fbpx
Wikipedia

Moral realism

Moral realism (also ethical realism) is the position that ethical sentences express propositions that refer to objective features of the world (that is, features independent of subjective opinion), some of which may be true to the extent that they report those features accurately. This makes moral realism a non-nihilist form of ethical cognitivism (which accepts that ethical sentences express propositions and can therefore be evaluated as true or false) with an ontological orientation, standing in opposition to all forms of moral anti-realism[1] and moral skepticism, including ethical subjectivism (which denies that moral propositions refer to objective facts), error theory (which denies that any moral propositions are true); and non-cognitivism (which denies that moral sentences express propositions at all). Within moral realism, the two main subdivisions are ethical naturalism and ethical non-naturalism.[2]

Many philosophers claim that moral realism may be dated back at least to Plato as a philosophical doctrine,[3] and that it is a fully defensible form of moral doctrine.[4] A survey from 2009 involving 3,226 respondents[5] found that 56% of philosophers accept or lean towards moral realism (28%: anti-realism; 16%: other).[6] Another study in 2020 found 62.1% accept or lean towards realism.[7] Some notable examples of robust moral realists include David Brink,[8] John McDowell, Peter Railton,[9] Geoffrey Sayre-McCord,[10] Michael Smith, Terence Cuneo,[11] Russ Shafer-Landau,[12] G. E. Moore,[13] John Finnis, Richard Boyd, Nicholas Sturgeon,[14] Thomas Nagel, Derek Parfit and Peter Singer. Norman Geras has argued that Karl Marx was a moral realist.[15] Moral realism has been studied in the various philosophical and practical applications.[16]

Robust versus minimal moral realism Edit

A delineation of moral realism into a minimal form, a moderate form, and a robust form has been put forward in the literature.[14]

The robust model of moral realism commits moral realists to three theses:[17]

  • The semantic thesis: The primary semantic role of moral predicates (such as "right" and "wrong") is to refer to moral properties (such as rightness and wrongness), so that moral statements (such as "honesty is good" and "slavery is unjust") purport to represent moral facts, and express propositions that are true or false (or approximately true, largely false, and so on).
  • The alethic thesis: Some moral propositions are in fact true.
  • The metaphysical thesis: Moral propositions are true when actions and other objects of moral assessment have the relevant moral properties (so that the relevant moral facts obtain), where these facts and properties are robust: their metaphysical status, whatever it is, is not relevantly different from that of (certain types of) ordinary non-moral facts and properties.

The minimal model leaves off the metaphysical thesis, treating it as matter of contention among moral realists (as opposed to between moral realists and moral anti-realists). This dispute is not insignificant, as acceptance or rejection of the metaphysical thesis is taken by those employing the robust model as the key difference between moral realism and moral anti-realism. Indeed, the question of how to classify certain logically possible (if eccentric) views—such as the rejection of the semantic and alethic theses in conjunction with the acceptance of the metaphysical thesis—turns on which model we accept.[18] Someone employing the robust model might call such a view "realist non-cognitivism," while someone employing the minimal model might simply place such a view alongside other, more traditional, forms of non-cognitivism.

The robust model and the minimal model also disagree over how to classify moral subjectivism (roughly, the view that moral facts are not mind-independent in the relevant sense, but that moral statements may still be true).[19] The historical association of subjectivism with moral anti-realism in large part explains why the robust model of moral realism has been dominant—even if only implicitly—both in the traditional and contemporary philosophical literature on metaethics.[18]

In the minimal sense of realism, R. M. Hare could be considered a realist in his later works, as he is committed to the objectivity of value judgments, even though he denies that moral statements express propositions with truth-values per se. Moral constructivists like John Rawls and Christine Korsgaard[20] may also be realists in this minimalist sense; the latter describes her own position as procedural realism. Some readings of evolutionary science such as those of Charles Darwin and James Mark Baldwin have suggested that in so far as an ethics may be associated with survival strategies and natural selection then such behavior may be associated with a moderate position of moral realism equivalent to an ethics of survival.

Advantages Edit

Moral realism allows the ordinary rules of logic (modus ponens, etc.) to be applied straightforwardly to moral statements. We can say that a moral belief is false or unjustified or contradictory in the same way we would about a factual belief. This is a problem for expressivism, as shown by the Frege–Geach problem.

