cause effect relations and a more sophisticated terminology and understanding of the diseases that ultimately yielded rational science 146 Cosmology Edit The pre Socratics were the first to attempt to provide reductive explanations for a plethora of natural phenomena 147 Firstly they were preoccupied with the mystery of the cosmic matter what was the basic substance of the universe Anaximander suggested apeiron limitless which hints as Aristotle analyzed there is no beginning and no end to it both chronologically and within the space 148 Anaximenes placed aer air as the primary principle probably after realizing the importance of air to life and or the need to explain various observable changes 149 Heraclitus also seeking to address the issue of the ever changing world placed fire as the primary principle of the universe that transforms to water and earth to produce the universe Ever transforming nature is summarized by Heraclitus axiom panta rhei everything is in a state of flux 150 Parmenides suggested two ever lasting primary building blocs night and day which together form the universe 151 Empedocles increased the building blocks to four and named them roots while also adding Love and Strife to serve as the driving force for the roots to mingle 152 Anaxagoras extended even more the plurality of Empedocles claiming everything is in everything myriads of substances were mixing among each other except one Nous mind that orchestrates everything but did not attribute divine characteristics to Nous 153 Leucippus and Democritus asserted the universe consists of atoms and void while the motion of atoms is responsible for the changes we observe 154 Rationalism observation and the beginning of scientific thought Edit The pre Socratic intellectual revolution is widely considered to have been the first step towards liberation of the human mind from the mythical world and initiated a march towards reason and scientific thought that yielded modern western philosophy and science 155 The pre Socratics sought to understand the various aspects of nature by means of rationalism observations and offering explanations that could be deemed as scientific giving birth to what became Western rationalism 156 Thales was the first to seek for a unitary arche of the world Whether arche meant the beginning the origin the main principle or the basic element is unclear but was the first attempt to reduce the explanations of the universe to a single cause based on reason and not guided by any sort of divinity 157 Anaximander offered the principle of sufficient reason 158 a revolutionary argument that would also yield the principle that nothing comes out of nothing 159 Most of pre Socratics seemed indifferent to the concept of teleology especially the Atomists who fiercely rejected the idea 160 According to them the various phenomena were the consequence of the motion of atoms without any purpose 161 Xenophanes also advanced a critique of anthropomorphic religion by highlighting in a rational way the inconsistency of depictions of the gods in Greek popular religion 162 Undoubtedly pre Socratics paved the way towards science but whether what they did could constitute science is a matter of debate 163 Thales had offered the first account of a reduction and a generalization a significant milestone towards scientific thought Other pre Socratics also sought to answer the question of arche offering various answers but the first step towards scientific thought was already taken 157 Philosopher Karl Popper in his seminal work Back to Presocratics 1958 traces the roots of modern science and the West to the early Greek philosophers He writes There can be little doubt that the Greek tradition of philosophical criticism had its main source in Ionia It thus leads the tradition which created the rational or scientific attitude and with it our Western civilization the only civilization which is based upon science though of course not upon science alone Elsewhere in the same study Popper diminishes the significance of the label they should carry as purely semantics There is the most perfect possible continuity of thought between the Presocratics theories and the later developments in physics Whether they are called philosophers or pre scientists or scientists matters very little 164 Other scholars