fbpx
Wikipedia

Animal consciousness

Animal consciousness, or animal awareness, is the quality or state of self-awareness within an animal, or of being aware of an external object or something within itself.[2][3] In humans, consciousness has been defined as: sentience, awareness, subjectivity, qualia, the ability to experience or to feel, wakefulness, having a sense of selfhood, and the executive control system of the mind.[4] Despite the difficulty in definition, many philosophers believe there is a broadly shared underlying intuition about what consciousness is.[5]

According to the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness, "near human-like levels of consciousness" have been observed in the grey parrot.[1]

The topic of animal consciousness is beset with a number of difficulties. It poses the problem of other minds in an especially severe form because animals, lacking the ability to use human language, cannot tell us about their experiences.[6] Also, it is difficult to reason objectively about the question, because a denial that an animal is conscious is often taken to imply that they do not feel, their life has no value, and that harming them is not morally wrong.[7] The 17th-century French philosopher René Descartes, for example, has sometimes been criticised for providing a rationale for the mistreatment of animals because he argued that only humans are conscious.[8]

Philosophers who consider subjective experience the essence of consciousness also generally believe, as a correlate, that the existence and nature of animal consciousness can never rigorously be known. The American philosopher Thomas Nagel spelled out this point of view in an influential essay titled What Is it Like to Be a Bat?. He said that an organism is conscious "if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism—something it is like for the organism"; and he argued that no matter how much we know about an animal's brain and behavior, we can never really put ourselves into the mind of the animal and experience their world in the way they do themself.[9] Other thinkers, such as the cognitive scientist Douglas Hofstadter, dismiss this argument as incoherent.[10] Several psychologists and ethologists have argued for the existence of animal consciousness by describing a range of behaviors that appear to show animals holding beliefs about things they cannot directly perceive—Donald Griffin's 2001 book Animal Minds reviews a substantial portion of the evidence.[11]

Animal consciousness has been actively researched for over one hundred years.[12] In 1927, the American functional psychologist Harvey Carr argued that any valid measure or understanding of awareness in animals depends on "an accurate and complete knowledge of its essential conditions in man".[13] A more recent review concluded in 1985 that "the best approach is to use experiment (especially psychophysics) and observation to trace the dawning and ontogeny of self-consciousness, perception, communication, intention, beliefs, and reflection in normal human fetuses, infants, and children".[12] In 2012, a group of neuroscientists signed the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness, which "unequivocally" asserted that "humans are not unique in possessing the neurological substrates that generate consciousness. Non-human animals, including all mammals and birds, and many other creatures, including octopuses, also possess these neural substrates."[14]

Philosophical background edit

 
René Descartes argued that only humans are conscious, and not other animals.

The mind–body problem in philosophy examines the relationship between mind and matter, and in particular the relationship between consciousness and the brain. A variety of approaches have been proposed. Most are either dualist or monist. Dualism maintains a rigid distinction between the realms of mind and matter. Monism maintains that there is only one kind of stuff, and that mind and matter are both aspects of it. The problem was addressed by pre-Aristotelian philosophers,[15][16] and was famously addressed by René Descartes in the 17th century, resulting in Cartesian dualism. Descartes believed that humans only, and not other animals have this non-physical mind.

The rejection of the mind–body dichotomy is found in French Structuralism, and is a position that generally characterized post-war French philosophy.[17] The absence of an empirically identifiable meeting point between the non-physical mind and its physical extension has proven problematic to dualism and many modern philosophers of mind maintain that the mind is not something separate from the body.[18] These approaches have been particularly influential in the sciences, particularly in the fields of sociobiology, computer science, evolutionary psychology, and the neurosciences.[19][20][21][22]

Epiphenomenalism edit

Epiphenomenalism is the theory in philosophy of mind that mental phenomena are caused by physical processes in the brain or that both are effects of a common cause, as opposed to mental phenomena driving the physical mechanics of the brain. The impression that thoughts, feelings, or sensations cause physical effects, is therefore to be understood as illusory to some extent. For example, it is not the feeling of fear that produces an increase in heart beat, both are symptomatic of a common physiological origin, possibly in response to a legitimate external threat.[23]

The history of epiphenomenalism goes back to the post-Cartesian attempt to solve the riddle of Cartesian dualism, i.e., of how mind and body could interact. La Mettrie, Leibniz and Spinoza all in their own way began this way of thinking. The idea that even if the animal were conscious nothing would be added to the production of behavior, even in animals of the human type, was first voiced by La Mettrie (1745), and then by Cabanis (1802), and was further explicated by Hodgson (1870) and Huxley (1874).[24][25] Huxley (1874) likened mental phenomena to the whistle on a steam locomotive. However, epiphenomenalism flourished primarily as it found a niche among methodological or scientific behaviorism. In the early 1900s scientific behaviorists such as Ivan Pavlov, John B. Watson, and B. F. Skinner began the attempt to uncover laws describing the relationship between stimuli and responses, without reference to inner mental phenomena. Instead of adopting a form of eliminativism or mental fictionalism, positions that deny that inner mental phenomena exist, a behaviorist was able to adopt epiphenomenalism in order to allow for the existence of mind. However, by the 1960s, scientific behaviourism met substantial difficulties and eventually gave way to the cognitive revolution. Participants in that revolution, such as Jerry Fodor, reject epiphenomenalism and insist upon the efficacy of the mind. Fodor even speaks of "epiphobia"—fear that one is becoming an epiphenomenalist.

Thomas Henry Huxley defends in an essay titled On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and its History an epiphenomenalist theory of consciousness according to which consciousness is a causally inert effect of neural activity—"as the steam-whistle which accompanies the work of a locomotive engine is without influence upon its machinery".[26] To this William James objects in his essay Are We Automata? by stating an evolutionary argument for mind-brain interaction implying that if the preservation and development of consciousness in the biological evolution is a result of natural selection, it is plausible that consciousness has not only been influenced by neural processes, but has had a survival value itself; and it could only have had this if it had been efficacious.[27][28] Karl Popper develops in the book The Self and Its Brain a similar evolutionary argument.[29]

Animal ethics edit

Bernard Rollin of Colorado State University, the principal author of two U.S. federal laws regulating pain relief for animals, writes that researchers remained unsure into the 1980s as to whether animals experience pain, and veterinarians trained in the U.S. before 1989 were simply taught to ignore animal pain.[30] In his interactions with scientists and other veterinarians, Rollin asserts that he was regularly asked to prove animals are conscious and provide scientifically acceptable grounds for claiming they feel pain.[30] The denial of animal consciousness by scientists has been described as mentophobia by Donald Griffin.[31] Academic reviews of the topic are equivocal, noting that the argument that animals have at least simple conscious thoughts and feelings has strong support,[32] but some critics continue to question how reliably animal mental states can be determined.[33][34] A refereed journal Animal Sentience[35] launched in 2015 by the Institute of Science and Policy of The Humane Society of the United States is devoted to research on this and related topics.

Defining consciousness edit

About forty meanings attributed to the term consciousness can be identified and categorized based on functions and experiences. The prospects for reaching any single, agreed-upon, theory-independent definition of consciousness appear remote.[36]

Consciousness is an elusive concept that presents many difficulties when attempts are made to define it.[37][38] Its study has progressively become an interdisciplinary challenge for numerous researchers, including ethologists, neurologists, cognitive neuroscientists, philosophers, psychologists and psychiatrists.[39][40]

In 1976 Richard Dawkins wrote, "The evolution of the capacity to simulate seems to have culminated in subjective consciousness. Why this should have happened is, to me, the most profound mystery facing modern biology".[41] In 2004, eight neuroscientists felt it was still too soon for a definition. They wrote an apology in "Human Brain Function":[42]

"We have no idea how consciousness emerges from the physical activity of the brain and we do not know whether consciousness can emerge from non-biological systems, such as computers... At this point the reader will expect to find a careful and precise definition of consciousness. You will be disappointed. Consciousness has not yet become a scientific term that can be defined in this way. Currently we all use the term consciousness in many different and often ambiguous ways. Precise definitions of different aspects of consciousness will emerge ... but to make precise definitions at this stage is premature."

Consciousness is sometimes defined as the quality or state of being aware of an external object or something within oneself.[3][43] It has been defined somewhat vaguely as: subjectivity, awareness, sentience, the ability to experience or to feel, wakefulness, having a sense of selfhood, and the executive control system of the mind.[4] Despite the difficulty in definition, many philosophers believe that there is a broadly shared underlying intuition about what consciousness is.[5] Max Velmans and Susan Schneider wrote in The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness: "Anything that we are aware of at a given moment forms part of our consciousness, making conscious experience at once the most familiar and most mysterious aspect of our lives."[44]

Related terms, also often used in vague or ambiguous ways, are:

  • Awareness: the state or ability to perceive, to feel, or to be conscious of events, objects, or sensory patterns. In this level of consciousness, sense data can be confirmed by an observer without necessarily implying understanding. More broadly, it is the state or quality of being aware of something. In biological psychology, awareness is defined as a human's or an animal's perception and cognitive reaction to a condition or event.
  • Self-awareness: the capacity for introspection and the ability to reconcile oneself as an individual separate from the environment and other individuals.
  • Self-consciousness: an acute sense of self-awareness. It is a preoccupation with oneself, as opposed to the philosophical state of self-awareness, which is the awareness that one exists as an individual being; although some writers use both terms interchangeably or synonymously.[45]
  • Sentience: the ability to be aware (feel, perceive, or be conscious) of one's surroundings or to have subjective experiences. Sentience is a minimalistic way of defining consciousness, which is otherwise commonly used to collectively describe sentience plus other characteristics of the mind.
  • Sapience: often defined as wisdom, or the ability of an organism or entity to act with appropriate judgment, a mental faculty which is a component of intelligence or alternatively may be considered an additional faculty, apart from intelligence, with its own properties.
  • Qualia: individual instances of subjective, conscious experience.

Sentience (the ability to feel, perceive, or to experience subjectivity) is not the same as self-awareness (being aware of oneself as an individual). The mirror test is sometimes considered to be an operational test for self-awareness, and the handful of animals that have passed it are often considered to be self-aware.[46][47] It remains debatable whether recognition of one's mirror image can be properly construed to imply full self-awareness,[48] particularly given that robots are being constructed which appear to pass the test.[49][50]

Much has been learned in neuroscience about correlations between brain activity and subjective, conscious experiences, and many suggest that neuroscience will ultimately explain consciousness; "...consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells...".[51] However, this view has been criticized because consciousness has yet to be shown to be a process,[52] and the so-called "hard problem" of relating consciousness directly to brain activity remains elusive.[53]

Scientific approaches edit

Since Descartes's proposal of dualism, it became a general consensus that the mind had become a matter of philosophy and that science was not able to penetrate the issue of consciousness – that consciousness was outside of space and time. However, in recent decades many scholars have begun to move toward a science of consciousness. Antonio Damasio and Gerald Edelman are two neuroscientists who have led the move to neural correlates of the self and of consciousness. Damasio has demonstrated that emotions and their biological foundation play a critical role in high level cognition,[54][55] and Edelman has created a framework for analyzing consciousness through a scientific outlook. The current problem consciousness researchers face involves explaining how and why consciousness arises from neural computation.[56][57] In his research on this problem, Edelman has developed a theory of consciousness, in which he has coined the terms primary consciousness and secondary consciousness.[58][59]

Eugene Linden, author of The Parrot's Lament suggests there are many examples of animal behavior and intelligence that surpass what people would suppose to be the boundary of animal consciousness. Linden contends that in many of these documented examples, a variety of animal species exhibit behavior that can only be attributed to emotion, and to a level of consciousness that we would normally ascribe only to our own species.[60]

Philosopher Daniel Dennett counters that:

Consciousness requires a certain kind of informational organization that does not seem to be 'hard-wired' in humans, but is instilled by human culture. Moreover, consciousness is not a black-or-white, all-or-nothing type of phenomenon, as is often assumed. The differences between humans and other species are so great that speculations about animal consciousness seem ungrounded. Many authors simply assume that an animal like a bat has a point of view, but there seems to be little interest in exploring the details involved.[61]

Consciousness in mammals (including humans) is an aspect of the mind generally thought to comprise qualities such as subjectivity, sentience, and the ability to perceive the relationship between oneself and one's environment. It is a subject of much research in philosophy of mind, psychology, neuroscience, and cognitive science. Some philosophers divide consciousness into phenomenal consciousness, which is subjective experience itself, and access consciousness, which refers to the global availability of information to processing systems in the brain.[62] Phenomenal consciousness has many different experienced qualities, often referred to as qualia. Phenomenal consciousness is usually consciousness of something or about something, a property known as intentionality in philosophy of mind.[62]

In humans, there are three common methods of studying consciousness, i.e. verbal report, behavioural demonstrations, and neural correlation with conscious activity. Unfortunately these can only be generalized to non-human taxa with varying degrees of difficulty.[63] While animals cannot speak their minds, a new study employed a very unique way that enabled neuroscientists to separate conscious awareness from non-conscious perception in animals.[64] In this study conducted in rhesus monkeys, Ben-Haim and his team used a process dissociation approach that predicted opposite behavioral outcomes towards the two modes of perception. They found that monkeys displayed the very same opposite behavioral outcomes as did humans when they were aware vs. unaware of the stimuli presented.

Mirror test edit

 
Elephants can recognize themselves in a mirror.[65]
External videos
  Self-recognition in apes
National Geographic

The sense in which animals (or human infants) can be said to have consciousness or a self-concept has been hotly debated; it is often referred to as the debate over animal minds. The best known research technique in this area is the mirror test devised by Gordon G. Gallup, in which the skin of an animal (or human infant) is marked, while they are asleep or sedated, with a mark that cannot be seen directly but is visible in a mirror. The animal is then allowed to see their reflection in a mirror; if the animal spontaneously directs grooming behaviour towards the mark, that is taken as an indication that they are aware of themself.[66][67] Over the past 30 years, many studies have found evidence that animals recognise themselves in mirrors. Self-awareness by this criterion has been reported for:

Until recently it was thought that self-recognition was absent from animals without a neocortex, and was restricted to mammals with large brains and well developed social cognition. However, in 2008 a study of self-recognition in corvids reported significant results for magpies. Mammals and birds inherited the same brain components from their last common ancestor nearly 300 million years ago, and have since independently evolved and formed significantly different brain types. The results of the mirror and mark tests showed that neocortex-less magpies are capable of understanding that a mirror image belongs to their own body. The findings show that magpies respond in the mirror and mark test in a manner similar to apes, dolphins and elephants. This is a remarkable capability that, although not fully concrete in its determination of self-recognition, is at least a prerequisite of self-recognition. This is not only of interest regarding the convergent evolution of social intelligence; it is also valuable for an understanding of the general principles that govern cognitive evolution and their underlying neural mechanisms. The magpies were chosen to study based on their empathy/lifestyle, a possible precursor for their ability of self-awareness.[67] However even in the chimpanzee, the species most studied and with the most convincing findings, clear-cut evidence of self-recognition is not obtained in all individuals tested. Occurrence is about 75% in young adults and considerably less in young and old individuals.[76] For monkeys, non-primate mammals, and in a number of bird species, exploration of the mirror and social displays were observed. However, hints at mirror-induced self-directed behavior have been obtained.[77]

According to a 2019 study, cleaner wrasses have become the first fish ever observed to pass the mirror test.[78] However, the test's inventor Gordon Gallup has said that the fish were most likely trying to scrape off a perceived parasite on another fish and that they did not demonstrate self-recognition. The authors of the study retorted that because the fish checked themselves in the mirror before and after the scraping, this meant that the fish had self-awareness and recognized that their reflections belonged to their own bodies.[79][80][81]

The mirror test has attracted controversy among some researchers because it is entirely focused on vision, the primary sense in humans, while other species rely more heavily on other senses such as the olfactory sense in dogs.[82][83][84] A study in 2015 showed that the "sniff test of self-recognition (STSR)" provides evidence of self-awareness in dogs.[84]

Language edit

External videos
  Whale song – Oceania Project
  This is Einstein! – Knoxville Zoo

Another approach to determine whether a non-human animal is conscious derives from passive speech research with a macaw (see Arielle). Some researchers propose that by passively listening to an animal's voluntary speech, it is possible to learn about the thoughts of another creature and to determine that the speaker is conscious. This type of research was originally used to investigate a child's crib speech by Weir (1962) and in investigations of early speech in children by Greenfield and others (1976).

Zipf's law might be able to be used to indicate if a given dataset of animal communication indicate an intelligent natural language. Some researchers have used this algorithm to study bottlenose dolphin language.[85]

Pain or suffering edit

Further arguments revolve around the ability of animals to feel pain or suffering. Suffering implies consciousness. If animals can be shown to suffer in a way similar or identical to humans, many of the arguments against human suffering could then, presumably, be extended to animals. Others have argued that pain can be demonstrated by adverse reactions to negative stimuli that are non-purposeful or even maladaptive.[86] One such reaction is transmarginal inhibition, a phenomenon observed in humans and some animals akin to mental breakdown.

Carl Sagan, the American cosmologist, points to reasons why humans have had a tendency to deny animals can suffer:

Humans – who enslave, castrate, experiment on, and fillet other animals – have had an understandable penchant for pretending animals do not feel pain. A sharp distinction between humans and 'animals' is essential if we are to bend them to our will, make them work for us, wear them, eat them – without any disquieting tinges of guilt or regret. It is unseemly of us, who often behave so unfeelingly toward other animals, to contend that only humans can suffer. The behavior of other animals renders such pretensions specious. They are just too much like us.[87]

John Webster, a professor of animal husbandry at Bristol, argues:

People have assumed that intelligence is linked to the ability to suffer and that because animals have smaller brains they suffer less than humans. That is a pathetic piece of logic, sentient animals have the capacity to experience pleasure and are motivated to seek it, you only have to watch how cows and lambs both seek and enjoy pleasure when they lie with their heads raised to the sun on a perfect English summer's day. Just like humans.[88]

However, there is no agreement where the line should be drawn between organisms that can feel pain and those that cannot. Justin Leiber, a philosophy professor at Oxford University writes that:

Montaigne is ecumenical in this respect, claiming consciousness for spiders and ants, and even writing of our duties to trees and plants. Singer and Clarke agree in denying consciousness to sponges. Singer locates the distinction somewhere between the shrimp and the oyster. He, with rather considerable convenience for one who is thundering hard accusations at others, slides by the case of insects and spiders and bacteria, they pace Montaigne, apparently and rather conveniently do not feel pain. The intrepid Midgley, on the other hand, seems willing to speculate about the subjective experience of tapeworms ...Nagel ... appears to draw the line at flounders and wasps, though more recently he speaks of the inner life of cockroaches.[89]

There are also some who reject the argument entirely, arguing that although suffering animals feel anguish, a suffering plant also struggles to stay alive (albeit in a less visible way). In fact, no living organism 'wants' to die for another organism's sustenance. In an article written for The New York Times, Carol Kaesuk Yoon argues that:

When a plant is wounded, its body immediately kicks into protection mode. It releases a bouquet of volatile chemicals, which in some cases have been shown to induce neighboring plants to pre-emptively step up their own chemical defenses and in other cases to lure in predators of the beasts that may be causing the damage to the plants. Inside the plant, repair systems are engaged and defenses are mounted, the molecular details of which scientists are still working out, but which involve signaling molecules coursing through the body to rally the cellular troops, even the enlisting of the genome itself, which begins churning out defense-related proteins ... If you think about it, though, why would we expect any organism to lie down and die for our dinner? Organisms have evolved to do everything in their power to avoid being extinguished. How long would any lineage be likely to last if its members effectively didn't care if you killed them?[90]

Cognitive bias and emotion edit

 
Is the glass half empty or half full?