Another advantage of moral realism is its capacity to resolve moral disagreements: if two moral beliefs contradict one another, realism says that they cannot both be right, and therefore everyone involved ought to be seeking out the right answer to resolve the disagreement. Contrary theories of meta-ethics have trouble even formulating the statement "this moral belief is wrong," and so they cannot resolve disagreements in this way.

Proponents Edit

Peter Railton's moral realism is often associated with a naturalist approach. He argues that moral facts can be reduced to non-moral facts and that our moral claims aim to describe an objective reality. In his well-known paper "Moral Realism" (1986),[9] Railton advocates for a form of moral realism that is naturalistic and scientifically accessible. He suggests that moral facts can be understood in terms of the naturalistic concept of an individual's good. He employs a hypothetical observer's standpoint to explain moral judgments. This standpoint considers what fully rational, well-informed, and sympathetic agents would agree upon under ideal conditions. Railton's naturalistic approach aims to bridge the is-ought gap by explaining moral facts in terms of natural facts, and his theory is generally considered to be a response to the challenge of moral skepticism and anti-realism. By doing so, he attempts to show that moral facts are not mysterious or disconnected from the rest of the world, but can be understood and studied much like other natural phenomena.

Philippa Foot adopts a moral realist position, criticizing Stevenson's idea that when evaluation is superposed on fact there has been a "committal in a new dimension."[21] She introduces, by analogy, the practical implications of using the word "injury." Not just anything counts as an injury. There must be some impairment. When we suppose a man wants the things the injury prevents him from obtaining, haven’t we fallen into the old naturalistic fallacy?

It may seem that the only way to make a necessary connection between 'injury' and the things that are to be avoided, is to say that it is only used in an 'action-guiding sense' when applied to something the speaker intends to avoid. But we should look carefully at the crucial move in that argument, and query the suggestion that someone might happen not to want anything for which he would need the use of hands or eyes. Hands and eyes, like ears and legs, play a part in so many operations that a man could only be said not to need them if he had no wants at all.[21]: 96 

Foot argues that the virtues, like hands and eyes in the analogy, play so large a part in so many operations that it is implausible to suppose that a committal in a non-naturalist dimension is necessary to demonstrate their goodness.

Philosophers who have supposed that actual action was required if 'good' were to be used in a sincere evaluation have got into difficulties over weakness of will, and they should surely agree that enough has been done if we can show that any man has reason to aim at virtue and avoid vice. But is this impossibly difficult if we consider the kinds of things that count as virtue and vice? Consider, for instance, the cardinal virtues, prudence, temperance, courage and justice. Obviously any man needs prudence, but does he not also need to resist the temptation of pleasure when there is harm involved? And how could it be argued that he would never need to face what was fearful for the sake of some good? It is not obvious what someone would mean if he said that temperance or courage were not good qualities, and this not because of the 'praising' sense of these words, but because of the things that courage and temperance are.[21]: 97 

W. D. Ross articulates his moral realism in analogy to mathematics by stating that the moral order is just as real as "the spatial or numerical structure expressed in the axioms of geometry or arithmetic".[22]: 29–30 

In his defense of Divine Command Theory and thereby moral realism, C. Stephen Evans comments that the fact that there are significant moral disagreements does not undermine moral realism. Much of what may appear to be moral disagreement is actually disagreement over facts. In abortion debates, for example, the crux of the issue may really be whether a fetus is a human person. He goes on to comment that there are in fact tremendous amounts of moral agreement. There are five common principles that are recognized by different human cultures, including (1) A general duty not to harm others and a general duty to benefit others; (2) Special duties to those with whom one has special relations, such as friends and family members; (3) Duties to be truthful; (4) Duties to keep one's commitments and promises; (5) Duties to deal fairly and justly with others.[23]

Criticisms Edit

Several criticisms have been raised against moral realism. A prominent criticism, articulated by J.L. Mackie, is that moral realism postulates the existence of "entities or qualities or relations of a very strange sort, utterly different from anything else in the universe. Correspondingly, if we were aware of them it would have to be by some faculty of moral perception or intuition, utterly different from our ordinary ways of knowing everything else."[24][25] A number of theories have been developed for how we access objective moral truths, including ethical intuitionism and moral sense theory.[26]

