fbpx
Wikipedia

Animal rights

Animal rights is the philosophy according to which many or all sentient animals have moral worth independent of their utility to humans, and that their most basic interests—such as avoiding suffering—should be afforded the same consideration as similar interests of human beings.[2] Broadly speaking, and particularly in popular discourse, the term "animal rights" is often used synonymously with "animal protection" or "animal liberation". More narrowly, "animal rights" refers to the idea that many animals have fundamental rights to be treated with respect as individuals—rights to life, liberty, and freedom from torture that may not be overridden by considerations of aggregate welfare.[3]

A man with a captive monkey seeking alms in Shanghai
Chickens held inside a battery cage in a factory farm
Parshwanatha, the 23rd Tirthankara, revived Jainism and ahimsa in the 9th century BCE, which led to a radical animal-rights movement in South Asia.[1]
The c. 5th-century CE Tamil scholar Valluvar, in his Tirukkural, taught ahimsa and moral vegetarianism as personal virtues. The plaque in this statue of Valluvar at an animal sanctuary in South India describes the Kural's teachings on ahimsa and non-killing, summing them up with the definition of veganism.

Many advocates of animal rights oppose the assignment of moral value and fundamental protections on the basis of species membership alone.[4] They consider this idea, known as speciesism, a prejudice as irrational as any other.[5] They maintain that animals should not be viewed as property or used as food, clothing, entertainment, or beasts of burden merely because they are not human.[6] Multiple cultural traditions around the world such as Jainism, Taoism, Hinduism, Buddhism, Shinto and Animism also espouse forms of animal rights.

In parallel to the debate about moral rights, law schools in North America now often teach animal law,[7] and several legal scholars, such as Steven M. Wise and Gary L. Francione, support the extension of basic legal rights and personhood to non-human animals. The animals most often considered in arguments for personhood are hominids. Some animal-rights academics support this because it would break the species barrier, but others oppose it because it predicates moral value on mental complexity rather than on sentience alone.[8] As of November 2019, 29 countries had enacted bans on hominoid experimentation; Argentina has granted captive orangutans basic human rights since 2014.[9]

Outside of primates, animal-rights discussions most often address the status of mammals (compare charismatic megafauna). Other animals (considered less sentient) have gained less attention—insects relatively little[10] (outside Jainism) and animal-like bacteria hardly any.[11] The vast majority of animals have no legally recognised rights.[12]

Critics of animal rights argue that nonhuman animals are unable to enter into a social contract, and thus cannot be possessors of rights, a view summarised by the philosopher Roger Scruton, who writes that only humans have duties, and therefore only humans have rights.[13] Another argument, associated with the utilitarian tradition, maintains that animals may be used as resources so long as there is no unnecessary suffering;[14] animals may have some moral standing, but any interests they have may be overridden in cases of comparatively greater gains to aggregate welfare made possible by their use, though what counts as "necessary" suffering or a legitimate sacrifice of interests can vary considerably.[15] Certain forms of animal-rights activism, such as the destruction of fur farms and of animal laboratories by the Animal Liberation Front, have attracted criticism, including from within the animal-rights movement itself,[16] and prompted the U.S. Congress to enact laws, including the Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act, allowing the prosecution of this sort of activity as terrorism.[17]

History Edit

In religion Edit

For some the basis of animal rights is in religion or animal worship (or in general nature worship), with some religions banning killing of any animal, and in other religions animals can be considered unclean.

Hindu and Buddhist societies abandoned animal sacrifice and embraced vegetarianism from the 3rd century BCE.[18] One of the most important sanctions of the Jain, Hindu and Buddhist faiths is the concept of ahimsa, or refraining from the destruction of life. According to Buddhist belief, humans do not deserve preferential treatment over other living beings.[19] The Dharmic interpretation of this doctrine prohibits the killing of any living being.[19] Ancient Tamil works such as the Tolkāppiyam and Tirukkural contain passages that extend the idea of non-violence to all living beings.[20]

In Islam, animal rights were recognized early by the Sharia. This recognition is based on both the Qur'an and the Hadith. In the Qur'an, there are many references to animals, detailing that they have souls, form communities, communicate with God and worship Him in their own way. Muhammad forbade his followers to harm any animal and asked them to respect the rights of animals.[21]

According to Christianity, all animals, from the smallest to the largest, are cared for and loved. According to the Bible, "All these animals waited for the Lord, that the Lord might give them food at the hour. The Lord gives them, they receive; The Lord opens his hand, and they are filled with good things".[22] It further says God "gave food to the animals, and made the crows cry."[23]

Philosophical and legal approaches Edit

Overview Edit

 
Martha Nussbaum, Professor of Law and Ethics at the University of Chicago, is a proponent of the capabilities approach to animal rights.

The two main philosophical approaches to animal ethics are utilitarian and rights-based. The former is exemplified by Peter Singer, and the latter by Tom Regan and Gary Francione. Their differences reflect a distinction philosophers draw between ethical theories that judge the rightness of an act by its consequences (consequentialism/teleological ethics, or utilitarianism), and those that focus on the principle behind the act, almost regardless of consequences (deontological ethics). Deontologists argue that there are acts we should never perform, even if failing to do so entails a worse outcome.[24]

There are a number of positions that can be defended from a consequentalist or deontologist perspective, including the capabilities approach, represented by Martha Nussbaum, and the egalitarian approach, which has been examined by Ingmar Persson and Peter Vallentyne. The capabilities approach focuses on what individuals require to fulfill their capabilities: Nussbaum (2006) argues that animals need a right to life, some control over their environment, company, play, and physical health.[25]

Stephen R. L. Clark, Mary Midgley, and Bernard Rollin also discuss animal rights in terms of animals being permitted to lead a life appropriate for their kind.[26] Egalitarianism favors an equal distribution of happiness among all individuals, which makes the interests of the worse off more important than those of the better off.[27] Another approach, virtue ethics, holds that in considering how to act we should consider the character of the actor, and what kind of moral agents we should be. Rosalind Hursthouse has suggested an approach to animal rights based on virtue ethics.[28] Mark Rowlands has proposed a contractarian approach.[29]

Utilitarianism Edit

Nussbaum (2004) writes that utilitarianism, starting with Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, has contributed more to the recognition of the moral status of animals than any other ethical theory.[30] The utilitarian philosopher most associated with animal rights is Peter Singer, professor of bioethics at Princeton University. Singer is not a rights theorist, but uses the language of rights to discuss how we ought to treat individuals.[citation needed] He is a preference utilitarian,[needs update] meaning that he judges the rightness of an act by the extent to which it satisfies the preferences (interests) of those affected.[31]

His position is that there is no reason not to give equal consideration to the interests of human and nonhumans, though his principle of equality does not require identical treatment. A mouse and a man both have an interest in not being kicked, and there are no moral or logical grounds for failing to accord those interests equal weight. Interests are predicated on the ability to suffer, nothing more, and once it is established that a being has interests, those interests must be given equal consideration.[32] Singer quotes the English philosopher Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900): "The good of any one individual is of no more importance, from the point of view ... of the Universe, than the good of any other."[33]

 
Peter Singer: interests are predicated on the ability to suffer.

Singer argues that equality of consideration is a prescription, not an assertion of fact: if the equality of the sexes were based only on the idea that men and women were equally intelligent, we would have to abandon the practice of equal consideration if this were later found to be false. But the moral idea of equality does not depend on matters of fact such as intelligence, physical strength, or moral capacity. Equality therefore cannot be grounded on the outcome of scientific investigations into the intelligence of nonhumans. All that matters is whether they can suffer.[34]

Commentators on all sides of the debate now accept that animals suffer and feel pain, although it was not always so. Bernard Rollin, professor of philosophy, animal sciences, and biomedical sciences at Colorado State University, writes that Descartes's influence continued to be felt until the 1980s. Veterinarians trained in the US before 1989 were taught to ignore pain, he writes, and at least one major veterinary hospital in the 1960s did not stock narcotic analgesics for animal pain control. In his interactions with scientists, he was often asked to "prove" that animals are conscious, and to provide "scientifically acceptable" evidence that they could feel pain.[35]

Scientific publications have made it clear since the 1980s that the majority of researchers do believe animals suffer and feel pain, though it continues to be argued that their suffering may be reduced by an inability to experience the same dread of anticipation as humans or to remember the suffering as vividly.[36] The ability of animals to suffer, even it may vary in severity, is the basis for Singer's application of equal consideration. The problem of animal suffering, and animal consciousness in general, arose primarily because it was argued that animals have no language. Singer writes that, if language were needed to communicate pain, it would often be impossible to know when humans are in pain, though we can observe pain behavior and make a calculated guess based on it. He argues that there is no reason to suppose that the pain behavior of nonhumans would have a different meaning from the pain behavior of humans.[37]

Subjects-of-a-life Edit

 
Tom Regan: animals are subjects-of-a-life.

Tom Regan, professor emeritus of philosophy at North Carolina State University, argues in The Case for Animal Rights (1983) that nonhuman animals are what he calls "subjects-of-a-life", and as such are bearers of rights.[38] He writes that, because the moral rights of humans are based on their possession of certain cognitive abilities, and because these abilities are also possessed by at least some nonhuman animals, such animals must have the same moral rights as humans. Although only humans act as moral agents, both marginal-case humans, such as infants, and at least some nonhumans must have the status of "moral patients".[38]

Moral patients are unable to formulate moral principles, and as such are unable to do right or wrong, even though what they do may be beneficial or harmful. Only moral agents are able to engage in moral action. Animals for Regan have "intrinsic value" as subjects-of-a-life, and cannot be regarded as a means to an end, a view that places him firmly in the abolitionist camp. His theory does not extend to all animals, but only to those that can be regarded as subjects-of-a-life.[38] He argues that all normal mammals of at least one year of age would qualify:

... individuals are subjects-of-a-life if they have beliefs and desires; perception, memory, and a sense of the future, including their own future; an emotional life together with feelings of pleasure and pain; preference- and welfare-interests; the ability to initiate action in pursuit of their desires and goals; a psychophysical identity over time; and an individual welfare in the sense that their experiential life fares well or ill for them, logically independently of their utility for others and logically independently of their being the object of anyone else's interests.[38]

Whereas Singer is primarily concerned with improving the treatment of animals and accepts that, in some hypothetical scenarios, individual animals might be used legitimately to further human or nonhuman ends, Regan believes we ought to treat nonhuman animals as we would humans. He applies the strict Kantian ideal (which Kant himself applied only to humans) that they ought never to be sacrificed as a means to an end, and must be treated as ends in themselves.[39]

Abolitionism Edit

 
Gary Francione: animals need only the right not to be regarded as property.

