fbpx
Wikipedia

John Stuart Mill

John Stuart Mill (20 May 1806 – 7 May 1873)[10] was an English philosopher, political economist, Member of Parliament (MP) and civil servant. One of the most influential thinkers in the history of classical liberalism, he contributed widely to social theory, political theory, and political economy. Dubbed "the most influential English-speaking philosopher of the nineteenth century",[11] he conceived of liberty as justifying the freedom of the individual in opposition to unlimited state and social control.[12]

John Stuart Mill
Mill, c. 1870
Member of Parliament
for the City of Westminster
In office
25 July 1865 – 17 November 1868
Serving with Robert Grosvenor
Preceded byDe Lacy Evans
Succeeded byWilliam Henry Smith
Personal details
Born(1806-05-20)20 May 1806
Pentonville, Middlesex, England
Died7 May 1873(1873-05-07) (aged 66)
Avignon, Vaucluse, France
Political partyLiberal
Spouse
(m. 1851; died 1858)
Parent
Alma materUniversity College London

Philosophy career
Era19th-century philosophy
Classical economics
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Main interests
Notable ideas
Public/private sphere, social liberty, hierarchy of pleasures in utilitarianism, rule utilitarianism, classical liberalism, early liberal feminism, harm principle, Mill's Methods, direct reference theory, Millian theory of proper names, emergentism
Signature

Mill was a proponent of utilitarianism, an ethical theory developed by his predecessor Jeremy Bentham. He contributed to the investigation of scientific methodology, though his knowledge of the topic was based on the writings of others, notably William Whewell, John Herschel, and Auguste Comte, and research carried out for Mill by Alexander Bain. He engaged in written debate with Whewell.[13]

A member of the Liberal Party and author of the early feminist work The Subjection of Women, Mill was also the second Member of Parliament to call for women's suffrage after Henry Hunt in 1832.[14][15]

Biography

John Stuart Mill was born at 13 Rodney Street in Pentonville, then on the edge of the capital and now in central London, the eldest son of Harriet Barrow and the Scottish philosopher, historian, and economist James Mill. John Stuart was educated by his father, with the advice and assistance of Jeremy Bentham and Francis Place. He was given an extremely rigorous upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. His father, a follower of Bentham and an adherent of associationism, had as his explicit aim to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of utilitarianism and its implementation after he and Bentham had died.[16]

Mill was a notably precocious child. He describes his education in his autobiography. At the age of three he was taught Greek.[17] By the age of eight, he had read Aesop's Fables, Xenophon's Anabasis,[17] and the whole of Herodotus,[17] and was acquainted with Lucian, Diogenes Laërtius, Isocrates and six dialogues of Plato.[17] He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught arithmetic, physics and astronomy.

At the age of eight, Mill began studying Latin, the works of Euclid, and algebra, and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the commonly taught Latin and Greek authors and by the age of ten could read Plato and Demosthenes with ease. His father also thought that it was important for Mill to study and compose poetry. One of his earliest poetic compositions was a continuation of the Iliad. In his spare time he also enjoyed reading about natural sciences and popular novels, such as Don Quixote and Robinson Crusoe.

His father's work, The History of British India, was published in 1818; immediately thereafter, at about the age of twelve, Mill began a thorough study of the scholastic logic, at the same time reading Aristotle's logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to political economy and studied Adam Smith and David Ricardo with his father, ultimately completing their classical economic view of factors of production. Mill's comptes rendus of his daily economy lessons helped his father in writing Elements of Political Economy in 1821, a textbook to promote the ideas of Ricardian economics; however, the book lacked popular support.[18] Ricardo, who was a close friend of his father, used to invite the young Mill to his house for a walk to talk about political economy.

At the age of fourteen, Mill stayed a year in France with the family of Sir Samuel Bentham, brother of Jeremy Bentham. The mountain scenery he saw led to a lifelong taste for mountain landscapes. The lively and friendly way of life of the French also left a deep impression on him. In Montpellier, he attended the winter courses on chemistry, zoology, logic of the Faculté des Sciences, as well as taking a course in higher mathematics. While coming and going from France, he stayed in Paris for a few days in the house of the renowned economist Jean-Baptiste Say, a friend of Mill's father. There he met many leaders of the Liberal party, as well as other notable Parisians, including Henri Saint-Simon.

Mill went through months of sadness and contemplated suicide at twenty years of age. According to the opening paragraphs of Chapter V of his autobiography, he had asked himself whether the creation of a just society, his life's objective, would actually make him happy. His heart answered "no", and unsurprisingly he lost the happiness of striving towards this objective. Eventually, the poetry of William Wordsworth showed him that beauty generates compassion for others and stimulates joy.[19] With renewed joy he continued to work towards a just society, but with more relish for the journey. He considered this one of the most pivotal shifts in his thinking. In fact, many of the differences between him and his father stemmed from this expanded source of joy.

Mill met Thomas Carlyle during one of the latter's visits to London in the early 1830s, and the two quickly became companions and correspondents. Mill offered to print Carlyle's works at his own expense and encouraged Carlyle to write his French Revolution, supplying him with materials in order to do so. In March 1835, while the manuscript of the completed first volume was in Mill's possession, Mill's housemaid unwittingly used it as tinder, destroying all "except some three or four bits of leaves".[20] Mortified, Mill offered Carlyle £200 (£17,742.16 in 2021) as compensation (Carlyle would only accept £100). Ideological differences would put an end to the friendship during the 1840s, though Carlyle's early influence on Mill would colour his later thought.[21]

Mill had been engaged in a pen-friendship with Auguste Comte, the founder of positivism and sociology, since Mill first contacted Comte in November 1841. Comte's sociologie was more an early philosophy of science than modern sociology is. Comte's positivism motivated Mill to eventually reject Bentham's psychological egoism and what he regarded as Bentham's cold, abstract view of human nature focused on legislation and politics, instead coming to favour Comte's more sociable view of human nature focused on historical facts and directed more towards human individuals in all their complexities.[22]

As a nonconformist who refused to subscribe to the Thirty-Nine Articles of the Church of England, Mill was not eligible to study at the University of Oxford or the University of Cambridge.[23] Instead he followed his father to work for the East India Company, and attended University College, London, to hear the lectures of John Austin, the first Professor of Jurisprudence.[24] He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1856.[25]

Mill's career as a colonial administrator at the East India Company spanned from when he was 17 years old in 1823 until 1858, when the Company's territories in India were directly annexed by the Crown, establishing direct Crown control over India.[26] In 1836, he was promoted to the Company's Political Department, where he was responsible for correspondence pertaining to the Company's relations with the princely states, and in 1856, was finally promoted to the position of Examiner of Indian Correspondence. In On Liberty, A Few Words on Non-Intervention, and other works, he opined that "To characterize any conduct whatever towards a barbarous people as a violation of the law of nations, only shows that he who so speaks has never considered the subject".[27] (Mill immediately added, however, that "A violation of the great principles of morality it may easily be.")[28] Mill viewed places such as India as having once been progressive in their outlook, but had now become stagnant in their development; he opined that this meant these regions had to be ruled via a form of "benevolent despotism", "provided the end is improvement".[29] When the Crown proposed to take direct control over the territories of the East India Company, he was tasked with defending Company rule, penning Memorandum on the Improvements in the Administration of India during the Last Thirty Years among other petitions.[30] He was offered a seat on the Council of India, the body created to advise the new Secretary of State for India, but declined, citing his disapproval of the new system of administration in India.[30]

On 21 April 1851, Mill married Harriet Taylor after 21 years of intimate friendship. Taylor was married when they met, and their relationship was close but generally believed to be chaste during the years before her first husband died in 1849. The couple waited two years before marrying in 1851. Brilliant in her own right, Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both friendship and marriage. His relationship with Taylor reinforced Mill's advocacy of women's rights. He said that in his stand against domestic violence, and for women's rights he was "chiefly an amanuensis to my wife". He called her mind a "perfect instrument", and said she was "the most eminently qualified of all those known to the author". He cites her influence in his final revision of On Liberty, which was published shortly after her death. Taylor died in 1858 after developing severe lung congestion, after only seven years of marriage to Mill.

Between the years 1865 and 1868 Mill served as Lord Rector of the University of St Andrews. At his inaugural address, delivered to the University on 1 February 1867, he made the now-famous (but often wrongly attributed) remark that "Bad men need nothing more to compass their ends, than that good men should look on and do nothing".[31] That Mill included that sentence in the address is a matter of historical record, but it by no means follows that it expressed a wholly original insight. During the same period, 1865–68, he was also a Member of Parliament (MP) for City of Westminster.[32][33] He was sitting for the Liberal Party. During his time as an MP, Mill advocated easing the burdens on Ireland. In 1866, he became the first person in the history of Parliament to call for women to be given the right to vote, vigorously defending this position in subsequent debate. He also became a strong advocate of such social reforms as labour unions and farm cooperatives. In Considerations on Representative Government, he called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially proportional representation, the single transferable vote, and the extension of suffrage. In April 1868, he favoured in a Commons debate the retention of capital punishment for such crimes as aggravated murder; he termed its abolition "an effeminacy in the general mind of the country".[34]

He was elected as a member to the American Philosophical Society in 1867.[35]

He was godfather to the philosopher Bertrand Russell.[36]

In his views on religion, Mill was an agnostic and a sceptic.[37][38][39][40]

Mill died in 1873, thirteen days before his 67th birthday, of erysipelas in Avignon, France, where his body was buried alongside his wife's.

Works and theories

 
Portrait of Mill by George Frederic Watts (1873)

A System of Logic

Mill joined the debate over scientific method which followed on from John Herschel's 1830 publication of A Preliminary Discourse on the study of Natural Philosophy, which incorporated inductive reasoning from the known to the unknown, discovering general laws in specific facts and verifying these laws empirically. William Whewell expanded on this in his 1837 History of the Inductive Sciences, from the Earliest to the Present Time, followed in 1840 by The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, Founded Upon their History, presenting induction as the mind superimposing concepts on facts. Laws were self-evident truths, which could be known without need for empirical verification.

Mill countered this in 1843 in A System of Logic (fully titled A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation). In "Mill's Methods" (of induction), as in Herschel's, laws were discovered through observation and induction, and required empirical verification.[41] Matilal remarks that Dignāga analysis is much like John Stuart Mill's Joint Method of Agreement and Difference, which is inductive. He suggested that it is very likely that during his stay in India he may have come across the tradition of logic, on which scholars started taking interest after 1824, though it is unknown whether it influenced his work or not.[42][43]

Theory of liberty

Mill's On Liberty (1859) addresses the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. Mill's idea is that only if a democratic society follows the Principle of Liberty can its political and social institutions fulfill their role of shaping national character so that its citizens can realise the permanent interests of people as progressive beings (Rawls, Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy; p 289).

Mill states the Principle of Liberty as: "the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection". "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant."[44]

One way to read Mill's Principle of Liberty as a principle of public reason is to see it excluding certain kinds of reasons from being taken into account in legislation, or in guiding the moral coercion of public opinion. (Rawls, Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy; p. 291). These reasons include those founded in other persons good; reasons of excellence and ideals of human perfection; reasons of dislike or disgust, or of preference.

Mill states that "harms" which may be prevented include acts of omission as well as acts of commission. Thus, failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act, as does failing to pay taxes, or failing to appear as a witness in court. All such harmful omissions may be regulated, according to Mill. By contrast, it does not count as harming someone if—without force or fraud—the affected individual consents to assume the risk: thus one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others, provided there is no deception involved. (He does, however, recognise one limit to consent: society should not permit people to sell themselves into slavery.)

The question of what counts as a self-regarding action and what actions, whether of omission or commission, constitute harmful actions subject to regulation, continues to exercise interpreters of Mill. He did not consider giving offence to constitute "harm"; an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society.[45]

 
John Stuart Mill and Helen Taylor. Helen was the daughter of Harriet Taylor and collaborated with Mill for fifteen years after her mother's death in 1858.

Social liberty and tyranny of majority

Mill believed that "the struggle between Liberty and Authority is the most conspicuous feature in the portions of history."[46] For him, liberty in antiquity was a "contest…between subjects, or some classes of subjects, and the government."[46]

Mill defined social liberty as protection from "the tyranny of political rulers". He introduced a number of different concepts of the form tyranny can take, referred to as social tyranny, and tyranny of the majority. Social liberty for Mill meant putting limits on the ruler's power so that he would not be able to use that power to further his own wishes and thus make decisions that could harm society. In other words, people should have the right to have a say in the government's decisions. He said that social liberty was "the nature and limits of the power which can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual." It was attempted in two ways: first, by obtaining recognition of certain immunities (called political liberties or rights); and second, by establishment of a system of "constitutional checks".

However, in Mill's view, limiting the power of government was not enough:[47]

Society can and does execute its own mandates: and if it issues wrong mandates instead of right, or any mandates at all in things with which it ought not to meddle, it practises a social tyranny more formidable than many kinds of political oppression, since, though not usually upheld by such extreme penalties, it leaves fewer means of escape, penetrating much more deeply into the details of life, and enslaving the soul itself.

Liberty

Mill's view on liberty, which was influenced by Joseph Priestley and Josiah Warren, is that individuals ought to be free to do as they wished unless they caused harm to others. Individuals are rational enough to make decisions about their well being. Government should interfere when it is for the protection of society. Mill explained:[44]

The sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier, because, in the opinion of others, to do so would be wise, or even right.… The only part of the conduct of anyone, for which he is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part which merely concerns him, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign.

Freedom of speech

On Liberty involves an impassioned defense of free speech. Mill argues that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. We can never be sure, he contends, that a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth. He also argues that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons. First, individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas. Second, by forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma. It is not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true; one must understand why the belief in question is the true one. Along those same lines Mill wrote, "unmeasured vituperation, employed on the side of prevailing opinion, really does deter people from expressing contrary opinions, and from listening to those who express them."[48][45]: 51 

As an influential advocate of freedom of speech, Mill objected to censorship:[49]

I choose, by preference the cases which are least favourable to me—In which the argument opposing freedom of opinion, both on truth and that of utility, is considered the strongest. Let the opinions impugned be the belief of God and in a future state, or any of the commonly received doctrines of morality ... But I must be permitted to observe that it is not the feeling sure of a doctrine (be it what it may) which I call an assumption of infallibility. It is the undertaking to decide that question for others, without allowing them to hear what can be said on the contrary side. And I denounce and reprobate this pretension not the less if it is put forth on the side of my most solemn convictions. However positive anyone's persuasion may be, not only of the faculty but of the pernicious consequences, but (to adopt expressions which I altogether condemn) the immorality and impiety of opinion.—yet if, in pursuance of that private judgement, though backed by the public judgement of his country or contemporaries, he prevents the opinion from being heard in its defence, he assumes infallibility. And so far from the assumption being less objectionable or less dangerous because the opinion is called immoral or impious, this is the case of all others in which it is most fatal.

Mill outlines the benefits of "searching for and discovering the truth" as a way to further knowledge. He argued that even if an opinion is false, the truth can be better understood by refuting the error. And as most opinions are neither completely true nor completely false, he points out that allowing free expression allows the airing of competing views as a way to preserve partial truth in various opinions.[50] Worried about minority views being suppressed, he argued in support of freedom of speech on political grounds, stating that it is a critical component for a representative government to have to empower debate over public policy.[50] He also eloquently argued that freedom of expression allows for personal growth and self-realization. He said that freedom of speech was a vital way to develop talents and realise a person's potential and creativity. He repeatedly said that eccentricity was preferable to uniformity and stagnation.[50]

Harm principle

The belief that freedom of speech would advance society presupposed a society sufficiently culturally and institutionally advanced to be capable of progressive improvement. If any argument is really wrong or harmful, the public will judge it as wrong or harmful, and then those arguments cannot be sustained and will be excluded. Mill argued that even any arguments which are used in justifying murder or rebellion against the government shouldn't be politically suppressed or socially persecuted. According to him, if rebellion is really necessary, people should rebel; if murder is truly proper, it should be allowed. However, the way to express those arguments should be a public speech or writing, not in a way that causes actual harm to others. Such is the harm principle: "That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others."[51]

At the beginning of the 20th century, Associate justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr. made the standard of "clear and present danger" based on Mill's idea. In the majority opinion, Holmes writes:

The question in every case is whether the words used are used in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils that Congress has a right to prevent.[52]

Holmes suggested that falsely shouting out "Fire!" in a dark theatre, which evokes panic and provokes injury, would be such a case of speech that creates an illegal danger.[53] But if the situation allows people to reason by themselves and decide to accept it or not, any argument or theology should not be blocked.

