fbpx
Wikipedia

Qualia

In philosophy of mind, qualia (/ˈkwɑːliə/ or /ˈkwliə/; singular form: quale) are defined as instances of subjective, conscious experience. The term qualia derives from the Latin neuter plural form (qualia) of the Latin adjective quālis (Latin pronunciation: [ˈkʷaːlɪs]) meaning "of what sort" or "of what kind" in a specific instance, such as "what it is like to taste a specific apple — this particular apple now".

The "redness" of red is a commonly used example of a quale.

Examples of qualia include the perceived sensation of pain of a headache, the taste of wine, and the redness of an evening sky. As qualitative characteristics of sensation, qualia stand in contrast to propositional attitudes,[1] where the focus is on beliefs about experience rather than what it is directly like to be experiencing.

Philosopher and cognitive scientist Daniel Dennett suggested that qualia was "an unfamiliar term for something that could not be more familiar to each of us: the ways things seem to us".[2]

Much of the debate over the importance of qualia hinges on the definition of the term, and various philosophers emphasize or deny the existence of certain features of qualia. Consequently, the nature and existence of qualia under various definitions remain controversial. While some philosophers of mind, like Daniel Dennett, argue that qualia do not exist and are incompatible with neuroscience and naturalism,[3] some neuroscientists and neurologists, like Gerald Edelman, Antonio Damasio, Vilayanur Ramachandran, Giulio Tononi, Christof Koch, and Rodolfo Llinás, state that qualia exist and that the desire by some philosophers to disregard qualia is based on an erroneous interpretation of what constitutes science.[4]

Definitions

Many definitions of qualia have been proposed. One of the simpler, broader definitions is: "The 'what it is like' character of mental states. The way it feels to have mental states such as pain, seeing red, smelling a rose, etc."[5]

C.S. Peirce introduced the term quale in philosophy in 1866[6][7]C.I. Lewis (1929)[7] was the first to use the term "qualia" in its generally agreed upon modern sense.

There are recognizable qualitative characters of the given, which may be repeated in different experiences, and are thus a sort of universals; I call these "qualia." But although such qualia are universals, in the sense of being recognized from one to another experience, they must be distinguished from the properties of objects. Confusion of these two is characteristic of many historical conceptions, as well as of current essence-theories. The quale is directly intuited, given, and is not the subject of any possible error because it is purely subjective.[7]

Frank Jackson later defined qualia as "...certain features of the bodily sensations especially, but also of certain perceptual experiences, which no amount of purely physical information includes".[8]: 273 

Daniel Dennett identifies four properties that are commonly ascribed to qualia.[2] According to these, qualia are:

  1. ineffable – they cannot be communicated, or apprehended by any means other than direct experience.
  2. intrinsic – they are non-relational properties, which do not change depending on the experience's relation to other things.
  3. private – all interpersonal comparisons of qualia are systematically impossible.
  4. directly or immediately apprehensible by consciousness – to experience a quale is to know one experiences a quale, and to know all there is to know about that quale.

If qualia of this sort exist, then a normally sighted person who sees red would be unable to describe the experience of this perception in such a way that a listener who has never experienced color will be able to know everything there is to know about that experience. Though it is possible to make an analogy, such as "red looks hot", or to provide a description of the conditions under which the experience occurs, such as "it's the color you see when light of 700-nm wavelength is directed at you", supporters of this definition of qualia contend that such descriptions cannot provide a complete description of the experience.[citation needed]

Another way of defining qualia is as "raw feels". A raw feel is a perception in and of itself, considered entirely in isolation from any effect it might have on behavior and behavioral disposition. In contrast, a cooked feel is that perception seen in terms of its effects. For example, the perception of the taste of wine is an ineffable, raw feel, while the behavioral reaction one has to the warmth or bitterness caused by that taste of wine would be a cooked feel. Cooked feels are not qualia.[citation needed]

Saul Kripke argues that one key consequence of the claim that such things as raw feels can be meaningfully discussed – that qualia exist[clarification needed] – is that it leads to the logical possibility of two entities exhibiting identical behavior in all ways despite one of them entirely lacking qualia.[9] While few claim that such an entity, called a philosophical zombie, actually exists, the possibility is raised as a refutation of physicalism.[10][further explanation needed]

Arguably, the idea of hedonistic utilitarianism, where the ethical value of things is determined from the amount of subjective pleasure or pain they cause, is dependent on the existence of qualia.[11]

Arguments for the existence of qualia

Since by definition one cannot fully convey qualia verbally, one also cannot demonstrate them directly in an argument; so a more nuanced approach is needed. Arguments for qualia generally come in the form of thought experiments designed to lead one to the conclusion that qualia exist.[12]

"What's it like to be?" argument

Thomas Nagel's paper "What is it like to be a bat?",[13] although it does not use the word "qualia", is often cited in debates about qualia. Nagel argues that consciousness has an essentially subjective character, a what-it-is-like aspect. He states that "an organism has conscious mental states if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism – something it is like for the organism."[13] Nagel suggests that this subjective aspect may never be sufficiently accounted for by the objective methods of reductionistic science. He claims that "if we acknowledge that a physical theory of mind must account for the subjective character of experience, we must admit that no presently available conception gives us a clue about how this could be done."[14]: 450  Furthermore, "it seems unlikely that any physical theory of mind can be contemplated until more thought has been given to the general problem of subjective and objective."[14]: 450 

Inverted spectrum argument

 
Inverted qualia

The inverted spectrum thought experiment, originally developed by John Locke,[15] invites us to imagine that we wake up one morning and find that for some unknown reason all the colors in the world have been inverted, i.e. swapped to the hue on the opposite side of a color wheel. Furthermore, we discover that no physical changes have occurred in our brains or bodies that would explain this phenomenon. Supporters of the existence of qualia argue that since we can imagine this happening without contradiction, it follows that we are imagining a change in a property that determines the way things look to us, but that has no physical basis.[16][17] In more detail:

  1. Metaphysical identity holds of necessity.[clarification needed]
  2. If something is possibly false, it is not necessary.
  3. It is conceivable that qualia could have a different relationship to physical brain-states.
  4. If it is conceivable, then it is possible.
  5. Since it is possible for qualia to have a different relationship with physical brain-states, they cannot be identical to brain states (by 1).
  6. Therefore, qualia are non-physical.

The argument thus claims that if we find the inverted spectrum plausible, we must admit that qualia exist (and are non-physical). Some philosophers find it absurd that armchair theorizing can prove something to exist, and the detailed argument does involve a lot of assumptions about conceivability and possibility, which are open to criticism. Perhaps it is not possible for a given brain state to produce anything other than a given quale in our universe, and that is all that matters.

The idea that an inverted spectrum would be undetectable in practice is also open to criticism on more scientific grounds (see main article).[16][17] There is an actual experiment – albeit somewhat obscure – that parallels the inverted spectrum argument. George M. Stratton, professor of psychology at the University of California, Berkeley, performed an experiment in which he wore special prism glasses that caused the external world to appear upside down.[18] After a few days of continually wearing the glasses, he adapted and the external world appeared upright to him. When he removed the glasses, his perception of the external world again returned to the "normal" perceptual state. If this argument provides indicia that qualia exist, it does not necessarily follow that they must be non-physical, because that distinction should be considered a separate epistemological issue.

Zombie argument

An argument holds that it is not inconceivable for a set of people to have qualia, while physical duplicates of that set, called "philosophical zombies", do not. These "zombies" would demonstrate outward behavior, including utterances, exactly the same as normal humans (who are assumed to have subjective phenomenology), without subjective phenomenology. For there to be a valid distinction between "normal humans" and philosophical zombies there must be no specific part or parts of the brain that directly give rise to qualia: The zombie/normal-human distinction can only be valid if subjective consciousness is causally separate from the physical brain.[citation needed]

Are zombies possible? They're not just possible, they're actual. We're all zombies: Nobody is conscious. — D.C. Dennett (1992)[19][page needed]

Explanatory gap argument

Joseph Levine's paper Conceivability, Identity, and the Explanatory Gap takes up where the criticisms of conceivability arguments (such as the inverted spectrum argument and the zombie argument) leave off. Levine agrees that conceivability is a flawed means of establishing metaphysical realities, but points out that even if we come to the metaphysical conclusion that qualia are physical, there is still an explanatory problem.

While I think this materialist response is right in the end, it does not suffice to put the mind-body problem to rest. Even if conceivability considerations do not establish that the mind is in fact distinct from the body, or that mental properties are metaphysically irreducible to physical properties, still they do demonstrate that we lack an explanation of the mental in terms of the physical.

However, such an epistemological or explanatory problem might indicate an underlying metaphysical issue – the non-physicality of qualia, even if not proven by conceivability arguments, is far from ruled out.

In the end, we are right back where we started. The explanatory gap argument doesn't demonstrate a gap in nature, but a gap in our understanding of nature. Of course a plausible explanation for there being a gap in our understanding of nature is that there is a genuine gap in nature. But so long as we have countervailing reasons for doubting the latter, we have to look elsewhere for an explanation of the former.[20]

Knowledge argument

F.C. Jackson offers what he calls the "knowledge argument" for qualia.[8] One example runs as follows:

Mary the color scientist knows all the physical facts about color, including every physical fact about the experience of color in other people, from the behavior a particular color is likely to elicit to the specific sequence of neurological firings that register that a color has been seen. However, she has been confined from birth to a room that is black and white, and is only allowed to observe the outside world through a black and white monitor. When she is allowed to leave the room, it must be admitted that she learns something about the color red the first time she sees it – specifically, she learns what it is like to see that color.

This thought experiment has two purposes. First, it is intended to show that qualia exist. If we accept the thought experiment, we believe that Mary gains something after she leaves the room – that she acquires knowledge of a particular thing that she did not possess before. That knowledge, Jackson argues, is knowledge of the quale that corresponds to the experience of seeing red, and it must thus be conceded that qualia are real properties, since there is a difference between a person who has access to a particular quale and one who does not.