Gary Francione, professor of law and philosophy at Rutgers Law School in Newark, is a leading abolitionist writer, arguing that animals need only one right, the right not to be owned. Everything else would follow from that paradigm shift. He writes that, although most people would condemn the mistreatment of animals, and in many countries there are laws that seem to reflect those concerns, "in practice the legal system allows any use of animals, however abhorrent." The law only requires that any suffering not be "unnecessary". In deciding what counts as "unnecessary", an animal's interests are weighed against the interests of human beings, and the latter almost always prevail.[40]

Francione's Animals, Property, and the Law (1995) was the first extensive jurisprudential treatment of animal rights. In it, Francione compares the situation of animals to the treatment of slaves in the United States, where legislation existed that appeared to protect them while the courts ignored that the institution of slavery itself rendered the protection unenforceable.[41] He offers as an example the United States Animal Welfare Act, which he describes as an example of symbolic legislation, intended to assuage public concern about the treatment of animals, but difficult to implement.[42]

He argues that a focus on animal welfare, rather than animal rights, may worsen the position of animals by making the public feel comfortable about using them and entrenching the view of them as property. He calls animal rights groups who pursue animal welfare issues, such as People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, the "new welfarists", arguing that they have more in common with 19th-century animal protectionists than with the animal rights movement; indeed, the terms "animal protection" and "protectionism" are increasingly favored. His position in 1996 was that there is no animal rights movement in the United States.[43]

Contractarianism Edit

Mark Rowlands, professor of philosophy at the University of Florida, has proposed a contractarian approach, based on the original position and the veil of ignorance—a "state of nature" thought experiment that tests intuitions about justice and fairness—in John Rawls's A Theory of Justice (1971). In the original position, individuals choose principles of justice (what kind of society to form, and how primary social goods will be distributed), unaware of their individual characteristics—their race, sex, class, or intelligence, whether they are able-bodied or disabled, rich or poor—and therefore unaware of which role they will assume in the society they are about to form.[29]

The idea is that, operating behind the veil of ignorance, they will choose a social contract in which there is basic fairness and justice for them no matter the position they occupy. Rawls did not include species membership as one of the attributes hidden from the decision-makers in the original position. Rowlands proposes extending the veil of ignorance to include rationality, which he argues is an undeserved property similar to characteristics including race, sex and intelligence.[29]

Prima facie rights theory Edit

American philosopher Timothy Garry has proposed an approach that deems nonhuman animals worthy of prima facie rights. In a philosophical context, a prima facie (Latin for "on the face of it" or "at first glance") right is one that appears to be applicable at first glance, but upon closer examination may be outweighed by other considerations. In his book Ethics: A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory, Lawrence Hinman characterizes such rights as "the right is real but leaves open the question of whether it is applicable and overriding in a particular situation".[44] The idea that nonhuman animals are worthy of prima facie rights is to say that, in a sense, animals have rights that can be overridden by many other considerations, especially those conflicting a human's right to life, liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness. Garry supports his view arguing:

... if a nonhuman animal were to kill a human being in the U.S., it would have broken the laws of the land and would probably get rougher sanctions than if it were a human. My point is that like laws govern all who interact within a society, rights are to be applied to all beings who interact within that society. This is not to say these rights endowed by humans are equivalent to those held by nonhuman animals, but rather that if humans possess rights then so must all those who interact with humans.[45]

In sum, Garry suggests that humans have obligations to nonhuman animals; animals do not, and ought not to, have uninfringible rights against humans.

Feminism and animal rights Edit

 
The American ecofeminist Carol Adams has written extensively about the link between feminism and animal rights, starting with The Sexual Politics of Meat (1990).

Women have played a central role in animal advocacy since the 19th century.[46] The anti-vivisection movement in the 19th and early 20th century in England and the United States was largely run by women, including Frances Power Cobbe, Anna Kingsford, Lizzy Lind af Hageby and Caroline Earle White (1833–1916).[47] Garner writes that 70 per cent of the membership of the Victoria Street Society (one of the anti-vivisection groups founded by Cobbe) were women, as were 70 per cent of the membership of the British RSPCA in 1900.[48]

The modern animal advocacy movement has a similar representation of women. They are not invariably in leadership positions: during the March for Animals in Washington, D.C., in 1990—the largest animal rights demonstration held until then in the United States—most of the participants were women, but most of the platform speakers were men.[49] Nevertheless, several influential animal advocacy groups have been founded by women, including the British Union for the Abolition of Vivisection by Cobbe in London in 1898; the Animal Welfare Board of India by Rukmini Devi Arundale in 1962; and People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, co-founded by Ingrid Newkirk in 1980. In the Netherlands, Marianne Thieme and Esther Ouwehand were elected to parliament in 2006 representing the Parliamentary group for Animals.

The preponderance of women in the movement has led to a body of academic literature exploring feminism and animal rights, such as feminism and vegetarianism or veganism, the oppression of women and animals, and the male association of women and animals with nature and emotion, rather than reason—an association that several feminist writers have embraced.[46] Lori Gruen writes that women and animals serve the same symbolic function in a patriarchal society: both are "the used"; the dominated, submissive "Other".[50] When the British feminist Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–1797) published A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792), Thomas Taylor (1758–1835), a Cambridge philosopher, responded with an anonymous parody, A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes (1792), saying that Wollstonecraft's arguments for women's rights could be applied equally to animals, a position he intended as reductio ad absurdum.[51] In her works The Sexual Politics of Meat: A Feminist-Vegetarian Critical Theory (1990) and The Pornography of Meat (2004), Carol J. Adams focuses in particular on what she argues are the links between the oppression of women and that of non-human animals.[52]

Transhumanism Edit

Some transhumanists argue for animal rights, liberation, and "uplift" of animal consciousness into machines.[53] Transhumanism also understands animal rights on a gradation or spectrum with other types of sentient rights, including human rights and the rights of conscious artificial intelligences (posthuman rights).[54]

Socialism and anti-capitalism Edit

According to sociologist David Nibert of Wittenberg University, the struggle for animal liberation must happen in tandem with a more generalized struggle against human oppression and exploitation under global capitalism. He says that under a more egalitarian democratic socialist system, one that would "allow a more just and peaceful order to emerge" and be "characterized by economic democracy and a democratically controlled state and mass media", there would be "much greater potential to inform the public about vital global issues—and the potential for "campaigns to improve the lives of other animals" to be "more abolitionist in nature."[55] Philosopher Steven Best of the University of Texas at El Paso states that the animal liberation movement, as characterized by the Animal Liberation Front and its various offshoots, "is a significant threat to global capital."

... Animal liberation challenges large sectors of the capitalist economy by assailing corporate agriculture and pharmaceutical companies and their suppliers. Far from being irrelevant to social movements, animal rights can form the basis for a broad coalition of progressive social groups and drive changes that strike at the heart of capitalist exploitation of animals, people and the earth.[56]

Critics Edit

R. G. Frey Edit

R. G. Frey, professor of philosophy at Bowling Green State University, is a preference utilitarian. In his early work, Interests and Rights (1980), Frey disagreed with Singer—who wrote in Animal Liberation (1975) that the interests of nonhuman animals must be given equal consideration when judging the consequences of an act—on the grounds that animals have no interests. Frey argues that interests are dependent on desire, and that no desire can exist without a corresponding belief. Animals have no beliefs, because a belief state requires the ability to hold a second-order belief—a belief about the belief—which he argues requires language: "If someone were to say, e.g. 'The cat believes that the door is locked,' then that person is holding, as I see it, that the cat holds the declarative sentence 'The door is locked' to be true; and I can see no reason whatever for crediting the cat or any other creature which lacks language, including human infants, with entertaining declarative sentences."[57]

Carl Cohen Edit

Carl Cohen, professor of philosophy at the University of Michigan, argues that rights holders must be able to distinguish between their own interests and what is right. "The holders of rights must have the capacity to comprehend rules of duty governing all, including themselves. In applying such rules, [they] ... must recognize possible conflicts between what is in their own interest and what is just. Only in a community of beings capable of self-restricting moral judgments can the concept of a right be correctly invoked." Cohen rejects Singer's argument that, since a brain-damaged human could not make moral judgments, moral judgments cannot be used as the distinguishing characteristic for determining who is awarded rights. Cohen writes that the test for moral judgment "is not a test to be administered to humans one by one", but should be applied to the capacity of members of the species in general.[58]

Richard Posner Edit

 
Judge Richard Posner: "facts will drive equality."[59]

Judge Richard Posner of the United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit debated the issue of animal rights in 2001 with Peter Singer.[60] Posner posits that his moral intuition tells him "that human beings prefer their own. If a dog threatens a human infant, even if it requires causing more pain to the dog to stop it, than the dog would have caused to the infant, then we favour the child. It would be monstrous to spare the dog."[59]

Singer challenges this by arguing that formerly unequal rights for gays, women, and certain races were justified using the same set of intuitions. Posner replies that equality in civil rights did not occur because of ethical arguments, but because facts mounted that there were no morally significant differences between humans based on race, sex, or sexual orientation that would support inequality. If and when similar facts emerge about humans and animals, the differences in rights will erode too. But facts will drive equality, not ethical arguments that run contrary to instinct, he argues. Posner calls his approach "soft utilitarianism", in contrast to Singer's "hard utilitarianism". He argues:

The "soft" utilitarian position on animal rights is a moral intuition of many, probably most, Americans. We realize that animals feel pain, and we think that to inflict pain without a reason is bad. Nothing of practical value is added by dressing up this intuition in the language of philosophy; much is lost when the intuition is made a stage in a logical argument. When kindness toward animals is levered into a duty of weighting the pains of animals and of people equally, bizarre vistas of social engineering are opened up.[59]

 
Roger Scruton: rights imply obligations.

Roger Scruton Edit

Roger Scruton, the British philosopher, argued that rights imply obligations. Every legal privilege, he wrote, imposes a burden on the one who does not possess that privilege: that is, "your right may be my duty." Scruton therefore regarded the emergence of the animal rights movement as "the strangest cultural shift within the liberal worldview", because the idea of rights and responsibilities is, he argued, distinctive to the human condition, and it makes no sense to spread them beyond our own species.[13]

He accused animal rights advocates of "pre-scientific" anthropomorphism, attributing traits to animals that are, he says, Beatrix Potter-like, where "only man is vile." It is within this fiction that the appeal of animal rights lies, he argued. The world of animals is non-judgmental, filled with dogs who return our affection almost no matter what we do to them, and cats who pretend to be affectionate when, in fact, they care only about themselves. It is, he argued, a fantasy, a world of escape.[13]

Scruton singled out Peter Singer, a prominent Australian philosopher and animal-rights activist, for criticism. He wrote that Singer's works, including Animal Liberation, "contain little or no philosophical argument. They derive their radical moral conclusions from a vacuous utilitarianism that counts the pain and pleasure of all living things as equally significant and that ignores just about everything that has been said in our philosophical tradition about the real distinction between persons and animals."[13]

Tom Regan countered this view of rights by distinguishing moral agents and moral patients.[61][unreliable source?]

Public attitudes Edit

According to a paper published in 2000 by Harold Herzog and Lorna Dorr, previous academic surveys of attitudes towards animal rights have tended to suffer from small sample sizes and non-representative groups.[62] However, a number of factors appear to correlate with the attitude of individuals regarding the treatment of animals and animal rights. These include gender, age, occupation, religion, and level of education. There has also been evidence to suggest that prior experience with pets may be a factor in people's attitudes.[63]

According to some studies, women are more likely to empathize with the cause of animal rights than men.[63][64] A 1996 study suggested that factors that may partially explain this discrepancy include attitudes towards feminism and science, scientific literacy, and the presence of a greater emphasis on "nurturance or compassion" among women.[65]

A common misconception on the concept of animal rights is that its proponents want to grant non-human animals the exact same legal rights as humans, such as the right to vote. This is not the case, as the concept is that animals should have rights with equal consideration to their interests (for example, cats do not have any interest in voting, so they should not have the right to vote).[66] A 2016 study found that support for animal testing may not be based on cogent philosophical rationales, and more open debate is warranted.[67]

A 2007 survey to examine whether or not people who believed in evolution were more likely to support animal rights than creationists and believers in intelligent design found that this was largely the case—according to the researchers, the respondents who were strong Christian fundamentalists and believers in creationism were less likely to advocate for animal rights than those who were less fundamentalist in their beliefs. The findings extended previous research, such as a 1992 study which found that 48% of animal rights activists were atheists or agnostic.[68][69] A 2019 study in The Washington Post found that those who have positive attitudes toward animal rights also tend to have a positive view of universal healthcare, favor reducing discrimination against African Americans, the LGBT community and undocumented immigrants, and expanding welfare to aid the poor.[70]

Two surveys found that attitudes towards animal rights tactics, such as direct action, are very diverse within the animal rights communities. Near half (50% and 39% in two surveys) of activists do not support direct action. One survey concluded "it would be a mistake to portray animal rights activists as homogeneous."[63][71]