Cognitive bias in animals is a pattern of deviation in judgment, whereby inferences about other animals and situations may be drawn in an illogical fashion.[91] Individuals create their own "subjective social reality" from their perception of the input.[92] It refers to the question "Is the glass half empty or half full?", used as an indicator of optimism or pessimism. Cognitive biases have been shown in a wide range of species including rats, dogs, rhesus macaques, sheep, chicks, starlings and honeybees.[93][94][95]

The neuroscientist Joseph LeDoux advocates avoiding terms derived from human subjective experience when discussing brain functions in animals.[96] For example, the common practice of calling brain circuits that detect and respond to threats "fear circuits" implies that these circuits are responsible for feelings of fear. LeDoux argues that Pavlovian fear conditioning should be renamed Pavlovian threat conditioning to avoid the implication that "fear" is being acquired in rats or humans.[97] Key to his theoretical change is the notion of survival functions mediated by survival circuits, the purpose of which is to keep organisms alive rather than to make emotions. For example, defensive survival circuits exist to detect and respond to threats. While all organisms can do this, only organisms that can be conscious of their own brain's activities can feel fear. Fear is a conscious experience and occurs the same way as any other kind of conscious experience: via cortical circuits that allow attention to certain forms of brain activity. LeDoux argues the only differences between an emotional and non-emotion state of consciousness are the underlying neural ingredients that contribute to the state.[98][99]

Neuroscience edit

 
Drawing by Santiago Ramón y Cajal (1899) of neurons in the pigeon cerebellum

Neuroscience is the scientific study of the nervous system.[100] It is a highly active interdisciplinary science that collaborates with many other fields. The scope of neuroscience has broadened recently to include molecular, cellular, developmental, structural, functional, evolutionary, computational, and medical aspects of the nervous system. Theoretical studies of neural networks are being complemented with techniques for imaging sensory and motor tasks in the brain. According to a 2008 paper, neuroscience explanations of psychological phenomena currently have a "seductive allure", and "seem to generate more public interest" than explanations which do not contain neuroscientific information.[101] They found that subjects who were not neuroscience experts "judged that explanations with logically irrelevant neuroscience information were more satisfying than explanations without.[101]

Neural correlates edit

The neural correlates of consciousness constitute the minimal set of neuronal events and mechanisms sufficient for a specific conscious percept.[102] Neuroscientists use empirical approaches to discover neural correlates of subjective phenomena.[103] The set should be minimal because, if the brain is sufficient to give rise to any given conscious experience, the question is which of its components is necessary to produce it.

Visual sense and representation was reviewed in 1998 by Francis Crick and Christof Koch. They concluded sensory neuroscience can be used as a bottom-up approach to studying consciousness, and suggested experiments to test various hypotheses in this research stream.[104]

A feature that distinguishes humans from most animals is that we are not born with an extensive repertoire of behavioral programs that would enable us to survive on our own ("physiological prematurity"). To compensate for this, we have an unmatched ability to learn, i.e., to consciously acquire such programs by imitation or exploration. Once consciously acquired and sufficiently exercised, these programs can become automated to the extent that their execution happens beyond the realms of our awareness. Take, as an example, the incredible fine motor skills exerted in playing a Beethoven piano sonata or the sensorimotor coordination required to ride a motorcycle along a curvy mountain road. Such complex behaviors are possible only because a sufficient number of the subprograms involved can be executed with minimal or even suspended conscious control. In fact, the conscious system may actually interfere somewhat with these automated programs.[105]

The growing ability of neuroscientists to manipulate neurons using methods from molecular biology in combination with optical tools depends on the simultaneous development of appropriate behavioural assays and model organisms amenable to large-scale genomic analysis and manipulation.[106] A combination of such fine-grained neuronal analysis in animals with ever more sensitive psychophysical and brain imaging techniques in humans, complemented by the development of a robust theoretical predictive framework, will hopefully lead to a rational understanding of consciousness.

Neocortex edit

 
Previously researchers had thought that patterns of neural sleep exhibited by zebra finches needed a mammalian neocortex.[1]

The neocortex is a part of the brain of mammals. It consists of the grey matter, or neuronal cell bodies and unmyelinated fibers, surrounding the deeper white matter (myelinated axons) in the cerebrum. The neocortex is smooth in rodents and other small mammals, whereas in primates and other larger mammals it has deep grooves and wrinkles. These folds increase the surface area of the neocortex considerably without taking up too much more volume. Also, neurons within the same wrinkle have more opportunity for connectivity, while neurons in different wrinkles have less opportunity for connectivity, leading to compartmentalization of the cortex. The neocortex is divided into frontal, parietal, occipital, and temporal lobes, which perform different functions. For example, the occipital lobe contains the primary visual cortex, and the temporal lobe contains the primary auditory cortex. Further subdivisions or areas of neocortex are responsible for more specific cognitive processes. The neocortex is the newest part of the cerebral cortex to evolve (hence the prefix "neo"); the other parts of the cerebral cortex are the paleocortex and archicortex, collectively known as the allocortex. In humans, 90% of the cerebral cortex is neocortex.

Researchers have argued that consciousness in mammals arises in the neocortex, and therefore cannot arise in animals which lack a neocortex. For example, Rose argued in 2002 that the "fishes have nervous systems that mediate effective escape and avoidance responses to noxious stimuli, but, these responses must occur without a concurrent, human-like awareness of pain, suffering or distress, which depend on separately evolved neocortex."[107] Recently that view has been challenged, and many researchers now believe that animal consciousness can arise from homologous subcortical brain networks.[1]

Attention edit

Attention is the cognitive process of selectively concentrating on one aspect of the environment while ignoring other things. Attention has also been referred to as the allocation of processing resources.[108] Attention also has variations amongst cultures. Voluntary attention develops in specific cultural and institutional contexts through engagement in cultural activities with more competent community members.[109]

Most experiments show that one neural correlate of attention is enhanced firing. If a neuron has a certain response to a stimulus when the animal is not attending to the stimulus, then when the animal does attend to the stimulus, the neuron's response will be enhanced even if the physical characteristics of the stimulus remain the same. In many cases attention produces changes in the EEG. Many animals, including humans, produce gamma waves (40–60 Hz) when focusing attention on a particular object or activity.[110]

Extended consciousness edit

Extended consciousness is an animal's autobiographical self-perception. It is thought to arise in the brains of animals which have a substantial capacity for memory and reason. It does not necessarily require language. The perception of a historic and future self arises from a stream of information from the immediate environment and from neural structures related to memory. The concept was popularised by Antonio Damasio and is used in biological psychology. Extended consciousness is said to arise in structures in the human brain described as image spaces and dispositional spaces. Image spaces imply areas where sensory impressions of all types are processed, including the focused awareness of the core consciousness. Dispositional spaces include convergence zones, which are networks in the brain where memories are processed and recalled, and where knowledge is merged with immediate experience.[111][112]

Metacognition edit

Metacognition is defined as "cognition about cognition", or "knowing about knowing."[113] It can take many forms; it includes knowledge about when and how to use particular strategies for learning or for problem solving.[113] It has been suggested that metacognition in some animals provides evidence for cognitive self-awareness.[114] There are generally two components of metacognition: knowledge about cognition, and regulation of cognition.[115] Writings on metacognition can be traced back at least as far as De Anima and the Parva Naturalia of the Greek philosopher Aristotle.[116] Metacognologists believe that the ability to consciously think about thinking is unique to sapient species and indeed is one of the definitions of sapience.[citation needed] There is evidence that rhesus monkeys and apes can make accurate judgments about the strengths of their memories of fact and monitor their own uncertainty,[117] while attempts to demonstrate metacognition in birds have been inconclusive.[118] A 2007 study provided some evidence for metacognition in rats,[119][120][121] but further analysis suggested that they may have been following simple operant conditioning principles,[122] or a behavioral economic model.[123]

Mirror neurons edit

Mirror neurons are neurons that fire both when an animal acts and when the animal observes the same action performed by another.[124][125][126] Thus, the neuron "mirrors" the behavior of the other, as though the observer were themself acting. Such neurons have been directly observed in primate and other species including birds. The function of the mirror system is a subject of much speculation. Many researchers in cognitive neuroscience and cognitive psychology consider that this system provides the physiological mechanism for the perception action coupling (see the common coding theory).[126] They argue that mirror neurons may be important for understanding the actions of other people, and for learning new skills by imitation. Some researchers also speculate that mirror systems may simulate observed actions, and thus contribute to theory of mind skills,[127][128] while others relate mirror neurons to language abilities.[129] Neuroscientists such as Marco Iacoboni (UCLA) have argued that mirror neuron systems in the human brain help us understand the actions and intentions of other people. In a study published in March 2005 Iacoboni and his colleagues reported that mirror neurons could discern if another person who was picking up a cup of tea planned to drink from it or clear it from the table. In addition, Iacoboni and a number of other researchers have argued that mirror neurons are the neural basis of the human capacity for emotions such as empathy.[126][130] Vilayanur S. Ramachandran has speculated that mirror neurons may provide the neurological basis of self-awareness.[131][132]

Evolutionary psychology edit

Consciousness is likely an evolved adaptation since it meets George Williams' criteria of species universality, complexity,[133] and functionality, and it is a trait that apparently increases fitness.[134] Opinions are divided as to where in biological evolution consciousness emerged and about whether or not consciousness has survival value. It has been argued that consciousness emerged (i) exclusively with the first humans, (ii) exclusively with the first mammals, (iii) independently in mammals and birds, or (iv) with the first reptiles.[135] Donald Griffin suggests in his book Animal Minds a gradual evolution of consciousness.[11] Each of these scenarios raises the question of the possible survival value of consciousness.

In his paper "Evolution of consciousness," John Eccles argues that special anatomical and physical adaptations of the mammalian cerebral cortex gave rise to consciousness.[136] In contrast, others have argued that the recursive circuitry underwriting consciousness is much more primitive, having evolved initially in pre-mammalian species because it improves the capacity for interaction with both social and natural environments by providing an energy-saving "neutral" gear in an otherwise energy-expensive motor output machine.[137] Once in place, this recursive circuitry may well have provided a basis for the subsequent development of many of the functions that consciousness facilitates in higher organisms, as outlined by Bernard J. Baars.[138] Richard Dawkins suggested that humans evolved consciousness in order to make themselves the subjects of thought.[139] Daniel Povinelli suggests that large, tree-climbing apes evolved consciousness to take into account one's own mass when moving safely among tree branches.[139] Consistent with this hypothesis, Gordon Gallup found that chimpanzees and orangutans, but not little monkeys or terrestrial gorillas, demonstrated self-awareness in mirror tests.[139]

The concept of consciousness can refer to voluntary action, awareness, or wakefulness. However, even voluntary behaviour involves unconscious mechanisms. Many cognitive processes take place in the cognitive unconscious, unavailable to conscious awareness. Some behaviours are conscious when learned but then become unconscious, seemingly automatic. Learning, especially implicitly learning a skill, can take place outside of consciousness. For example, plenty of people know how to turn right when they ride a bike, but very few can accurately explain how they actually do so.[139]

Neural Darwinism edit

Neural Darwinism is a large scale theory of brain function initially proposed in 1978 by the American biologist Gerald Edelman.[140] Edelman distinguishes between what he calls primary and secondary consciousness:

  • Primary consciousness: is the ability, found in humans and some animals, to integrate observed events with memory to create an awareness of the present and immediate past of the world around them. This form of consciousness is also sometimes called "sensory consciousness". Put another way, primary consciousness is the presence of various subjective sensory contents of consciousness such as sensations, perceptions, and mental images. For example, primary consciousness includes a person's experience of the blueness of the ocean, a bird's song, and the feeling of pain. Thus, primary consciousness refers to being mentally aware of things in the world in the present without any sense of past and future; it is composed of mental images bound to a time around the measurable present.[141]
  • Secondary consciousness: is an individual's accessibility to their history and plans. The concept is also loosely and commonly associated with having awareness of one's own consciousness. The ability allows its possessors to go beyond the limits of the remembered present of primary consciousness.[58]

Primary consciousness can be defined as simple awareness that includes perception and emotion. As such, it is ascribed to most animals. By contrast, secondary consciousness depends on and includes such features as self-reflective awareness, abstract thinking, volition and metacognition.[58][142]

Edelman's theory focuses on two nervous system organizations: the brainstem and limbic systems on one side and the thalamus and cerebral cortex on the other side. The brain stem and limbic system take care of essential body functioning and survival, while the thalamocortical system receives signals from sensory receptors and sends out signals to voluntary muscles such as those of the arms and legs. The theory asserts that the connection of these two systems during evolution helped animals learn adaptive behaviors.[141]

Other scientists have argued against Edelman's theory, instead suggesting that primary consciousness might have emerged with the basic vegetative systems of the brain. That is, the evolutionary origin might have come from sensations and primal emotions arising from sensors and receptors, both internal and surface, signaling that the well-being of the creature was immediately threatened—for example, hunger for air, thirst, hunger, pain, and extreme temperature change. This is based on neurological data showing the thalamic, hippocampal, orbitofrontal, insula, and midbrain sites are the key to consciousness of thirst.[143] These scientists also point out that the cortex might not be as important to primary consciousness as some neuroscientists have believed.[143] Evidence of this lies in the fact that studies show that systematically disabling parts of the cortex in animals does not remove consciousness. Another study found that children born without a cortex are conscious. Instead of cortical mechanisms, these scientists emphasize brainstem mechanisms as essential to consciousness.[143] Still, these scientists concede that higher order consciousness does involve the cortex and complex communication between different areas of the brain.

While animals with primary consciousness have long-term memory, they lack explicit narrative, and, at best, can only deal with the immediate scene in the remembered present. While they still have an advantage over animals lacking such ability, evolution has brought forth a growing complexity in consciousness, particularly in mammals. Animals with this complexity are said to have secondary consciousness. Secondary consciousness is seen in animals with semantic capabilities, such as the four great apes. It is present in its richest form in the human species, which is unique in possessing complex language made up of syntax and semantics. In considering how the neural mechanisms underlying primary consciousness arose and were maintained during evolution, it is proposed that at some time around the divergence of reptiles into mammals and then into birds, the embryological development of large numbers of new reciprocal connections allowed rich re-entrant activity to take place between the more posterior brain systems carrying out perceptual categorization and the more frontally located systems responsible for value-category memory.[58] The ability of an animal to relate a present complex scene to their own previous history of learning conferred an adaptive evolutionary advantage. At much later evolutionary epochs, further re-entrant circuits appeared that linked semantic and linguistic performance to categorical and conceptual memory systems. This development enabled the emergence of secondary consciousness.[144][145]

Ursula Voss of the Universität Bonn believes that the theory of protoconsciousness[146] may serve as adequate explanation for self-recognition found in birds, as they would develop secondary consciousness during REM sleep.[147] She added that many types of birds have very sophisticated language systems. Don Kuiken of the University of Alberta finds such research interesting as well as if we continue to study consciousness with animal models (with differing types of consciousness), we would be able to separate the different forms of reflectiveness found in today's world.[148]

For the advocates of the idea of a secondary consciousness, self-recognition serves as a critical component and a key defining measure. What is most interesting then, is the evolutionary appeal that arises with the concept of self-recognition. In non-human species and in children, the mirror test (see above) has been used as an indicator of self-awareness.

Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness edit

Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness

The absence of a neocortex does not appear to preclude an organism from experiencing affective states. Convergent evidence indicates that non-human animals have the neuroanatomical, neurochemical, and neurophysiological substrates of conscious states along with the capacity to exhibit intentional behaviors. Consequently, the weight of evidence indicates that humans are not unique in possessing the neurological substrates that generate consciousness. Non-human animals, including all mammals and birds, and many other creatures, including octopuses, also possess these neurological substrates.[149]

In 2012, a group of neuroscientists attending a conference on "Consciousness in Human and non-Human Animals" at the University of Cambridge in the UK, signed the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness (see box on the right).[1][150]

In the accompanying text they "unequivocally" asserted:[1]

  • "The field of Consciousness research is rapidly evolving. Abundant new techniques and strategies for human and non-human animal research have been developed. Consequently, more data is becoming readily available, and this calls for a periodic reevaluation of previously held preconceptions in this field. Studies of non-human animals have shown that homologous brain circuits correlated with conscious experience and perception can be selectively facilitated and disrupted to assess whether they are in fact necessary for those experiences. Moreover, in humans, new non-invasive techniques are readily available to survey the correlates of consciousness."[1]
  • "The neural substrates of emotions do not appear to be confined to cortical structures. In fact, subcortical neural networks aroused during affective states in humans are also critically important for generating emotional behaviors in animals. Artificial arousal of the same brain regions generates corresponding behavior and feeling states in both humans and non-human animals. Wherever in the brain one evokes instinctual emotional behaviors in non-human animals, many of the ensuing behaviors are consistent with experienced feeling states, including those internal states that are rewarding and punishing. Deep brain stimulation of these systems in humans can also generate similar affective states. Systems associated with affect are concentrated in subcortical regions where neural homologies abound. Young human and non-human animals without neocortices retain these brain-mind functions. Furthermore, neural circuits supporting behavioral/electrophysiological states of attentiveness, sleep and decision making appear to have arisen in evolution as early as the invertebrate radiation, being evident in insects and cephalopod mollusks (e.g., octopus)."[1]
  • "Birds appear to offer, in their behavior, neurophysiology, and neuroanatomy a striking case of parallel evolution of consciousness. Evidence of near human-like levels of consciousness has been most dramatically observed in grey parrots. Mammalian and avian emotional networks and cognitive microcircuitries appear to be far more homologous than previously thought. Moreover, certain species of birds have been found to exhibit neural sleep patterns similar to those of mammals, including REM sleep and, as was demonstrated in zebra finches, neurophysiological patterns previously thought to require a mammalian neocortex. Magpies in particular have been shown to exhibit striking similarities to humans, great apes, dolphins, and elephants in studies of mirror self-recognition."[1]
  • "In humans, the effect of certain hallucinogens appears to be associated with a disruption in cortical feedforward and feedback processing. Pharmacological interventions in non-human animals with compounds known to affect conscious behavior in humans can lead to similar perturbations in behavior in non-human animals. In humans, there is evidence to suggest that awareness is correlated with cortical activity, which does not exclude possible contributions by subcortical or early cortical processing, as in visual awareness. Evidence that human and non-human animal emotional feelings arise from homologous subcortical brain networks provide compelling evidence for evolutionarily shared primal affective qualia."[1]

Examples edit

 
Theories of brain evolution in animals. The old scala naturae model versus the modern approach.

A common image is the scala naturae, the ladder of nature on which animals of different species occupy successively higher rungs, with humans typically at the top.[151] A more useful approach has been to recognize that different animals may have different kinds of cognitive processes, which are better understood in terms of the ways in which they are cognitively adapted to their different ecological niches, than by positing any kind of hierarchy.[152][153]

Mammals edit

Dogs edit

Dogs were previously listed as non-self-aware animals. Traditionally, self-consciousness was evaluated via the mirror test. But dogs, and many other animals, are not (as) visually oriented.[154][155] A 2015 study claims that the "sniff test of self-recognition" (STSR) provides significant evidence of self-awareness in dogs, and could play a crucial role in showing that this capacity is not a specific feature of only great apes, humans and a few other animals, but it depends on the way in which researchers try to verify it. According to the biologist Roberto Cazzolla Gatti (who published the study), "the innovative approach to test the self-awareness with a smell test highlights the need to shift the paradigm of the anthropocentric idea of consciousness to a species-specific perspective".[84][156] This study has been confirmed by another study.[157]

Birds edit

Grey parrots edit

Research with captive grey parrots, especially Irene Pepperberg's work with an individual named Alex, has demonstrated they possess the ability to associate simple human words with meanings, and to intelligently apply the abstract concepts of shape, colour, number, zero-sense, etc. According to Pepperberg and other scientists, they perform many cognitive tasks at the level of dolphins, chimpanzees, and even human toddlers.[158] Another notable African grey is N'kisi, which in 2004 was said to have a vocabulary of over 950 words which she used in creative ways.[159] For example, when Jane Goodall visited N'kisi in his New York home, he greeted her with "Got a chimp?" because he had seen pictures of her with chimpanzees in Africa.[160]

In 2011, research led by Dalila Bovet of Paris West University Nanterre La Défense, demonstrated grey parrots were able to coordinate and collaborate with each other to an extent. They were able to solve problems such as two birds having to pull strings at the same time to obtain food. In another example, one bird stood on a perch to release a food-laden tray, while the other pulled the tray out from the test apparatus. Both would then feed. The birds were observed waiting for their partners to perform the necessary actions so their behaviour could be synchronized. The parrots appeared to express individual preferences as to which of the other test birds they would work with.[161]

Corvids edit

 
The Eurasian magpie passes the mirror test.