The second purpose of this argument is to refute the physicalist account of the mind. Specifically, the knowledge argument is an attack on the physicalist claim about the completeness of physical truths. The challenge posed to physicalism by the knowledge argument runs as follows:

  1. Before her release, Mary was in possession of all the physical information about color experiences of other people.
  2. After her release, Mary learns something about the color experiences of other people.
    Therefore,
  3. Before her release, Mary was not in possession of all the information about other people's color experiences, even though she was in possession of all the physical information.
          Therefore,
  4. There are truths about other people's color experience that are not physical.
          Therefore,
  5. Physicalism is false.

At first Jackson argued that qualia are epiphenomenal: not causally efficacious with respect to the physical world. Jackson does not give a positive justification for this claim – rather, he seems to assert it simply because it defends qualia against the classic problems of dualism. Our[who?] natural assumption would be that qualia must be causally efficacious in the physical world, but some would ask how we[who?] could argue for their existence if they did not affect our brains. If qualia are non-physical properties (which they must be in order to constitute an argument against physicalism), some[who?] question how they could have a causal effect on the physical world. By redefining qualia as epiphenomenal, Jackson attempts to protect them from the demand of playing a causal role.

Later, however, Jackson rejected epiphenomenalism. This, he argues, is because when Mary first sees red, she says "wow", so it must be Mary's qualia that cause her to say "wow". This contradicts epiphenomenalism. Since the Mary's room thought experiment seems to create this contradiction, there must be something wrong with it.[clarification needed] This[ambiguous] is often referred to as the "there must be a reply" reply.[citation needed]

Analytical philosophers who are critics of qualia

Daniel Dennett

 
Daniel Dennett

In Consciousness Explained (1991)[19] and "Quining Qualia" (1988),[21] Daniel Dennett argues against qualia by claiming that the[which?] above definition breaks down if one tries to practically apply it. In a series of thought experiments, which he calls "intuition pumps", he brings qualia into the world of neurosurgery, clinical psychology, and psychological experimentation. He argues that, once the concept of qualia is so imported, we can either make no use of it, or the questions introduced by it are unanswerable precisely because of the special properties defined for qualia.[citation needed]

In Dennett's updated version of the inverted spectrum thought experiment, "alternative neurosurgery", you again awake to find that your qualia have been inverted – grass appears red, the sky appears orange, etc. According to the original account, you should be immediately aware that something has gone horribly wrong. Dennett argues, however, that it is impossible to know whether the diabolical neurosurgeons have indeed inverted your qualia (by tampering with your optic nerve, say), or have simply inverted your connection to memories of past qualia. Since both operations would produce the same result, you would have no means on your own to tell which operation has actually been conducted, and you are thus in the odd position of not knowing whether there has been a change in your "immediately apprehensible" qualia.[citation needed]

Dennett's argues that for qualia to be taken seriously as a component of experience – for them to make sense as a discrete concept – it must be possible to show that

  1. it is possible to know that a change in qualia has occurred, as opposed to a change in something else; or that
  2. there is a difference between having a change in qualia and not having one.

Dennett attempts to show that we cannot satisfy (a) either through introspection or through observation, and that qualia's very definition undermines its chances of satisfying (b).

Supporters of qualia could point out that in order for you to notice a change in qualia, you must compare your current qualia with your memories of past qualia. Arguably, such a comparison would involve immediate apprehension of your current qualia and your memories of past qualia, but not the past qualia themselves. Furthermore, modern functional brain imaging has increasingly suggested that the memory of an experience is processed in similar ways and in similar zones of the brain as those originally involved in the original perception.[22] This may mean that there would be asymmetry in outcomes between altering the mechanism of perception of qualia and altering their memories. If the diabolical neurosurgery altered the immediate perception of qualia, you might not even notice the inversion directly, since the brain zones which re-process the memories would themselves invert the qualia remembered. On the other hand, alteration of the qualia memories themselves would be processed without inversion, and thus you would perceive them as an inversion. Thus, you might know immediately if memory of your qualia had been altered, but might not know if immediate qualia were inverted or whether the diabolical neurosurgeons had done a sham procedure.[original research?]

Dennett responds to the "Mary the color scientist" thought experiment by arguing that Mary would not, in fact, learn something new if she stepped out of her black and white room to see the color red. Dennett asserts that if she already truly knew "everything about color", that knowledge would include a deep understanding of why and how human neurology causes us to sense the "quale" of color. Mary would therefore already know exactly what to expect of seeing red, before ever leaving the room. Dennett argues that the misleading aspect of the story is that Mary is supposed to not merely be knowledgeable about color but to actually know all the physical facts about it, which would be a knowledge so deep that it exceeds what can be imagined, and twists our intuitions.

If Mary really does know everything physical there is to know about the experience of color, then this effectively grants her almost omniscient powers of knowledge. Using this, she will be able to deduce her own reaction, and figure out exactly what the experience of seeing red will feel like.

Dennett finds that many people find it difficult to see this, so he uses the case of RoboMary to further illustrate what it would be like for Mary to possess such a vast knowledge of the physical workings of the human brain and color vision. RoboMary is an intelligent robot who has, instead of the ordinary color camera-eyes, a software lock such that she is only able to perceive black and white and shades in-between.[citation needed]

RoboMary can examine the computer brain of similar non-color-locked robots when they look at a red tomato, and see exactly how they react and what kinds of impulses occur. RoboMary can also construct a simulation of her own brain, unlock the simulation's color-lock and, with reference to the other robots, simulate exactly how this simulation of herself reacts to seeing a red tomato. RoboMary naturally has control over all of her internal states except for the color-lock. With the knowledge of her simulation's internal states upon seeing a red tomato, RoboMary can put her own internal states directly into the states they would be in upon seeing a red tomato. In this way, without ever seeing a red tomato through her cameras, she will know exactly what it is like to see a red tomato.[citation needed]

Dennett uses this example as attempt to show us that Mary's all-encompassing physical knowledge makes her own internal states as transparent as those of a robot or computer, and it is almost straightforward for her to figure out exactly how it feels to see red.[citation needed]

Perhaps Mary's failure to learn exactly what seeing red feels like is simply a failure of language, or a failure of our ability to describe experiences. An alien race with a different method of communication or description might be perfectly able to teach their version of Mary exactly how seeing the color red would feel. Perhaps it is simply a uniquely human failing to communicate first-person experiences from a third-person perspective. Dennett suggests that the description might even be possible using English. He uses a simpler version of the Mary thought experiment to show how this might work. What if Mary was in a room without triangles and was prevented from seeing or making any triangles? An English-language description of just a few words would be sufficient for her to imagine what it is like to see a triangle – she can simply and directly visualize a triangle in her mind. Similarly, Dennett proposes, it is perfectly, logically possible that the quale of what it is like to see red could eventually be described in an English-language description of millions or billions of words.[citation needed]

In "Are we explaining consciousness yet?" (2001),[23] Dennett approves of an account of qualia defined as the deep, rich collection of individual neural responses that are too fine-grained for language to capture. For instance, a person might have an alarming reaction to yellow because of a yellow car that hit her previously, and someone else might have a nostalgic reaction to a comfort food. These effects are too individual-specific to be captured by English words. "If one dubs this inevitable residue qualia, then qualia are guaranteed to exist, but they are just more of the same, dispositional properties that have not yet been entered in the catalog [...]."[23]

Paul Churchland

According to Paul Churchland, Mary might be considered to be like a feral child. Feral children have suffered extreme isolation during childhood. Technically when Mary leaves the room, she would not have the ability to see or know what the color red is. A brain has to learn and develop how to see colors. Patterns need to form in the V4 section of the visual cortex. These patterns are formed from exposure to wavelengths of light. This exposure is needed during the early stages of brain development. In Mary's case, the identifications and categorizations of color will only be in respect to representations of black and white.[24]

Gary Drescher

In his book Good and Real (2006),[25] Gary Drescher compares qualia with "gensyms" (generated symbols) in Common Lisp. These are objects that Lisp treats as having no properties or components and which can only be identified as equal or not equal to other objects. Drescher explains, "we have no introspective access to whatever internal properties make the red gensym recognizably distinct from the green [...] even though we know the sensation when we experience it."[25] Under this interpretation of qualia, Drescher responds to the Mary thought experiment by noting that "knowing about red-related cognitive structures and the dispositions they engender – even if that knowledge were implausibly detailed and exhaustive – would not necessarily give someone who lacks prior color-experience the slightest clue whether the card now being shown is of the color called red." This does not, however, imply that our experience of red is non-mechanical; "on the contrary, gensyms are a routine feature of computer-programming languages".[14]: 82 

David Lewis

D.K. Lewis introduced a hypothesis about types of knowledge and their transmission in qualia cases. Lewis agrees that Mary cannot learn what red looks like through her monochrome physicalist studies. But he proposes that this does not matter. Learning transmits information, but experiencing qualia does not transmit information; instead it communicates abilities. When Mary sees red, she does not get any new information. She gains new abilities – now she can remember what red looks like, imagine what other red things might look like and recognize further instances of redness.

Lewis states that Jackson's thought experiment uses the phenomenal information hypothesis – that is, that the new knowledge that Mary gains upon seeing red is phenomenal information. Lewis then proposes a different ability hypothesis that differentiates between two types of knowledge: knowledge "that" (information) and knowledge "how" (abilities). Normally the two are entangled; ordinary learning is also an experience of the subject concerned, and people both learn information (for instance, that Freud was a psychologist) and gain ability (to recognize images of Freud). However, in the thought experiment, Mary can only use ordinary learning to gain know-that knowledge. She is prevented from using experience to gain the know-how knowledge that would allow her to remember, imagine and recognize the color red.