did not share the same view F M Cornford considered the Ionanians as dogmatic speculators due to their lack of empiricism 165 Reception and legacy EditAntiquity Edit The pre Socratics had a direct influence on classical antiquity in many ways The philosophic thought produced by the pre Socratics heavily influenced later philosophers historians and playwrights 166 One line of influence was the Socrato Ciceronian tradition while the other was the Platonic Aristotelian 1 Socrates Xenophon and Cicero were highly influenced by the physiologoi naturalists as they were named in ancient times The naturalists impressed young Socrates and he was interested in the quest for the substance of the cosmos but his interest waned as he became steadily more focused on epistemology virtue and ethics rather than the natural world According to Xenophon the reason was that Socrates believed humans incapable of comprehending the cosmos 167 Plato in the Phaedo claims that Socrates was uneasy with the materialistic approach of the pre Socratics particularly Anaxagoras 168 Cicero analyzed his views on the pre Socratics in his Tusculanae Disputationes as he distinguished the theoretical nature of pre Socratic thought from previous sages who were interested in more practical issues Xenophon like Cicero saw the difference between pre Socratics and Socrates being his interest in human affairs ta anthropina 169 The pre Socratics deeply influenced both Plato and Aristotle 170 Aristotle discussed the pre Socratics in the first book of Metaphysics as an introduction to his own philosophy and the quest for arche 171 He was the first to state that philosophy starts with Thales 172 It is not clear whether Thales talked of water as arche or that was a retrospective interpretation by Aristotle who was examining his predecessors under the scope of his views 173 More crucially Aristotle criticized the pre Socratics for not identifying a purpose as a final cause a fundamental idea in Aristotelian metaphysics 174 Plato also attacked pre Socratic materialism 175 Later during the Hellenistic era philosophers of various currents focused on the study of nature and advanced pre Socratic ideas 176 The Stoics incorporated features from Anaxagoras and Heraclitus such as nous and fire respectively 177 The Epicureans saw Democritus atomism as their predecessor while the Sceptics were linked to Xenophanes 178 Modern era Edit The pre Socratics along with the rest of ancient Greece invented the central concepts of Western civilization freedom democracy individual autonomy and rationalism 179 Francis Bacon a 16th century philosopher known for advancing the scientific method was probably the first philosopher of the modern era to use pre Socratic axioms extensively in his texts He criticized the pre Socratic theory of knowledge by Xenophanes and others claiming that their deductive reasoning could not yield meaningful results an opinion contemporary philosophy of science rejects 180 Bacon s fondness for the pre Socratics especially Democritus atomist theory might have been because of his anti Aristotelianism 181 Friedrich Nietzsche admired the pre Socratics deeply calling them tyrants of the spirit to mark their antithesis and his preference against Socrates and his successors 182 Nietzsche also weaponized pre Socratic antiteleology coupled with the materialism exemplified by Democritus for his attack on Christianity and its morals Nietzsche saw the pre Socratics as the first ancestors of contemporary science linking Empedocles to Darwinism and Heraclitus to physicist Helmholtz 183 According to his narrative limned in many of his books the pre Socratic era was the glorious era of Greece while the so called Golden Age that followed was an age of decay according to Nietzsche Nietzsche incorporated the pre Socratics in his Apollonian and Dionysian dialectics with them representing the creative Dionysian aspect of the duo 184 Martin Heidegger found the roots of his phenomenology and later thinking of Things and the Fourfold 185 in the pre Socratics 186 considering Anaximander Parmenides and Heraclitus as the original thinkers on being which he identified in their work as physis fysis emergence contrasted against kryptes8ai kryptesthai in Heraclitus Fragment 123 187 or aletheia alh8eia truth as unconcealment 188 