fbpx
Wikipedia

Epicurus

Epicurus (/ˌɛpɪˈkjʊərəs/, EH-pih-KURE-əs;[2] Greek: Ἐπίκουρος Epikouros; 341–270 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher and sage who founded Epicureanism, a highly influential school of philosophy. He was born on the Greek island of Samos to Athenian parents. Influenced by Democritus, Aristippus, Pyrrho,[3] and possibly the Cynics, he turned against the Platonism of his day and established his own school, known as "the Garden", in Athens. Epicurus and his followers were known for eating simple meals and discussing a wide range of philosophical subjects. He openly allowed women and slaves[4] to join the school as a matter of policy. Of the over 300 works said to have been written by Epicurus about various subjects, the vast majority have been destroyed. Only three letters written by him—the letters to Menoeceus, Pythocles, and Herodotus—and two collections of quotes—the Principal Doctrines and the Vatican Sayings—have survived intact, along with a few fragments of his other writings. As a result of his work's destruction, most knowledge about his philosophy is due to later authors, particularly the biographer Diogenes Laërtius, the Epicurean Roman poet Lucretius and the Epicurean philosopher Philodemus, and with hostile but largely accurate accounts by the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus, and the Academic Skeptic and statesman Cicero.

Epicurus
Roman marble bust of Epicurus
BornFebruary 341 BC
Samos, Greece
Died270 BC (aged about 72)
Athens, Greece
EraHellenistic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolEpicureanism
Main interests
Notable ideas

Attributed:

Epicurus asserted that philosophy's purpose is to attain as well as to help others attain happy (eudaimonic), tranquil lives characterized by ataraxia (peace and freedom from fear) and aponia (the absence of pain). He advocated that people were best able to pursue philosophy by living a self-sufficient life surrounded by friends. He taught that the root of all human neuroses is death denial and the tendency for human beings to assume that death will be horrific and painful, which he claimed causes unnecessary anxiety, selfish self-protective behaviors, and hypocrisy. According to Epicurus, death is the end of both the body and the soul and therefore should not be feared. Epicurus taught that although the gods exist, they have no involvement in human affairs. He taught that people should act ethically not because the gods punish or reward them for their actions but because, due to the power of guilt, amoral behavior would inevitably lead to remorse weighing on their consciences and as a result, they would be prevented from attaining ataraxia.

Epicurus derived much of his physics and cosmology from the earlier philosopher Democritus (c. 460–c. 370 BC). Like Democritus, Epicurus taught that the universe is infinite and eternal and that all matter is made up of extremely tiny, invisible particles known as atoms. All occurrences in the natural world are ultimately the result of atoms moving and interacting in empty space. Epicurus deviated from Democritus by proposing the idea of atomic "swerve", which holds that atoms may deviate from their expected course, thus permitting humans to possess free will in an otherwise deterministic universe.

Though popular, Epicurean teachings were controversial from the beginning. Epicureanism reached the height of its popularity during the late years of the Roman Republic. It died out in late antiquity, subject to hostility from early Christianity. Throughout the Middle Ages Epicurus was popularly, though inaccurately, remembered as a patron of drunkards, whoremongers, and gluttons. His teachings gradually became more widely known in the fifteenth century with the rediscovery of important texts, but his ideas did not become acceptable until the seventeenth century, when the French Catholic priest Pierre Gassendi revived a modified version of them, which was promoted by other writers, including Walter Charleton and Robert Boyle. His influence grew considerably during and after the Enlightenment, profoundly impacting the ideas of major thinkers, including John Locke, Thomas Jefferson, Jeremy Bentham, and Karl Marx.

Life edit

Upbringing and influences edit

class=notpageimage|
Map of Greece showing locations associated with Epicurus

Epicurus was born in the Athenian settlement on the Aegean island of Samos in February 341 BC.[5][6][7] His parents, Neocles and Chaerestrate, were both Athenian-born, and his father was an Athenian citizen.[5] Epicurus grew up during the final years of the Greek Classical Period.[8] Plato had died seven years before Epicurus was born and Epicurus was seven years old when Alexander the Great crossed the Hellespont into Persia.[9] As a child, Epicurus would have received a typical ancient Greek education.[10] As such, according to Norman Wentworth DeWitt, "it is inconceivable that he would have escaped the Platonic training in geometry, dialectic, and rhetoric."[10] Epicurus is known to have studied under the instruction of a Samian Platonist named Pamphilus, probably for about four years.[10] His Letter of Menoeceus and surviving fragments of his other writings strongly suggest that he had extensive training in rhetoric.[10][11] After the death of Alexander the Great, Perdiccas expelled the Athenian settlers on Samos to Colophon, on the coast of what is now Turkey.[12][11] Epicurus joined his family there after the completion of his military service. He studied under Nausiphanes, who followed the teachings of Democritus,[11][12] and later those of Pyrrho,[13][14] whose way of life Epicurus greatly admired.[15]

 
Allocation of key positions and satrapies following the Partition of Babylon in 323 BC after the death of Alexander the Great. Epicurus came of age at a time when Greek intellectual horizons were vastly expanding due to the rise of the Hellenistic Kingdoms across the Near East.[16]

Epicurus's teachings were heavily influenced by those of earlier philosophers, particularly Democritus. Nonetheless, Epicurus differed from his predecessors on several key points of determinism and vehemently denied having been influenced by any previous philosophers, whom he denounced as "confused". Instead, he insisted that he had been "self-taught".[17][18][19] According to DeWitt, Epicurus's teachings also show influences from the contemporary philosophical school of Cynicism.[20] The Cynic philosopher Diogenes of Sinope was still alive when Epicurus would have been in Athens for his required military training and it is possible they may have met.[20] Diogenes's pupil Crates of Thebes (c. 365 – c. 285 BC) was a close contemporary of Epicurus.[20] Epicurus agreed with the Cynics' quest for honesty, but rejected their "insolence and vulgarity", instead teaching that honesty must be coupled with courtesy and kindness.[20] Epicurus shared this view with his contemporary, the comic playwright Menander.[21]

Epicurus's Letter to Menoeceus, possibly an early work of his, is written in an eloquent style similar to that of the Athenian rhetorician Isocrates (436–338 BC),[20] but, for his later works, he seems to have adopted the bald, intellectual style of the mathematician Euclid.[20] Epicurus's epistemology also bears an unacknowledged debt to the later writings of Aristotle (384–322 BC), who rejected the Platonic idea of hypostatic Reason and instead relied on nature and empirical evidence for knowledge about the universe.[16] During Epicurus's formative years, Greek knowledge about the rest of the world was rapidly expanding due to the Hellenization of the Near East and the rise of Hellenistic kingdoms.[16] Epicurus's philosophy was consequently more universal in its outlook than those of his predecessors, since it took cognizance of non-Greek peoples as well as Greeks.[16] He may have had access to the now-lost writings of the historian and ethnographer Megasthenes, who wrote during the reign of Seleucus I Nicator (ruled 305–281 BC).[16]

Teaching career edit

 
Reconstruction by K. Fittschen of an Epicurus enthroned statue, presumably set up after his death. University of Göttingen, Abgußsammlung.[22]

During Epicurus's lifetime, Platonism was the dominant philosophy in higher education.[23] Epicurus's opposition to Platonism formed a large part of his thought.[24][25] Over half of the forty Principal Doctrines of Epicureanism are flat contradictions of Platonism.[24] In around 311 BC, Epicurus, when he was around thirty years old, began teaching in Mytilene.[24][11] Around this time, Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism, arrived in Athens, at the age of about twenty-one, but Zeno did not begin teaching what would become Stoicism for another twenty years.[24] Although later texts, such as the writings of the first-century BC Roman orator Cicero, portray Epicureanism and Stoicism as rivals,[24] this rivalry seems to have only emerged after Epicurus's death.[24][24]

Epicurus's teachings caused strife in Mytilene and he was forced to leave. He then founded a school in Lampsacus before returning to Athens in c. 306 BC, where he remained until his death.[6] There he founded The Garden (κῆπος), a school named for the garden he owned that served as the school's meeting place, about halfway between the locations of two other schools of philosophy, the Stoa and the Academy.[26][11] The Garden was more than just a school;[7] it was "a community of like-minded and aspiring practitioners of a particular way of life."[7] The primary members were Hermarchus, the financier Idomeneus, Leonteus and his wife Themista, the satirist Colotes, the mathematician Polyaenus of Lampsacus, and Metrodorus of Lampsacus, the most famous popularizer of Epicureanism. His school was the first of the ancient Greek philosophical schools to admit women as a rule rather than an exception,[citation needed] and the biography of Epicurus by Diogenes Laërtius lists female students such as Leontion and Nikidion.[27] An inscription on the gate to The Garden is recorded by Seneca the Younger in epistle XXI of Epistulae morales ad Lucilium: "Stranger, here you will do well to tarry; here our highest good is pleasure."[28]

According to Diskin Clay, Epicurus himself established a custom of celebrating his birthday annually with common meals, befitting his stature as heros ktistes ("founding hero") of the Garden. He ordained in his will annual memorial feasts for himself on the same date (10th of Gamelion month).[29] Epicurean communities continued this tradition,[30] referring to Epicurus as their "saviour" (soter) and celebrating him as hero. The hero cult of Epicurus may have operated as a Garden variety civic religion.[31] However, clear evidence of an Epicurean hero cult, as well as the cult itself, seems buried by the weight of posthumous philosophical interpretation.[32] Epicurus never married and had no known children. He was most likely a vegetarian.[33][34]

Death edit

Diogenes Laërtius records that, according to Epicurus's successor Hermarchus, Epicurus died a slow and painful death in 270 BC at the age of seventy-two from a stone blockage of his urinary tract.[35][36] Despite being in immense pain, Epicurus is said to have remained cheerful and to have continued to teach until the very end.[35] Possible insights into Epicurus's death may be offered by the extremely brief Epistle to Idomeneus, included by Diogenes Laërtius in Book X of his Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers.[37] The authenticity of this letter is uncertain and it may be a later pro-Epicurean forgery intended to paint an admirable portrait of the philosopher to counter the large number of forged epistles in Epicurus's name portraying him unfavorably.[37]

I have written this letter to you on a happy day to me, which is also the last day of my life. For I have been attacked by a painful inability to urinate, and also dysentery, so violent that nothing can be added to the violence of my sufferings. But the cheerfulness of my mind, which comes from the recollection of all my philosophical contemplation, counterbalances all these afflictions. And I beg you to take care of the children of Metrodorus, in a manner worthy of the devotion shown by the young man to me, and to philosophy.[38]

If authentic, this letter would support the tradition that Epicurus was able to remain joyful to the end, even in the midst of his suffering.[37] It would also indicate that he maintained a special concern for the wellbeing of children.[39]

Philosophy edit

 
Illustration from 1885 of a small bronze bust of Epicurus from Herculaneum. Three Epicurus bronze busts were recovered from the Villa of the Papyri, as well as text fragments.[40]

Epistemology edit

Epicurus and his followers had a well-developed epistemology, which developed as a result of their rivalry with other philosophical schools.[41][42] Epicurus wrote a treatise entitled Κανών, or Rule, in which he explained his methods of investigation and theory of knowledge.[43] This book, however, has not survived,[43] nor does any other text that fully and clearly explains Epicurean epistemology, leaving only mentions of this epistemology by several authors to reconstruct it.[41][42] Epicurus rejected the Platonic idea of "Reason" as a reliable source of knowledge about the world apart from the senses[16] and was bitterly opposed to the Pyrrhonists and Academic Skeptics, who not only questioned the ability of the senses to provide accurate knowledge about the world, but also whether it is even possible to know anything about the world at all.[44]

Epicurus maintained that the senses never deceive humans, but that the senses can be misinterpreted.[45][46] Epicurus held that the purpose of all knowledge is to aid humans in attaining ataraxia.[47][48] He taught that knowledge is learned through experiences rather than innate[49] and that the acceptance of the fundamental truth of the things a person perceives is essential to a person's moral and spiritual health.[50][48] In the Letter to Pythocles, he states, "If a person fights the clear evidence of his senses he will never be able to share in genuine tranquility."[51] Epicurus regarded gut feelings as the ultimate authority on matters of morality and held that whether a person feels an action is right or wrong is a far more cogent guide to whether that act really is right or wrong than abstracts maxims, strict codified rules of ethics, or even reason itself.[52]

Epicurus permitted that any and every statement that is not directly contrary to human perception has the possibility to be true.[53] Nonetheless, anything contrary to a person's experience can be ruled out as false.[54] Epicureans often used analogies to everyday experience to support their argument of so-called "imperceptibles", which included anything that a human being cannot perceive, such as the motion of atoms.[55] In line with this principle of non-contradiction, the Epicureans believed that events in the natural world may have multiple causes that are all equally possible and probable.[56] Lucretius writes in On the Nature of Things, as translated by William Ellery Leonard:

There be, besides, some thing
Of which 'tis not enough one only cause
To state—but rather several, whereof one
Will be the true: lo, if thou shouldst espy
Lying afar some fellow's lifeless corse,
'Twere meet to name all causes of a death,
That cause of his death might thereby be named:
For prove thou mayst he perished not by steel,
By cold, nor even by poison nor disease,
Yet somewhat of this sort hath come to him
We know—And thus we have to say the same
In divers cases.[57]

Epicurus strongly favored naturalistic explanations over theological ones.[58] In his Letter to Pythocles, he offers four different possible natural explanations for thunder, six different possible natural explanations for lightning, three for snow, three for comets, two for rainbows, two for earthquakes, and so on.[59] Although all of these explanations are now known to be false, they were an important step in the history of science, because Epicurus was trying to explain natural phenomena using natural explanations, rather than resorting to inventing elaborate stories about gods and mythic heroes.[59]

Ethics edit

 
Marble relief from the first or second century showing the mythical transgressor Ixion being tortured on a spinning fiery wheel in Tartarus. Epicurus taught that stories of such punishment in the afterlife are ridiculous superstitions and that believing in them prevents people from attaining ataraxia.[60][61]

Epicurus was a hedonist, meaning he taught that what is pleasurable is morally good and what is painful is morally evil.[62][63][64][7] He idiosyncratically defined "pleasure" as the absence of suffering[63][7] and taught that all humans should seek to attain the state of ataraxia, meaning "untroubledness", a state in which the person is completely free from all pain or suffering.[65][66][67] He argued that most of the suffering which human beings experience is caused by the irrational fears of death, divine retribution, and punishment in the afterlife.[60][61] In his Letter to Menoeceus, Epicurus explains that people seek wealth and power on account of these fears, believing that having more money, prestige, or political clout will save them from death.[60][61] He, however, maintains that death is the end of existence, that the terrifying stories of punishment in the afterlife are ridiculous superstitions, and that death is therefore nothing to be feared.[60][61][68] He writes in his Letter to Menoeceus: "Accustom thyself to believe that death is nothing to us, for good and evil imply sentience, and death is the privation of all sentience;... Death, therefore, the most awful of evils, is nothing to us, seeing that, when we are, death is not come, and, when death is come, we are not."[69] From this doctrine arose the Epicurean epitaph: Non fui, fui, non-sum, non-curo ("I was not; I was; I am not; I do not care"), which is inscribed on the gravestones of his followers and seen on many ancient gravestones of the Roman Empire. This quotation is often used today at humanist funerals.[70]