Nowadays, Mill's argument is generally accepted by many democratic countries, and they have laws at least guided by the harm principle. For example, in American law some exceptions limit free speech such as obscenity, defamation, breach of peace, and "fighting words".[54]

Freedom of the press

In On Liberty, Mill thought it was necessary for him to restate the case for press freedom. He considered that argument already won. Almost no politician or commentator in mid-19th-century Britain wanted a return to Tudor and Stuart-type press censorship. However, Mill warned new forms of censorship could emerge in the future.[55] Indeed, in 2013 the Cameron Tory government considered setting up a so-called independent official regulator of the UK press.[56] This prompted demands for better basic legal protection of press freedom. A new British Bill of Rights could include a US-type constitutional ban on governmental infringement of press freedom and block other official attempts to control freedom of opinion and expression.[57]

Colonialism

Mill, an employee of the East India Company from 1823 to 1858,[58] argued in support of what he called a "benevolent despotism" with regard to the administration of overseas colonies.[59] Mill argued:[60]

To suppose that the same international customs, and the same rules of international morality, can obtain between one civilized nation and another, and between civilized nations and barbarians, is a grave error.… To characterize any conduct whatever towards a barbarous people as a violation of the law of nations, only shows that he who so speaks has never considered the subject.

Mill expressed general support for Company rule in India, but expressed reservations on specific Company policies in India which he disagreed with.[61]

Slavery and racial equality

In 1850, Mill sent an anonymous letter (which came to be known under the title "The Negro Question"),[62] in rebuttal to Thomas Carlyle's letter to Fraser's Magazine for Town and Country in which Carlyle argued for slavery. Mill supported abolishing slavery in the United States, expressing his opposition to slavery in his essay of 1869, The Subjection of Women:[63]

This absolutely extreme case of the law of force, condemned by those who can tolerate almost every other form of arbitrary power, and which, of all others, presents features the most revolting to the feeling of all who look at it from an impartial position, was the law of civilized and Christian England within the memory of persons now living: and in one half of Anglo-Saxon America three or four years ago, not only did slavery exist, but the slave trade, and the breeding of slaves expressly for it, was a general practice between slave states. Yet not only was there a greater strength of sentiment against it, but, in England at least, a less amount either of feeling or of interest in favour of it, than of any other of the customary abuses of force: for its motive was the love of gain, unmixed and undisguised: and those who profited by it were a very small numerical fraction of the country, while the natural feeling of all who were not personally interested in it, was unmitigated abhorrence.

Mill corresponded with John Appleton, an American legal reformer from Maine, extensively on the topic of racial equality. Appleton influenced Mill's work on such, especially swaying him on the optimal economic and social welfare plan for the Antebellum South.[64][65][66] In a letter sent to Appleton in response to a previous letter, Mill expressed his view on antebellum integration:[64]

I cannot look forward with satisfaction to any settlement but complete emancipation—land given to every negro family either separately or in organized communities under such rules as may be found temporarily necessary—the schoolmaster set to work in every village & the tide of free immigration turned on in those fertile regions from which slavery has hitherto excluded it. If this be done, the gentle & docile character which seems to distinguish the negroes will prevent any mischief on their side, while the proofs they are giving of fighting powers will do more in a year than all other things in a century to make the whites respect them & consent to their being politically & socially equals.

Women's rights

 
"A Feminine Philosopher". Caricature by Spy published in Vanity Fair in 1873

Mill's view of history was that right up until his time "the whole of the female" and "the great majority of the male sex" were simply "slaves". He countered arguments to the contrary, arguing that relations between sexes simply amounted to "the legal subordination of one sex to the other—[which] is wrong itself, and now one of the chief hindrances to human improvement; and that it ought to be replaced by a principle of perfect equality." Here, then, we have an instance of Mill's use of "slavery" in a sense which, compared to its fundamental meaning of absolute unfreedom of person, is an extended and arguably a rhetorical rather than a literal sense.

With this, Mill can be considered among the earliest male proponents of gender equality, having been recruited by American feminist John Neal during his stay in London circa 1825–1827.[67] His book The Subjection of Women (1861, publ.1869) is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author.[68] In The Subjection of Women, Mill attempts to make a case for perfect equality.[69]

In his proposal for a universal education system sponsored by the state, Mill expands benefits for many marginalized groups, especially for women. For Mill, a universal education held the potential to create new abilities and novel types of behavior of which the current receiving generation and their descendants could both benefit from. Such a pathway to opportunity would enable women to gain "industrial and social independence" that would allow them the same movement in their agency and citizenship as men. Mill's view of opportunity stands out in its reach, but even more so for the population he foresees who could benefit from it. Mill was hopeful of the autonomy such an education could allow for its recipients and especially for women. Through the consequential sophistication and knowledge attained, individuals are able to properly act in ways that recedes away from those leading towards overpopulation. This stands directly in contrast with the view held by many of Mill's contemporaries and predecessors who viewed such inclusive programs to be counter intuitive. Aiming such help at marginalized groups, such as the poor and working class, would only serve to reward them with the opportunity to move to a higher status, thus encouraging greater fertility which at its extreme could lead to overproduction.

He talks about the role of women in marriage and how it must be changed. Mill comments on three major facets of women's lives that he felt are hindering them:

  1. society and gender construction;
  2. education; and
  3. marriage.

He argues that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity.[63][70] As a Member of Parliament, Mill introduced an unsuccessful amendment to the Reform Bill to substitute the word "person" in place of "man".[71]

Utilitarianism

 
"The utilitarian doctrine is, that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to that end." ~ John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (1863)[72]

The canonical statement of Mill's utilitarianism can be found in his book, Utilitarianism. Although this philosophy has a long tradition, Mill's account is primarily influenced by Jeremy Bentham and Mill's father James Mill.

John Stuart Mill believed in the philosophy of utilitarianism, which he would describe as the principle that holds "that actions are right in the proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness". By happiness he means, "intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure".[73] It is clear that we do not all value virtues as a path to happiness and that we sometimes only value them for selfish reasons. However, Mill asserts that upon reflection, even when we value virtues for selfish reasons we are in fact cherishing them as a part of our happiness.

Bentham's famous formulation of utilitarianism is known as the greatest-happiness principle. It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest aggregate happiness among all sentient beings, within reason. In a similar vein, Mill's method of determining the best utility is that a moral agent, when given the choice between two or more actions, ought to choose the action that contributes most to (maximizes) the total happiness in the world. Happiness, in this context, is understood as the production of pleasure or privation of pain. Given that determining the action that produces the most utility is not always so clear cut, Mill suggests that the utilitarian moral agent, when attempting to rank the utility of different actions, should refer to the general experience of persons. That is, if people generally experience more happiness following action X than they do action Y, the utilitarian should conclude that action X produces more utility than action Y, and so is to be preferred.[74]

Utilitarianism is a consequentialist ethical theory, meaning that it holds that acts are justified insofar as they produce a desirable outcome. The overarching goal of utilitarianism—the ideal consequence—is to achieve the "greatest good for the greatest number as the end result of human action."[75] In Utilitarianism, Mill states that "happiness is the sole end of human action".[34] This statement aroused some controversy, which is why Mill took it a step further, explaining how the very nature of humans wanting happiness, and who "take it to be reasonable under free consideration", demands that happiness is indeed desirable.[11] In other words, free will leads everyone to make actions inclined on their own happiness, unless reasoned that it would improve the happiness of others, in which case, the greatest utility is still being achieved. To that extent, the utilitarianism that Mill is describing is a default lifestyle that he believes is what people who have not studied a specific opposing field of ethics would naturally and subconsciously use when faced with a decision.

Utilitarianism is thought of by some of its activists to be a more developed and overarching ethical theory of Immanuel Kant's belief in goodwill, and not just some default cognitive process of humans. Where Kant (1724–1804) would argue that reason can only be used properly by goodwill, Mill would say that the only way to universally create fair laws and systems would be to step back to the consequences, whereby Kant's ethical theories become based around the ultimate good—utility.[76] By this logic the only valid way to discern what is the proper reason would be to view the consequences of any action and weigh the good and the bad, even if on the surface, the ethical reasoning seems to indicate a different train of thought.

Higher and lower pleasures

Mill's major contribution to utilitarianism is his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures. Bentham treats all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argues that intellectual and moral pleasures (higher pleasures) are superior to more physical forms of pleasure (lower pleasures). He distinguishes between happiness and contentment, claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter, a belief wittily encapsulated in the statement that, "it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool, or the pig, are of a different opinion, it is because they only know their own side of the question."[74]

This made Mill believe that "our only ultimate end"[77] is happiness. One unique part of his utilitarian view, that is not seen in others, is the idea of higher and lower pleasures. Mill explains the different pleasures as:

If I am asked, what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference […] that is the more desirable pleasure.[78]

He defines higher pleasures as mental, moral, and aesthetic pleasures, and lower pleasures as being more sensational. He believed that higher pleasures should be seen as preferable to lower pleasures since they have a greater quality in virtue. He holds that pleasures gained in activity are of a higher quality than those gained passively.[79]

Mill defines the difference between higher and lower forms of pleasure with the principle that those who have experienced both tend to prefer one over the other. This is, perhaps, in direct contrast with Bentham's statement that "Quantity of pleasure being equal, push-pin is as good as poetry",[80] that, if a simple child's game like hopscotch causes more pleasure to more people than a night at the opera house, it is more incumbent upon a society to devote more resources to propagating hopscotch than running opera houses. Mill's argument is that the "simple pleasures" tend to be preferred by people who have no experience with high art, and are therefore not in a proper position to judge. He also argues that people who, for example, are noble or practise philosophy, benefit society more than those who engage in individualist practices for pleasure, which are lower forms of happiness. It is not the agent's own greatest happiness that matters "but the greatest amount of happiness altogether".[81]

Chapters

Mill separated his explanation of Utilitarianism into five different sections:

  1. General Remarks;
  2. What Utilitarianism Is;
  3. Of the Ultimate Sanction of the Principle of Utility;
  4. Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible;
  5. and Of the Connection between Justice and Utility.

In the General Remarks portion of his essay, he speaks how next to no progress has been made when it comes to judging what is right and what is wrong of morality and if there is such a thing as moral instinct (which he argues that there may not be). However, he agrees that in general "Our moral faculty, according to all those of its interpreters who are entitled to the name of thinkers, supplies us only with the general principles of moral judgments".[82]

In What Utilitarianism Is, he focuses no longer on background information but utilitarianism itself. He quotes utilitarianism as "The greatest happiness principle", defining this theory by saying that pleasure and no pain are the only inherently good things in the world and expands on it by saying that "actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure."[83] He views it not as an animalistic concept because he sees seeking out pleasure as a way of using our higher facilities. He also says in this chapter that the happiness principle is based not exclusively on the individual but mainly on the community.

Mill also defends the idea of a "strong utilitarian conscience (i.e. a strong feeling of obligation to the general happiness)".[77] He argued that humans have a desire to be happy and that that desire causes us to want to be in unity with other humans. This causes us to care about the happiness of others, as well as the happiness of complete strangers. But this desire also causes us to experience pain when we perceive harm to other people. He believes in internal sanctions that make us experience guilt and appropriate our actions. These internal sanctions make us want to do good because we do not want to feel guilty for our actions. Happiness is our ultimate end because it is our duty. He argues that we do not need to be constantly motivated by the concern of people's happiness because most of the actions done by people are done out of good intention, and the good of the world is made up of the good of the people.

In Mill's fourth chapter, Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible, he speaks of what proofs of Utility are affected. He starts this chapter off by saying that all of his claims cannot be backed up by reasoning. He claims that the only proof that something brings one pleasure is if someone finds it pleasurable. Next, he talks about how morality is the basic way to achieve happiness. He also discusses in this chapter that Utilitarianism is beneficial for virtue. He says that "it maintains not only that virtue is to be desired, but that it is to be desired disinterestedly, for itself."[84] In his final chapter he looks at the connection between Utilitarianism and justice. He contemplates the question of whether justice is something distinct from Utility or not. He reasons this question in several different ways and finally comes to the conclusion that in certain cases justice is essential for Utility, but in others, social duty is far more important than justice. Mill believes that "justice must give way to some other moral principle, but that what is just in ordinary cases is, by reason of that other principle, not just in the particular case."[85]

The qualitative account of happiness that Mill advocates thus sheds light on his account presented in On Liberty. As he suggests in that text, utility is to be conceived in relation to humanity "as a progressive being", which includes the development and exercise of rational capacities as we strive to achieve a "higher mode of existence". The rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to provide the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge and the greatest ability for the greatest number to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities.

Mill redefines the definition of happiness as "the ultimate end, for the sake of which all other things are desirable (whether we are considering our own good or that of other people) is an existence as free as possible from pain and as rich as possible in enjoyments".[86] He firmly believed that moral rules and obligations could be referenced to promoting happiness, which connects to having a noble character. While Mill is not a standard act utilitarian or rule utilitarian, he is a minimizing utilitarian, which "affirms that it would be desirable to maximize happiness for the greatest number, but not that we are morally required to do so".[87]

Achieving happiness

Mill believed that for the majority of people (those with but a moderate degree of sensibility and of capacity for enjoyment) happiness is best achieved en passant, rather than striving for it directly. This meant no self-consciousness, scrutiny, self-interrogation, dwelling on, thinking about, imagining or questioning on one's happiness. Then, if otherwise fortunately circumstanced, one would "inhale happiness with the air you breathe".[88][89]

Economic philosophy

 
Essays on Economics and Society, 1967

Mill's early economic philosophy was one of free markets. However, he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare.[90] He originally believed that "equality of taxation" meant "equality of sacrifice" and that progressive taxation penalized those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore "a mild form of robbery".[91]

Given an equal tax rate regardless of income, Mill agreed that inheritance should be taxed. A utilitarian society would agree that everyone should be equal one way or another. Therefore, receiving inheritance would put one ahead of society unless taxed on the inheritance. Those who donate should consider and choose carefully where their money goes—some charities are more deserving than others. Considering public charities boards such as a government will disburse the money equally. However, a private charity board like a church would disburse the monies fairly to those who are in more need than others.[92]

Later he altered his views toward a more socialist bent, adding chapters to his Principles of Political Economy in defence of a socialist outlook, and defending some socialist causes.[93] Within this revised work he also made the radical proposal that the whole wage system be abolished in favour of a co-operative wage system. Nonetheless, some of his views on the idea of flat taxation remained,[94] albeit altered in the third edition of the Principles of Political Economy to reflect a concern for differentiating restrictions on "unearned" incomes, which he favoured, and those on "earned" incomes, which he did not favour.[95]

In his autobiography, Mill stated that in relation to his later views on political economy, his "ideal of ultimate improvement... would class [him] decidedly under the general designation of Socialists". His views shifted partly due to reading the works of utopian socialists, but also from the influence of Harriet Taylor.[96] In his work Socialism, Mill argued that the prevalence of poverty in contemporary industrial capitalist societies was "pro tanto a failure of the social arrangements", and that attempts to condone this state of affairs as being the result of individual failings did not represent a justification of them but instead were "an irresistible claim upon every human being for protection against suffering".[97]

Mill's Principles, first published in 1848, was one of the most widely read of all books on economics in the period.[98] As Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations had during an earlier period, Principles came to dominate economics teaching. In the case of Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919, when it was replaced by Marshall's Principles of Economics.