References Edit a b Laks amp Most 2018 p 1 Most 1999 pp 332 362 Curd 2020 section 1 Who Were the Presocratic Philosophers Barnes 1987 p 10 Warren 2014 pp 1 2 Warren 2014 pp 180 181 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 1 2 12 13 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 29 31 Runia 2008 p 28 Irwin 1999 p 6 Barnes 1987 pp 24 35 Warren 2014 pp 7 9 Barnes 1987 pp 24 25 Waterfield 2000 p ix Kirk amp Raven 1977 pp 3 Warren 2014 p 3 Curd 2020 Introduction Runia 2008 p 35 Curd 2008 p 3 Burkert 2008 pp 55 56 Sandywell 1996 pp 82 83 Warren 2014 pp 18 21 Warren 2014 p 181 Evans 2019 pp 12 14 Barnes 1987 p 14 Laks amp Most 2018 p 53 Burkert 2008 p 55 57 Barnes 1987 pp 10 12 Barnes 1987 p 14 Laks amp Most 2018 p 53 Sandywell 1996 pp 79 80 Barnes 1987 p 16 Kirk amp Raven 1977 pp 8 9 71 72 Barnes 1987 pp 55 59 Waterfield 2000 pp xx xxiv Kirk amp Raven 1977 pp 10 19 Barnes 1987 p 55 Waterfield 2000 p xxii Barnes 1987 pp 56 67 Kirk amp Raven 1977 p 37 39 Kirk amp Raven 1977 pp 70 71 Osborne 2004 p 13 Vamvacas 2009 pp 19 20 Barnes 1987 pp 16 24 Vamvacas 2009 p 27 Curd 2020 Introduction Vamvacas 2009 p 27 Warren 2014 p 25 Sandywell 1996 p 38 Vamvacas 2009 p 20 21 Barnes 1987 pp 16 22 Barnes 1987 pp 16 17 Barnes 1987 pp 36 39 a b c d Warren 2014 p 3 Barnes 1987 pp 39 42 Warren 2014 p 3 Barnes 1987 p 9 Sandywell 1996 pp 75 78 Kirk amp Raven 1977 p 73 Barnes 1987 p 36 Warren 2014 p 23 Sandywell 1996 p 86 Sandywell 1996 p 89 Kirk amp Raven 1977 pp 74 75 Sandywell 1996 p 89 Sandywell 1996 p 87 Sandywell 1996 pp 86 90 Sandywell 1996 p 90 Warren 2014 p 28 Sandywell 1996 p 93 Sandywell 1996 p 90 94 Sandywell 1996 p 94 96 Sandywell 1996 p 97 Sandywell 1996 pp 97 98 Warren 2014 p 27 Sandywell 1996 p 139 Sandywell 1996 pp 136 138 Barnes 1987 pp 36 37 Warren 2014 pp 28 33 Sandywell 1996 p 141 Warren 2014 pp 33 37 Sandywell 1996 pp 172 173 Mourelatos 2008 pp 134 135 Warren 2014 pp 41 50 Mourelatos 2008 pp 134 139 Warren 2014 pp 50 56 Mourelatos 2008 Curd 2020 Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus a b Graham 2008 pp 170 172 Warren 2014 pp 72 74 Graham 2008 p 175 Sandywell 1996 pp 263 265 Graham 2008 pp 175 177 Sandywell 1996 pp 263 265 Curd 2020 Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus Warren 2014 p 63 Sandywell 1996 p 237 Warren 2014 p 63 Barnes 1987 p 81 Sandywell 1996 p 189 Warren 2014 p 39 Sandywell 1996 p 197 Sandywell 1996 p 199 Curd 2020 The Pythagorean Tradition Sandywell 1996 p 192 Curd 2020 The Pythagorean Tradition Sandywell 1996 pp 192 194 Warren 2014 p 38 Curd 2020 The Pythagorean Tradition Sandywell 1996 p 195 Sandywell 1996 pp 196 197 Sandywell 1996 pp 191 192 Huffman 2008 pp 284 285 Barnes 1987 p 129 Sandywell 1996 p 295 Barnes 1987 p 40 a b Sandywell 1996 p 295 Sandywell 1996 pp 309 310 Warren 2014 p 77 Barnes 1987 pp 40 41 Warren 2014 p 79 Warren 2014 pp 79 80 Warren 2014 pp 77 80 Sandywell 1996 p 300 Warren 2014 pp 98 Warren 2014 p 80 Curd 2020 Parmenides of Elea Sandywell 1996 p 312 Sandywell 1996 p 298 Warren 2014 pp 103 104 Warren 2014 p 108 Barnes 1987 pp 148 149 Warren 2014 pp 103 104 Sandywell 1996 pp 349 350 Sandywell 1996 p 356 Warren 2014 p 3 Warren also adds Democritus as a pluralist Warren 2014 p 119 Warren 2014 pp 132 133 Curd 2008 p 230 a b Curd 2008 p 231 Warren 2014 pp 121 122 Warren 2014 p 125 DK 59 B11 6 Primavesi 2008 pp 250 Warren 2014 pp 135 137 Warren 2014 pp 137 141 Vamvacas 2009 pp 169 172 Warren 2014 p 146 Primavesi 2008 p 251 Sandywell 1996 p 380 Warren 2014 pp 153 154 Warren 2014 pp 155 157 Warren 2014 pp 157 161 Warren 2014 p 163 Warren 2014 pp 164 165 Warren 2014 pp 166 167 Warren 2014 p 169 Gagarin amp Woodruff 2008 p 367 Gagarin amp Woodruff 2008 pp 365 367 Graham 2021 The Sophists and Anonymous Sophistic Texts Gagarin amp Woodruff 2008 pp 366 368 Graham 2021 Protagoras Graham 2021 Gorgias Graham 2021 Antiphon Warren 2014 p 179 Warren 2014 pp 175 177 Warren 2014 pp 178 179 Lesher 2008 pp 458 459 a b Lesher 2008 p 476 Lesher 2008 pp 466 468 Warren 2014 pp 51 Robinson 2008 pp 496 497 Robinson 2008 p 497 Sedley 2013 p 140 Robinson 2008 pp 485 487 Robinson 2008 pp 487 488 Robinson 2008 pp 490 492 Robinson 2008 p 496 Longrigg 1989 p 1 2 Van der Eijk 2008 p 385 Van der Eijk 2008 pp 385 386 Van der Eijk 2008 p 387 Longrigg 2013 pp 1 2 Van der Eijk 2008 pp 387 395 399 Longrigg 2013 