We have the intuition that Mary has been deprived of some vital data to do with the experience of redness. It is also uncontroversial that some things cannot be learned inside the room; for example, we do not expect Mary to learn how to ski within the room. Lewis has articulated that information and ability are potentially different things. In this way, physicalism is still compatible with the conclusion that Mary gains new knowledge. It is also useful for considering other instances of qualia; "being a bat" is an ability, so it is know-how knowledge.[26]

Marvin Minsky

 
Marvin Minsky

Artificial intelligence researcher Marvin Minsky thinks the problems posed by qualia are essentially issues of complexity, or rather of mistaking complexity for simplicity.

Now, a philosophical dualist might then complain: "You've described how hurting affects your mind – but you still can't express how hurting feels." This, I maintain, is a huge mistake – that attempt to reify "feeling" as an independent entity, with an essence that's indescribable. As I see it, feelings are not strange alien things. It is precisely those cognitive changes themselves that constitute what "hurting" is – and this also includes all those clumsy attempts to represent and summarize those changes. The big mistake comes from looking for some single, simple, "essence" of hurting, rather than recognizing that this is the word we use for complex rearrangement of our disposition of resources.[27]

Michael Tye

 
Michael Tye

Michael Tye believes there are no qualia, no "veils of perception" between us and the referents of our thought. He describes our experience of an object in the world as "transparent". By this he means that no matter what private understandings and/or misunderstandings we may have of some public entity, it is still there before us in reality. The idea that qualia intervene between ourselves and their origins he regards as "a massive error"; as he says, "it is just not credible that visual experiences are systematically misleading in this way";[14]: 46  "the only objects of which you are aware are the external ones making up the scene before your eyes";[14]: 47  there are "no such things as the qualities of experiences" for "they are qualities of external surfaces (and volumes and films) if they are qualities of anything."[14]: 48  He believes we can take our experiences at face value since there is no fear of losing contact with the realness of public objects.

In Tye's thought there is no question of qualia without information being contained within them; it is always "an awareness that", always "representational". He characterizes the perception of children as a misperception of referents that are undoubtedly as present for them as they are for grown-ups. As he puts it, they may not know that "the house is dilapidated", but there is no doubt about their seeing the house. After-images are dismissed as presenting no problem for the Transparency theory because, as he puts it, after-images being illusory, there is nothing that one sees.

Tye proposes that phenomenal experience has five basic elements, for which he has coined the acronym PANIC – Poised, Abstract, Nonconceptual, Intentional Content.[14]: 63  It is "Poised" in the sense that the phenomenal experience is always presented to the understanding, whether or not the agent is able to apply a concept to it. Tye adds that the experience is "maplike" in that, in most cases, it reaches through to the distribution[clarification needed] of shapes, edges, volumes, etc. in the world – you may not be reading the "map" but, as with an actual map there is a reliable match with what it is mapping. It is "Abstract" because it is still an open question in a particular case whether you are in touch with a concrete object (someone may feel a pain in a "left leg" when that leg has actually been amputated). It is "Nonconceptual" because a phenomenon can exist although one does not have the concept by which to recognize it. Nevertheless, it is "Intentional" in the sense that it represents something, again whether or not the particular observer is taking advantage of that fact; this is why Tye calls his theory "representationalism". This last makes it plain that Tye believes that he has retained a direct contact with what produces the phenomena and is therefore not hampered by any trace of a "veil of perception".[28]

Roger Scruton

Roger Scruton, while sceptical that neurobiology can tell us much about consciousness, believes qualia is an incoherent concept, and that Wittgenstein's private language argument effectively disproves it. Scruton writes,

The belief that these essentially private features of mental states exist, and that they form the introspectible essence of whatever possesses them, is grounded in a confusion, one that Wittgenstein tried to sweep away in his arguments against the possibility of a private language. When you judge that I am in pain, it is on the basis of my circumstances and behavior, and you could be wrong. When I ascribe a pain to myself, I don’t use any such evidence. I don’t find out that I am in pain by observation, nor can I be wrong. But that is not because there is some other fact about my pain, accessible only to me, which I consult in order to establish what I am feeling. For if there were this inner private quality, I could misperceive it; I could get it wrong, and I would have to find out whether I am in pain. To describe my inner state, I would also have to invent a language, intelligible only to me – and that, Wittgenstein plausibly argues, is impossible. The conclusion to draw is that I ascribe pain to myself not on the basis of some inner quale but on no basis at all.

In his book On Human Nature, Scruton poses a potential line of criticism to this, which is that while Wittgenstein's private language argument does disprove the concept of reference to qualia, or the idea that we can talk even to ourselves of their nature, it does not disprove their existence altogether. Scruton believes that this is a valid criticism, and this is why he stops short of actually saying that qualia do not exist, and instead merely suggests that we should abandon them as a concept. However, he quotes Wittgenstein in response: "Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent."[29]

Analytical philosophers who are proponents of qualia

David Chalmers

 
David Chalmers

David Chalmers formulated the hard problem of consciousness, which raised the issue of qualia to a new level of importance and acceptance in the field[clarification needed].[30] In Chalmers (1995)[31] he also argued for what he called "the principle of organizational invariance": If a system such as one of appropriately configured computer hardware reproduces the functional organization of the brain, it will also reproduce the qualia associated with the brain.

E. J. Lowe

E. J. Lowe denies that indirect realism (in which we have access only to sensory features internal to the brain) necessarily implies a Cartesian dualism. He agrees with Bertrand Russell that our "retinal images" – that is, the distributions across[clarification needed] our retinas – are connected to[vague] "patterns of neural activity in the cortex".[32] He defends a version of the causal theory of perception in which a causal path can be traced between the external object and the perception of it. He is careful to deny that we do any inferring from the sensory field[clarification needed]; he believes this allows us to found an access to knowledge on that causal connection. In a later work he moves closer to the non-epistemic argument in that he postulates "a wholly non-conceptual component of perceptual experience",[32] but he refrains from analyzing the relation between the perceptual and the "non-conceptual". More recently he drew attention to the problems that hallucination raises for the direct realist and to their disinclination to enter the discussion on the topic.[33]

J. B. Maund

John Barry Maund, an Australian philosopher of perception, argues that qualia can be described on two levels, a fact that he refers to as "dual coding".[34]

If asked what we see on a television screen there are two varieties of answer that we might give. Consider the example of a "Movitype" screen, often used for advertisements and announcements in public places. A Movitype screen consists of a matrix – or "raster" as the neuroscientists prefer to call it (from the Latin rastrum, a "rake"; think of the lines on a TV screen as "raked" across) – that is made up of an array of tiny light-sources. A computer can excite these lights so as to give the impression of letters passing from right to left, or even to show moving pictures. In describing what we see on such a screen, we could adopt the everyday public language and say "I saw some sentences, followed by a picture of a 7-Up can." Although that is a perfectly adequate way of describing the sight, nevertheless, there is a scientific way of describing it which bears no relation whatsoever to this commonsense description. One could ask an electronics engineer to provide us with a computer print-out, staged across the seconds that we were watching, of the point-states of the raster of lights. This would no doubt be a long and complex document, with the state of each tiny light-source given its place in the sequence. Although such a list would give a comprehensive and point-by-point-detailed description of the state of the screen, nowhere would it contain mention of "English sentences" or "a 7-Up can".

This illustrates that there are two ways to describe such a screen, (1) the "commonsense" one which refers to publicly recognizable objects, and (2) an accurate point-by-point account of the actual state of the field that makes no mention of what any passer-by would or would not make of it. This second description would be non-epistemic from the common sense point of view, since no objects are mentioned in the print-out, but perfectly acceptable from the engineer's point of view. Note that, if one carries this analysis across to human sensing and perceiving, this rules out Dennett's claim that all qualiaphiles must regard qualia as "ineffable", for at this second level they are in principle quite "effable" – indeed, it is not ruled out that some neurophysiologist of the future might be able to describe the neural detail of qualia at this level.

Maund extended his argument with reference to color.[35] Color he sees as a dispositional property, not an objective one. Colors are "virtual properties"; is as if things possessed them. Although the naïve view attributes them to objects, they are intrinsic, non-relational, inner experiences. This allows for the facts of difference[clarification needed] between person and person, and also leaves aside the claim that external objects are colored.

Moreland Perkins

In his book Sensing the World,[36] Moreland Perkins argues that qualia need not be identified with their objective sources: a smell, for instance, bears no direct resemblance to the molecular shape that gives rise to it, nor is a toothache actually in the tooth. Like Hobbes he views the process of sensing as complete in itself; as he puts it, it is not like "kicking a football" where an external object is required – it is more like "kicking a kick". This explanation evades the Homunculus Objection, as adhered to, for example, by Gilbert Ryle. Ryle was unable to entertain this possibility, protesting that "in effect it explained the having of sensations as the not having of sensations."[37] However, A.J. Ayer called this objection "very weak" as it betrayed an inability to detach the notion of eyes, or indeed any sensory organ, from the neural sensory experience.[38]

Howard Robinson and William Robinson

Howard Robinson specialized in philosophy of mind. He argued against explanations of sensory experience that reduce them to physical origins. He never regarded the theory of sense-data[clarification needed] as refuted, but set out to refute persuasive objections to it. The version of the theory of sense-data he defends takes what is before consciousness in perception to be qualia as mental presentations that are causally linked to external entities, but which are not physical in themselves.[needs copy edit] He is therefore a dualist: one who takes both matter and mind to have real and metaphysically distinct natures. One of his articles takes the physicalist to task for ignoring the fact that sensory experience can be entirely free of representational character. He cites phosphenes as a stubborn example (phosphenes are flashes of light that result either from sudden pressure in the brain – as induced, for example, by intense coughing, or through direct physical pressure on the retina), and points out that it is counter-intuitive to argue that these are not visual experiences on a par with open-eye seeing.