Another criticism of moral realism put forth by Mackie is that it can offer no plausible explanation for cross-cultural moral differences— ethical relativism. "The actual variations in the moral codes are more readily explained by the hypothesis that they reflect ways of life than by the hypothesis that they express perceptions, most of them seriously inadequate and badly distorted, of objective values".[27]

The evolutionary debunking argument suggests that because human psychology is primarily produced by evolutionary processes which do not seem to have a reason to be sensitive to moral facts, taking a moral realist stance can only lead to moral skepticism. The aim of the argument is to undercut the motivations for taking a moral realist stance, namely to be able to assert there are reliable moral standards.[28]

See also Edit

References Edit

  1. ^ "Moral Realism | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 2020-05-28.
  2. ^ Dancy, Jonathan (2016), "Moral realism", Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1 ed.), Routledge, doi:10.4324/9780415249126-l059-1, ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6, retrieved 2020-05-28
  3. ^ Plato's Moral Realism: The Discovery of the Presuppositions of Ethics, by John M. Rist (Jul 15, 2012)
  4. ^ Moral Realism as a Moral Doctrine, (New Directions in Ethics), by Matthew H. Kramer
  5. ^ "The PhilPapers Surveys". philpapers.org. Retrieved 21 December 2016.
  6. ^ PhilPapers survey, 2009, under the heading 'Meta-ethics'
  7. ^ "What Philosophers Believe: Results from the 2020 PhilPapers Survey | Daily Nous". November 2021.
  8. ^ Brink, David O., Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
  9. ^ a b Railton, Peter (1986). "Moral Realism". Philosophical Review. 95 (2): 163–207. doi:10.2307/2185589. JSTOR 2185589.
  10. ^ Sayre-McCord, Geoff (2005). "Moral Realism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). (link)
  11. ^ Cuneo, Terence (2007). "The Normative Web: An Argument for Moral Realism", Oxford.
  12. ^ Shafer-Landau, Russ (2003) "Moral Realism: A Defense", Oxford, ISBN 0-19-925975-5.
  13. ^ Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  14. ^ a b Sturgeon, Nicholas (1985). "Moral Explanations", in Morality, Reason, and Truth, edited by David Copp and David Zimmerman, Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld, pp. 49-78.
  15. ^ Geras, Norman (1985). "The Controversy about Marx and Justice". New Left Review. 150: 47–85.
  16. ^ Praise and Blame: Moral Realism and Its Applications, (New Forum Books), by Daniel N. Robinson (Jul 29, 2002).
  17. ^ Väyrynen, Pekka (2005). "Moral Realism", Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition, Donald M. Borchert (ed.). (link 2008-05-12 at the Wayback Machine)
  18. ^ a b Joyce, Richard (2007), "Moral Anti-Realism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2007 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). (link)
  19. ^ Joyce, Richard (2016), "Moral Anti-Realism", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-03-08, Non-objectivism (as it will be called here) allows that moral facts exist but holds that they are, in some manner to be specified, constituted by mental activity...The present discussion uses the label "non-objectivism" instead of the simple "subjectivism" since there is an entrenched usage in metaethics for using the latter to denote the thesis that in making a moral judgment one is reporting (as opposed to expressing) one's own mental attitudes (e.g., "Stealing is wrong" means "I disapprove of stealing").
  20. ^ Korsgaard, Christine (1996). The Sources of Normativity, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  21. ^ a b c Foot, Philippa (1958). "Moral Beliefs". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 59: 83–104. doi:10.1093/aristotelian/59.1.83.
  22. ^ Ross, W. D. (2002) [1930]. The Right and the Good. Clarendon Press.
  23. ^ Evans, C. Stephen (2013). God & Moral Obligation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 178.
  24. ^ Mackie, John, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Viking Press, 1977) part 1, chap. 1, section 9 : The argument from Queerness
  25. ^ Harman, Gilbert, The Nature of Morality : An Introduction to Ethics (Oxford,1977), I.1, "Ethics and observation"
  26. ^ The need to postulate a special faculty of moral perception is avoided by ethical naturalism, a form of moral realism which holds that moral claims refer to observable conditions (such as wellbeing). Terence Cuneo argues that criticisms that moral properties are not empirically observable can also be leveled against our concepts of non-moral epistemic justification. See Terence Cuneo, The Normative Web: An Argument for Moral Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
  27. ^ Mackie, John, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Viking Press, 1977) part 1, chap. 1, section 8 : The argument from relativity:
  28. ^ Vavova, Katia (2015). "Evolutionary Debunking of Moral Realism". Philosophy Compass. 10 (2): 104–116. doi:10.1111/phc3.12194.