pp 1 2 Wright 2008 p 414 Wright 2008 p 415 Wright 2008 p 416 Wright 2008 pp 416 417 Wright 2008 p 417 Wright 2008 p 418 Wright 2008 p 419 amp 425 Wright 2008 pp 419 420 Barnes 1987 p 17 Hankinson 2008 pp 453 455 Barnes 1987 p 16 Laks amp Most 2018 p 36 a b Hankinson 2008 pp 435 437 Hankinson 2008 pp 445 Hankinson 2008 pp 446 Hankinson 2008 pp 449 Hankinson 2008 pp 449 450 Hankinson 2008 p 453 Taub 2020 pp 7 9 Vamvacas 2009 pp 19 23 Curd 2008 p 18 19 Barnes 1987 p 14 Palmer 2008 p 534 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 1 8 Palmer 2008 pp 534 554 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 9 11 Palmer 2008 p 548 Frede 2008 p 503 Palmer 2008 p 536 Frede 2008 p 503 Frede 2008 pp 505 522 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 16 Palmer 2008 p 536 Curd 2008 p 40 Palmer 2008 pp 547 548 Curd 2008 p 11 Sandywell 1996 p 6 7 Vamvacas 2009 pp 20 23 McCarthy 1999 pp 183 187 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 21 22 Sandywell 1996 p 7 Laks amp Most 2018 pp 21 22 Sandywell 1996 p 7 Mitchell Andrew 2015 The Fourfold Reading the Late Heidegger Evanston Northwestern University Press ISBN 9780810130760 Curd 2008 pp 19 20 Heidegger Martin 1991 The Principle of Reason Bloomington Indiana University Press ISBN 9780253210661 Sandywell 1996 pp 69 71 Laks amp Most 2018 p 73 Cited sources EditBarnes Jonathan 1987 Early Greek Philosophy Penguin Books ISBN 978 0 14 044461 2 Burkert Walter 27 October 2008 Prehistory of Presocratic Philosophy in an Orientalizing Context In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 55 88 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Curd Patricia 27 October 2008 Anaxagoras and the Theory of Everything In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Curd Patricia 2020 Presocratic Philosophy In Edward N Zalta ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Evans C Stephen 2019 A History of Western Philosophy From the Pre Socratics to Postmodernism InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 7369 2 Frede Michael 27 October 2008 Aristotle s Account of the Origins of Philosophy In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 501 529 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Graham Daniel W 27 October 2008 Heraclitus Flux Order and Knowledge In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 169 187 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Graham Jacob N 2021 Pre Socratic philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Gagarin Michael Woodruff Paul 27 October 2008 The Sophists In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Hankinson R J 27 October 2008 Reason Cause and Explanation in Presocratic Philosophy In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 434 457 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Huffman Carl 27 October 2008 Two Problems in Pythagoreanism In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 284 304 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Kirk Geoffrey Raven J E 1977 The Presocratic Philosophers A Critical History with a Selection of Texts Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 27455 5 Lesher J H 27 October 2008 The humanizing of knowledge in presocratic thought In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 458 484 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Mourelatos Alexander P D 27 October 2008 The Cloud Astrophysics of Xenophanes and Ionian Material Monism In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 134 168 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Irwin Terence 1999 Classical Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 289253 9 Laks Andre Most Glenn 1 January 2018 The Concept of Presocratic Philosophy Its Origin Development and Significance Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 8791 0 Longrigg James 1989 Presocratic Philosophy and Hippocratic Medicine History of Science SAGE Publications 27 1 1 39 Bibcode 1989HisSc 27 1L doi 10 1177 007327538902700101 ISSN 0073 2753 PMID 11621888 S2CID 742356 Longrigg James 7 March 2013 Greek Rational Medicine Philosophy and Medicine from Alcmaeon to the Alexandrians Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 97366 8 McCarthy John C 1999 Bacon s Third Sailing The Pre Socratic Origins of Modern Philosophy In McCoy