fbpx
Wikipedia

Justice

Justice, in its broadest sense, is the principle that people receive that which they deserve, with the interpretation of what then constitutes "deserving" being impacted upon by numerous fields, with many differing viewpoints and perspectives, including the concepts of moral correctness based on ethics, rationality, law, religion, equity and fairness. The state will sometimes endeavor to increase justice by operating courts and enforcing their rulings.

Evidence about the Nazi Ernst Kaltenbrunner's war crimes is presented at the Nuremberg trials

Early theories of justice were set out by the Ancient Greek philosophers Plato in his work The Republic, and Aristotle in his Nicomachean Ethics. Advocates of divine command theory have said that justice issues from God. In the 17th century, philosophers such as John Locke said that justice derives from natural law. Social contract theory said that justice is derived from the mutual agreement of everyone. In the 19th century, utilitarian philosophers such as John Stuart Mill said that justice is based on the best outcomes for the greatest number of people.

Theories of distributive justice study what is to be distributed, between whom they are to be distributed, and what is the proper distribution. Egalitarians have said that justice can only exist within the coordinates of equality. John Rawls used a social contract theory to say that justice, and especially distributive justice, is a form of fairness. Robert Nozick and others said that property rights, also within the realm of distributive justice and natural law, maximizes the overall wealth of an economic system. Theories of retributive justice say that wrongdoing should be punished to ensure justice. The closely related restorative justice (also sometimes called "reparative justice") is an approach to justice that focuses on the needs of victims and offenders.

Harmony

Justice is a proper, harmonious relationship between the warring parts of the person or city. Hence, Plato's definition of justice is that justice is the having and doing of what is one's own. A just man is a man in just the right place, doing his best and giving the precise equivalent of what he has received. This applies both at the individual level and at the universal level. A person's soul has three parts – reason, spirit and desire. Similarly, a city has three parts – Socrates uses the parable of the chariot to illustrate his point: a chariot works as a whole because the two horses' power is directed by the charioteer. Lovers of wisdom – philosophers, in one sense of the term – should rule because only they understand what is good. If one is ill, one goes to a medic rather than a farmer, because the medic is expert in the subject of health. Similarly, one should trust one's city to an expert in the subject of the good, not to a mere politician who tries to gain power by giving people what they want, rather than what's good for them. Socrates uses the parable of the ship to illustrate this point: the unjust city is like a ship in open ocean, crewed by a powerful but drunken captain (the common people), a group of untrustworthy advisors who try to manipulate the captain into giving them power over the ship's course (the politicians), and a navigator (the philosopher) who is the only one who knows how to get the ship to port. For Socrates, the only way the ship will reach its destination – the good – is if the navigator takes charge.[1]

Divine command

Advocates of divine command theory say that justice, and indeed the whole of morality, is the authoritative command of God. Murder is wrong and must be punished, for instance, because God says it so. Some versions of the theory assert that God must be obeyed because of the nature of his relationship with humanity, others assert that God must be obeyed because he is goodness itself, and thus doing what he says would be best for everyone.

A meditation on the divine command theory by Plato can be found in his dialogue, Euthyphro. Called the Euthyphro dilemma, it goes as follows: "Is what is morally good commanded by God because it is morally good, or is it morally good because it is commanded by God?" The implication is that if the latter is true, then justice is beyond mortal understanding; if the former is true, then morality exists independently from God, and is therefore subject to the judgment of mortals. A response, popularized in two contexts by Immanuel Kant and C. S. Lewis, is that it is deductively valid to say that the existence of an objective morality implies the existence of God and vice versa.

Natural law

 
Justitia by Maarten van Heemskerk, 1556. Justitia carries symbolic items such as: a sword, scales and a blindfold[2]

For advocates of the theory that justice is part of natural law (e.g., John Locke), justice involves the nature of man.[3]

Despotism and skepticism

In Republic by Plato, the character Thrasymachus argues that justice is the interest of the strong – merely a name for what the powerful or cunning ruler has imposed on the people.

Mutual agreement

Advocates of the social contract say that justice is derived from the mutual agreement of everyone; or, in many versions, from what they would agree to under hypothetical conditions including equality and absence of bias. This account is considered further below, under 'Justice as Fairness'. The absence of bias refers to an equal ground for all people involved in a disagreement (or trial in some cases).[citation needed]

Subordinate value

According to utilitarian thinkers including John Stuart Mill, justice is not as fundamental as we often think. Rather, it is derived from the more basic standard of rightness, consequentialism: what is right is what has the best consequences (usually measured by the total or average welfare caused). So, the proper principles of justice are those that tend to have the best consequences. These rules may turn out to be familiar ones such as keeping contracts; but equally, they may not, depending on the facts about real consequences. Either way, what is important is those consequences, and justice is important, if at all, only as derived from that fundamental standard. Mill tries to explain our mistaken belief that justice is overwhelmingly important by arguing that it derives from two natural human tendencies: our desire to retaliate against those who hurt us, or the feeling of self-defense and our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in another's place, sympathy. So, when we see someone harmed, we project ourselves into their situation and feel a desire to retaliate on their behalf. If this process is the source of our feelings about justice, that ought to undermine our confidence in them.[4]

Theories of distributive justice

 
Lex, justitia, pax (Latin for "Law, justice, peace") on the pediment of the Supreme Court of Switzerland

Theories of distributive justice need to answer three questions:

  1. What goods are to be distributed? Is it to be wealth, power, respect, opportunities or some combination of these things?
  2. Between what entities are they to be distributed? Humans (dead, living, future), sentient beings, the members of a single society, nations?
  3. What is the proper distribution? Equal, meritocratic, according to social status, according to need, based on property rights and non-aggression?

Distributive justice theorists generally do not answer questions of who has the right to enforce a particular favored distribution, while property rights theorists say that there is no "favored distribution". Rather, distribution should be based simply on whatever distribution results from lawful interactions or transactions (that is, transactions which are not illicit).

Social justice

Social justice encompasses the just relationship between individuals and their society, often considering how privileges, opportunities, and wealth ought to be distributed among individuals.[5] Social justice is also associated with social mobility, especially the ease with which individuals and families may move between social strata.[6] Social justice is distinct from cosmopolitanism, which is the idea that all people belong to a single global community with a shared morality.[7] Social justice is also distinct from egalitarianism, which is the idea that all people are equal in terms of status, value, or rights, as social justice theories do not all require equality.[8] For example, sociologist George C. Homans suggested that the root of the concept of justice is that each person should receive rewards that are proportional to their contributions.[9][10] Economist Friedrich Hayek said that the concept of social justice was meaningless, saying that justice is a result of individual behavior and unpredictable market forces.[11] Social justice is closely related to the concept of relational justice, which is about the just relationship with individuals who possess features in common such as nationality, or who are engaged in cooperation or negotiation.[12][13]

Fairness

 
J. L. Urban, statue of Lady Justice at court building in Olomouc, Czech Republic

In his A Theory of Justice, John Rawls used a social contract argument to show that justice, and especially distributive justice, is a form of fairness: an impartial distribution of goods. Rawls asks us to imagine ourselves behind a veil of ignorance that denies us all knowledge of our personalities, social statuses, moral characters, wealth, talents and life plans, and then asks what theory of justice we would choose to govern our society when the veil is lifted, if we wanted to do the best that we could for ourselves. We don't know who in particular we are, and therefore can't bias the decision in our own favor. So, the decision-in-ignorance models fairness, because it excludes selfish bias. Rawls said that each of us would reject the utilitarian theory of justice that we should maximize welfare (see below) because of the risk that we might turn out to be someone whose own good is sacrificed for greater benefits for others. Instead, we would endorse Rawls's two principles of justice:

  • Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all.
  • Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both
    • to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, and
    • attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.[14]

This imagined choice justifies these principles as the principles of justice for us, because we would agree to them in a fair decision procedure. Rawls's theory distinguishes two kinds of goods – (1) the good of liberty rights and (2) social and economic goods, i.e. wealth, income and power – and applies different distributions to them – equality between citizens for (1), equality unless inequality improves the position of the worst off for (2).