The Tetrapharmakos presents a summary of the key points of Epicurean ethics:[71]

  • Don't fear god
  • Don't worry about death
  • What is good is easy to get
  • What is terrible is easy to endure

Although Epicurus has been commonly misunderstood as an advocate of the rampant pursuit of pleasure, he, in fact, maintained that a person can only be happy and free from suffering by living wisely, soberly, and morally.[63][72][73] He strongly disapproved of raw, excessive sensuality and warned that a person must take into account whether the consequences of his actions will result in suffering,[63][74][64][73] writing, "the pleasant life is produced not by a string of drinking bouts and revelries, nor by the enjoyment of boys and women, nor by fish and the other items on an expensive menu, but by sober reasoning."[63] He also wrote that a single good piece of cheese could be equally pleasing as an entire feast.[64][75] Furthermore, Epicurus taught that "it is not possible to live pleasurably without living sensibly and nobly and justly", because a person who engages in acts of dishonesty or injustice will be "loaded with troubles" on account of his own guilty conscience and will live in constant fear that his wrongdoings will be discovered by others.[63][76][77] A person who is kind and just to others, however, will have no fear and will be more likely to attain ataraxia.[63][76]

Epicurus distinguished between two different types of pleasure: "moving" pleasures (κατὰ κίνησιν ἡδοναί) and "static" pleasures (καταστηματικαὶ ἡδοναί).[78][79] "Moving" pleasures occur when one is in the process of satisfying a desire and involve an active titillation of the senses.[78] After one's desires have been satisfied (e.g. when one is full after eating), the pleasure quickly goes away and the suffering of wanting to fulfill the desire again returns.[78][80] For Epicurus, static pleasures are the best pleasures because moving pleasures are always bound up with pain.[78][80] Epicurus had a low opinion of sex and marriage, regarding both as having dubious value.[81] Instead, he maintained that platonic friendships are essential to living a happy life.[82] One of the Principal Doctrines states, "Of the things wisdom acquires for the blessedness of life as a whole, far the greatest is the possession of friendship."[83][84] He also taught that philosophy is itself a pleasure to engage in.[82] One of the quotes from Epicurus recorded in the Vatican Sayings declares, "In other pursuits, the hard-won fruit comes at the end. But in philosophy, delight keeps pace with knowledge. It is not after the lesson that enjoyment comes: learning and enjoyment happen at the same time."[85][84]

Epicurus distinguishes between three types of desires: natural and necessary, natural but unnecessary, and vain and empty. Natural and necessary desires include the desires for food and shelter. These are easy to satisfy, difficult to eliminate, bring pleasure when satisfied, and are naturally limited. Going beyond these limits produces unnecessary desires, such as the desire for luxury foods. Although food is necessary, luxury food is not necessary. Correspondingly, Epicurus advocates a life of hedonistic moderation by reducing desire, thus eliminating the unhappiness caused by unfulfilled desires. Vain desires include desires for power, wealth, and fame. These are difficult to satisfy because no matter how much one gets, one can always want more. These desires are inculcated by society and by false beliefs about what we need. They are not natural and are to be shunned.[86]

Epicurus' teachings were introduced into medical philosophy and practice by the Epicurean doctor Asclepiades of Bithynia, who was the first physician who introduced Greek medicine in Rome. Asclepiades introduced the friendly, sympathetic, pleasing and painless treatment of patients. He advocated humane treatment of mental disorders, had insane persons freed from confinement and treated them with natural therapy, such as diet and massages. His teachings are surprisingly modern; therefore Asclepiades is considered to be a pioneer physician in psychotherapy, physical therapy and molecular medicine.[87]

Physics edit

Epicurus writes in his Letter to Herodotus (not the historian)[88] that "nothing ever arises from the nonexistent", indicating that all events therefore have causes, regardless of whether those causes are known or unknown.[89] Similarly, he also writes that nothing ever passes away into nothingness, because, "if an object that passes from our view were completely annihilated, everything in the world would have perished, since that into which things were dissipated would be nonexistent."[90] He therefore states: "The totality of things was always just as it is at present and will always remain the same because there is nothing into which it can change, inasmuch as there is nothing outside the totality that could intrude and effect change."[90] Like Democritus before him, Epicurus taught that all matter is entirely made of extremely tiny particles called "atoms" (Greek: ἄτομος; atomos, meaning "indivisible").[91] For Epicurus and his followers, the existence of atoms was a matter of empirical observation;[92] Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius, cites the gradual wearing down of rings from being worn, statues from being kissed, stones from being dripped on by water, and roads from being walked on in On the Nature of Things as evidence for the existence of atoms as tiny, imperceptible particles.[92]

Also like Democritus, Epicurus was a materialist who taught that the only things that exist are atoms and void.[93][11] Void occurs in any place where there are no atoms.[94] Epicurus and his followers believed that atoms and void are both infinite and that the universe is therefore boundless.[95] In On the Nature of Things, Lucretius argues this point using the example of a man throwing a javelin at the theoretical boundary of a finite universe.[96] He states that the javelin must either go past the edge of the universe, in which case it is not really a boundary, or it must be blocked by something and prevented from continuing its path, but, if that happens, then the object blocking it must be outside the confines of the universe.[96] As a result of this belief that the universe and the number of atoms in it are infinite, Epicurus and the Epicureans believed that there must also be infinitely many worlds within the universe.[97]

Epicurus taught that the motion of atoms is constant, eternal, and without beginning or end.[98] He held that there are two kinds of motion: the motion of atoms and the motion of visible objects.[98] Both kinds of motion are real and not illusory.[99] Democritus had described atoms as not only eternally moving, but also eternally flying through space, colliding, coalescing, and separating from each other as necessary.[100] In a rare departure from Democritus's physics, Epicurus posited the idea of atomic "swerve" (παρέγκλισις parénklisis; Latin: clinamen), one of his best-known original ideas.[101][a] According to this idea, atoms, as they are travelling through space, may deviate slightly from the course they would ordinarily be expected to follow.[101] Epicurus's reason for introducing this doctrine was because he wanted to preserve the concepts of free will and ethical responsibility while still maintaining the deterministic physical model of atomism.[102] Lucretius describes it, saying, "It is this slight deviation of primal bodies, at indeterminate times and places, which keeps the mind as such from experiencing an inner compulsion in doing everything it does and from being forced to endure and suffer like a captive in chains."[103]

Epicurus was first to assert human freedom as a result of the fundamental indeterminism in the motion of atoms. This has led some philosophers to think that, for Epicurus, free will was caused directly by chance. In his On the Nature of Things, Lucretius appears to suggest this in the best-known passage on Epicurus' position.[104] In his Letter to Menoeceus, however, Epicurus follows Aristotle and clearly identifies three possible causes: "some things happen of necessity, others by chance, others through our own agency." Aristotle said some things "depend on us" (eph'hemin). Epicurus agreed, and said it is to these last things that praise and blame naturally attach. For Epicurus, the "swerve" of the atoms simply defeated determinism to leave room for autonomous agency.[105]

Theology edit

 
First-century AD Roman fresco from Pompeii, showing the mythical human sacrifice of Iphigenia, daughter of Agamemnon. Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius, cited this myth as an example of the evils of popular religion, in contrast to the more wholesome theology advocated by Epicurus.[106]

In his Letter to Menoeceus, a summary of his own moral and theological teachings, the first piece of advice Epicurus himself gives to his student is: "First, believe that a god is an indestructible and blessed animal, in accordance with the general conception of god commonly held, and do not ascribe to god anything foreign to his indestructibility or repugnant to his blessedness."[107] Epicurus maintained that he and his followers knew that the gods exist because "our knowledge of them is a matter of clear and distinct perception", meaning that people can empirically sense their presences.[108] He did not mean that people can see the gods as physical objects, but rather that they can see visions of the gods sent from the remote regions of interstellar space in which they actually reside.[108] According to George K. Strodach, Epicurus could have easily dispensed of the gods entirely without greatly altering his materialist worldview,[108] but the gods still play one important function in Epicurus's theology as the paragons of moral virtue to be emulated and admired.[108]

Epicurus rejected the conventional Greek view of the gods as anthropomorphic beings who walked the earth like ordinary people, fathered illegitimate offspring with mortals, and pursued personal feuds.[108] Instead, he taught that the gods are morally perfect, but detached and immobile beings who live in the remote regions of interstellar space.[109] In line with these teachings, Epicurus adamantly rejected the idea that deities were involved in human affairs in any way.[107][110] Epicurus maintained that the gods are so utterly perfect and removed from the world that they are incapable of listening to prayers or supplications or doing virtually anything aside from contemplating their own perfections.[109] In his Letter to Herodotus, he specifically denies that the gods have any control over natural phenomena, arguing that this would contradict their fundamental nature, which is perfect, because any kind of worldly involvement would tarnish their perfection.[110] He further warned that believing that the gods control natural phenomena would only mislead people into believing the superstitious view that the gods punish humans for wrongdoing, which only instills fear and prevents people from attaining ataraxia.[110]

Epicurus himself criticizes popular religion in both his Letter to Menoeceus and his Letter to Herodotus, but in a restrained and moderate tone.[111] Later Epicureans mainly followed the same ideas as Epicurus, believing in the existence of the gods, but emphatically rejecting the idea of divine providence.[107] Their criticisms of popular religion, however, are often less gentle than those of Epicurus himself.[112] The Letter to Pythocles, written by a later Epicurean, is dismissive and contemptuous towards popular religion[112] and Epicurus's devoted follower, the Roman poet Lucretius (c. 99 BC – c. 55 BC), passionately assailed popular religion in his philosophical poem On the Nature of Things.[112] In this poem, Lucretius declares that popular religious practices not only do not instill virtue, but rather result in "misdeeds both wicked and ungodly", citing the mythical sacrifice of Iphigenia as an example.[106] Lucretius argues that divine creation and providence are illogical, not because the gods do not exist, but rather because these notions are incompatible with the Epicurean principles of the gods' indestructibility and blessedness.[113][114] The later Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus (c. 160 – c. 210 AD) rejected the teachings of the Epicureans specifically because he regarded them as theological "Dogmaticists".[115]

Epicurean paradox edit

 
The most famous version of the problem of evil is attributed to Epicurus by David Hume (pictured), who was relying on an attribution of it to him by the Christian apologist Lactantius. The trilemma does not occur in any of Epicurus's extant writings, however. If Epicurus did write some version of it, it would have been an argument against divine providence, not the existence of deities.[116]

The Epicurean paradox or riddle of Epicurus or Epicurus' trilemma is a version of the problem of evil. Lactantius attributes this trilemma to Epicurus in De Ira Dei, 13, 20-21:

God, he says, either wishes to take away evils, and is unable; or He is able, and is unwilling; or He is neither willing nor able, or He is both willing and able. If He is willing and is unable, He is feeble, which is not in accordance with the character of God; if He is able and unwilling, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God; if He is neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble, and therefore not God; if He is both willing and able, which alone is suitable to God, from what source then are evils? Or why does He not remove them?

In Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779), David Hume also attributes the argument to Epicurus:

Epicurus’s old questions are yet unanswered. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?

No extant writings of Epicurus contain this argument.[116] However, the vast majority of Epicurus's writings have been lost and it is possible that some form of this argument may have been found in his lost treatise On the Gods, which Diogenes Laërtius describes as one of his greatest works.[116] If Epicurus really did make some form of this argument, it would not have been an argument against the existence of deities, but rather an argument against divine providence.[116] Epicurus's extant writings demonstrate that he did believe in the existence of deities.[107] Furthermore, religion was such an integral part of daily life in Greece during the early Hellenistic Period that it is doubtful anyone during that period could have been an atheist in the modern sense of the word.[107] Instead, the Greek word ἄθεος (átheos), meaning "without a god", was used as a term of abuse, not as an attempt to describe a person's beliefs.[107]

Politics edit

Epicurus promoted an innovative theory of justice as a social contract. Justice, Epicurus said, is an agreement neither to harm nor be harmed, and we need to have such a contract in order to enjoy fully the benefits of living together in a well-ordered society. Laws and punishments are needed to keep misguided fools in line who would otherwise break the contract. But the wise person sees the usefulness of justice, and because of his limited desires, he has no need to engage in the conduct prohibited by the laws in any case. Laws that are useful for promoting happiness are just, but those that are not useful are not just. (Principal Doctrines 31–40)

Epicurus discouraged participation in politics, as doing so leads to perturbation and status seeking. He instead advocated not drawing attention to oneself. This principle is epitomised by the phrase lathe biōsas (λάθε βιώσας), meaning "live in obscurity", "get through life without drawing attention to yourself", i.e., live without pursuing glory or wealth or power, but anonymously, enjoying little things like food, the company of friends, etc. Plutarch elaborated on this theme in his essay Is the Saying "Live in Obscurity" Right? (Εἰ καλῶς εἴρηται τὸ λάθε βιώσας, An recte dictum sit latenter esse vivendum) 1128c; cf. Flavius Philostratus, Vita Apollonii 8.28.12.[117]

Works edit

 
Epicurus, in the Nuremberg Chronicle

Epicurus was an extremely prolific writer.[118][116][61][65] According to Diogenes Laërtius, he wrote around 300 treatises on a variety of subjects.[116][61] Although more original writings of Epicurus have survived to the present day than of any other Hellenistic Greek philosopher,[65] the vast majority of everything he wrote has still been lost,[118][116][61] and most of what is known about Epicurus's teachings come from the writings of his later followers, particularly the Roman poet Lucretius.[61] The only surviving complete works by Epicurus are three relatively lengthy letters, which are quoted in their entirety in Book X of Diogenes Laërtius's Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, and two groups of quotes: the Principal Doctrines (Κύριαι Δόξαι), which are likewise preserved through quotation by Diogenes Laërtius, and the Vatican Sayings, preserved in a manuscript from the Vatican Library that was first discovered in 1888.[61] In the Letter to Herodotus and the Letter to Pythocles, Epicurus summarizes his philosophy on nature and, in the Letter to Menoeceus, he summarizes his moral teachings.[61] Numerous fragments of Epicurus's lost thirty-seven volume treatise On Nature have been found among the charred papyrus fragments at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum.[61][65] Scholars first began attempting to unravel and decipher these scrolls in 1800, but the efforts are painstaking and are still ongoing.[61] According to Diogenes Laertius (10.27-9), the major works of Epicurus include:

  1. On Nature, in 37 books
  2. On Atoms and the Void
  3. On Love
  4. Abridgment of the Arguments employed against the Natural Philosophers
  5. Against the Megarians
  6. Problems
  7. Fundamental Propositions (Kyriai Doxai)
  8. On Choice and Avoidance
  9. On the Chief Good
  10. On the Criterion (the Canon)
  11. Chaeridemus,
  12. On the Gods
  13. On Piety
  14. Hegesianax
  15. Four essays on Lives
  16. Essay on Just Dealing
  17. Neocles
  18. Essay addressed to Themista
  19. The Banquet (Symposium)
  20. Eurylochus
  21. Essay addressed to Metrodorus
  22. Essay on Seeing
  23. Essay on the Angle in an Atom
  24. Essay on Touch
  25. Essay on Fate
  26. Opinions on the Passions
  27. Treatise addressed to Timocrates
  28. Prognostics
  29. Exhortations
  30. On Images
  31. On Perceptions
  32. Aristobulus
  33. Essay on Music (i.e., on music, poetry, and dance)
  34. On Justice and the other Virtues
  35. On Gifts and Gratitude
  36. Polymedes
  37. Timocrates (three books)
  38. Metrodorus (five books)
  39. Antidorus (two books)
  40. Opinions about Diseases and Death, addressed to Mithras
  41. Callistolas
  42. Essay on Kingly Power
  43. Anaximenes
  44. Letters