Joe ed Early Greek Philosophy Reason at the Beginning of Philosophy Washington D C The Catholic University of America Press pp 157 188 ISBN 978 0 19 964465 0 Most Glenn W 28 June 1999 16 The poetics of early Greek philosophy In A A Long ed The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 44667 9 Osborne Catherine 22 April 2004 Presocratic Philosophy A Very Short Introduction OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 284094 3 Palmer John 27 October 2008 Classical Representations and Uses of the Presocratics In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 530 554 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Primavesi Oliver 27 October 2008 Empedocles Physical and Mythical Divinity In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Robinson T M 27 October 2008 Presocratic Theology In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 485 499 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Runia David T 27 October 2008 The sources of pre Socratic philosophy In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 27 54 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Sandywell Barry 1996 Presocratic Reflexivity The Construction of Philosophical Discourse c 600 450 B C Logological Investigations Volume Three Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 85347 2 Sedley David November 2013 The Pre Socratics to the Hellenistic Age In Bullivant Stephen ed The Oxford Handbook of Atheism Michael Ruse OUP Oxford doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199644650 013 002 ISBN 978 0 19 964465 0 Taub Liba 30 January 2020 The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Greek and Roman Science Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 09248 8 Vamvacas Constantine J 28 May 2009 The Founders of Western Thought The Presocratics A diachronic parallelism between Presocratic Thought and Philosophy and the Natural Sciences Springer Science amp Business Media pp 20 ISBN 978 1 4020 9791 1 Van der Eijk Philip 27 October 2008 The Role of Medicine in the Formation of Early Greek Thought In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 385 412 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Warren James 5 December 2014 Presocratics Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 49337 2 Waterfield Robin 7 September 2000 The First Philosophers The Presocratics and Sophists Oxford University Press UK ISBN 978 0 19 282454 7 Wright M R 27 October 2008 Presocratic cosmologies In Curd Patricia ed The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy Daniel W Graham Oxford University Press USA pp 413 432 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Further reading EditCornford F M 1991 From Religion to Philosophy A Study in the Origins of Western Speculation Princeton NJ Princeton University Press Graham D W 2010 The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics 2 vols Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press Furley D J and R E Allen eds 1970 Studies in Presocratic Philosophy Vol 1 The Beginnings of Philosophy London Routledge amp Kegan Paul Jaeger W 1947 The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers Oxford Oxford Univ Press Lloyd G E R Early Greek Science Thales to Aristotle New York Norton 1970 Luchte James 2011 Early Greek Thought Before the Dawn New York Continuum International Publishing Group McKirahan R D 2011 Philosophy Before Socrates Indianapolis IN Hackett Publishing Company Robb K ed 1983 Language and Thought in Early Greek Philosophy La Salle IL Hegeler Institute Stamatellos G 2012 Introduction to Presocratics A Thematic Approach to Early Greek Philosophy with Key Readings Wiley Blackwell Vlastos G 1995 Studies in Greek Philosophy Vol 1 The Presocratics Edited by D W Graham Princeton NJ Princeton Univ Press Vassallo Ch 2021 The Presocratics at Herculaneum A Study of Early Greek Philosophy in the Epicurean Tradition Berlin Boston De Gruyter External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Pre Socratic philosophy Look up Presocratic in Wiktionary the free dictionary Collections Containing Articles on Presocratic Philosophy Pre Socratic philosophy at PhilPapers Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Pre Socratic philosophy amp oldid 1130074958, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.