Criticism

In Karl Marx's critique of political economy, he mentioned Mill in the Grundrisse. Marx claimed that Mill's thinking posited the categories of capital in an ahistorical fashion.[99]

Economic democracy

Mill's main objection to Marxism focused on what he saw its destruction of competition. He wrote, "I utterly dissent from the most conspicuous and vehement part of their teaching—their declamations against competition." He was an egalitarian, but he argued more for equal opportunity and placed meritocracy above all other ideals in this regard. According to Mill, a socialist society would only be attainable through the provision of basic education for all, promoting economic democracy instead of capitalism, in the manner of substituting capitalist businesses with worker cooperatives. He says:

The form of association, however, which if mankind continue to improve, must be expected in the end to predominate, is not that which can exist between a capitalist as chief, and work-people without a voice in the management, but the association of the labourers themselves on terms of equality, collectively owning the capital with which they carry on their operations, and working under managers elected and removable by themselves.[100][101]

Political democracy

Mill's major work on political democracy, Considerations on Representative Government, defends two fundamental principles: extensive participation by citizens and enlightened competence of rulers.[102] The two values are obviously in tension, and some readers have concluded that he is an elitist democrat,[103] while others count him as an earlier participatory democrat.[104] In one section, he appears to defend plural voting, in which more competent citizens are given extra votes (a view he later repudiated). However, in another chapter he argues cogently for the value of participation by all citizens. He believed that the incompetence of the masses could eventually be overcome if they were given a chance to take part in politics, especially at the local level.

Mill is one of the few political philosophers ever to serve in government as an elected official. In his three years in Parliament, he was more willing to compromise than the "radical" principles expressed in his writing would lead one to expect.[105]

Mill was a major proponent of the diffusion and use of public education to the working class. He saw the value of the individual person, and believed that "man had the inherent capability of guiding his own destiny-but only if his faculties were developed and fulfilled", which could be achieved through education.[106] He regarded education as a pathway to improve human nature which to him meant "to encourage, among other characteristics, diversity and originality, the energy of character, initiative, autonomy, intellectual cultivation, aesthetic sensibility, non-self-regarding interests, prudence, responsibility, and self-control".[107] Education allowed for humans to develop into full informed citizens that had the tools to improve their condition and make fully informed electoral decisions. The power of education lay in its ability to serve as a great equalizer among the classes allowing the working class the ability to control their own destiny and compete with the upper classes. Mill recognized the paramount importance of public education in avoiding the tyranny of the majority by ensuring that all the voters and political participants were fully developed individuals. It was through education, he believed, that an individual could become a full participant within representative democracy.

Theories of wealth and income distribution

In Principles of Political Economy, Mill offered an analysis of two economic phenomena often linked together: the laws of production and wealth and the modes of its distribution. Regarding the former, he believed that it was not possible to alter to laws of production, "the ultimate properties of matter and mind... only to employ these properties to bring about events we are interested".[108] The modes of distribution of wealth is a matter of human institutions solely, starting with what Mill believed to be the primary and fundamental institution: Individual Property.[109] He believed that all individuals must start on equal terms, with division of the instruments of production fairly among all members of society. Once each member has an equal amount of individual property, they must be left to their own exertion not to be interfered with by the state. Regarding inequality of wealth, Mill believed that it was the role of the government to establish both social and economic policies that promote the equality of opportunity.

The government, according to Mill, should implement three tax policies to help alleviate poverty:[110]

  1. fairly-assessed income tax;
  2. an inheritance tax; and
  3. a policy to restrict sumptuary consumption.

Inheritance of capital and wealth plays a large role in development of inequality, because it provides greater opportunity for those receiving the inheritance. Mill's solution to inequality of wealth brought about by inheritance was to implement a greater tax on inheritances, because he believed the most important authoritative function of the government is taxation, and taxation judiciously implemented could promote equality.[110]

The environment

Mill demonstrated an early insight into the value of the natural world—in particular in Book IV, chapter VI of Principles of Political Economy: "Of the Stationary State"[111][112] in which Mill recognised wealth beyond the material, and argued that the logical conclusion of unlimited growth was destruction of the environment and a reduced quality of life. He concludes that a stationary state could be preferable to unending economic growth:

I cannot, therefore, regard the stationary states of capital and wealth with the unaffected aversion so generally manifested towards it by political economists of the old school.

If the earth must lose that great portion of its pleasantness which it owes to things that the unlimited increase of wealth and population would extirpate from it, for the mere purpose of enabling it to support a larger, but not a better or a happier population, I sincerely hope, for the sake of posterity, that they will be content to be stationary, long before necessity compel them to it.

Rate of profit

According to Mill, the ultimate tendency in an economy is for the rate of profit to decline due to diminishing returns in agriculture and increase in population at a Malthusian rate.[113]

In popular culture

 
Statue of Mill by Thomas Woolner in Victoria Embankment Gardens, London

John Stuart Mill,
By a mighty effort of will,
Overcame his natural bonhomie
And wrote Principles of Political Economy.

John Stuart Mill, of his own free will,
On half a pint of shandy was particularly ill.

Major publications

Title Date Source
"Two Letters on the Measure of Value" 1822 "The Traveller"
"Questions of Population" 1823 "Black Dwarf"
"War Expenditure" 1824 Westminster Review
"Quarterly Review – Political Economy" 1825 Westminster Review
"Review of Miss Martineau's Tales" 1830 Examiner
"The Spirit of the Age" 1831 Examiner
"Use and Abuse of Political Terms" 1832
"What is Poetry" 1833, 1859
"Rationale of Representation" 1835
"De Tocqueville on Democracy in America [i]" 1835
"State of Society in America" 1836
"Civilization" 1836
"Essay on Bentham" 1838
"Essay on Coleridge" 1840
"Essays on Government" 1840
"De Tocqueville on Democracy in America [ii]" 1840
A System of Logic 1843
Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy 1844
"Claims of Labour" 1845 Edinburgh Review
The Principles of Political Economy: with some of their applications to social philosophy 1848
"The Negro Question" 1850 Fraser's Magazine
"Reform of the Civil Service" 1854
Dissertations and Discussions 1859
A Few Words on Non-intervention 1859
On Liberty 1859
Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform 1859
Considerations on Representative Government 1861
"Centralisation" 1862 Edinburgh Review
"The Contest in America" 1862 Harper's Magazine
Utilitarianism 1863
An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy 1865
Auguste Comte and Positivism 1865
Inaugural Address at St. Andrews Concerning the value of culture 1867
"Speech in Favour of Capital Punishment"[116][117] 1868
England and Ireland 1868
"Thornton on Labour and its Claims" 1869 Fortnightly Review
The Subjection of Women 1869
Chapters and Speeches on the Irish Land Question 1870
Autobiography 1873
Three Essays on Religion: Nature, the Utility of religion, and Theism 1874 Internet Archive
Socialism 1879 Belfords, Clarke & Co.
"Notes on N. W. Senior's Political Economy" 1945 Economica N.S. 12