Legacy edit

Ancient Epicureanism edit

 
Bust of Epicurus leaning against his disciple Metrodorus in the Louvre Museum

Epicureanism was extremely popular from the very beginning.[119][120][121] Diogenes Laërtius records that the number of Epicureans throughout the world exceeded the populations of entire cities.[121] Nonetheless, Epicurus was not universally admired and, within his own lifetime, he was vilified as an ignorant buffoon and egoistic sybarite.[63][122] He remained the most simultaneously admired and despised philosopher in the Mediterranean for the next nearly five centuries.[122] Epicureanism rapidly spread beyond the Greek mainland all across the Mediterranean world.[119] By the first century BC, it had established a strong foothold in Italy.[119] The Roman orator Cicero (106 – 43 BC), who deplored Epicurean ethics, lamented, "the Epicureans have taken Italy by storm."[119]

The overwhelming majority of surviving Greek and Roman sources are vehemently negative towards Epicureanism[123] and, according to Pamela Gordon, they routinely depict Epicurus himself as "monstrous or laughable".[123] Many Romans in particular took a negative view of Epicureanism, seeing its advocacy of the pursuit of voluptas ("pleasure") as contrary to the Roman ideal of virtus ("manly virtue").[124] The Romans therefore often stereotyped Epicurus and his followers as weak and effeminate.[125] Prominent critics of his philosophy include prominent authors such as the Roman Stoic Seneca the Younger (c. 4 BC – AD 65) and the Greek Middle Platonist Plutarch (c. 46 – c. 120), who both derided these stereotypes as immoral and disreputable.[121] Gordon characterizes anti-Epicurean rhetoric as so "heavy-handed" and misrepresentative of Epicurus's actual teachings that they sometimes come across as "comical".[126] In his De vita beata, Seneca states that the "sect of Epicurus... has a bad reputation, and yet it does not deserve it." and compares it to "a man in a dress: your chastity remains, your virility is unimpaired, your body has not submitted sexually, but in your hand is a tympanum."[127]

Epicureanism was a notoriously conservative philosophical school;[6][18][19] although Epicurus's later followers did expand on his philosophy, they dogmatically retained what he himself had originally taught without modifying it.[6][18][19] Epicureans and admirers of Epicureanism revered Epicurus himself as a great teacher of ethics, a savior, and even a god.[128] His image was worn on finger rings, portraits of him were displayed in living rooms, and wealthy followers venerated likenesses of him in marble sculpture.[129] His admirers revered his sayings as divine oracles, carried around copies of his writings, and cherished copies of his letters like the letters of an apostle.[129] On the twentieth day of every month, admirers of his teachings would perform a solemn ritual to honor his memory.[120] At the same time, opponents of his teachings denounced him with vehemence and persistence.[120]

However, in the first and second centuries AD, Epicureanism gradually began to decline as it failed to compete with Stoicism, which had an ethical system more in line with traditional Roman values.[130] Epicureanism also suffered decay in the wake of Christianity, which was also rapidly expanding throughout the Roman Empire.[131] Of all the Greek philosophical schools, Epicureanism was the one most at odds with the new Christian teachings, since Epicureans believed that the soul was mortal, denied the existence of an afterlife, denied that the divine had any active role in human life, and advocated pleasure as the foremost goal of human existence.[131] As such, Christian writers such as Justin Martyr (c. 100–c. 165 AD), Athenagoras of Athens (c. 133–c. 190), Tertullian (c. 155–c. 240), and Clement of Alexandria (c. 150–c. 215), Arnobius (died c. 330), and Lactantius (c. 250-c.325) all singled it out for the most vitriolic criticism.[131]

In spite of this, DeWitt argues that Epicureanism and Christianity share much common language, calling Epicureanism "the first missionary philosophy" and "the first world philosophy".[132] Both Epicureanism and Christianity placed strong emphasis on the importance of love and forgiveness[133] and early Christian portrayals of Jesus are often similar to Epicurean portrayals of Epicurus.[133] DeWitt argues that Epicureanism, in many ways, helped pave the way for the spread of Christianity by "helping to bridge the gap between Greek intellectualism and a religious way of life" and "shunt[ing] the emphasis from the political to the social virtues and offer[ing] what may be called a religion of humanity."[134]

Middle Ages edit

 
Dante Alighieri meets Farinata, an Epicurean from Florence, in his Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell (canto 10). Epicurus and his followers are imprisoned in flaming coffins for the heretical belief that the soul dies with the body,[131] shown here in an illustration by Gustave Doré.

By the early fifth century AD, Epicureanism was virtually extinct.[131] The Christian Church Father Augustine of Hippo (354–430 AD) declared, "its ashes are so cold that not a single spark can be struck from them."[131] While the ideas of Plato and Aristotle could easily be adapted to suit a Christian worldview, the ideas of Epicurus were not nearly as easily amenable.[131] As such, while Plato and Aristotle enjoyed a privileged place in Christian philosophy throughout the Middle Ages, Epicurus was not held in such esteem.[131] Information about Epicurus's teachings was available, through Lucretius's On the Nature of Things, quotations of it found in medieval Latin grammars and florilegia, and encyclopedias, such as Isidore of Seville's Etymologiae (seventh century) and Hrabanus Maurus's De universo (ninth century),[131] but there is little evidence that these teachings were systematically studied or comprehended.[131]

During the Middle Ages, Epicurus was remembered by the educated as a philosopher,[131] but he frequently appeared in popular culture as a gatekeeper to the Garden of Delights, the "proprietor of the kitchen, the tavern, and the brothel."[131] He appears in this guise in Martianus Capella's Marriage of Mercury and Philology (fifth century), John of Salisbury's Policraticus (1159), John Gower's Mirour de l'Omme, and Geoffrey Chaucer's Canterbury Tales.[131] Epicurus and his followers appear in Dante Alighieri's Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell, where they are imprisoned in flaming coffins for having believed that the soul dies with the body.[131]

Renaissance edit

 
Epicurus is shown among other famous philosophers in the Italian Renaissance painter Raphael's School of Athens (1509–1511).[135] Epicurus's genuine busts were unknown prior to 1742, so early modern artists who wanted to depict him were forced to make up their own iconographies.[136]

In 1417, a manuscript-hunter named Poggio Bracciolini discovered a copy of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things in a monastery near Lake Constance.[131] The discovery of this manuscript was met with immense excitement, because scholars were eager to analyze and study the teachings of classical philosophers and this previously-forgotten text contained the most comprehensive account of Epicurus's teachings known in Latin.[131] The first scholarly dissertation on Epicurus, De voluptate (On Pleasure) by the Italian Humanist and Catholic priest Lorenzo Valla was published in 1431.[131] Valla made no mention of Lucretius or his poem.[131] Instead, he presented the treatise as a discussion on the nature of the highest good between an Epicurean, a Stoic, and a Christian.[131] Valla's dialogue ultimately rejects Epicureanism,[131] but, by presenting an Epicurean as a member of the dispute, Valla lent Epicureanism credibility as a philosophy that deserved to be taken seriously.[131]

None of the Quattrocento Humanists ever clearly endorsed Epicureanism,[131] but scholars such as Francesco Zabarella (1360–1417), Francesco Filelfo (1398–1481), Cristoforo Landino (1424–1498), and Leonardo Bruni (c. 1370–1444) did give Epicureanism a fairer analysis than it had traditionally received and provided a less overtly hostile assessment of Epicurus himself.[131] Nonetheless, "Epicureanism" remained a pejorative, synonymous with extreme egoistic pleasure-seeking, rather than a name of a philosophical school.[131] This reputation discouraged orthodox Christian scholars from taking what others might regard as an inappropriately keen interest in Epicurean teachings.[131] Epicureanism did not take hold in Italy, France, or England until the seventeenth century.[137] Even the liberal religious skeptics who might have been expected to take an interest in Epicureanism evidently did not;[137] Étienne Dolet (1509–1546) only mentions Epicurus once in all his writings and François Rabelais (between 1483 and 1494–1553) never mentions him at all.[138] Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) is the exception to this trend, quoting a full 450 lines of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things in his Essays.[138] His interest in Lucretius, however, seems to have been primarily literary and he is ambiguous about his feelings on Lucretius's Epicurean worldview.[138] During the Protestant Reformation, the label "Epicurean" was bandied back and forth as an insult between Protestants and Catholics.[138]

Revival edit

 
The French priest and philosopher Pierre Gassendi is responsible for reviving Epicureanism in modernity as an alternative to Aristotelianism.[138]

In the seventeenth century, the French Catholic priest and scholar Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) sought to dislodge Aristotelianism from its position of the highest dogma by presenting Epicureanism as a better and more rational alternative.[138] In 1647, Gassendi published his book De vita et moribus Epicuri (The Life and Morals of Epicurus), a passionate defense of Epicureanism.[138] In 1649, he published a commentary on Diogenes Laërtius's Life of Epicurus.[138] He left Syntagma philosophicum (Philosophical Compendium), a synthesis of Epicurean doctrines, unfinished at the time of his death in 1655.[138] It was finally published in 1658, after undergoing revision by his editors.[138] Gassendi modified Epicurus's teachings to make them palatable for a Christian audience.[138] For instance, he argued that atoms were not eternal, uncreated, and infinite in number, instead contending that an extremely large but finite number of atoms were created by God at creation.[138]

As a result of Gassendi's modifications, his books were never censored by the Catholic Church.[138] They came to exert profound influence on later writings about Epicurus.[138] Gassendi's version of Epicurus's teachings became popular among some members of English scientific circles.[138] For these scholars, however, Epicurean atomism was merely a starting point for their own idiosyncratic adaptations of it.[138] To orthodox thinkers, Epicureanism was still regarded as immoral and heretical.[138] For instance, Lucy Hutchinson (1620–1681), the first translator of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things into English, railed against Epicurus as "a lunatic dog" who formulated "ridiculous, impious, execrable doctrines".[138]

Epicurus's teachings were made respectable in England by the natural philosopher Walter Charleton (1619–1707), whose first Epicurean work, The Darkness of Atheism Dispelled by the Light of Nature (1652), advanced Epicureanism as a "new" atomism.[138] His next work Physiologia Epicuro-Gassendo-Charletoniana, or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon a Hypothesis of Atoms, Founded by Epicurus, Repaired by Petrus Gassendus, and Augmented by Walter Charleton (1654) emphasized this idea.[138] These works, together with Charleton's Epicurus's Morals (1658), provided the English public with readily available descriptions of Epicurus's philosophy and assured orthodox Christians that Epicureanism was no threat to their beliefs.[138] The Royal Society, chartered in 1662, advanced Epicurean atomism.[139] One of the most prolific defenders of atomism was the chemist Robert Boyle (1627–1691), who argued for it in publications such as The Origins of Forms and Qualities (1666), Experiments, Notes, etc. about the Mechanical Origin and Production of Divers Particular Qualities (1675), and Of the Excellency and Grounds of the Mechanical Hypothesis (1674).[139] By the end of the seventeenth century, Epicurean atomism was widely accepted by members of the English scientific community as the best model for explaining the physical world,[140] but it had been modified so greatly that Epicurus was no longer seen as its original parent.[140]

Enlightenment and after edit

The Anglican bishop Joseph Butler's anti-Epicurean polemics in his Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel (1726) and Analogy of Religion (1736) set the tune for what most orthodox Christians believed about Epicureanism for the remainder of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.[140] Nonetheless, there are a few indications from this time period of Epicurus's improving reputation.[140] Epicureanism was beginning to lose its associations with indiscriminate and insatiable gluttony, which had been characteristic of its reputation ever since antiquity.[140] Instead, the word "epicure" began to refer to a person with extremely refined taste in food.[140][141] Examples of this usage include "Epicurean cooks / sharpen with cloyless sauce his appetite" from William Shakespeare's Antony and Cleopatra (Act II. scene i; c. 1607)[141] and "such an epicure was Potiphar—to please his tooth and pamper his flesh with delicacies" from William Whately's Prototypes (1646).[140]

Around the same time, the Epicurean injunction to "live in obscurity" was beginning to gain popularity as well.[140] In 1685, Sir William Temple (1628–1699) abandoned a promising career as a diplomat and instead retired to his garden, devoting himself to writing essays on Epicurus's moral teachings.[140] That same year, John Dryden translated the celebrated lines from Book II of Lucretius's On the Nature of Things: "'Tis pleasant, safely to behold from shore / The rowling ship, and hear the Tempest roar."[140] Meanwhile, John Locke (1632–1704) adapted Gassendi's modified version of Epicurus's epistemology, which became highly influential on English empiricism.[140] Many thinkers with sympathies towards the Enlightenment endorsed Epicureanism as an admirable moral philosophy.[140] Thomas Jefferson (1743–1826), one of the Founding Fathers of the United States, declared in 1819, "I too am an Epicurean. I consider the genuine (not imputed) doctrines of Epicurus as containing everything rational in moral philosophy which Greece and Rome have left us."[140]

The German philosopher Karl Marx (1818–1883), whose ideas are the basis of Marxism, was profoundly influenced as a young man by the teachings of Epicurus[142][143] and his doctoral thesis was a Hegelian dialectical analysis of the differences between the natural philosophies of Democritus and Epicurus.[144] Marx viewed Democritus as a rationalist skeptic, whose epistemology was inherently contradictory, but saw Epicurus as a dogmatic empiricist, whose worldview is internally consistent and practically applicable.[145] The British poet Alfred Tennyson (1809–1892) praised "the sober majesties / of settled, sweet, Epicurean life" in his 1868 poem "Lucretius".[140] Epicurus's ethical teachings also had an indirect impact on the philosophy of Utilitarianism in England during the nineteenth century.[140] Soviet politician Joseph Stalin (1878–1953) lauded Epicurus by stating: "He was the greatest philosopher of all time. He was the one who recommended practicing virtue to derive the greatest joy from life".[146]

Friedrich Nietzsche once noted: "Even today many educated people think that the victory of Christianity over Greek philosophy is a proof of the superior truth of the former – although in this case it was only the coarser and more violent that conquered the more spiritual and delicate. So far as superior truth is concerned, it is enough to observe that the awakening sciences have allied themselves point by point with the philosophy of Epicurus, but point by point rejected Christianity."[147]

Academic interest in Epicurus and other Hellenistic philosophers increased over the course of the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries, with an unprecedented number of monographs, articles, abstracts, and conference papers being published on the subject.[140] The texts from the library of Philodemus of Gadara in the Villa of the Papyri in Herculaneum, first discovered between 1750 and 1765, are being deciphered, translated, and published by scholars part of the Philodemus Translation Project, funded by the United States National Endowment for the Humanities, and part of the Centro per lo Studio dei Papiri Ercolanesi in Naples.[140] Epicurus's popular appeal among non-scholars is difficult to gauge,[140] but it seems to be relatively comparable to the appeal of more traditionally popular ancient Greek philosophical subjects such as Stoicism, Aristotle, and Plato.[148]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ The only fragment in Greek about this central notion is from the Oenoanda inscription (fr. 54 in Smith's edition). The best known reference is in Lucretius's On the Nature of Things, 2.251.