William Robinson (no relation) takes a similar view in his book, Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness.[39] He is unusual as a dualist in calling for research programs that investigate the relation of qualia to the brain. The problem is so stubborn, he says, that too many philosophers would prefer "to explain it away", but he would rather have it explained and does not see why the effort should not be made. However, he does not expect a straightforward scientific reduction of phenomenal experience to neural architecture; he regards this as a forlorn hope. The "Qualitative Event Realism" that Robinson espouses sees phenomenal consciousness as non-material events that are caused by brain events but not identical with them.

He refuses to set aside the vividness – and commonness – of mental images, both visual and aural. In this he opposes Daniel Dennett, who has difficulty crediting such experience in others. He is similar to Moreland Perkins in keeping his investigation wide enough to apply to all the senses.

Edmond Wright

Edmond Wright is a philosopher who considers the inter-subjective aspect of perception.[40] From John Locke onwards it had been typical to frame perception problems in terms of a single subject S looking at a single entity E with a property p. However, if we begin with the facts of the differences in sensory registration from person to person, coupled with the differences in the criteria we have learned for distinguishing what we together call "the same" things, then a problem arises of how two persons align their differences on these two levels so that they can still get a practical overlap on parts of the real about them – and, in particular, update each other about them.[needs copy edit]

Wright was struck by the hearing difference between himself and his son: he discovered that his son could hear sounds up to nearly 20 kHz while his range only reached to 14 kHz or so. This implies that a difference in qualia could emerge in human action (for example, the son could warn the father of a high-pitched escape of a dangerous gas kept under pressure, the sound-waves of which would be producing no qualia evidence at all for the father). The relevance for language thus becomes critical, for an informative statement can best be understood as an updating of a perception – and this may involve a radical re-selection from the qualia fields viewed as non-epistemic, even perhaps of the presumed singularity of "the" referent, a fortiori if that "referent" is the self.[needs copy edit] He distinguishes his view from that of Revonsuo[clarification needed], who too readily makes his "virtual space" "egocentric".[importance?]

Wright emphasizes what he asserts is a core feature of communication, that, in order for an updating to be set up and made possible[clarification needed], both speaker and hearer have to behave as if they have identified "the same singular thing", which, he notes, partakes of the structure of a joke or a story[how?].[40] Wright says that this systematic ambiguity[clarification needed] seems to opponents of qualia to be a sign of fallacy in the argument (as ambiguity is in pure logic) whereas, on the contrary, it is sign – in talk about "what" is perceived – of something those speaking to each other have to learn to take advantage of. He argues that an important feature of human communication is the degree and character of the faith[clarification needed] maintained by the participants in the dialogue, something that has priority over such virtues of language as "sincerity", "truth", and "objectivity". Indeed, he considers that to prioritize them over faith is to move into superstition.

Erwin Schrödinger

Erwin Schrödinger, a theoretical physicist and one of the leading pioneers of quantum mechanics, also published in the areas of colorimetry and color perception. In several of his philosophical writings, he defends the notion that qualia are not physical.

The sensation of colour cannot be accounted for by the physicist's objective picture of light-waves. Could the physiologist account for it, if he had fuller knowledge than he has of the processes in the retina and the nervous processes set up by them in the optical nerve bundles and in the brain? I do not think so.[41]: 154 

He continues on to remark that subjective experiences do not form a one-to-one correspondence with stimuli. For example, light of wavelengths in the neighborhood of 590 nm produces the sensation of yellow, whereas exactly the same sensation is produced by mixing red light, with wavelength 760 nm, with green light, at 535 nm. From this he concludes that there is no "numerical connection with these physical, objective characteristics of the waves" and the sensations they produce.

Schrödinger concludes with a proposal of how it is that we might arrive at the mistaken belief that a satisfactory theoretical account of qualitative experience has been – or might ever be – achieved:

Scientific theories serve to facilitate the survey of our observations and experimental findings. Every scientist knows how difficult it is to remember a moderately extended group of facts, before at least some primitive theoretical picture about them has been shaped. It is therefore small wonder, and by no means to be blamed on the authors of original papers or of text-books, that after a reasonably coherent theory has been formed, they do not describe the bare facts they have found or wish to convey to the reader, but clothe them in the terminology of that theory or theories. This procedure, while very useful for our remembering the fact in a well-ordered pattern, tends to obliterate the distinction between the actual observations and the theory arisen from them. And since the former always are of some sensual quality, theories are easily thought to account for sensual qualities; which, of course, they never do.[41]: 163–164 

Neuroscientists who state that qualia exist

Gerald Edelman

Neuroscientist and Nobel laureate in Physiology / Medicine Gerald Edelman, in his book Bright Air, Brilliant Fire, argues:[42]

One alternative that definitely does not seem feasible is to ignore completely the reality of qualia, formulating a theory of consciousness that aims by its descriptions alone to convey to a hypothetical “qualia-free” observer what it is to feel warmth, see green, and so on. In other words, this is an attempt to propose a theory based on a kind of God's-eye view of consciousness. But no scientific theory of whatever kind can be presented without already assuming that observers have sensation as well as perception. To assume otherwise is to indulge the errors of theories that attempt syntactical formulations mapped onto objectivist interpretations – theories that ignore embodiment as a source of meaning (see the Postscript). There is no qualia-free scientific observer.

Antonio Damasio

Neurologist Antonio Damasio, in his book The Feeling Of What Happens, states:[43]

Qualia are the simple sensory qualities to be found in the blueness of the sky or the tone of sound produced by a cello, and the fundamental components of the images in the movie metaphor are thus made of qualia.

Damasio also argues that consciousness is subjective and is different from behavior:[43]: 307–309 

The resistance found in some scientific quarters to the use of subjective observations is a revisitation of an old argument between behaviorists, who believed that only behaviors, not mental experiences, could be studied objectively, and cognitivists, who believed that studying only behavior did not do justice to human complexity. The mind and its consciousness are first and foremost private phenomena, much as they offer many public signs of their existence to the interested observer. The conscious mind and its constituent properties are real entities, not illusions, and they must be investigated as the personal, private, subjective experiences that they are. The idea that subjective experiences are not scientifically accessible is nonsense.

Subjective entities require, as do objective ones, that enough observers undertake rigorous observations according to the same experimental design; and they require that those observations be checked for consistency across observers and that they yield some form of measurement. Moreover, knowledge gathered from subjective observations, e.g., introspective insights, can inspire objective experiments, and, no less importantly, subjective experiences can be explained in terms of the available scientific knowledge. The idea that the nature of subjective experiences can be grasped effectively by the study of their behavioral correlates is wrong. Although both mind and behavior are biological phenomena, mind is mind and behavior is behavior.

Mind and behavior can be correlated, and the correlation will become closer as science progresses, but in their respective specifications, mind and behavior are different. This is why, in all likelihood, I will never know your thoughts unless you tell me, and you will never know mine until I tell you.

Damasio also addresses qualia in his book Self Comes to Mind.[44][importance?]

Rodolfo Llinás

Neurologist Rodolfo Llinás states in his book I of the Vortex that from a strictly neurological perspective, qualia exist and are important to the organism's survival. He argues that qualia were important for the evolution of the nervous system of organisms, including simple organisms such as insects:[45]: 201–221 

There are today two similar beliefs concerning the nature of qualia. The first is that qualia represent an epiphenomenon that is not necessary for the acquisition of consciousness. Second and somewhat related is the belief that while being the basis for consciousness, qualia appeared only in the highest life forms, suggesting that qualia represent a recently evolved central function that is present in only the more advanced brains. This view relegates the more lowly animals, for example ants, to a realm characterized by the absence of subjective experiences of any kind. It implies that these animals are wired with sets of automatic, reflexively organized circuits that provide for survival by maintaining a successful, albeit purely reactive interaction with the ongoing external world. Although primitive creatures such as ants and cockroaches may be wildly successful, for all practical purposes they are biological automatons.

[…] To me, these views lack a proper evolutionary perspective, which is perhaps why qualia are given so little overall emphasis in the study of brain function. We clearly understand that the functional architecture of the brain is a product of the slow tumblings of evolution and that brain function implements what natural selection has found to be the most beneficial in terms of species survivability. What is not often understood is how deeply related qualia truly are to the evolutionary, functional structure of the brain. […]

One cannot operate without qualia; they are properties of mind of monumental importance.

Llinás argues that qualia are ancient and necessary for an organism's survival and a product of neuronal oscillation. He gives the evidence of anesthesia of the brain and subsequent stimulation of limbs to demonstrate that qualia can be "turned off" by changing only the variable of neuronal oscillation (local brain electrical activity), while all other connections remain intact. He argues for an oscillatory-electrical origin of qualia, or important aspects of them.[45]: 202–207 

Vilayanur Ramachandran

 
Vilayanur S. Ramachandran

Vilayanur S. Ramachandran and William Hirstein[46] proposed three laws of qualia (with a fourth later added), which are "functional criteria that need to be fulfilled in order for certain neural events to be associated with qualia" by philosophers of the mind:

  1. Qualia are irrevocable and indubitable. You don't say 'maybe it is red but I can visualize it as green if I want to'. An explicit neural representation of red is created that invariably and automatically 'reports' this to higher brain centres.
  2. Once the representation is created, what can be done with it is open-ended. You have the luxury of choice, e.g., if you have the percept of an apple you can use it to tempt Adam, to keep the doctor away, bake a pie, or just to eat. Even though the representation at the input level is immutable and automatic, the output is potentially infinite. This isn't true for, say, a spinal reflex arc where the output is also inevitable and automatic. Indeed, a paraplegic can even have an erection and ejaculate without an orgasm.
  3. Short-term memory. The input invariably creates a representation that persists in short-term memory – long enough to allow time for choice of output. Without this component, again, you get just a reflex arc.
  4. Attention. Qualia and attention are closely linked. You need attention to fulfill criterion number two; to choose. A study of circuits involved in attention, therefore, will shed much light on the riddle of qualia.[47]

These authors approach qualia from an empirical perspective and not as a logical or philosophical problem. They wonder how qualia evolved. They consider a skeptical point of view in which, since the objective scientific description of the world is complete without qualia, it is nonsense to ask the question of why they evolved or what qualia are for. But they rule out such an option.