See also Edit

References Edit

  1. ^ Kumar, Satish (September 2002). You are, therefore I am: A declaration of dependence. Bloomsbury USA. ISBN 9781903998182.
  2. ^ DeGrazia (2002), ch. 2; Taylor (2009), ch. 1.
  3. ^ Taylor (2009), ch. 3.
  4. ^ Compare for example similar usage of the term in 1938: The American Biology Teacher. Vol. 53. National Association of Biology Teachers. 1938. p. 211. Retrieved 16 April 2021. The foundation from which these behaviors spring is the ideology known as speciesism. Speciesism is deeply rooted in the widely-held belief that the human species is entitled to certain rights and privileges.
  5. ^ Horta (2010).
  6. ^ That a central goal of animal rights is to eliminate the property status of animals, see Sunstein (2004), p. 11ff.
    • For speciesism and fundamental protections, see Waldau (2011).
    • For food, clothing, research subjects or entertainment, see Francione (1995), p. 17.
  7. ^ "Animal Law Courses". Animal Legal Defense Fund. from the original on 2020-12-04. Retrieved 2020-12-13.
  8. ^ For animal-law courses in North America, see "Animal law courses" 2010-06-13 at the Wayback Machine, Animal Legal Defense Fund. Retrieved July 12, 2012.
    • For a discussion of animals and personhood, see Wise (2000), pp. 4, 59, 248ff; Wise (2004); Posner (2004); Wise (2007) 2008-06-14 at the Wayback Machine.
    • For the arguments and counter-arguments about awarding personhood only to great apes, see Garner (2005), p. 22.
    • Also see Sunstein, Cass R. (February 20, 2000). "The Chimps' Day in Court" 2017-05-01 at the Wayback Machine, The New York Times.
  9. ^ Giménez, Emiliano (January 4, 2015). "Argentine orangutan granted unprecedented legal rights". edition.cnn.com. CNN Espanol. from the original on April 3, 2021. Retrieved April 21, 2015.
  10. ^ Cohen, Carl; Regan, Tom (2001). The Animal Rights Debate. Point/Counterpoint: Philosophers Debate Contemporary Issues Series. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. p. 47. ISBN 9780847696628. Retrieved 16 April 2021. Too often overlooked in the animal world, according to Sapontzis, are insects that have interests, and therefore rights.
  11. ^ The concept of "bacteria rights" can appear coupled with disdain or irony: Pluhar, Evelyn B. (1995). "Human "superiority" and the argument from marginal cases". Beyond Prejudice: The Moral Significance of Human and Nonhuman Animals. Book collections on Project MUSE. Durham, North Carolina: Duke University Press. p. 9. ISBN 9780822316480. Retrieved 16 April 2021. For example, in an editorial entitled 'Animal Rights Nonsense,' ... in the prestigious science journal Nature, defenders of animal rights are accused of being committed to the absurdity of 'bacteria rights.'
  12. ^ Jakopovich, Daniel (2021). "The UK's Animal Welfare (Sentience) Bill Excludes the Vast Majority of Animals: Why We Must Expand Our Moral Circle to Include Invertebrates". Animals & Society Research Initiative, University of Victoria, Canada. from the original on 2022-11-29. Retrieved 2022-06-18.
  13. ^ a b c d Scruton, Roger (Summer 2000). "Animal Rights". City Journal. New York: Manhattan Institute for Policy Research.
  14. ^ Liguori, G.; et al. (2017). "Ethical Issues in the Use of Animal Models for Tissue Engineering: Reflections on Legal Aspects, Moral Theory, 3Rs Strategies, and Harm-Benefit Analysis" (PDF). Tissue Engineering Part C: Methods. 23 (12): 850–862. doi:10.1089/ten.TEC.2017.0189. PMID 28756735. S2CID 206268293. (PDF) from the original on 2020-09-15. Retrieved 2019-07-12.
  15. ^ Garner (2005), pp. 11, 16.
    • Also see Frey (1980); and for a review of Frey, see Sprigge (1981) 2016-02-19 at the Wayback Machine.
  16. ^ Singer (2000), pp. 151–156.
  17. ^ Martin, Gus (15 June 2011). The SAGE Encyclopedia of Terrorism, Second Edition. SAGE. ISBN 9781412980166 – via Google Books.
  18. ^ Garner (2005), pp. 21–22.
  19. ^ a b Grant, Catharine (2006). The No-nonsense Guide to Animal Rights. New Internationalist. p. 24. ISBN 9781904456407. These religions emphasize ahimsa, which is the principle of non-violence towards all living things. The first precept is a prohibition against the killing of any creature. The Jain, Hindu and Buddhist injunctions against killing serve to teach that all creatures are spiritually equal.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  20. ^ Meenakshi Sundaram, T. P. (1957). "Vegetarianism in Tamil Literature". 15th World Vegetarian Congress 1957. International Vegetarian Union (IVU). from the original on 22 January 2022. Retrieved 17 April 2022. Ahimsa is the ruling principle of Indian life from the very earliest times. ... This positive spiritual attitude is easily explained to the common man in a negative way as "ahimsa" and hence this way of denoting it. Tiruvalluvar speaks of this as "kollaamai" or "non-killing."
  21. ^ "BBC - Religions - Islam: Animals". bbc.co.uk. from the original on 2020-02-04. Retrieved 2019-12-20.
  22. ^ Proverbs 30:24 and NW; Psalm 104:24, 25, 27, 28
  23. ^ Ps 147:9
  24. ^ Craig (1988).
  25. ^ Nussbaum (2006), pp. 388ff, 393ff; also see Nussbaum (2004), p. 299ff.
  26. ^ Weir (2009): see Clark (1977); Rollin (1981); Midgley (1984).
  27. ^ Vallentyne (2005) 2016-04-13 at the Wayback Machine; Vallentyne (2007).
  28. ^ Rowlands (2009), p. 98ff; Hursthouse (2000a); Hursthouse (2000b), p. 146ff.
  29. ^ a b c Rowlands (1998), p. 118ff, particularly pp. 147–152.
  30. ^ Nussbaum (2004), p. 302.
  31. ^ For a discussion of preference utilitarianism, see Singer (2011), pp. 14ff, 94ff.
  32. ^ Singer (1990), pp. 7–8.
  33. ^ Singer 1990, p. 5.
  34. ^ Singer (1990), p. 4.
  35. ^ Rollin (1989), pp. xii, pp. 117–118; Rollin (2007) 2020-07-28 at the Wayback Machine.
  36. ^ Singer (1990), pp. 10–17, citing Stamp Dawkins (1980), Walker (1983), and Griffin (1984); Garner (2005), pp. 13–14.
  37. ^ Singer (1990) p. 12ff.
  38. ^ a b c d Regan (1983), p. 243.
  39. ^ Regan (1983).
  40. ^ Francione (1990), pp. 4, 17ff.
  41. ^ Francione (1995), pp. 4–5.
  42. ^ Francione (1995), p. 208ff.
  43. ^ Francione (1996), p. 32ff
    • Francione and Garner (2010), pp. 1ff, 175ff.
    • Hall, Lee. "An Interview with Professor Gary L. Francione" May 8, 2009, at the Wayback Machine, Friends of Animals. Retrieved February 3, 2011.
  44. ^ Hinman, Lawrence M. Ethics: A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace College, 1998. Print.
  45. ^ Garry, Timothy J. Nonhuman Animals: Possessors of Prima Facie Rights (2012), p.6
  46. ^ a b Lansbury (1985); Adams (1990); Donovan (1993); Gruen (1993); Adams (1994); Adams and Donovan (1995); Adams (2004); MacKinnon (2004).
  47. ^ Kean (1995) 2020-04-13 at the Wayback Machine.
  48. ^ Garner (2005), p. 141, citing Elston (1990), p. 276.
  49. ^ Garner (2005), pp. 142–143.
  50. ^ Gruen (1993), p. 60ff.
  51. ^ Singer (1990), p. 1.
  52. ^ Green, Elizabeth W. (10 October 2003). "Fifteen Questions For Carol J. Adams". The Harvard Crimson. Retrieved 22 November 2008.
  53. ^ George Dvorsky. "The Ethics of Animal Enhancement". from the original on 2017-04-25. Retrieved 2017-04-24.
  54. ^ Evans, Woody (2015). "Posthuman Rights: Dimensions of Transhuman Worlds". Teknokultura. 12 (2). doi:10.5209/rev_TK.2015.v12.n2.49072.
  55. ^ Nibert 2013, p. 270.
  56. ^ Best 2014, p. 103.
  57. ^ Frey (1989), p. 40.
  58. ^ pg. 94-100 2011-11-27 at the Wayback Machine. Cohen and Regan (2001).
  59. ^ a b c Posner (June 15, 2001) August 21, 2011, at the Wayback Machine; Posner-Singer debate in full 2015-05-09 at the Wayback Machine, courtesy link on utilitarian.net.
    • Also see Posner (2004).
  60. ^ Singer (June 15, 2001) September 14, 2017, at the Wayback Machine.
  61. ^ "Tom Regan: The Case For Animal Rights". The Vegetarian Site. from the original on November 2, 2019. Retrieved November 2, 2019.
  62. ^ Herzog, Harold; Dorr, Lorna (2000). "Electronically Available Surveys of Attitudes Toward Animals". Society & Animals. 10 (2).
  63. ^ a b c Apostol, L.; Rebega, O.L.; Miclea, M. (2013). "Psychological and Socio-Demographic Predictors of Attitudes towards Animals". Social and Behavioural Sciences (78): 521–525.
  64. ^ Herzog, Harold (2007). "Gender Differences in Human-Animal Interactions: A Review". Anthrozoös. 20 (1): 7–21. doi:10.2752/089279307780216687. S2CID 14988443.
  65. ^ Pifer, Linda (1996). "Exploring the Gender Gap in Young Adults' Attitudes about Animal Research" (PDF). Society and Animals. 4 (1): 37–52. doi:10.1163/156853096X00034. PMID 11654528. (PDF) from the original on 2021-09-17. Retrieved 2021-06-04.
  66. ^ "Ethics - Animal ethics: Animal rights". BBC Online. from the original on March 24, 2022. Retrieved February 10, 2022.
  67. ^ Joffe, Ari R.; Bara, Meredith; Anton, Natalie; Nobis, Nathan (March 29, 2016). "The ethics of animal research: a survey of the public and scientists in North America". BMC Medical Ethics. 17: 17. doi:10.1186/s12910-016-0100-x. ISSN 1472-6939. PMC 4812627. PMID 27025215.
  68. ^ DeLeeuwa, Jamie; Galen, Luke; Aebersold, Cassandra; Stanton, Victoria (2007). (PDF). Society and Animals (15): 353–363. Archived from the original (PDF) on June 20, 2013.
  69. ^ Galvin, Shelley L.; Herzog, Harold A. Jr. (1992). "Ethical Ideology, Animal Rights Activism, And Attitudes Toward The Treatment Of Animals". Ethics & Behavior. 2 (3): 141–149. doi:10.1207/s15327019eb0203_1. PMID 11651362. from the original on 2020-05-31. Retrieved 2020-08-29.
  70. ^ Park, Yon Soo; Valentino, Benjamin (July 26, 2019). "Who supports animal rights? Here's what we found". The Washington Post. from the original on July 26, 2019. Retrieved July 26, 2019.
  71. ^ Plous, S. (1991). "An attitude survey of animal rights activists". Psychological Science. 2 (3): 194–196. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1991.tb00131.x. S2CID 145549994.

Bibliography Edit

Books and papers are cited in short form in the footnotes, with full citations here. News and other sources are cited in full in the footnotes.