References edit

  1. ^ Bunnin & Yu (2004). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
  2. ^ Jones, Daniel (2006). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary. 17th edition. Cambridge UP.
  3. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Book IX, Chapter 11, Section 64.
  4. ^ "Diogenes Laertius, Lives and Opinions of the Eminent Philosophers Book X Section 3".
  5. ^ a b Apollodorus of Athens (reported by Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.14–15) gives his birth on the fourth day of the month February in the third year of the 109th Olympiad, in the archonship of Sosigenes
  6. ^ a b c d Barnes 1986, p. 367.
  7. ^ a b c d e Gordon 2012, p. 3.
  8. ^ DeWitt 1954, pp. 8–9.
  9. ^ DeWitt 1954, p. 8.
  10. ^ a b c d DeWitt 1954, p. 12.
  11. ^ a b c d e f Wasson 2016.
  12. ^ a b "Epicurus". Epicurus - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018.
  13. ^ Diogenes Laertius, ix.
  14. ^ Sextus Empiricus, adv. Math. i. 1.
  15. ^ Hicks, Robert Drew. Diogenes Laërtius "Lives of the Eminent Philosophers" Book IX, Chapter 11, Section 61.
  16. ^ a b c d e f DeWitt 1954, p. 10.
  17. ^ Huby, Pamela M. (1978). "Epicurus' Attitude to Democritus". Phronesis. 23 (1): 80–86. doi:10.1163/156852878X00235. JSTOR 4182030.
  18. ^ a b c Erler 2011, p. 9.
  19. ^ a b c Fish & Sanders 2011, pp. 1–2.
  20. ^ a b c d e f DeWitt 1954, p. 9.
  21. ^ DeWitt 1954, pp. 9–10.
  22. ^ Zanker, Paul. The Mask of Socrates: The Image of the Intellectual in Antiquity. III. The Rigors of Thinking. The "Throne" of Epicurus. Berkeley, Calif: University of California Press, 1995.
  23. ^ DeWitt 1954, pp. 9, 11.
  24. ^ a b c d e f g DeWitt 1954, p. 11.
  25. ^ Long 1999, pp. 239–240.
  26. ^ David Konstan (2018). "Epicurus". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  27. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Book X, Section 7
  28. ^ "Epistulae morales ad Lucilium".
  29. ^ D. Smith, Nicholas (2000). Reason and religion in Socratic philosophy. p. 160. ISBN 978-0-19-513322-6.
  30. ^ Glad, Clarence E. (1995). Paul and Philodemus: adaptability in Epicurean and early Christian psychology. p. 176. ISBN 978-90-04-10067-1.
  31. ^ Nussbaum, Martha Craven (2009). The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. p. 119. ISBN 978-0-691-14131-2.
  32. ^ Clay, Diskin (1998). Paradosis and survival: three chapters in the history of Epicurean philosophy. p. 76. ISBN 978-0-472-10896-1.
  33. ^ "The Hidden History of Greco-Roman Vegetarianism". 10 August 2010.
  34. ^ Dombrowski, Daniel A. (1984). The Philosophy of Vegetarianism. University of Massachusetts Press. ISBN 978-0870234316.
  35. ^ a b Bitsori, Maria; Galanakis, Emmanouil (2004). "Epicurus' death". World Journal of Urology. 22 (6): 466–469. doi:10.1007/s00345-004-0448-2. PMID 15372192. S2CID 41741603.
  36. ^ In the second year of the 127th Olympiad, in the archonship of Pytharatus, according to Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.15
  37. ^ a b c Gordon 2012, pp. 141–142.
  38. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 10.22 (trans. C.D. Yonge).
  39. ^ Gordon 2012, p. 142.
  40. ^ Sheila Dillon (2006). Ancient Greek Portrait Sculpture: Contexts, Subjects, and Styles. Cambridge University Press. p. 45. ISBN 9780521854986 – via Google Books.
  41. ^ a b Strodach 2012, p. 26.
  42. ^ a b Asmis 1984, pp. 9–13.
  43. ^ a b Asmis 1984, pp. 10, 19.
  44. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 23.
  45. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 23–24.
  46. ^ Asmis 1984, p. 11.
  47. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 26–27.
  48. ^ a b Asmis 1984, p. 12.
  49. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 27–28.
  50. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 28–29.
  51. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 29.
  52. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 30–31.
  53. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 32–34.
  54. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 34.
  55. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 34–35.
  56. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 35–39.
  57. ^ Carus, Titus Lucretius (July 2008). Of The Nature of Things. Project Gutenberg EBook. Vol. 785. William Ellery Leonard (translator). Project Gutenberg.
    Book VI, Section Extraordinary and Paradoxical Telluric Phenomena, Line 9549–9560
  58. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 36–38.
  59. ^ a b Strodach 2012, p. 38.
  60. ^ a b c d Strodach 2012, pp. 56–58.
  61. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Kenny 2004, p. 94.
  62. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 58.
  63. ^ a b c d e f g h Barnes 1986, p. 372.
  64. ^ a b c Kenny 2004, p. 95.
  65. ^ a b c d Barnes 1986, p. 371.
  66. ^ Folse, Henry (2005). How Epicurean Metaphysics leads to Epicurean Ethics. Department of Philosophy, Loyola University, New Orleans, LA.
  67. ^ Konstan, David (2018). "Epicurus". Epicurus, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/epicurus/>
  68. ^ Gordon 2012, pp. 3–4.
  69. ^ Rosenbaum 2004, p. 175.
  70. ^ "Epicurus (c 341-270 BC)". British Humanist Association.
  71. ^ Hutchinson, D. S. (Introduction) (1994). The Epicurus Reader: Selected Writings and Testimonia. Cambridge: Hackett. p. vi.
  72. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 58–60.
  73. ^ a b Gordon 2012, pp. 5–7.
  74. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 59.
  75. ^ Gordon 2013, p. 141.
  76. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 58–59.
  77. ^ "Epicurus Principal Doctrines 5 and 31 transl. by Robert Drew Hicks". 1925.
  78. ^ a b c d "Epicurus | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  79. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, X:136.
  80. ^ a b Kenny 2004, pp. 95–96.
  81. ^ Gordon 2012, p. 4.
  82. ^ a b Gordon 2012, pp. 4–5.
  83. ^ Epicurus, Principal Doctrines 27
  84. ^ a b Gordon 2012, p. 5.
  85. ^ Epicurus, Vatican Sayings 27
  86. ^ "Epicurus | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  87. ^ C, Yapijakis (2009). "Hippocrates of Kos, the father of clinical medicine, and Asclepiades of Bithynia, the father of molecular medicine. Review". In Vivo. 23 (4): 507–14. PMID 19567383.
  88. ^ Naragon, S. "Letter to Herodotus" (PDF). manchester.edu. Manchester University, Indiana. Retrieved 13 June 2021.
  89. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 8–9.
  90. ^ a b Strodach 2012, p. 10.
  91. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 1–8, 11.
  92. ^ a b Strodach 2012, p. 11.
  93. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 12–13.
  94. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 12.
  95. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 13.
  96. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 13–14.
  97. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 14–15.
  98. ^ a b Strodach 2012, p. 15.
  99. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 15–16.
  100. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 16.
  101. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 16–17.
  102. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 17–18.
  103. ^ Strodach 2012, p. 18.
  104. ^ "On the Nature of Things, 289-293" – via Perseus Project.
  105. ^ "Epicurus page on Information Philosopher; cf. Letter to Menoeceus, §134".
  106. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 46–47.
  107. ^ a b c d e f Hickson 2014, pp. 27.
  108. ^ a b c d e Strodach 2012, p. 39.
  109. ^ a b Strodach 2012, pp. 39–40.
  110. ^ a b c Strodach 2012, pp. 42–43.
  111. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 45–46.
  112. ^ a b c Strodach 2012, p. 46.
  113. ^ Hickson 2014, pp. 27–28.
  114. ^ Strodach 2012, pp. 43–45.
  115. ^ Hickson 2014, p. 28.
  116. ^ a b c d e f g Hickson 2014, pp. 26–27.
  117. ^ "Philostratus, Life of Apollonius 8.26-31 - Livius".
  118. ^ a b Long 1999, p. 240.
  119. ^ a b c d Jones 2010, p. 320.
  120. ^ a b c DeWitt 1954, p. 3.
  121. ^ a b c Gordon 2012, p. 1.
  122. ^ a b DeWitt 1954, pp. 3–4.
  123. ^ a b Gordon 2012, pp. 1–2.
  124. ^ Gordon 2012, p. 9.
  125. ^ Gordon 2012, pp. 9, 12–13.
  126. ^ Gordon 2012, p. 10.
  127. ^ Seneca. Of a Happy Life.
  128. ^ DeWitt 1954, pp. 3, 31–32.
  129. ^ a b DeWitt 1954, pp. 3, 32.
  130. ^ Jones 2010, pp. 320–321.
  131. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y Jones 2010, p. 321.
  132. ^ DeWitt 1954, pp. 8, 26–33.
  133. ^ a b DeWitt 1954, pp. 31–32.
  134. ^ DeWitt 1954, pp. 8, cf. 26–33.
  135. ^ Frischer 1982, p. 155.
  136. ^ Frischer 1982, pp. 155–156.
  137. ^ a b Jones 2010, pp. 321–322.
  138. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u Jones 2010, p. 322.
  139. ^ a b Jones 2010, pp. 322–323.
  140. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r Jones 2010, p. 323.
  141. ^ a b Brewer & Evans 1989, p. 388.
  142. ^ Schafer 2003, p. 127.
  143. ^ Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works – Volume 1, p 30
  144. ^ Schafer 2003, pp. 127–128.
  145. ^ Schafer 2003, pp. 127–129.
  146. ^ Svanidze, Budu (1953). My Uncle, Joseph Stalin. G. P. Putnam's Sons. p. 213.
  147. ^ Friedrich Nietzsche: Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits, p. 44.
  148. ^ Jones 2010, pp. 323–324.

Bibliography edit

  • Asmis, Elizabeth (1984), Epicurus' Scientific Method, Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, ISBN 978-08014-1465-7
  • Barnes, Jonathan (1986), "15: Hellenistic Philosophy and Science", in Boardman, John; Griffin, Jasper; Murray, Oswyn (eds.), The Oxford History of the Classical World, Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, pp. 365–385, ISBN 978-0198721123
  • Brewer, Ebenezer Cobham; Evans, Ivor H. (1989), Brewer's Dictionary of Phrase and Fable (14th ed.), New York City, New York, Grand Rapids, Michigan, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, St. Louis, Missouri, San Francisco, California, London, England, Singapore, Singapore, Sydney, Australia, Tokyo, Japan, and Toronto, Canada: Harper & Row Publishers, ISBN 978-0-06-016200-9
  • DeWitt, Norman Wentworth (1954), Epicurus and His Philosophy, Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, ISBN 978-0-816-65745-2
  • Erler, Michael (2011), "Chapter II: Autodidact and student: on the relationship of authority and autonomy in Epicurus and the Epicurean tradition", in Fish, Jeffrey; Sanders, Kirk R. (eds.), Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, pp. 9–28, ISBN 978-0-521-19478-5
  • Fish, Jeffrey; Sanders, Kirk R. (2011), "Chapter I: Introduction", in Fish, Jeffrey; Sanders, Kirk R. (eds.), Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–8, ISBN 978-0-521-19478-5
  • Frischer, Bernard (1982), The Sculpted Word: Epicureanism and Philosophical Recruitment in Ancient Greece, Berkeley and Los Angeles, California and London, England: University of California Press, ISBN 978-0-520-04190-5
  • Gordon, Pamela (2012), The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus, Ann Arbor, Michigan: The University of Michigan Press, ISBN 978-0-472-02817-7
  • Gordon, Pamela (2013), "Epistulatory Epicureans", in Boter, G. J.; Chaniotis, A.; Coleman, K. M.; de Jong, I. J. F.; Reinhardt, T. (eds.), Epistolary Narratives in Ancient Greek Literature, Mnemosyne: Supplements: Monographs on Greek and Latin Language and Literature, vol. 359, Leiden, The Netherlands: Koninklijke Brill, ISBN 978-90-04-25303-2
  • Jones, Howard (2010), "Epicurus and Epicureanism", in Grafton, Anthony; Most, Glenn W.; Settis, Salvatore (eds.), The Classical Tradition, Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, pp. 320–324, ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0
  • Hickson, Michael W. (2014), "A Brief History of Problems of Evil", in McBrayer, Justin P.; Howard-Snyder, Daniel (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to The Problem of Evil, Hoboken, New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 26–27, ISBN 978-1-118-60797-8
  • Kenny, Anthony (2004), Ancient Philosophy, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 1, Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, pp. 94–96, ISBN 978-0-19-875273-8
  • Long, A. A. (1999), "Epicurus", A Companion to Philosophers, Malden, Massachusetts and Oxford, England: Wiley Publishers, Ltd., pp. 239–243, ISBN 978-0-63-122967-4
  • Rosenbaum, Stephen E. (2004), "Chapter 11: How to Be Dead and Not Care: A Defense of Epicurus", in Benatar, David (ed.), Life, Death & Meaning: Key Philosophical Readings on the Big Questions, Lanham, Maryland, Boulder, Colorado, New York City, New York, Toronto, Canada, and Oxford, England: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., ISBN 978-1-442-20169-9
  • Schafer, Paul M. (2003), "The Young Marx on Epicurus: Dialectical Atomism and Human Freedom", in Gordon, Dane L.; Suits, David B. (eds.), Epicurus: His Continuing Influence and Contemporary Relevance, Rochester, New York: Rochester Institute of Technology, Cary Graphic Arts Press, pp. 127–138, ISBN 978-0-9713-4596-6
  • Strodach, George K. (2012), "Introduction", The Art of Happiness, New York City, New York: Penguin Classics, ISBN 978-0-14-310721-7
  • Wasson, Donald L. (7 September 2016), "Epicurus", World History Encyclopedia