Further reading Edit

moral, realism, also, ethical, realism, position, that, ethical, sentences, express, propositions, that, refer, objective, features, world, that, features, independent, subjective, opinion, some, which, true, extent, that, they, report, those, features, accura. Moral realism also ethical realism is the position that ethical sentences express propositions that refer to objective features of the world that is features independent of subjective opinion some of which may be true to the extent that they report those features accurately This makes moral realism a non nihilist form of ethical cognitivism which accepts that ethical sentences express propositions and can therefore be evaluated as true or false with an ontological orientation standing in opposition to all forms of moral anti realism 1 and moral skepticism including ethical subjectivism which denies that moral propositions refer to objective facts error theory which denies that any moral propositions are true and non cognitivism which denies that moral sentences express propositions at all Within moral realism the two main subdivisions are ethical naturalism and ethical non naturalism 2 Many philosophers claim that moral realism may be dated back at least to Plato as a philosophical doctrine 3 and that it is a fully defensible form of moral doctrine 4 A survey from 2009 involving 3 226 respondents 5 found that 56 of philosophers accept or lean towards moral realism 28 anti realism 16 other 6 Another study in 2020 found 62 1 accept or lean towards realism 7 Some notable examples of robust moral realists include David Brink 8 John McDowell Peter Railton 9 Geoffrey Sayre McCord 10 Michael Smith Terence Cuneo 11 Russ Shafer Landau 12 G E Moore 13 John Finnis Richard Boyd Nicholas Sturgeon 14 Thomas Nagel Derek Parfit and Peter Singer Norman Geras has argued that Karl Marx was a moral realist 15 Moral realism has been studied in the various philosophical and practical applications 16 Contents 1 Robust versus minimal moral realism 2 Advantages 3 Proponents 4 Criticisms 5 See also 6 References 7 Further readingRobust versus minimal moral realism EditA delineation of moral realism into a minimal form a moderate form and a robust form has been put forward in the literature 14 The robust model of moral realism commits moral realists to three theses 17 The semantic thesis The primary semantic role of moral predicates such as right and wrong is to refer to moral properties such as rightness and wrongness so that moral statements such as honesty is good and slavery is unjust purport to represent moral facts and express propositions that are true or false or approximately true largely false and so on The alethic thesis Some moral propositions are in fact true The metaphysical thesis Moral propositions are true when actions and other objects of moral assessment have the relevant moral properties so that the relevant moral facts obtain where these facts and properties are robust their metaphysical status whatever it is is not relevantly different from that of certain types of ordinary non moral facts and properties The minimal model leaves off the metaphysical thesis treating it as matter of contention among moral realists as opposed to between moral realists and moral anti realists This dispute is not insignificant as acceptance or rejection of the metaphysical thesis is taken by those employing the robust model as the key difference between moral realism and moral anti realism Indeed the question of how to classify certain logically possible if eccentric views such as the rejection of the semantic and alethic theses in conjunction with the acceptance of the metaphysical thesis turns on which model we accept 18 Someone employing the robust model might call such a view realist non cognitivism while someone employing the minimal model might simply place such a view alongside other more traditional forms of non cognitivism The robust model and the minimal model also disagree over how to classify moral subjectivism roughly the view that moral facts are not mind independent in the relevant sense but that moral statements may still be true 19 The historical association of subjectivism with moral anti realism in large part explains why the robust model of moral realism has been dominant even if only implicitly both in the traditional and contemporary philosophical literature on metaethics 18 In the minimal sense of realism R M Hare could be considered a realist in his later works as he is committed to the objectivity of value judgments even though he denies that moral statements express propositions with truth values per se Moral constructivists like John Rawls and Christine Korsgaard 20 may also be realists in this minimalist sense the latter describes her own position as procedural realism Some readings of evolutionary science such as those of Charles Darwin and James Mark Baldwin have suggested that in so far as an ethics may be associated with survival strategies and natural selection then such behavior may be associated with a moderate position of moral realism equivalent to an ethics of survival Advantages EditMoral realism allows the ordinary rules of logic modus ponens etc to be applied straightforwardly to moral statements We can say that a moral belief is