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Hyman, Anthony (1982). Charles Babbage: Pioneer of the Computer. Princeton University Press. pp. 120–121. What effect did Babbages Economy of Machinery and Manufacturers have? Generally his book received little attention as it not greatly concerned with such traditional problems of economics as the nature of 'value'. Actually the effect was considerable, his discussion of factories and manufactures entering the main currents of economic thought. Here it must suffice to look briefly at its influence on two major figures; John Stuart Mill and Adam Smith
  2. ^ Varouxakis, Georgios (1999). "Guizot's historical works and J.S. Mill's reception of Tocqueville". History of Political Thought. 20 (2): 292–312. JSTOR 26217580.
  3. ^ Friedrich Hayek (1941). "The Counter-Revolution of Science". Economica. 8 (31): 281–320. doi:10.2307/2549335. JSTOR 2549335.
  4. ^ a b c "The Project Gutenberg EBook of Autobiography, by John Stuart Mill" 18 May 2020 at the Wayback Machine gutenberg.org. Retrieved 11 June 2013.
  5. ^ Michael N. Forster, After Herder: Philosophy of Language in the German Tradition, Oxford University Press, 2010, p. 9.
  6. ^ Ralph Raico (27 January 2018). Mises Institute (ed.). "John Stuart Mill and the New Liberalism".
  7. ^ Bertrand Russell (1998). "2: Adolescence". Autobiography. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0415189859.
  8. ^ . Canadian Broadcasting Corporation. 1959. Archived from the original on 26 January 2010. Retrieved 8 March 2010.
  9. ^ Mommsen, Wolfgang J. (2013). Max Weber and His Contemporaries. Routledge. pp. 8–10.
  10. ^ Thouverez, Emile. 1908. Stuart Mill (4th ed.) Paris: Bloud & Cie. p. 23.
  11. ^ a b Macleod, Christopher (14 November 2017). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  12. ^ "John Stuart Mill's On Liberty". victorianweb. Retrieved 23 July 2009. On Liberty is a rational justification of the freedom of the individual in opposition to the claims of the state to impose unlimited control and is thus a defense of the rights of the individual against the state.
  13. ^ "John Stuart Mill (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 31 July 2009.
  14. ^ "Orator Hunt and the first suffrage petition 1832". UK Parliament.
  15. ^ "John Stuart Mill and the 1866 petition". UK Parliament.
  16. ^ Halevy, Elie (1966). The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism. Beacon Press. pp. 282–284. ISBN 978-0191010200.
  17. ^ a b c d "Cornell University Library Making of America Collection". collections.library.cornell.edu.
  18. ^ Murray N. Rothbard (1 February 2006). An Austrian Perspective on the History of Economic Thought. Ludwig von Mises Institute. p. 105. ISBN 978-0945466482. Retrieved 21 January 2011.
  19. ^ "John Stuart Mill's Mental Breakdown, Victorian Unconversions, and Romantic Poetry". victorianweb.org.
  20. ^ Carlyle, Thomas (7 March 1835). Kinser, Brent E. (ed.). "TC TO JAMES FRASER". The Carlyle Letters Online. doi:10.1215/lt-18350307-TC-JFR-01.
  21. ^ Baumgarten, Murray (2004). "Mill, John Stuart". In Cumming, Mark (ed.). The Carlyle Encyclopedia. Madison and Teaneck, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press. p. 326. ISBN 9780838637920.
  22. ^ Pickering, Mary. 1993. Auguste Comte: an intellectual biography. Cambridge University Press. pp. 509, 512, 535, 537.
  23. ^ Capaldi, Nicholas. John Stuart Mill: A Biography. p. 33, Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0521620244.
  24. ^ "Cornell University Library Making of America Collection". collections.library.cornell.edu.
  25. ^ "Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter M" (PDF). American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 15 April 2011.
  26. ^ Mill, John Stuart. Writings on India. Edited by John M. Robson, Martin Moir and Zawahir Moir. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge, c. 1990.
  27. ^ Klausen, Jimmy Casas (7 January 2016). "Violence and Epistemology J. S. Mill's Indians after the "Mutiny"". Political Research Quarterly. 69: 96–107. doi:10.1177/1065912915623379. ISSN 1065-9129. S2CID 157038995.
  28. ^ Jennifer Pitts, Boundaries of the International: Law and Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2018), 165.
  29. ^ Harris, Abram L. (1 January 1964). "John Stuart Mill: Servant of the East India Company". The Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science. 30 (2): 185–202. doi:10.2307/139555. JSTOR 139555.
  30. ^ a b Lal, Vinay. 1998. "'John Stuart Mill and India', a review-article". New Quest 54(1):54–64.
  31. ^ Inaugural Address at St Andrews, Longmans, Green, Reader, And Dyer, 1867.
  32. ^ "No. 22991". The London Gazette. 14 July 1865. p. 3528.
  33. ^ Capaldi, Nicholas. John Stuart Mill: A Biography. pp. 321–322, Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0521620244.
  34. ^ a b Sher, George, ed. 2001. Utilitarianism and the 1868 Speech on Capital Punishment, by J. S. Mill. Hackett Publishing Co.
  35. ^ "APS Member History". search.amphilsoc.org. Retrieved 21 April 2021.
  36. ^ "More Adept With Concepts Than People". The New York Times. 6 December 1996. Retrieved 19 March 2022.
  37. ^ "Editorial Notes". Secular Review. 16 (13): 203. 28 March 1885. It has always seemed to us that this is one of the instances in which Mill approached, out of deference to conventional opinion, as near to the borderland of Cant as he well could without compromising his pride of place as a recognised thinker and sceptic
  38. ^ Linda C. Raeder (2002). "Spirit of the Age". John Stuart Mill and the Religion of Humanity. University of Missouri Press. p. 65. ISBN 978-0826263278. Comte welcomed the prospect of being attacked publicly for his irreligion, he said, as this would permit him to clarify the nonatheistic nature of his and Mill's "atheism".
  39. ^ Larsen, Timothy (2018). John Stuart Mill: A Secular Life. Oxford University Press. p. 14. ISBN 978-0198753155. A letter John wrote from Forde Abbey when he was eight years old casually mentions in his general report of his activities that he too had been to Thorncombe parish church, so even when Bentham had home-field advantage, the boy was still receiving a Christian spiritual formation. Indeed, Mill occasionally attended Christian worship services during his teen years and thereafter for the rest of his life. The sea of faith was full and all around
  40. ^ Larsen, Timothy (7 December 2018). "A surprisingly religious John Stuart Mill". TL: Mill decided that strictly in terms of proof the right answer to that question of God's existence is that it is 'a very probable hypothesis.' He also thought it was perfectly rational and legitimate to believe in God as an act of hope or as the result of one's efforts to discern the meaning of life as a whole.
  41. ^ Shermer, Michael (15 August 2002). In Darwin's Shadow: The Life and Science of Alfred Russel Wallace: A Biographical Study on the Psychology of History. Oxford University Press. p. 212. ISBN 978-0199923854.
  42. ^ Arindam., Matilal, Bimal Krishna. Chakrabarti (1994). Knowing from words : Western and Indian philosophical analysis of understanding and testimony. Kluwer Academic. ISBN 0792323459. OCLC 28016267.
  43. ^ Matilal, BimalKrishna (March 1989). "Ny?ya critique of the Buddhist doctrine of non-soul". Journal of Indian Philosophy. 17 (1). doi:10.1007/bf00160139. ISSN 0022-1791. S2CID 170181380.
  44. ^ a b Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 1869. On Liberty (4th ed.). London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer. pp. 21–22 17 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
  45. ^ a b Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 2001. On Liberty 14 November 2019 at the Wayback Machine. Kitchener, ON: Batoche Books. Retrieved 17 June 2020.
  46. ^ a b "I. Introductory. Mill, John Stuart. 1869. On Liberty". bartleby.com. Retrieved 16 July 2018.
  47. ^ Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 2006. On Liberty. Penguin Classics. ISBN 978-0141441474. pp. 10–11.
  48. ^ Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 1909. "On Liberty". pp. 195–290 in Harvard Classics 25, edited by C. W. Eliot. New York: PF Collier & Son. p. 248.
  49. ^ Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 1985. On Liberty, edited by G. Himmelfarb, UK: Penguin. pp. 83–84.
  50. ^ a b c Paul, Ellen Frankel, Fred Dycus Miller, and Jeffrey Paul. 2004. Freedom of Speech 21. Cambridge University Press.
  51. ^ Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 1863. On Liberty. Ticknor and Fields. p. 23
  52. ^ Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919).
  53. ^ George & Kline 2006, p. 409.
  54. ^ George & Kline 2006, p. 410.
  55. ^ John Stuart Mill's On Liberty: A Translation into Modern English, Kindle edition, 2013. . 38. ISBN 978-0906321638
  56. ^ "British Press Freedom under Threat", New York Times, 14 November 2013.
  57. ^ Abbott, Lewis F. Defending Liberty: the Case for a New Bill of Rights. ISR/Google Books, 2019. p. 22. ISBN 978-0906321737
  58. ^ "J. S. Mill's Career at the East India Company". victorianweb.org.
  59. ^ Theo Goldberg, David (2000). ""Liberalism's limits: Carlyle and Mill on "the negro question". Nineteenth-Century Contexts. 22 (2): 203–216. doi:10.1080/08905490008583508. S2CID 194002917.
  60. ^ John Stuart Mill, Dissertations and Discussions: Political, Philosophical, and Historical (New York 1874) Vol. 3, pp. 252–253.
  61. ^ Williams, David (7 February 2020). "John Stuart Mill and the practice of colonial rule in India". Journal of International Political Theory. 17 (3): 412–428. doi:10.1177/1755088220903349. ISSN 1755-0882. S2CID 214445850.
  62. ^ Mill, John Stuart. 1850. "The Negro Question 17 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine". Fraser's Magazine for Town and Country 41:25–31.
  63. ^ a b Mill, John Stuart. 1869. The Subjection of Women 29 April 2015 at the Wayback Machine. ch. 1.
  64. ^ a b "The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume XV – The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill 1849–1873 Part II – Online Library of Liberty". oll.libertyfund.org. Retrieved 28 April 2020.
  65. ^ Vile, John R. (2003). Great American Judges: An Encyclopedia. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1576079898.
  66. ^ P, T. Peter (1991). "John Stuart Mill, Thomas Carlyle, and the U.s. Civil War". Historian. 54 (1): 93–106. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6563.1991.tb00843.x. ISSN 1540-6563.
  67. ^ Daggett, Windsor (1920). A Down-East Yankee From the District of Maine. Portland, Maine: A.J. Huston. p. 32.
  68. ^ Divinity, Jone Johnson Lewis Jone Johnson Lewis has a Master of; Member, Is a Humanist Clergy; late 1960s, certified transformational coach She has been involved in the women's movement since the. "About Male Feminist John Stuart Mill". ThoughtCo. Retrieved 9 July 2019.
  69. ^ Cunningham Wood, John. John Stuart Mill: Critical Assessments 4.
  70. ^ Mill, John Stuart. [1869] 2005. "The Subjection of Women". pp. 17–26 in Feminist Theory: A Philosophical Anthology, edited by A. E. Cudd and R. O. Andreasen. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 978-1405116619.
  71. ^ West, Henry R. (1 September 2015). "J. S. Mill". In Crisp, Roger (ed.). The Oxford handbook of the history of ethics. Oxford. p. 528. ISBN 978-0198744405. OCLC 907652431.
  72. ^ Mill 1863, p. 51.
  73. ^ Mill, John (2002). The Basic Writings of John Stuart Mill. The Modern Library. p. 239.
  74. ^ a b Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill. February 2004 – via Project Gutenberg.
  75. ^ Freeman, Stephen J., Dennis W. Engels, and Michael K. Altekruse. "Foundations for Ethical Standards and Codes: The Role of Moral Philosophy and Theory in Ethics", Counseling and Values, vol. 48, no. 3, 2004, pp. 163–173, eLibrary.
  76. ^ Davis, G. Scott. 2005. "Introduction", Introduction to Utilitarianism, by John Stuart Mill, vii–xiv. Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading.
  77. ^ a b Heydt, Colin. "John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  78. ^ Mill, John (1961). Utilitarianism. Doubleday. p. 211.
  79. ^ Driver, Julia (27 March 2009). "The History of Utilitarianism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  80. ^ Bronfenbrenner, Martin (1977). "Poetry, Pushpin, and Utility". Economic Inquiry. 15: 95–110. doi:10.1111/j.1465-7295.1977.tb00452.x.
  81. ^ Mill 1863, p. 16.
  82. ^ Mill 1863, p. 2.
  83. ^ Mill 1863, p. 3.
  84. ^ Mill 1863, p. 24.
  85. ^ Mill 1863, p. 29.
  86. ^ Mill 1863, p. 8.
  87. ^ Fitzpatrick 2006, p. 84.
  88. ^ "Autobiography, by John Stuart Mill". Retrieved 11 March 2021 – via Project Gutenberg.
  89. ^ "AUTO Chapter 5, John Stuart Mill, Autobiography". laits.utexas.edu. Retrieved 11 March 2021.
  90. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 26 June 2008.
  91. ^ IREF | Pour la liberte economique et la concurrence fiscale 27 March 2009 at the Wayback Machine (PDF)
  92. ^ Strasser 1991.
  93. ^ Mill, John Stuart; Bentham, Jeremy (2004). Ryan, Alan. (ed.). Utilitarianism and other essays. London: Penguin Books. p. 11. ISBN 978-0140432725.
  94. ^ Wilson, Fred (2007). "John Stuart Mill: Political Economy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 4 May 2009.
  95. ^ Mill, John Stuart (1852). "On The General Principles of Taxation, V.2.14". Principles of Political Economy (3rd ed.). Library of Economics and Liberty. The passage about flat taxation was altered by the author in this edition, which is acknowledged in this online edition's footnote 8: "[This sentence replaced in the 3rd ed. a sentence of the original: 'It is partial taxation, which is a mild form of robbery.']")
  96. ^ McManus, Matt (30 May 2021). "Was John Stuart Mill a Socialist?". Jacobin. Retrieved 1 June 2021.
  97. ^ Mill, John Stuart (2011) [1st pub. Belfords, Clarke & Co.:1879]. Socialism. Project Gutenberg. p. 29. Retrieved 1 June 2021.
  98. ^ Ekelund, Robert B., Jr.; Hébert, Robert F. (1997). A History of Economic Theory and Method (4th ed.). Waveland Press [Long Grove, Illinois]. p. 172. ISBN 978-1577663812.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  99. ^ Marx. "Grundrisse". The aim is, rather, to present production – see e.g. Mill – as distinct from distribution etc., as encased in eternal natural laws independent of history, at which opportunity bourgeois relations are then quietly smuggled in as the inviolable natural laws on which society in the abstract is founded. This is the more or less conscious purpose of the whole proceeding. In distribution, by contrast, humanity has allegedly permitted itself to be considerably more arbitrary. Quite apart from this crude tearing-apart of production and distribution and of their real relationship, it must be apparent from the outset that, no matter how differently distribution may have been arranged in different stages of social development, it must be possible here also, just as with production, to single out common characteristics, and just as possible to confound or to extinguish all historic differences under general human laws.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  100. ^ Principles of Political Economy with some of their Applications to Social Philosophy, IV.7.21 John Stuart Mill: Political Economy, IV.7.21
  101. ^ Principles of Political Economy and On Liberty, Chapter IV, Of the Limits to the Authority of Society Over the Individual
  102. ^ Thompson, Dennis F. (1976). John Stuart Mill and Representative Government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0691021874.
  103. ^ Letwin, Shirley (1965). The Pursuit of Certainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 306. ISBN 978-0865971943.
  104. ^ Pateman, Carole (1970). Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 28. ISBN 978-0521290043.
  105. ^ Thompson, Dennis (2007). "Mill in Parliament: when should a philosopher compromise?". In Urbinati, N.; Zakaras, A. (eds.). J. S. Mill's Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 166–199. ISBN 978-0521677561.
  106. ^ Davis, Elynor G. (1985). "Mill, Socialism and the English Romantics: An Interpretation". Economica. 52 (207): 345–358 (351). doi:10.2307/2553857. JSTOR 2553857.
  107. ^ De Mattos, Laura Valladão (2000). "John Stuart Mill, socialism, and his Liberal Utopia: an application of his view of social institutions". History of Economic Ideas. 8 (2): 95–120 (97).
  108. ^ Mill, John Stuart (1885). Principles of Political Economy. New York: D. Appleton and Company.
  109. ^ Jensen, Hans (December 2001). "John Stuart Mill's Theories of Wealth and Income Distribution". Review of Social Economy. 59 (4): 491–507. doi:10.1080/00346760110081599. S2CID 145340813.
  110. ^ a b Ekelund, Robert; Tollison, Robert (May 1976). "The New Political Economy of J. S. Mill: Means to Social Justice". The Canadian Journal of Economics. 9 (2): 213–231. doi:10.2307/134519. JSTOR 134519.
  111. ^ . Archived from the original on 23 September 2015. Retrieved 9 March 2008.
  112. ^ Røpke, Inge (1 October 2004). "The early history of modern ecological economics". Ecological Economics. 50 (3–4): 293–314. doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2004.02.012.
  113. ^ Mill, John Stuart. Principles of Political Economy (PDF). p. 25. Retrieved 1 November 2016.
  114. ^ Swainson, Bill, ed. (2000). Encarta Book of Quotations. Macmillan. pp. 642–643. ISBN 978-0312230005.
  115. ^ "Radio pick of the day". The Guardian. 17 May 2006. Retrieved 20 April 2022.
  116. ^ Hansard report of Commons Sitting: Capital Punishment Within Prisons Bill – [Bill 36.] Committee stage: HC Deb 21 April 1868 vol. 191 cc 1033–63 including Mill's speech Col. 1047–1055 30 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine
  117. ^ His speech against the abolition of capital punishment was commented upon in an editorial in The Times, Wednesday, 22 April 1868; p. 8; Issue 26105; col E:

References

Mill's work

  • Mill, John Stuart (1863). Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son, and Bourn, West Strand. OCLC 78070085.

Other sources

  • Bell, Duncan, "John Stuart Mill on Colonies", Political Theory, Vol. 38 (February 2010), pp. 34–64
  • Brink, David O. (1992). "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 21: 67–103.
  • Brink, David, "Mill's Moral and Political Philosophy" 17 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  • Claeys, Gregory. Mill and Paternalism (Cambridge University Press, 2013)
  • Christians, Clifford G. & John C. Merrill (eds) Ethical Communication: Five Moral Stances in Human Dialogue, Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2009
  • Fitzpatrick, J. R. (2006). John Stuart Mill's Political Philosophy. Continuum Studies in British Philosophy. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1847143440.
  • George, Roger Z.; Kline, Robert D. (2006). Intelligence and the national security strategist: enduring issues and challenges. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0742540385.
  • Gopnick, Adam, "Right Again, The passions of John Stuart Mill", The New Yorker, 6 October 2008 20 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine
  • Harrington, Jack (2010). Sir John Malcolm and the Creation of British India, Ch. 5. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-0230108851.
  • Harwood, Sterling. "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism", in Louis P. Pojman, ed., Moral Philosophy: A Reader (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1998), and in Sterling Harwood, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1996), Chapter 7
  • Hollander, Samuel, The Economics of John Stuart Mill (University of Toronto Press, 1985)
  • Kolmar, Wendy & Frances Bartowski. Feminist Theory. 2nd ed. New York: Mc Graw Hill, 2005
  • Letwin, Letwin, The Pursuit of Certainty (Cambridge University Press, 1965). ISBN 978-0865971943
  • Packe, Michael St. John, The Life of John Stuart Mill (Macmillan, 1952)
  • Pateman, Carole, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1970). ISBN 978-0521290043
  • Reeves, Richard, John Stuart Mill: Victorian Firebrand, Atlantic Books (2007), paperback 2008. ISBN 978-1843546443
  • Robinson, Dave & Groves, Judy (2003). Introducing Political Philosophy. Icon Books. ISBN 184046450X
  • Rosen, Frederick, Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill (Routledge Studies in Ethics & Moral Theory), 2003. ISBN 0415220947
  • Skoble, Aeon (2008). "Mill, John Stuart (1806–1873)". In Hamowy, Ronald (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage; Cato Institute. pp. 329–331. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n202. ISBN 978-1412965804.
  • Spiegel, H. W. (1991). The Growth of Economic Thought. Economic history. Duke University Press. ISBN 978-0822309734.
  • Strasser, Mark Philip (1991). The Moral Philosophy of John Stuart Mill: Toward Modifications of Contemporary Utilitarianism. Wakefield, New Hampshire: Longwood Academic. ISBN 978-0893416812.
  • Ten, Chin Liew, Mill on Liberty, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1980, full-text online at Victorianweb.org (National University of Singapore)
  • Thompson, Dennis F., John Stuart Mill and Representative Government (Princeton University Press, 1976). ISBN 978-0691021874
  • Thompson, Dennis F., "Mill in Parliament: When Should a Philosopher Compromise?" in J. S. Mill's Political Thought, eds. N. Urbinati and A. Zakaras (Cambridge University Press, 2007). ISBN 978-0521677561
  • Walker, Francis Amasa (1876). The Wages Question: A Treatise on Wages and the Wages Class. Henry Holt.

Further reading

  • Alican, Necip Fikri (1994). Mill's Principle of Utility: A Defense of John Stuart Mill's Notorious Proof. Amsterdam and Atlanta: Editions Rodopi B. V. ISBN 978-9051837483.
  • Bayles, M. D. (1968). Contemporary Utilitarianism. Anchor Books, Doubleday.
  • Bentham, Jeremy (2009). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (Dover Philosophical Classics). Dover Publications Inc. ISBN 978-0486454528.
  • Brandt, Richard B. (1979). A Theory of the Good and the Right. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0198245506.
  • Lee, Sidney, ed. (1894). "Mill, John Stuart" . Dictionary of National Biography. Vol. 37. London: Smith, Elder & Co.
  • López, Rosario (2016). Contexts of John Stuart Mill's Liberalism: Politics and the Science of Society in Victorian Britain. Baden-Baden, Nomos. ISBN 978-3848736959.
  • Lyons, David (1965). Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism. Oxford University Press (UK). ISBN 978-0198241973.
  • Mill, John Stuart (2011). A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive (Classic Reprint). Forgotten Books. ISBN 978-1440090820.
  • Mill, John Stuart (1981). "Autobiography". In Robson, John (ed.). Collected Works, volume XXXI. University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-0710007186.
  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Prometheus Books UK. ISBN 978-0879754983.
  • Rosen, Frederick (2003). Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill. Routledge.
  • Scheffler, Samuel (August 1994). The Rejection of Consequentialism: A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions, Second Edition. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0198235118.
  • Smart, J. J. C.; Williams, Bernard (January 1973). Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521098229.
  • Francisco Vergara, « Bentham and Mill on the "Quality" of Pleasures», Revue d'études benthamiennes, Paris, 2011.
  • Francisco Vergara, « A Critique of Elie Halévy; refutation of an important distortion of British moral philosophy », Philosophy, Journal of The Royal Institute of Philosophy, London, 1998.