Further reading edit

Texts
  • Epicurus (1994). Inwood, Brad; Gerson, Lloyd P. (eds.). The Epicurus Reader. Selected Writings and Testimonia. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 978-0-87220-242-9.
  • Epicurus (1993). The essential Epicurus : letters, principal doctrines, Vatican sayings, and fragments. Translated by O'Connor, Eugene. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-0-87975-810-3.
  • Epicurus (1964). Letters, principal doctrines, and Vatican sayings. Translated by Geer, Russel M. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
  • Laërtius, Diogenes (1969). Caponigri, A. Robert (ed.). Lives of the Philosophers. Chicago: Henry Regnery Co.
  • Lucretius Carus, Titus (1976). On the nature of the universe. Translated by Latham, R. E. London: Penguin Books. ISBN 978-0-14-044018-8.
  • Körte, Alfred (1987). Epicureanism : two collections of fragments and studies (in Greek). New York: Garland. ISBN 978-0-8240-6915-5.
  • Oates, Whitney J. (1940). The Stoic and Epicurean philosophers, The Complete Extant Writings of Epicurus, Epictetus, Lucretius and Marcus Aurelius. New York: Modern Library.
  • Diogenes of Oinoanda (1993). The Epicurean inscription. Translated by Smith, Martin Ferguson. Napoli: Bibliopolis. ISBN 978-88-7088-270-4.
Studies
  • Bailey C. (1928). The Greek Atomists and Epicurus, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy from Thales to the Stoics. Analysis and fragments. Victoria: Trafford. ISBN 978-1-4120-4843-9.
  • Gordon, Pamela (1996). Epicurus in Lycia. The Second-Century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Ann Arbor: Univ. of Michigan Press. ISBN 978-0-472-10461-1.
  • Gottlieb, Anthony (2000). The Dream of Reason. A History of Western Philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance. New York: W.W. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-04951-0.
  • Hibler, Richard W. (1984). Happiness Through Tranquillity. The school of Epicurus. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-8191-3861-3.
  • Hicks, R. D. (1910). Stoic and Epicurean. New York: Scribner.
  • Jones, Howard (1989). The Epicurean Tradition. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-02069-5.
  • Obbink, Dirk (1989). "The Atheism of Epicurus". Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies. 30 (2): 187–223.
  • O'Keefe, Tim (2009). Epicureanism. University of California Press.
  • Panichas, George Andrew (1967). Epicurus. New York: Twayne Publishers.
  • Rist, J.M. (1972). Epicurus. An introduction. London: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-08426-0.
  • Warren, James (2009). The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-05218-7347-5.
  • William Wallace. Epicureanism. SPCK (1880)