  • Adams, Carol J. (1996). The Sexual Politics of Meat: A Feminist-Vegetarian Critical Theory. Continuum. ISBN 1501312839
  • Adams, Carol J.; Donovan, Josephine, eds. (1995). Animals and Women: Feminist Theoretical Explorations. Duke University Press. ISBN 0822316552
  • Adams, Carol J. (2004). The Pornography of Meat. Continuum. ISBN 9781590565100
  • Benthall, Jonathan (2007). "Animal liberation and rights", Anthropology Today, volume 23, issue 2, April.
  • Bentham, Jeremy (1781). Principles of Penal Law. ISBN 1379912326
  • Beauchamp, Tom (2009). "The Moral Standing of Animals", in Marc Bekoff. Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare. Greenwood. ISBN 0313352593
  • Beauchamp, Tom (2011a). "Introduction," in Tom Beauchamp and R.G. Frey (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 019935197X
  • Beauchamp, Tom (2011b). "Rights Theory and Animal Rights," in Beauchamp and Frey, op cit. ISBN 019935197X
  • Best, Steven (2014). The Politics of Total Liberation: Revolution for the 21st Century. Palgrave Macmillan. doi:10.1057/9781137440723. ISBN 978-1137471116.
  • Clark, Stephen R. L. (1977). The Moral Status of Animals. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0192830406
  • Cohen, Carl (1986). "The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research" 2011-11-27 at the Wayback Machine, New England Journal of Medicine, vol. 315, issue 14, October, pp. 865–870.
  • Cohen, Carl and Regan, Tom (2001). The Animal Rights Debate. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 0847696626
  • Craig, Edward (ed.) (1988). "Deontological Ethics" and "Consequentalism." Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • DeGrazia, David (2002). Animal Rights: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.
  • Donovan, Josephine (1993). "Animal Rights and Feminist Theory," in Greta Gaard. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Temple University Press.
  • Francione, Gary (1996). Rain Without Thunder: The Ideology of the Animal Rights Movement. Temple University Press.
  • Francione, Gary (1995). Animals, Property, and the Law. Temple University Press.
  • Francione, Gary (2008). Animals as Persons. Columbia University Press.
  • Francione, Gary and Garner, Robert (2010). The Animal Rights Debate: Abolition Or Regulation? Columbia University Press.
  • Fellenz, Mark R. (2007). The Moral Menagerie: Philosophy and Animal Rights. University of Illinois Press.
  • Frey, R.G. (1980). Interests and Rights: The Case against Animals. Clarendon Press.
  • Frey, R.G. (1989). "Why Animals Lack Beliefs and Desires," in Peter Singer and Tom Regan (eds.). Animal Rights and Human Obligations. Prentice Hall.
  • Garner, Robert (2004). Animals, Politics and Morality. Manchester University Press.
  • Garner, Robert (2005). The Political Theory of Animals Rights. Manchester University Press.
  • Giannelli, Michael A. (1985). "Three Blind Mice, See How They Run: A Critique of Behavioral Research With Animals". In M.W. Fox & L.D. Mickley (eds.), Advances in Animal Welfare Science 1985/1986 (pp. 109–164). Washington, DC: The Humane Society of the United States
  • Gruen, Lori (1993). "Dismantling Oppression: An Analysis of the Connection Between Women and Animals", in Greta Gaard. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Temple University Press.
  • Griffin, Donald (1984). Animal Thinking. Harvard University Press.
  • Horta, Oscar (2010). "What Is Speciesism?", The Journal of Environmental and Agricultural Ethics, Vol. 23, No. 3, June, pp. 243–266.
  • Hursthouse, Rosalind (2000a). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.
  • Hursthouse, Rosalind (2000b). Ethics, Humans and Other Animals. Routledge.
  • Jakopovich, Daniel (2021). "The UK's Animal Welfare (Sentience) Bill Excludes the Vast Majority of Animals: Why We Must Expand Our Moral Circle to Include Invertebrates" 2022-11-29 at the Wayback Machine, Animals & Society Research Initiative, University of Victoria, Canada.
  • Kant, Immanuel (1785). Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals.
  • Kean, Hilda (1995). "The 'Smooth Cool Men of Science': The Feminist and Socialist Response to Vivisection" 2020-04-13 at the Wayback Machine, History Workshop Journal, No. 40 (Autumn), pp. 16–38.
  • Kelch, Thomas G. (2011). Globalization and Animal Law. Kluwer Law International.
  • Lansbury, Coral (1985). The Old Brown Dog: Women, Workers, and Vivisection in Edwardian England. University of Wisconsin Press.
  • Legge, Debbi and Brooman, Simon (1997). Law Relating to Animals. Cavendish Publishing. ISBN 1859412386
  • Leneman, Leah (1999). "No Animal Food: The Road to Veganism in Britain, 1909–1944," Society and Animals, 7, 1–5.
  • Locke, John (1693). Some Thoughts Concerning Education.
  • MacKinnon, Catharine A. (2004). "Of Mice and Men," in Nussbaum and Sunstein, op cit.
  • Mason, Peter (1997). The Brown Dog Affair. Two Sevens Publishing.
  • Midgley, Mary (1984). Animals and Why They Matter. University of Georgia Press. ISBN 0820320412
  • Molland, Neil (2004). "Thirty Years of Direct Action" in Best and Nocella, op cit.
  • Monaghan, Rachael (2000). "Terrorism in the Name of Animal Rights," in Taylor, Maxwell and Horgan, John. The Future of Terrorism. Routledge.
  • Murray, L. (2006). "The ASPCA–Pioneers in Animal Welfare" 2011-07-26 at the Wayback Machine, Encyclopædia Britannica's Advocacy for Animals.
  • Nash, Roderick (1989). The Rights of Nature: A History of Environmental Ethics. University of Wisconsin Press.
  • Newkirk, Ingrid (2004). "The ALF: Who, Why, and What?", in Steven Best and Anthony Nocella. (eds).Terrorists or Freedom Fighters? Reflections on the Liberation of Animals. Lantern 2004.
  • Nibert, David (2013). Animal Oppression and Human Violence: Domesecration, Capitalism, and Global Conflict. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0231151894. from the original on 2022-11-04. Retrieved 2022-09-14.
  • Nussbaum, Martha (2004). "Beyond Compassion and Humanity: Justice for Nonhuman Animals", in Cass Sunstein and Martha Nussbaum (eds.). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press.
  • Nussbaum, Martha (2006). Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Belknap Press.
  • Posner, Richard and Singer, Peter (June 15, 2001). Posner-Singer debate 2017-09-14 at the Wayback Machine, Slate.
  • Posner, Richard and Singer, Peter (2004). "Animal rights" in Sunstein and Nussbaum, op cit.
  • Rachels, James (2009). "Darwin, Charles," in Bekoff, op cit.
  • Redclift, Michael R. (2010). The International Handbook of Environmental Sociology. Edward Elgar Publishing.
  • Regan, Tom (1983). The Case for Animal Rights. University of California Press.
  • Regan, Tom (2001). Defending Animal Rights. University of Illinois Press.
  • Rollin, Bernard (1981). Animal Rights and Human Morality. Prometheus Books.
  • Rollin, Bernard (1989). The Unheeded Cry: Animal Consciousness, Animal Pain, and Science. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Rollin, Bernard (2007). "Animal research: a moral science" 2020-07-28 at the Wayback Machine, Nature, EMBO Reports 8, 6, pp. 521–525.
  • Rowlands, Mark (2009) [1998]. Animal Rights. A Defense. Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Ryder, Richard (2000) [1989]. Animal Revolution: Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism. Berg.
  • Sapontzis, Steve (1985). "Moral Community and Animal Rights" 2016-04-13 at the Wayback Machine, American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 22, No. 3 (July), pp. 251–257.
  • Scruton, Roger (1998). Animal Rights and Wrongs. Claridge Press.
  • Scruton, Roger (2000). "Animal Rights" 2016-03-03 at the Wayback Machine, City Journal, summer.
  • Singer, Peter (April 5, 1973). "Animal liberation" 2010-02-24 at the Wayback Machine, The New York Review of Books, Volume 20, Number 5.
  • Singer, Peter (1990) [1975]. Animal Liberation. New York Review Books.
  • Singer, Peter (2000) [1998]. Ethics into Action: Henry Spira and the Animal Rights Movement. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
  • Singer, Peter (2003). "Animal liberation at 30" 2010-03-30 at the Wayback Machine, The New York Review of Books, vol 50, no. 8, May 15.
  • Singer, Peter (2004). "Ethics Beyond Species and Beyond Instincts," in Sunstein and Nussbaum, op cit.
  • Singer, Peter (2011) [1979]. Practical Ethics. Cambridge University Press.
  • Sprigge, T.L.S. (1981) "Interests and Rights: The Case against Animals" 2016-02-19 at the Wayback Machine, Journal of Medical Ethics. June, 7(2): 95–102.
  • Stamp Dawkins, Marian (1980). Animal Suffering: The Science of Animal Welfare. Chapman and Hall.
  • Stucki, Saskia (2020) "Towards a Theory of Legal Animal Rights: Simple and Fundamental Rights" 2021-01-09 at the Wayback Machine, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 40:533-560.
  • Sunstein, Cass R. (2004). "Introduction: What are Animal Rights?" in Sunstein and Nussbaum, op cit.
  • Sunstein, Cass R. and Nussbaum, Martha (2005). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0195305108
  • Taylor, Angus (2009). Animals and Ethics: An Overview of the Philosophical Debate. Broadview Press.
  • Taylor, Thomas (1792). "A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes," in Craciun, Adriana (2002). A Routledge Literary Sourcebook on Mary Wollstonecraft's A Vindication of the Rights of Woman. Routledge.
  • Vallentyne, Peter (2005). "Of Mice and Men: Equality and Animals" 2016-04-13 at the Wayback Machine, The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 9, No. 3/4, pp. 403–433.
  • Vallentyne, Peter (2007). "Of Mice and Men: Equality and Animals" in Nils Holtug, and Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen (eds.) (2007). Egalitarianism: New Essays on the Nature and Value of Equality. Oxford University Press.
  • Waldau, Paul (2011). Animal Rights: What Everyone Needs to Know. Oxford University Press.
  • Walker, Stephen (1983). Animal Thoughts. Routledge.
  • Weir, Jack (2009). "Virtue Ethics," in Marc Bekoff. Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare. Greenwood. ISBN 0313352593
  • Williams, Erin E. and DeMello, Margo (2007). Why Animals Matter. Prometheus Books.
  • Wise, Steven M. (2000). Rattling the Cage: Toward Legal Rights for Animals. Da Capo Press.
  • Wise, Steven M. (2002). Drawing the Line: Science and the Case for Animal Rights. Perseus.
  • Wise, Steven M. (2004). "Animal Rights, One Step at a Time," in Sunstein and Nussbaum, op cit.
  • Wise, Steven M. (2007). "Animal Rights" 2008-11-18 at the Wayback Machine, Encyclopædia Britannica.