It was recently thought that self-recognition was restricted to mammals with large brains and highly evolved social cognition, but absent from animals without a neocortex. However, in 2008, an investigation of self-recognition in corvids was conducted revealing the ability of self-recognition in the magpie. Mammals and birds inherited the same brain components from their last common ancestor nearly 300 million years ago, and have since independently evolved and formed significantly different brain types. The results of the mirror test showed that although magpies do not have a neocortex, they are capable of understanding that a mirror image belongs to their own body. The findings show that magpies respond in the mirror test in a manner similar to apes, dolphins, killer whales, pigs and elephants. This is a remarkable capability that, although not fully concrete in its determination of self-recognition, is at least a prerequisite of self-recognition. This is not only of interest regarding the convergent evolution of social intelligence, it is also valuable for an understanding of the general principles that govern cognitive evolution and their underlying neural mechanisms. The magpies were chosen to study based on their empathy/lifestyle, a possible precursor for their ability of self-awareness.[67]

A 2020 study found that carrion crows show a neuronal response that correlates with their perception of a stimulus, which they argue to be an empirical marker of (avian) sensory consciousness – the conscious perception of sensory input – in the crows which do not have a cerebral cortex. The study thereby substantiates the theory that conscious perception does not require a cerebral cortex and that the basic foundations for it – and possibly for human-type consciousness – may have evolved before the last common ancestor >320 Mya or independently in birds.[162][163] A related study showed that the birds' pallium's neuroarchitecture is reminiscent of the mammalian cortex.[164]

Invertebrates edit

 
Octopus travelling with shells collected for protection

Octopuses are highly intelligent, possibly more so than any other order of invertebrates. The level of their intelligence and learning capability are debated,[165][166][167][168] but maze and problem-solving studies show they have both short- and long-term memory. Octopus have a highly complex nervous system, only part of which is localized in their brain. Two-thirds of an octopus's neurons are found in the nerve cords of their arms. Octopus arms show a variety of complex reflex actions that persist even when they have no input from the brain.[169] Unlike vertebrates, the complex motor skills of octopuses are not organized in their brain using an internal somatotopic map of their body, instead using a non-somatotopic system unique to large-brained invertebrates.[170] Some octopuses, such as the mimic octopus, move their arms in ways that emulate the shape and movements of other sea creatures.

In laboratory studies, octopuses can easily be trained to distinguish between different shapes and patterns. They reportedly use observational learning,[171] although the validity of these findings is contested.[165][166] Octopuses have also been observed to play: repeatedly releasing bottles or toys into a circular current in their aquariums and then catching them.[172] Octopuses often escape from their aquarium and sometimes enter others. They have boarded fishing boats and opened holds to eat crabs.[167] At least four specimens of the veined octopus (Amphioctopus marginatus) have been witnessed retrieving discarded coconut shells, manipulating them, and then reassembling them to use as shelter.[173][174]

Shamanistic and religious views edit

Shamanistic and other traditional cultures and folk tales speak of animal spirits and the consciousness of animals.[175][176] In India, Jains consider all the jivas (living organisms including plants, animals and insects) as conscious. According to Jain scriptures, even nigoda (microscopic creatures) possess high levels of consciousness and have decision-making abilities.[citation needed]

Researchers edit

Some contributors to relevant research on animal consciousness include:

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i 7 July 2012. Written by Philip Low and edited by Jaak Panksepp, Diana Reiss, David Edelman, Bruno Van Swinderen, Philip Low and Christof Koch. University of Cambridge.
  2. ^ "consciousness". Merriam-Webster. Retrieved 22 April 2014.
  3. ^ a b Robert van Gulick (2004). "Consciousness". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  4. ^ a b Farthing G (1992). The Psychology of Consciousness. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-728668-3.
  5. ^ a b John Searle (2005). "Consciousness". In Honderich T (ed.). The Oxford companion to philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
  6. ^ Colin Allen (6 February 2024). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Animal consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition).
  7. ^ Peter Carruthers (1999). "Sympathy and subjectivity". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 77 (4): 465–482. doi:10.1080/00048409912349231. S2CID 49227874.
  8. ^ Miller, Michael R. (2013). "Descartes on Animals Revisited". Journal of Philosophical Research. 38: 89–114. doi:10.5840/jpr2013386.
  9. ^ Thomas Nagel (1991). "Ch. 12 What is it like to be a bat?". Mortal Questions. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-40676-5.
  10. ^ Douglas Hofstadter (1981). "Reflections on What Is It Like to Be a Bat?". In Douglas Hofstadter; Daniel Dennett (eds.). The Mind's I. Basic Books. pp. 403–414. ISBN 978-0-7108-0352-8.
  11. ^ a b Donald Griffin (2001). Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-30865-4.
  12. ^ a b Burghardt, Gordon M (1985). (PDF). American Psychologist. 40 (8): 905–919. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.40.8.905. PMID 3898938. Archived from the original (PDF) on 16 September 2012.
  13. ^ Carr, H (1927). "The interpretation of the animal mind". Psychological Review. 34 (2): 87–106 [94]. doi:10.1037/h0072244.
  14. ^ Andrews, K. (2014). The Animal Mind: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition. Taylor & Francis. p. 51. ISBN 978-1-317-67676-8.
  15. ^ Robert M. Young (1996). "The mind-body problem". In RC Olby; GN Cantor; JR Christie; MJS Hodges (eds.). Companion to the History of Modern Science (Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 ed.). Taylor and Francis. pp. 702–11. ISBN 978-0415145787.
  16. ^ Robinson, Howard (3 November 2011). "Dualism". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition).
  17. ^ Bryan S. Turner (2008). The Body and Society: Explorations in Social Theory (3rd ed.). Sage Publications. p. 78. ISBN 978-1412929875. ...a rejection of any dualism between mind and body, and a consequent insistence on the argument that the body is never simply a physical object but always an embodiment of consciousness.
  18. ^ Kim, Jaegwan (1995). "Emergent properties". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). Problems in the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 240. ISBN 9780198661320.
  19. ^ Pinel, J. (2009). Psychobiology (7th ed.). Pearson/Allyn and Bacon. ISBN 978-0205548927.
  20. ^ LeDoux, J. (2002). The Synaptic Self: How Our Brains Become Who We Are. Viking Penguin. ISBN 978-88-7078-795-5.
  21. ^ Russell, S.; Norvig, P. (2010). Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach (3rd ed.). Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0136042594.
  22. ^ Dawkins, R. (2006). The Selfish Gene (3rd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199291144.
  23. ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. "Epiphenomenalism". Retrieved 27 December 2016.
  24. ^ Huxley, T. H. (1874). "On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and its History", The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555-580. Reprinted in Method and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1898)
  25. ^ Gallagher, S. 2006. "Where's the action?: Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will". In W. Banks, S. Pockett, and S. Gallagher. Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? An Investigation of the Nature of Intuition (109-124). Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
  26. ^ T. H. Huxley (1874). "On the hypothesis that animals are automata, and its history". The Fortnightly Review. 16 (253): 555–580. Bibcode:1874Natur..10..362.. doi:10.1038/010362a0.
  27. ^ W. James (1879). "Are we automata?". Mind. 4 (13): 1–22. doi:10.1093/mind/os-4.13.1.
  28. ^ B. I. B. Lindahl (1997). "Consciousness and biological evolution". Journal of Theoretical Biology. 187 (4): 613–629. Bibcode:1997JThBi.187..613L. doi:10.1006/jtbi.1996.0394. PMID 9299304.
  29. ^ Karl R. Popper; John C. Eccles (1977). The Self and Its Brain. Springer International. ISBN 978-0-387-08307-0.
  30. ^ a b Rollin, Bernard. The Unheeded Cry: Animal Consciousness, Animal Pain, and Science. New York: Oxford University Press, 1989, pp. xii, 117-118, cited in Carbone 2004, p. 150.
  31. ^ Ricard, Matthieu (2016). A Plea for the Animals: The Moral, Philosophical, and Evolutionary Imperative to Treat All Beings with Compassion (First English ed.). Boulder: Shambhala. p. 132. ISBN 978-0-8348-4054-6. OCLC 960042213.
  32. ^ Griffin, DR; Speck, GB (2004). (PDF). Animal Cognition. 7 (1): 5–18. doi:10.1007/s10071-003-0203-x. PMID 14658059. S2CID 8650837. Archived from the original (PDF) on 21 January 2013. Retrieved 29 November 2013.
  33. ^ The Ethics of research involving animals 25 June 2008 at the Wayback Machine Nuffield Council on Bioethics, Accessed 27 February 2008
  34. ^ Allen, C (1998). . J. Anim. Sci. 76 (1): 42–7. doi:10.2527/1998.76142x. PMID 9464883. Archived from the original on 21 January 2016. Retrieved 5 October 2015.
  35. ^ Animal Sentience An Interdisciplinary Journal on Animal Feeling
  36. ^ Vimal, RLP; Sansthana, DA (2010). "On the Quest of Defining Consciousness" (PDF). Mind and Matter. 8 (1): 93–121.
  37. ^ Hirstein, W (2013). "Conscious states: Where are they in the brain and what are their necessary ingredients?"". Mens Sana Monographs. 11 (1): 230–8. doi:10.4103/0973-1229.109343. PMC 3653223. PMID 23678244.
  38. ^ Dulany, D. E. (2014). "What Explains Consciousness? Or... What Consciousness Explains?"". Mens Sana Monographs. 12 (1): 11–34. doi:10.4103/0973-1229.130283. PMC 4037891. PMID 24891796.
  39. ^ De Sousa, Avinash (2013). "Towards an integrative theory of consciousness: Part 1 (Neurobiological and cognitive models)"". Mens Sana Monographs. 11 (1): 100–50. doi:10.4103/0973-1229.109335. PMC 3653219. PMID 23678241.
  40. ^ Pereira, A Jr. (2013). "'A Commentary on De Sousa's "Towards An Integrative Theory of Consciousness"'". Mens Sana Monographs. 11 (1): 210–29. doi:10.4103/0973-1229.104495. PMC 3653222. PMID 23678243.
  41. ^ Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene.
  42. ^ Human Brain Function, by Richard Frackowiak and 7 other neuroscientists, page 269 in chapter 16 "The Neural Correlates of Consciousness" (consisting of 32 pages), published 2004
  43. ^ "consciousness". Merriam-Webster. Retrieved 4 June 2012.
  44. ^ Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (2008). "Introduction". In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.). The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Wiley. ISBN 978-0-470-75145-9.
  45. ^ Richard P. Lipka/Thomas M. Brinthaupt Self-perspectives Across the Life Span, p. 228, SUNY Press, 1992 ISBN 978-0-7914-1003-5
  46. ^ Gallup Jr GG; Anderson JR; Shillito DJ (2002). (PDF). In Bekoff M; Allen C; Burghardt GM (eds.). The cognitive animal: Empirical and Theoretical perspectives on animal cognition. University of Chicago Press. pp. 325–333. Archived from the original (PDF) on 6 October 2014.
  47. ^ Haikonen POA (2007) "Reflections of consciousness: The mirror test" Proceedings of the 2007 AAAI Fall Symposium on Consciousness, pp. 67–71.
  48. ^ Asendorpf, J. B.; Warkentin, V.; Baudonniere, P.-M. (1996). "Self-Awareness and Other Awareness II: Mirror Self-Recognition, Social Contingency Awareness, and Synchronic Imitation". Developmental Psychology. 32 (2): 313–321. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.32.2.313. S2CID 21762291.
  49. ^ The World First Self-Aware Robot and the Success of Mirror Image Cognition 3 February 2009 at the Wayback Machine (Lecture at the Karlsruhe University and the Munich University, Germany), 8 November 2006.
  50. ^ Moreno, Raúl Arrabales (8 January 2008). . Conscious Robots. Archived from the original on 5 January 2013.
  51. ^ Eric R. Kandel (2007). In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. WW Norton. p. 9. ISBN 978-0393329377.
  52. ^ Oswald Hanfling (2002). Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life. Psychology Press. pp. 108–109. ISBN 978-0415256452.
  53. ^ A term attributed to David Chalmers by Eugene O Mills (1999). "Giving up on the hard problem of consciousness". In Jonathan Shear (ed.). Explaining Consciousness: The Hard Problem. MIT Press. p. 109. ISBN 978-0262692212.
  54. ^ Damasio, A. (1999). The Feeling of What Happens: Body, Emotion and the Making of Consciousness. Harcourt Brace, 1999.
  55. ^ Damasio, A. (2003). Feelings of emotion and the self. In J. LeDoux, J. Debiec & H. Moss (Eds.), Self: from Soul to Brain (Vol. 1001, pp. 253-261). New York: New York Acad Sciences.
  56. ^ Chalmers D J, Facing up to the problem of consciousness, J Cons Stud, 2 (1995) 200.
  57. ^ Chalmers D J, The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory (Oxford University Press, New York) 1996.
  58. ^ a b c d Edelman, G. M. (2003). "Naturalizing consciousness: a theoretical framework". Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 100 (9): 5520–5524. Bibcode:2003PNAS..100.5520E. doi:10.1073/pnas.0931349100. PMC 154377. PMID 12702758.
  59. ^ Edelman, G. M., Tononi, G. (2000). A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. New York: Basic Books
  60. ^ Linden, Eugene (2000). The parrot's lament: and other true tales of animal intrigue, intelligence, and ingenuity. Thorndike, Me.: G.K. Hall. ISBN 978-0-7838-9031-9.
  61. ^ Animal consciousness: what matters and why Daniel Dennett
  62. ^ a b Block, Ned (1995). "On a confusion about a function of consciousness" (PDF). The Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 18 (2): 227–287. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.207.6880. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00038188. S2CID 146168066.
  63. ^ Barron, A.B.; Klein, C. (2016). "What insects can tell us about the origins of consciousness". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 113 (18): 4900–4908. Bibcode:2016PNAS..113.4900B. doi:10.1073/pnas.1520084113. PMC 4983823. PMID 27091981.
  64. ^ Ben-Haim, Moshe Shay; Monte, Olga Dal; Fagan, Nicholas A.; Dunham, Yarrow; Hassin, Ran R.; Chang, Steve W. C.; Santos, Laurie R. (13 April 2021). "Disentangling perceptual awareness from nonconscious processing in rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta)". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 118 (15): e2017543118. Bibcode:2021PNAS..11817543B. doi:10.1073/pnas.2017543118. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 8053918. PMID 33785543.
  65. ^ a b Plotnik, JM; de Waal, FBM; Reiss, D (2006). "Self-recognition in an Asian elephant". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 103 (45): 17053–17057. Bibcode:2006PNAS..10317053P. doi:10.1073/pnas.0608062103. PMC 1636577. PMID 17075063.
  66. ^ Bischof-Köhler, D. (1991). The development of empathy in infants. In M.E. Lamb & H. Keller (eds.), Infant Development. Perspectives from German speaking countries (245-273).
  67. ^ a b c d Prior, H; Schwarz, A; Gunturkun, O (2008). "Mirror-induced behavior in the magpie (Pica pica): Evidence of self-recognition". PLOS Biology. 6 (8): 1642–1650. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0060202. PMC 2517622. PMID 18715117.
  68. ^ Gallup, GG Jr (1970). "Chimpanzees: self-recognition". Science. 167 (3914): 86–87. Bibcode:1970Sci...167...86G. doi:10.1126/science.167.3914.86. PMID 4982211. S2CID 145295899.
  69. ^ Walraven, V; van Elsacker, L; Verheyen, R (1995). "Reactions of a group of pygmy chimpanzees (Pan paniscus) to their mirror images: evidence of self-recognition". Primates. 36: 145–150. doi:10.1007/bf02381922. S2CID 38985498.
  70. ^ Patterson FGP, Cohn RH (1994) Self-recognition and self-awareness in lowland gorillas. In: Parker ST, Mitchell RW, editors. Self-awareness in animals and humans: developmental perspectives. New York (New York): Cambridge University Press. pp. 273–290.
  71. ^ Marten, K.; Psarakos, S. (1995). . In Parker, S.T.; Mitchell, R.; Boccia, M. (eds.). Self-awareness in Animals and Humans: Developmental Perspectives. Cambridge University Press. pp. 361–379. Archived from the original on 13 October 2008.
  72. ^ Reiss, D.; Marino, L. (2001). "Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: A case of cognitive convergence". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 98 (10): 5937–5942. Bibcode:2001PNAS...98.5937R. doi:10.1073/pnas.101086398. PMC 33317. PMID 11331768.
  73. ^ Delfour, F.; Marten, K. (2001). "Mirror image processing in three marine mammal species: Killer whales (Orcinus orca), false killer whales (Pseudorca crassidens) and California sea lions (Zalophus californianus)". Behavioural Processes. 53 (3): 181–190. doi:10.1016/s0376-6357(01)00134-6. PMID 11334706. S2CID 31124804.
  74. ^ Prior, Helmut; Schwarz, A; Güntürkün, O; De Waal, Frans (2008). De Waal, Frans (ed.). "Mirror-Induced Behavior in the Magpie (Pica pica): Evidence of Self-Recognition". PLOS Biology. 6 (8): e202. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0060202. PMC 2517622. PMID 18715117.
  75. ^ Uchino, Emiko; Watanabe, Shigeru (1 November 2014). "Self-recognition in pigeons revisited". Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior. 102 (3): 327–334. doi:10.1002/jeab.112. ISSN 1938-3711. PMID 25307108. S2CID 31499014.
  76. ^ Povinelli, DJ; Rulf, AB; Landau, KR; Bierschwale, DT (1993). "Self-recognition in chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes): distribution, ontogeny, and patterns of emergence". J Comp Psychol. 107 (4): 347–372. doi:10.1037/0735-7036.107.4.347. PMID 8112048.
  77. ^ Hyatt, CW (1998). "Responses of gibbons (Hylobates lar) to their mirror images". Am J Primatol. 45 (3): 307–311. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1098-2345(1998)45:3<307::AID-AJP7>3.0.CO;2-#. PMID 9651653. S2CID 196596255.
  78. ^ Ye, Yvaine. "A species of fish has passed the mirror test for the first time". New Scientist.
  79. ^ . Animals. 7 February 2019. Archived from the original on 17 September 2018. Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  80. ^ Ye, Yvaine. "A species of fish has passed the mirror test for the first time". New Scientist. Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  81. ^ Kohda, Masanori; Takashi, Hatta; Takeyama, Tmohiro; Awata, Satoshi; Tanaka, Hirokazu; Asai, Jun-ya; Jordan, Alex (21 August 2018). "Cleaner wrasse pass the mark test. What are the implications for consciousness and self-awareness testing in animals?". bioRxiv: 397067. doi:10.1101/397067.
  82. ^ Lea SEG (2010) Concept learning in nonprimate mammals: In search of evidence In D Mareschal, PC Quinn and SEG Lea, The Making of Human Concepts, pp. 173–199. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199549221.
  83. ^ The Superior Human? – Documentary. Transcription on the official website
  84. ^ a b c Cazzolla Gatti, Roberto (2015). "Self-consciousness: beyond the looking-glass and what dogs found there". Ethology Ecology & Evolution. 28 (2): 232–240. doi:10.1080/03949370.2015.1102777. ISSN 0394-9370. S2CID 217507938.
  85. ^ Suzuki, Ryuji; Buck, John; Tyack, Peter (January 2005). "The use of Zipf's law in animal communication analysis" (PDF). Animal Behaviour. 69 (1): F9–F17. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.112.5869. doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2004.08.004. S2CID 14968885.
  86. ^ Carter, Alan (2005). "Animals, Pain and Morality". Journal of Applied Philosophy. 22 (1): 17–22. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.2005.00289.x. PMID 15948329.
  87. ^ Sagan, Carl and Ann Druyan (1993) Shadows of Forgotten Ancestors, Ballantine Books. ISBN 9780345384720
  88. ^ Webster, John (27 February 2005). "The secret life of moody cows". The Times.
  89. ^ Leiber, Justin (December 1988). "Cartesian Linguistics?". Philosophia. 18 (4): 309–46. doi:10.1007/BF02380646. S2CID 189835510.
  90. ^ No Face, but Plants Like Life Too Carol Kaesuk Yoon, The New York Times
  91. ^ Haselton, M. G.; Nettle, D. & Andrews, P. W. (2005). "The evolution of cognitive bias.". In D.M. Buss (ed.). The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology. Hoboken, NJ, US: John Wiley & Sons Inc. pp. 724–746.
  92. ^ Bless, H.; Fiedler, K. & Strack, F. (2004). Social cognition: How individuals construct social reality. Hove and New York: Psychology Press. p. 2.
  93. ^ Mendl, M.; Burman, O.H.P.; Parker, R.M.A. & Paul, E.S. (2009). "Cognitive bias as an indicator of animal emotion and welfare: emerging evidence and underlying mechanisms". Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 118 (3–4): 161–181. doi:10.1016/j.applanim.2009.02.023.
  94. ^ Harding, EJ; Paul, ES; Mendl, M (2004). "Animal behaviour: cognitive bias and affective state". Nature. 427 (6972): 312. Bibcode:2004Natur.427..312H. doi:10.1038/427312a. PMID 14737158. S2CID 4411418.
  95. ^ Rygula, R; Pluta, H; P, Popik (2012). "Laughing rats are optimistic". PLOS ONE. 7 (12): e51959. Bibcode:2012PLoSO...751959R. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0051959. PMC 3530570. PMID 23300582.
  96. ^ LeDoux, J (2012). "Rethinking the emotional brain". Neuron. 73 (4): 653–676. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2012.02.004. PMC 3625946. PMID 22365542.
  97. ^ LeDoux, JE (2014). "Coming to terms with fear". Proc Natl Acad Sci USA. 111 (8): 2871–2878. Bibcode:2014PNAS..111.2871L. doi:10.1073/pnas.1400335111. PMC 3939902. PMID 24501122.
  98. ^ LeDoux, JE (2015). (PDF). Daedalus. 144 (1): 96–111. doi:10.1162/DAED_a_00319. S2CID 57561276. Archived from the original (PDF) on 1 May 2015. Retrieved 5 October 2015.
  99. ^ LeDoux JE (2015) Anxious: Using the Brain to Understand and Treat Fear and Anxiety, Penguin Publishing Group. ISBN 9781101619940.
  100. ^ "Neuroscience". Merriam-Webster Medical Dictionary.
  101. ^ a b Weisberg, DS; Keil, FC; Goodstein, J; Rawson, E; Gray, JR (2008). "The seductive allure of neuroscience explanations". Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. 20 (3): 470–477. doi:10.1162/jocn.2008.20040. PMC 2778755. PMID 18004955.
  102. ^ Koch, Christof (2004). The quest for consciousness: a neurobiological approach. Englewood, US-CO: Roberts & Company Publishers. p. 304. ISBN 978-0-9747077-0-9.
  103. ^ See here 13 March 2013 at the Wayback Machine for a glossary of related terms.
  104. ^ Crick, F.; Koch, C. (1998). "Consciousness and neuroscience" (PDF). Cereb Cortex. 8 (2): 97–107. doi:10.1093/cercor/8.2.97. PMID 9542889. Full text.
  105. ^ Sian Beilock, Carr T.H., MacMahon C. and Starkes J.L. (2002) When paying attention becomes counterproductive: impact of divided versus skill-focused attention on novice and experienced performance of sensorimotor skills. J. Exp. Psychol. Appl. 8: 6–16.
  106. ^ Adamantidis A.R., Zhang F., Aravanis A.M., Deisseroth K. and de Lecea L. (2007) "Neural substrates of awakening probed with optogenetic control of hypocretin neurons". Nature.
  107. ^ Rose, James D (2002). (PDF). Reviews in Fisheries Science. 10 (1): 1–38. Bibcode:2002RvFS...10....1R. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.598.8119. doi:10.1080/20026491051668. S2CID 16220451. Archived from the original (PDF) on 10 October 2012.
  108. ^ Anderson, John R. (2004). Cognitive psychology and its implications (6th ed.). Worth Publishers. p. 519. ISBN 978-0-7167-0110-1.
  109. ^ Chavajay, Pablo; Barbara Rogoff (1999). "Cultural variation in management of attention by children and their caregivers". Developmental Psychology. 35 (4): 1079–1090. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.35.4.1079. PMID 10442876.
  110. ^ Kaiser J, Lutzenberger W (2003). "Induced gamma-band activity and human brain function". Neuroscientist. 9 (6): 475–84. doi:10.1177/1073858403259137. PMID 14678580. S2CID 23574844.
  111. ^ 'Layers' or 'levels' of consciousness? 10 April 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  112. ^ Nash, J. Madeleine (18 October 1999). . Time. Vol. 154, no. 16. Archived from the original on 11 February 2001.
  113. ^ a b Metcalfe, J., & Shimamura, A. P. (1994). Metacognition: knowing about knowing. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
  114. ^ Couchman, Justin J.; Coutinho, M. V. C.; Beran, M. J.; Smith, J. D. (2010). (PDF). Journal of Comparative Psychology. 124 (4): 356–368. doi:10.1037/a0020129. PMC 2991470. PMID 20836592. Archived from the original (PDF) on 24 March 2012.
  115. ^ Schraw, Gregory (1998). "Promoting general metacognitive awareness". Instructional Science. 26 (1/2): 113–125. doi:10.1023/A:1003044231033. S2CID 15715418.
  116. ^ Oxford Psychology Dictionary; metacognition[full citation needed]
  117. ^ Couchman, Justin J.; Coutinho, M. V. C.; Beran, M. J.; Smith, J. D. (2010). "Beyond Stimulus Cues and Reinforcement Signals: A New Approach to Animal Metacognition" (PDF). Journal of Comparative Psychology. 124 (4): 356–368. doi:10.1037/a0020129. PMC 2991470. PMID 20836592.
  118. ^ "Metacognition: Known unknowns". Issue 2582 of New Scientist magazine, subscribers only.
  119. ^ "Rats Capable Of Reflecting On Mental Processes". ScienceDaily. 9 March 2007.
  120. ^ Foote, AL; Crystal, JD (March 2007). "Metacognition in the rat". Curr. Biol. 17 (6): 551–5. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2007.01.061. PMC 1861845. PMID 17346969.
  121. ^ Foote, Allison L.; Crystal, J. D. (20 March 2007). "Metacognition in the Rat". Current Biology. 17 (6): 551–555. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2007.01.061. PMC 1861845. PMID 17346969. Archived from the original on 3 July 2012.
  122. ^ Smith, J. David; Beran, M. J.; Couchman, J. J.; Coutinho, M. V. C. (2008). "The Comparative Study of Metacognition: Sharper Paradigms, Safer Inferences". Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 15 (4): 679–691. doi:10.3758/pbr.15.4.679. PMC 4607312. PMID 18792496.
  123. ^ Jozefowiez, J.; Staddon, J. E. R.; Cerutti, D. T. (2009). "Metacognition in animals: how do we know that they know?". Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews. 4: 29–39. doi:10.3819/ccbr.2009.40003.
  124. ^ Rizzolatti, Giacomo; Craighero, Laila (2004). "The mirror-neuron system" (PDF). Annual Review of Neuroscience. 27: 169–192. doi:10.1146/annurev.neuro.27.070203.144230. PMID 15217330. S2CID 1729870.
  125. ^ Keysers, Christian (2010). (PDF). Current Biology. 19 (21): R971–973. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2009.08.026. PMID 19922849. S2CID 12668046. Archived from the original (PDF) on 19 January 2013.
  126. ^ a b c Keysers, Christian (23 June 2011). The Empathic Brain. Kindle.
  127. ^ Christian Keysers; Valeria Gazzola (2006). "Towards a unifying neural theory of social cognition". In Anders; Ende; Unghofer; Kissler; Wildgruber (eds.). (PDF). Progress in Brain Research. Vol. 156. pp. 379–401. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.132.4591. doi:10.1016/S0079-6123(06)56021-2. ISBN 9780444521828. ISSN 0079-6123. PMID 17015092. Archived from the original (PDF) on 30 June 2007.
  128. ^ Michael Arbib, The Mirror System Hypothesis. Linking Language to Theory of Mind 29 March 2009 at the Wayback Machine, 2005, retrieved 17 February 2006
  129. ^ Théoret, Hugo; Pascual-Leone, Alvaro (2002). "Language Acquisition: Do as You Hear". Current Biology. 12 (21): R736–7. doi:10.1016/S0960-9822(02)01251-4. PMID 12419204. S2CID 12867585.
  130. ^ Blakeslee, Sandra (10 January 2006). "Cells That Read Minds". The New York Times. Science.
  131. ^ Oberman, L.; Ramachandran, V.S. (2009). "Reflections on the Mirror Neuron System: Their Evolutionary Functions Beyond Motor Representation". In Pineda, J.A. (ed.). Mirror Neuron Systems: The Role of Mirroring Processes in Social Cognition. Humana Press. pp. 39–62. ISBN 978-1-934115-34-3.
  132. ^ Ramachandran, V.S. (1 January 2009). "Self Awareness: The Last Frontier, Edge Foundation web essay". Retrieved 26 July 2011.
  133. ^ * Nichols, S.; Grantham, T. (2000). "Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness". Philosophy of Science. 67 (4): 648–670. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.515.9722. doi:10.1086/392859. JSTOR 188711. S2CID 16484193.
  134. ^ Freeman and Herron. Evolutionary Analysis. 2007. Pearson Education, NJ.
  135. ^ Peter Århem; B. I. B. Lindahl; Paul R. Manger & Ann B. Butler (2008). "On the origin of consciousness—some amniote scenarios". In Hans Liljenström & Peter Århem (eds.). Consciousness Transitions: Phylogenetic, Ontogenetic, and Physiological Aspects. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-444-52977-0.
  136. ^ Eccles, J. C. (1992). "Evolution of consciousness". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 89 (16): 7320–7324. Bibcode:1992PNAS...89.7320E. doi:10.1073/pnas.89.16.7320. JSTOR 2360081. PMC 49701. PMID 1502142.
  137. ^ Peters, Frederic "Consciousness as Recursive, Spatiotemporal Self-Location"
  138. ^ Baars, Bernard J. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. 1993. Cambridge University Press.
  139. ^ a b c d Gaulin, Steven J. C. and Donald H. McBurney (2003) Evolutionary psychology. Prentice Hall, pp. 101–121. ISBN 978-0-13-111529-3
  140. ^ Seth, A.K.; Baars, B.J. (2005). "Neural Darwinism and consciousness". Consciousness and Cognition. 14 (1): 140–168. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2004.08.008. PMID 15766895. S2CID 6262356.
  141. ^ a b Edelman, G. (2004). Wider than the sky: The phenomenal gift of consciousness: Yale Univ Pr.
  142. ^ Edelman, G. M. (1992). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. Basic Books, New York.
  143. ^ a b c Merker, B (2007). "Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 30 (1): 63–81. doi:10.1017/s0140525x07000891. PMID 17475053. S2CID 16994436.
  144. ^ Edelman, G. M. (2004). Wider than the sky: a revolutionary view of consciousness. Penguin Press Science, London, UK.
  145. ^ Edelman, G. M. (200). Second Nature:Brain Science and Human Knowledge. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT.
  146. ^ Hobson, J. A. (2009). "REM sleep and dreaming: towards a theory of protoconsciousness" (PDF). Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 10 (11): 803–862. doi:10.1038/nrn2716. PMID 19794431. S2CID 205505278.[permanent dead link]
  147. ^ Voss, Ursula (2010). "Changes in EEG pre and post awakening". Science of Awakening. International Review of Neurobiology. Vol. 93. pp. 23–56. doi:10.1016/S0074-7742(10)93002-X. ISBN 9780123813244. PMID 20970000.
  148. ^ Kuiken, Don (2010). "Primary and secondary consciousness during dreaming". International Journal of Dream Research. 3 (1): 21–25.
  149. ^ Low, Philip et al. (2012) The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness Publicly proclaimed in Cambridge, UK, on 7 July 2012, at the Francis Crick Memorial Conference on Consciousness in Human and non-Human Animals.
  150. ^ "Consciousness in Human and non-Human Animals" Francis Crick Memorial Conference, 7 July 2012, Cambridge, UK.
  151. ^ Campbell, C.B.G.; Hodos, W. (1991). "The Scala Naturae revisited: Evolutionary scales and anagenesis in comparative psychology". J. Comp. Psychol. 105 (3): 211–221. doi:10.1037/0735-7036.105.3.211. PMID 1935002.
  152. ^ Shettleworth (1998).
  153. ^ Reznikova (2007).
  154. ^ Crew, Bec (10 December 2015). "Dogs Show Signs of Self-Consciousness in New 'Sniff Test'". ScienceAlert.
  155. ^ Coren, Stanley (2008). How Dogs Think. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 9781847397065. Retrieved 8 July 2018. The important thing to remember is that dogs are not as visually oriented as humans
  156. ^ "Dogs (and probably many other animals) have a conscience too!". en.tsu.ru. Retrieved 5 December 2016.
  157. ^ "Dogs have self-awareness. It was confirmed by STSR tests". en.tsu.ru. Tomsk State University. Retrieved 8 July 2018.
  158. ^ PEPPERBERG, Irene M. (30 June 2009). The Alex Studies: cognitive and communicative abilities of grey parrots. Harvard University Press. ISBN 9780674041998.
  159. ^ "Nkisi Audio Text 1". www.sheldrake.org.
  160. ^ Maria Armental (8 May 2008). . www.projo.com. Archived from the original on 29 June 2011.
  161. ^ Péron F, Rat-Fischer L, Bovet D (2011). "Cooperative problem solving in African grey parrots (Psittacus erithacus)". Animal Cognition. 14 (4): 545–553. doi:10.1007/s10071-011-0389-2. PMID 21384141. S2CID 5616569.
  162. ^ "Researchers show conscious processes in birds' brains for the first time". phys.org. Retrieved 9 October 2020.
  163. ^ Nieder, Andreas; Wagener, Lysann; Rinnert, Paul (25 September 2020). "A neural correlate of sensory consciousness in a corvid bird". Science. 369 (6511): 1626–1629. Bibcode:2020Sci...369.1626N. doi:10.1126/science.abb1447. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 32973028. S2CID 221881862. Retrieved 9 October 2020.
  164. ^ Stacho, Martin; Herold, Christina; Rook, Noemi; Wagner, Hermann; Axer, Markus; Amunts, Katrin; Güntürkün, Onur (25 September 2020). "A cortex-like canonical circuit in the avian forebrain". Science. 369 (6511): eabc5534. doi:10.1126/science.abc5534. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 32973004. S2CID 221882087. Retrieved 16 October 2020.
  165. ^ a b What is this octopus thinking? 7 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine. By Garry Hamilton.
  166. ^ a b NFW.org? 15 December 2009 at the Wayback Machine, Is the octopus really the invertebrate intellect of the sea, by Doug Stewart. In: National Wildlife. Feb/Mar 1997, vol.35 no.2.
  167. ^ a b
  168. ^ Slate.com, How Smart is the Octopus?
  169. ^ Yekutieli, Yoram; Sagiv-Zohar, Roni; Aharonov, Ranit; Enge, Yaakov; Hochner, Binyamin; Flash, Tamar (2005). "Dynamic Model of the Octopus Arm. I. Biomechanics of the Octopus Reaching Movement". J. Neurophysiol. 94 (2): 1443–1458. doi:10.1152/jn.00684.2004. PMID 15829594. S2CID 14711055.
  170. ^ Zullo, L; Sumbre, G; Agnisola, C; Flash, T; Hochner, B (2009). "Nonsomatotopic organization of the higher motor centers in octopus". Curr. Biol. 19 (19): 1632–6. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2009.07.067. PMID 19765993. S2CID 15852956.
  171. ^ "Octopus twists for shrimps". 25 February 2003 – via news.bbc.co.uk.
  172. ^ What behavior can we expect of octopuses?. By Dr. Jennifer Mather, Department of Psychology and Neuroscience, University of Lethbridge and Roland C. Anderson, The Seattle Aquarium.
  173. ^ "Octopus snatches coconut and runs". BBC News. 14 December 2009. Retrieved 20 May 2010.
  174. ^ . Archived from the original on 24 October 2013. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
  175. ^ Stone-Miller, Rebecca (2004). "Human-Animal Imagery, Shamanic Visions, and Ancient American Aesthetics". Res: Anthropology and Aesthetics. 45 (45): 47–68. doi:10.1086/RESv45n1ms20167621. JSTOR 20167621. S2CID 193758322.
  176. ^ Metzner, Ralf (1987) "Transformation Process in Shamanism, Alchemy, and Yoga". In: Nicholson, S. Shamanism, pp. 233–252, Quest Books. ISBN 9780835631266.

Further reading edit

  • Bayn T, Cleeremans A and Wilken P (2009) The Oxford companion to consciousness pp. 43f, Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-856951-0.
  • Bekoff, Marc (2013) Why Dogs Hump and Bees Get Depressed New World Library. ISBN 978-1-60868-220-1.
  • Bekoff, Marc; Jane Goodall (2007). The Emotional Lives of Animals. New World Library. ISBN 978-1-57731-502-5.
  • Bekoff, Marc (2003). "Consciousness and Self in Animals: Some Reflections" (PDF). Zygon. 38 (2): 229–245. doi:10.1111/1467-9744.00497.[permanent dead link]
  • Brown, Jason W (2010) Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience pp. 200–210, Les Editions Chromatika. ISBN 978-2-930517-07-0.
  • Cartmill, M (2000). "Animal consciousness: some philosophical, methodological, and evolutionary problems". American Zoologist. 40 (6): 835–846. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.576.9419. doi:10.1668/0003-1569(2000)040[0835:acspma]2.0.co;2. S2CID 198153826.
  • Dawkins, Marian Stamp (2012) Why animals matter: Animal consciousness, animal welfare, and human well-being Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-958782-7.
  • Dawkins, Marian Stamp (1998) Through our eyes only? The search for animal consciousness Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-850320-0.
  • Dol, Marcel (1997) Animal consciousness and animal ethics: perspectives from the Netherlands Uitgeverij Van Gorcum. ISBN 978-90-232-3215-5.
  • Griffin, Donald Redfield (1976) The Question of Animal Awareness Rockefeller Univ. Press.
  • Griffin, Donald Redfield (2001) Animal minds: beyond cognition to consciousness University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-30865-4.
  • Huxley, TH (1874). "On the hypothesis that animals are automata, and its history" (PDF). Nature. 10 (253): 362–366. Bibcode:1874Natur..10..362.. doi:10.1038/010362a0. S2CID 4113131.
  • Kunkel HO (2000) Human issues in animal agriculture pp. 213–214. Texas A&M University Press. ISBN 978-0-89096-927-4.
  • Lurz, Robert "Animal Minds" Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Phillips, Clive (2009) The Welfare of Animals: The Silent Majority Springer. ISBN 978-1-4020-9218-3.
  • Reznikova, Zh. I. (2007) Animal Intelligence: From Individual to Social Cognition. Cambridge University Press
  • Samorini, Giorgio (2002) Animals and Psychedelics: The Natural World and the Instinct to Alter Consciousness Inner Traditions/Bear. ISBN 978-0-89281-986-7. Review
  • Schönfeld, Martin (2006). "Animal Consciousness: Paradigm Change in the Life Sciences". Perspectives on Science. 14 (3): 354–381. doi:10.1162/posc.2006.14.3.354. S2CID 145128785.
  • Shettleworth, S. J. (1998) (2010,2nd ed) Cognition, evolution and behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Smith, J. D., Beran, M. J., Couchman, J. J., Coutinho, M. V. C., & Boomer, J. B. (2009). Animal metacognition: Problems and prospects,[1] Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews, 4, 40–53.
  • Steiner, Gary (2008) Animals and the moral community: mental life, moral status, and kinship pp. 11–12, Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-14234-2.
  • Stenholm, Stig (2011) The Quest for Reality: Bohr and Wittgenstein: Two Complementary Views pp. 88–92, Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-960358-9.
  • Van Riel, Gerd (2009) Ancient perspectives on Aristotle's De anima Leuven University Press. ISBN 978-90-5867-772-3.
  • Walker, Stephen (1983) Animal thought p. 98, Routledge. ISBN 978-0-7100-9037-9.
Invertebrates
  • Smith, FA (1991). . ILAR Journal. 33 (1–2): 25–31. doi:10.1093/ilar.33.1-2.25. Archived from the original on 4 March 2016. Retrieved 23 December 2012.
  • Sømme, Lauritz S. (2005) "Sentience and pain in invertebrates"[permanent dead link] Report to Norwegian Scientific Committee for Food Safety.
  • Consciousness in a Cockroach Discover, 10 January 2007.
  • Do insects Feel pain?