In one sense, theories of distributive justice may assert that everyone should get what they deserve. Theories vary on the meaning of what is "deserved". The main distinction is between theories that say the basis of just deserts ought to be held equally by everyone, and therefore derive egalitarian accounts of distributive justice – and theories that say the basis of just deserts is unequally distributed on the basis of, for instance, hard work, and therefore derive accounts of distributive justice by which some should have more than others.

According to meritocratic theories, goods, especially wealth and social status, should be distributed to match individual merit, which is usually understood as some combination of talent and hard work. According to needs-based theories, goods, especially such basic goods as food, shelter and medical care, should be distributed to meet individuals' basic needs for them. Marxism is a needs-based theory, expressed succinctly in Marx's slogan "from each according to his ability, to each according to his need".[15] According to contribution-based theories, goods should be distributed to match an individual's contribution to the overall social good.

Property rights

In Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Robert Nozick said that distributive justice is not a matter of the whole distribution matching an ideal pattern, but of each individual entitlement having the right kind of history. It is just that a person has some good (especially, some property right) if and only if they came to have it by a history made up entirely of events of two kinds:

  • Just acquisition, especially by working on unowned things; and
  • Just transfer, that is free gift, sale or other agreement, but not theft (i.e. by force or fraud).

If the chain of events leading up to the person having something meets this criterion, they are entitled to it: that they possess it is just, and what anyone else does or doesn't have or need is irrelevant.

On the basis of this theory of distributive justice, Nozick said that all attempts to redistribute goods according to an ideal pattern, without the consent of their owners, are theft. In particular, redistributive taxation is theft.

Some property rights theorists (such as Nozick) also take a consequentialist view of distributive justice and say that property rights based justice also has the effect of maximizing the overall wealth of an economic system. They explain that voluntary (non-coerced) transactions always have a property called Pareto efficiency. The result is that the world is better off in an absolute sense and no one is worse off. They say that respecting property rights maximizes the number of Pareto efficient transactions in the world and minimized the number of non-Pareto efficient transactions in the world (i.e. transactions where someone is made worse off). The result is that the world will have generated the greatest total benefit from the limited, scarce resources available in the world. Further, this will have been accomplished without taking anything away from anyone unlawfully.

Welfare-maximization

According to the utilitarian, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals.[16] This may require sacrifice of some for the good of others, so long as everyone's good is taken impartially into account. Utilitarianism, in general, says that the standard of justification for actions, institutions, or the whole world, is impartial welfare consequentialism, and only indirectly, if at all, to do with rights, property, need, or any other non-utilitarian criterion. These other criteria might be indirectly important, to the extent that human welfare involves them. But even then, such demands as human rights would only be elements in the calculation of overall welfare, not uncrossable barriers to action.

Theories of retributive justice

Theories of retributive justice involve punishment for wrongdoing, and need to answer three questions:

  1. why punish?
  2. who should be punished?
  3. what punishment should they receive?

This section considers the two major accounts of retributive justice, and their answers to these questions. Utilitarian theories look forward to the future consequences of punishment, while retributive theories look back to particular acts of wrongdoing, and attempt to balance them with deserved punishment.

Utilitarianism

According to the utilitarian, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals. Punishment fights crime in three ways:

  1. Deterrence. The credible threat of punishment might lead people to make different choices; well-designed threats might lead people to make choices that maximize welfare. This matches some strong intuitions about just punishment: that it should generally be proportional to the crime.
  2. Rehabilitation. Punishment might make "bad people" into "better" ones. For the utilitarian, all that "bad person" can mean is "person who's likely to cause unwanted things (like suffering)". So, utilitarianism could recommend punishment that changes someone such that they are less likely to cause bad things.
  3. Security/Incapacitation. Perhaps there are people who are irredeemable causers of bad things. If so, imprisoning them might maximize welfare by limiting their opportunities to cause harm and therefore the benefit lies within protecting society.

So, the reason for punishment is the maximization of welfare, and punishment should be of whomever, and of whatever form and severity, are needed to meet that goal. This may sometimes justify punishing the innocent, or inflicting disproportionately severe punishments, when that will have the best consequences overall (perhaps executing a few suspected shoplifters live on television would be an effective deterrent to shoplifting, for instance). It also suggests that punishment might turn out never to be right, depending on the facts about what actual consequences it has.[17]

Retributivism

The retributivist will think consequentialism is mistaken. If someone does something wrong we must respond by punishing for the committed action itself, regardless of what outcomes punishment produces. Wrongdoing must be balanced or made good in some way, and so the criminal deserves to be punished. It says that all guilty people, and only guilty people, deserve appropriate punishment. This matches some strong intuitions about just punishment: that it should be proportional to the crime, and that it should be of only and all of the guilty.[18] However, it is sometimes said that retributivism is merely revenge in disguise.[19] However, there are differences between retribution and revenge: the former is impartial and has a scale of appropriateness, whereas the latter is personal and potentially unlimited in scale.[20]

Restorative justice

Restorative justice (also sometimes called "reparative justice") is an approach to justice that focuses on the needs of victims and offenders, instead of satisfying abstract legal principles or punishing the offender. Victims take an active role in the process, while offenders are encouraged to take responsibility for their actions, "to repair the harm they've done – by apologizing, returning stolen money, or community service". It is based on a theory of justice that considers crime and wrongdoing to be an offense against an individual or community rather than the state. Restorative justice that fosters dialogue between victim and offender shows the highest rates of victim satisfaction and offender accountability.[21]

Mixed theories

Some modern philosophers have said that Utilitarian and Retributive theories are not mutually exclusive. For example, Andrew von Hirsch, in his 1976 book Doing Justice, suggested that we have a moral obligation to punish greater crimes more than lesser ones.[22] However, so long as we adhere to that constraint then utilitarian ideals would play a significant secondary role.

Theories

Introduction

 
Bonino da Campione, Justice, c. 1357, National Gallery of Art

It has been said[23] that 'systematic' or 'programmatic' political and moral philosophy in the West begins, in Plato's Republic, with the question, 'What is Justice?'[24] According to most contemporary theories of justice, justice is overwhelmingly important: John Rawls claims that "Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought."[25] In classical approaches, evident from Plato through to Rawls, the concept of 'justice' is always construed in logical or 'etymological' opposition to the concept of injustice. Such approaches cite various examples of injustice, as problems which a theory of justice must overcome. A number of post-World War II approaches do, however, challenge that seemingly obvious dualism between those two concepts.[26] Justice can be thought of as distinct from benevolence, charity, prudence, mercy, generosity, or compassion, although these dimensions are regularly understood to also be interlinked. Justice is the concept of cardinal virtues, of which it is one.[27] Metaphysical justice has often been associated with concepts of fate, reincarnation or Divine Providence, i.e., with a life in accordance with a cosmic plan.

The equivalence of justice and fairness has been historically and culturally established.[28]

Equality

In political theory, liberalism includes two traditional elements: liberty and equality. Most contemporary theories of justice emphasize the concept of equality, including Rawls' theory of justice as fairness. For Ronald Dworkin, a complex notion of equality is the sovereign political virtue.[29] Dworkin raises the question of whether society is under a duty of justice to help those responsible for the fact that they need help. Complications arise in distinguishing matters of choice and matters of chance, as well as justice for future generations in the redistribution of resources that he advocates.[30]

Equality before the law

Law raises important and complex issues about equality, fairness, and justice. There is an old saying that 'All are equal before the law'. The belief in equality before the law is called legal egalitarianism. In criticism of this belief, the author Anatole France said in 1894, "In its majestic equality, the law forbids rich and poor alike to sleep under bridges, beg in the streets, and steal loaves of bread."[31] With this saying, France illustrated the fundamental shortcoming of a theory of legal equality that remains blind to social inequality; the same law applied to all may have disproportionately harmful effects on the least powerful.