false or unjustified or contradictory in the same way we would about a factual belief This is a problem for expressivism as shown by the Frege Geach problem Another advantage of moral realism is its capacity to resolve moral disagreements if two moral beliefs contradict one another realism says that they cannot both be right and therefore everyone involved ought to be seeking out the right answer to resolve the disagreement Contrary theories of meta ethics have trouble even formulating the statement this moral belief is wrong and so they cannot resolve disagreements in this way Proponents EditPeter Railton s moral realism is often associated with a naturalist approach He argues that moral facts can be reduced to non moral facts and that our moral claims aim to describe an objective reality In his well known paper Moral Realism 1986 9 Railton advocates for a form of moral realism that is naturalistic and scientifically accessible He suggests that moral facts can be understood in terms of the naturalistic concept of an individual s good He employs a hypothetical observer s standpoint to explain moral judgments This standpoint considers what fully rational well informed and sympathetic agents would agree upon under ideal conditions Railton s naturalistic approach aims to bridge the is ought gap by explaining moral facts in terms of natural facts and his theory is generally considered to be a response to the challenge of moral skepticism and anti realism By doing so he attempts to show that moral facts are not mysterious or disconnected from the rest of the world but can be understood and studied much like other natural phenomena Philippa Foot adopts a moral realist position criticizing Stevenson s idea that when evaluation is superposed on fact there has been a committal in a new dimension 21 She introduces by analogy the practical implications of using the word injury Not just anything counts as an injury There must be some impairment When we suppose a man wants the things the injury prevents him from obtaining haven t we fallen into the old naturalistic fallacy It may seem that the only way to make a necessary connection between injury and the things that are to be avoided is to say that it is only used in an action guiding sense when applied to something the speaker intends to avoid But we should look carefully at the crucial move in that argument and query the suggestion that someone might happen not to want anything for which he would need the use of hands or eyes Hands and eyes like ears and legs play a part in so many operations that a man could only be said not to need them if he had no wants at all 21 96 Foot argues that the virtues like hands and eyes in the analogy play so large a part in so many operations that it is implausible to suppose that a committal in a non naturalist dimension is necessary to demonstrate their goodness Philosophers who have supposed that actual action was required if good were to be used in a sincere evaluation have got into difficulties over weakness of will and they should surely agree that enough has been done if we can show that any man has reason to aim at virtue and avoid vice But is this impossibly difficult if we consider the kinds of things that count as virtue and vice Consider for instance the cardinal virtues prudence temperance courage and justice Obviously any man needs prudence but does he not also need to resist the temptation of pleasure when there is harm involved And how could it be argued that he would never need to face what was fearful for the sake of some good It is not obvious what someone would mean if he said that temperance or courage were not good qualities and this not because of the praising sense of these words but because of the things that courage and temperance are 21 97 W D Ross articulates his moral realism in analogy to mathematics by stating that the moral order is just as real as the spatial or numerical structure expressed in the axioms of geometry or arithmetic 22 29 30 In his defense of Divine Command Theory and thereby moral realism C Stephen Evans comments that the fact that there are significant moral disagreements does not undermine moral realism Much of what may appear to be moral disagreement is actually disagreement over facts In abortion debates for example the crux of the issue may really be whether a fetus is a human person He goes on to comment that there are in fact tremendous amounts of moral agreement There are five common principles that are recognized by different human cultures including 1 A general duty not to harm others and a general duty to benefit others 2 Special duties to those with whom one has special relations such as friends and family members 3 Duties to be truthful 4 Duties to keep one s commitments and promises 5 Duties to deal fairly and justly with others 23 Criticisms EditSeveral criticisms have been raised against moral realism A prominent criticism articulated by J L Mackie is that moral realism postulates the existence of entities or qualities or relations of a very strange sort utterly different from anything else in the universe Correspondingly if we were aware of them it would have to be by some faculty of moral perception or intuition utterly different from our ordinary ways of knowing everything else 24 