External links edit

  • Animal consciousness at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Bekoff, Marc 2012 Animals are conscious and should be treated as such New Scientist, 24 September 2012.
  • Koch, Christof (2012) Consciousness Is Everywhere Huffington Post, 15 August 2012.
  • Octopuses Gain Consciousness (According to Scientists' Declaration) Scientific American, 21 August 2012.
  • The absence of a neocortex does not appear to preclude an organism from experiencing affective states 4 September 2012.
  • Animals are as with it as humans, scientists say Discovery, 24 August 2012.
  •   Video of the Cambridge declaration 26 September 2014 at the Wayback Machine
  • How do octopuses think? ABC interview with Peter Godfrey-Smith.
  • Do animals demonstrate consciousness? HowStuffWorks. Accessed 30 January 2012.
  • I, cockroach 14 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine Aeon, 19 November 2013.
  • Essay by John Jeremiah Sullivan in Lapham's Quarterly, 25 March 2014.
  • Elephants mourn. Dogs love. Why do we deny the feelings of other species? The Guardian. 11 October 2017.

animal, consciousness, animal, sentience, redirects, here, journal, animal, sentience, journal, animal, awareness, quality, state, self, awareness, within, animal, being, aware, external, object, something, within, itself, humans, consciousness, been, defined,. Animal sentience redirects here For the journal see Animal Sentience journal Animal consciousness or animal awareness is the quality or state of self awareness within an animal or of being aware of an external object or something within itself 2 3 In humans consciousness has been defined as sentience awareness subjectivity qualia the ability to experience or to feel wakefulness having a sense of selfhood and the executive control system of the mind 4 Despite the difficulty in definition many philosophers believe there is a broadly shared underlying intuition about what consciousness is 5 According to the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness near human like levels of consciousness have been observed in the grey parrot 1 The topic of animal consciousness is beset with a number of difficulties It poses the problem of other minds in an especially severe form because animals lacking the ability to use human language cannot tell us about their experiences 6 Also it is difficult to reason objectively about the question because a denial that an animal is conscious is often taken to imply that they do not feel their life has no value and that harming them is not morally wrong 7 The 17th century French philosopher Rene Descartes for example has sometimes been criticised for providing a rationale for the mistreatment of animals because he argued that only humans are conscious 8 Philosophers who consider subjective experience the essence of consciousness also generally believe as a correlate that the existence and nature of animal consciousness can never rigorously be known The American philosopher Thomas Nagel spelled out this point of view in an influential essay titled What Is it Like to Be a Bat He said that an organism is conscious if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism something it is like for the organism and he argued that no matter how much we know about an animal s brain and behavior we can never really put ourselves into the mind of the animal and experience their world in the way they do themself 9 Other thinkers such as the cognitive scientist Douglas Hofstadter dismiss this argument as incoherent 10 Several psychologists and ethologists have argued for the existence of animal consciousness by describing a range of behaviors that appear to show animals holding beliefs about things they cannot directly perceive Donald Griffin s 2001 book Animal Minds reviews a substantial portion of the evidence 11 Animal consciousness has been actively researched for over one hundred years 12 In 1927 the American functional psychologist Harvey Carr argued that any valid measure or understanding of awareness in animals depends on an accurate and complete knowledge of its essential conditions in man 13 A more recent review concluded in 1985 that the best approach is to use experiment especially psychophysics and observation to trace the dawning and ontogeny of self consciousness perception communication intention beliefs and reflection in normal human fetuses infants and children 12 In 2012 a group of neuroscientists signed the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness which unequivocally asserted that humans are not unique in possessing the neurological substrates that generate consciousness Non human animals including all mammals and birds and many other creatures including octopuses also possess these neural substrates 14 Contents 1 Philosophical background 1 1 Epiphenomenalism 1 2 Animal ethics 2 Defining consciousness 3 Scientific approaches 3 1 Mirror test 3 2 Language 3 3 Pain or suffering 3 4 Cognitive bias and emotion 3 5 Neuroscience 3 5 1 Neural correlates 3 5 2 Neocortex 3 5 3 Attention 3 5 4 Extended consciousness 3 5 5 Metacognition 3 5 6 Mirror neurons 3 6 Evolutionary psychology 3 7 Neural Darwinism 4 Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness 5 Examples 5 1 Mammals 5 1 1 Dogs 5 2 Birds 5 2 1 Grey parrots 5 2 2 Corvids 5 3 Invertebrates 6 Shamanistic and religious views 7 Researchers 8 See also 9 References 10 Further reading 11 External linksPhilosophical background edit nbsp Rene Descartes argued that only humans are conscious and not other animals The mind body problem in philosophy examines the relationship between mind and matter and in particular the relationship between consciousness and the brain A variety of approaches have been proposed Most are either dualist or monist Dualism maintains a rigid distinction between the realms of mind and matter Monism maintains that there is only one kind of stuff and that mind and matter are both aspects of it The problem was addressed by pre Aristotelian philosophers 15 16 and was famously addressed by Rene Descartes in the 17th century resulting in Cartesian dualism Descartes believed that humans only and not other animals have this non physical mind The rejection of the mind body dichotomy is found in French Structuralism and is a position that generally characterized post war French philosophy 17 The absence of an empirically identifiable meeting point between the non physical mind and its physical extension has proven problematic to dualism and many modern philosophers of mind maintain that the mind is not something separate from the body 18 These approaches have been particularly influential in the sciences particularly in the fields of sociobiology computer science evolutionary psychology and the neurosciences 19 20 21 22 Epiphenomenalism edit Main article Epiphenomenalism Epiphenomenalism is the theory in philosophy of mind that mental phenomena are caused by physical processes in the brain or that both are effects of a common cause as opposed to mental phenomena driving the physical mechanics of the brain The impression that thoughts feelings or sensations cause physical effects is therefore to be understood as illusory to some extent For example it is not the feeling of fear that produces an increase in heart beat both are symptomatic of a common physiological origin possibly in response to a legitimate external threat 23 The history of epiphenomenalism goes back to the post Cartesian attempt to solve the riddle of Cartesian dualism i e of how mind and body could interact La Mettrie Leibniz and Spinoza all in their own way began this way of thinking The idea that even if the animal were conscious nothing would be added to the production of behavior even in animals of the human type was first voiced by La Mettrie 1745 and then by Cabanis 1802 and was further explicated by Hodgson 1870 and Huxley 1874 24 25 Huxley 1874 likened mental phenomena to the whistle on a steam locomotive However epiphenomenalism flourished primarily as it found a niche among methodological or scientific behaviorism In the early 1900s scientific behaviorists such as Ivan Pavlov John B Watson and B F Skinner began the attempt to uncover laws describing the relationship between stimuli and responses without reference to inner mental phenomena Instead of adopting a form of eliminativism or mental fictionalism positions that deny that inner mental phenomena exist a behaviorist was able to adopt epiphenomenalism in order to allow for the existence of mind However by the 1960s scientific behaviourism met substantial difficulties and eventually gave way to the cognitive revolution Participants in that revolution such as Jerry Fodor reject epiphenomenalism and insist upon the efficacy of the mind Fodor even speaks of epiphobia fear that one is becoming an epiphenomenalist Thomas Henry Huxley defends in an essay titled On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata and its History an epiphenomenalist theory of consciousness according to which consciousness is a causally inert effect of neural activity as the steam whistle which accompanies the work of a locomotive engine is without influence upon its machinery 26 To this William James objects in his essay Are We Automata by stating an evolutionary argument for mind brain interaction implying that if the preservation and development of consciousness in the biological evolution is a result of natural selection it is plausible that consciousness has not only been influenced by neural processes but has had a survival value itself and it could only have had this if it had been efficacious 27 28 Karl Popper develops in the book The Self and Its Brain a similar evolutionary argument 29 Animal ethics edit Bernard Rollin of Colorado State University the principal author of two U S federal laws regulating pain relief for animals writes that researchers remained unsure into the 1980s as to whether animals experience pain and veterinarians trained in the U S before 1989 were simply taught to ignore animal pain 30 In his interactions with scientists and other veterinarians Rollin asserts that he was regularly asked to prove animals are conscious and provide scientifically acceptable grounds for claiming they feel pain 30 The denial of animal consciousness by scientists has been described as mentophobia by Donald Griffin 31 Academic reviews of the topic are equivocal noting that the argument that animals have at least simple conscious thoughts and feelings has strong support 32 but some critics continue to question how reliably animal mental states can be determined 33 34 A refereed journal Animal Sentience 35 launched in 2015 by the Institute of Science and Policy of The Humane Society of the United States is devoted to research on this and related topics Defining consciousness editAbout forty meanings attributed to the term consciousness can be identified and categorized based on functions and experiences The prospects for reaching any single agreed upon theory independent definition of consciousness appear remote 36 Consciousness is an elusive concept that presents many difficulties when attempts are made to define it 37 38 Its study has progressively become an interdisciplinary challenge for numerous researchers including ethologists neurologists cognitive neuroscientists philosophers psychologists and psychiatrists 39 40 In 1976 Richard Dawkins wrote The evolution of the capacity to simulate seems to have culminated in subjective consciousness Why this should have happened is to me the most profound mystery facing modern biology 41 In 2004 eight neuroscientists felt it was still too soon for a definition They wrote an apology in Human Brain Function 42 We have no idea how consciousness emerges from the physical activity of the brain and we do not know whether consciousness can emerge from non biological systems such as computers At this point the reader will expect to find a careful and precise definition of consciousness You will be disappointed Consciousness has not yet become a scientific term that can be defined in this way Currently we all use the term consciousness in many different and often ambiguous ways Precise definitions of different aspects of consciousness will emerge but to make precise definitions at this stage is premature dd Consciousness is sometimes defined as the quality or state of being aware of an external object or something within oneself 3 43 It has been defined somewhat vaguely as subjectivity awareness sentience the ability to experience or to feel wakefulness having a sense of selfhood and the executive control system of the mind 4 Despite the difficulty in definition many philosophers believe that there is a broadly shared underlying intuition about what consciousness is 5 Max Velmans and Susan Schneider wrote in The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness Anything that we are aware of at a given moment forms part of our consciousness making conscious experience at once the most familiar and most mysterious aspect of our lives 44 Related terms also often used in vague or ambiguous ways are Awareness the state or ability to perceive to feel or to be conscious of events objects or sensory patterns In this level of consciousness sense data can be confirmed by an observer without necessarily implying understanding More broadly it is the state or quality of being aware of something In biological psychology awareness is defined as a human s or an animal s perception and cognitive reaction to a condition or event Self awareness the capacity for introspection and the ability to reconcile oneself as an individual separate from the environment and other individuals Self consciousness an acute sense of self awareness It is a preoccupation with oneself as opposed to the philosophical state of self awareness which is the awareness that one exists as an individual being although some writers use both terms interchangeably or synonymously 45 Sentience the ability to be aware feel perceive or be conscious of one s surroundings or to have subjective experiences Sentience is a minimalistic way of defining consciousness which is otherwise commonly used to collectively describe sentience plus other characteristics of the mind Sapience often defined as wisdom or the ability of an organism or entity to act with appropriate judgment a mental faculty which is a component of intelligence or alternatively may be considered an additional faculty apart from intelligence with its own properties Qualia individual instances of subjective conscious experience Sentience the ability to feel perceive or to experience subjectivity is not the same as self awareness being aware of oneself as an individual The mirror test is sometimes considered to be an operational test for self awareness and the handful of animals that have passed it are often considered to be self aware 46 47 It remains debatable whether recognition of one s mirror image can be properly construed to imply full self awareness 48 particularly given that robots are being constructed which appear to pass the test 49 50 Much has been learned in neuroscience about correlations between brain activity and subjective conscious experiences and many suggest that neuroscience will ultimately explain consciousness consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells 51 However this view has been criticized because consciousness has yet to be shown to be a process 52 and the so called hard problem of relating consciousness directly to brain activity remains elusive 53 Scientific approaches editSince Descartes s proposal of dualism it became a general consensus that the mind had become a matter of philosophy and that science was not able to penetrate the issue of consciousness that consciousness was outside of space and time However in recent decades many scholars have begun to move toward a science of consciousness Antonio Damasio and Gerald Edelman are two neuroscientists who have led the move to neural correlates of the self and of consciousness Damasio has demonstrated that emotions and their biological foundation play a critical role in high level cognition 54 55 and Edelman has created a framework for analyzing consciousness through a scientific outlook The current problem consciousness researchers face involves explaining how and why consciousness arises from neural computation 56 57 In his research on this problem Edelman has developed a theory of consciousness in which he has coined the terms primary consciousness and secondary consciousness 58 59 Eugene Linden author of The Parrot s Lament suggests there are many examples of animal behavior and intelligence that surpass what people would suppose to be the boundary of animal consciousness Linden contends that in many of these documented examples a variety of animal species exhibit behavior that can only be attributed to emotion and to a level of consciousness that we would normally ascribe only to our own species 60 Philosopher Daniel Dennett counters that Consciousness requires a certain kind of informational organization that does not seem to be hard wired in humans but is instilled by human culture Moreover consciousness is not a black or white all or nothing type of phenomenon as is often assumed The differences between humans and other species are so great that speculations about animal consciousness seem ungrounded Many authors simply assume that an animal like a bat has a point of view but there seems to be little interest in exploring the details involved 61 Consciousness in mammals including humans is an aspect of the mind generally thought to comprise qualities such as subjectivity sentience and the ability to perceive the relationship between oneself and one s environment It is a subject of much research in philosophy of mind psychology neuroscience and cognitive science Some philosophers divide consciousness into phenomenal consciousness which is subjective experience itself and access consciousness which refers to the global availability of information to processing systems in the brain 62 Phenomenal consciousness has many different experienced qualities often referred to as qualia Phenomenal consciousness is usually consciousness of something or about something a property known as intentionality in philosophy of mind 62 In humans there are three common methods of studying consciousness i e verbal report behavioural demonstrations and neural correlation with conscious activity Unfortunately these can only be generalized to non human taxa with varying degrees of difficulty 63 While animals cannot speak their minds a new study employed a very unique way that enabled neuroscientists to separate conscious awareness from non conscious perception in animals 64 In this study conducted in rhesus monkeys Ben Haim and his team used a process dissociation approach that predicted opposite behavioral outcomes towards the two modes of perception They found that monkeys displayed the very same opposite behavioral outcomes as did humans when they were aware vs unaware of the stimuli presented Mirror test edit nbsp Elephants can recognize themselves in a mirror 65 External videos nbsp Self recognition in apes National GeographicMain article Mirror test The sense in which animals or human infants can be said to have consciousness or a self concept has been hotly debated it is often referred to as the debate over animal minds The best known research technique in this area is the mirror test devised by Gordon G Gallup in which the skin of an animal or human infant is marked while they are asleep or sedated with a mark that cannot be seen directly but is visible in a mirror The animal is then allowed to see their reflection in a mirror if the animal spontaneously directs grooming behaviour towards the mark that is taken as an indication that they are aware of themself 66 67 Over the past 30 years many studies have found evidence that animals recognise themselves in mirrors Self awareness by this criterion has been reported for Land mammals apes chimpanzees bonobos orangutans and gorillas 68 69 70 and elephants 65 Cetaceans bottlenose dolphins 71 72 killer whales and possibly false killer whales 73 Birds magpies 67 74 pigeons can pass the mirror test after training in the prerequisite behaviors 75 Until recently it was thought that self recognition was absent from animals without a neocortex and was restricted to mammals with large brains and well developed social cognition However in 2008 a study of self recognition in corvids reported significant results for magpies Mammals and birds inherited the same brain components from their last common ancestor nearly 300 million years ago and have since independently evolved and formed significantly different brain types The results of the mirror and mark tests showed that neocortex less magpies are capable of understanding that a mirror image belongs to their own body The findings show that magpies respond in the mirror and mark test in a manner similar to apes dolphins and elephants This is a remarkable capability that although not fully concrete in its determination of self recognition is at least a prerequisite of self recognition This is not only of interest regarding the convergent evolution of social intelligence it is also valuable for an understanding of the general principles that govern cognitive evolution and their underlying neural mechanisms The magpies were chosen to study based on their empathy lifestyle a possible precursor for their ability of self awareness 67 However even in the chimpanzee the species most studied and with the most convincing findings clear cut evidence of self recognition is not obtained in all individuals tested Occurrence is about 75 in young adults and considerably less in young and old individuals 76 For monkeys non primate mammals and in a number of bird species exploration of the mirror and social displays were observed However hints at mirror induced self directed behavior have been obtained 77 According to a 2019 study cleaner wrasses have become the first fish ever observed to pass the mirror test 78 However the test s inventor Gordon Gallup has said that the fish were most likely trying to scrape off a perceived parasite on another fish and that they did not demonstrate self recognition The authors of the study retorted that because the fish checked themselves in the mirror before and after the scraping this meant that the fish had self awareness and recognized that their reflections belonged to their own bodies 79 80 81 The mirror test has attracted controversy among some researchers because it is entirely focused on vision the primary sense in humans while other species rely more heavily on other senses such as the olfactory sense in dogs 82 83 84 A study in 2015 showed that the sniff test of self recognition STSR provides evidence of self awareness in dogs 84 Language edit External videos nbsp Whale song Oceania Project nbsp This is Einstein Knoxville ZooSee also Animal language Origin of language Evolutionary linguistics Talking bird and FOXP2 Another approach to determine whether a non human animal is conscious derives from passive speech research with a macaw see Arielle