Relational justice

Relational justice seeks to examine the connections between individuals and focuses on their relations in societies, with respect to how these relationships are established and configured. In a normative view, this focus includes an understanding of what these relations should be. In a political view, this focus includes the method of organizing persons in society. Rawls’ theory of justice stakes out the task of justice as equalizing the distribution of primary social goods to benefit the worst-off in society. However, his distributive scheme, and other distributive accounts of justice do not directly consider power relations between and among individuals. Nor do they address such political considerations as various structures of decision-making, such as divisions of labor culture, or the construction of social meanings. Even Rawls’ own basic value of self-respect cannot be said to be amenable to distribution.[32] Iris Marion Young charges that distributive accounts of justice fail to provide an adequate way of conceptualizing political justice in that they fail to take into account many of the demands of ordinary life and that a relational view of justice grounded upon understanding the differences among social groups offers a better approach, one which acknowledges unjust power relations among individuals, groups, and institutional structures.[33] Young Kim also takes a relational approach to the question of justice, but departs from Iris Marion Young's political advocacy of group rights and instead, he emphasizes the individual and moral aspects of justice.[34] As to its moral aspects, he said that justice includes responsible actions based on rational and autonomous moral agency, with the individual as the proper bearer of rights and responsibilities. Politically, he maintains that the proper context for justice is a form of liberalism with the traditional elements of liberty and equality, together with the concepts of diversity and tolerance.

Classical liberalism

Equality before the law is one of the basic principles of classical liberalism.[35][36] Classical liberalism calls for equality before the law, not for equality of outcome.[35] Classical liberalism opposes pursuing group rights at the expense of individual rights.[36] In addition to equality, individual liberty serves as a core notion of classical liberalism. As to the liberty component, British social and political theorist, philosopher, and historian of ideas Isaiah Berlin identifies positive and negative liberty in "Two Concepts of Liberty",[37] subscribing to a view of negative liberty, in the form of freedom from governmental interference. He further extends the concept of negative liberty in endorsing John Stuart Mills' harm principle: "the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually and collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection",[38] which represents a classical liberal view of liberty.[39]

Religion and spirituality

Abrahamic justice

 

Jews, Christians, and Muslims traditionally believe that justice is a present, real, right, and, specifically, governing concept along with mercy, and that justice is ultimately derived from and held by God. According to the Bible, such institutions as the Mosaic Law were created by God to require the Israelites to live by and apply His standards of justice.

The Hebrew Bible describes God as saying about the Judeo-Christian patriarch Abraham: "No, for I have chosen him, that he may charge his children and his household after him to keep the way of the Lord by doing righteousness and justice;...." (Genesis 18:19, NRSV). The Psalmist describes God as having "Righteousness and justice [as] the foundation of [His] throne;...." (Psalms 89:14, NRSV).

The New Testament also describes God and Jesus Christ as having and displaying justice, often in comparison with God displaying and supporting mercy (Matthew 5:7).

Theories of sentencing

In criminal law, a sentence forms the final explicit act of a judge-ruled process, and also the symbolic principal act connected to his function.[40] The sentence can generally involve a decree of imprisonment, a fine and/or other punishments against a defendant convicted of a crime. Laws may specify the range of penalties that can be imposed for various offenses, and sentencing guidelines sometimes regulate what punishment within those ranges can be imposed given a certain set of offense and offender characteristics.[41] The most common purposes of sentencing in legal theory are:

Theory Aim of theory Suitable punishment
Retribution Punishment imposed for no reason other than an offense being committed, on the basis that if proportionate, punishment is morally acceptable as a response that satisfies the aggrieved party, their intimates and society.
  • Tariff sentences
  • Sentence must be proportionate to the crime
Deterrence
  • To the individual – the individual is deterred through fear of further punishment.
  • To the general public – Potential offenders warned as to likely punishment
  • Prison Sentence
  • Heavy Fine
  • Long sentence as an example to others
Rehabilitation To reform the offender's behavior
  • Individualized sentences
  • Community service orders
  • moral education
  • vocational education
Incapacitation Offender is made incapable of committing further crime to protect society at large from crime
  • Long prison sentence
  • Electronic tagging
  • Banning orders
Reparation Repayment to victim(s) or to community
  • Compensation
  • Unpaid work
  • Reparation Schemes
Denunciation Society expressing its disapproval reinforcing moral boundaries
  • Reflects blameworthiness of offense
  • punishment in public
  • punishment reported to public

In civil cases the decision is usually known as a verdict, or judgment, rather than a sentence.[42] Civil cases are settled primarily by means of monetary compensation for harm done ("damages") and orders intended to prevent future harm (for example injunctions). Under some legal systems an award of damages involves some scope for retribution, denunciation and deterrence, by means of additional categories of damages beyond simple compensation, covering a punitive effect, social disapprobation, and potentially, deterrence, and occasionally disgorgement (forfeit of any gain, even if no loss was caused to the other party).

Evolutionary perspectives

Evolutionary ethics and evolution of morality suggest evolutionary bases for the concept of justice.[43] Biosocial criminology research says that human perceptions of what is appropriate criminal justice are based on how to respond to crimes in the ancestral small-group environment and that these responses may not always be appropriate for today's societies.[44]

Reactions to fairness

Studies at UCLA in 2008 have indicated that reactions to fairness are "wired" into the brain and that, "Fairness is activating the same part of the brain that responds to food in rats... This is consistent with the notion that being treated fairly satisfies a basic need".[45] Research conducted in 2003 at Emory University involving capuchin monkeys demonstrated that other cooperative animals also possess such a sense and that "inequity aversion may not be uniquely human".[46]

Institutions and justice

In a world where people are interconnected but they disagree, institutions are required to instantiate ideals of justice. These institutions may be justified by their approximate instantiation of justice, or they may be deeply unjust when compared with ideal standards – consider the institution of slavery. Justice is an ideal the world fails to live up to, sometimes due to deliberate opposition to justice despite understanding, which could be disastrous. The question of institutive justice raises issues of legitimacy, procedure, codification and interpretation, which are considered by legal theorists and by philosophers of law.[47] The United Nations Sustainable Development Goal 16 emphasizes the need for strong institutions in order to uphold justice.[48]