Further reading Edit

  • Lubinski, Joseph (2002). "Overview Summary of Animal Rights", The Animal Legal and Historical Center at Michigan State University College of Law.
  • , The Animal Legal and Historical Center at Michigan State University College of Law.
  • Bekoff, Marc (ed.) (2009). The Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare. Greenwood.
  • Best, Steven and Nocella II, Anthony J. (eds). (2004). Terrorists or Freedom Fighters? Reflections on the Liberation of Animals. Lantern Books
  • Chapouthier, Georges and Nouët, Jean-Claude (eds.) (1998). The Universal Declaration of Animal Rights. Ligue Française des Droits de l'Animal.
  • Dawkins, Richard (1993). Gaps in the mind, in Cavalieri, Paola and Singer, Peter (eds.). The Great Ape Project. St. Martin's Griffin.
  • Dombrowski, Daniel (1997). Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases. University of Illinois Press.
  • Favre, David S. (2018). Respecting Animals: A Balanced Approach to Our Relationship with Pets, Food, and Wildlife. Prometheus. ISBN 978-1633884250.
  • Foltz, Richard (2006). Animals in Islamic Tradition and Muslim Cultures. Oneworld Publications.
  • Franklin, Julian H. (2005). Animal Rights and Moral Philosophy. University of Columbia Press.
  • Gruen, Lori (2003). "The Moral Status of Animals", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, July 1, 2003.
  • Gruen, Lori (2011). Ethics and Animals. Cambridge University Press.
  • Hall, Lee (2006). Capers in the Churchyard: Animal Rights Advocacy in the Age of Terror. Nectar Bat Press.
  • Linzey, Andrew and Clarke, Paul A. B.(eds.) (1990). Animal Rights: A Historic Anthology. Columbia University Press.
  • Mann, Keith (2007). From Dusk 'til Dawn: An Insider's View of the Growth of the Animal Liberation Movement. Puppy Pincher Press.
  • McArthur, Jo-Anne and Wilson, Keith (eds). (2020). Hidden: Animals in the Anthropocene. Lantern Publishing & Media.
  • Neumann, Jean-Marc (2012). "The Universal Declaration of Animal Rights or the Creation of a New Equilibrium between Species". Animal Law Review volume 19–1.
  • Nibert, David (2002). Animal Rights, Human Rights: Entanglements of Oppression and Liberation. Rowman and Litterfield.
  • Nibert, David, ed. (2017). Animal Oppression and Capitalism. Praeger Publishing. ISBN 978-1440850738.
  • Patterson, Charles (2002). Eternal Treblinka: Our Treatment of Animals and the Holocaust. Lantern.
  • Rachels, James (1990). Created from Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism. Oxford University Press.
  • Regan, Tom and Singer, Peter (eds.) (1976). Animal Rights and Human Obligations. Prentice-Hall.
  • Spiegel, Marjorie (1996). The Dreaded Comparison: Human and Animal Slavery. Mirror Books.
  • Sztybel, David (2006). "Can the Treatment of Animals Be Compared to the Holocaust?" Ethics and the Environment 11 (Spring): 97–132.
  • Tobias, Michael (2000). Life Force: The World of Jainism. Asian Humanities Press.
  • Wilson, Scott (2010). "Animals and Ethics" Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Kymlicka, W., Donaldson, S. (2011) Zoopolis. A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford University Press.