Some researchers propose that by passively listening to an animal s voluntary speech it is possible to learn about the thoughts of another creature and to determine that the speaker is conscious This type of research was originally used to investigate a child s crib speech by Weir 1962 and in investigations of early speech in children by Greenfield and others 1976 Zipf s law might be able to be used to indicate if a given dataset of animal communication indicate an intelligent natural language Some researchers have used this algorithm to study bottlenose dolphin language 85 Pain or suffering edit This section contains too many or overly lengthy quotations Please help summarize the quotations Consider transferring direct quotations to Wikiquote or excerpts to Wikisource February 2020 See also Pain in animals and Animal cruelty Further arguments revolve around the ability of animals to feel pain or suffering Suffering implies consciousness If animals can be shown to suffer in a way similar or identical to humans many of the arguments against human suffering could then presumably be extended to animals Others have argued that pain can be demonstrated by adverse reactions to negative stimuli that are non purposeful or even maladaptive 86 One such reaction is transmarginal inhibition a phenomenon observed in humans and some animals akin to mental breakdown Carl Sagan the American cosmologist points to reasons why humans have had a tendency to deny animals can suffer Humans who enslave castrate experiment on and fillet other animals have had an understandable penchant for pretending animals do not feel pain A sharp distinction between humans and animals is essential if we are to bend them to our will make them work for us wear them eat them without any disquieting tinges of guilt or regret It is unseemly of us who often behave so unfeelingly toward other animals to contend that only humans can suffer The behavior of other animals renders such pretensions specious They are just too much like us 87 John Webster a professor of animal husbandry at Bristol argues People have assumed that intelligence is linked to the ability to suffer and that because animals have smaller brains they suffer less than humans That is a pathetic piece of logic sentient animals have the capacity to experience pleasure and are motivated to seek it you only have to watch how cows and lambs both seek and enjoy pleasure when they lie with their heads raised to the sun on a perfect English summer s day Just like humans 88 However there is no agreement where the line should be drawn between organisms that can feel pain and those that cannot Justin Leiber a philosophy professor at Oxford University writes that Montaigne is ecumenical in this respect claiming consciousness for spiders and ants and even writing of our duties to trees and plants Singer and Clarke agree in denying consciousness to sponges Singer locates the distinction somewhere between the shrimp and the oyster He with rather considerable convenience for one who is thundering hard accusations at others slides by the case of insects and spiders and bacteria they pace Montaigne apparently and rather conveniently do not feel pain The intrepid Midgley on the other hand seems willing to speculate about the subjective experience of tapeworms Nagel appears to draw the line at flounders and wasps though more recently he speaks of the inner life of cockroaches 89 There are also some who reject the argument entirely arguing that although suffering animals feel anguish a suffering plant also struggles to stay alive albeit in a less visible way In fact no living organism wants to die for another organism s sustenance In an article written for The New York Times Carol Kaesuk Yoon argues that When a plant is wounded its body immediately kicks into protection mode It releases a bouquet of volatile chemicals which in some cases have been shown to induce neighboring plants to pre emptively step up their own chemical defenses and in other cases to lure in predators of the beasts that may be causing the damage to the plants Inside the plant repair systems are engaged and defenses are mounted the molecular details of which scientists are still working out but which involve signaling molecules coursing through the body to rally the cellular troops even the enlisting of the genome itself which begins churning out defense related proteins If you think about it though why would we expect any organism to lie down and die for our dinner Organisms have evolved to do everything in their power to avoid being extinguished How long would any lineage be likely to last if its members effectively didn t care if you killed them 90 Cognitive bias and emotion edit nbsp Is the glass half empty or half full See also Cognitive bias in animals and Emotion in animals Cognitive bias in animals is a pattern of deviation in judgment whereby inferences about other animals and situations may be drawn in an illogical fashion 91 Individuals create their own subjective social reality from their perception of the input 92 It refers to the question Is the glass half empty or half full used as an indicator of optimism or pessimism Cognitive biases have been shown in a wide range of species including rats dogs rhesus macaques sheep chicks starlings and honeybees 93 94 95 The neuroscientist Joseph LeDoux advocates avoiding terms derived from human subjective experience when discussing brain functions in animals 96 For example the common practice of calling brain circuits that detect and respond to threats fear circuits implies that these circuits are responsible for feelings of fear LeDoux argues that Pavlovian fear conditioning should be renamed Pavlovian threat conditioning to avoid the implication that fear is being acquired in rats or humans 97 Key to his theoretical change is the notion of survival functions mediated by survival circuits the purpose of which is to keep organisms alive rather than to make emotions For example defensive survival circuits exist to detect and respond to threats While all organisms can do this only organisms that can be conscious of their own brain s activities can feel fear Fear is a conscious experience and occurs the same way as any other kind of conscious experience via cortical circuits that allow attention to certain forms of brain activity LeDoux argues the only differences between an emotional and non emotion state of consciousness are the underlying neural ingredients that contribute to the state 98 99 Neuroscience edit nbsp Drawing by Santiago Ramon y Cajal 1899 of neurons in the pigeon cerebellumNeuroscience is the scientific study of the nervous system 100 It is a highly active interdisciplinary science that collaborates with many other fields The scope of neuroscience has broadened recently to include molecular cellular developmental structural functional evolutionary computational and medical aspects of the nervous system Theoretical studies of neural networks are being complemented with techniques for imaging sensory and motor tasks in the brain According to a 2008 paper neuroscience explanations of psychological phenomena currently have a seductive allure and seem to generate more public interest than explanations which do not contain neuroscientific information 101 They found that subjects who were not neuroscience experts judged that explanations with logically irrelevant neuroscience information were more satisfying than explanations without 101 Neural correlates edit See also Neural correlates of consciousness The neural correlates of consciousness constitute the minimal set of neuronal events and mechanisms sufficient for a specific conscious percept 102 Neuroscientists use empirical approaches to discover neural correlates of subjective phenomena 103 The set should be minimal because if the brain is sufficient to give rise to any given conscious experience the question is which of its components is necessary to produce it Visual sense and representation was reviewed in 1998 by Francis Crick and Christof Koch They concluded sensory neuroscience can be used as a bottom up approach to studying consciousness and suggested experiments to test various hypotheses in this research stream 104 A feature that distinguishes humans from most animals is that we are not born with an extensive repertoire of behavioral programs that would enable us to survive on our own physiological prematurity To compensate for this we have an unmatched ability to learn i e to consciously acquire such programs by imitation or exploration Once consciously acquired and sufficiently exercised these programs can become automated to the extent that their execution happens beyond the realms of our awareness Take as an example the incredible fine motor skills exerted in playing a Beethoven piano sonata or the sensorimotor coordination required to ride a motorcycle along a curvy mountain road Such complex behaviors are possible only because a sufficient number of the subprograms involved can be executed with minimal or even suspended conscious control In fact the conscious system may actually interfere somewhat with these automated programs 105 The growing ability of neuroscientists to manipulate neurons using methods from molecular biology in combination with optical tools depends on the simultaneous development of appropriate behavioural assays and model organisms amenable to large scale genomic analysis and manipulation 106 A combination of such fine grained neuronal analysis in animals with ever more sensitive psychophysical and brain imaging techniques in humans complemented by the development of a robust theoretical predictive framework will hopefully lead to a rational understanding of consciousness Neocortex edit nbsp Previously researchers had thought that patterns of neural sleep exhibited by zebra finches needed a mammalian neocortex 1 The neocortex is a part of the brain of mammals It consists of the grey matter or neuronal cell bodies and unmyelinated fibers surrounding the deeper white matter myelinated axons in the cerebrum The neocortex is smooth in rodents and other small mammals whereas in primates and other larger mammals it has deep grooves and wrinkles These folds increase the surface area of the neocortex considerably without taking up too much more volume Also neurons within the same wrinkle have more opportunity for connectivity while neurons in different wrinkles have less opportunity for connectivity leading to compartmentalization of the cortex The neocortex is divided into frontal parietal occipital and temporal lobes which perform different functions For example the occipital lobe contains the primary visual cortex and the temporal lobe contains the primary auditory cortex Further subdivisions or areas of neocortex are responsible for more specific cognitive processes The neocortex is the newest part of the cerebral cortex to evolve hence the prefix neo the other parts of the cerebral cortex are the paleocortex and archicortex collectively known as the allocortex In humans 90 of the cerebral cortex is neocortex Researchers have argued that consciousness in mammals arises in the neocortex and therefore cannot arise in animals which lack a neocortex For example Rose argued in 2002 that the fishes have nervous systems that mediate effective escape and avoidance responses to noxious stimuli but these responses must occur without a concurrent human like awareness of pain suffering or distress which depend on separately evolved neocortex 107 Recently that view has been challenged and many researchers now believe that animal consciousness can arise from homologous subcortical brain networks 1 Attention edit Attention is the cognitive process of selectively concentrating on one aspect of the environment while ignoring other things Attention has also been referred to as the allocation of processing resources 108 Attention also has variations amongst cultures Voluntary attention develops in specific cultural and institutional contexts through engagement in cultural activities with more competent community members 109 Most experiments show that one neural correlate of attention is enhanced firing If a neuron has a certain response to a stimulus when the animal is not attending to the stimulus then when the animal does attend to the stimulus the neuron s response will be enhanced even if the physical characteristics of the stimulus remain the same In many cases attention produces changes in the EEG Many animals including humans produce gamma waves 40 60 Hz when focusing attention on a particular object or activity 110 Extended consciousness edit Extended consciousness is an animal s autobiographical self perception It is thought to arise in the brains of animals which have a substantial capacity for memory and reason It does not necessarily require language The perception of a historic and future self arises from a stream of information from the immediate environment and from neural structures related to memory The concept was popularised by Antonio Damasio and is used in biological psychology Extended consciousness is said to arise in structures in the human brain described as image spaces and dispositional spaces Image spaces imply areas where sensory impressions of all types are processed including the focused awareness of the core consciousness Dispositional spaces include convergence zones which are networks in the brain where memories are processed and recalled and where knowledge is merged with immediate experience 111 112 Metacognition edit Metacognition is defined as cognition about cognition or knowing about knowing 113 It can take many forms it includes knowledge about when and how to use particular strategies for learning or for problem solving 113 It has been suggested that metacognition in some animals provides evidence for cognitive self awareness 114 There are generally two components of metacognition knowledge about cognition and regulation of cognition 115 Writings on metacognition can be traced back at least as far as De Anima and the Parva Naturalia of the Greek philosopher Aristotle 116 Metacognologists believe that the ability to consciously think about thinking is unique to sapient species and indeed is one of the definitions of sapience citation needed There is evidence that rhesus monkeys and apes can make accurate judgments about the strengths of their memories of fact and monitor their own uncertainty 117 while attempts to demonstrate metacognition in birds have been inconclusive 118 A 2007 study provided some evidence for metacognition in rats 119 120 121 but further analysis suggested that they may have been following simple operant conditioning principles 122 or a behavioral economic model 123 Mirror neurons edit Mirror neurons are neurons that fire both when an animal acts and when the animal observes the same action performed by another 124 125 126 Thus the neuron mirrors the behavior of the other as though the observer were themself acting Such neurons have been directly observed in primate and other species including birds The function of the mirror system is a subject of much speculation Many researchers in cognitive neuroscience and cognitive psychology consider that this system provides the physiological mechanism for the perception action coupling see the common coding theory 126 They argue that mirror neurons may be important for understanding the actions of other people and for learning new skills by imitation Some researchers also speculate that mirror systems may simulate observed actions and thus contribute to theory of mind skills 127 128 while others relate mirror neurons to language abilities 129 Neuroscientists such as Marco Iacoboni UCLA have argued that mirror neuron systems in the human brain help us understand the actions and intentions of other people In a study published in March 2005 Iacoboni and his colleagues reported that mirror neurons could discern if another person who was picking up a cup of tea planned to drink from it or clear it from the table In addition Iacoboni and a number of other researchers have argued that mirror neurons are the neural basis of the human capacity for emotions such as empathy 126 130 Vilayanur S Ramachandran has speculated that mirror neurons may provide the neurological basis of self awareness 131 132 Evolutionary psychology edit See also Evolutionary psychology Consciousness is likely an evolved adaptation since it meets George Williams criteria of species universality complexity 133 and functionality and it is a trait that apparently increases fitness 134 Opinions are divided as to where in biological evolution consciousness emerged and about whether or not consciousness has survival value It has been argued that consciousness emerged i exclusively with the first humans ii exclusively with the first mammals iii independently in mammals and birds or iv with the first reptiles 135 Donald Griffin suggests in his book Animal Minds a gradual evolution of consciousness 11 Each of these scenarios raises the question of the possible survival value of consciousness In his paper Evolution of consciousness John Eccles argues that special anatomical and physical adaptations of the mammalian cerebral cortex gave rise to consciousness 136 In contrast others have argued that the recursive circuitry underwriting consciousness is much more primitive having evolved initially in pre mammalian species because it improves the capacity for interaction with both social and natural environments by providing an energy saving neutral gear in an otherwise energy expensive motor output machine 137 Once in place this recursive circuitry may well have provided a basis for the subsequent development of many of the functions that consciousness facilitates in higher organisms as outlined by Bernard J Baars 138 Richard Dawkins suggested that humans evolved consciousness in order to make themselves the subjects of thought 139 Daniel Povinelli suggests that large tree climbing apes evolved consciousness to take into account one s own mass when moving safely among tree branches 139 Consistent with this hypothesis Gordon Gallup found that chimpanzees and orangutans but not little monkeys or terrestrial gorillas demonstrated self awareness in mirror tests 139 The concept of consciousness can refer to voluntary action awareness or wakefulness However even voluntary behaviour involves unconscious mechanisms Many cognitive processes take place in the cognitive unconscious unavailable to conscious awareness Some behaviours are conscious when learned but then become unconscious seemingly automatic Learning especially implicitly learning a skill can take place outside of consciousness For example plenty of people know how to turn right when they ride a bike but very few can accurately explain how they actually do so 139 Neural Darwinism edit Main article Neural Darwinism Neural Darwinism is a large scale theory of brain function initially proposed in 1978 by the American biologist Gerald Edelman 140 Edelman distinguishes between what he calls primary and secondary consciousness Primary consciousness is the ability found in humans and some animals to integrate observed events with memory to create an awareness of the present and immediate past of the world around them This form of consciousness is also sometimes called sensory consciousness Put another way primary consciousness is the presence of various subjective sensory contents of consciousness such as sensations perceptions and mental images For example primary consciousness includes a person s experience of the blueness of the ocean a bird s song and the feeling of pain Thus primary consciousness refers to being mentally aware of things in the world in the present without any sense of past and future it is composed of mental images bound to a time around the measurable present 141 Secondary consciousness is an individual s accessibility to their history and plans The concept is also loosely and commonly associated with having awareness of one s own consciousness The ability allows its possessors to go beyond the limits of the remembered present of primary consciousness 58 Primary consciousness can be defined as simple awareness that includes perception and emotion As such it is ascribed to most animals By contrast secondary consciousness depends on and includes such features as self reflective awareness abstract thinking volition and metacognition 58 142 Edelman s theory focuses on two nervous system organizations the brainstem and limbic systems on one side and the thalamus and cerebral cortex on the other side The brain stem and limbic system take care of essential body functioning and survival while the thalamocortical system receives signals from sensory receptors and sends out signals to voluntary muscles such as those of the arms and legs The theory asserts that the connection of these two systems during evolution helped animals learn adaptive behaviors 141 Other scientists have argued against Edelman s theory instead suggesting that primary consciousness might have emerged with the basic vegetative systems of the brain That is the evolutionary origin might have come from sensations and primal emotions arising from sensors and receptors both internal and surface signaling that the well being of the creature was immediately threatened for example hunger for air thirst hunger pain and extreme temperature change This is based on neurological data showing the thalamic hippocampal orbitofrontal insula and midbrain sites are the key to consciousness of thirst 143 These scientists also point out that the cortex might not be as important to primary consciousness as some neuroscientists have believed 143 Evidence of this lies in the fact that studies show that systematically disabling parts of the cortex in animals does not remove consciousness Another study found that children born without a cortex are conscious Instead of cortical mechanisms these scientists emphasize brainstem mechanisms as essential to consciousness 143 Still these scientists concede that higher order consciousness does involve the cortex and complex communication between different areas of the brain While animals with primary consciousness have long term memory they lack explicit narrative and at best can only deal with the immediate scene in the remembered present While they still have an advantage over animals lacking such ability evolution has brought forth a growing complexity in consciousness particularly in mammals Animals with this complexity are said to have secondary consciousness Secondary consciousness is seen in animals with semantic capabilities such as the four great apes It is present in its richest form in the human species which is unique in possessing complex language made up of syntax and semantics In considering how the neural mechanisms underlying primary consciousness arose and were maintained during evolution it is proposed that at some time around the divergence of reptiles into mammals and then into birds the embryological development of large numbers of new reciprocal connections allowed rich re entrant activity to take place between the more posterior brain systems carrying out