External links

Mill's works

  • Works by John Stuart Mill in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
  • Works by John Stuart Mill at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by or about John Stuart Mill at Internet Archive
  • Works by John Stuart Mill at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  
  • The Online Books Page lists works on various sites
  • , readable and downloadable
  • More easily readable versions of On Liberty, Utilitarianism, Three Essays on Religion, The Subjection of Women, A System of Logic, and Autobiography
  • Of the Composition of Causes, Chapter VI of System of Logic (1859)
  • John Stuart Mill's diary of a walking tour at Mount Holyoke College 3 December 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  • A System of Logic, University Press of the Pacific, Honolulu, 2002, ISBN 1410202526

Secondary works

Further information

  • Minto, William; Mitchell, John Malcolm (1911). "Mill, John Stuart" . In Chisholm, Hugh (ed.). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 18 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 454–459.
  • Catalogue of Mill's correspondence and papers held at the of the London School of Economics. View the Archives Catalogue of the contents of this important holding, which also includes letters of James Mill and Helen Taylor.
  • John Stuart Mill's library, Somerville College Library in Oxford holds ≈ 1700 volumes owned by John Stuart Mill and his father James Mill, many containing their marginalia
  • "John Stuart Mill (Obituary Notice, Tuesday, November 4, 1873)". Eminent Persons: Biographies reprinted from The Times. Vol. I (1870–1875). Macmillan & Co. 1892. pp. 195–224. hdl:2027/uc2.ark:/13960/t6n011x45 – via HathiTrust.
  • Mill, BBC Radio 4 discussion with A. C. Grayling, Janet Radcliffe Richards & Alan Ryan (In Our Time, 18 May 2006)
  • Portraits of John Stuart Mill at the National Portrait Gallery, London  
  • John Stuart Mill 17 April 2019 at the Wayback Machine on Google Scholar
  • John Stuart Mill, biographical profile, including quotes and further resources, at Utilitarianism.net.