animal, rights, this, article, about, philosophy, animal, rights, current, animal, rights, around, world, country, territory, timeline, animal, rights, timeline, animal, welfare, rights, other, uses, disambiguation, philosophy, according, which, many, sentient. This article is about the philosophy of animal rights For current animal rights around the world see Animal rights by country or territory For a timeline of animal rights see Timeline of animal welfare and rights For other uses see Animal rights disambiguation Animal rights is the philosophy according to which many or all sentient animals have moral worth independent of their utility to humans and that their most basic interests such as avoiding suffering should be afforded the same consideration as similar interests of human beings 2 Broadly speaking and particularly in popular discourse the term animal rights is often used synonymously with animal protection or animal liberation More narrowly animal rights refers to the idea that many animals have fundamental rights to be treated with respect as individuals rights to life liberty and freedom from torture that may not be overridden by considerations of aggregate welfare 3 A man with a captive monkey seeking alms in ShanghaiChickens held inside a battery cage in a factory farmParshwanatha the 23rd Tirthankara revived Jainism and ahimsa in the 9th century BCE which led to a radical animal rights movement in South Asia 1 The c 5th century CE Tamil scholar Valluvar in his Tirukkural taught ahimsa and moral vegetarianism as personal virtues The plaque in this statue of Valluvar at an animal sanctuary in South India describes the Kural s teachings on ahimsa and non killing summing them up with the definition of veganism Many advocates of animal rights oppose the assignment of moral value and fundamental protections on the basis of species membership alone 4 They consider this idea known as speciesism a prejudice as irrational as any other 5 They maintain that animals should not be viewed as property or used as food clothing entertainment or beasts of burden merely because they are not human 6 Multiple cultural traditions around the world such as Jainism Taoism Hinduism Buddhism Shinto and Animism also espouse forms of animal rights In parallel to the debate about moral rights law schools in North America now often teach animal law 7 and several legal scholars such as Steven M Wise and Gary L Francione support the extension of basic legal rights and personhood to non human animals The animals most often considered in arguments for personhood are hominids Some animal rights academics support this because it would break the species barrier but others oppose it because it predicates moral value on mental complexity rather than on sentience alone 8 As of November 2019 update 29 countries had enacted bans on hominoid experimentation Argentina has granted captive orangutans basic human rights since 2014 9 Outside of primates animal rights discussions most often address the status of mammals compare charismatic megafauna Other animals considered less sentient have gained less attention insects relatively little 10 outside Jainism and animal like bacteria hardly any 11 The vast majority of animals have no legally recognised rights 12 Critics of animal rights argue that nonhuman animals are unable to enter into a social contract and thus cannot be possessors of rights a view summarised by the philosopher Roger Scruton who writes that only humans have duties and therefore only humans have rights 13 Another argument associated with the utilitarian tradition maintains that animals may be used as resources so long as there is no unnecessary suffering 14 animals may have some moral standing but any interests they have may be overridden in cases of comparatively greater gains to aggregate welfare made possible by their use though what counts as necessary suffering or a legitimate sacrifice of interests can vary considerably 15 Certain forms of animal rights activism such as the destruction of fur farms and of animal laboratories by the Animal Liberation Front have attracted criticism including from within the animal rights movement itself 16 and prompted the U S Congress to enact laws including the Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act allowing the prosecution of this sort of activity as terrorism 17 Contents 1 History 2 In religion 3 Philosophical and legal approaches 3 1 Overview 3 2 Utilitarianism 3 3 Subjects of a life 3 4 Abolitionism 3 5 Contractarianism 3 6 Prima facie rights theory 3 7 Feminism and animal rights 3 8 Transhumanism 3 9 Socialism and anti capitalism 3 10 Critics 3 10 1 R G Frey 3 10 2 Carl Cohen 3 10 3 Richard Posner 3 10 4 Roger Scruton 4 Public attitudes 5 See also 6 References 7 Bibliography 8 Further readingHistory EditMain article History of animal rightsIn religion EditSee also Animals in Islam Christianity and animal rights and Animal rights in Jainism Hinduism and Buddhism For some the basis of animal rights is in religion or animal worship or in general nature worship with some religions banning killing of any animal and in other religions animals can be considered unclean Hindu and Buddhist societies abandoned animal sacrifice and embraced vegetarianism from the 3rd century BCE 18 One of the most important sanctions of the Jain Hindu and Buddhist faiths is the concept of ahimsa or refraining from the destruction of life According to Buddhist belief humans do not deserve preferential treatment over other living beings 19 The Dharmic interpretation of this doctrine prohibits the killing of any living being 19 Ancient Tamil works such as the Tolkappiyam and Tirukkural contain passages that extend the idea of non violence to all living beings 20 In Islam animal rights were recognized early by the Sharia This recognition is based on both the Qur an and the Hadith In the Qur an there are many references to animals detailing that they have souls form communities communicate with God and worship Him in their own way Muhammad forbade his followers to harm any animal and asked them to respect the rights of animals 21 According to Christianity all animals from the smallest to the largest are cared for and loved According to the Bible All these animals waited for the Lord that the Lord might give them food at the hour The Lord gives them they receive The Lord opens his hand and they are filled with good things 22 It further says God gave food to the animals and made the crows cry 23 Philosophical and legal approaches EditOverview Edit Further information Consequentialism and Deontological ethics nbsp Martha Nussbaum Professor of Law and Ethics at the University of Chicago is a proponent of the capabilities approach to animal rights The two main philosophical approaches to animal ethics are utilitarian and rights based The former is exemplified by Peter Singer and the latter by Tom Regan and Gary Francione Their differences reflect a distinction philosophers draw between ethical theories that judge the rightness of an act by its consequences consequentialism teleological ethics or utilitarianism and those that focus on the principle behind the act almost regardless of consequences deontological ethics Deontologists argue that there are acts we should never perform even if failing to do so entails a worse outcome 24 There are a number of positions that can be defended from a consequentalist or deontologist perspective including the capabilities approach represented by Martha Nussbaum and the egalitarian approach which has been examined by Ingmar Persson and Peter Vallentyne The capabilities approach focuses on what individuals require to fulfill their capabilities Nussbaum 2006 argues that animals need a right to life some control over their environment company play and physical health 25 Stephen R L Clark Mary Midgley and Bernard Rollin also discuss animal rights in terms of animals being permitted to lead a life appropriate for their kind 26 Egalitarianism favors an equal distribution of happiness among all individuals which makes the interests of the worse off more important than those of the better off 27 Another approach virtue ethics holds that in considering how to act we should consider the character of the actor and what kind of moral agents we should be Rosalind Hursthouse has suggested an approach to animal rights based on virtue ethics 28 Mark Rowlands has proposed a contractarian approach 29 Utilitarianism Edit Further information Equal consideration of interests and Utilitarianism Nussbaum 2004 writes that utilitarianism starting with Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill has contributed more to the recognition of the moral status of animals than any other ethical theory 30 The utilitarian philosopher most associated with animal rights is Peter Singer professor of bioethics at Princeton University Singer is not a rights theorist but uses the language of rights to discuss how we ought to treat individuals citation needed He is a preference utilitarian needs update meaning that he judges the rightness of an act by the extent to which it satisfies the preferences interests of those affected 31 His position is that there is no reason not to give equal consideration to the interests of human and nonhumans though his principle of equality does not require identical treatment A mouse and a man both have an interest in not being kicked and there are no moral or logical grounds for failing to accord those interests equal weight Interests are predicated on the ability to suffer nothing more and once it is established that a being has interests those interests must be given equal consideration 32 Singer quotes the English philosopher Henry Sidgwick 1838 1900 The good of any one individual is of no more importance from the point of view of the Universe than the good of any other 33 nbsp Peter Singer interests are predicated on the ability to suffer Singer argues that equality of consideration is a prescription not an assertion of fact if the equality of the sexes were based only on the idea that men and women were equally intelligent we would have to abandon the practice of equal consideration if this were later found to be false But the moral idea of equality does not depend on matters of fact such as intelligence physical strength or moral capacity Equality therefore cannot be grounded on the outcome of scientific investigations into the intelligence of nonhumans All that matters is whether they can suffer 34 Commentators on all sides of the debate now accept that animals suffer and feel pain although it was not always so Bernard Rollin professor of philosophy animal sciences and biomedical sciences at Colorado State University writes that Descartes s influence continued to be felt until the 1980s Veterinarians trained in the US before 1989 were taught to ignore pain he writes and at least one major veterinary hospital in the 1960s did not stock narcotic analgesics for animal pain control In his interactions with scientists he was often asked to prove that animals are conscious and to provide scientifically acceptable evidence that they could feel pain 35 Scientific publications have made it clear since the 1980s that the majority of researchers do believe animals suffer and feel pain though it continues to be argued that their suffering may be reduced by an inability to experience the same dread of anticipation as humans or to remember the suffering as vividly 36 The ability of animals to suffer even it may vary in severity is the basis for Singer s application of equal consideration The problem of animal suffering and animal consciousness in general arose primarily because it was argued that animals have no language Singer writes that if language were needed to communicate pain it would often be impossible to know when humans are in pain though we can observe pain behavior and make a calculated guess based on it He argues that there is no reason to suppose that the pain behavior of nonhumans would have a different meaning from the pain behavior of humans 37 Subjects of a life Edit Further information The Case for Animal Rights nbsp Tom Regan animals are subjects of a life Tom Regan professor emeritus of philosophy at North Carolina State University argues in The Case for Animal Rights 1983 that nonhuman animals are what he calls subjects of a life and as such are bearers of rights 38 He writes that because the moral rights of humans are based on their possession of certain cognitive abilities and because these abilities are also possessed by at least some nonhuman animals such animals must have the same moral rights as humans Although only humans act as moral agents both marginal case humans such as infants and at least some nonhumans must have the status of moral patients 38 Moral patients are unable to formulate moral principles and as such are unable to do right or wrong even though what they do may be beneficial or harmful Only moral agents are able to engage in moral action Animals for Regan have intrinsic value as subjects of a life and cannot be regarded as a means to an end a view that places him firmly in the abolitionist camp His theory does not extend to all animals but only to those that can be regarded as subjects of a life 38 He argues that all normal mammals of at least one year of age would qualify individuals are subjects of a life if they have beliefs and desires perception memory and a sense of the future including their own future an emotional life together with feelings of pleasure and pain preference and welfare interests the ability to initiate action in pursuit of their desires and goals a psychophysical identity over time and an individual welfare in the sense that their experiential life fares well or ill for them logically independently of their utility for others and logically independently of their being the object of anyone else s interests 38 Whereas Singer is primarily concerned with improving the treatment of animals and accepts that in some hypothetical scenarios individual animals might be used legitimately to further human or nonhuman ends Regan believes we ought to treat nonhuman animals as we would humans He applies the strict Kantian ideal which Kant himself applied only to humans that they ought never to be sacrificed as a means to an end and must be treated as ends in themselves 39 Abolitionism Edit Further information Abolitionism animal rights and Animals Property and the Law nbsp Gary Francione animals need only the right not to be regarded as property Gary Francione professor of law and philosophy at Rutgers Law School in Newark is a leading abolitionist writer arguing that animals need only one right the right not to be owned Everything else would follow from that paradigm shift He writes that although most people would condemn the mistreatment of animals and in many countries there are laws that seem to reflect those concerns in practice the legal system allows any use of animals however abhorrent The law only requires that any suffering not be unnecessary In deciding what counts as unnecessary an animal s interests are weighed against the interests of human beings and the latter almost always prevail 40 Francione s Animals Property and the Law 1995 was the first extensive jurisprudential treatment of animal rights In it Francione compares the situation of animals to the treatment of slaves in the United States where legislation existed that appeared to protect them while the courts ignored that the institution of slavery itself rendered the protection unenforceable 41 He offers as an example the United States Animal Welfare Act which he describes as an example of symbolic legislation intended to assuage public concern about the treatment of animals but difficult to implement 42 He argues that a focus on animal welfare rather than animal rights may worsen the position of animals by making the public feel comfortable about using them and entrenching the view of them as property He calls animal rights groups who pursue animal welfare issues such as People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals the new welfarists arguing that they have more in common with 19th century animal protectionists than with the animal rights movement indeed the terms animal protection and protectionism are increasingly favored His position in 1996 was that there is no animal rights movement in the United States 43 Contractarianism Edit Further information Social contract Mark Rowlands professor of philosophy at the University of Florida has proposed a contractarian approach based on the original position and the veil of ignorance a state of nature thought experiment that tests intuitions about justice and fairness in John Rawls s A Theory of Justice 1971 In the original position individuals choose principles of justice what kind of society to form and how primary social goods will be distributed unaware of their individual characteristics their race sex class or intelligence whether they are able bodied or disabled rich or poor and therefore unaware of which role they will assume in the society they are about to form 29 The idea is that operating behind the veil of ignorance they will choose a social contract in which there is basic fairness and justice for them no matter the position they occupy Rawls did not include species membership as one of the attributes hidden from the decision makers in the original position Rowlands proposes extending the veil of ignorance to include rationality which he argues is an undeserved property similar to characteristics including race sex and intelligence 29 Prima facie rights theory Edit Further information Prima facie right American philosopher Timothy Garry has proposed an approach that deems nonhuman animals worthy of prima facie rights In a philosophical context a prima facie