perceptual categorization and the more frontally located systems responsible for value category memory 58 The ability of an animal to relate a present complex scene to their own previous history of learning conferred an adaptive evolutionary advantage At much later evolutionary epochs further re entrant circuits appeared that linked semantic and linguistic performance to categorical and conceptual memory systems This development enabled the emergence of secondary consciousness 144 145 Ursula Voss of the Universitat Bonn believes that the theory of protoconsciousness 146 may serve as adequate explanation for self recognition found in birds as they would develop secondary consciousness during REM sleep 147 She added that many types of birds have very sophisticated language systems Don Kuiken of the University of Alberta finds such research interesting as well as if we continue to study consciousness with animal models with differing types of consciousness we would be able to separate the different forms of reflectiveness found in today s world 148 For the advocates of the idea of a secondary consciousness self recognition serves as a critical component and a key defining measure What is most interesting then is the evolutionary appeal that arises with the concept of self recognition In non human species and in children the mirror test see above has been used as an indicator of self awareness Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness editCambridge Declaration on Consciousness The absence of a neocortex does not appear to preclude an organism from experiencing affective states Convergent evidence indicates that non human animals have the neuroanatomical neurochemical and neurophysiological substrates of conscious states along with the capacity to exhibit intentional behaviors Consequently the weight of evidence indicates that humans are not unique in possessing the neurological substrates that generate consciousness Non human animals including all mammals and birds and many other creatures including octopuses also possess these neurological substrates 149 In 2012 a group of neuroscientists attending a conference on Consciousness in Human and non Human Animals at the University of Cambridge in the UK signed the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness see box on the right 1 150 In the accompanying text they unequivocally asserted 1 The field of Consciousness research is rapidly evolving Abundant new techniques and strategies for human and non human animal research have been developed Consequently more data is becoming readily available and this calls for a periodic reevaluation of previously held preconceptions in this field Studies of non human animals have shown that homologous brain circuits correlated with conscious experience and perception can be selectively facilitated and disrupted to assess whether they are in fact necessary for those experiences Moreover in humans new non invasive techniques are readily available to survey the correlates of consciousness 1 The neural substrates of emotions do not appear to be confined to cortical structures In fact subcortical neural networks aroused during affective states in humans are also critically important for generating emotional behaviors in animals Artificial arousal of the same brain regions generates corresponding behavior and feeling states in both humans and non human animals Wherever in the brain one evokes instinctual emotional behaviors in non human animals many of the ensuing behaviors are consistent with experienced feeling states including those internal states that are rewarding and punishing Deep brain stimulation of these systems in humans can also generate similar affective states Systems associated with affect are concentrated in subcortical regions where neural homologies abound Young human and non human animals without neocortices retain these brain mind functions Furthermore neural circuits supporting behavioral electrophysiological states of attentiveness sleep and decision making appear to have arisen in evolution as early as the invertebrate radiation being evident in insects and cephalopod mollusks e g octopus 1 Birds appear to offer in their behavior neurophysiology and neuroanatomy a striking case of parallel evolution of consciousness Evidence of near human like levels of consciousness has been most dramatically observed in grey parrots Mammalian and avian emotional networks and cognitive microcircuitries appear to be far more homologous than previously thought Moreover certain species of birds have been found to exhibit neural sleep patterns similar to those of mammals including REM sleep and as was demonstrated in zebra finches neurophysiological patterns previously thought to require a mammalian neocortex Magpies in particular have been shown to exhibit striking similarities to humans great apes dolphins and elephants in studies of mirror self recognition 1 In humans the effect of certain hallucinogens appears to be associated with a disruption in cortical feedforward and feedback processing Pharmacological interventions in non human animals with compounds known to affect conscious behavior in humans can lead to similar perturbations in behavior in non human animals In humans there is evidence to suggest that awareness is correlated with cortical activity which does not exclude possible contributions by subcortical or early cortical processing as in visual awareness Evidence that human and non human animal emotional feelings arise from homologous subcortical brain networks provide compelling evidence for evolutionarily shared primal affective qualia 1 Examples edit nbsp Theories of brain evolution in animals The old scala naturae model versus the modern approach A common image is the scala naturae the ladder of nature on which animals of different species occupy successively higher rungs with humans typically at the top 151 A more useful approach has been to recognize that different animals may have different kinds of cognitive processes which are better understood in terms of the ways in which they are cognitively adapted to their different ecological niches than by positing any kind of hierarchy 152 153 Mammals edit See also Elephant cognition Primate cognition and Cetacean intelligence Self awareness Dogs edit See also Dog intelligence Dogs were previously listed as non self aware animals Traditionally self consciousness was evaluated via the mirror test But dogs and many other animals are not as visually oriented 154 155 A 2015 study claims that the sniff test of self recognition STSR provides significant evidence of self awareness in dogs and could play a crucial role in showing that this capacity is not a specific feature of only great apes humans and a few other animals but it depends on the way in which researchers try to verify it According to the biologist Roberto Cazzolla Gatti who published the study the innovative approach to test the self awareness with a smell test highlights the need to shift the paradigm of the anthropocentric idea of consciousness to a species specific perspective 84 156 This study has been confirmed by another study 157 Birds edit See also Bird intelligence Grey parrots edit Research with captive grey parrots especially Irene Pepperberg s work with an individual named Alex has demonstrated they possess the ability to associate simple human words with meanings and to intelligently apply the abstract concepts of shape colour number zero sense etc According to Pepperberg and other scientists they perform many cognitive tasks at the level of dolphins chimpanzees and even human toddlers 158 Another notable African grey is N kisi which in 2004 was said to have a vocabulary of over 950 words which she used in creative ways 159 For example when Jane Goodall visited N kisi in his New York home he greeted her with Got a chimp because he had seen pictures of her with chimpanzees in Africa 160 In 2011 research led by Dalila Bovet of Paris West University Nanterre La Defense demonstrated grey parrots were able to coordinate and collaborate with each other to an extent They were able to solve problems such as two birds having to pull strings at the same time to obtain food In another example one bird stood on a perch to release a food laden tray while the other pulled the tray out from the test apparatus Both would then feed The birds were observed waiting for their partners to perform the necessary actions so their behaviour could be synchronized The parrots appeared to express individual preferences as to which of the other test birds they would work with 161 Corvids edit nbsp The Eurasian magpie passes the mirror test It was recently thought that self recognition was restricted to mammals with large brains and highly evolved social cognition but absent from animals without a neocortex However in 2008 an investigation of self recognition in corvids was conducted revealing the ability of self recognition in the magpie Mammals and birds inherited the same brain components from their last common ancestor nearly 300 million years ago and have since independently evolved and formed significantly different brain types The results of the mirror test showed that although magpies do not have a neocortex they are capable of understanding that a mirror image belongs to their own body The findings show that magpies respond in the mirror test in a manner similar to apes dolphins killer whales pigs and elephants This is a remarkable capability that although not fully concrete in its determination of self recognition is at least a prerequisite of self recognition This is not only of interest regarding the convergent evolution of social intelligence it is also valuable for an understanding of the general principles that govern cognitive evolution and their underlying neural mechanisms The magpies were chosen to study based on their empathy lifestyle a possible precursor for their ability of self awareness 67 A 2020 study found that carrion crows show a neuronal response that correlates with their perception of a stimulus which they argue to be an empirical marker of avian sensory consciousness the conscious perception of sensory input in the crows which do not have a cerebral cortex The study thereby substantiates the theory that conscious perception does not require a cerebral cortex and that the basic foundations for it and possibly for human type consciousness may have evolved before the last common ancestor gt 320 Mya or independently in birds 162 163 A related study showed that the birds pallium s neuroarchitecture is reminiscent of the mammalian cortex 164 Invertebrates edit nbsp Octopus travelling with shells collected for protectionSee also Cephalopod intelligence and Pain in invertebrates Octopuses are highly intelligent possibly more so than any other order of invertebrates The level of their intelligence and learning capability are debated 165 166 167 168 but maze and problem solving studies show they have both short and long term memory Octopus have a highly complex nervous system only part of which is localized in their brain Two thirds of an octopus s neurons are found in the nerve cords of their arms Octopus arms show a variety of complex reflex actions that persist even when they have no input from the brain 169 Unlike vertebrates the complex motor skills of octopuses are not organized in their brain using an internal somatotopic map of their body instead using a non somatotopic system unique to large brained invertebrates 170 Some octopuses such as the mimic octopus move their arms in ways that emulate the shape and movements of other sea creatures In laboratory studies octopuses can easily be trained to distinguish between different shapes and patterns They reportedly use observational learning 171 although the validity of these findings is contested 165 166 Octopuses have also been observed to play repeatedly releasing bottles or toys into a circular current in their aquariums and then catching them 172 Octopuses often escape from their aquarium and sometimes enter others They have boarded fishing boats and opened holds to eat crabs 167 At least four specimens of the veined octopus Amphioctopus marginatus have been witnessed retrieving discarded coconut shells manipulating them and then reassembling them to use as shelter 173 174 Shamanistic and religious views editShamanistic and other traditional cultures and folk tales speak of animal spirits and the consciousness of animals 175 176 In India Jains consider all the jivas living organisms including plants animals and insects as conscious According to Jain scriptures even nigoda microscopic creatures possess high levels of consciousness and have decision making abilities citation needed Researchers editSee also the categories Ethologists and Consciousness researchers and theorists Some contributors to relevant research on animal consciousness include Marc Bekoff Peter Carruthers Antonio Damasio Marian Stamp Dawkins Frans de Waal Shaun Gallagher Gordon G Gallup Donald Griffin Nicholas Humphrey Christof Koch Thomas Nagel Irene Pepperberg Bernard Rollin Jeffrey M Schwartz Jakob von UexkullSee also editAnimal cognition Animal communication Animal rights Animal rights by country or territory Artificial consciousness Awareness Biosemiotics Brain in a vat Cognitive ethology Consciousness Descartes Error Emotion in animals Epiphenomenalism Explanatory gap Ethics of uncertain sentience Externalism Hard problem of consciousness Human animal communication Internalism and externalism Meat paradox Mind body problem Neural correlates of consciousness Philosophy of mind Plant perception paranormal Problem of other minds Self awareness in animals Sentience Sentient beings Buddhism Spindle neuron Veganism ZoosemioticsReferences edit a b c d e f g h i The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness Archive 7 July 2012 Written by Philip Low and edited by Jaak Panksepp Diana Reiss David Edelman Bruno Van Swinderen Philip Low and Christof Koch University of Cambridge consciousness Merriam Webster Retrieved 22 April 2014 a b Robert van Gulick 2004 Consciousness Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Farthing G 1992 The Psychology of Consciousness Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 728668 3 a b John Searle 2005 Consciousness In Honderich T ed The Oxford companion to philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Colin Allen 6 February 2024 Edward N Zalta ed Animal consciousness Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition Peter Carruthers 1999 Sympathy and subjectivity Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 4 465 482 doi 10 1080 00048409912349231 S2CID 49227874 Miller Michael R 2013 Descartes on Animals Revisited Journal of Philosophical Research 38 89 114 doi 10 5840 jpr2013386 Thomas Nagel 1991 Ch 12 What is it like to be a bat Mortal Questions Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 40676 5 Douglas Hofstadter 1981 Reflections on What Is It Like to Be a Bat In Douglas Hofstadter Daniel Dennett eds The Mind s I Basic Books pp 403 414 ISBN 978 0 7108 0352 8 a b Donald Griffin 2001 Animal Minds Beyond Cognition to Consciousness University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 30865 4 a b Burghardt Gordon M 1985 Animal awareness Current perceptions and historical perspective PDF American Psychologist 40 8 905 919 doi 10 1037 0003 066X 40 8 905 PMID 3898938 Archived from the original PDF on 16 September 2012 Carr H 1927 The interpretation of the animal mind Psychological Review 34 2 87 106 94 doi 10 1037 h0072244 Andrews K 2014 The Animal Mind An Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition Taylor amp Francis p 51 ISBN 978 1 317 67676 8 Robert M Young 1996 The mind body problem In RC Olby GN Cantor JR Christie MJS Hodges eds Companion to the History of Modern Science Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 ed Taylor and Francis pp 702 11 ISBN 978 0415145787 Robinson Howard 3 November 2011 Dualism In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2011 Edition Bryan S Turner 2008 The Body and Society Explorations in Social Theory 3rd ed Sage Publications p 78 ISBN 978 1412929875 a rejection of any dualism between mind and body and a consequent insistence on the argument that the body is never simply a physical object but always an embodiment of consciousness Kim Jaegwan 1995 Emergent properties In Honderich Ted ed Problems in the Philosophy of Mind Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press p 240 ISBN 9780198661320 Pinel J 2009 Psychobiology 7th ed Pearson Allyn and Bacon ISBN 978 0205548927 LeDoux J 2002 The Synaptic Self How Our Brains Become Who We Are Viking Penguin ISBN 978 88 7078 795 5 Russell S Norvig P 2010 Artificial Intelligence A Modern Approach 3rd ed Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0136042594 Dawkins R 2006 The Selfish Gene 3rd ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0199291144 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Epiphenomenalism Retrieved 27 December 2016 Huxley T H 1874 On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata and its History The Fortnightly Review n s 16 555 580 Reprinted in Method and Results Essays by Thomas H Huxley New York D Appleton and Company 1898 Gallagher S 2006 Where s the action Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will In W Banks S Pockett and S Gallagher Does Consciousness Cause Behavior An Investigation of the Nature of Intuition 109 124 Cambridge Massachusetts MIT Press T H Huxley 1874 On the hypothesis that animals are automata and its history The Fortnightly Review 16 253 555 580 Bibcode 1874Natur 10 362 doi 10 1038 010362a0 W James 1879 Are we automata Mind 4 13 1 22 doi 10 1093 mind os 4 13 1 B I B Lindahl 1997 Consciousness and biological evolution Journal of Theoretical Biology 187 4 613 629 Bibcode 1997JThBi 187 613L doi 10 1006 jtbi 1996 0394 PMID 9299304 Karl R Popper John C Eccles 1977 The Self and Its Brain Springer International ISBN 978 0 387 08307 0 a b Rollin Bernard The Unheeded Cry Animal Consciousness Animal Pain and Science New York Oxford University Press 1989 pp xii 117 118 cited in Carbone 2004 p 150 Ricard Matthieu 2016 A Plea for the Animals The Moral Philosophical and Evolutionary Imperative to Treat All Beings with Compassion First English ed Boulder Shambhala p 132 ISBN 978 0 8348 4054 6 OCLC 960042213 Griffin DR Speck GB 2004 New evidence of animal consciousness PDF Animal Cognition 7 1 5 18 doi 10 1007 s10071 003 0203 x PMID 14658059 S2CID 8650837 Archived from the original PDF on 21 January 2013 Retrieved 29 November 2013 The Ethics of research involving animals Archived 25 June 2008 at the Wayback Machine Nuffield Council on Bioethics Accessed 27 February 2008 Allen C 1998 Assessing animal cognition ethological and philosophical perspectives J Anim Sci 76 1 42 7 doi 10 2527 1998 76142x PMID 9464883 Archived from the original on 21 January 2016 Retrieved 5 October 2015 Animal Sentience An Interdisciplinary Journal on Animal Feeling Vimal RLP Sansthana DA 2010 On the Quest of Defining Consciousness PDF Mind and Matter 8 1 93 121 Hirstein W 2013 Conscious states Where are they in the brain and what are their necessary ingredients Mens Sana Monographs 11 1 230 8 doi 10 4103 0973 1229 109343 PMC 3653223 PMID 23678244 Dulany D E 2014 What Explains Consciousness Or What Consciousness Explains Mens Sana Monographs 12 1 11 34 doi 10 4103 0973 1229 130283 PMC 4037891 PMID 24891796 De Sousa Avinash 2013 Towards an integrative theory of consciousness Part 1 Neurobiological and cognitive models Mens Sana Monographs 11 1 100 50 doi 10 4103 0973 1229 109335 PMC 3653219 PMID 23678241 Pereira A Jr 2013 A Commentary on De Sousa s Towards An Integrative Theory of Consciousness Mens Sana Monographs 11 1 210 29 doi 10 4103 0973 1229 104495 PMC 3653222 PMID 23678243 Richard Dawkins The Selfish Gene Human Brain Function by Richard Frackowiak and 7 other neuroscientists page 269 in chapter 16 The Neural Correlates of Consciousness consisting of 32 pages published 2004 consciousness Merriam Webster Retrieved 4 June 2012 Susan Schneider amp Max Velmans 2008 Introduction In Max Velmans amp Susan Schneider eds The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness Wiley ISBN 978 0 470 75145 9 Richard P Lipka Thomas M Brinthaupt Self perspectives Across the Life Span p 228 SUNY Press 1992 ISBN 978 0 7914 1003 5 Gallup Jr GG Anderson JR Shillito DJ 2002 The mirror test PDF In Bekoff M Allen C Burghardt GM eds The cognitive animal Empirical and Theoretical perspectives on animal cognition University of Chicago Press pp 325 333 Archived from the original PDF on 6 October 2014 Haikonen POA 2007 Reflections of consciousness The mirror test Proceedings of the 2007 AAAI Fall Symposium on Consciousness pp 67 71 Asendorpf J B Warkentin V Baudonniere P M 1996 Self Awareness and Other Awareness II Mirror Self Recognition Social Contingency Awareness and Synchronic Imitation Developmental Psychology 32 2 313 321 doi 10 1037 0012 1649 32 2 313 S2CID 21762291 The World First Self Aware Robot and the Success of Mirror Image Cognition Archived 3 February 2009 at the Wayback Machine Lecture at the Karlsruhe University and the Munich University Germany 8 November 2006 Moreno Raul Arrabales 8 January 2008 Can a robot pass the mirror test Conscious Robots Archived from the original on 5 January 2013 Eric R Kandel 2007 In Search of Memory The Emergence of a New Science of Mind WW Norton p 9 ISBN 978 0393329377 Oswald Hanfling 2002 Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life Psychology Press pp 108 109 ISBN 978 0415256452 A term attributed to David Chalmers by Eugene O Mills 1999 Giving up on the hard problem of consciousness In Jonathan Shear ed Explaining Consciousness The Hard Problem MIT Press p 109 ISBN 978 0262692212 Damasio A 1999 The Feeling of What Happens Body Emotion and the Making of Consciousness Harcourt Brace 1999 Damasio A 2003 Feelings of emotion and the self In J LeDoux J Debiec amp H Moss Eds Self from Soul to Brain Vol 1001 pp 253 261 New York New York Acad Sciences Chalmers D J Facing up to the problem of consciousness J Cons Stud 2 1995 200 Chalmers D J The conscious mind In search of a fundamental theory Oxford University Press New York 1996 a b c d Edelman G M 2003 Naturalizing consciousness a theoretical framework Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 100 9 5520 5524 Bibcode 2003PNAS 100 5520E doi 10 1073 pnas 0931349100 PMC 154377 PMID 12702758 Edelman G M Tononi G 2000 A Universe of Consciousness How Matter Becomes Imagination New York Basic Books Linden Eugene 2000 The parrot s lament and other true tales of animal intrigue intelligence and ingenuity Thorndike Me G K Hall ISBN 978 0 7838 9031 9 Animal consciousness what matters and why Daniel Dennett a b Block Ned 1995 On a confusion about a function of consciousness PDF The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 2 227 287 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 207 6880 doi 10 1017 s0140525x00038188 S2CID 146168066 Barron A B Klein C 2016 What insects can tell us about the origins of consciousness Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113 