Based on the parsimony principle of Occam's razor, one could accept epiphenomenalism and deny qualia since they are not necessary for a description of the functioning of the brain. However, they argue that Occam's razor is not useful for scientific discovery.[46] For example, the discovery of relativity in physics was not the product of accepting Occam's razor but rather of rejecting it and asking the question of whether a deeper generalization, not required by the currently available data, was true and would allow for unexpected predictions. Most scientific discoveries arise, these authors argue, from ontologically promiscuous conjectures that do not come from current data.

The authors then point out that skepticism might be justified in the philosophical field, but that science is the wrong place for such skepticism. Such skeptical questions might include asking if "your red is not my green" or if we can be logically certain that we are not dreaming. Science, these authors assert, deals with what is probably true, beyond reasonable doubt, not with what can be known with complete and absolute certainty. The authors say that most neuroscientists and even most psychologists dispute the very existence of the “problem” of qualia[46]

Roger Orpwood

Roger Orpwood, an engineer who studies neural mechanisms, proposed a neurobiological model that gives rise to qualia and ultimately, consciousness. Advancements in cognitive and computational neuroscience necessitate study of the mind and qualia from a scientific perspective. Orpwood does not deny the existence of qualia, nor does he debate its physical or non-physical existence. He suggests that qualia are created through the neurobiological mechanism of re-entrant feedback in cortical systems.[48][49]

Orpwood first addresses the issue of information. One unsolved aspect of qualia is the concept of the fundamental information[clarification needed] involved in creating the experience. He does not take a position on the metaphysics of the information underlying the experience of qualia, nor does he state what information actually is, but he does say that information is of two types: the information structure and information message. Information structures are defined by the physical vehicles and structural, biological patterns that encode information. That encoded information is the information message: a source that describes what that information is. The neural mechanism or network receives input information structures, completes a designated instructional task (firing of the neuron or network), and outputs a modified information structure to downstream regions. The information message is the purpose and meaning of the information structure and causally exists as a result of that particular information structure. Modification of the information structure changes the meaning of the information message, but the message itself cannot be directly altered.

Local cortical networks can receive feedback from their own output information structures. This form of local feedback continuously cycles part of the network's output structures as its next input information structure. Since the output structure must represent the information message derived from the input structure, each consecutive cycle that is fed-back represents the output structure the network just generated. As the network of mechanisms cannot recognize the information message, but only the input information structure, the network is unaware that it is representing its own previous outputs. The neural mechanisms are merely completing their instructional tasks and outputting any recognizable[clarification needed] information structures. Orpwood proposes that these local networks come into an attractor state that consistently outputs exactly the same information structure as the input structure. Instead of only representing the information message derived from the input structure, the network will now represent its own output and thereby its own information message. As the input structures are fed-back, the network identifies the previous information structure as being a previous representation of the information message. As Orpwood writes:

Once an attractor state has been established, the output [of a network] is a representation of its own identity to the network.[49]: 4 

Orpwood explains the neurobiological manifestation of qualia as representations of the network's own output structures, by which it represents its own information message. This is particular to networks of pyramidal neurons. Although computational neuroscience still has much to investigate regarding pyramidal neurons, their complex circuitry is unusual. The complexity of pyramidal neuron networks in a species is directly related to the increase in that species's functional capabilities.[50] When human pyramidal networks are compared with other primate species and with species with less intricate behavioral and social interactions, the complexity of these neural networks drastically decline.[needs copy edit] These networks are also more complex[compared to?] in frontal brain regions. These regions are often associated with[weasel words] conscious assessment and modification of one's immediate environment; often referred to as executive functions.

One needs sensory input to gain information from the environment. Perception of that input is necessary in order to navigate and modify interactions with the environment. This suggests that frontal regions containing more complex pyramidal networks are associated with an increased perceptive capacity.[how?] As perception is necessary for conscious thought to occur,[citation needed] and since qualia derive from[clarification needed] consciousness of some perception, qualia may be specific to the functional capacity of[clarification needed] pyramidal networks.[non sequitur] For this reason Orpwood believes that the mechanisms of re-entrant feedback may not only create qualia, but also be the foundation to consciousness.

Other issues

Indeterminacy

A criticism similar to Nietzsche's criticism of Kant's "thing in itself" applies also to qualia: Qualia are unobservable in others and unquantifiable in us. We cannot possibly be sure, when discussing individual qualia, that we are even discussing the same phenomena. Thus, any discussion of them is of indeterminate value, as descriptions of qualia are necessarily of indeterminate accuracy.[citation needed]

Qualia, like "things in themselves", have no publicly demonstrable properties. This, along with the impossibility of being sure that we are communicating about the same qualia, makes them of indeterminate value and definition in any philosophy in which proof relies upon precise definition.[citation needed]

On the other hand, qualia could be considered akin to Kantian phenomena since they are held to be seemings of appearances. Revonsuo[clarification needed], however, considers that, within neurophysiological inquiry, a definition[vague] at the level of the fields[clarification needed] may become possible (just as we can define a television picture at the level of liquid crystal pixels).[non sequitur]

Causal efficacy

Whether qualia or consciousness can play any causal role in the physical world remains an open question. Epiphenomenalism acknowledges the existence of qualia while denying them any causal power. The position has been criticized by a number of philosophers,[a] if only because our own consciousness seem to be causally active.[54] In order to avoid epiphenomenalism, one who believes that qualia are nonphysical would need to embrace something like interactionist dualism; or perhaps emergentism, the claim that there are as yet unknown causal relations between the mental and physical. This in turn would imply that qualia can be detected by an external agency[clarification needed] through their causal powers.

Epistemological issues

Examples of qualia might include "the pain of a headache, the taste of wine, or the redness of an evening sky". But such examples prejudge a central debate on qualia.[citation needed] Suppose someone wants to know the nature of the liquid crystal pixels on a television screen—those tiny elements that make up the picture. It would not suffice as an answer to say that they are the "redness of an evening sky" as it appears on the screen; this would ignore their real character. Relying on a list like the one above assumes that we must tie sensations to both the notion of given objects in the world (the "head", "wine", "an evening sky") and to the properties with which we characterize the experiences themselves ("redness", for example).

Nor is it satisfactory to print a little red square as at the top of this article, for, since each person has a slightly different registration of the light-rays,[55] it confusingly suggests that we all have the same response.[how?] Imagine in a television shop seeing "a red square" on twenty screens at once, each slightly different – something of vital importance would be overlooked if a single example were to be taken as defining them all.[further explanation needed]

Yet it has been argued whether or not identification with the external object should still be the core of a correct approach to sensation, for there are many who state the definition thus because they regard the link with external reality as crucial.[needs copy edit] If sensations are defined as "raw feels", this threatens the reliability of knowledge because if one sees them as neurophysiological happenings in the brain, it is difficult to understand how they could have any connection to entities, whether in the body or the external world.

John McDowell, for example, declared that to countenance qualia as a "bare presence" prevents us ever gaining a certain ground for our knowledge.[56] The issue is epistemological: it would appear that access to knowledge is blocked if one allows the existence of qualia as fields in which only virtual constructs are before[clarification needed] the mind. His reason is that it[ambiguous] puts the entities about which we require knowledge behind a "veil of perception", an occult field of "appearance" which leaves us ignorant of the reality presumed to be beyond it. He is convinced that such uncertainty propels[needs copy edit] into the dangerous regions of relativism and solipsism. These constitute an ethical argument against qualia being something going on in the brain,[clarification needed] and these implications are probably largely responsible for the fact that in the 20th century it was regarded as not only freakish, but also dangerously misguided to uphold the notion of sensations as going on inside the head.[citation needed] The argument was usually strengthened with mockery at the very idea of "redness" being in the brain:[57] – "How can there be red neurons in the brain?"

Viewing sensations as "raw feels" implies that initially they have not yet – to carry on the metaphor – been "cooked", that is, unified into "things" and "persons", which is something the mind does after the sensation has responded to the blank input, that response driven by motivation, that is, initially by pain and pleasure, and subsequently, when memories have been implanted, by desire and fear.[needs copy edit] Such a "raw-feel" state has been called "non-epistemic". In support of this view, the theorists[who?] cite a range of empirical facts, for example:

  • There are brain-damaged persons, known as "agnosics" (literally "not-knowing") who still have vivid visual sensations but are quite unable to identify any entity before them, including parts of their own body.
  • There is also the similar predicament of persons, formerly blind, who are given sight for the first time. And consider what it is a newborn baby experiences.

German physicist Hermann von Helmholtz proposed an experiment to demonstrate the non-epistemic nature of qualia: His instructions were to stand in front of a familiar landscape, turn your back on it, bend down and look at the landscape between your legs – you will find it difficult in the upside-down view to recognize what you found familiar before.[58]

These examples suggest the reality of a "bare presence" – that is, knowledgeless sensation that is no more than evidence. Supporters of the non-epistemic theory thus regard sensations as only data in the sense that they are "given" (Latin datum, "given") and fundamentally involuntary, which is a good reason for not regarding them as basically mental.[why?] In the 20th century they were called "sense-data" by the proponents of qualia, but this led to the confusion that they carried with them reliable proofs of objective causal origins. For instance, one supporter of qualia was happy to speak of the redness and bulginess of a cricket ball as a typical "sense-datum",[59] though not all of them were happy to define qualia by their relation to external entities.[60] The modern argument centers on how we learn under the regime of motivation[definition needed] to interpret sensory evidence in terms of "things", "persons", and "selves" through a continuing process of feedback.