See also

Other pages

  • Education for Justice

Types of justice

References

  1. ^ Plato, Republic trans. Robin Waterfield (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984).
  2. ^ Cuban Law's Blindfold, 23.
  3. ^ See Two Treatises of Government: In The Former the False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer and His Followers, are Detected and Overthrown. The Latter is An Essay Concerning the True Original Extent and End of Civil Government (3 ed.). London: Awnsham and John Churchill. 1698. Retrieved 20 November 2014. via Google Books
  4. ^ John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism in On Liberty and Other Essays ed. John Gray (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), Chapter 5.
  5. ^ . Oxford Dictionaries | English. Archived from the original on 14 January 2017. Retrieved 13 November 2018.
  6. ^ Ornstein, Allan C. (1 December 2017). "Social Justice: History, Purpose and Meaning". Society. 54 (6): 541–548. doi:10.1007/s12115-017-0188-8. ISSN 1936-4725.
  7. ^ Kleingeld, Pauline; Brown, Eric (2014), "Cosmopolitanism", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 14 December 2018
  8. ^ . Oxford Dictionaries | English. Archived from the original on 13 November 2018. Retrieved 13 November 2018.
  9. ^ Rubinstein, David (1988). "The Concept of Justice in Sociology". Theory and Society. 17 (4): 527–550. doi:10.1007/BF00158887. JSTOR 657654. S2CID 143622666.
  10. ^ Homans, George Caspar (1974). Social behavior; its elementary forms (Rev. ed.). New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich. pp. 246–249. ISBN 978-0-15-581417-2. OCLC 2668194.
  11. ^ Hayek, F.A. (1976). Law, legislation and liberty : a new statement of the liberal principles of justice and political economy. Routledge & Kegan Paul. p. 78. ISBN 978-0-7100-8403-3. OCLC 769281087.
  12. ^ Poblet, Marta; Casanovas, Pompeu (2008), "Concepts and Fields of Relational Justice", Computable Models of the Law, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, pp. 323–339, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-85569-9_21, ISBN 978-3-540-85568-2
  13. ^ Nagel, Thomas (2005). "The Problem of Global Justice". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 33 (2): 113–147. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2005.00027.x. ISSN 1088-4963. S2CID 144307058.
  14. ^ John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (revised edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 266.
  15. ^ Karl Marx, 'Critique of the Gotha Program' in Karl Marx: Selected writings ed. David McLellan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977): 564–70 [569].
  16. ^ "The Project Gutenberg eBook of on Liberty, by John Stuart Mill". gutenberg.org. Retrieved 3 May 2019.
  17. ^ C.L. Ten, 'Crime and Punishment' in Peter Singer ed., A Companion to Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1993): 366–372.
  18. ^ . California State University. Archived from the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 12 August 2020.
  19. ^ Ted Honderich, Punishment: The supposed justifications (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1969), Chapter 1.
  20. ^ "Retribution vs Revenge - What's the difference?". 9 October 2015.
  21. ^ Michael Braswell, and John Fuller, Corrections, Peacemaking and Restorative Justice: Transforming Individuals and Institutions (Routledge, 2014).
  22. ^ Andrew Von Hirsch, Doing Justice: The Choice of Punishments (Lebanon NH: Northeastern Univ. Press, 1976). ISBN 9780930350833
  23. ^ See, e.g., Eric Heinze, The Concept of Injustice (Routledge, 2013), pp. 4–10, 50–60.
  24. ^ Plato, The Republic, Book I, 331b–c.
  25. ^ John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (revised edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 3
  26. ^ *See, e.g., Eric Heinze, The Concept of Injustice (Routledge, 2013).
    • Clive Barnett The Priority of Injustice: Locating Democracy in Critical Theory
  27. ^ Wenar, Leif (2021), "John Rawls", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 20 May 2021
  28. ^ Daston, Lorraine (2008). "Life, Chance and Life Chances". Daedalus. 137: 5–14. doi:10.1162/daed.2008.137.1.5. S2CID 57563698.
  29. ^ (Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Harvard University Press, 2000)
  30. ^ Young Kim, Justice as Right Actions (Lexington Books, 2015), ch.7 (ISBN 978-1498516518)
  31. ^ (France, The Red Lily, Chapter VII).
  32. ^ Young Kim, Justice as Right Actions (Lexington Books, 2015), ch.10 (ISBN 978-1498516518)
  33. ^ Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Oxford University Press, 1990).
  34. ^ Young Kim, Justice as Right Actions (Lexington Books, 2015) (ISBN 978-1498516518)
  35. ^ a b Chandran Kukathas, "Ethical Pluralism from a Classical Liberal Perspective," in The Many and the One: Religious and Secular Perspectives on Ethical Pluralism in the Modern World, ed. Richard Madsen and Tracy B. Strong, Ethikon Series in Comparative Ethics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003), 61 (ISBN 0-691-09993-6).
  36. ^ a b Mark Evans, ed., Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism: Evidence and Experience (London: Routledge, 2001), 55 (ISBN 1-57958-339-3).
  37. ^ Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty" in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford University Press, 1969)
  38. ^ John Stuart Mill, "On Liberty" in John Stuart Mill on Liberty and Other Essays, ed. John Gray (Oxford University Press, 1998)
  39. ^ Young Kim, Justice as Right Actions (Lexington Books, 2015), p.79 (ISBN 978-1498516518)
  40. ^ "laws rules justice".
  41. ^ "sentencing guidelines" (PDF). Library of Congress.
  42. ^ "how court works".
  43. ^ Morality and evolutionary biology. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  44. ^ Kruger, Daniel J.; Nedelec, Joseph L.; Reischl, Thomas M.; Zimmerman, Marc A. (2015). "Life History Predicts Perceptions of Procedural Justice and Crime Reporting Intentions". Evolutionary Psychological Science. 1 (3): 183–194. doi:10.1007/s40806-015-0021-9. S2CID 142324638.
  45. ^ . UCLA Newsroom. UCLA. 21 April 2008. Archived from the original on 26 February 2010. Retrieved 15 January 2015.
  46. ^ Nature 425, 297–299 (18 September 2003)
  47. ^ David Miller (26 June 2017). "Justice". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  48. ^ Doss, Eric. "Sustainable Development Goal 16". United Nations and the Rule of Law. Retrieved 25 September 2020.

Further reading

  • Clive Barnett, The Priority of Injustice: Locating Democracy in Critical Theory (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 2017), ISBN 978-0-8203-5152-0
  • Brian Barry, Theories of Justice (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989)
  • Gad Barzilai, Communities and Law: Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2003)
  • Harry Brighouse, Justice (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2004)
  • Anthony Duff & David Garland eds, A Reader on Punishment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994)
  • Colin Farrelly, An Introduction to Contemporary Political Theory (London: Sage, 2004)
  • David Gauthier, Morals By Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986)
  • Robert E. Goodin & Philip Pettit eds, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An anthology (2nd edition, Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell, 2006), Part III
  • Serge Guinchard, La justice et ses institutions (Judicial institutions), Dalloz editor, 12 edition, 2013
  • Eric Heinze, The Concept of Injustice (Routledge, 2013)
  • Ted Honderich, Punishment: The supposed justifications (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1969)
  • James Konow (2003) "Which Is the Fairest One of All? A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories", Journal of Economic Literature, 41(4)pp. 1188–1239
  • Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An introduction (2nd edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)
  • Nicola Lacey, State Punishment (London: Routledge, 1988)
  • John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism in On Liberty and Other Essays ed. John Gray (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991)
  • Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974)
  • Amartya Sen (2011). The Idea of Justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-06047-0.
  • Marek Piechowiak, Plato's Conception of Justice and the Question of Human Dignity (2nd edition, revised and extended, Berlin: Peter Lang Academic Publishers, 2021), ISBN 978-3-631-84524-0.
  • C.L. Ten, Crime, Guilt, and Punishment: A philosophical introduction (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987)
  • Plato, Republic trans. Robin Waterfield (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994)
  • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (revised edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999)
  • David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice (New York: Columbia University Press, 2006)
  • Peter Singer ed., A Companion to Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), Part IV
  • Reinhold Zippelius, Rechtsphilosophie, §§ 11–22 (6th edition, Munich: C.H. Beck, 2011), ISBN 978-3-406-61191-9

External links

  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy entries:
    • Distributive Justice, by Michael Allingham
    • Punishment, by Kevin Murtagh
    • Western Theories of Justice, by Wayne P. Pomerleau
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entries:
    • "Justice" by David Miller
    • "Distributive Justice" by Julian Lamont
    • "Justice as a Virtue" by Michael Slote
    • "Punishment" by Hugo Adam Bedau and Erin Kelly
  • , on the relationship between informal/community justice, the rule of law and the United Nations
  • Justice: What's The Right Thing To Do? 27 April 2014 at the Wayback Machine, a series of 12 videos on the subject of justice by Harvard University's Michael Sandel, with reading materials and comments from participants.