25 A number of theories have been developed for how we access objective moral truths including ethical intuitionism and moral sense theory 26 Another criticism of moral realism put forth by Mackie is that it can offer no plausible explanation for cross cultural moral differences ethical relativism The actual variations in the moral codes are more readily explained by the hypothesis that they reflect ways of life than by the hypothesis that they express perceptions most of them seriously inadequate and badly distorted of objective values 27 The evolutionary debunking argument suggests that because human psychology is primarily produced by evolutionary processes which do not seem to have a reason to be sensitive to moral facts taking a moral realist stance can only lead to moral skepticism The aim of the argument is to undercut the motivations for taking a moral realist stance namely to be able to assert there are reliable moral standards 28 See also EditCognitivism Cornell realism Emotivism Evolution of morality Moral absolutism Moral relativism Morality Nominalism The Right and the GoodReferences Edit Moral Realism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy www iep utm edu Retrieved 2020 05 28 Dancy Jonathan 2016 Moral realism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 ed Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 l059 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 retrieved 2020 05 28 Plato s Moral Realism The Discovery of the Presuppositions of Ethics by John M Rist Jul 15 2012 Moral Realism as a Moral Doctrine New Directions in Ethics by Matthew H Kramer The PhilPapers Surveys philpapers org Retrieved 21 December 2016 PhilPapers survey 2009 under the heading Meta ethics What Philosophers Believe Results from the 2020 PhilPapers Survey Daily Nous November 2021 Brink David O Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics New York Cambridge University Press 1989 a b Railton Peter 1986 Moral Realism Philosophical Review 95 2 163 207 doi 10 2307 2185589 JSTOR 2185589 Sayre McCord Geoff 2005 Moral Realism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2005 Edition Edward N Zalta ed link Cuneo Terence 2007 The Normative Web An Argument for Moral Realism Oxford Shafer Landau Russ 2003 Moral Realism A Defense Oxford ISBN 0 19 925975 5 Moore G E 1903 Principia Ethica Cambridge Cambridge University Press a b Sturgeon Nicholas 1985 Moral Explanations in Morality Reason and Truth edited by David Copp and David Zimmerman Totowa N J Rowman and Allanheld pp 49 78 Geras Norman 1985 The Controversy about Marx and Justice New Left Review 150 47 85 Praise and Blame Moral Realism and Its Applications New Forum Books by Daniel N Robinson Jul 29 2002 Vayrynen Pekka 2005 Moral Realism Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Donald M Borchert ed link Archived 2008 05 12 at the Wayback Machine a b Joyce Richard 2007 Moral Anti Realism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2007 Edition Edward N Zalta ed link Joyce Richard 2016 Moral Anti Realism in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2021 03 08 Non objectivism as it will be called here allows that moral facts exist but holds that they are in some manner to be specified constituted by mental activity The present discussion uses the label non objectivism instead of the simple subjectivism since there is an entrenched usage in metaethics for using the latter to denote the thesis that in making a moral judgment one is reporting as opposed to expressing one s own mental attitudes e g Stealing is wrong means I disapprove of stealing Korsgaard Christine 1996 The Sources of Normativity New York Cambridge University Press a b c Foot Philippa 1958 Moral Beliefs Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59 83 104 doi 10 1093 aristotelian 59 1 83 Ross W D 2002 1930 The Right and the Good Clarendon Press Evans C Stephen 2013 God amp Moral Obligation Oxford Oxford University Press p 178 Mackie John Ethics Inventing Right and Wrong Viking Press 1977 part 1 chap 1 section 9 The argument from Queerness Harman Gilbert The Nature of Morality An Introduction to Ethics Oxford 1977 I 1 Ethics and observation The need to postulate a special faculty of moral perception is avoided by ethical naturalism a form of moral realism which holds that moral claims refer to observable conditions such as wellbeing Terence Cuneo argues that criticisms that moral properties are not empirically observable can also be leveled against our concepts of non moral epistemic justification See Terence Cuneo The Normative Web An Argument for Moral Realism Oxford Oxford University Press 2007 Mackie John Ethics Inventing Right and Wrong Viking Press 1977 part 1 chap 1 section 8 The argument from relativity Vavova Katia 2015 Evolutionary Debunking of Moral Realism Philosophy Compass 10 2 104 116 doi 10 1111 phc3 12194 Further reading EditMoral Realism article from Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Moral realism article from Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Hume David 1739 Treatise Concerning Human Nature edited by L A Selby Bigge Oxford Oxford University Press 1888 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Moral realism amp oldid 1178013560, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.