External links edit

epicurus, confused, with, epictetus, ʊər, kure, greek, Ἐπίκουρος, epikouros, ancient, greek, philosopher, sage, founded, epicureanism, highly, influential, school, philosophy, born, greek, island, samos, athenian, parents, influenced, democritus, aristippus, p. Not to be confused with Epictetus Epicurus ˌ ɛ p ɪ ˈ k j ʊer e s EH pih KURE es 2 Greek Ἐpikoyros Epikouros 341 270 BC was an ancient Greek philosopher and sage who founded Epicureanism a highly influential school of philosophy He was born on the Greek island of Samos to Athenian parents Influenced by Democritus Aristippus Pyrrho 3 and possibly the Cynics he turned against the Platonism of his day and established his own school known as the Garden in Athens Epicurus and his followers were known for eating simple meals and discussing a wide range of philosophical subjects He openly allowed women and slaves 4 to join the school as a matter of policy Of the over 300 works said to have been written by Epicurus about various subjects the vast majority have been destroyed Only three letters written by him the letters to Menoeceus Pythocles and Herodotus and two collections of quotes the Principal Doctrines and the Vatican Sayings have survived intact along with a few fragments of his other writings As a result of his work s destruction most knowledge about his philosophy is due to later authors particularly the biographer Diogenes Laertius the Epicurean Roman poet Lucretius and the Epicurean philosopher Philodemus and with hostile but largely accurate accounts by the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus and the Academic Skeptic and statesman Cicero EpicurusRoman marble bust of EpicurusBornFebruary 341 BCSamos GreeceDied270 BC aged about 72 Athens GreeceEraHellenistic philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolEpicureanismMain interestsethicsepistemologyphysicstheologyNotable ideasaponiaataraxia moving and static pleasures 1 Attributed Epicurean paradoxEpicurus asserted that philosophy s purpose is to attain as well as to help others attain happy eudaimonic tranquil lives characterized by ataraxia peace and freedom from fear and aponia the absence of pain He advocated that people were best able to pursue philosophy by living a self sufficient life surrounded by friends He taught that the root of all human neuroses is death denial and the tendency for human beings to assume that death will be horrific and painful which he claimed causes unnecessary anxiety selfish self protective behaviors and hypocrisy According to Epicurus death is the end of both the body and the soul and therefore should not be feared Epicurus taught that although the gods exist they have no involvement in human affairs He taught that people should act ethically not because the gods punish or reward them for their actions but because due to the power of guilt amoral behavior would inevitably lead to remorse weighing on their consciences and as a result they would be prevented from attaining ataraxia Epicurus derived much of his physics and cosmology from the earlier philosopher Democritus c 460 c 370 BC Like Democritus Epicurus taught that the universe is infinite and eternal and that all matter is made up of extremely tiny invisible particles known as atoms All occurrences in the natural world are ultimately the result of atoms moving and interacting in empty space Epicurus deviated from Democritus by proposing the idea of atomic swerve which holds that atoms may deviate from their expected course thus permitting humans to possess free will in an otherwise deterministic universe Though popular Epicurean teachings were controversial from the beginning Epicureanism reached the height of its popularity during the late years of the Roman Republic It died out in late antiquity subject to hostility from early Christianity Throughout the Middle Ages Epicurus was popularly though inaccurately remembered as a patron of drunkards whoremongers and gluttons His teachings gradually became more widely known in the fifteenth century with the rediscovery of important texts but his ideas did not become acceptable until the seventeenth century when the French Catholic priest Pierre Gassendi revived a modified version of them which was promoted by other writers including Walter Charleton and Robert Boyle His influence grew considerably during and after the Enlightenment profoundly impacting the ideas of major thinkers including John Locke Thomas Jefferson Jeremy Bentham and Karl Marx Contents 1 Life 1 1 Upbringing and influences 1 2 Teaching career 1 3 Death 2 Philosophy 2 1 Epistemology 2 2 Ethics 2 3 Physics 2 4 Theology 2 4 1 Epicurean paradox 2 5 Politics 3 Works 4 Legacy 4 1 Ancient Epicureanism 4 2 Middle Ages 4 3 Renaissance 4 4 Revival 4 5 Enlightenment and after 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 7 1 Bibliography 8 Further reading 9 External linksLife editUpbringing and influences edit nbsp nbsp Athens nbsp Mytilene nbsp Samos nbsp Colophon nbsp Lampsacusclass notpageimage Map of Greece showing locations associated with Epicurus Epicurus was born in the Athenian settlement on the Aegean island of Samos in February 341 BC 5 6 7 His parents Neocles and Chaerestrate were both Athenian born and his father was an Athenian citizen 5 Epicurus grew up during the final years of the Greek Classical Period 8 Plato had died seven years before Epicurus was born and Epicurus was seven years old when Alexander the Great crossed the Hellespont into Persia 9 As a child Epicurus would have received a typical ancient Greek education 10 As such according to Norman Wentworth DeWitt it is inconceivable that he would have escaped the Platonic training in geometry dialectic and rhetoric 10 Epicurus is known to have studied under the instruction of a Samian Platonist named Pamphilus probably for about four years 10 His Letter of Menoeceus and surviving fragments of his other writings strongly suggest that he had extensive training in rhetoric 10 11 After the death of Alexander the Great Perdiccas expelled the Athenian settlers on Samos to Colophon on the coast of what is now Turkey 12 11 Epicurus joined his family there after the completion of his military service He studied under Nausiphanes who followed the teachings of Democritus 11 12 and later those of Pyrrho 13 14 whose way of life Epicurus greatly admired 15 nbsp Allocation of key positions and satrapies following the Partition of Babylon in 323 BC after the death of Alexander the Great Epicurus came of age at a time when Greek intellectual horizons were vastly expanding due to the rise of the Hellenistic Kingdoms across the Near East 16 Epicurus s teachings were heavily influenced by those of earlier philosophers particularly Democritus Nonetheless Epicurus differed from his predecessors on several key points of determinism and vehemently denied having been influenced by any previous philosophers whom he denounced as confused Instead he insisted that he had been self taught 17 18 19 According to DeWitt Epicurus s teachings also show influences from the contemporary philosophical school of Cynicism 20 The Cynic philosopher Diogenes of Sinope was still alive when Epicurus would have been in Athens for his required military training and it is possible they may have met 20 Diogenes s pupil Crates of Thebes c 365 c 285 BC was a close contemporary of Epicurus 20 Epicurus agreed with the Cynics quest for honesty but rejected their insolence and vulgarity instead teaching that honesty must be coupled with courtesy and kindness 20 Epicurus shared this view with his contemporary the comic playwright Menander 21 Epicurus s Letter to Menoeceus possibly an early work of his is written in an eloquent style similar to that of the Athenian rhetorician Isocrates 436 338 BC 20 but for his later works he seems to have adopted the bald intellectual style of the mathematician Euclid 20 Epicurus s epistemology also bears an unacknowledged debt to the later writings of Aristotle 384 322 BC who rejected the Platonic idea of hypostatic Reason and instead relied on nature and empirical evidence for knowledge about the universe 16 During Epicurus s formative years Greek knowledge about the rest of the world was rapidly expanding due to the Hellenization of the Near East and the rise of Hellenistic kingdoms 16 Epicurus s philosophy was consequently more universal in its outlook than those of his predecessors since it took cognizance of non Greek peoples as well as Greeks 16 He may have had access to the now lost writings of the historian and ethnographer Megasthenes who wrote during the reign of Seleucus I Nicator ruled 305 281 BC 16 Teaching career edit nbsp Reconstruction by K Fittschen of an Epicurus enthroned statue presumably set up after his death University of Gottingen Abgusssammlung 22 During Epicurus s lifetime Platonism was the dominant philosophy in higher education 23 Epicurus s opposition to Platonism formed a large part of his thought 24 25 Over half of the forty Principal Doctrines of Epicureanism are flat contradictions of Platonism 24 In around 311 BC Epicurus when he was around thirty years old began teaching in Mytilene 24 11 Around this time Zeno of Citium the founder of Stoicism arrived in Athens at the age of about twenty one but Zeno did not begin teaching what would become Stoicism for another twenty years 24 Although later texts such as the writings of the first century BC Roman orator Cicero portray Epicureanism and Stoicism as rivals 24 this rivalry seems to have only emerged after Epicurus s death 24 24 Epicurus s teachings caused strife in Mytilene and he was forced to leave He then founded a school in Lampsacus before returning to Athens in c 306 BC where he remained until his death 6 There he founded The Garden kῆpos a school named for the garden he owned that served as the school s meeting place about halfway between the locations of two other schools of philosophy the Stoa and the Academy 26 11 The Garden was more than just a school 7 it was a community of like minded and aspiring practitioners of a particular way of life 7 The primary members were Hermarchus the financier Idomeneus Leonteus and his wife Themista the satirist Colotes the mathematician Polyaenus of Lampsacus and Metrodorus of Lampsacus the most famous popularizer of Epicureanism His school was the first of the ancient Greek philosophical schools to admit women as a rule rather than an exception citation needed and the biography of Epicurus by Diogenes Laertius lists female students such as Leontion and Nikidion 27 An inscription on the gate to The Garden is recorded by Seneca the Younger in epistle XXI of Epistulae morales ad Lucilium Stranger here you will do well to tarry here our highest good is pleasure 28 According to Diskin Clay Epicurus himself established a custom of celebrating his birthday annually with common meals befitting his stature as heros ktistes founding hero of the Garden He ordained in his will annual memorial feasts for himself on the same date 10th of Gamelion month 29 Epicurean communities continued this tradition 30 referring to Epicurus as their saviour soter and celebrating him as hero The hero cult of Epicurus may have operated as a Garden variety civic religion 31 However clear evidence of an Epicurean hero cult as well as the cult itself seems buried by the weight of posthumous philosophical interpretation 32 Epicurus never married and had no known children He was most likely a vegetarian 33 34 Death edit Diogenes Laertius records that according to Epicurus s successor Hermarchus Epicurus died a slow and painful death in 270 BC at the age of seventy two from a stone blockage of his urinary tract 35 36 Despite being in immense pain Epicurus is said to have remained cheerful and to have continued to teach until the very end 35 Possible insights into Epicurus s death may be offered by the extremely brief Epistle to Idomeneus included by Diogenes Laertius in Book X of his Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 37 The authenticity of this letter is uncertain and it may be a later pro Epicurean forgery intended to paint an admirable portrait of the philosopher to counter the large number of forged epistles in Epicurus s name portraying him unfavorably 37 I have written this letter to you on a happy day to me which is also the last day of my life For I have been attacked by a painful inability to urinate and also dysentery so violent that nothing can be added to the violence of my sufferings But the cheerfulness of my mind which comes from the recollection of all my philosophical contemplation counterbalances all these afflictions And I beg you to take care of the children of Metrodorus in a manner worthy of the devotion shown by the young man to me and to philosophy 38 If authentic this letter would support the tradition that Epicurus was able to remain joyful to the end even in the midst of his suffering 37 It would also indicate that he maintained a special concern for the wellbeing of children 39 Philosophy editMain article Epicureanism nbsp Illustration from 1885 of a small bronze bust of Epicurus from Herculaneum Three Epicurus bronze busts were recovered from the Villa of the Papyri as well as text fragments 40 Epistemology edit Epicurus and his followers had a well developed epistemology which developed as a result of their rivalry with other philosophical schools 41 42 Epicurus wrote a treatise entitled Kanwn or Rule in which he explained his methods of investigation and theory of knowledge 43 This book however has not survived 43 nor does any other text that fully and clearly explains Epicurean epistemology leaving only mentions of this epistemology by several authors to reconstruct it 41 42 Epicurus rejected the Platonic idea of Reason as a reliable source of knowledge about the world apart from the senses 16 and was bitterly opposed to the Pyrrhonists and Academic Skeptics who not only questioned the ability of the senses to provide accurate knowledge about the world but also whether it is even possible to know anything about the world at all 44 Epicurus maintained that the senses never deceive humans but that the senses can be misinterpreted 45 46 Epicurus held that the purpose of all knowledge is to aid humans in attaining ataraxia 47 48 He taught that knowledge is learned through experiences rather than innate 49 and that the acceptance of the fundamental truth of the things a person perceives is essential to a person s moral and spiritual health 50 48 In the Letter to Pythocles he states If a person fights the clear evidence of his senses he will never be able to share in genuine tranquility 51 Epicurus regarded gut feelings as the ultimate authority on matters of morality and held that whether a person feels an action is right or wrong is a far more cogent guide to whether that act really is right or wrong than abstracts maxims strict codified rules of ethics or even reason itself 52 Epicurus permitted that any and every statement that is not directly contrary to human perception has the possibility to be true 53 Nonetheless anything contrary to a person s experience can be ruled out as false 54 Epicureans often used analogies to everyday experience to support their argument of so called imperceptibles which included anything that a human being cannot perceive such as the motion of atoms 55 In line with this principle of non contradiction the Epicureans believed that events in the natural world may have multiple causes that are all equally possible and probable 56 Lucretius writes in On the Nature of Things as translated by William Ellery Leonard There be besides some thing Of which tis not enough one only cause To state but rather several whereof one Will be the true lo if thou shouldst espy Lying afar some fellow s lifeless corse Twere meet to name all causes of a death That cause of his death might thereby be named For prove thou mayst he perished not by steel By cold nor even by poison nor disease Yet somewhat of this sort hath come to him We know And thus we have to say the same In divers cases 57 Epicurus strongly favored naturalistic explanations over theological ones 58 In his Letter to Pythocles he offers four different possible natural explanations for thunder six different possible natural explanations for lightning three for snow three for comets two for rainbows two for earthquakes and so on 59 Although all of these explanations are now known to be false they were an important step in the history of science because Epicurus was trying to explain natural phenomena using natural explanations rather than resorting to inventing elaborate stories about gods and mythic heroes 59 Ethics edit nbsp Marble relief from the first or second century showing the mythical transgressor Ixion being tortured on a spinning fiery wheel in Tartarus Epicurus taught that stories of such punishment in the afterlife are ridiculous superstitions and that believing in them prevents people from attaining ataraxia 60 61 Epicurus was a hedonist meaning he taught that what is pleasurable is morally good and what is painful is morally evil 62 63 64 7 He idiosyncratically defined pleasure as the absence of suffering 63 7 and taught that all humans should seek to attain the state of ataraxia meaning untroubledness a state in which the person is completely free from all pain or suffering 65 66 67 He argued that most of the suffering which human beings experience is caused by the irrational fears of death divine retribution and punishment in the afterlife 60 61 In his Letter to Menoeceus Epicurus explains that people seek wealth and power on account of these fears believing that having more money prestige or political clout will save them from death 60 61 He however maintains that death is the end of existence that the terrifying stories of punishment in the afterlife are ridiculous superstitions and that death is therefore nothing to be feared 60 61 68 He writes in his Letter to Menoeceus Accustom thyself to believe that death is nothing to us for good and evil imply sentience and death is the privation of all sentience Death therefore the most awful of evils is nothing to us seeing that when we are death is not come and when death is come we are not 69 From this doctrine arose the Epicurean epitaph Non fui fui non sum non curo I was not I was I am not I do not care which is inscribed on the gravestones of his followers and seen on many ancient gravestones of the Roman Empire This quotation is often used today at humanist funerals 70 The Tetrapharmakos presents a summary of the key points of Epicurean ethics 71 Don t fear god Don t worry about death What is good is easy to get What is terrible is easy to endureAlthough Epicurus has been commonly misunderstood as an advocate of the rampant pursuit of pleasure he in fact maintained that a person can only be happy and free from suffering by living wisely soberly and morally 63 72 73 He strongly disapproved of raw excessive sensuality and warned that a person must take into account whether the consequences of his actions will result in suffering 63 74 64 73 writing the pleasant life is produced not by a string of drinking bouts and revelries nor by the enjoyment of boys and women nor by fish and the other items on an expensive menu but by sober reasoning 63 He also wrote that a single good piece of cheese could be equally pleasing as an entire feast 64 75 Furthermore Epicurus taught that it is not possible to live pleasurably without living sensibly and nobly and justly because a person who engages in acts of dishonesty or injustice will be loaded with troubles on account of his own guilty conscience and will live in constant fear that his wrongdoings will be discovered by others 63 76 77 A person who is kind and just to others however will have no fear and will be more likely to attain ataraxia 63 76 Epicurus distinguished between two different types of pleasure moving pleasures katὰ kinhsin ἡdonai and static pleasures katasthmatikaὶ ἡdonai 78 79 Moving pleasures occur when one is in the process of satisfying a desire and involve an active titillation of the senses 78 After one s desires have been satisfied e g when one is full after eating the pleasure quickly goes away and the suffering of wanting to fulfill the desire again returns 78 80 For Epicurus static pleasures are the best pleasures because moving pleasures are always bound up with pain 78 80 Epicurus had a low opinion of sex and marriage regarding both as having dubious value 81 Instead he maintained that platonic friendships are essential to living a happy life 82 One of the Principal Doctrines states Of the things wisdom acquires for the blessedness of life as a whole far the greatest is the possession of friendship 83 84 He also taught that philosophy is itself a pleasure to engage in 82 One of the quotes from Epicurus recorded in the Vatican Sayings declares In other pursuits the hard won fruit comes at the end But in philosophy delight keeps pace with knowledge It is not after the lesson that enjoyment comes learning and enjoyment happen at the same time 85 84 Epicurus distinguishes between three types of desires natural and necessary natural but unnecessary and vain and empty Natural and necessary desires include the desires for food and shelter These are easy to satisfy difficult to eliminate bring pleasure when satisfied and are naturally limited Going beyond these limits produces unnecessary desires such as the desire for luxury foods Although food is necessary luxury food is not necessary Correspondingly Epicurus advocates a life of hedonistic moderation by reducing desire thus eliminating the unhappiness caused by unfulfilled desires Vain desires include desires for power wealth and fame These are difficult to satisfy because no matter how much one gets one can always want more These desires are inculcated by society and by false beliefs about what we need They are not natural and are to be shunned 86 Epicurus teachings were introduced into medical philosophy and practice by the Epicurean doctor Asclepiades of Bithynia who was the first physician who introduced Greek medicine in Rome Asclepiades introduced the friendly sympathetic pleasing and painless treatment of patients He advocated humane treatment of mental disorders had insane persons freed from confinement and treated them with natural therapy such as diet and massages His teachings are surprisingly modern therefore Asclepiades is