justice, other, uses, disambiguation, this, article, needs, attention, from, expert, please, reason, talk, parameter, this, template, explain, issue, with, article, wikiproject, able, help, recruit, expert, january, 2023, broadest, sense, principle, that, peop. For other uses see Justice disambiguation This article needs attention from an expert in Law Please add a reason or a talk parameter to this template to explain the issue with the article WikiProject Law may be able to help recruit an expert January 2023 Justice in its broadest sense is the principle that people receive that which they deserve with the interpretation of what then constitutes deserving being impacted upon by numerous fields with many differing viewpoints and perspectives including the concepts of moral correctness based on ethics rationality law religion equity and fairness The state will sometimes endeavor to increase justice by operating courts and enforcing their rulings Evidence about the Nazi Ernst Kaltenbrunner s war crimes is presented at the Nuremberg trials Early theories of justice were set out by the Ancient Greek philosophers Plato in his work The Republic and Aristotle in his Nicomachean Ethics Advocates of divine command theory have said that justice issues from God In the 17th century philosophers such as John Locke said that justice derives from natural law Social contract theory said that justice is derived from the mutual agreement of everyone In the 19th century utilitarian philosophers such as John Stuart Mill said that justice is based on the best outcomes for the greatest number of people Theories of distributive justice study what is to be distributed between whom they are to be distributed and what is the proper distribution Egalitarians have said that justice can only exist within the coordinates of equality John Rawls used a social contract theory to say that justice and especially distributive justice is a form of fairness Robert Nozick and others said that property rights also within the realm of distributive justice and natural law maximizes the overall wealth of an economic system Theories of retributive justice say that wrongdoing should be punished to ensure justice The closely related restorative justice also sometimes called reparative justice is an approach to justice that focuses on the needs of victims and offenders Contents 1 Harmony 2 Divine command 3 Natural law 3 1 Despotism and skepticism 3 2 Mutual agreement 3 3 Subordinate value 4 Theories of distributive justice 4 1 Social justice 4 2 Fairness 4 3 Property rights 4 4 Welfare maximization 5 Theories of retributive justice 5 1 Utilitarianism 5 2 Retributivism 5 3 Restorative justice 5 4 Mixed theories 6 Theories 6 1 Introduction 6 2 Equality 6 3 Equality before the law 6 4 Relational justice 6 5 Classical liberalism 6 6 Religion and spirituality 6 6 1 Abrahamic justice 6 7 Theories of sentencing 6 8 Evolutionary perspectives 6 9 Reactions to fairness 6 10 Institutions and justice 7 See also 7 1 Other pages 7 2 Types of justice 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External linksHarmony EditMain article The Republic Plato Justice is a proper harmonious relationship between the warring parts of the person or city Hence Plato s definition of justice is that justice is the having and doing of what is one s own A just man is a man in just the right place doing his best and giving the precise equivalent of what he has received This applies both at the individual level and at the universal level A person s soul has three parts reason spirit and desire Similarly a city has three parts Socrates uses the parable of the chariot to illustrate his point a chariot works as a whole because the two horses power is directed by the charioteer Lovers of wisdom philosophers in one sense of the term should rule because only they understand what is good If one is ill one goes to a medic rather than a farmer because the medic is expert in the subject of health Similarly one should trust one s city to an expert in the subject of the good not to a mere politician who tries to gain power by giving people what they want rather than what s good for them Socrates uses the parable of the ship to illustrate this point the unjust city is like a ship in open ocean crewed by a powerful but drunken captain the common people a group of untrustworthy advisors who try to manipulate the captain into giving them power over the ship s course the politicians and a navigator the philosopher who is the only one who knows how to get the ship to port For Socrates the only way the ship will reach its destination the good is if the navigator takes charge 1 Divine command EditMain article Divine command theorySee also Divine command Advocates of divine command theory say that justice and indeed the whole of morality is the authoritative command of God Murder is wrong and must be punished for instance because God says it so Some versions of the theory assert that God must be obeyed because of the nature of his relationship with humanity others assert that God must be obeyed because he is goodness itself and thus doing what he says would be best for everyone A meditation on the divine command theory by Plato can be found in his dialogue Euthyphro Called the Euthyphro dilemma it goes as follows Is what is morally good commanded by God because it is morally good or is it morally good because it is commanded by God The implication is that if the latter is true then justice is beyond mortal understanding if the former is true then morality exists independently from God and is therefore subject to the judgment of mortals A response popularized in two contexts by Immanuel Kant and C S Lewis is that it is deductively valid to say that the existence of an objective morality implies the existence of God and vice versa Natural law EditMain article Natural lawThis section needs expansion You can help by adding to it October 2020 Justitia by Maarten van Heemskerk 1556 Justitia carries symbolic items such as a sword scales and a blindfold 2 For advocates of the theory that justice is part of natural law e g John Locke justice involves the nature of man 3 Despotism and skepticism Edit In Republic by Plato the character Thrasymachus argues that justice is the interest of the strong merely a name for what the powerful or cunning ruler has imposed on the people Further information The Republic Plato Mutual agreement Edit Main article Social contract Advocates of the social contract say that justice is derived from the mutual agreement of everyone or in many versions from what they would agree to under hypothetical conditions including equality and absence of bias This account is considered further below under Justice as Fairness The absence of bias refers to an equal ground for all people involved in a disagreement or trial in some cases citation needed Subordinate value Edit According to utilitarian thinkers including John Stuart Mill justice is not as fundamental as we often think Rather it is derived from the more basic standard of rightness consequentialism what is right is what has the best consequences usually measured by the total or average welfare caused So the proper principles of justice are those that tend to have the best consequences These rules may turn out to be familiar ones such as keeping contracts but equally they may not depending on the facts about real consequences Either way what is important is those consequences and justice is important if at all only as derived from that fundamental standard Mill tries to explain our mistaken belief that justice is overwhelmingly important by arguing that it derives from two natural human tendencies our desire to retaliate against those who hurt us or the feeling of self defense and our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in another s place sympathy So when we see someone harmed we project ourselves into their situation and feel a desire to retaliate on their behalf If this process is the source of our feelings about justice that ought to undermine our confidence in them 4 Theories of distributive justice EditMain article Distributive justice Lex justitia pax Latin for Law justice peace on the pediment of the Supreme Court of SwitzerlandTheories of distributive justice need to answer three questions What goods are to be distributed Is it to be wealth power respect opportunities or some combination of these things Between what entities are they to be distributed Humans dead living future sentient beings the members of a single society nations What is the proper distribution Equal meritocratic according to social status according to need based on property rights and non aggression Distributive justice theorists generally do not answer questions of who has the right to enforce a particular favored distribution while property rights theorists say that there is no favored distribution Rather distribution should be based simply on whatever distribution results from lawful interactions or transactions that is transactions which are not illicit Social justice Edit Main article Social justice Social justice encompasses the just relationship between individuals and their society often considering how privileges opportunities and wealth ought to be distributed among individuals 5 Social justice is also associated with social mobility especially the ease with which individuals and families may move between social strata 6 Social justice is distinct from cosmopolitanism which is the idea that all people belong to a single global community with a shared morality 7 Social justice is also distinct from egalitarianism which is the idea that all people are equal in terms of status value or rights as social justice theories do not all require equality 8 For example sociologist George C Homans suggested that the root of the concept of justice is that each person should receive rewards that are proportional to their contributions 9 10 Economist Friedrich Hayek said that the concept of social justice was meaningless saying that justice is a result of individual behavior and unpredictable