john, stuart, mill, stuart, mill, redirects, here, town, australia, stuart, mill, victoria, 1806, 1873, english, philosopher, political, economist, member, parliament, civil, servant, most, influential, thinkers, history, classical, liberalism, contributed, wi. Stuart Mill redirects here For the town in Australia see Stuart Mill Victoria John Stuart Mill 20 May 1806 7 May 1873 10 was an English philosopher political economist Member of Parliament MP and civil servant One of the most influential thinkers in the history of classical liberalism he contributed widely to social theory political theory and political economy Dubbed the most influential English speaking philosopher of the nineteenth century 11 he conceived of liberty as justifying the freedom of the individual in opposition to unlimited state and social control 12 John Stuart MillMill c 1870Member of Parliamentfor the City of WestminsterIn office 25 July 1865 17 November 1868Serving with Robert GrosvenorPreceded byDe Lacy EvansSucceeded byWilliam Henry SmithPersonal detailsBorn 1806 05 20 20 May 1806Pentonville Middlesex EnglandDied7 May 1873 1873 05 07 aged 66 Avignon Vaucluse FrancePolitical partyLiberalSpouseHarriet Taylor m 1851 died 1858 wbr ParentJames Mill father Alma materUniversity College LondonPhilosophy careerEra19th century philosophyClassical economicsRegionWestern philosophySchoolEmpiricism Utilitarianism Consequentialism Psychologism Classical liberalismMain interestsEconomics Ethics Logic PoliticsNotable ideasPublic private sphere social liberty hierarchy of pleasures in utilitarianism rule utilitarianism classical liberalism early liberal feminism harm principle Mill s Methods direct reference theory Millian theory of proper names emergentismInfluences Plato Aristotle Socrates Demosthenes Epicurus Aquinas Hobbes Locke Hume Babbage 1 Berkeley Bentham Place Mill J Hardy Smith Senior Ricardo Tocqueville Humboldt Goethe Bain Guizot 2 Comte Saint Simon 3 Warren Marmontel 4 Wordsworth 4 Coleridge 4 Herder 5 SismondiInfluenced Social liberalism 6 Russell 7 8 CrispWeber 9 Henry SidgwickJohn RawlsOrtega y GassetAdam HeydelSignatureMill was a proponent of utilitarianism an ethical theory developed by his predecessor Jeremy Bentham He contributed to the investigation of scientific methodology though his knowledge of the topic was based on the writings of others notably William Whewell John Herschel and Auguste Comte and research carried out for Mill by Alexander Bain He engaged in written debate with Whewell 13 A member of the Liberal Party and author of the early feminist work The Subjection of Women Mill was also the second Member of Parliament to call for women s suffrage after Henry Hunt in 1832 14 15 Contents 1 Biography 2 Works and theories 2 1 A System of Logic 2 2 Theory of liberty 2 2 1 Social liberty and tyranny of majority 2 2 2 Liberty 2 2 3 Freedom of speech 2 2 3 1 Harm principle 2 2 3 2 Freedom of the press 2 3 Colonialism 2 4 Slavery and racial equality 2 5 Women s rights 2 6 Utilitarianism 2 6 1 Higher and lower pleasures 2 6 2 Chapters 2 7 Achieving happiness 2 8 Economic philosophy 2 8 1 Criticism 2 8 2 Economic democracy 2 8 3 Political democracy 2 8 4 Theories of wealth and income distribution 2 8 5 The environment 2 8 6 Rate of profit 3 In popular culture 4 Major publications 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 7 1 Mill s work 7 2 Other sources 8 Further reading 9 External links 9 1 Mill s works 9 2 Secondary works 9 3 Further informationBiography EditJohn Stuart Mill was born at 13 Rodney Street in Pentonville then on the edge of the capital and now in central London the eldest son of Harriet Barrow and the Scottish philosopher historian and economist James Mill John Stuart was educated by his father with the advice and assistance of Jeremy Bentham and Francis Place He was given an extremely rigorous upbringing and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings His father a follower of Bentham and an adherent of associationism had as his explicit aim to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of utilitarianism and its implementation after he and Bentham had died 16 Mill was a notably precocious child He describes his education in his autobiography At the age of three he was taught Greek 17 By the age of eight he had read Aesop s Fables Xenophon s Anabasis 17 and the whole of Herodotus 17 and was acquainted with Lucian Diogenes Laertius Isocrates and six dialogues of Plato 17 He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught arithmetic physics and astronomy At the age of eight Mill began studying Latin the works of Euclid and algebra and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family His main reading was still history but he went through all the commonly taught Latin and Greek authors and by the age of ten could read Plato and Demosthenes with ease His father also thought that it was important for Mill to study and compose poetry One of his earliest poetic compositions was a continuation of the Iliad In his spare time he also enjoyed reading about natural sciences and popular novels such as Don Quixote and Robinson Crusoe His father s work The History of British India was published in 1818 immediately thereafter at about the age of twelve Mill began a thorough study of the scholastic logic at the same time reading Aristotle s logical treatises in the original language In the following year he was introduced to political economy and studied Adam Smith and David Ricardo with his father ultimately completing their classical economic view of factors of production Mill s comptes rendus of his daily economy lessons helped his father in writing Elements of Political Economy in 1821 a textbook to promote the ideas of Ricardian economics however the book lacked popular support 18 Ricardo who was a close friend of his father used to invite the young Mill to his house for a walk to talk about political economy At the age of fourteen Mill stayed a year in France with the family of Sir Samuel Bentham brother of Jeremy Bentham The mountain scenery he saw led to a lifelong taste for mountain landscapes The lively and friendly way of life of the French also left a deep impression on him In Montpellier he attended the winter courses on chemistry zoology logic of the Faculte des Sciences as well as taking a course in higher mathematics While coming and going from France he stayed in Paris for a few days in the house of the renowned economist Jean Baptiste Say a friend of Mill s father There he met many leaders of the Liberal party as well as other notable Parisians including Henri Saint Simon Mill went through months of sadness and contemplated suicide at twenty years of age According to the opening paragraphs of Chapter V of his autobiography he had asked himself whether the creation of a just society his life s objective would actually make him happy His heart answered no and unsurprisingly he lost the happiness of striving towards this objective Eventually the poetry of William Wordsworth showed him that beauty generates compassion for others and stimulates joy 19 With renewed joy he continued to work towards a just society but with more relish for the journey He considered this one of the most pivotal shifts in his thinking In fact many of the differences between him and his father stemmed from this expanded source of joy Mill met Thomas Carlyle during one of the latter s visits to London in the early 1830s and the two quickly became companions and correspondents Mill offered to print Carlyle s works at his own expense and encouraged Carlyle to write his French Revolution supplying him with materials in order to do so In March 1835 while the manuscript of the completed first volume was in Mill s possession Mill s housemaid unwittingly used it as tinder destroying all except some three or four bits of leaves 20 Mortified Mill offered Carlyle 200 17 742 16 in 2021 as compensation Carlyle would only accept 100 Ideological differences would put an end to the friendship during the 1840s though Carlyle s early influence on Mill would colour his later thought 21 Mill had been engaged in a pen friendship with Auguste Comte the founder of positivism and sociology since Mill first contacted Comte in November 1841 Comte s sociologie was more an early philosophy of science than modern sociology is Comte s positivism motivated Mill to eventually reject Bentham s psychological egoism and what he regarded as Bentham s cold abstract view of human nature focused on legislation and politics instead coming to favour Comte s more sociable view of human nature focused on historical facts and directed more towards human individuals in all their complexities 22 As a nonconformist who refused to subscribe to the Thirty Nine Articles of the Church of England Mill was not eligible to study at the University of Oxford or the University of Cambridge 23 Instead he followed his father to work for the East India Company and attended University College London to hear the lectures of John Austin the first Professor of Jurisprudence 24 He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1856 25 Mill s career as a colonial administrator at the East India Company spanned from when he was 17 years old in 1823 until 1858 when the Company s territories in India were directly annexed by the Crown establishing direct Crown control over India 26 In 1836 he was promoted to the Company s Political Department where he was responsible for correspondence pertaining to the Company s relations with the princely states and in 1856 was finally promoted to the position of Examiner of Indian Correspondence In On Liberty A Few Words on Non Intervention and other works he opined that To characterize any conduct whatever towards a barbarous people as a violation of the law of nations only shows that he who so speaks has never considered the subject 27 Mill immediately added however that A violation of the great principles of morality it may easily be 28 Mill viewed places such as India as having once been progressive in their outlook but had now become stagnant in their development he opined that this meant these regions had to be ruled via a form of benevolent despotism provided the end is improvement 29 When the Crown proposed to take direct control over the territories of the East India Company he was tasked with defending Company rule penning Memorandum on the Improvements in the Administration of India during the Last Thirty Years among other petitions 30 He was offered a seat on the Council of India the body created to advise the new Secretary of State for India but declined citing his disapproval of the new system of administration in India 30 On 21 April 1851 Mill married Harriet Taylor after 21 years of intimate friendship Taylor was married when they met and their relationship was close but generally believed to be chaste during the years before her first husband died in 1849 The couple waited two years before marrying in 1851 Brilliant in her own right Taylor was a significant influence on Mill s work and ideas during both friendship and marriage His relationship with Taylor reinforced Mill s advocacy of women s rights He said that in his stand against domestic violence and for women s rights he was chiefly an amanuensis to my wife He called her mind a perfect instrument and said she was the most eminently qualified of all those known to the author He cites her influence in his final revision of On Liberty which was published shortly after her death Taylor died in 1858 after developing severe lung congestion after only seven years of marriage to Mill Between the years 1865 and 1868 Mill served as Lord Rector of the University of St Andrews At his inaugural address delivered to the University on 1 February 1867 he made the now famous but often wrongly attributed remark that Bad men need nothing more to compass their ends than that good men should look on and do nothing 31 That Mill included that sentence in the address is a matter of historical record but it by no means follows that it expressed a wholly original insight During the same period 1865 68 he was also a Member of Parliament MP for City of Westminster 32 33 He was sitting for the Liberal Party During his time as an MP Mill advocated easing the burdens on Ireland In 1866 he became the first person in the history of Parliament to call for women to be given the right to vote vigorously defending this position in subsequent debate He also became a strong advocate of such social reforms as labour unions and farm cooperatives In Considerations on Representative Government he called for various reforms of Parliament and voting especially proportional representation the single transferable vote and the extension of suffrage In April 1868 he favoured in a Commons debate the retention of capital punishment for such crimes as aggravated murder he termed its abolition an effeminacy in the general mind of the country 34 He was elected as a member to the American Philosophical Society in 1867 35 He was godfather to the philosopher Bertrand Russell 36 In his views on religion Mill was an agnostic and a sceptic 37 38 39 40 Mill died in 1873 thirteen days before his 67th birthday of erysipelas in Avignon France where his body was buried alongside his wife s Works and theories Edit Portrait of Mill by George Frederic Watts 1873 A System of Logic Edit Main article A System of Logic Mill joined the debate over scientific method which followed on from John Herschel s 1830 publication of A Preliminary Discourse on the study of Natural Philosophy which incorporated inductive reasoning from the known to the unknown discovering general laws in specific facts and verifying these laws empirically William Whewell expanded on this in his 1837 History of the Inductive Sciences from the Earliest to the Present Time followed in 1840 by The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences Founded Upon their History presenting induction as the mind superimposing concepts on facts Laws were self evident truths which could be known without need for empirical verification Mill countered this in 1843 in A System of Logic fully titled A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation In Mill s Methods of induction as in Herschel s laws were discovered through observation and induction and required empirical verification 41 Matilal remarks that Dignaga analysis is much like John Stuart Mill s Joint Method of Agreement and Difference which is inductive He suggested that it is very likely that during his stay in India he may have come across the tradition of logic on which scholars started taking interest after 1824 though it is unknown whether it influenced his work or not 42 43 Theory of liberty Edit Main article On Liberty Mill s On Liberty 1859 addresses the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual Mill s idea is that only if a democratic society follows the Principle of Liberty can its political and social institutions fulfill their role of shaping national character so that its citizens can realise the permanent interests of people as progressive beings Rawls Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy p 289 Mill states the Principle of Liberty as the sole end for which mankind are warranted individually or collectively in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number is self protection The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community against his will is to prevent harm to others His own good either physical or moral is not a sufficient warrant 44 One way to read Mill s Principle of Liberty as a principle of public reason is to see it excluding certain kinds of reasons from being taken into account in legislation or in guiding the moral coercion of public opinion Rawls Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy p 291 These reasons include those founded in other persons good reasons of excellence and ideals of human perfection reasons of dislike or disgust or of preference Mill states that harms which may be prevented include acts of omission as well as acts of commission Thus failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act as does failing to pay taxes or failing to appear as a witness in court All such harmful omissions may be regulated according to Mill By contrast it does not count as harming someone if without force or fraud the affected individual consents to assume the risk thus one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others provided there is no deception involved He does however recognise one limit to consent society should not permit people to sell themselves into slavery The question of what counts as a self regarding action and what actions whether of omission or commission constitute harmful actions subject to regulation continues to exercise interpreters of Mill He did not consider giving offence to constitute harm an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society 45 John Stuart Mill and Helen Taylor Helen was the daughter of Harriet Taylor and collaborated with Mill for fifteen years after her mother s death in 1858 Social liberty and tyranny of majority Edit Mill believed that the struggle between Liberty and Authority is the most conspicuous feature in the portions of history 46 For him liberty in antiquity was a contest between subjects or some classes of subjects and the government 46 Mill defined social liberty as protection from the tyranny of political rulers He introduced a number of different concepts of the form tyranny can take referred to as social tyranny and tyranny of the majority Social liberty for Mill meant putting limits on the ruler s power so that he would not be able to use that power to further his own wishes and thus make decisions that could harm society In other words people should have the right to have a say in the government s decisions He said that social liberty was the nature and limits of the power which can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual It was attempted in two ways first by obtaining recognition of certain immunities called political liberties or rights and second by establishment of a system of constitutional checks However in Mill s view limiting the power of government was not enough 47 Society can and does execute its own mandates and if it issues wrong mandates instead of right or any mandates at all in things with which it ought not to meddle it practises a social tyranny more formidable than many kinds of political oppression since though not usually upheld by such extreme penalties it leaves fewer means of escape penetrating much more deeply into the details of life and enslaving the soul itself Liberty Edit Mill s view on liberty which was influenced by Joseph Priestley and Josiah Warren is that individuals ought to be free to do as they wished unless they caused harm to others Individuals are rational enough to make decisions about their well being Government should interfere when it is for the protection of society Mill explained 44 The sole end for which mankind are warranted individually or collectively in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number is self protection That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community against his will is to prevent harm to others His own good either physical or moral is not sufficient warrant He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so because it will make him happier because in the opinion of others to do so would be wise or even right The only part of the conduct of anyone for which he is amenable to society is that which concerns others In the part which merely concerns him his independence is of right absolute Over himself over his own body and mind the individual is sovereign Freedom of speech Edit On Liberty involves an impassioned defense of free speech Mill argues that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress We can never be sure he contends that a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth He also argues that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons First individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas Second by forcing other individuals to re examine and re affirm their beliefs in the process of debate these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma It is not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true one must understand why the belief in question is the true one Along those same lines Mill wrote unmeasured vituperation employed on the side of prevailing opinion really does deter people from expressing contrary opinions and from listening to those who express them 48 45 51 As an influential advocate of freedom of speech Mill objected to censorship 49 I choose by preference the cases which are least favourable to me In which the argument opposing freedom of opinion both on truth and that of utility is considered the strongest Let the opinions impugned be the belief of God and in a future state or any of the commonly received doctrines of morality But I must be permitted to observe that it is not the feeling sure of a doctrine be it what it may which I call an assumption of infallibility It is the undertaking to decide that question for others without allowing them to hear what can be said on the contrary side And I denounce and reprobate this pretension not the less if it is put forth on the side of my most solemn convictions However positive anyone s persuasion may be not only of the faculty but of the pernicious consequences but to adopt expressions which I altogether condemn the immorality and impiety of opinion yet if in pursuance of that private judgement though backed by the public judgement of his country or contemporaries he prevents the opinion from being heard in its defence he assumes infallibility And so far from the assumption being less objectionable or less dangerous because the opinion is called immoral or impious this is the case of all others in which it is most fatal Mill outlines the benefits of searching for and discovering the truth as a way to further knowledge He argued that even if an opinion is false the truth can be better understood by refuting the error And as most opinions are neither completely true nor completely false he points out that allowing free expression allows the airing of competing views as a way to preserve partial truth in various opinions 50 Worried about minority views being suppressed he argued in support of freedom of speech on political grounds stating that it is a critical component for a representative government to have to empower debate over public policy 50 He also eloquently argued that freedom of expression allows for personal growth and self realization He said that freedom of speech was a vital way to develop talents and realise a person s potential and creativity He repeatedly said that eccentricity was preferable to uniformity and stagnation 50 Harm principle Edit The belief that freedom of speech would advance society presupposed a society sufficiently culturally and institutionally advanced to be capable of progressive improvement If any argument is really wrong or harmful the public will judge it as wrong or harmful and then those arguments cannot be sustained and will be excluded Mill argued that even any arguments which are used in justifying murder or rebellion against the government shouldn t be politically suppressed or socially persecuted According to him if rebellion is really necessary people should rebel if murder is truly proper it should be allowed However the way to express those arguments should be a public speech or writing not in a way that causes actual harm to others Such is the harm principle That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community against his will is to prevent harm to others 51 At the beginning of the 20th century Associate justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr made the standard of clear and present danger based on Mill s idea In the majority opinion Holmes writes The question in every case is whether the words used are used in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils that Congress has a right to prevent 52 Holmes suggested that falsely shouting out Fire in a dark theatre which evokes panic and provokes injury would be such a case of speech that creates an illegal danger 53 But if the situation allows people to reason by themselves and decide to accept it or not any argument or theology should not be blocked Nowadays Mill s argument is generally accepted by many democratic countries and they have laws at least guided by the harm principle For example in American law some exceptions limit free speech such as obscenity defamation breach of peace and fighting words 54 Freedom of the press Edit In On Liberty Mill thought it was necessary for him to restate the case for press freedom He considered that argument already won Almost no politician or commentator in mid 19th century Britain wanted a return to Tudor and Stuart type press censorship However Mill warned new forms of censorship could emerge in the future 55 Indeed in 2013 the Cameron Tory government considered setting up a so called independent official regulator of the UK press 56 This prompted demands for better basic legal protection of press freedom A new British Bill of Rights could include a US type constitutional ban on governmental infringement of press freedom and block other official attempts to control freedom of opinion and expression 57 Colonialism EditMill an employee of the East India Company from 1823 to 1858 58 argued in support of what he called a benevolent despotism with regard to the administration of overseas colonies 59 Mill argued 60 To suppose that the same international customs and the same rules of international morality can obtain between one civilized nation and another and between civilized nations and barbarians is a grave error To characterize any conduct whatever towards a barbarous people as a violation of the law of nations only shows that he who so speaks has never considered the subject Mill expressed general support for Company rule in India but expressed reservations on specific Company policies in India which he disagreed with 61 Slavery and racial equality Edit In 