The definition of qualia inevitably brings with it philosophical and neurophysiological presuppositions. The question of what qualia can be raises profound issues in the philosophy of mind, since some materialists want to deny their existence altogether: on the other hand, if they are accepted, they cannot be easily accounted for as they raise the difficult problem of consciousness. There are committed dualists such as Richard L. Amoroso or John Hagelin who believe that the mental and the material are two distinct aspects of physical reality like the distinction between the classical and quantum regimes.[61] In contrast, there are direct realists for whom qualia are unscientific as there appears to be no way of making them fit within the modern scientific picture; and there are committed proselytizers for a final truth who reject them as forcing knowledge out of reach.

See also

  • Binding problem – Unanswered question in the study of consciousness
  • Blockhead (thought experiment) – philosophical thought experiment about a computer which has been programmed with all possible sentences in a natural language, so as to be able to pass the Turing test despite lacking intelligence
  • Chinese room – Thought experiment on artificial intelligence by John Searle
  • Explanatory gap – Inability to describe conscious experiences in solely physical or structural terms
  • Feeling – Conscious subjective experience of emotion
  • Form constant – Recurringly observed geometric pattern
  • Further facts – Philosophy idea
  • Hard problem of consciousness – Philosophical concept, first stated by David Chalmers in 1995
  • Ideasthesia – Phenomenon in which concepts evoke sensory experiences
  • Knowledge argument – Thought experiment
  • Mind–body problem – Open question in philosophy of how abstract minds interact with physical bodies
  • Open individualism – Philosophical concept
  • Philosophical zombie – Thought experiment in philosophy
  • Process philosophy – Philosophical approach
  • Self-awareness – Capacity for introspection and individuation as a subject
  • Self-reference – Sentence, idea or formula that refers to itself
  • Subjectivity – Philosophical concept, related to consciousness, agency, personhood, reality, and truth
  • Synesthesia – Neurological condition involving the crossing of senses
  • Vertiginous question – philosophical question: “of all the subjects of experience out there, why is this one—the one corresponding to the human being referred to as me—the one whose experiences are live?”

Notes

  1. ^ Epiphenomenalism has few friends. It has been deemed "thoughtless and incoherent" – Taylor (1927)[51]
    • "unintelligible" – Benecke (1901)[52]
    • "truly incredible" – McLaughlin (1994)[53]

References

  1. ^ Kriegel, Uriah (2014). Current Controversies In Philosophy of Mind. New York: Taylor & Francis. p. 201. ISBN 978-0415530866.
  2. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel (1985-11-21). Quining Qualia. Oxford University Press. Retrieved 2020-05-19.
  3. ^ Dennett, D. (2002). "Quining qualia". In Chalmers, D. (ed.). Philosophy of mind. Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 226–246.
    • Dennett, D. (2015). "Why and how does consciousness seem the way it seems?". In Metzinger, T.; Windt, J. (eds.). Open mind. Mind Group. pp. 387–398.
  4. ^ Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens. Harcourt Brace.
    • Edelman, G.; Gally, J.; Baars, B. (2011). "Biology of consciousness". Frontiers In Psychology. 2 (4): 1–6.
    • Edelman, G. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire. BasicBooks.
    • Edelman, G. (2003). "Naturalizing consciousness: A theoretical framework". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 100 (9): 5520–5524.
    • Koch, C. (2019). The feeling of life itself. The MIT Press.
    • Llinás, R. (2003). I of the Vortex. MIT Press. pp. 202–207.
    • Oizumi, M.; Albantakis, L.; Tononi, G. (2014). "From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated information theory 3.0". PLOS Computational Biology. 10. e1003588
    • Overgaard, M.; Mogensen, J.; Kirkeby-Hinrup, A., eds. (2021). Beyond neural correlates of consciousness. Routledge Taylor & Francis.
    • Ramachandran, V.; Hirstein, W. (1997). "Three laws of qualia. What neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness, qualia and the self". Journal of consciousness studies. 4 (5–6): 429–458.
    • Tononi, G.; Boly, M.; Massimini, M.; Koch, C. (2016). "Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical substrate". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 17: 450–461.
  5. ^ Eliasmith, Chris (2004-05-11). "qualia". Philosophy. Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind. Canada: University of Waterloo. Retrieved 2010-12-03.
  6. ^ Peirce, C.S. Writings Chronological Edition. Vol. 1. pp. 477–478.
  7. ^ a b c Lewis, C.I. (1929). Mind and the World-Order: Outline of a theory of knowledge. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. p. 121.
  8. ^ a b Jackson, Frank (1982). "Epiphenomenal Qualia" (PDF). The Philosophical Quarterly. 32 (127): 127–136. doi:10.2307/2960077. JSTOR 2960077. Retrieved August 7, 2019.
  9. ^ Kripke, Saul "Identity and Necessity" (1971)
  10. ^ Kripke, Saul A. (1972), "Naming and Necessity", Semantics of Natural Language, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 253–355, ISBN 978-90-277-0310-1, retrieved 2023-04-26
  11. ^ Levy, Neil (1 January 2014). "The value of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 21 (1–2): 127–138. PMC 4001209. PMID 24791144.
    • Shepherd, J. (2018). Consciousness and Moral Status. Routledge, Taylor & Francis group.
  12. ^ Jackson, Frank (1982); Feigl, H. (1958); Broad, C.D. (1925) (2021). "Qualia: The Knowledge Argument". § 1. History of the underlying ideas. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Qualia knowledge. Stanford U.
  13. ^ a b Nagel, Thomas (October 1974). "What is it like to be a bat?". The Philosophical Review. 83 (4): 435–450. doi:10.2307/2183914. JSTOR 2183914.
  14. ^ a b c d e f g Tye, Michael (2000). Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  15. ^ Locke, John (1975) [1689]. "Essay Concerning Human Understanding". [title not cited]. Oxford: Oxford University Press. II, xxxii, 15.[full citation needed]
  16. ^ a b "Inverted qualia". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 2010-12-03 – via Plato.stanford.edu.
  17. ^ a b Hardin, C.L. (1987). "Qualia and materialism: Closing the explanatory gap". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (2): 281–298. doi:10.2307/2107629. JSTOR 2107629.
  18. ^ Stratton, George M. (1896). "Some preliminary experiments on vision" (PDF). Psychological Review.
    • Slater, A.M., ed. (1999). Perceptual Development: Visual, auditory and speech perception in infancy. East Sussex: Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0863778513 – via Google Books.
  19. ^ a b Dennett, D.C. (20 October 1992). Consciousness Explained (1st ed.). Back Bay Books. ISBN 978-0316180665.
  20. ^ . Cognet.mit.edu. 2000-09-26. Archived from the original on 2010-08-31. Retrieved 2010-12-03.
  21. ^ Dennett, D.C. (1988). "Quining qualia". In Marcel, A.J.; Bisiach, E. (eds.). Consciousness in Contemporary Science. Clarendon Press / Oxford University Press. pp. 42–77.
  22. ^ Ungerleider, L.G. (3 November 1995). "Functional brain imaging studies of cortical mechanisms for memory". Science. 270 (5237): 769–775. Bibcode:1995Sci...270..769U. doi:10.1126/science.270.5237.769. PMID 7481764. S2CID 37665998.
  23. ^ a b Dennett, D.C. (April 2001). "Are we explaining consciousness yet?". Cognition. 79 (1–2): 221–237. doi:10.1016/s0010-0277(00)00130-x. PMID 11164029. S2CID 2235514.
  24. ^ Churchland, Paul (2004). "Knowing qualia: A reply to Jackson (with postscript 1997)". In Ludlow, Peter; Nagasawa, Yujin; Stoljar, Daniel (eds.). There's Something about Mary. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 163–178.
  25. ^ a b Drescher, G. (2006). Good and Real. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 978-0262042338 – via Google Books.
  26. ^ Lewis, D.K. (2004). "What experience teaches". In Ludlow, Peter; Nagasawa, Yujin; Stoljar, Daniel (eds.). There's Something about Mary. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 77–103.
  27. ^ "Edge interview with Marvin Minsky". Edge.org. Edge Foundation, Inc. 1998-02-26. Retrieved 2010-12-03.
  28. ^ Tye, M. (1991). The Imagery Debate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
    • Tye, M. (1995). Ten Problems of Consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  29. ^ Scruton, Roger (2017). On Human Nature.
  30. ^ Kind, Amy. "Qualia". Internet Encyclopedia of Philoshopy. Retrieved 6 November 2022.
  31. ^ Chalmers, D. (1995). "Absent qualia, fading qualia, dancing qualia". In Metzinger, Thomas (ed.). Conscious Experience. Imprint Academic;
          free copy available from
    "qualia on consc.net".
  32. ^ a b Lowe, E. J. (1996). Subjects of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 101.
  33. ^ Lowe, E. J. (2008). "Illusions and hallucinations as evidence for sense-data". In Wright, Edmond (ed.). The Case for Qualia. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 59–72. ISBN 978-0262731881 – via Google Books.
  34. ^ Maund, J.B. (September 1975). "The representative theory of perception". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 5 (1): 41–55. doi:10.1080/00455091.1975.10716096. S2CID 146937154.
  35. ^ Maund, J.B. (1995). Colours: Their nature and representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521472739 – via Google Books;
    • Maund, J.B. (2003). Perception. Chesham: Acumen Pub. Ltd.
  36. ^ Perkins, Moreland (1983). Sensing the World. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. Co. ISBN 978-0915145751 – via Archive.org.
  37. ^ Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson. p. 215.
  38. ^ Ayer, A.J. (1957). The Problem of Knowledge. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. p. 107.
  39. ^ Robinson, William (2004). Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  40. ^ a b Wright, Edmond, ed. (2008). The Case for Qualia (publisher's abstract). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
    • Wright, Edmond (2005-11-16). "Narrative, Perception, Language, and Faith". Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan. Retrieved 2010-12-03.
  41. ^ a b Schrödinger, Erwin (2001) [1958]. What is Life? : The physical aspects of the living cell (reprint ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521427081.
  42. ^ Edelman, G. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire. On the matter of mind. Basic Books. p. 115.
  43. ^ a b Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens. Heineman.
  44. ^ Damasio, A. (2010). Self comes to mind. Constructing the conscious brain. Knopf Doubleday Publishing.
  45. ^ a b Llinás, R. (2002). I of the Vortex. From neurons to self. The MIT Press.
  46. ^ a b c Ramachandran, V.S.; Hirstein, W. (1 May 1997). "Three laws of qualia: What neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (5–6): 429–457;
        also available from
    "Three laws of qualia" (PDF). imprint.co.uk.
  47. ^ Ramachandran, V.S.; Hirstein, W. (1 December 2001). "Synaesthesia – a window into perception, thought, and language". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 8 (12): 3–34.
  48. ^ Orpwood, Roger D. (December 2007). "Neurobiological mechanisms underlying qualia". Journal of Integrative Neuroscience. 06 (4): 523–540. doi:10.1142/s0219635207001696. PMID 18181267.
    • Orpwood, Roger D. (June 2010). "Perceptual qualia and local network behavior in the cerebral cortex". Journal of Integrative Neuroscience. 09 (2): 123–152. doi:10.1142/s021963521000241x. PMID 20589951.
  49. ^ a b Orpwood, Roger D. (2013). "Qualia could arise from information processing in local cortical networks". Frontiers in Psychology. 4: 121. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00121. PMC 3596736. PMID 23504586.
  50. ^ Elston, G.N. (1 November 2003). "Cortex, cognition, and the cell: New insights into the pyramidal neuron and prefrontal function". Cerebral Cortex. 13 (11): 1124–1138. doi:10.1093/cercor/bhg093. PMID 14576205.
  51. ^ Taylor, A. (1927). Plato: The man and his work. New York: MacVeagh. p. 198.
  52. ^ Benecke, E.C. (1900–1901). "On the aspect theory of the relation of mind to body". Aristotelian Society Proceedings. n.s. 1: 18–44. doi:10.1093/aristotelian/1.1.18.
  53. ^ McLaughlin, B. (1994). Guttenplan, S. (ed.). Epiphenomenalism, a Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 277–288.
  54. ^ Georgiev, Danko D. (2017). Quantum Information and Consciousness: A gentle introduction. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press. p. 362. doi:10.1201/9780203732519. ISBN 978-1138104488. OCLC 1003273264. Zbl 1390.81001.
    • Georgiev, Danko D. (2020). "Inner privacy of conscious experiences and quantum information". BioSystems. 187: 104051. arXiv:2001.00909. doi:10.1016/j.biosystems.2019.104051. PMID 31629783. S2CID 204813557.
  55. ^ Hardin, C.L. (1988). Color for Philosophers. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. Co. ISBN 0872200396 – via Google Books.
  56. ^ McDowell, John (1994). Mind and World. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. p. 42.
  57. ^ Roberson, Gwendolyn E.; Wallace, Mark T.; Schirillo, James A. (October 2001). "The sensorimotor contingency of multisensory localization correlates with the conscious percept of spatial unity". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 24 (5): 1001–1002. doi:10.1017/S0140525X0154011X.
  58. ^ Warren, Richard M.; Warren, Roslyn P., eds. (1968). Helmholtz on Perception: Its physiology and development. New York: John Wiley & Sons. p. 178.
  59. ^ Price, Hubert H. (1932). Perception. London: Methuen. p. 32.
  60. ^ Sellars, Roy Wood (1922). Evolutionary Naturalism. Chicago & London: Open Court Pub. Co.
  61. ^ Amoroso, Richard L. (2010). Complementarity of Mind & Body: Realizing the dream of Descartes, Einstein, & Eccles. New York: Nova Science Publishers.