market forces 11 Social justice is closely related to the concept of relational justice which is about the just relationship with individuals who possess features in common such as nationality or who are engaged in cooperation or negotiation 12 13 Fairness Edit This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Justice news newspapers books scholar JSTOR February 2018 Learn how and when to remove this template message J L Urban statue of Lady Justice at court building in Olomouc Czech Republic In his A Theory of Justice John Rawls used a social contract argument to show that justice and especially distributive justice is a form of fairness an impartial distribution of goods Rawls asks us to imagine ourselves behind a veil of ignorance that denies us all knowledge of our personalities social statuses moral characters wealth talents and life plans and then asks what theory of justice we would choose to govern our society when the veil is lifted if we wanted to do the best that we could for ourselves We don t know who in particular we are and therefore can t bias the decision in our own favor So the decision in ignorance models fairness because it excludes selfish bias Rawls said that each of us would reject the utilitarian theory of justice that we should maximize welfare see below because of the risk that we might turn out to be someone whose own good is sacrificed for greater benefits for others Instead we would endorse Rawls s two principles of justice Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged consistent with the just savings principle and attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity 14 This imagined choice justifies these principles as the principles of justice for us because we would agree to them in a fair decision procedure Rawls s theory distinguishes two kinds of goods 1 the good of liberty rights and 2 social and economic goods i e wealth income and power and applies different distributions to them equality between citizens for 1 equality unless inequality improves the position of the worst off for 2 In one sense theories of distributive justice may assert that everyone should get what they deserve Theories vary on the meaning of what is deserved The main distinction is between theories that say the basis of just deserts ought to be held equally by everyone and therefore derive egalitarian accounts of distributive justice and theories that say the basis of just deserts is unequally distributed on the basis of for instance hard work and therefore derive accounts of distributive justice by which some should have more than others According to meritocratic theories goods especially wealth and social status should be distributed to match individual merit which is usually understood as some combination of talent and hard work According to needs based theories goods especially such basic goods as food shelter and medical care should be distributed to meet individuals basic needs for them Marxism is a needs based theory expressed succinctly in Marx s slogan from each according to his ability to each according to his need 15 According to contribution based theories goods should be distributed to match an individual s contribution to the overall social good Property rights Edit Further information Libertarianism Entitlement theory and Constitutional economics This section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2018 Learn how and when to remove this template message In Anarchy State and Utopia Robert Nozick said that distributive justice is not a matter of the whole distribution matching an ideal pattern but of each individual entitlement having the right kind of history It is just that a person has some good especially some property right if and only if they came to have it by a history made up entirely of events of two kinds Just acquisition especially by working on unowned things and Just transfer that is free gift sale or other agreement but not theft i e by force or fraud If the chain of events leading up to the person having something meets this criterion they are entitled to it that they possess it is just and what anyone else does or doesn t have or need is irrelevant On the basis of this theory of distributive justice Nozick said that all attempts to redistribute goods according to an ideal pattern without the consent of their owners are theft In particular redistributive taxation is theft Some property rights theorists such as Nozick also take a consequentialist view of distributive justice and say that property rights based justice also has the effect of maximizing the overall wealth of an economic system They explain that voluntary non coerced transactions always have a property called Pareto efficiency The result is that the world is better off in an absolute sense and no one is worse off They say that respecting property rights maximizes the number of Pareto efficient transactions in the world and minimized the number of non Pareto efficient transactions in the world i e transactions where someone is made worse off The result is that the world will have generated the greatest total benefit from the limited scarce resources available in the world Further this will have been accomplished without taking anything away from anyone unlawfully Welfare maximization Edit Main article Utilitarianism According to the utilitarian justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals 16 This may require sacrifice of some for the good of others so long as everyone s good is taken impartially into account Utilitarianism in general says that the standard of justification for actions institutions or the whole world is impartial welfare consequentialism and only indirectly if at all to do with rights property need or any other non utilitarian criterion These other criteria might be indirectly important to the extent that human welfare involves them But even then such demands as human rights would only be elements in the calculation of overall welfare not uncrossable barriers to action Theories of retributive justice EditMain article Retributive justice Walter Seymour Allward s Justitia Justice outside Supreme Court of Canada Ottawa Ontario Canada Theories of retributive justice involve punishment for wrongdoing and need to answer three questions why punish who should be punished what punishment should they receive This section considers the two major accounts of retributive justice and their answers to these questions Utilitarian theories look forward to the future consequences of punishment while retributive theories look back to particular acts of wrongdoing and attempt to balance them with deserved punishment Utilitarianism Edit According to the utilitarian justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals Punishment fights crime in three ways Deterrence The credible threat of punishment might lead people to make different choices well designed threats might lead people to make choices that maximize welfare This matches some strong intuitions about just punishment that it should generally be proportional to the crime Rehabilitation Punishment might make bad people into better ones For the utilitarian all that bad person can mean is person who s likely to cause unwanted things like suffering So utilitarianism could recommend punishment that changes someone such that they are less likely to cause bad things Security Incapacitation Perhaps there are people who are irredeemable causers of bad things If so imprisoning them might maximize welfare by limiting their opportunities to cause harm and therefore the benefit lies within protecting society So the reason for punishment is the maximization of welfare and punishment should be of whomever and of whatever form and severity are needed to meet that goal This may sometimes justify punishing the innocent or inflicting disproportionately severe punishments when that will have the best consequences overall perhaps executing a few suspected shoplifters live on television would be an effective deterrent to shoplifting for instance It also suggests that punishment might turn out never to be right depending on the facts about what actual consequences it has 17 Retributivism Edit The retributivist will think consequentialism is mistaken If someone does something wrong we must respond by punishing for the committed action itself regardless of what outcomes punishment produces Wrongdoing must be balanced or made good in some way and so the criminal deserves to be punished It says that all guilty people and only guilty people deserve appropriate punishment This matches some strong intuitions about just punishment that it should be proportional to the crime and that it should be of only and all of the guilty 18 However it is sometimes said that retributivism is merely revenge in disguise 19 However there are differences between retribution and revenge the former is impartial and has a scale of appropriateness whereas the latter is personal and potentially unlimited in scale 20 Restorative justice Edit Main article Restorative justice Restorative justice also sometimes called reparative justice is an approach to justice that focuses on the needs of victims and offenders instead of satisfying abstract legal principles or punishing the offender Victims take an active role in the process while offenders are encouraged to take responsibility for their actions to repair the harm they ve done by apologizing returning stolen money or community service It is based on a theory of justice that considers crime and wrongdoing to be an offense against an individual or community rather than the state Restorative justice that fosters dialogue between victim and offender shows the highest rates of victim satisfaction and offender accountability 21 Mixed theories Edit Some modern philosophers have said that Utilitarian and Retributive theories are not mutually exclusive For example Andrew von Hirsch in his 1976 book Doing Justice suggested that we have a moral obligation to punish greater crimes more than lesser ones 22 However so long as we adhere to that constraint then utilitarian