1850 Mill sent an anonymous letter which came to be known under the title The Negro Question 62 in rebuttal to Thomas Carlyle s letter to Fraser s Magazine for Town and Country in which Carlyle argued for slavery Mill supported abolishing slavery in the United States expressing his opposition to slavery in his essay of 1869 The Subjection of Women 63 This absolutely extreme case of the law of force condemned by those who can tolerate almost every other form of arbitrary power and which of all others presents features the most revolting to the feeling of all who look at it from an impartial position was the law of civilized and Christian England within the memory of persons now living and in one half of Anglo Saxon America three or four years ago not only did slavery exist but the slave trade and the breeding of slaves expressly for it was a general practice between slave states Yet not only was there a greater strength of sentiment against it but in England at least a less amount either of feeling or of interest in favour of it than of any other of the customary abuses of force for its motive was the love of gain unmixed and undisguised and those who profited by it were a very small numerical fraction of the country while the natural feeling of all who were not personally interested in it was unmitigated abhorrence Mill corresponded with John Appleton an American legal reformer from Maine extensively on the topic of racial equality Appleton influenced Mill s work on such especially swaying him on the optimal economic and social welfare plan for the Antebellum South 64 65 66 In a letter sent to Appleton in response to a previous letter Mill expressed his view on antebellum integration 64 I cannot look forward with satisfaction to any settlement but complete emancipation land given to every negro family either separately or in organized communities under such rules as may be found temporarily necessary the schoolmaster set to work in every village amp the tide of free immigration turned on in those fertile regions from which slavery has hitherto excluded it If this be done the gentle amp docile character which seems to distinguish the negroes will prevent any mischief on their side while the proofs they are giving of fighting powers will do more in a year than all other things in a century to make the whites respect them amp consent to their being politically amp socially equals Women s rights Edit A Feminine Philosopher Caricature by Spy published in Vanity Fair in 1873 Mill s view of history was that right up until his time the whole of the female and the great majority of the male sex were simply slaves He countered arguments to the contrary arguing that relations between sexes simply amounted to the legal subordination of one sex to the other which is wrong itself and now one of the chief hindrances to human improvement and that it ought to be replaced by a principle of perfect equality Here then we have an instance of Mill s use of slavery in a sense which compared to its fundamental meaning of absolute unfreedom of person is an extended and arguably a rhetorical rather than a literal sense With this Mill can be considered among the earliest male proponents of gender equality having been recruited by American feminist John Neal during his stay in London circa 1825 1827 67 His book The Subjection of Women 1861 publ 1869 is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author 68 In The Subjection of Women Mill attempts to make a case for perfect equality 69 In his proposal for a universal education system sponsored by the state Mill expands benefits for many marginalized groups especially for women For Mill a universal education held the potential to create new abilities and novel types of behavior of which the current receiving generation and their descendants could both benefit from Such a pathway to opportunity would enable women to gain industrial and social independence that would allow them the same movement in their agency and citizenship as men Mill s view of opportunity stands out in its reach but even more so for the population he foresees who could benefit from it Mill was hopeful of the autonomy such an education could allow for its recipients and especially for women Through the consequential sophistication and knowledge attained individuals are able to properly act in ways that recedes away from those leading towards overpopulation This stands directly in contrast with the view held by many of Mill s contemporaries and predecessors who viewed such inclusive programs to be counter intuitive Aiming such help at marginalized groups such as the poor and working class would only serve to reward them with the opportunity to move to a higher status thus encouraging greater fertility which at its extreme could lead to overproduction He talks about the role of women in marriage and how it must be changed Mill comments on three major facets of women s lives that he felt are hindering them society and gender construction education and marriage He argues that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity 63 70 As a Member of Parliament Mill introduced an unsuccessful amendment to the Reform Bill to substitute the word person in place of man 71 Utilitarianism Edit Main article Utilitarianism book The utilitarian doctrine is that happiness is desirable and the only thing desirable as an end all other things being only desirable as means to that end John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism 1863 72 The canonical statement of Mill s utilitarianism can be found in his book Utilitarianism Although this philosophy has a long tradition Mill s account is primarily influenced by Jeremy Bentham and Mill s father James Mill John Stuart Mill believed in the philosophy of utilitarianism which he would describe as the principle that holds that actions are right in the proportion as they tend to promote happiness wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness By happiness he means intended pleasure and the absence of pain by unhappiness pain and the privation of pleasure 73 It is clear that we do not all value virtues as a path to happiness and that we sometimes only value them for selfish reasons However Mill asserts that upon reflection even when we value virtues for selfish reasons we are in fact cherishing them as a part of our happiness Bentham s famous formulation of utilitarianism is known as the greatest happiness principle It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest aggregate happiness among all sentient beings within reason In a similar vein Mill s method of determining the best utility is that a moral agent when given the choice between two or more actions ought to choose the action that contributes most to maximizes the total happiness in the world Happiness in this context is understood as the production of pleasure or privation of pain Given that determining the action that produces the most utility is not always so clear cut Mill suggests that the utilitarian moral agent when attempting to rank the utility of different actions should refer to the general experience of persons That is if people generally experience more happiness following action X than they do action Y the utilitarian should conclude that action X produces more utility than action Y and so is to be preferred 74 Utilitarianism is a consequentialist ethical theory meaning that it holds that acts are justified insofar as they produce a desirable outcome The overarching goal of utilitarianism the ideal consequence is to achieve the greatest good for the greatest number as the end result of human action 75 In Utilitarianism Mill states that happiness is the sole end of human action 34 This statement aroused some controversy which is why Mill took it a step further explaining how the very nature of humans wanting happiness and who take it to be reasonable under free consideration demands that happiness is indeed desirable 11 In other words free will leads everyone to make actions inclined on their own happiness unless reasoned that it would improve the happiness of others in which case the greatest utility is still being achieved To that extent the utilitarianism that Mill is describing is a default lifestyle that he believes is what people who have not studied a specific opposing field of ethics would naturally and subconsciously use when faced with a decision Utilitarianism is thought of by some of its activists to be a more developed and overarching ethical theory of Immanuel Kant s belief in goodwill and not just some default cognitive process of humans Where Kant 1724 1804 would argue that reason can only be used properly by goodwill Mill would say that the only way to universally create fair laws and systems would be to step back to the consequences whereby Kant s ethical theories become based around the ultimate good utility 76 By this logic the only valid way to discern what is the proper reason would be to view the consequences of any action and weigh the good and the bad even if on the surface the ethical reasoning seems to indicate a different train of thought Higher and lower pleasures Edit Mill s major contribution to utilitarianism is his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures Bentham treats all forms of happiness as equal whereas Mill argues that intellectual and moral pleasures higher pleasures are superior to more physical forms of pleasure lower pleasures He distinguishes between happiness and contentment claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter a belief wittily encapsulated in the statement that it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied And if the fool or the pig are of a different opinion it is because they only know their own side of the question 74 This made Mill believe that our only ultimate end 77 is happiness One unique part of his utilitarian view that is not seen in others is the idea of higher and lower pleasures Mill explains the different pleasures as If I am asked what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another merely as a pleasure except its being greater in amount there is but one possible answer Of two pleasures if there be one to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference that is the more desirable pleasure 78 He defines higher pleasures as mental moral and aesthetic pleasures and lower pleasures as being more sensational He believed that higher pleasures should be seen as preferable to lower pleasures since they have a greater quality in virtue He holds that pleasures gained in activity are of a higher quality than those gained passively 79 Mill defines the difference between higher and lower forms of pleasure with the principle that those who have experienced both tend to prefer one over the other This is perhaps in direct contrast with Bentham s statement that Quantity of pleasure being equal push pin is as good as poetry 80 that if a simple child s game like hopscotch causes more pleasure to more people than a night at the opera house it is more incumbent upon a society to devote more resources to propagating hopscotch than running opera houses Mill s argument is that the simple pleasures tend to be preferred by people who have no experience with high art and are therefore not in a proper position to judge He also argues that people who for example are noble or practise philosophy benefit society more than those who engage in individualist practices for pleasure which are lower forms of happiness It is not the agent s own greatest happiness that matters but the greatest amount of happiness altogether 81 Chapters Edit Mill separated his explanation of Utilitarianism into five different sections General Remarks What Utilitarianism Is Of the Ultimate Sanction of the Principle of Utility Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible and Of the Connection between Justice and Utility In the General Remarks portion of his essay he speaks how next to no progress has been made when it comes to judging what is right and what is wrong of morality and if there is such a thing as moral instinct which he argues that there may not be However he agrees that in general Our moral faculty according to all those of its interpreters who are entitled to the name of thinkers supplies us only with the general principles of moral judgments 82 In What Utilitarianism Is he focuses no longer on background information but utilitarianism itself He quotes utilitarianism as The greatest happiness principle defining this theory by saying that pleasure and no pain are the only inherently good things in the world and expands on it by saying that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness By happiness is intended pleasure and the absence of pain by unhappiness pain and the privation of pleasure 83 He views it not as an animalistic concept because he sees seeking out pleasure as a way of using our higher facilities He also says in this chapter that the happiness principle is based not exclusively on the individual but mainly on the community Mill also defends the idea of a strong utilitarian conscience i e a strong feeling of obligation to the general happiness 77 He argued that humans have a desire to be happy and that that desire causes us to want to be in unity with other humans This causes us to care about the happiness of others as well as the happiness of complete strangers But this desire also causes us to experience pain when we perceive harm to other people He believes in internal sanctions that make us experience guilt and appropriate our actions These internal sanctions make us want to do good because we do not want to feel guilty for our actions Happiness is our ultimate end because it is our duty He argues that we do not need to be constantly motivated by the concern of people s happiness because most of the actions done by people are done out of good intention and the good of the world is made up of the good of the people In Mill s fourth chapter Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible he speaks of what proofs of Utility are affected He starts this chapter off by saying that all of his claims cannot be backed up by reasoning He claims that the only proof that something brings one pleasure is if someone finds it pleasurable Next he talks about how morality is the basic way to achieve happiness He also discusses in this chapter that Utilitarianism is beneficial for virtue He says that it maintains not only that virtue is to be desired but that it is to be desired disinterestedly for itself 84 In his final chapter he looks at the connection between Utilitarianism and justice He contemplates the question of whether justice is something distinct from Utility or not He reasons this question in several different ways and finally comes to the conclusion that in certain cases justice is essential for Utility but in others social duty is far more important than justice Mill believes that justice must give way to some other moral principle but that what is just in ordinary cases is by reason of that other principle not just in the particular case 85 The qualitative account of happiness that Mill advocates thus sheds light on his account presented in On Liberty As he suggests in that text utility is to be conceived in relation to humanity as a progressive being which includes the development and exercise of rational capacities as we strive to achieve a higher mode of existence The rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to provide the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge and the greatest ability for the greatest number to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities Mill redefines the definition of happiness as the ultimate end for the sake of which all other things are desirable whether we are considering our own good or that of other people is an existence as free as possible from pain and as rich as possible in enjoyments 86 He firmly believed that moral rules and obligations could be referenced to promoting happiness which connects to having a noble character While Mill is not a standard act utilitarian or rule utilitarian he is a minimizing utilitarian which affirms that it would be desirable to maximize happiness for the greatest number but not that we are morally required to do so 87 Achieving happiness Edit Mill believed that for the majority of people those with but a moderate degree of sensibility and of capacity for enjoyment happiness is best achieved en passant rather than striving for it directly This meant no self consciousness scrutiny self interrogation dwelling on thinking about imagining or questioning on one s happiness Then if otherwise fortunately circumstanced one would inhale happiness with the air you breathe 88 89 Economic philosophy Edit Main article Principles of Political Economy Essays on Economics and Society 1967 Mill s early economic philosophy was one of free markets However he accepted interventions in the economy such as a tax on alcohol if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare 90 He originally believed that equality of taxation meant equality of sacrifice and that progressive taxation penalized those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore a mild form of robbery 91 Given an equal tax rate regardless of income Mill agreed that inheritance should be taxed A utilitarian society would agree that everyone should be equal one way or another Therefore receiving inheritance would put one ahead of society unless taxed on the inheritance Those who donate should consider and choose carefully where their money goes some charities are more deserving than others Considering public charities boards such as a government will disburse the money equally However a private charity board like a church would disburse the monies fairly to those who are in more need than others 92 Later he altered his views toward a more socialist bent adding chapters to his Principles of Political Economy in defence of a socialist outlook and defending some socialist causes 93 Within this revised work he also made the radical proposal that the whole wage system be abolished in favour of a co operative wage system Nonetheless some of his views on the idea of flat taxation remained 94 albeit altered in the third edition of the Principles of Political Economy to reflect a concern for differentiating restrictions on unearned incomes which he favoured and those on earned incomes which he did not favour 95 In his autobiography Mill stated that in relation to his later views on political economy his ideal of ultimate improvement would class him decidedly under the general designation of Socialists His views shifted partly due to reading the works of utopian socialists but also from the influence of Harriet Taylor 96 In his work Socialism Mill argued that the prevalence of poverty in contemporary industrial capitalist societies was pro tanto a failure of the social arrangements and that attempts to condone this state of affairs as being the result of individual failings did not represent a justification of them but instead were an irresistible claim upon every human being for protection against suffering 97 Mill s Principles first published in 1848 was one of the most widely read of all books on economics in the period 98 As Adam Smith s Wealth of Nations had during an earlier period Principles came to dominate economics teaching In the case of Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919 when it was replaced by Marshall s Principles of Economics Criticism Edit In Karl Marx s critique of political economy he mentioned Mill in the Grundrisse Marx claimed that Mill s thinking posited the categories of capital in an ahistorical fashion 99 Economic democracy Edit Mill s main objection to Marxism focused on what he saw its destruction of competition He wrote I utterly dissent from the most conspicuous and vehement part of their teaching their declamations against competition He was an egalitarian but he argued more for equal opportunity and placed meritocracy above all other ideals in this regard According to Mill a socialist society would only be attainable through the provision of basic education for all promoting economic democracy instead of capitalism in the manner of substituting capitalist businesses with worker cooperatives He says The form of association however which if mankind continue to improve must be expected in the end to predominate is not that which can exist between a capitalist as chief and work people without a voice in the management but the association of the labourers themselves on terms of equality collectively owning the capital with which they carry on their operations and working under managers elected and removable by themselves 100 101 Political democracy Edit Mill s major work on political democracy Considerations on Representative Government defends two fundamental principles extensive participation by citizens and enlightened competence of rulers 102 The two values are obviously in tension and some readers have concluded that he is an elitist democrat 103 while others count him as an earlier participatory democrat 104 In one section he appears to defend plural voting in which more competent citizens are given extra votes a view he later repudiated However in another chapter he argues cogently for the value of participation by all citizens He believed that the incompetence of the masses could eventually be overcome if they were given a chance to take part in politics especially at the local level Mill is one of the few political philosophers ever to serve in government as an elected official In his three years in Parliament he was more willing to compromise than the radical principles expressed in his writing would lead one to expect 105 Mill was a major proponent of the diffusion and use of public education to the working class He saw the value of the individual person and believed that man had the inherent capability of guiding his own destiny but only if his faculties were developed and fulfilled which could be achieved through education 106 He regarded education as a pathway to improve human nature which to him meant to encourage among other characteristics diversity and originality the energy of character initiative autonomy intellectual cultivation aesthetic sensibility non self regarding interests prudence responsibility and self control 107 Education allowed for humans to develop into full informed citizens that had the tools to improve their condition and make fully informed electoral decisions The power of education lay in its ability to serve as a great equalizer among the classes allowing the working class the ability to control their own destiny and compete with the upper classes Mill recognized the paramount importance of public education in avoiding the tyranny of the majority by ensuring that all the voters and political participants were fully developed individuals It was through education he believed that an individual could become a full participant within representative democracy Theories of wealth and income distribution Edit In Principles of Political Economy Mill offered an analysis of two economic phenomena often linked together the laws of production and wealth and the modes of its distribution Regarding the former he believed that it was not possible to alter to laws of production the ultimate properties of matter and mind only to employ these properties to bring about events we are interested 108 The modes of distribution of wealth is a matter of human institutions solely starting with what Mill believed to be the primary and fundamental institution Individual Property 109 He believed that all individuals must start on equal terms with division of the instruments of production fairly among all members of society Once each member has an equal amount of individual property they must be left to their own exertion not to be interfered with by the state Regarding inequality of wealth Mill believed that it was the role of the government to establish both social and economic policies that promote the equality of opportunity The government according to Mill should implement three tax policies to help alleviate poverty 110 fairly assessed income tax an inheritance tax and a policy to restrict sumptuary consumption Inheritance of capital and wealth plays a large role in development of inequality because it provides greater opportunity for those receiving the inheritance Mill s solution to inequality of wealth brought about by inheritance was to implement a greater tax on inheritances because he believed the most important authoritative function of the government is taxation and taxation judiciously implemented could promote equality 110 The environment Edit Mill demonstrated an early insight into the value of the natural world in particular in Book IV chapter VI of Principles of Political Economy Of the Stationary State 111 112 in which Mill recognised wealth beyond the material and argued that the logical conclusion of unlimited growth was destruction of the environment and a reduced quality of life He concludes that a stationary state could be preferable to unending economic growth I cannot therefore regard the stationary states of capital and wealth with the unaffected aversion so generally manifested towards it by political economists of the old school If the earth must lose that great portion of its pleasantness which it owes to things that the unlimited increase of wealth and population would extirpate from it for the mere purpose of enabling it to support a larger but not a better or a happier population I sincerely hope for the sake of posterity that they will be content to be stationary long before necessity compel them to it Rate of profit Edit According to Mill the ultimate tendency in an economy is for the rate of profit to decline due to diminishing returns in agriculture and increase in population at a Malthusian rate 113 In popular culture Edit Statue of Mill by Thomas Woolner in Victoria Embankment Gardens London Mill is the subject of a 1905 clerihew by E C Bentley 114 John Stuart Mill By a mighty effort of will Overcame his natural bonhomie And wrote Principles of Political Economy Mill is mentioned in