18 4900 4908 Bibcode 2016PNAS 113 4900B doi 10 1073 pnas 1520084113 PMC 4983823 PMID 27091981 Ben Haim Moshe Shay Monte Olga Dal Fagan Nicholas A Dunham Yarrow Hassin Ran R Chang Steve W C Santos Laurie R 13 April 2021 Disentangling perceptual awareness from nonconscious processing in rhesus monkeys Macaca mulatta Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 118 15 e2017543118 Bibcode 2021PNAS 11817543B doi 10 1073 pnas 2017543118 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 8053918 PMID 33785543 a b Plotnik JM de Waal FBM Reiss D 2006 Self recognition in an Asian elephant Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 103 45 17053 17057 Bibcode 2006PNAS 10317053P doi 10 1073 pnas 0608062103 PMC 1636577 PMID 17075063 Bischof Kohler D 1991 The development of empathy in infants In M E Lamb amp H Keller eds Infant Development Perspectives from German speaking countries 245 273 a b c d Prior H Schwarz A Gunturkun O 2008 Mirror induced behavior in the magpie Pica pica Evidence of self recognition PLOS Biology 6 8 1642 1650 doi 10 1371 journal pbio 0060202 PMC 2517622 PMID 18715117 Gallup GG Jr 1970 Chimpanzees self recognition Science 167 3914 86 87 Bibcode 1970Sci 167 86G doi 10 1126 science 167 3914 86 PMID 4982211 S2CID 145295899 Walraven V van Elsacker L Verheyen R 1995 Reactions of a group of pygmy chimpanzees Pan paniscus to their mirror images evidence of self recognition Primates 36 145 150 doi 10 1007 bf02381922 S2CID 38985498 Patterson FGP Cohn RH 1994 Self recognition and self awareness in lowland gorillas In Parker ST Mitchell RW editors Self awareness in animals and humans developmental perspectives New York New York Cambridge University Press pp 273 290 Marten K Psarakos S 1995 Evidence of self awareness in the bottlenose dolphin Tursiops truncatus In Parker S T Mitchell R Boccia M eds Self awareness in Animals and Humans Developmental Perspectives Cambridge University Press pp 361 379 Archived from the original on 13 October 2008 Reiss D Marino L 2001 Mirror self recognition in the bottlenose dolphin A case of cognitive convergence Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 98 10 5937 5942 Bibcode 2001PNAS 98 5937R doi 10 1073 pnas 101086398 PMC 33317 PMID 11331768 Delfour F Marten K 2001 Mirror image processing in three marine mammal species Killer whales Orcinus orca false killer whales Pseudorca crassidens and California sea lions Zalophus californianus Behavioural Processes 53 3 181 190 doi 10 1016 s0376 6357 01 00134 6 PMID 11334706 S2CID 31124804 Prior Helmut Schwarz A Gunturkun O De Waal Frans 2008 De Waal Frans ed Mirror Induced Behavior in the Magpie Pica pica Evidence of Self Recognition PLOS Biology 6 8 e202 doi 10 1371 journal pbio 0060202 PMC 2517622 PMID 18715117 Uchino Emiko Watanabe Shigeru 1 November 2014 Self recognition in pigeons revisited Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 102 3 327 334 doi 10 1002 jeab 112 ISSN 1938 3711 PMID 25307108 S2CID 31499014 Povinelli DJ Rulf AB Landau KR Bierschwale DT 1993 Self recognition in chimpanzees Pan troglodytes distribution ontogeny and patterns of emergence J Comp Psychol 107 4 347 372 doi 10 1037 0735 7036 107 4 347 PMID 8112048 Hyatt CW 1998 Responses of gibbons Hylobates lar to their mirror images Am J Primatol 45 3 307 311 doi 10 1002 SICI 1098 2345 1998 45 3 lt 307 AID AJP7 gt 3 0 CO 2 PMID 9651653 S2CID 196596255 Ye Yvaine A species of fish has passed the mirror test for the first time New Scientist This tiny fish can recognize itself in a mirror Is it self aware Animals 7 February 2019 Archived from the original on 17 September 2018 Retrieved 11 May 2020 Ye Yvaine A species of fish has passed the mirror test for the first time New Scientist Retrieved 11 May 2020 Kohda Masanori Takashi Hatta Takeyama Tmohiro Awata Satoshi Tanaka Hirokazu Asai Jun ya Jordan Alex 21 August 2018 Cleaner wrasse pass the mark test What are the implications for consciousness and self awareness testing in animals bioRxiv 397067 doi 10 1101 397067 Lea SEG 2010 Concept learning in nonprimate mammals In search of evidence In D Mareschal PC Quinn and SEG Lea The Making of Human Concepts pp 173 199 Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199549221 The Superior Human Documentary Transcription on the official website a b c Cazzolla Gatti Roberto 2015 Self consciousness beyond the looking glass and what dogs found there Ethology Ecology amp Evolution 28 2 232 240 doi 10 1080 03949370 2015 1102777 ISSN 0394 9370 S2CID 217507938 Suzuki Ryuji Buck John Tyack Peter January 2005 The use of Zipf s law in animal communication analysis PDF Animal Behaviour 69 1 F9 F17 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 112 5869 doi 10 1016 j anbehav 2004 08 004 S2CID 14968885 Carter Alan 2005 Animals Pain and Morality Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 1 17 22 doi 10 1111 j 1468 5930 2005 00289 x PMID 15948329 Sagan Carl and Ann Druyan 1993 Shadows of Forgotten Ancestors Ballantine Books ISBN 9780345384720 Webster John 27 February 2005 The secret life of moody cows The Times Leiber Justin December 1988 Cartesian Linguistics Philosophia 18 4 309 46 doi 10 1007 BF02380646 S2CID 189835510 No Face but Plants Like Life Too Carol Kaesuk Yoon The New York Times Haselton M G Nettle D amp Andrews P W 2005 The evolution of cognitive bias In D M Buss ed The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology Hoboken NJ US John Wiley amp Sons Inc pp 724 746 Bless H Fiedler K amp Strack F 2004 Social cognition How individuals construct social reality Hove and New York Psychology Press p 2 Mendl M Burman O H P Parker R M A amp Paul E S 2009 Cognitive bias as an indicator of animal emotion and welfare emerging evidence and underlying mechanisms Applied Animal Behaviour Science 118 3 4 161 181 doi 10 1016 j applanim 2009 02 023 Harding EJ Paul ES Mendl M 2004 Animal behaviour cognitive bias and affective state Nature 427 6972 312 Bibcode 2004Natur 427 312H doi 10 1038 427312a PMID 14737158 S2CID 4411418 Rygula R Pluta H P Popik 2012 Laughing rats are optimistic PLOS ONE 7 12 e51959 Bibcode 2012PLoSO 751959R doi 10 1371 journal pone 0051959 PMC 3530570 PMID 23300582 LeDoux J 2012 Rethinking the emotional brain Neuron 73 4 653 676 doi 10 1016 j neuron 2012 02 004 PMC 3625946 PMID 22365542 LeDoux JE 2014 Coming to terms with fear Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 111 8 2871 2878 Bibcode 2014PNAS 111 2871L doi 10 1073 pnas 1400335111 PMC 3939902 PMID 24501122 LeDoux JE 2015 Feelings What are they amp how does the brain make them PDF Daedalus 144 1 96 111 doi 10 1162 DAED a 00319 S2CID 57561276 Archived from the original PDF on 1 May 2015 Retrieved 5 October 2015 LeDoux JE 2015 Anxious Using the Brain to Understand and Treat Fear and Anxiety Penguin Publishing Group ISBN 9781101619940 Neuroscience Merriam Webster Medical Dictionary a b Weisberg DS Keil FC Goodstein J Rawson E Gray JR 2008 The seductive allure of neuroscience explanations Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 20 3 470 477 doi 10 1162 jocn 2008 20040 PMC 2778755 PMID 18004955 Koch Christof 2004 The quest for consciousness a neurobiological approach Englewood US CO Roberts amp Company Publishers p 304 ISBN 978 0 9747077 0 9 See here Archived 13 March 2013 at the Wayback Machine for a glossary of related terms Crick F Koch C 1998 Consciousness and neuroscience PDF Cereb Cortex 8 2 97 107 doi 10 1093 cercor 8 2 97 PMID 9542889 Full text Sian Beilock Carr T H MacMahon C and Starkes J L 2002 When paying attention becomes counterproductive impact of divided versus skill focused attention on novice and experienced performance of sensorimotor skills J Exp Psychol Appl 8 6 16 Adamantidis A R Zhang F Aravanis A M Deisseroth K and de Lecea L 2007 Neural substrates of awakening probed with optogenetic control of hypocretin neurons Nature Rose James D 2002 The neurobehavioral nature of fishes and the question of awareness and pain PDF Reviews in Fisheries Science 10 1 1 38 Bibcode 2002RvFS 10 1R CiteSeerX 10 1 1 598 8119 doi 10 1080 20026491051668 S2CID 16220451 Archived from the original PDF on 10 October 2012 Anderson John R 2004 Cognitive psychology and its implications 6th ed Worth Publishers p 519 ISBN 978 0 7167 0110 1 Chavajay Pablo Barbara Rogoff 1999 Cultural variation in management of attention by children and their caregivers Developmental Psychology 35 4 1079 1090 doi 10 1037 0012 1649 35 4 1079 PMID 10442876 Kaiser J Lutzenberger W 2003 Induced gamma band activity and human brain function Neuroscientist 9 6 475 84 doi 10 1177 1073858403259137 PMID 14678580 S2CID 23574844 Layers or levels of consciousness Archived 10 April 2013 at the Wayback Machine Nash J Madeleine 18 October 1999 Mystery Of Consciousness Time Vol 154 no 16 Archived from the original on 11 February 2001 a b Metcalfe J amp Shimamura A P 1994 Metacognition knowing about knowing Cambridge Massachusetts MIT Press Couchman Justin J Coutinho M V C Beran M J Smith J D 2010 Beyond Stimulus Cues and Reinforcement Signals A New Approach to Animal Metacognition PDF Journal of Comparative Psychology 124 4 356 368 doi 10 1037 a0020129 PMC 2991470 PMID 20836592 Archived from the original PDF on 24 March 2012 Schraw Gregory 1998 Promoting general metacognitive awareness Instructional Science 26 1 2 113 125 doi 10 1023 A 1003044231033 S2CID 15715418 Oxford Psychology Dictionary metacognition full citation needed Couchman Justin J Coutinho M V C Beran M J Smith J D 2010 Beyond Stimulus Cues and Reinforcement Signals A New Approach to Animal Metacognition PDF Journal of Comparative Psychology 124 4 356 368 doi 10 1037 a0020129 PMC 2991470 PMID 20836592 Metacognition Known unknowns Issue 2582 of New Scientist magazine subscribers only Rats Capable Of Reflecting On Mental Processes ScienceDaily 9 March 2007 Foote AL Crystal JD March 2007 Metacognition in the rat Curr Biol 17 6 551 5 doi 10 1016 j cub 2007 01 061 PMC 1861845 PMID 17346969 Foote Allison L Crystal J D 20 March 2007 Metacognition in the Rat Current Biology 17 6 551 555 doi 10 1016 j cub 2007 01 061 PMC 1861845 PMID 17346969 Archived from the original on 3 July 2012 Smith J David Beran M J Couchman J J Coutinho M V C 2008 The Comparative Study of Metacognition Sharper Paradigms Safer Inferences Psychonomic Bulletin amp Review 15 4 679 691 doi 10 3758 pbr 15 4 679 PMC 4607312 PMID 18792496 Jozefowiez J Staddon J E R Cerutti D T 2009 Metacognition in animals how do we know that they know Comparative Cognition amp Behavior Reviews 4 29 39 doi 10 3819 ccbr 2009 40003 Rizzolatti Giacomo Craighero Laila 2004 The mirror neuron system PDF Annual Review of Neuroscience 27 169 192 doi 10 1146 annurev neuro 27 070203 144230 PMID 15217330 S2CID 1729870 Keysers Christian 2010 Mirror Neurons PDF Current Biology 19 21 R971 973 doi 10 1016 j cub 2009 08 026 PMID 19922849 S2CID 12668046 Archived from the original PDF on 19 January 2013 a b c Keysers Christian 23 June 2011 The Empathic Brain Kindle Christian Keysers Valeria Gazzola 2006 Towards a unifying neural theory of social cognition In Anders Ende Unghofer Kissler Wildgruber eds Understanding Emotions PDF Progress in Brain Research Vol 156 pp 379 401 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 132 4591 doi 10 1016 S0079 6123 06 56021 2 ISBN 9780444521828 ISSN 0079 6123 PMID 17015092 Archived from the original PDF on 30 June 2007 Michael Arbib The Mirror System Hypothesis Linking Language to Theory of Mind Archived 29 March 2009 at the Wayback Machine 2005 retrieved 17 February 2006 Theoret Hugo Pascual Leone Alvaro 2002 Language Acquisition Do as You Hear Current Biology 12 21 R736 7 doi 10 1016 S0960 9822 02 01251 4 PMID 12419204 S2CID 12867585 Blakeslee Sandra 10 January 2006 Cells That Read Minds The New York Times Science Oberman L Ramachandran V S 2009 Reflections on the Mirror Neuron System Their Evolutionary Functions Beyond Motor Representation In Pineda J A ed Mirror Neuron Systems The Role of Mirroring Processes in Social Cognition Humana Press pp 39 62 ISBN 978 1 934115 34 3 Ramachandran V S 1 January 2009 Self Awareness The Last Frontier Edge Foundation web essay Retrieved 26 July 2011 Nichols S Grantham T 2000 Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness Philosophy of Science 67 4 648 670 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 515 9722 doi 10 1086 392859 JSTOR 188711 S2CID 16484193 Freeman and Herron Evolutionary Analysis 2007 Pearson Education NJ Peter Arhem B I B Lindahl Paul R Manger amp Ann B Butler 2008 On the origin of consciousness some amniote scenarios In Hans Liljenstrom amp Peter Arhem eds Consciousness Transitions Phylogenetic Ontogenetic and Physiological Aspects Elsevier ISBN 978 0 444 52977 0 Eccles J C 1992 Evolution of consciousness Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 89 16 7320 7324 Bibcode 1992PNAS 89 7320E doi 10 1073 pnas 89 16 7320 JSTOR 2360081 PMC 49701 PMID 1502142 Peters Frederic Consciousness as Recursive Spatiotemporal Self Location Baars Bernard J A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness 1993 Cambridge University Press a b c d Gaulin Steven J C and Donald H McBurney 2003 Evolutionary psychology Prentice Hall pp 101 121 ISBN 978 0 13 111529 3 Seth A K Baars B J 2005 Neural Darwinism and consciousness Consciousness and Cognition 14 1 140 168 doi 10 1016 j concog 2004 08 008 PMID 15766895 S2CID 6262356 a b Edelman G 2004 Wider than the sky The phenomenal gift of consciousness Yale Univ Pr Edelman G M 1992 Bright Air Brilliant Fire On the Matter of the Mind Basic Books New York a b c Merker B 2007 Consciousness without a cerebral cortex A challenge for neuroscience and medicine Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 1 63 81 doi 10 1017 s0140525x07000891 PMID 17475053 S2CID 16994436 Edelman G M 2004 Wider than the sky a revolutionary view of consciousness Penguin Press Science London UK Edelman G M 200 Second Nature Brain Science and Human Knowledge Yale University Press New Haven CT Hobson J A 2009 REM sleep and dreaming towards a theory of protoconsciousness PDF Nature Reviews Neuroscience 10 11 803 862 doi 10 1038 nrn2716 PMID 19794431 S2CID 205505278 permanent dead link Voss Ursula 2010 Changes in EEG pre and post awakening Science of Awakening International Review of Neurobiology Vol 93 pp 23 56 doi 10 1016 S0074 7742 10 93002 X ISBN 9780123813244 PMID 20970000 Kuiken Don 2010 Primary and secondary consciousness during dreaming International Journal of Dream Research 3 1 21 25 Low Philip et al 2012 The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness Publicly proclaimed in Cambridge UK on 7 July 2012 at the Francis Crick Memorial Conference on Consciousness in Human and non Human Animals Consciousness in Human and non Human Animals Francis Crick Memorial Conference 7 July 2012 Cambridge UK Campbell C B G Hodos W 1991 The Scala Naturae revisited Evolutionary scales and anagenesis in comparative psychology J Comp Psychol 105 3 211 221 doi 10 1037 0735 7036 105 3 211 PMID 1935002 Shettleworth 1998 Reznikova 2007 Crew Bec 10 December 2015 Dogs Show Signs of Self Consciousness in New Sniff Test ScienceAlert Coren Stanley 2008 How Dogs Think Simon and Schuster ISBN 9781847397065 Retrieved 8 July 2018 The important thing to remember is that dogs are not as visually oriented as humans Dogs and probably many other animals have a conscience too en tsu ru Retrieved 5 December 2016 Dogs have self awareness It was confirmed by STSR tests en tsu ru Tomsk State University Retrieved 8 July 2018 PEPPERBERG Irene M 30 June 2009 The Alex Studies cognitive and communicative abilities of grey parrots Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674041998 Nkisi Audio Text 1 www sheldrake org Maria Armental 8 May 2008 Jane Goodall attends opening of bird sanctuary www projo com Archived from the original on 29 June 2011 Peron F Rat Fischer L Bovet D 2011 Cooperative problem solving in African grey parrots Psittacus erithacus Animal Cognition 14 4 545 553 doi 10 1007 s10071 011 0389 2 PMID 21384141 S2CID 5616569 Researchers show conscious processes in birds brains for the first time phys org Retrieved 9 October 2020 Nieder Andreas Wagener Lysann Rinnert Paul 25 September 2020 A neural correlate of sensory consciousness in a corvid bird Science 369 6511 1626 1629 Bibcode 2020Sci 369 1626N doi 10 1126 science abb1447 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 32973028 S2CID 221881862 Retrieved 9 October 2020 Stacho Martin Herold Christina Rook Noemi Wagner Hermann Axer Markus Amunts Katrin Gunturkun Onur 25 September 2020 A cortex like canonical circuit in the avian forebrain Science 369 6511 eabc5534 doi 10 1126 science abc5534 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 32973004 S2CID 221882087 Retrieved 16 October 2020 a b What is this octopus thinking Archived 7 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine By Garry Hamilton a b NFW org Archived 15 December 2009 at the Wayback Machine Is the octopus really the invertebrate intellect of the sea by Doug Stewart In National Wildlife Feb Mar 1997 vol 35 no 2 a b Giant Octopus Mighty but Secretive Denizen of the Deep Slate com How Smart is the Octopus Yekutieli Yoram Sagiv Zohar Roni Aharonov Ranit Enge Yaakov Hochner Binyamin Flash Tamar 2005 Dynamic Model of the Octopus Arm I Biomechanics of the Octopus Reaching Movement J Neurophysiol 94 2 1443 1458 doi 10 1152 jn 00684 2004 PMID 15829594 S2CID 14711055 Zullo L Sumbre G Agnisola C Flash T Hochner B 2009 Nonsomatotopic organization of the higher motor centers in octopus Curr Biol 19 19 1632 6 doi 10 1016 j cub 2009 07 067 PMID 19765993 S2CID 15852956 Octopus twists for shrimps 25 February 2003 via news bbc co uk What behavior can we expect of octopuses By Dr Jennifer Mather Department of Psychology and Neuroscience University of Lethbridge and Roland C Anderson The Seattle Aquarium Octopus snatches coconut and runs BBC News 14 December 2009 Retrieved 20 May 2010 Coconut shelter Evidence of tool use by octopuses EduTube Educational Videos Archived from the original on 24 October 2013 Retrieved 21 December 2012 Stone Miller Rebecca 2004 Human Animal Imagery Shamanic Visions and Ancient American Aesthetics Res Anthropology and Aesthetics 45 45 47 68 doi 10 1086 RESv45n1ms20167621 JSTOR 20167621 S2CID 193758322 Metzner Ralf 1987 Transformation Process in Shamanism Alchemy and Yoga In Nicholson S Shamanism pp 233 252 Quest Books ISBN 9780835631266 Further reading editBayn T Cleeremans A and Wilken P 2009 The Oxford companion to consciousness pp 43f Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 856951 0 Bekoff Marc 2013 Why Dogs Hump and Bees Get Depressed New World Library ISBN 978 1 60868 220 1 Bekoff Marc Jane Goodall 2007 The Emotional Lives of Animals New World Library ISBN 978 1 57731 502 5 Bekoff Marc 2003 Consciousness and Self in Animals Some Reflections PDF Zygon 38 2 229 245 doi 10 1111 1467 9744 00497 permanent dead link Brown Jason W 2010 Neuropsychological Foundations of Conscious Experience pp 200 210 Les Editions Chromatika ISBN 978 2 930517 07 0 Cartmill M 2000 Animal consciousness some philosophical methodological and evolutionary problems American Zoologist 40 6 835 846 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 576 9419 doi 10 1668 0003 1569 2000 040 0835 acspma 2 0 co 2 S2CID 198153826 Dawkins Marian Stamp 2012 Why animals matter Animal consciousness animal welfare and human well being Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 958782 7 Dawkins Marian Stamp 1998 Through our eyes only The search for animal consciousness Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 850320 0 Dol Marcel 1997 Animal consciousness and animal ethics perspectives from the Netherlands Uitgeverij Van Gorcum ISBN 978 90 232 3215 5 Griffin Donald Redfield 1976 The Question of Animal Awareness Rockefeller Univ Press Griffin Donald Redfield 2001 Animal minds beyond cognition to consciousness University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 30865 4 Huxley TH 1874 On the hypothesis that animals are automata and its history PDF Nature 10 253 362 366 Bibcode 1874Natur 10 362 doi 10 1038 010362a0 S2CID 4113131 Kunkel HO 2000 Human issues in animal agriculture pp 213 214 Texas A amp M University Press ISBN 978 0 89096 927 4 Lurz Robert Animal Minds Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Phillips Clive 2009 The Welfare of Animals The Silent Majority Springer ISBN 978 1 4020 9218 3 Reznikova Zh I 2007 Animal Intelligence From Individual to Social Cognition Cambridge University Press Samorini Giorgio 2002 Animals and Psychedelics The Natural World and the Instinct to Alter Consciousness Inner Traditions Bear ISBN 978 0 89281 986 7 Review Schonfeld Martin 2006 Animal Consciousness Paradigm Change in the Life Sciences Perspectives on Science 14 3 354 381 doi 10 1162 posc 2006 14 3 354 S2CID 145128785 Shettleworth S J 1998 2010 2nd ed Cognition evolution and behavior New York Oxford University Press Smith J D Beran M J Couchman J J Coutinho M V C amp Boomer J B 2009 Animal metacognition Problems and prospects 1 Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews 4 40 53 Steiner Gary 2008 Animals and the moral community mental life moral status and kinship pp 11 12 Columbia University Press ISBN 978 0 231 14234 2 Stenholm Stig 2011 The Quest for Reality Bohr and Wittgenstein Two Complementary Views pp 88 92 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 960358 9 Van Riel Gerd 2009 Ancient perspectives on Aristotle s De anima Leuven University Press ISBN 978 90 5867 772 3 Walker Stephen 1983 Animal thought p 98 Routledge ISBN 978 0 7100 9037 9 InvertebratesSmith FA 1991 A Question of Pain in Invertebrates ILAR Journal 33 1 2 25 31 doi 10 1093 ilar 33 1 2 25 Archived from the original on 4 March 2016 Retrieved 23 December 2012 Somme Lauritz S 2005 Sentience and pain in invertebrates permanent dead link Report to Norwegian Scientific Committee for Food Safety Consciousness in a Cockroach Discover 10 January 2007 Do insects Feel pain External links editAnimal consciousness at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Bekoff Marc 2012 Animals are conscious and should be treated as such New Scientist 24 September 2012 Koch Christof 2012 Consciousness Is Everywhere Huffington Post 15 August 2012 Octopuses Gain Consciousness According to Scientists Declaration Scientific American 21 August 2012 The absence of a neocortex does not appear to preclude an organism from experiencing affective states 4 September 2012 Animals are as with it as humans scientists say Discovery 24 August 2012 nbsp Video of the Cambridge declaration Archived 26 September 2014 at the Wayback Machine How do octopuses think ABC interview with Peter Godfrey Smith Do animals demonstrate consciousness HowStuffWorks Accessed 30 January 2012 I cockroach Archived 14 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine Aeon 19 November 2013 One of Us Essay by John Jeremiah Sullivan in Lapham s Quarterly 25 March 2014 Elephants mourn Dogs love Why do we deny the feelings of other species The Guardian 11 October 2017 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Animal consciousness amp oldid 1204037907, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.