ideals would play a significant secondary role Theories EditIntroduction Edit Further information Justice virtue and Cardinal virtues Bonino da Campione Justice c 1357 National Gallery of ArtIt has been said 23 that systematic or programmatic political and moral philosophy in the West begins in Plato s Republic with the question What is Justice 24 According to most contemporary theories of justice justice is overwhelmingly important John Rawls claims that Justice is the first virtue of social institutions as truth is of systems of thought 25 In classical approaches evident from Plato through to Rawls the concept of justice is always construed in logical or etymological opposition to the concept of injustice Such approaches cite various examples of injustice as problems which a theory of justice must overcome A number of post World War II approaches do however challenge that seemingly obvious dualism between those two concepts 26 Justice can be thought of as distinct from benevolence charity prudence mercy generosity or compassion although these dimensions are regularly understood to also be interlinked Justice is the concept of cardinal virtues of which it is one 27 Metaphysical justice has often been associated with concepts of fate reincarnation or Divine Providence i e with a life in accordance with a cosmic plan The equivalence of justice and fairness has been historically and culturally established 28 Equality Edit In political theory liberalism includes two traditional elements liberty and equality Most contemporary theories of justice emphasize the concept of equality including Rawls theory of justice as fairness For Ronald Dworkin a complex notion of equality is the sovereign political virtue 29 Dworkin raises the question of whether society is under a duty of justice to help those responsible for the fact that they need help Complications arise in distinguishing matters of choice and matters of chance as well as justice for future generations in the redistribution of resources that he advocates 30 Equality before the law Edit Law raises important and complex issues about equality fairness and justice There is an old saying that All are equal before the law The belief in equality before the law is called legal egalitarianism In criticism of this belief the author Anatole France said in 1894 In its majestic equality the law forbids rich and poor alike to sleep under bridges beg in the streets and steal loaves of bread 31 With this saying France illustrated the fundamental shortcoming of a theory of legal equality that remains blind to social inequality the same law applied to all may have disproportionately harmful effects on the least powerful Relational justice Edit Relational justice seeks to examine the connections between individuals and focuses on their relations in societies with respect to how these relationships are established and configured In a normative view this focus includes an understanding of what these relations should be In a political view this focus includes the method of organizing persons in society Rawls theory of justice stakes out the task of justice as equalizing the distribution of primary social goods to benefit the worst off in society However his distributive scheme and other distributive accounts of justice do not directly consider power relations between and among individuals Nor do they address such political considerations as various structures of decision making such as divisions of labor culture or the construction of social meanings Even Rawls own basic value of self respect cannot be said to be amenable to distribution 32 Iris Marion Young charges that distributive accounts of justice fail to provide an adequate way of conceptualizing political justice in that they fail to take into account many of the demands of ordinary life and that a relational view of justice grounded upon understanding the differences among social groups offers a better approach one which acknowledges unjust power relations among individuals groups and institutional structures 33 Young Kim also takes a relational approach to the question of justice but departs from Iris Marion Young s political advocacy of group rights and instead he emphasizes the individual and moral aspects of justice 34 As to its moral aspects he said that justice includes responsible actions based on rational and autonomous moral agency with the individual as the proper bearer of rights and responsibilities Politically he maintains that the proper context for justice is a form of liberalism with the traditional elements of liberty and equality together with the concepts of diversity and tolerance Classical liberalism Edit Equality before the law is one of the basic principles of classical liberalism 35 36 Classical liberalism calls for equality before the law not for equality of outcome 35 Classical liberalism opposes pursuing group rights at the expense of individual rights 36 In addition to equality individual liberty serves as a core notion of classical liberalism As to the liberty component British social and political theorist philosopher and historian of ideas Isaiah Berlin identifies positive and negative liberty in Two Concepts of Liberty 37 subscribing to a view of negative liberty in the form of freedom from governmental interference He further extends the concept of negative liberty in endorsing John Stuart Mills harm principle the sole end for which mankind are warranted individually and collectively in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number is self protection 38 which represents a classical liberal view of liberty 39 Religion and spirituality Edit Abrahamic justice Edit Moses with the Tablets of Law by Rembrandt van Rijn Jews Christians and Muslims traditionally believe that justice is a present real right and specifically governing concept along with mercy and that justice is ultimately derived from and held by God According to the Bible such institutions as the Mosaic Law were created by God to require the Israelites to live by and apply His standards of justice The Hebrew Bible describes God as saying about the Judeo Christian patriarch Abraham No for I have chosen him that he may charge his children and his household after him to keep the way of the Lord by doing righteousness and justice Genesis 18 19 NRSV The Psalmist describes God as having Righteousness and justice as the foundation of His throne Psalms 89 14 NRSV The New Testament also describes God and Jesus Christ as having and displaying justice often in comparison with God displaying and supporting mercy Matthew 5 7 Theories of sentencing Edit In criminal law a sentence forms the final explicit act of a judge ruled process and also the symbolic principal act connected to his function 40 The sentence can generally involve a decree of imprisonment a fine and or other punishments against a defendant convicted of a crime Laws may specify the range of penalties that can be imposed for various offenses and sentencing guidelines sometimes regulate what punishment within those ranges can be imposed given a certain set of offense and offender characteristics 41 The most common purposes of sentencing in legal theory are Theory Aim of theory Suitable punishmentRetribution Punishment imposed for no reason other than an offense being committed on the basis that if proportionate punishment is morally acceptable as a response that satisfies the aggrieved party their intimates and society Tariff sentences Sentence must be proportionate to the crimeDeterrence To the individual the individual is deterred through fear of further punishment To the general public Potential offenders warned as to likely punishment Prison Sentence Heavy Fine Long sentence as an example to othersRehabilitation To reform the offender s behavior Individualized sentences Community service orders moral education vocational educationIncapacitation Offender is made incapable of committing further crime to protect society at large from crime Long prison sentence Electronic tagging Banning ordersReparation Repayment to victim s or to community Compensation Unpaid work Reparation SchemesDenunciation Society expressing its disapproval reinforcing moral boundaries Reflects blameworthiness of offense punishment in public punishment reported to publicIn civil cases the decision is usually known as a verdict or judgment rather than a sentence 42 Civil cases are settled primarily by means of monetary compensation for harm done damages and orders intended to prevent future harm for example injunctions Under some legal systems an award of damages involves some scope for retribution denunciation and deterrence by means of additional categories of damages beyond simple compensation covering a punitive effect social disapprobation and potentially deterrence and occasionally disgorgement forfeit of any gain even if no loss was caused to the other party Evolutionary perspectives Edit Evolutionary ethics and evolution of morality suggest evolutionary bases for the concept of justice 43 Biosocial criminology research says that human perceptions of what is appropriate criminal justice are based on how to respond to crimes in the ancestral small group environment and that these responses may not always be appropriate for today s societies 44 Reactions to fairness Edit Studies at UCLA in 2008 have indicated that reactions to fairness are wired into the brain and that Fairness is activating the same part of the brain that responds to food in rats This is consistent with the notion that being treated fairly satisfies a basic need 45 Research conducted in 2003 at Emory University involving capuchin monkeys demonstrated that other cooperative animals also possess such a sense and that inequity aversion may not be uniquely human 46 Institutions and justice Edit Main article Law In a world where people are interconnected but they disagree institutions are required to instantiate ideals of justice These institutions may be justified by their approximate instantiation of justice or they may be deeply unjust when compared with ideal standards