Latin for on the face of it or at first glance right is one that appears to be applicable at first glance but upon closer examination may be outweighed by other considerations In his book Ethics A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory Lawrence Hinman characterizes such rights as the right is real but leaves open the question of whether it is applicable and overriding in a particular situation 44 The idea that nonhuman animals are worthy of prima facie rights is to say that in a sense animals have rights that can be overridden by many other considerations especially those conflicting a human s right to life liberty property and the pursuit of happiness Garry supports his view arguing if a nonhuman animal were to kill a human being in the U S it would have broken the laws of the land and would probably get rougher sanctions than if it were a human My point is that like laws govern all who interact within a society rights are to be applied to all beings who interact within that society This is not to say these rights endowed by humans are equivalent to those held by nonhuman animals but rather that if humans possess rights then so must all those who interact with humans 45 In sum Garry suggests that humans have obligations to nonhuman animals animals do not and ought not to have uninfringible rights against humans Feminism and animal rights Edit Further information Women and animal advocacy Ethics of care and Feminist ethics nbsp The American ecofeminist Carol Adams has written extensively about the link between feminism and animal rights starting with The Sexual Politics of Meat 1990 Women have played a central role in animal advocacy since the 19th century 46 The anti vivisection movement in the 19th and early 20th century in England and the United States was largely run by women including Frances Power Cobbe Anna Kingsford Lizzy Lind af Hageby and Caroline Earle White 1833 1916 47 Garner writes that 70 per cent of the membership of the Victoria Street Society one of the anti vivisection groups founded by Cobbe were women as were 70 per cent of the membership of the British RSPCA in 1900 48 The modern animal advocacy movement has a similar representation of women They are not invariably in leadership positions during the March for Animals in Washington D C in 1990 the largest animal rights demonstration held until then in the United States most of the participants were women but most of the platform speakers were men 49 Nevertheless several influential animal advocacy groups have been founded by women including the British Union for the Abolition of Vivisection by Cobbe in London in 1898 the Animal Welfare Board of India by Rukmini Devi Arundale in 1962 and People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals co founded by Ingrid Newkirk in 1980 In the Netherlands Marianne Thieme and Esther Ouwehand were elected to parliament in 2006 representing the Parliamentary group for Animals The preponderance of women in the movement has led to a body of academic literature exploring feminism and animal rights such as feminism and vegetarianism or veganism the oppression of women and animals and the male association of women and animals with nature and emotion rather than reason an association that several feminist writers have embraced 46 Lori Gruen writes that women and animals serve the same symbolic function in a patriarchal society both are the used the dominated submissive Other 50 When the British feminist Mary Wollstonecraft 1759 1797 published A Vindication of the Rights of Woman 1792 Thomas Taylor 1758 1835 a Cambridge philosopher responded with an anonymous parody A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes 1792 saying that Wollstonecraft s arguments for women s rights could be applied equally to animals a position he intended as reductio ad absurdum 51 In her works The Sexual Politics of Meat A Feminist Vegetarian Critical Theory 1990 and The Pornography of Meat 2004 Carol J Adams focuses in particular on what she argues are the links between the oppression of women and that of non human animals 52 Transhumanism Edit Some transhumanists argue for animal rights liberation and uplift of animal consciousness into machines 53 Transhumanism also understands animal rights on a gradation or spectrum with other types of sentient rights including human rights and the rights of conscious artificial intelligences posthuman rights 54 Socialism and anti capitalism EditAccording to sociologist David Nibert of Wittenberg University the struggle for animal liberation must happen in tandem with a more generalized struggle against human oppression and exploitation under global capitalism He says that under a more egalitarian democratic socialist system one that would allow a more just and peaceful order to emerge and be characterized by economic democracy and a democratically controlled state and mass media there would be much greater potential to inform the public about vital global issues and the potential for campaigns to improve the lives of other animals to be more abolitionist in nature 55 Philosopher Steven Best of the University of Texas at El Paso states that the animal liberation movement as characterized by the Animal Liberation Front and its various offshoots is a significant threat to global capital Animal liberation challenges large sectors of the capitalist economy by assailing corporate agriculture and pharmaceutical companies and their suppliers Far from being irrelevant to social movements animal rights can form the basis for a broad coalition of progressive social groups and drive changes that strike at the heart of capitalist exploitation of animals people and the earth 56 Critics Edit R G Frey Edit R G Frey professor of philosophy at Bowling Green State University is a preference utilitarian In his early work Interests and Rights 1980 Frey disagreed with Singer who wrote in Animal Liberation 1975 that the interests of nonhuman animals must be given equal consideration when judging the consequences of an act on the grounds that animals have no interests Frey argues that interests are dependent on desire and that no desire can exist without a corresponding belief Animals have no beliefs because a belief state requires the ability to hold a second order belief a belief about the belief which he argues requires language If someone were to say e g The cat believes that the door is locked then that person is holding as I see it that the cat holds the declarative sentence The door is locked to be true and I can see no reason whatever for crediting the cat or any other creature which lacks language including human infants with entertaining declarative sentences 57 Carl Cohen Edit Carl Cohen professor of philosophy at the University of Michigan argues that rights holders must be able to distinguish between their own interests and what is right The holders of rights must have the capacity to comprehend rules of duty governing all including themselves In applying such rules they must recognize possible conflicts between what is in their own interest and what is just Only in a community of beings capable of self restricting moral judgments can the concept of a right be correctly invoked Cohen rejects Singer s argument that since a brain damaged human could not make moral judgments moral judgments cannot be used as the distinguishing characteristic for determining who is awarded rights Cohen writes that the test for moral judgment is not a test to be administered to humans one by one but should be applied to the capacity of members of the species in general 58 Richard Posner Edit nbsp Judge Richard Posner facts will drive equality 59 Judge Richard Posner of the United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit debated the issue of animal rights in 2001 with Peter Singer 60 Posner posits that his moral intuition tells him that human beings prefer their own If a dog threatens a human infant even if it requires causing more pain to the dog to stop it than the dog would have caused to the infant then we favour the child It would be monstrous to spare the dog 59 Singer challenges this by arguing that formerly unequal rights for gays women and certain races were justified using the same set of intuitions Posner replies that equality in civil rights did not occur because of ethical arguments but because facts mounted that there were no morally significant differences between humans based on race sex or sexual orientation that would support inequality If and when similar facts emerge about humans and animals the differences in rights will erode too But facts will drive equality not ethical arguments that run contrary to instinct he argues Posner calls his approach soft utilitarianism in contrast to Singer s hard utilitarianism He argues The soft utilitarian position on animal rights is a moral intuition of many probably most Americans We realize that animals feel pain and we think that to inflict pain without a reason is bad Nothing of practical value is added by dressing up this intuition in the language of philosophy much is lost when the intuition is made a stage in a logical argument When kindness toward animals is levered into a duty of weighting the pains of animals and of people equally bizarre vistas of social engineering are opened up 59 nbsp Roger Scruton rights imply obligations Roger Scruton Edit Roger Scruton the British philosopher argued that rights imply obligations Every legal privilege he wrote imposes a burden on the one who does not possess that privilege that is your right may be my duty Scruton therefore regarded the emergence of the animal rights movement as the strangest cultural shift within the liberal worldview because the idea of rights and responsibilities is he argued distinctive to the human condition and it makes no sense to spread them beyond our own species 13 He accused animal rights advocates of pre scientific anthropomorphism attributing traits to animals that are he says Beatrix Potter like where only man is vile It is within this fiction that the appeal of animal rights lies he argued The world of animals is non judgmental filled with dogs who return our affection almost no matter what we do to them and cats who pretend to be affectionate when in fact they care only about themselves It is he argued a fantasy a world of escape 13 Scruton singled out Peter Singer a prominent Australian philosopher and animal rights activist for criticism He wrote that Singer s works including Animal Liberation contain little or no philosophical argument They derive their radical moral conclusions from a vacuous utilitarianism that counts the pain and pleasure of all living things as equally significant and that ignores just about everything that has been said in our philosophical tradition about the real distinction between persons and animals 13 Tom Regan countered this view of rights by distinguishing moral agents and moral patients 61 unreliable source Public attitudes EditAccording to a paper published in 2000 by Harold Herzog and Lorna Dorr previous academic surveys of attitudes towards animal rights have tended to suffer from small sample sizes and non representative groups 62 However a number of factors appear to correlate with the attitude of individuals regarding the treatment of animals and animal rights These include gender age occupation religion and level of education There has also been evidence to suggest that prior experience with pets may be a factor in people s attitudes 63 According to some studies women are more likely to empathize with the cause of animal rights than men 63 64 A 1996 study suggested that factors that may partially explain this discrepancy include attitudes towards feminism and science scientific literacy and the presence of a greater emphasis on nurturance or compassion among women 65 A common misconception on the concept of animal rights is that its proponents want to grant non human animals the exact same legal rights as humans such as the right to vote This is not the case as the concept is that animals should have rights with equal consideration to their interests for example cats do not have any interest in voting so they should not have the right to vote 66 A 2016 study found that support for animal testing may not be based on cogent philosophical rationales and more open debate is warranted 67 A 2007 survey to examine whether or not people who believed in evolution were more likely to support animal rights than creationists and believers in intelligent design found that this was largely the case according to the researchers the respondents who were strong Christian fundamentalists and believers in creationism were less likely to advocate for animal rights than those who were less fundamentalist in their beliefs The findings extended previous research such as a 1992 study which found that 48 of animal rights activists were atheists or agnostic 68 69 A 2019 study in The Washington Post found that those who have positive attitudes toward animal rights also tend to have a positive view of universal healthcare favor reducing discrimination against African Americans the LGBT community and undocumented immigrants and expanding welfare to aid the poor 70 Two surveys found that attitudes towards animal rights tactics such as direct action are very diverse within the animal rights communities Near half 50 and 39 in two surveys of activists do not support direct action One survey concluded it would be a mistake to portray animal rights activists as homogeneous 63 71 See also Edit nbsp Animals portal Animal cognition Animal consciousness Animal industrial complex Animal liberation Animal liberation movement Animal liberationist Animal rights by country or territory Animal studies Animal suffering Animal trial Animal Welfare Institute Antinaturalism politics Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness Chick culling Cruelty to animals Critical animal studies Deep ecology Do Animals Have Rights book List of animal rights advocates List of songs about animal rights Moral circle expansion Open rescue Plant rights Sentientism Timeline of animal welfare and rights Wild animal suffering World Animal DayReferences Edit Kumar Satish September 2002 You are therefore I am A declaration of dependence Bloomsbury USA ISBN 9781903998182 DeGrazia 2002 ch 2 Taylor 2009 ch 1 Taylor 2009 ch 3 Compare for example similar usage of the term in 1938 The American Biology Teacher Vol 53 National Association of Biology Teachers 1938 p 211 Retrieved 16 April 2021 The foundation from which these behaviors spring is the ideology known as speciesism Speciesism is deeply rooted in the widely held belief that the human species is entitled to certain rights and privileges Horta 2010 That a central goal of animal rights is to eliminate the property status of animals see Sunstein 2004 p 11ff For speciesism and fundamental protections see Waldau 2011 For food clothing research subjects or entertainment see Francione 1995 p 17 Animal Law Courses Animal Legal Defense Fund Archived from the original on 2020 12 04 Retrieved 2020 12 13 For animal law courses in North America see Animal law courses Archived 2010 06 13 at the Wayback Machine Animal Legal Defense Fund Retrieved July 12 2012 For a discussion of animals and personhood see Wise 2000 pp 4 59 248ff Wise 2004 Posner 2004 Wise 2007 Archived 2008 06 14 at the Wayback Machine For the arguments and counter arguments about awarding personhood only to great apes see Garner 2005 p 22 Also see Sunstein Cass R February 20 2000 The Chimps Day in Court Archived 2017 05 01 at the Wayback Machine The New York Times Gimenez Emiliano January 4 2015 Argentine orangutan granted unprecedented legal rights edition cnn com CNN Espanol Archived from the original on April 3 2021 Retrieved April 21 2015 Cohen Carl Regan Tom 2001 The Animal Rights Debate Point Counterpoint Philosophers Debate Contemporary Issues Series Lanham Maryland Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers p 47 ISBN 9780847696628 Retrieved 16 April 2021 Too often overlooked in the animal world according to Sapontzis are insects that have interests and therefore rights The concept of bacteria rights can appear coupled with disdain or irony Pluhar Evelyn B 1995 Human superiority and the argument from marginal cases Beyond Prejudice The Moral Significance of Human and Nonhuman Animals Book collections on Project MUSE Durham North Carolina Duke University Press p 9 ISBN 9780822316480 Retrieved 16 April 2021 For example in an editorial entitled Animal Rights Nonsense in the prestigious science journal Nature defenders of animal rights are accused of being committed to the absurdity of bacteria rights Jakopovich Daniel 2021 The UK s Animal Welfare Sentience Bill Excludes the Vast Majority of Animals Why We Must Expand Our Moral Circle to Include Invertebrates Animals amp Society Research Initiative University of Victoria Canada Archived from the original on 2022 11 29 Retrieved 2022 06 18 a b c d Scruton Roger Summer 2000 Animal Rights City Journal New York Manhattan Institute for Policy Research Liguori G et al 2017 Ethical Issues in the Use of Animal Models for Tissue Engineering Reflections on Legal Aspects Moral Theory 3Rs Strategies and Harm Benefit Analysis PDF Tissue Engineering Part C Methods 23 12 850 862 doi 10 1089 ten TEC 2017 0189 PMID 28756735 S2CID 206268293 Archived PDF from the original on 2020 09 15 Retrieved 2019 07 12 Garner 2005 pp 11 16 Also see Frey 1980 and for a review of Frey see Sprigge 1981 Archived 2016 02 19 at the Wayback Machine Singer 2000 pp 151 156 Martin Gus 15 June 2011 The SAGE Encyclopedia of Terrorism Second Edition SAGE ISBN 9781412980166 via Google Books Garner 2005 pp 21 22 a b Grant Catharine 2006 The No nonsense Guide to Animal Rights New Internationalist p 24 ISBN 9781904456407 