considered to be a pioneer physician in psychotherapy physical therapy and molecular medicine 87 Physics edit Epicurus writes in his Letter to Herodotus not the historian 88 that nothing ever arises from the nonexistent indicating that all events therefore have causes regardless of whether those causes are known or unknown 89 Similarly he also writes that nothing ever passes away into nothingness because if an object that passes from our view were completely annihilated everything in the world would have perished since that into which things were dissipated would be nonexistent 90 He therefore states The totality of things was always just as it is at present and will always remain the same because there is nothing into which it can change inasmuch as there is nothing outside the totality that could intrude and effect change 90 Like Democritus before him Epicurus taught that all matter is entirely made of extremely tiny particles called atoms Greek ἄtomos atomos meaning indivisible 91 For Epicurus and his followers the existence of atoms was a matter of empirical observation 92 Epicurus s devoted follower the Roman poet Lucretius cites the gradual wearing down of rings from being worn statues from being kissed stones from being dripped on by water and roads from being walked on in On the Nature of Things as evidence for the existence of atoms as tiny imperceptible particles 92 Also like Democritus Epicurus was a materialist who taught that the only things that exist are atoms and void 93 11 Void occurs in any place where there are no atoms 94 Epicurus and his followers believed that atoms and void are both infinite and that the universe is therefore boundless 95 In On the Nature of Things Lucretius argues this point using the example of a man throwing a javelin at the theoretical boundary of a finite universe 96 He states that the javelin must either go past the edge of the universe in which case it is not really a boundary or it must be blocked by something and prevented from continuing its path but if that happens then the object blocking it must be outside the confines of the universe 96 As a result of this belief that the universe and the number of atoms in it are infinite Epicurus and the Epicureans believed that there must also be infinitely many worlds within the universe 97 Epicurus taught that the motion of atoms is constant eternal and without beginning or end 98 He held that there are two kinds of motion the motion of atoms and the motion of visible objects 98 Both kinds of motion are real and not illusory 99 Democritus had described atoms as not only eternally moving but also eternally flying through space colliding coalescing and separating from each other as necessary 100 In a rare departure from Democritus s physics Epicurus posited the idea of atomic swerve paregklisis parenklisis Latin clinamen one of his best known original ideas 101 a According to this idea atoms as they are travelling through space may deviate slightly from the course they would ordinarily be expected to follow 101 Epicurus s reason for introducing this doctrine was because he wanted to preserve the concepts of free will and ethical responsibility while still maintaining the deterministic physical model of atomism 102 Lucretius describes it saying It is this slight deviation of primal bodies at indeterminate times and places which keeps the mind as such from experiencing an inner compulsion in doing everything it does and from being forced to endure and suffer like a captive in chains 103 Epicurus was first to assert human freedom as a result of the fundamental indeterminism in the motion of atoms This has led some philosophers to think that for Epicurus free will was caused directly by chance In his On the Nature of Things Lucretius appears to suggest this in the best known passage on Epicurus position 104 In his Letter to Menoeceus however Epicurus follows Aristotle and clearly identifies three possible causes some things happen of necessity others by chance others through our own agency Aristotle said some things depend on us eph hemin Epicurus agreed and said it is to these last things that praise and blame naturally attach For Epicurus the swerve of the atoms simply defeated determinism to leave room for autonomous agency 105 Theology edit nbsp First century AD Roman fresco from Pompeii showing the mythical human sacrifice of Iphigenia daughter of Agamemnon Epicurus s devoted follower the Roman poet Lucretius cited this myth as an example of the evils of popular religion in contrast to the more wholesome theology advocated by Epicurus 106 In his Letter to Menoeceus a summary of his own moral and theological teachings the first piece of advice Epicurus himself gives to his student is First believe that a god is an indestructible and blessed animal in accordance with the general conception of god commonly held and do not ascribe to god anything foreign to his indestructibility or repugnant to his blessedness 107 Epicurus maintained that he and his followers knew that the gods exist because our knowledge of them is a matter of clear and distinct perception meaning that people can empirically sense their presences 108 He did not mean that people can see the gods as physical objects but rather that they can see visions of the gods sent from the remote regions of interstellar space in which they actually reside 108 According to George K Strodach Epicurus could have easily dispensed of the gods entirely without greatly altering his materialist worldview 108 but the gods still play one important function in Epicurus s theology as the paragons of moral virtue to be emulated and admired 108 Epicurus rejected the conventional Greek view of the gods as anthropomorphic beings who walked the earth like ordinary people fathered illegitimate offspring with mortals and pursued personal feuds 108 Instead he taught that the gods are morally perfect but detached and immobile beings who live in the remote regions of interstellar space 109 In line with these teachings Epicurus adamantly rejected the idea that deities were involved in human affairs in any way 107 110 Epicurus maintained that the gods are so utterly perfect and removed from the world that they are incapable of listening to prayers or supplications or doing virtually anything aside from contemplating their own perfections 109 In his Letter to Herodotus he specifically denies that the gods have any control over natural phenomena arguing that this would contradict their fundamental nature which is perfect because any kind of worldly involvement would tarnish their perfection 110 He further warned that believing that the gods control natural phenomena would only mislead people into believing the superstitious view that the gods punish humans for wrongdoing which only instills fear and prevents people from attaining ataraxia 110 Epicurus himself criticizes popular religion in both his Letter to Menoeceus and his Letter to Herodotus but in a restrained and moderate tone 111 Later Epicureans mainly followed the same ideas as Epicurus believing in the existence of the gods but emphatically rejecting the idea of divine providence 107 Their criticisms of popular religion however are often less gentle than those of Epicurus himself 112 The Letter to Pythocles written by a later Epicurean is dismissive and contemptuous towards popular religion 112 and Epicurus s devoted follower the Roman poet Lucretius c 99 BC c 55 BC passionately assailed popular religion in his philosophical poem On the Nature of Things 112 In this poem Lucretius declares that popular religious practices not only do not instill virtue but rather result in misdeeds both wicked and ungodly citing the mythical sacrifice of Iphigenia as an example 106 Lucretius argues that divine creation and providence are illogical not because the gods do not exist but rather because these notions are incompatible with the Epicurean principles of the gods indestructibility and blessedness 113 114 The later Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus c 160 c 210 AD rejected the teachings of the Epicureans specifically because he regarded them as theological Dogmaticists 115 Epicurean paradox edit nbsp The most famous version of the problem of evil is attributed to Epicurus by David Hume pictured who was relying on an attribution of it to him by the Christian apologist Lactantius The trilemma does not occur in any of Epicurus s extant writings however If Epicurus did write some version of it it would have been an argument against divine providence not the existence of deities 116 See also Problem of evil Epicurus Trilemma Epicurus trilemma and Epicurus paradox The Epicurean paradox or riddle of Epicurus or Epicurus trilemma is a version of the problem of evil Lactantius attributes this trilemma to Epicurus in De Ira Dei 13 20 21 God he says either wishes to take away evils and is unable or He is able and is unwilling or He is neither willing nor able or He is both willing and able If He is willing and is unable He is feeble which is not in accordance with the character of God if He is able and unwilling He is envious which is equally at variance with God if He is neither willing nor able He is both envious and feeble and therefore not God if He is both willing and able which alone is suitable to God from what source then are evils Or why does He not remove them In Dialogues concerning Natural Religion 1779 David Hume also attributes the argument to Epicurus Epicurus s old questions are yet unanswered Is he willing to prevent evil but not able then is he impotent Is he able but not willing then is he malevolent Is he both able and willing whence then is evil No extant writings of Epicurus contain this argument 116 However the vast majority of Epicurus s writings have been lost and it is possible that some form of this argument may have been found in his lost treatise On the Gods which Diogenes Laertius describes as one of his greatest works 116 If Epicurus really did make some form of this argument it would not have been an argument against the existence of deities but rather an argument against divine providence 116 Epicurus s extant writings demonstrate that he did believe in the existence of deities 107 Furthermore religion was such an integral part of daily life in Greece during the early Hellenistic Period that it is doubtful anyone during that period could have been an atheist in the modern sense of the word 107 Instead the Greek word ἄ8eos atheos meaning without a god was used as a term of abuse not as an attempt to describe a person s beliefs 107 Politics edit Epicurus promoted an innovative theory of justice as a social contract Justice Epicurus said is an agreement neither to harm nor be harmed and we need to have such a contract in order to enjoy fully the benefits of living together in a well ordered society Laws and punishments are needed to keep misguided fools in line who would otherwise break the contract But the wise person sees the usefulness of justice and because of his limited desires he has no need to engage in the conduct prohibited by the laws in any case Laws that are useful for promoting happiness are just but those that are not useful are not just Principal Doctrines 31 40 Epicurus discouraged participation in politics as doing so leads to perturbation and status seeking He instead advocated not drawing attention to oneself This principle is epitomised by the phrase lathe biōsas la8e biwsas meaning live in obscurity get through life without drawing attention to yourself i e live without pursuing glory or wealth or power but anonymously enjoying little things like food the company of friends etc Plutarch elaborated on this theme in his essay Is the Saying Live in Obscurity Right Eἰ kalῶs eἴrhtai tὸ la8e biwsas An recte dictum sit latenter esse vivendum 1128c cf Flavius Philostratus Vita Apollonii 8 28 12 117 Works edit nbsp Epicurus in the Nuremberg ChronicleEpicurus was an extremely prolific writer 118 116 61 65 According to Diogenes Laertius he wrote around 300 treatises on a variety of subjects 116 61 Although more original writings of Epicurus have survived to the present day than of any other Hellenistic Greek philosopher 65 the vast majority of everything he wrote has still been lost 118 116 61 and most of what is known about Epicurus s teachings come from the writings of his later followers particularly the Roman poet Lucretius 61 The only surviving complete works by Epicurus are three relatively lengthy letters which are quoted in their entirety in Book X of Diogenes Laertius s Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers and two groups of quotes the Principal Doctrines Kyriai Do3ai which are likewise preserved through quotation by Diogenes Laertius and the Vatican Sayings preserved in a manuscript from the Vatican Library that was first discovered in 1888 61 In the Letter to Herodotus and the Letter to Pythocles Epicurus summarizes his philosophy on nature and in the Letter to Menoeceus he summarizes his moral teachings 61 Numerous fragments of Epicurus s lost thirty seven volume treatise On Nature have been found among the charred papyrus fragments at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum 61 65 Scholars first began attempting to unravel and decipher these scrolls in 1800 but the efforts are painstaking and are still ongoing 61 According to Diogenes Laertius 10 27 9 the major works of Epicurus include On Nature in 37 books On Atoms and the Void On Love Abridgment of the Arguments employed against the Natural Philosophers Against the Megarians Problems Fundamental Propositions Kyriai Doxai On Choice and Avoidance On the Chief Good On the Criterion the Canon Chaeridemus On the Gods On Piety Hegesianax Four essays on Lives Essay on Just Dealing Neocles Essay addressed to Themista The Banquet Symposium Eurylochus Essay addressed to Metrodorus Essay on Seeing Essay on the Angle in an Atom Essay on Touch Essay on Fate Opinions on the Passions Treatise addressed to Timocrates Prognostics Exhortations On Images On Perceptions Aristobulus Essay on Music i e on music poetry and dance On Justice and the other Virtues On Gifts and Gratitude Polymedes Timocrates three books Metrodorus five books Antidorus two books Opinions about Diseases and Death addressed to Mithras Callistolas Essay on Kingly Power Anaximenes LettersLegacy editAncient Epicureanism edit nbsp Bust of Epicurus leaning against his disciple Metrodorus in the Louvre MuseumEpicureanism was extremely popular from the very beginning 119 120 121 Diogenes Laertius records that the number of Epicureans throughout the world exceeded the populations of entire cities 121 Nonetheless Epicurus was not universally admired and within his own lifetime he was vilified as an ignorant buffoon and egoistic sybarite 63 122 He remained the most simultaneously admired and despised philosopher in the Mediterranean for the next nearly five centuries 122 Epicureanism rapidly spread beyond the Greek mainland all across the Mediterranean world 119 By the first century BC it had established a strong foothold in Italy 119 The Roman orator Cicero 106 43 BC who deplored Epicurean ethics lamented the Epicureans have taken Italy by storm 119 The overwhelming majority of surviving Greek and Roman sources are vehemently negative towards Epicureanism 123 and according to Pamela Gordon they routinely depict Epicurus himself as monstrous or laughable 123 Many Romans in particular took a negative view of Epicureanism seeing its advocacy of the pursuit of voluptas pleasure as contrary to the Roman ideal of virtus manly virtue 124 The Romans therefore often stereotyped Epicurus and his followers as weak and effeminate 125 Prominent critics of his philosophy include prominent authors such as the Roman Stoic Seneca the Younger c 4 BC AD 65 and the Greek Middle Platonist Plutarch c 46 c 120 who both derided these stereotypes as immoral and disreputable 121 Gordon characterizes anti Epicurean rhetoric as so heavy handed and misrepresentative of Epicurus s actual teachings that they sometimes come across as comical 126 In his De vita beata Seneca states that the sect of Epicurus has a bad reputation and yet it does not deserve it and compares it to a man in a dress your chastity remains your virility is unimpaired your body has not submitted sexually but in your hand is a tympanum 127 Epicureanism was a notoriously conservative philosophical school 6 18 19 although Epicurus s later followers did expand on his philosophy they dogmatically retained what he himself had originally taught without modifying it 6 18 19 Epicureans and admirers of Epicureanism revered Epicurus himself as a great teacher of ethics a savior and even a god 128 His image was worn on finger rings portraits of him were displayed in living rooms and wealthy followers venerated likenesses of him in marble sculpture 129 His admirers revered his sayings as divine oracles carried around copies of his writings and cherished copies of his letters like the letters of an apostle 129 On the twentieth day of every month admirers of his teachings would perform a solemn ritual to honor his memory 120 At the same time opponents of his teachings denounced him with vehemence and persistence 120 However in the first and second centuries AD Epicureanism gradually began to decline as it failed to compete with Stoicism which had an ethical system more in line with traditional Roman values 130 Epicureanism also suffered decay in the wake of Christianity which was also rapidly expanding throughout the Roman Empire 131 Of all the Greek philosophical schools Epicureanism was the one most at odds with the new Christian teachings since Epicureans believed that the soul was mortal denied the existence of an afterlife denied that the divine had any active role in human life and advocated pleasure as the foremost goal of human existence 131 As such Christian writers such as Justin Martyr c 100 c 165 AD Athenagoras of Athens c 133 c 190 Tertullian c 155 c 240 and Clement of Alexandria c 150 c 215 Arnobius died c 330 and Lactantius c 250 c 325 all singled it out for the most vitriolic criticism 131 In spite of this DeWitt argues that Epicureanism and Christianity share much common language calling Epicureanism the first missionary philosophy and the first world philosophy 132 Both Epicureanism and Christianity placed strong emphasis on the importance of love and forgiveness 133 and early Christian portrayals of Jesus are often similar to Epicurean portrayals of Epicurus 133 DeWitt argues that Epicureanism in many ways helped pave the way for the spread of Christianity by helping to bridge the gap between Greek intellectualism and a religious way of life and shunt ing the emphasis from the political to the social virtues and offer ing what may be called a religion of humanity 134 Middle Ages edit nbsp Dante Alighieri meets Farinata an Epicurean from Florence in his Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell canto 10 Epicurus and his followers are imprisoned in flaming coffins for the heretical belief that the soul dies with the body 131 shown here in an illustration by Gustave Dore By the early fifth century AD Epicureanism was virtually extinct 131 The Christian Church Father Augustine of Hippo 354 430 AD declared its ashes are so cold that not a single spark can be struck from them 131 While the ideas of Plato and Aristotle could easily be adapted to suit a Christian worldview the ideas of Epicurus were not nearly as easily amenable 131 As such while Plato and Aristotle enjoyed a privileged place in Christian philosophy throughout the Middle Ages Epicurus was not held in such esteem 131 Information about Epicurus s teachings was available through Lucretius s On the Nature of Things quotations of it found in medieval Latin grammars and florilegia and encyclopedias such as Isidore of Seville s Etymologiae seventh century and Hrabanus Maurus s De universo ninth century 131 but there is little evidence that these teachings were systematically studied or comprehended 131 During the Middle Ages Epicurus was remembered by the educated as a philosopher 131 but he frequently appeared in popular culture as a gatekeeper to the Garden of Delights the proprietor of the kitchen the tavern and the brothel 131 He appears in this guise in Martianus Capella s Marriage of Mercury and Philology fifth century John of Salisbury s Policraticus 1159 John Gower s Mirour de l Omme and Geoffrey Chaucer s Canterbury Tales 131 Epicurus and his followers appear in Dante Alighieri s Inferno in the Sixth Circle of Hell where they are imprisoned in flaming coffins for having believed that the soul dies with the body 131 Renaissance edit nbsp Epicurus is shown among other famous philosophers in the Italian Renaissance painter Raphael s School of Athens 1509 1511 135 Epicurus s genuine busts were unknown prior to 1742 so early modern artists who wanted to depict him were forced to make up their own iconographies 136 In 1417 a manuscript hunter named Poggio Bracciolini discovered a copy of Lucretius s On the Nature of Things in a monastery near Lake Constance 131 The discovery of this manuscript was met with immense excitement because scholars were eager to analyze and study the teachings of classical philosophers and this previously forgotten text contained the most comprehensive account of Epicurus s teachings known in Latin 131 The first scholarly dissertation on Epicurus De voluptate On Pleasure by the Italian Humanist and Catholic priest Lorenzo Valla was published in 1431 131 Valla made no mention of Lucretius or his poem 131 Instead he presented the treatise as a discussion on the nature of the highest good between an Epicurean a Stoic and a Christian 131 Valla s dialogue ultimately rejects Epicureanism 131 but by presenting an Epicurean as a member of the dispute Valla lent Epicureanism credibility as a philosophy that deserved to be taken seriously 131 None of the Quattrocento Humanists ever clearly endorsed Epicureanism 131 but scholars such as Francesco Zabarella 1360 1417 Francesco Filelfo 1398 1481 Cristoforo Landino 1424 1498 and Leonardo Bruni c 1370 1444 did give Epicureanism a fairer analysis than it had traditionally received and provided a less overtly hostile assessment of Epicurus himself 131 Nonetheless Epicureanism remained a pejorative synonymous with extreme egoistic pleasure seeking rather than a name of a philosophical school 131 