consider the institution of slavery Justice is an ideal the world fails to live up to sometimes due to deliberate opposition to justice despite understanding which could be disastrous The question of institutive justice raises issues of legitimacy procedure codification and interpretation which are considered by legal theorists and by philosophers of law 47 The United Nations Sustainable Development Goal 16 emphasizes the need for strong institutions in order to uphold justice 48 See also EditOther pages Edit Education for JusticeAdl Arabic for Justice in Islam Criminal justice Ethics Global justice International Court of Justice International Criminal Court Just war theory Just world hypothesis Justice economics Morality Napoleonic Code Rationality Rule according to higher law Sociology of law A Theory of Justice by John Rawls Types of justice Edit Distributive justice Environmental justice Injustice Occupational injustice Open justice Organizational justice Poetic justice Social justice Spatial justiceReferences Edit Plato Republic trans Robin Waterfield Oxford Oxford University Press 1984 Cuban Law s Blindfold 23 See Two Treatises of Government In The Former the False Principles and Foundation of Sir Robert Filmer and His Followers are Detected and Overthrown The Latter is An Essay Concerning the True Original Extent and End of Civil Government 3 ed London Awnsham and John Churchill 1698 Retrieved 20 November 2014 via Google Books John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism in On Liberty and Other Essays ed John Gray Oxford Oxford University Press 1991 Chapter 5 social justice Definition of social justice in English by Oxford Dictionaries Oxford Dictionaries English Archived from the original on 14 January 2017 Retrieved 13 November 2018 Ornstein Allan C 1 December 2017 Social Justice History Purpose and Meaning Society 54 6 541 548 doi 10 1007 s12115 017 0188 8 ISSN 1936 4725 Kleingeld Pauline Brown Eric 2014 Cosmopolitanism in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2014 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 14 December 2018 egalitarianism Definition of egalitarianism in English by Oxford Dictionaries Oxford Dictionaries English Archived from the original on 13 November 2018 Retrieved 13 November 2018 Rubinstein David 1988 The Concept of Justice in Sociology Theory and Society 17 4 527 550 doi 10 1007 BF00158887 JSTOR 657654 S2CID 143622666 Homans George Caspar 1974 Social behavior its elementary forms Rev ed New York Harcourt Brace Jovanovich pp 246 249 ISBN 978 0 15 581417 2 OCLC 2668194 Hayek F A 1976 Law legislation and liberty a new statement of the liberal principles of justice and political economy Routledge amp Kegan Paul p 78 ISBN 978 0 7100 8403 3 OCLC 769281087 Poblet Marta Casanovas Pompeu 2008 Concepts and Fields of Relational Justice Computable Models of the Law Lecture Notes in Computer Science Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 323 339 doi 10 1007 978 3 540 85569 9 21 ISBN 978 3 540 85568 2 Nagel Thomas 2005 The Problem of Global Justice Philosophy amp Public Affairs 33 2 113 147 doi 10 1111 j 1088 4963 2005 00027 x ISSN 1088 4963 S2CID 144307058 John Rawls A Theory of Justice revised edition Oxford Oxford University Press 1999 p 266 Karl Marx Critique of the Gotha Program in Karl Marx Selected writings ed David McLellan Oxford Oxford University Press 1977 564 70 569 The Project Gutenberg eBook of on Liberty by John Stuart Mill gutenberg org Retrieved 3 May 2019 C L Ten Crime and Punishment in Peter Singer ed A Companion to Ethics Oxford Blackwell Publishing 1993 366 372 Punishment California State University Archived from the original on 13 April 2021 Retrieved 12 August 2020 Ted Honderich Punishment The supposed justifications London Hutchinson amp Co 1969 Chapter 1 Retribution vs Revenge What s the difference 9 October 2015 Michael Braswell and John Fuller Corrections Peacemaking and Restorative Justice Transforming Individuals and Institutions Routledge 2014 Andrew Von Hirsch Doing Justice The Choice of Punishments Lebanon NH Northeastern Univ Press 1976 ISBN 9780930350833 See e g Eric Heinze The Concept of Injustice Routledge 2013 pp 4 10 50 60 Plato The Republic Book I 331b c John Rawls A Theory of Justice revised edn Oxford Oxford University Press 1999 p 3 See e g Eric Heinze The Concept of Injustice Routledge 2013 Clive Barnett The Priority of Injustice Locating Democracy in Critical Theory Wenar Leif 2021 John Rawls in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2021 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 20 May 2021 Daston Lorraine 2008 Life Chance and Life Chances Daedalus 137 5 14 doi 10 1162 daed 2008 137 1 5 S2CID 57563698 Ronald Dworkin Sovereign Virtue Harvard University Press 2000 Young Kim Justice as Right Actions Lexington Books 2015 ch 7 ISBN 978 1498516518 France The Red Lily Chapter VII Young Kim Justice as Right Actions Lexington Books 2015 ch 10 ISBN 978 1498516518 Iris Marion Young Justice and the Politics of Difference Oxford University Press 1990 Young Kim Justice as Right Actions Lexington Books 2015 ISBN 978 1498516518 a b Chandran Kukathas Ethical Pluralism from a Classical Liberal Perspective in The Many and the One Religious and Secular Perspectives on Ethical Pluralism in the Modern World ed Richard Madsen and Tracy B Strong Ethikon Series in Comparative Ethics Princeton NJ Princeton University Press 2003 61 ISBN 0 691 09993 6 a b Mark Evans ed Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism Evidence and Experience London Routledge 2001 55 ISBN 1 57958 339 3 Isaiah Berlin Two Concepts of Liberty in Four Essays on Liberty Oxford University Press 1969 John Stuart Mill On Liberty in John Stuart Mill on Liberty and Other Essays ed John Gray Oxford University Press 1998 Young Kim Justice as Right Actions Lexington Books 2015 p 79 ISBN 978 1498516518 laws rules justice sentencing guidelines PDF Library of Congress how court works Morality and evolutionary biology Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2021 Kruger Daniel J Nedelec Joseph L Reischl Thomas M Zimmerman Marc A 2015 Life History Predicts Perceptions of Procedural Justice and Crime Reporting Intentions Evolutionary Psychological Science 1 3 183 194 doi 10 1007 s40806 015 0021 9 S2CID 142324638 Brain reacts to fairness as it does to money and chocolate study shows UCLA Newsroom UCLA 21 April 2008 Archived from the original on 26 February 2010 Retrieved 15 January 2015 Nature 425 297 299 18 September 2003 David Miller 26 June 2017 Justice Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Doss Eric Sustainable Development Goal 16 United Nations and the Rule of Law Retrieved 25 September 2020 Further reading EditClive Barnett The Priority of Injustice Locating Democracy in Critical Theory Athens GA University of Georgia Press 2017 ISBN 978 0 8203 5152 0 Brian Barry Theories of Justice Berkeley University of California Press 1989 Gad Barzilai Communities and Law Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities Ann Arbor University of Michigan Press 2003 Harry Brighouse Justice Cambridge Polity Press 2004 Anthony Duff amp David Garland eds A Reader on Punishment Oxford Oxford University Press 1994 Colin Farrelly An Introduction to Contemporary Political Theory London Sage 2004 David Gauthier Morals By Agreement Oxford Clarendon Press 1986 Robert E Goodin amp Philip Pettit eds Contemporary Political Philosophy An anthology 2nd edition Malden Massachusetts Blackwell 2006 Part III Serge Guinchard La justice et ses institutions Judicial institutions Dalloz editor 12 edition 2013 Eric Heinze The Concept of Injustice Routledge 2013 Ted Honderich Punishment The supposed justifications London Hutchinson amp Co 1969 James Konow 2003 Which Is the Fairest One of All A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories Journal of Economic Literature 41 4 pp 1188 1239 Will Kymlicka Contemporary Political Philosophy An introduction 2nd edition Oxford Oxford University Press 2002 Nicola Lacey State Punishment London Routledge 1988 John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism in On Liberty and Other Essays ed John Gray Oxford Oxford University Press 1991 Robert Nozick Anarchy State and Utopia Oxford Blackwell 1974 Amartya Sen 2011 The Idea of Justice Cambridge Belknap Press of Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 06047 0 Marek Piechowiak Plato s Conception of Justice and the Question of Human Dignity 2nd edition revised and extended Berlin Peter Lang Academic Publishers 2021 ISBN 978 3 631 84524 0 C L Ten Crime Guilt and Punishment A philosophical introduction Oxford Clarendon Press 1987 Plato Republic trans Robin Waterfield Oxford Oxford University Press 1994 John Rawls A Theory of Justice revised edition Oxford Oxford University Press 1999 David Schmidtz Elements of Justice New York Columbia University Press 2006 Peter Singer ed A Companion to Ethics Oxford Blackwell 1993 Part IV Reinhold Zippelius Rechtsphilosophie 11 22 6th edition Munich C H Beck 2011 ISBN 978 3 406 61191 9External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Justice Wikimedia Commons has media related to Justice Wikivoyage has a travel guide for Justice history Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy entries Distributive Justice by Michael Allingham Punishment by Kevin Murtagh Western Theories of Justice by Wayne P Pomerleau Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entries Justice by David Miller Distributive Justice by Julian Lamont Justice as a Virtue by Michael Slote Punishment by Hugo Adam Bedau and Erin Kelly United Nations Rule of Law Informal Justice on the relationship between informal community justice the rule of law and the United Nations Justice What s The Right Thing To Do Archived 27 April 2014 at the Wayback Machine a series of 12 videos on the subject of justice by Harvard University s Michael Sandel with reading materials and comments from participants Portals Law Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Justice amp oldid 1135555015, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.