Other references

Further reading

  • Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A.; Nikolić, D. (2014). "Semantic mechanisms may be responsible for developing synesthesia" (PDF). Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 8: 509. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00509. PMC 4137691. PMID 25191239.

External links

qualia, this, article, about, philosophical, concept, other, uses, disambiguation, philosophy, mind, qualia, ɑː, singular, form, quale, defined, instances, subjective, conscious, experience, term, qualia, derives, from, latin, neuter, plural, form, qualia, lat. This article is about the philosophical concept For other uses see Qualia disambiguation In philosophy of mind qualia ˈ k w ɑː l i e or ˈ k w eɪ l i e singular form quale are defined as instances of subjective conscious experience The term qualia derives from the Latin neuter plural form qualia of the Latin adjective qualis Latin pronunciation ˈkʷaːlɪs meaning of what sort or of what kind in a specific instance such as what it is like to taste a specific apple this particular apple now The redness of red is a commonly used example of a quale Examples of qualia include the perceived sensation of pain of a headache the taste of wine and the redness of an evening sky As qualitative characteristics of sensation qualia stand in contrast to propositional attitudes 1 where the focus is on beliefs about experience rather than what it is directly like to be experiencing Philosopher and cognitive scientist Daniel Dennett suggested that qualia was an unfamiliar term for something that could not be more familiar to each of us the ways things seem to us 2 Much of the debate over the importance of qualia hinges on the definition of the term and various philosophers emphasize or deny the existence of certain features of qualia Consequently the nature and existence of qualia under various definitions remain controversial While some philosophers of mind like Daniel Dennett argue that qualia do not exist and are incompatible with neuroscience and naturalism 3 some neuroscientists and neurologists like Gerald Edelman Antonio Damasio Vilayanur Ramachandran Giulio Tononi Christof Koch and Rodolfo Llinas state that qualia exist and that the desire by some philosophers to disregard qualia is based on an erroneous interpretation of what constitutes science 4 Contents 1 Definitions 2 Arguments for the existence of qualia 2 1 What s it like to be argument 2 2 Inverted spectrum argument 2 3 Zombie argument 2 4 Explanatory gap argument 2 5 Knowledge argument 3 Analytical philosophers who are critics of qualia 3 1 Daniel Dennett 3 2 Paul Churchland 3 3 Gary Drescher 3 4 David Lewis 3 5 Marvin Minsky 3 6 Michael Tye 3 7 Roger Scruton 4 Analytical philosophers who are proponents of qualia 4 1 David Chalmers 4 2 E J Lowe 4 3 J B Maund 4 4 Moreland Perkins 4 5 Howard Robinson and William Robinson 4 6 Edmond Wright 4 7 Erwin Schrodinger 5 Neuroscientists who state that qualia exist 5 1 Gerald Edelman 5 2 Antonio Damasio 5 3 Rodolfo Llinas 5 4 Vilayanur Ramachandran 5 5 Roger Orpwood 6 Other issues 6 1 Indeterminacy 6 2 Causal efficacy 6 3 Epistemological issues 7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 9 1 Other references 10 Further reading 11 External linksDefinitions EditMany definitions of qualia have been proposed One of the simpler broader definitions is The what it is like character of mental states The way it feels to have mental states such as pain seeing red smelling a rose etc 5 C S Peirce introduced the term quale in philosophy in 1866 6 7 C I Lewis 1929 7 was the first to use the term qualia in its generally agreed upon modern sense There are recognizable qualitative characters of the given which may be repeated in different experiences and are thus a sort of universals I call these qualia But although such qualia are universals in the sense of being recognized from one to another experience they must be distinguished from the properties of objects Confusion of these two is characteristic of many historical conceptions as well as of current essence theories The quale is directly intuited given and is not the subject of any possible error because it is purely subjective 7 Frank Jackson later defined qualia as certain features of the bodily sensations especially but also of certain perceptual experiences which no amount of purely physical information includes 8 273 Daniel Dennett identifies four properties that are commonly ascribed to qualia 2 According to these qualia are ineffable they cannot be communicated or apprehended by any means other than direct experience intrinsic they are non relational properties which do not change depending on the experience s relation to other things private all interpersonal comparisons of qualia are systematically impossible directly or immediately apprehensible by consciousness to experience a quale is to know one experiences a quale and to know all there is to know about that quale If qualia of this sort exist then a normally sighted person who sees red would be unable to describe the experience of this perception in such a way that a listener who has never experienced color will be able to know everything there is to know about that experience Though it is possible to make an analogy such as red looks hot or to provide a description of the conditions under which the experience occurs such as it s the color you see when light of 700 nm wavelength is directed at you supporters of this definition of qualia contend that such descriptions cannot provide a complete description of the experience citation needed Another way of defining qualia is as raw feels A raw feel is a perception in and of itself considered entirely in isolation from any effect it might have on behavior and behavioral disposition In contrast a cooked feel is that perception seen in terms of its effects For example the perception of the taste of wine is an ineffable raw feel while the behavioral reaction one has to the warmth or bitterness caused by that taste of wine would be a cooked feel Cooked feels are not qualia citation needed Saul Kripke argues that one key consequence of the claim that such things as raw feels can be meaningfully discussed that qualia exist clarification needed is that it leads to the logical possibility of two entities exhibiting identical behavior in all ways despite one of them entirely lacking qualia 9 While few claim that such an entity called a philosophical zombie actually exists the possibility is raised as a refutation of physicalism 10 further explanation needed Arguably the idea of hedonistic utilitarianism where the ethical value of things is determined from the amount of subjective pleasure or pain they cause is dependent on the existence of qualia 11 Arguments for the existence of qualia EditSee also Hard problem of consciousness Since by definition one cannot fully convey qualia verbally one also cannot demonstrate them directly in an argument so a more nuanced approach is needed Arguments for qualia generally come in the form of thought experiments designed to lead one to the conclusion that qualia exist 12 What s it like to be argument Edit Main article Subjective character of experience Thomas Nagel s paper What is it like to be a bat 13 although it does not use the word qualia is often cited in debates about qualia Nagel argues that consciousness has an essentially subjective character a what it is like aspect He states that an organism has conscious mental states if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism something it is like for the organism 13 Nagel suggests that this subjective aspect may never be sufficiently accounted for by the objective methods of reductionistic science He claims that if we acknowledge that a physical theory of mind must account for the subjective character of experience we must admit that no presently available conception gives us a clue about how this could be done 14 450 Furthermore it seems unlikely that any physical theory of mind can be contemplated until more thought has been given to the general problem of subjective and objective 14 450 Inverted spectrum argument Edit Main article Inverted spectrum Inverted qualia The inverted spectrum thought experiment originally developed by John Locke 15 invites us to imagine that we wake up one morning and find that for some unknown reason all the colors in the world have been inverted i e swapped to the hue on the opposite side of a color wheel Furthermore we discover that no physical changes have occurred in our brains or bodies that would explain this phenomenon Supporters of the existence of qualia argue that since we can imagine this happening without contradiction it follows that we are imagining a change in a property that determines the way things look to us but that has no physical basis 16 17 In more detail Metaphysical identity holds of necessity clarification needed If something is possibly false it is not necessary It is conceivable that qualia could have a different relationship to physical brain states If it is conceivable then it is possible Since it is possible for qualia to have a different relationship with physical brain states they cannot be identical to brain states by 1 Therefore qualia are non physical The argument thus claims that if we find the inverted spectrum plausible we must admit that qualia exist and are non physical Some philosophers find it absurd that armchair theorizing can prove something to exist and the detailed argument does involve a lot of assumptions about conceivability and possibility which are open to criticism Perhaps it is not possible for a given brain state to produce anything other than a given quale in our universe and that is all that matters The idea that an inverted spectrum would be undetectable in practice is also open to criticism on more scientific grounds see main article 16 17 There is an actual experiment albeit somewhat obscure that parallels the inverted spectrum argument George M Stratton professor of psychology at the University of California Berkeley performed an experiment in which he wore special prism glasses that caused the external world to appear upside down 18 After a few days of continually wearing the glasses he adapted and the external world appeared upright to him When he removed the glasses his perception of the external world again returned to the normal perceptual state If this argument provides indicia that qualia exist it does not necessarily follow that they must be non physical because that distinction should be considered a separate epistemological issue Zombie argument Edit Main article Philosophical zombie An argument holds that it is not inconceivable