This reputation discouraged orthodox Christian scholars from taking what others might regard as an inappropriately keen interest in Epicurean teachings 131 Epicureanism did not take hold in Italy France or England until the seventeenth century 137 Even the liberal religious skeptics who might have been expected to take an interest in Epicureanism evidently did not 137 Etienne Dolet 1509 1546 only mentions Epicurus once in all his writings and Francois Rabelais between 1483 and 1494 1553 never mentions him at all 138 Michel de Montaigne 1533 1592 is the exception to this trend quoting a full 450 lines of Lucretius s On the Nature of Things in his Essays 138 His interest in Lucretius however seems to have been primarily literary and he is ambiguous about his feelings on Lucretius s Epicurean worldview 138 During the Protestant Reformation the label Epicurean was bandied back and forth as an insult between Protestants and Catholics 138 Revival edit nbsp The French priest and philosopher Pierre Gassendi is responsible for reviving Epicureanism in modernity as an alternative to Aristotelianism 138 In the seventeenth century the French Catholic priest and scholar Pierre Gassendi 1592 1655 sought to dislodge Aristotelianism from its position of the highest dogma by presenting Epicureanism as a better and more rational alternative 138 In 1647 Gassendi published his book De vita et moribus Epicuri The Life and Morals of Epicurus a passionate defense of Epicureanism 138 In 1649 he published a commentary on Diogenes Laertius s Life of Epicurus 138 He left Syntagma philosophicum Philosophical Compendium a synthesis of Epicurean doctrines unfinished at the time of his death in 1655 138 It was finally published in 1658 after undergoing revision by his editors 138 Gassendi modified Epicurus s teachings to make them palatable for a Christian audience 138 For instance he argued that atoms were not eternal uncreated and infinite in number instead contending that an extremely large but finite number of atoms were created by God at creation 138 As a result of Gassendi s modifications his books were never censored by the Catholic Church 138 They came to exert profound influence on later writings about Epicurus 138 Gassendi s version of Epicurus s teachings became popular among some members of English scientific circles 138 For these scholars however Epicurean atomism was merely a starting point for their own idiosyncratic adaptations of it 138 To orthodox thinkers Epicureanism was still regarded as immoral and heretical 138 For instance Lucy Hutchinson 1620 1681 the first translator of Lucretius s On the Nature of Things into English railed against Epicurus as a lunatic dog who formulated ridiculous impious execrable doctrines 138 Epicurus s teachings were made respectable in England by the natural philosopher Walter Charleton 1619 1707 whose first Epicurean work The Darkness of Atheism Dispelled by the Light of Nature 1652 advanced Epicureanism as a new atomism 138 His next work Physiologia Epicuro Gassendo Charletoniana or a Fabrick of Science Natural upon a Hypothesis of Atoms Founded by Epicurus Repaired by Petrus Gassendus and Augmented by Walter Charleton 1654 emphasized this idea 138 These works together with Charleton s Epicurus s Morals 1658 provided the English public with readily available descriptions of Epicurus s philosophy and assured orthodox Christians that Epicureanism was no threat to their beliefs 138 The Royal Society chartered in 1662 advanced Epicurean atomism 139 One of the most prolific defenders of atomism was the chemist Robert Boyle 1627 1691 who argued for it in publications such as The Origins of Forms and Qualities 1666 Experiments Notes etc about the Mechanical Origin and Production of Divers Particular Qualities 1675 and Of the Excellency and Grounds of the Mechanical Hypothesis 1674 139 By the end of the seventeenth century Epicurean atomism was widely accepted by members of the English scientific community as the best model for explaining the physical world 140 but it had been modified so greatly that Epicurus was no longer seen as its original parent 140 Enlightenment and after edit The Anglican bishop Joseph Butler s anti Epicurean polemics in his Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel 1726 and Analogy of Religion 1736 set the tune for what most orthodox Christians believed about Epicureanism for the remainder of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries 140 Nonetheless there are a few indications from this time period of Epicurus s improving reputation 140 Epicureanism was beginning to lose its associations with indiscriminate and insatiable gluttony which had been characteristic of its reputation ever since antiquity 140 Instead the word epicure began to refer to a person with extremely refined taste in food 140 141 Examples of this usage include Epicurean cooks sharpen with cloyless sauce his appetite from William Shakespeare s Antony and Cleopatra Act II scene i c 1607 141 and such an epicure was Potiphar to please his tooth and pamper his flesh with delicacies from William Whately s Prototypes 1646 140 Around the same time the Epicurean injunction to live in obscurity was beginning to gain popularity as well 140 In 1685 Sir William Temple 1628 1699 abandoned a promising career as a diplomat and instead retired to his garden devoting himself to writing essays on Epicurus s moral teachings 140 That same year John Dryden translated the celebrated lines from Book II of Lucretius s On the Nature of Things Tis pleasant safely to behold from shore The rowling ship and hear the Tempest roar 140 Meanwhile John Locke 1632 1704 adapted Gassendi s modified version of Epicurus s epistemology which became highly influential on English empiricism 140 Many thinkers with sympathies towards the Enlightenment endorsed Epicureanism as an admirable moral philosophy 140 Thomas Jefferson 1743 1826 one of the Founding Fathers of the United States declared in 1819 I too am an Epicurean I consider the genuine not imputed doctrines of Epicurus as containing everything rational in moral philosophy which Greece and Rome have left us 140 The German philosopher Karl Marx 1818 1883 whose ideas are the basis of Marxism was profoundly influenced as a young man by the teachings of Epicurus 142 143 and his doctoral thesis was a Hegelian dialectical analysis of the differences between the natural philosophies of Democritus and Epicurus 144 Marx viewed Democritus as a rationalist skeptic whose epistemology was inherently contradictory but saw Epicurus as a dogmatic empiricist whose worldview is internally consistent and practically applicable 145 The British poet Alfred Tennyson 1809 1892 praised the sober majesties of settled sweet Epicurean life in his 1868 poem Lucretius 140 Epicurus s ethical teachings also had an indirect impact on the philosophy of Utilitarianism in England during the nineteenth century 140 Soviet politician Joseph Stalin 1878 1953 lauded Epicurus by stating He was the greatest philosopher of all time He was the one who recommended practicing virtue to derive the greatest joy from life 146 Friedrich Nietzsche once noted Even today many educated people think that the victory of Christianity over Greek philosophy is a proof of the superior truth of the former although in this case it was only the coarser and more violent that conquered the more spiritual and delicate So far as superior truth is concerned it is enough to observe that the awakening sciences have allied themselves point by point with the philosophy of Epicurus but point by point rejected Christianity 147 Academic interest in Epicurus and other Hellenistic philosophers increased over the course of the late twentieth and early twenty first centuries with an unprecedented number of monographs articles abstracts and conference papers being published on the subject 140 The texts from the library of Philodemus of Gadara in the Villa of the Papyri in Herculaneum first discovered between 1750 and 1765 are being deciphered translated and published by scholars part of the Philodemus Translation Project funded by the United States National Endowment for the Humanities and part of the Centro per lo Studio dei Papiri Ercolanesi in Naples 140 Epicurus s popular appeal among non scholars is difficult to gauge 140 but it seems to be relatively comparable to the appeal of more traditionally popular ancient Greek philosophical subjects such as Stoicism Aristotle and Plato 148 See also editEikas Epikoros Philosophy of happiness Separation of church and stateNotes edit The only fragment in Greek about this central notion is from the Oenoanda inscription fr 54 in Smith s edition The best known reference is in Lucretius s On the Nature of Things 2 251 References edit Bunnin amp Yu 2004 The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy Oxford Blackwell Publishing Jones Daniel 2006 Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary 17th edition Cambridge UP Diogenes Laertius Book IX Chapter 11 Section 64 Diogenes Laertius Lives and Opinions of the Eminent Philosophers Book X Section 3 a b Apollodorus of Athens reported by Diogenes Laertius Lives of Eminent Philosophers 10 14 15 gives his birth on the fourth day of the month February in the third year of the 109th Olympiad in the archonship of Sosigenes a b c d Barnes 1986 p 367 a b c d e Gordon 2012 p 3 DeWitt 1954 pp 8 9 DeWitt 1954 p 8 a b c d DeWitt 1954 p 12 a b c d e f Wasson 2016 a b Epicurus Epicurus Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2018 Diogenes Laertius ix Sextus Empiricus adv Math i 1 Hicks Robert Drew Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Book IX Chapter 11 Section 61 a b c d e f DeWitt 1954 p 10 Huby Pamela M 1978 Epicurus Attitude to Democritus Phronesis 23 1 80 86 doi 10 1163 156852878X00235 JSTOR 4182030 a b c Erler 2011 p 9 a b c Fish amp Sanders 2011 pp 1 2 a b c d e f DeWitt 1954 p 9 DeWitt 1954 pp 9 10 Zanker Paul The Mask of Socrates The Image of the Intellectual in Antiquity III The Rigors of Thinking The Throne of Epicurus Berkeley Calif University of California Press 1995 DeWitt 1954 pp 9 11 a b c d e f g DeWitt 1954 p 11 Long 1999 pp 239 240 David Konstan 2018 Epicurus Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Book X Section 7 Epistulae morales ad Lucilium D Smith Nicholas 2000 Reason and religion in Socratic philosophy p 160 ISBN 978 0 19 513322 6 Glad Clarence E 1995 Paul and Philodemus adaptability in Epicurean and early Christian psychology p 176 ISBN 978 90 04 10067 1 Nussbaum Martha Craven 2009 The Therapy of Desire Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics p 119 ISBN 978 0 691 14131 2 Clay Diskin 1998 Paradosis and survival three chapters in the history of Epicurean philosophy p 76 ISBN 978 0 472 10896 1 The Hidden History of Greco Roman Vegetarianism 10 August 2010 Dombrowski Daniel A 1984 The Philosophy of Vegetarianism University of Massachusetts Press ISBN 978 0870234316 a b Bitsori Maria Galanakis Emmanouil 2004 Epicurus death World Journal of Urology 22 6 466 469 doi 10 1007 s00345 004 0448 2 PMID 15372192 S2CID 41741603 In the second year of the 127th Olympiad in the archonship of Pytharatus according to Diogenes Laertius Lives of Eminent Philosophers 10 15 a b c Gordon 2012 pp 141 142 Diogenes Laertius Lives of Eminent Philosophers 10 22 trans C D Yonge Gordon 2012 p 142 Sheila Dillon 2006 Ancient Greek Portrait Sculpture Contexts Subjects and Styles Cambridge University Press p 45 ISBN 9780521854986 via Google Books a b Strodach 2012 p 26 a b Asmis 1984 pp 9 13 a b Asmis 1984 pp 10 19 Strodach 2012 p 23 Strodach 2012 pp 23 24 Asmis 1984 p 11 Strodach 2012 pp 26 27 a b Asmis 1984 p 12 Strodach 2012 pp 27 28 Strodach 2012 pp 28 29 Strodach 2012 p 29 Strodach 2012 pp 30 31 Strodach 2012 pp 32 34 Strodach 2012 p 34 Strodach 2012 pp 34 35 Strodach 2012 pp 35 39 Carus Titus Lucretius July 2008 Of The Nature of Things Project Gutenberg EBook Vol 785 William Ellery Leonard translator Project Gutenberg Book VI Section Extraordinary and Paradoxical Telluric Phenomena Line 9549 9560 Strodach 2012 pp 36 38 a b Strodach 2012 p 38 a b c d Strodach 2012 pp 56 58 a b c d e f g h i j k l Kenny 2004 p 94 Strodach 2012 p 58 a b c d e f g h Barnes 1986 p 372 a b c Kenny 2004 p 95 a b c d Barnes 1986 p 371 Folse Henry 2005 How Epicurean Metaphysics leads to Epicurean Ethics Department of Philosophy Loyola University New Orleans LA Konstan David 2018 Epicurus Epicurus The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2013 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University forthcoming URL lt http plato stanford edu archives fall2013 entries epicurus gt Gordon 2012 pp 3 4 Rosenbaum 2004 p 175 Epicurus c 341 270 BC British Humanist Association Hutchinson D S Introduction 1994 The Epicurus Reader Selected Writings and Testimonia Cambridge Hackett p vi Strodach 2012 pp 58 60 a b Gordon 2012 pp 5 7 Strodach 2012 p 59 Gordon 2013 p 141 a b Strodach 2012 pp 58 59 Epicurus Principal Doctrines 5 and 31 transl by Robert Drew Hicks 1925 a b c d Epicurus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Diogenes Laertius The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers X 136 a b Kenny 2004 pp 95 96 Gordon 2012 p 4 a b Gordon 2012 pp 4 5 Epicurus Principal Doctrines 27 a b Gordon 2012 p 5 Epicurus Vatican Sayings 27 Epicurus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy C Yapijakis 2009 Hippocrates of Kos the father of clinical medicine and Asclepiades of Bithynia the father of molecular medicine Review In Vivo 23 4 507 14 PMID 19567383 Naragon S Letter to Herodotus PDF manchester edu Manchester University Indiana Retrieved 13 June 2021 Strodach 2012 pp 8 9 a b Strodach 2012 p 10 Strodach 2012 pp 1 8 11 a b Strodach 2012 p 11 Strodach 2012 pp 12 13 Strodach 2012 pp 12 Strodach 2012 p 13 a b Strodach 2012 pp 13 14 Strodach 2012 pp 14 15 a b Strodach 2012 p 15 Strodach 2012 pp 15 16 Strodach 2012 p 16 a b Strodach 2012 pp 16 17 Strodach 2012 pp 17 18 Strodach 2012 p 18 On the Nature of Things 289 293 via Perseus Project Epicurus page on Information Philosopher cf Letter to Menoeceus 134 a b Strodach 2012 pp 46 47 a b c d e f Hickson 2014 pp 27 a b c d e Strodach 2012 p 39 a b Strodach 2012 pp 39 40 a b c Strodach 2012 pp 42 43 Strodach 2012 pp 45 46 a b c Strodach 2012 p 46 Hickson 2014 pp 27 28 Strodach 2012 pp 43 45 Hickson 2014 p 28 a b c d e f g Hickson 2014 pp 26 27 Philostratus Life of Apollonius 8 26 31 Livius a b Long 1999 p 240 a b c d Jones 2010 p 320 a b c DeWitt 1954 p 3 a b c Gordon 2012 p 1 a b DeWitt 1954 pp 3 4 a b Gordon 2012 pp 1 2 Gordon 2012 p 9 Gordon 2012 pp 9 12 13 Gordon 2012 p 10 Seneca Of a Happy Life DeWitt 1954 pp 3 31 32 a b DeWitt 1954 pp 3 32 Jones 2010 pp 320 321 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y Jones 2010 p 321 DeWitt 1954 pp 8 26 33 a b DeWitt 1954 pp 31 32 DeWitt 1954 pp 8 cf 26 33 Frischer 1982 p 155 Frischer 1982 pp 155 156 a b Jones 2010 pp 321 322 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u Jones 2010 p 322 a b Jones 2010 pp 322 323 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r Jones 2010 p 323 a b Brewer amp Evans 1989 p 388 Schafer 2003 p 127 Karl Marx Frederick Engels Collected Works Volume 1 p 30 Schafer 2003 pp 127 128 Schafer 2003 pp 127 129 Svanidze Budu 1953 My Uncle Joseph Stalin G P Putnam s Sons p 213 Friedrich Nietzsche Human All Too Human A Book for Free Spirits p 44 Jones 2010 pp 323 324 Bibliography edit Asmis Elizabeth 1984 Epicurus Scientific Method Ithaca New York Cornell University Press ISBN 978 08014 1465 7 Barnes Jonathan 1986 15 Hellenistic Philosophy and Science in Boardman John Griffin Jasper Murray Oswyn eds The Oxford History of the Classical World Oxford England Oxford University Press pp 365 385 ISBN 978 0198721123 Brewer Ebenezer Cobham Evans Ivor H 1989 Brewer s Dictionary of Phrase and Fable 14th ed New York City New York Grand Rapids Michigan Philadelphia Pennsylvania St Louis Missouri San Francisco California London England Singapore Singapore Sydney Australia Tokyo Japan and Toronto Canada Harper amp Row Publishers ISBN 978 0 06 016200 9 DeWitt Norman Wentworth 1954 Epicurus and His Philosophy Minneapolis Minnesota University of Minnesota Press ISBN 978 0 816 65745 2 Erler Michael 2011 Chapter II Autodidact and student on the relationship of authority and autonomy in Epicurus and the Epicurean tradition in Fish Jeffrey Sanders Kirk R eds Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition Cambridge England Cambridge University Press pp 9 28 ISBN 978 0 521 19478 5 Fish Jeffrey Sanders Kirk R 2011 Chapter I Introduction in Fish Jeffrey Sanders Kirk R eds Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition Cambridge England Cambridge University Press pp 1 8 ISBN 978 0 521 19478 5 Frischer Bernard 1982 The Sculpted Word Epicureanism and Philosophical Recruitment in Ancient Greece Berkeley and Los Angeles California and London England University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 04190 5 Gordon Pamela 2012 The Invention and Gendering of Epicurus Ann Arbor Michigan The University of Michigan Press ISBN 978 0 472 02817 7 Gordon Pamela 2013 Epistulatory Epicureans in Boter G J Chaniotis A Coleman K M de Jong I J F Reinhardt T eds Epistolary Narratives in Ancient Greek Literature Mnemosyne Supplements Monographs on Greek and Latin Language and Literature vol 359 Leiden The Netherlands Koninklijke Brill ISBN 978 90 04 25303 2 Jones Howard 2010 Epicurus and Epicureanism in Grafton Anthony Most Glenn W Settis Salvatore eds The Classical Tradition Cambridge Massachusetts and London England The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press pp 320 324 ISBN 978 0 674 03572 0 Hickson Michael W 2014 A Brief History of Problems of Evil in McBrayer Justin P Howard Snyder Daniel eds The Blackwell Companion to The Problem of Evil Hoboken New Jersey Wiley Blackwell pp 26 27 ISBN 978 1 118 60797 8 Kenny Anthony 2004 Ancient Philosophy A New History of Western Philosophy vol 1 Oxford England Oxford University Press pp 94 96 ISBN 978 0 19 875273 8 Long A A 1999 Epicurus A Companion to Philosophers Malden Massachusetts and Oxford England Wiley Publishers Ltd pp 239 243 ISBN 978 0 63 122967 4 Rosenbaum Stephen E 2004 Chapter 11 How to Be Dead and Not Care A Defense of Epicurus in Benatar David ed Life Death amp Meaning Key Philosophical Readings on the Big Questions Lanham Maryland Boulder Colorado New York City New York Toronto Canada and Oxford England Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers Inc ISBN 978 1 442 20169 9 Schafer Paul M 2003 The Young Marx on Epicurus Dialectical Atomism and Human Freedom in Gordon Dane L Suits David B eds Epicurus His Continuing Influence and Contemporary Relevance Rochester New York Rochester Institute of Technology Cary Graphic Arts Press pp 127 138 ISBN 978 0 9713 4596 6 Strodach George K 2012 Introduction The Art of Happiness New York City New York Penguin Classics ISBN 978 0 14 310721 7 Wasson Donald L 7 September 2016 Epicurus World History EncyclopediaFurther reading editTextsEpicurus 1994 Inwood Brad Gerson Lloyd P eds The Epicurus Reader Selected Writings and Testimonia Indianapolis Hackett ISBN 978 0 87220 242 9 Epicurus 1993 The essential Epicurus letters principal doctrines Vatican sayings and fragments Translated by O Connor Eugene Buffalo N Y Prometheus Books ISBN 978 0 87975 810 3 Epicurus 1964 Letters principal doctrines and Vatican sayings Translated by Geer Russel M Indianapolis Bobbs Merrill Laertius Diogenes 1969 Caponigri A Robert ed Lives of the Philosophers Chicago Henry Regnery Co Lucretius Carus Titus 1976 On the nature of the universe Translated by Latham R E London Penguin Books ISBN 978 0 14 044018 8 Korte Alfred 1987 Epicureanism two collections of fragments and studies in Greek New York Garland ISBN 978 0 8240 6915 5 Oates Whitney J 1940 The Stoic and Epicurean philosophers The Complete Extant Writings of Epicurus Epictetus Lucretius and Marcus Aurelius New York Modern Library Diogenes of Oinoanda 1993 The Epicurean inscription Translated by Smith Martin Ferguson Napoli Bibliopolis ISBN 978 88 7088 270 4 StudiesBailey C 1928 The Greek Atomists and Epicurus Oxford Clarendon Press Bakalis Nikolaos 2005 Handbook of Greek Philosophy from Thales to the Stoics Analysis and fragments Victoria Trafford ISBN 978 1 4120 4843 9 Gordon Pamela 1996 Epicurus in Lycia The Second Century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda Ann Arbor Univ of Michigan Press ISBN 978 0 472 10461 1 Gottlieb Anthony 2000 The Dream of Reason A History of Western Philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance New York W W Norton ISBN 978 0 393 04951 0 Hibler Richard W 1984 Happiness Through Tranquillity The school of Epicurus Lanham MD University Press of America ISBN 978 0 8191 3861 3 Hicks R D 1910 Stoic and Epicurean New York Scribner Jones Howard 1989 The Epicurean Tradition London Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 02069 5 Obbink Dirk 1989 The Atheism of Epicurus Greek Roman and Byzantine Studies 30 2 187 223 O Keefe Tim 2009 Epicureanism University of California Press Panichas George Andrew 1967 Epicurus New York Twayne Publishers Rist J M 1972 Epicurus An introduction London Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 08426 0 Warren James 2009 The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism New York Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 05218 7347 5 William Wallace Epicureanism SPCK 1880 External links editEpicurus at Wikipedia s sister projects nbsp Definitions from Wiktionary nbsp Media from Commons nbsp Quotations from Wikiquote nbsp Texts from Wikisource nbsp Data from Wikidata nbsp Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article Kyriai Do3ai nbsp Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article Ἐpistolὴ prὸs Menoikea Konstan David Epicurus In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy O Keefe Tim Epicurus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stoic And Epicurean by Robert Drew Hicks 1910 Internet Archive Epicurea Hermann Usener full text Works by or about Epicurus at Internet Archive Works by Epicurus at LibriVox public domain audiobooks nbsp Society of Friends of Epicurus Discussion Forum for Epicurus and Epicurean philosophy EpicureanFriends com Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Epicurus amp oldid 1198191121, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.