Monty Python s Bruces Philosophers Song 1973 in the lines 115 John Stuart Mill of his own free will On half a pint of shandy was particularly ill Major publications EditTitle Date Source Two Letters on the Measure of Value 1822 The Traveller Questions of Population 1823 Black Dwarf War Expenditure 1824 Westminster Review Quarterly Review Political Economy 1825 Westminster Review Review of Miss Martineau s Tales 1830 Examiner The Spirit of the Age 1831 Examiner Use and Abuse of Political Terms 1832 What is Poetry 1833 1859 Rationale of Representation 1835 De Tocqueville on Democracy in America i 1835 State of Society in America 1836 Civilization 1836 Essay on Bentham 1838 Essay on Coleridge 1840 Essays on Government 1840 De Tocqueville on Democracy in America ii 1840A System of Logic 1843Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy 1844 Claims of Labour 1845 Edinburgh ReviewThe Principles of Political Economy with some of their applications to social philosophy 1848 The Negro Question 1850 Fraser s Magazine Reform of the Civil Service 1854Dissertations and Discussions 1859A Few Words on Non intervention 1859On Liberty 1859Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform 1859Considerations on Representative Government 1861 Centralisation 1862 Edinburgh Review The Contest in America 1862 Harper s MagazineUtilitarianism 1863An Examination of Sir William Hamilton s Philosophy 1865Auguste Comte and Positivism 1865Inaugural Address at St Andrews Concerning the value of culture 1867 Speech in Favour of Capital Punishment 116 117 1868England and Ireland 1868 Thornton on Labour and its Claims 1869 Fortnightly ReviewThe Subjection of Women 1869Chapters and Speeches on the Irish Land Question 1870Autobiography 1873Three Essays on Religion Nature the Utility of religion and Theism 1874 Internet ArchiveSocialism 1879 Belfords Clarke amp Co Notes on N W Senior s Political Economy 1945 Economica N S 12See also EditJohn Stuart Mill Institute Mill s methods John Stuart Mill Library List of liberal theorists On Social Freedom Women s suffrage in the United KingdomNotes Edit Hyman Anthony 1982 Charles Babbage Pioneer of the Computer Princeton University Press pp 120 121 What effect did Babbages Economy of Machinery and Manufacturers have Generally his book received little attention as it not greatly concerned with such traditional problems of economics as the nature of value Actually the effect was considerable his discussion of factories and manufactures entering the main currents of economic thought Here it must suffice to look briefly at its influence on two major figures John Stuart Mill and Adam Smith Varouxakis Georgios 1999 Guizot s historical works and J S Mill s reception of Tocqueville History of Political Thought 20 2 292 312 JSTOR 26217580 Friedrich Hayek 1941 The Counter Revolution of Science Economica 8 31 281 320 doi 10 2307 2549335 JSTOR 2549335 a b c The Project Gutenberg EBook of Autobiography by John Stuart Mill Archived 18 May 2020 at the Wayback Machine gutenberg org Retrieved 11 June 2013 Michael N Forster After Herder Philosophy of Language in the German Tradition Oxford University Press 2010 p 9 Ralph Raico 27 January 2018 Mises Institute ed John Stuart Mill and the New Liberalism Bertrand Russell 1998 2 Adolescence Autobiography Psychology Press ISBN 978 0415189859 Bertrand Russell on God Canadian Broadcasting Corporation 1959 Archived from the original on 26 January 2010 Retrieved 8 March 2010 Mommsen Wolfgang J 2013 Max Weber and His Contemporaries Routledge pp 8 10 Thouverez Emile 1908 Stuart Mill 4th ed Paris Bloud amp Cie p 23 a b Macleod Christopher 14 November 2017 Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy John Stuart Mill s On Liberty victorianweb Retrieved 23 July 2009 On Liberty is a rational justification of the freedom of the individual in opposition to the claims of the state to impose unlimited control and is thus a defense of the rights of the individual against the state John Stuart Mill Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy plato stanford edu Retrieved 31 July 2009 Orator Hunt and the first suffrage petition 1832 UK Parliament John Stuart Mill and the 1866 petition UK Parliament Halevy Elie 1966 The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism Beacon Press pp 282 284 ISBN 978 0191010200 a b c d Cornell University Library Making of America Collection collections library cornell edu Murray N Rothbard 1 February 2006 An Austrian Perspective on the History of Economic Thought Ludwig von Mises Institute p 105 ISBN 978 0945466482 Retrieved 21 January 2011 John Stuart Mill s Mental Breakdown Victorian Unconversions and Romantic Poetry victorianweb org Carlyle Thomas 7 March 1835 Kinser Brent E ed TC TO JAMES FRASER The Carlyle Letters Online doi 10 1215 lt 18350307 TC JFR 01 Baumgarten Murray 2004 Mill John Stuart In Cumming Mark ed The Carlyle Encyclopedia Madison and Teaneck NJ Fairleigh Dickinson University Press p 326 ISBN 9780838637920 Pickering Mary 1993 Auguste Comte an intellectual biography Cambridge University Press pp 509 512 535 537 Capaldi Nicholas John Stuart Mill A Biography p 33 Cambridge 2004 ISBN 0521620244 Cornell University Library Making of America Collection collections library cornell edu Book of Members 1780 2010 Chapter M PDF American Academy of Arts and Sciences Retrieved 15 April 2011 Mill John Stuart Writings on India Edited by John M Robson Martin Moir and Zawahir Moir Toronto University of Toronto Press London Routledge c 1990 Klausen Jimmy Casas 7 January 2016 Violence and Epistemology J S Mill s Indians after the Mutiny Political Research Quarterly 69 96 107 doi 10 1177 1065912915623379 ISSN 1065 9129 S2CID 157038995 Jennifer Pitts Boundaries of the International Law and Empire Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press 2018 165 Harris Abram L 1 January 1964 John Stuart Mill Servant of the East India Company The Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science 30 2 185 202 doi 10 2307 139555 JSTOR 139555 a b Lal Vinay 1998 John Stuart Mill and India a review article New Quest 54 1 54 64 Inaugural Address at St Andrews Longmans Green Reader And Dyer 1867 No 22991 The London Gazette 14 July 1865 p 3528 Capaldi Nicholas John Stuart Mill A Biography pp 321 322 Cambridge 2004 ISBN 0521620244 a b Sher George ed 2001 Utilitarianism and the 1868 Speech on Capital Punishment by J S Mill Hackett Publishing Co APS Member History search amphilsoc org Retrieved 21 April 2021 More Adept With Concepts Than People The New York Times 6 December 1996 Retrieved 19 March 2022 Editorial Notes Secular Review 16 13 203 28 March 1885 It has always seemed to us that this is one of the instances in which Mill approached out of deference to conventional opinion as near to the borderland of Cant as he well could without compromising his pride of place as a recognised thinker and sceptic Linda C Raeder 2002 Spirit of the Age John Stuart Mill and the Religion of Humanity University of Missouri Press p 65 ISBN 978 0826263278 Comte welcomed the prospect of being attacked publicly for his irreligion he said as this would permit him to clarify the nonatheistic nature of his and Mill s atheism Larsen Timothy 2018 John Stuart Mill A Secular Life Oxford University Press p 14 ISBN 978 0198753155 A letter John wrote from Forde Abbey when he was eight years old casually mentions in his general report of his activities that he too had been to Thorncombe parish church so even when Bentham had home field advantage the boy was still receiving a Christian spiritual formation Indeed Mill occasionally attended Christian worship services during his teen years and thereafter for the rest of his life The sea of faith was full and all around Larsen Timothy 7 December 2018 A surprisingly religious John Stuart Mill TL Mill decided that strictly in terms of proof the right answer to that question of God s existence is that it is a very probable hypothesis He also thought it was perfectly rational and legitimate to believe in God as an act of hope or as the result of one s efforts to discern the meaning of life as a whole Shermer Michael 15 August 2002 In Darwin s Shadow The Life and Science of Alfred Russel Wallace A Biographical Study on the Psychology of History Oxford University Press p 212 ISBN 978 0199923854 Arindam Matilal Bimal Krishna Chakrabarti 1994 Knowing from words Western and Indian philosophical analysis of understanding and testimony Kluwer Academic ISBN 0792323459 OCLC 28016267 Matilal BimalKrishna March 1989 Ny ya critique of the Buddhist doctrine of non soul Journal of Indian Philosophy 17 1 doi 10 1007 bf00160139 ISSN 0022 1791 S2CID 170181380 a b Mill John Stuart 1859 1869 On Liberty 4th ed London Longmans Green Reader and Dyer pp 21 22 Archived 17 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine a b Mill John Stuart 1859 2001 On Liberty Archived 14 November 2019 at the Wayback Machine Kitchener ON Batoche Books Retrieved 17 June 2020 a b I Introductory Mill John Stuart 1869 On Liberty bartleby com Retrieved 16 July 2018 Mill John Stuart 1859 2006 On Liberty Penguin Classics ISBN 978 0141441474 pp 10 11 Mill John Stuart 1859 1909 On Liberty pp 195 290 in Harvard Classics 25 edited by C W Eliot New York PF Collier amp Son p 248 Mill John Stuart 1859 1985 On Liberty edited by G Himmelfarb UK Penguin pp 83 84 a b c Paul Ellen Frankel Fred Dycus Miller and Jeffrey Paul 2004 Freedom of Speech 21 Cambridge University Press Mill John Stuart 1859 1863 On Liberty Ticknor and Fields p 23 Schenck v United States 249 U S 47 1919 George amp Kline 2006 p 409 George amp Kline 2006 p 410 John Stuart Mill s On Liberty A Translation into Modern English Kindle edition 2013 38 ISBN 978 0906321638 British Press Freedom under Threat New York Times 14 November 2013 Abbott Lewis F Defending Liberty the Case for a New Bill of Rights ISR Google Books 2019 p 22 ISBN 978 0906321737 J S Mill s Career at the East India Company victorianweb org Theo Goldberg David 2000 Liberalism s limits Carlyle and Mill on the negro question Nineteenth Century Contexts 22 2 203 216 doi 10 1080 08905490008583508 S2CID 194002917 John Stuart Mill Dissertations and Discussions Political Philosophical and Historical New York 1874 Vol 3 pp 252 253 Williams David 7 February 2020 John Stuart Mill and the practice of colonial rule in India Journal of International Political Theory 17 3 412 428 doi 10 1177 1755088220903349 ISSN 1755 0882 S2CID 214445850 Mill John Stuart 1850 The Negro Question Archived 17 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Fraser s Magazine for Town and Country 41 25 31 a b Mill John Stuart 1869 The Subjection of Women Archived 29 April 2015 at the Wayback Machine ch 1 a b The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill Volume XV The Later Letters of John Stuart Mill 1849 1873 Part II Online Library of Liberty oll libertyfund org Retrieved 28 April 2020 Vile John R 2003 Great American Judges An Encyclopedia ABC CLIO ISBN 978 1576079898 P T Peter 1991 John Stuart Mill Thomas Carlyle and the U s Civil War Historian 54 1 93 106 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6563 1991 tb00843 x ISSN 1540 6563 Daggett Windsor 1920 A Down East Yankee From the District of Maine Portland Maine A J Huston p 32 Divinity Jone Johnson Lewis Jone Johnson Lewis has a Master of Member Is a Humanist Clergy late 1960s certified transformational coach She has been involved in the women s movement since the About Male Feminist John Stuart Mill ThoughtCo Retrieved 9 July 2019 Cunningham Wood John John Stuart Mill Critical Assessments 4 Mill John Stuart 1869 2005 The Subjection of Women pp 17 26 in Feminist Theory A Philosophical Anthology edited by A E Cudd and R O Andreasen Oxford UK Blackwell Publishing ISBN 978 1405116619 West Henry R 1 September 2015 J S Mill In Crisp Roger ed The Oxford handbook of the history of ethics Oxford p 528 ISBN 978 0198744405 OCLC 907652431 Mill 1863 p 51 Mill John 2002 The Basic Writings of John Stuart Mill The Modern Library p 239 a b Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill February 2004 via Project Gutenberg Freeman Stephen J Dennis W Engels and Michael K Altekruse Foundations for Ethical Standards and Codes The Role of Moral Philosophy and Theory in Ethics Counseling and Values vol 48 no 3 2004 pp 163 173 eLibrary Davis G Scott 2005 Introduction Introduction to Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill vii xiv Barnes amp Noble Library of Essential Reading a b Heydt Colin John Stuart Mill 1806 1873 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Mill John 1961 Utilitarianism Doubleday p 211 Driver Julia 27 March 2009 The History of Utilitarianism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Bronfenbrenner Martin 1977 Poetry Pushpin and Utility Economic Inquiry 15 95 110 doi 10 1111 j 1465 7295 1977 tb00452 x Mill 1863 p 16 Mill 1863 p 2 Mill 1863 p 3 Mill 1863 p 24 Mill 1863 p 29 Mill 1863 p 8 Fitzpatrick 2006 p 84 Autobiography by John Stuart Mill Retrieved 11 March 2021 via Project Gutenberg AUTO Chapter 5 John Stuart Mill Autobiography laits utexas edu Retrieved 11 March 2021 Ifaw org PDF Archived from the original PDF on 26 June 2008 IREF Pour la liberte economique et la concurrence fiscale Archived 27 March 2009 at the Wayback Machine PDF Strasser 1991 Mill John Stuart Bentham Jeremy 2004 Ryan Alan ed Utilitarianism and other essays London Penguin Books p 11 ISBN 978 0140432725 Wilson Fred 2007 John Stuart Mill Political Economy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 4 May 2009 Mill John Stuart 1852 On The General Principles of Taxation V 2 14 Principles of Political Economy 3rd ed Library of Economics and Liberty The passage about flat taxation was altered by the author in this edition which is acknowledged in this online edition s footnote 8 This sentence replaced in the 3rd ed a sentence of the original It is partial taxation which is a mild form of robbery McManus Matt 30 May 2021 Was John Stuart Mill a Socialist Jacobin Retrieved 1 June 2021 Mill John Stuart 2011 1st pub Belfords Clarke amp Co 1879 Socialism Project Gutenberg p 29 Retrieved 1 June 2021 Ekelund Robert B Jr Hebert Robert F 1997 A History of Economic Theory and Method 4th ed Waveland Press Long Grove Illinois p 172 ISBN 978 1577663812 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Marx Grundrisse The aim is rather to present production see e g Mill as distinct from distribution etc as encased in eternal natural laws independent of history at which opportunity bourgeois relations are then quietly smuggled in as the inviolable natural laws on which society in the abstract is founded This is the more or less conscious purpose of the whole proceeding In distribution by contrast humanity has allegedly permitted itself to be considerably more arbitrary Quite apart from this crude tearing apart of production and distribution and of their real relationship it must be apparent from the outset that no matter how differently distribution may have been arranged in different stages of social development it must be possible here also just as with production to single out common characteristics and just as possible to confound or to extinguish all historic differences under general human laws a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Principles of Political Economy with some of their Applications to Social Philosophy IV 7 21 John Stuart Mill Political Economy IV 7 21 Principles of Political Economy and On Liberty Chapter IV Of the Limits to the Authority of Society Over the Individual Thompson Dennis F 1976 John Stuart Mill and Representative Government Princeton NJ Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0691021874 Letwin Shirley 1965 The Pursuit of Certainty Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 306 ISBN 978 0865971943 Pateman Carole 1970 Participation and Democratic Theory Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 28 ISBN 978 0521290043 Thompson Dennis 2007 Mill in Parliament when should a philosopher compromise In Urbinati N Zakaras A eds J S Mill s Political Thought Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 166 199 ISBN 978 0521677561 Davis Elynor G 1985 Mill Socialism and the English Romantics An Interpretation Economica 52 207 345 358 351 doi 10 2307 2553857 JSTOR 2553857 De Mattos Laura Valladao 2000 John Stuart Mill socialism and his Liberal Utopia an application of his view of social institutions History of Economic Ideas 8 2 95 120 97 Mill John Stuart 1885 Principles of Political Economy New York D Appleton and Company Jensen Hans December 2001 John Stuart Mill s Theories of Wealth and Income Distribution Review of Social Economy 59 4 491 507 doi 10 1080 00346760110081599 S2CID 145340813 a b Ekelund Robert Tollison Robert May 1976 The New Political Economy of J S Mill Means to Social Justice The Canadian Journal of Economics 9 2 213 231 doi 10 2307 134519 JSTOR 134519 The Principles of Political Economy Book 4 Chapter VI Archived from the original on 23 September 2015 Retrieved 9 March 2008 Ropke Inge 1 October 2004 The early history of modern ecological economics Ecological Economics 50 3 4 293 314 doi 10 1016 j ecolecon 2004 02 012 Mill John Stuart Principles of Political Economy PDF p 25 Retrieved 1 November 2016 Swainson Bill ed 2000 Encarta Book of Quotations Macmillan pp 642 643 ISBN 978 0312230005 Radio pick of the day The Guardian 17 May 2006 Retrieved 20 April 2022 Hansard report of Commons Sitting Capital Punishment Within Prisons Bill Bill 36 Committee stage HC Deb 21 April 1868 vol 191 cc 1033 63 including Mill s speech Col 1047 1055 Archived 30 June 2009 at the Wayback Machine His speech against the abolition of capital punishment was commented upon in an editorial in The Times Wednesday 22 April 1868 p 8 Issue 26105 col E References EditMill s work Edit Mill John Stuart 1863 Utilitarianism London Parker Son and Bourn West Strand OCLC 78070085 Other sources Edit Bell Duncan John Stuart Mill on Colonies Political Theory Vol 38 February 2010 pp 34 64 Brink David O 1992 Mill s Deliberative Utilitarianism Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 67 103 Brink David Mill s Moral and Political Philosophy Archived 17 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Claeys Gregory Mill and Paternalism Cambridge University Press 2013 Christians Clifford G amp John C Merrill eds Ethical Communication Five Moral Stances in Human Dialogue Columbia MO University of Missouri Press 2009 Fitzpatrick J R 2006 John Stuart Mill s Political Philosophy Continuum Studies in British Philosophy Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1847143440 George Roger Z Kline Robert D 2006 Intelligence and the national security strategist enduring issues and challenges Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0742540385 Gopnick Adam Right Again The passions of John Stuart Mill The New Yorker 6 October 2008 Archived 20 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine Harrington Jack 2010 Sir John Malcolm and the Creation of British India Ch 5 New York Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 0230108851 Harwood Sterling Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism in Louis P Pojman ed Moral Philosophy A Reader Indianapolis IN Hackett Publishing Co 1998 and in Sterling Harwood ed Business as Ethical and Business as Usual Belmont CA Wadsworth Publishing Co 1996 Chapter 7 Hollander Samuel The Economics of John Stuart Mill University of Toronto Press 1985 Kolmar Wendy amp Frances Bartowski Feminist Theory 2nd ed New York Mc Graw Hill 2005 Letwin Letwin The Pursuit of Certainty Cambridge University Press 1965 ISBN 978 0865971943 Packe Michael St John The Life of John Stuart Mill Macmillan 1952 Pateman Carole Participation and Democratic Theory Cambridge University Press 1970 ISBN 978 0521290043 Reeves Richard John Stuart Mill Victorian Firebrand Atlantic Books 2007 paperback 2008 ISBN 978 1843546443 Robinson Dave amp Groves Judy 2003 Introducing Political Philosophy Icon Books ISBN 184046450X Rosen Frederick Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill Routledge Studies in Ethics amp Moral Theory 2003 ISBN 0415220947 Skoble Aeon 2008 Mill John Stuart 1806 1873 In Hamowy Ronald ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA Sage Cato Institute pp 329 331 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 n202 ISBN 978 1412965804 Spiegel H W 1991 The Growth of Economic Thought Economic history Duke University Press ISBN 978 0822309734 Strasser Mark Philip 1991 The Moral Philosophy of John Stuart Mill Toward Modifications of Contemporary Utilitarianism Wakefield New Hampshire Longwood Academic ISBN 978 0893416812 Ten Chin Liew Mill on Liberty Clarendon Press Oxford 1980 full text online at Contents Victorianweb org National University of Singapore Thompson Dennis F John Stuart Mill and Representative Government Princeton University Press 1976 ISBN 978 0691021874 Thompson Dennis F Mill in Parliament When Should a Philosopher Compromise in J S Mill s Political Thought eds N Urbinati and A Zakaras Cambridge University Press 2007 ISBN 978 0521677561 Walker Francis Amasa 1876 The Wages Question A Treatise on Wages and the Wages Class Henry Holt Further reading EditAlican Necip Fikri 1994 Mill s Principle of Utility A Defense of John Stuart Mill s Notorious Proof Amsterdam and Atlanta Editions Rodopi B V ISBN 978 9051837483 Bayles M D 1968 Contemporary Utilitarianism Anchor Books Doubleday Bentham Jeremy 2009 An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation Dover Philosophical Classics Dover Publications Inc ISBN 978 0486454528 Brandt Richard B 1979 A Theory of the Good and the Right Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0198245506 Lee Sidney ed 1894 Mill John Stuart Dictionary of National Biography Vol 37 London Smith Elder amp Co Lopez Rosario 2016 Contexts of John Stuart Mill s Liberalism Politics and the Science of Society in Victorian Britain Baden Baden Nomos ISBN 978 3848736959 Lyons David 1965 Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism Oxford University Press UK ISBN 978 0198241973 Mill John Stuart 2011 A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive Classic Reprint Forgotten Books ISBN 978 1440090820 Mill John Stuart 1981 Autobiography In Robson John ed Collected Works volume XXXI University of Toronto Press ISBN 978 0710007186 Moore G E 1903 Principia Ethica Prometheus Books UK ISBN 978 0879754983 Rosen Frederick 2003 Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill Routledge Scheffler Samuel August 1994 The Rejection of Consequentialism A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions Second Edition Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0198235118 Smart J J C Williams Bernard January 1973 Utilitarianism For and Against Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521098229 Francisco Vergara Bentham and Mill on the Quality of Pleasures Revue d etudes benthamiennes Paris 2011 Francisco Vergara A Critique of Elie Halevy refutation of an important distortion of British moral philosophy Philosophy Journal of The Royal Institute of Philosophy London 1998 External links EditThis section s use of external links may not follow Wikipedia s policies or guidelines Please improve this article by removing excessive or inappropriate external links and converting useful links where appropriate into footnote references December 2015 Learn how and when to remove this template message John Stuart Mill at Wikipedia s sister projects Media from Commons Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Textbooks from Wikibooks Resources from Wikiversity Data from Wikidata Mill s works Edit Works by John Stuart Mill in eBook form at Standard Ebooks Works by John Stuart Mill at Project Gutenberg Works by or about John Stuart Mill at Internet Archive Works by John Stuart Mill at LibriVox public domain audiobooks The Online Books Page lists works on various sites Works readable and downloadable Primary and secondary works More easily readable versions of On Liberty Utilitarianism Three Essays on Religion The Subjection of Women A System of Logic and Autobiography Of the Composition of Causes Chapter VI of System of Logic 1859 John Stuart Mill s diary of a walking tour at Mount Holyoke College Archived 3 December 2013 at the Wayback Machine A System of Logic University Press of the Pacific Honolulu 2002 ISBN 1410202526Secondary works Edit Macleod Christopher John Stuart Mill In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy John Stuart Mill in the Internet Encyclopedia of PhilosophyFurther information Edit Minto William Mitchell John Malcolm 1911 Mill John Stuart In Chisholm Hugh ed Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 18 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 454 459 Catalogue of Mill s correspondence and papers held at the Archives Division of the London School of Economics View the Archives Catalogue of the contents of this important holding which also includes letters of James Mill and Helen Taylor John Stuart Mill s library Somerville College Library in Oxford holds 1700 volumes owned by John Stuart Mill and his father James Mill many containing their marginalia John Stuart Mill Obituary Notice Tuesday November 4 1873 Eminent Persons Biographies reprinted from The Times Vol I 1870 1875 Macmillan amp Co 1892 pp 195 224 hdl 2027 uc2 ark 13960 t6n011x45 via HathiTrust Mill BBC Radio 4 discussion with A C Grayling Janet Radcliffe Richards amp Alan Ryan In Our Time 18 May 2006 Portraits of John Stuart Mill at the National Portrait Gallery London John Stuart Mill Archived 17 April 2019 at the Wayback Machine on Google Scholar John Stuart Mill biographical profile including quotes and further resources at Utilitarianism net Parliament of the United KingdomPreceded bySir George de Lacy Evans Member of Parliament for Westminster1865 1868 Succeeded byWilliam Henry SmithAcademic officesPreceded byWilliam Stirling of Keir Rector of the University of St Andrews1865 1868 Succeeded byJames Anthony Froude Portals Biography Politics United Kingdom Economics England Liberalism Philosophy Science Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title John Stuart Mill amp oldid 1135628287, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.