These religions emphasize ahimsa which is the principle of non violence towards all living things The first precept is a prohibition against the killing of any creature The Jain Hindu and Buddhist injunctions against killing serve to teach that all creatures are spiritually equal a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Meenakshi Sundaram T P 1957 Vegetarianism in Tamil Literature 15th World Vegetarian Congress 1957 International Vegetarian Union IVU Archived from the original on 22 January 2022 Retrieved 17 April 2022 Ahimsa is the ruling principle of Indian life from the very earliest times This positive spiritual attitude is easily explained to the common man in a negative way as ahimsa and hence this way of denoting it Tiruvalluvar speaks of this as kollaamai or non killing BBC Religions Islam Animals bbc co uk Archived from the original on 2020 02 04 Retrieved 2019 12 20 Proverbs 30 24 and NW Psalm 104 24 25 27 28 Ps 147 9 Craig 1988 Nussbaum 2006 pp 388ff 393ff also see Nussbaum 2004 p 299ff Weir 2009 see Clark 1977 Rollin 1981 Midgley 1984 Vallentyne 2005 Archived 2016 04 13 at the Wayback Machine Vallentyne 2007 Rowlands 2009 p 98ff Hursthouse 2000a Hursthouse 2000b p 146ff a b c Rowlands 1998 p 118ff particularly pp 147 152 Nussbaum 2004 p 302 For a discussion of preference utilitarianism see Singer 2011 pp 14ff 94ff Singer 1990 pp 7 8 Singer 1990 p 5 Singer 1990 p 4 Rollin 1989 pp xii pp 117 118 Rollin 2007 Archived 2020 07 28 at the Wayback Machine Singer 1990 pp 10 17 citing Stamp Dawkins 1980 Walker 1983 and Griffin 1984 Garner 2005 pp 13 14 Singer 1990 p 12ff a b c d Regan 1983 p 243 Regan 1983 Francione 1990 pp 4 17ff Francione 1995 pp 4 5 Francione 1995 p 208ff Francione 1996 p 32ff Francione and Garner 2010 pp 1ff 175ff Hall Lee An Interview with Professor Gary L Francione Archived May 8 2009 at the Wayback Machine Friends of Animals Retrieved February 3 2011 Hinman Lawrence M Ethics A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory Fort Worth TX Harcourt Brace College 1998 Print Garry Timothy J Nonhuman Animals Possessors of Prima Facie Rights 2012 p 6 a b Lansbury 1985 Adams 1990 Donovan 1993 Gruen 1993 Adams 1994 Adams and Donovan 1995 Adams 2004 MacKinnon 2004 Kean 1995 Archived 2020 04 13 at the Wayback Machine Garner 2005 p 141 citing Elston 1990 p 276 Garner 2005 pp 142 143 Gruen 1993 p 60ff Singer 1990 p 1 Green Elizabeth W 10 October 2003 Fifteen Questions For Carol J Adams The Harvard Crimson Retrieved 22 November 2008 George Dvorsky The Ethics of Animal Enhancement Archived from the original on 2017 04 25 Retrieved 2017 04 24 Evans Woody 2015 Posthuman Rights Dimensions of Transhuman Worlds Teknokultura 12 2 doi 10 5209 rev TK 2015 v12 n2 49072 Nibert 2013 p 270 Best 2014 p 103 Frey 1989 p 40 pg 94 100 Archived 2011 11 27 at the Wayback Machine Cohen and Regan 2001 a b c Posner June 15 2001 Archived August 21 2011 at the Wayback Machine Posner Singer debate in full Archived 2015 05 09 at the Wayback Machine courtesy link on utilitarian net Also see Posner 2004 Singer June 15 2001 Archived September 14 2017 at the Wayback Machine Tom Regan The Case For Animal Rights The Vegetarian Site Archived from the original on November 2 2019 Retrieved November 2 2019 Herzog Harold Dorr Lorna 2000 Electronically Available Surveys of Attitudes Toward Animals Society amp Animals 10 2 a b c Apostol L Rebega O L Miclea M 2013 Psychological and Socio Demographic Predictors of Attitudes towards Animals Social and Behavioural Sciences 78 521 525 Herzog Harold 2007 Gender Differences in Human Animal Interactions A Review Anthrozoos 20 1 7 21 doi 10 2752 089279307780216687 S2CID 14988443 Pifer Linda 1996 Exploring the Gender Gap in Young Adults Attitudes about Animal Research PDF Society and Animals 4 1 37 52 doi 10 1163 156853096X00034 PMID 11654528 Archived PDF from the original on 2021 09 17 Retrieved 2021 06 04 Ethics Animal ethics Animal rights BBC Online Archived from the original on March 24 2022 Retrieved February 10 2022 Joffe Ari R Bara Meredith Anton Natalie Nobis Nathan March 29 2016 The ethics of animal research a survey of the public and scientists in North America BMC Medical Ethics 17 17 doi 10 1186 s12910 016 0100 x ISSN 1472 6939 PMC 4812627 PMID 27025215 DeLeeuwa Jamie Galen Luke Aebersold Cassandra Stanton Victoria 2007 Support for Animal Rights as a Function of Belief in Evolution Religious Fundamentalism and Religious Denomination PDF Society and Animals 15 353 363 Archived from the original PDF on June 20 2013 Galvin Shelley L Herzog Harold A Jr 1992 Ethical Ideology Animal Rights Activism And Attitudes Toward The Treatment Of Animals Ethics amp Behavior 2 3 141 149 doi 10 1207 s15327019eb0203 1 PMID 11651362 Archived from the original on 2020 05 31 Retrieved 2020 08 29 Park Yon Soo Valentino Benjamin July 26 2019 Who supports animal rights Here s what we found The Washington Post Archived from the original on July 26 2019 Retrieved July 26 2019 Plous S 1991 An attitude survey of animal rights activists Psychological Science 2 3 194 196 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9280 1991 tb00131 x S2CID 145549994 Bibliography EditBooks and papers are cited in short form in the footnotes with full citations here News and other sources are cited in full in the footnotes Adams Carol J 1996 The Sexual Politics of Meat A Feminist Vegetarian Critical Theory Continuum ISBN 1501312839 Adams Carol J Donovan Josephine eds 1995 Animals and Women Feminist Theoretical Explorations Duke University Press ISBN 0822316552 Adams Carol J 2004 The Pornography of Meat Continuum ISBN 9781590565100 Benthall Jonathan 2007 Animal liberation and rights Anthropology Today volume 23 issue 2 April Bentham Jeremy 1781 Principles of Penal Law ISBN 1379912326 Beauchamp Tom 2009 The Moral Standing of Animals in Marc Bekoff Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare Greenwood ISBN 0313352593 Beauchamp Tom 2011a Introduction in Tom Beauchamp and R G Frey eds The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics Oxford University Press ISBN 019935197X Beauchamp Tom 2011b Rights Theory and Animal Rights in Beauchamp and Frey op cit ISBN 019935197X Best Steven 2014 The Politics of Total Liberation Revolution for the 21st Century Palgrave Macmillan doi 10 1057 9781137440723 ISBN 978 1137471116 Clark Stephen R L 1977 The Moral Status of Animals Oxford University Press ISBN 0192830406 Cohen Carl 1986 The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research Archived 2011 11 27 at the Wayback Machine New England Journal of Medicine vol 315 issue 14 October pp 865 870 Cohen Carl and Regan Tom 2001 The Animal Rights Debate Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 0847696626 Craig Edward ed 1988 Deontological Ethics and Consequentalism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy DeGrazia David 2002 Animal Rights A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press Donovan Josephine 1993 Animal Rights and Feminist Theory in Greta Gaard Ecofeminism Women Animals Nature Temple University Press Francione Gary 1996 Rain Without Thunder The Ideology of the Animal Rights Movement Temple University Press Francione Gary 1995 Animals Property and the Law Temple University Press Francione Gary 2008 Animals as Persons Columbia University Press Francione Gary and Garner Robert 2010 The Animal Rights Debate Abolition Or Regulation Columbia University Press Fellenz Mark R 2007 The Moral Menagerie Philosophy and Animal Rights University of Illinois Press Frey R G 1980 Interests and Rights The Case against Animals Clarendon Press Frey R G 1989 Why Animals Lack Beliefs and Desires in Peter Singer and Tom Regan eds Animal Rights and Human Obligations Prentice Hall Garner Robert 2004 Animals Politics and Morality Manchester University Press Garner Robert 2005 The Political Theory of Animals Rights Manchester University Press Giannelli Michael A 1985 Three Blind Mice See How They Run A Critique of Behavioral Research With Animals In M W Fox amp L D Mickley eds Advances in Animal Welfare Science 1985 1986 pp 109 164 Washington DC The Humane Society of the United States Gruen Lori 1993 Dismantling Oppression An Analysis of the Connection Between Women and Animals in Greta Gaard Ecofeminism Women Animals Nature Temple University Press Griffin Donald 1984 Animal Thinking Harvard University Press Horta Oscar 2010 What Is Speciesism The Journal of Environmental and Agricultural Ethics Vol 23 No 3 June pp 243 266 Hursthouse Rosalind 2000a On Virtue Ethics Oxford University Press Hursthouse Rosalind 2000b Ethics Humans and Other Animals Routledge Jakopovich Daniel 2021 The UK s Animal Welfare Sentience Bill Excludes the Vast Majority of Animals Why We Must Expand Our Moral Circle to Include Invertebrates Archived 2022 11 29 at the Wayback Machine Animals amp Society Research Initiative University of Victoria Canada Kant Immanuel 1785 Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals Kean Hilda 1995 The Smooth Cool Men of Science The Feminist and Socialist Response to Vivisection Archived 2020 04 13 at the Wayback Machine History Workshop Journal No 40 Autumn pp 16 38 Kelch Thomas G 2011 Globalization and Animal Law Kluwer Law International Lansbury Coral 1985 The Old Brown Dog Women Workers and Vivisection in Edwardian England University of Wisconsin Press Legge Debbi and Brooman Simon 1997 Law Relating to Animals Cavendish Publishing ISBN 1859412386 Leneman Leah 1999 No Animal Food The Road to Veganism in Britain 1909 1944 Society and Animals 7 1 5 Locke John 1693 Some Thoughts Concerning Education MacKinnon Catharine A 2004 Of Mice and Men in Nussbaum and Sunstein op cit Mason Peter 1997 The Brown Dog Affair Two Sevens Publishing Midgley Mary 1984 Animals and Why They Matter University of Georgia Press ISBN 0820320412 Molland Neil 2004 Thirty Years of Direct Action in Best and Nocella op cit Monaghan Rachael 2000 Terrorism in the Name of Animal Rights in Taylor Maxwell and Horgan John The Future of Terrorism Routledge Murray L 2006 The ASPCA Pioneers in Animal Welfare Archived 2011 07 26 at the Wayback Machine Encyclopaedia Britannica s Advocacy for Animals Nash Roderick 1989 The Rights of Nature A History of Environmental Ethics University of Wisconsin Press Newkirk Ingrid 2004 The ALF Who Why and What in Steven Best and Anthony Nocella eds Terrorists or Freedom Fighters Reflections on the Liberation of Animals Lantern 2004 Nibert David 2013 Animal Oppression and Human Violence Domesecration Capitalism and Global Conflict Columbia University Press ISBN 978 0231151894 Archived from the original on 2022 11 04 Retrieved 2022 09 14 Nussbaum Martha 2004 Beyond Compassion and Humanity Justice for Nonhuman Animals in Cass Sunstein and Martha Nussbaum eds Animal Rights Current Debates and New Directions Oxford University Press Nussbaum Martha 2006 Frontiers of Justice Disability Nationality Species Membership Belknap Press Posner Richard and Singer Peter June 15 2001 Posner Singer debate Archived 2017 09 14 at the Wayback Machine Slate Posner Richard and Singer Peter 2004 Animal rights in Sunstein and Nussbaum op cit Rachels James 2009 Darwin Charles in Bekoff op cit Redclift Michael R 2010 The International Handbook of Environmental Sociology Edward Elgar Publishing Regan Tom 1983 The Case for Animal Rights University of California Press Regan Tom 2001 Defending Animal Rights University of Illinois Press Rollin Bernard 1981 Animal Rights and Human Morality Prometheus Books Rollin Bernard 1989 The Unheeded Cry Animal Consciousness Animal Pain and Science New York Oxford University Press Rollin Bernard 2007 Animal research a moral science Archived 2020 07 28 at the Wayback Machine Nature EMBO Reports 8 6 pp 521 525 Rowlands Mark 2009 1998 Animal Rights A Defense Palgrave Macmillan Ryder Richard 2000 1989 Animal Revolution Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism Berg Sapontzis Steve 1985 Moral Community and Animal Rights Archived 2016 04 13 at the Wayback Machine American Philosophical Quarterly Vol 22 No 3 July pp 251 257 Scruton Roger 1998 Animal Rights and Wrongs Claridge Press Scruton Roger 2000 Animal Rights Archived 2016 03 03 at the Wayback Machine City Journal summer Singer Peter April 5 1973 Animal liberation Archived 2010 02 24 at the Wayback Machine The New York Review of Books Volume 20 Number 5 Singer Peter 1990 1975 Animal Liberation New York Review Books Singer Peter 2000 1998 Ethics into Action Henry Spira and the Animal Rights Movement Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers Inc Singer Peter 2003 Animal liberation at 30 Archived 2010 03 30 at the Wayback Machine The New York Review of Books vol 50 no 8 May 15 Singer Peter 2004 Ethics Beyond Species and Beyond Instincts in Sunstein and Nussbaum op cit Singer Peter 2011 1979 Practical Ethics Cambridge University Press Sprigge T L S 1981 Interests and Rights The Case against Animals Archived 2016 02 19 at the Wayback Machine Journal of Medical Ethics June 7 2 95 102 Stamp Dawkins Marian 1980 Animal Suffering The Science of Animal Welfare Chapman and Hall Stucki Saskia 2020 Towards a Theory of Legal Animal Rights Simple and Fundamental Rights Archived 2021 01 09 at the Wayback Machine Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 40 533 560 Sunstein Cass R 2004 Introduction What are Animal Rights in Sunstein and Nussbaum op cit Sunstein Cass R and Nussbaum Martha 2005 Animal Rights Current Debates and New Directions Oxford University Press ISBN 0195305108 Taylor Angus 2009 Animals and Ethics An Overview of the Philosophical Debate Broadview Press Taylor Thomas 1792 A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes in Craciun Adriana 2002 A Routledge Literary Sourcebook on Mary Wollstonecraft s A Vindication of the Rights of Woman Routledge Vallentyne Peter 2005 Of Mice and Men Equality and Animals Archived 2016 04 13 at the Wayback Machine The Journal of Ethics Vol 9 No 3 4 pp 403 433 Vallentyne Peter 2007 Of Mice and Men Equality and Animals in Nils Holtug and Kasper Lippert Rasmussen eds 2007 Egalitarianism New Essays on the Nature and Value of Equality Oxford University Press Waldau Paul 2011 Animal Rights What Everyone Needs to Know Oxford University Press Walker Stephen 1983 Animal Thoughts Routledge Weir Jack 2009 Virtue Ethics in Marc Bekoff Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare Greenwood ISBN 0313352593 Williams Erin E and DeMello Margo 2007 Why Animals Matter Prometheus Books Wise Steven M 2000 Rattling the Cage Toward Legal Rights for Animals Da Capo Press Wise Steven M 2002 Drawing the Line Science and the Case for Animal Rights Perseus Wise Steven M 2004 Animal Rights One Step at a Time in Sunstein and Nussbaum op cit Wise Steven M 2007 Animal Rights Archived 2008 11 18 at the Wayback Machine Encyclopaedia Britannica Further reading Edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Animal rights Lubinski Joseph 2002 Overview Summary of Animal Rights The Animal Legal and Historical Center at Michigan State University College of Law Great Apes and the Law The Animal Legal and Historical Center at Michigan State University College of Law Bekoff Marc ed 2009 The Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare Greenwood Best Steven and Nocella II Anthony J eds 2004 Terrorists or Freedom Fighters Reflections on the Liberation of Animals Lantern Books Chapouthier Georges and Nouet Jean Claude eds 1998 The Universal Declaration of Animal Rights Ligue Francaise des Droits de l Animal Dawkins Richard 1993 Gaps in the mind in Cavalieri Paola and Singer Peter eds The Great Ape Project St Martin s Griffin Dombrowski Daniel 1997 Babies and Beasts The Argument from Marginal Cases University of Illinois Press Favre David S 2018 Respecting Animals A Balanced Approach to Our Relationship with Pets Food and Wildlife Prometheus ISBN 978 1633884250 Foltz Richard 2006 Animals in Islamic Tradition and Muslim Cultures Oneworld Publications Franklin Julian H 2005 Animal Rights and Moral Philosophy University of Columbia Press Gruen Lori 2003 The Moral Status of Animals Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy July 1 2003 Gruen Lori 2011 Ethics and Animals Cambridge University Press Hall Lee 2006 Capers in the Churchyard Animal Rights Advocacy in the Age of Terror Nectar Bat Press Linzey Andrew and Clarke Paul A B eds 1990 Animal Rights A Historic Anthology Columbia University Press Mann Keith 2007 From Dusk til Dawn An Insider s View of the Growth of the Animal Liberation Movement Puppy Pincher Press McArthur Jo Anne and Wilson Keith eds 2020 Hidden Animals in the Anthropocene Lantern Publishing amp Media Neumann Jean Marc 2012 The Universal Declaration of Animal Rights or the Creation of a New Equilibrium between Species Animal Law Review volume 19 1 Nibert David 2002 Animal Rights Human Rights Entanglements of Oppression and Liberation Rowman and Litterfield Nibert David ed 2017 Animal Oppression and Capitalism Praeger Publishing ISBN 978 1440850738 Patterson Charles 2002 Eternal Treblinka Our Treatment of Animals and the Holocaust Lantern Rachels James 1990 Created from Animals The Moral Implications of Darwinism Oxford University Press Regan Tom and Singer Peter eds 1976 Animal Rights and Human Obligations Prentice Hall Spiegel Marjorie 1996 The Dreaded Comparison Human and Animal Slavery Mirror Books Sztybel David 2006 Can the Treatment of Animals Be Compared to the Holocaust Ethics and the Environment 11 Spring 97 132 Tobias Michael 2000 Life Force The World of Jainism Asian Humanities Press Wilson Scott 2010 Animals and Ethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Kymlicka W Donaldson S 2011 Zoopolis A Political Theory of Animal Rights Oxford University Press Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Animal rights amp oldid 1179991314, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.