for a set of people to have qualia while physical duplicates of that set called philosophical zombies do not These zombies would demonstrate outward behavior including utterances exactly the same as normal humans who are assumed to have subjective phenomenology without subjective phenomenology For there to be a valid distinction between normal humans and philosophical zombies there must be no specific part or parts of the brain that directly give rise to qualia The zombie normal human distinction can only be valid if subjective consciousness is causally separate from the physical brain citation needed Are zombies possible They re not just possible they re actual We re all zombies Nobody is conscious D C Dennett 1992 19 page needed Explanatory gap argument Edit Main article Explanatory gap Joseph Levine s paper Conceivability Identity and the Explanatory Gap takes up where the criticisms of conceivability arguments such as the inverted spectrum argument and the zombie argument leave off Levine agrees that conceivability is a flawed means of establishing metaphysical realities but points out that even if we come to the metaphysical conclusion that qualia are physical there is still an explanatory problem While I think this materialist response is right in the end it does not suffice to put the mind body problem to rest Even if conceivability considerations do not establish that the mind is in fact distinct from the body or that mental properties are metaphysically irreducible to physical properties still they do demonstrate that we lack an explanation of the mental in terms of the physical However such an epistemological or explanatory problem might indicate an underlying metaphysical issue the non physicality of qualia even if not proven by conceivability arguments is far from ruled out In the end we are right back where we started The explanatory gap argument doesn t demonstrate a gap in nature but a gap in our understanding of nature Of course a plausible explanation for there being a gap in our understanding of nature is that there is a genuine gap in nature But so long as we have countervailing reasons for doubting the latter we have to look elsewhere for an explanation of the former 20 Knowledge argument Edit Main article Knowledge argument F C Jackson offers what he calls the knowledge argument for qualia 8 One example runs as follows Mary the color scientist knows all the physical facts about color including every physical fact about the experience of color in other people from the behavior a particular color is likely to elicit to the specific sequence of neurological firings that register that a color has been seen However she has been confined from birth to a room that is black and white and is only allowed to observe the outside world through a black and white monitor When she is allowed to leave the room it must be admitted that she learns something about the color red the first time she sees it specifically she learns what it is like to see that color This thought experiment has two purposes First it is intended to show that qualia exist If we accept the thought experiment we believe that Mary gains something after she leaves the room that she acquires knowledge of a particular thing that she did not possess before That knowledge Jackson argues is knowledge of the quale that corresponds to the experience of seeing red and it must thus be conceded that qualia are real properties since there is a difference between a person who has access to a particular quale and one who does not The second purpose of this argument is to refute the physicalist account of the mind Specifically the knowledge argument is an attack on the physicalist claim about the completeness of physical truths The challenge posed to physicalism by the knowledge argument runs as follows Before her release Mary was in possession of all the physical information about color experiences of other people After her release Mary learns something about the color experiences of other people Therefore Before her release Mary was not in possession of all the information about other people s color experiences even though she was in possession of all the physical information Therefore There are truths about other people s color experience that are not physical Therefore Physicalism is false At first Jackson argued that qualia are epiphenomenal not causally efficacious with respect to the physical world Jackson does not give a positive justification for this claim rather he seems to assert it simply because it defends qualia against the classic problems of dualism Our who natural assumption would be that qualia must be causally efficacious in the physical world but some would ask how we who could argue for their existence if they did not affect our brains If qualia are non physical properties which they must be in order to constitute an argument against physicalism some who question how they could have a causal effect on the physical world By redefining qualia as epiphenomenal Jackson attempts to protect them from the demand of playing a causal role Later however Jackson rejected epiphenomenalism This he argues is because when Mary first sees red she says wow so it must be Mary s qualia that cause her to say wow This contradicts epiphenomenalism Since the Mary s room thought experiment seems to create this contradiction there must be something wrong with it clarification needed This ambiguous is often referred to as the there must be a reply reply citation needed Analytical philosophers who are critics of qualia EditDaniel Dennett Edit Daniel Dennett In Consciousness Explained 1991 19 and Quining Qualia 1988 21 Daniel Dennett argues against qualia by claiming that the which above definition breaks down if one tries to practically apply it In a series of thought experiments which he calls intuition pumps he brings qualia into the world of neurosurgery clinical psychology and psychological experimentation He argues that once the concept of qualia is so imported we can either make no use of it or the questions introduced by it are unanswerable precisely because of the special properties defined for qualia citation needed In Dennett s updated version of the inverted spectrum thought experiment alternative neurosurgery you again awake to find that your qualia have been inverted grass appears red the sky appears orange etc According to the original account you should be immediately aware that something has gone horribly wrong Dennett argues however that it is impossible to know whether the diabolical neurosurgeons have indeed inverted your qualia by tampering with your optic nerve say or have simply inverted your connection to memories of past qualia Since both operations would produce the same result you would have no means on your own to tell which operation has actually been conducted and you are thus in the odd position of not knowing whether there has been a change in your immediately apprehensible qualia citation needed Dennett s argues that for qualia to be taken seriously as a component of experience for them to make sense as a discrete concept it must be possible to show that it is possible to know that a change in qualia has occurred as opposed to a change in something else or thatthere is a difference between having a change in qualia and not having one Dennett attempts to show that we cannot satisfy a either through introspection or through observation and that qualia s very definition undermines its chances of satisfying b Supporters of qualia could point out that in order for you to notice a change in qualia you must compare your current qualia with your memories of past qualia Arguably such a comparison would involve immediate apprehension of your current qualia and your memories of past qualia but not the past qualia themselves Furthermore modern functional brain imaging has increasingly suggested that the memory of an experience is processed in similar ways and in similar zones of the brain as those originally involved in the original perception 22 This may mean that there would be asymmetry in outcomes between altering the mechanism of perception of qualia and altering their memories If the diabolical neurosurgery altered the immediate perception of qualia you might not even notice the inversion directly since the brain zones which re process the memories would themselves invert the qualia remembered On the other hand alteration of the qualia memories themselves would be processed without inversion and thus you would perceive them as an inversion Thus you might know immediately if memory of your qualia had been altered but might not know if immediate qualia were inverted or whether the diabolical neurosurgeons had done a sham procedure original research Dennett responds to the Mary the color scientist thought experiment by arguing that Mary would not in fact learn something new if she stepped out of her black and white room to see the color red Dennett asserts that if she already truly knew everything about color that knowledge would include a deep understanding of why and how human neurology causes us to sense the quale of color Mary would therefore already know exactly what to expect of seeing red before ever leaving the room Dennett argues that the misleading aspect of the story is that Mary is supposed to not merely be knowledgeable about color but to actually know all the physical facts about it which would be a knowledge so deep that it exceeds what can be imagined and twists our intuitions If Mary really does know everything physical there is to know about the experience of color then this effectively grants her almost omniscient powers of knowledge Using this she will be able to deduce her own reaction and figure out exactly what the experience of seeing red will feel like Dennett finds that many people find it difficult to see this so he uses the case of RoboMary to further illustrate what it would be like for Mary to possess such a vast knowledge of the physical workings of the human brain and color vision RoboMary is an intelligent robot who has instead of the ordinary color camera eyes a software lock such that she is only able to perceive black and white and shades in between citation needed RoboMary can examine the computer brain of similar non color locked robots when they look at a red tomato and see exactly how they react and what kinds of impulses occur RoboMary can also construct a simulation of her own brain unlock the simulation s color lock and with reference to the other robots simulate exactly how this simulation of herself reacts to seeing a red tomato RoboMary naturally has control over all of her internal states except for the color lock With the knowledge of her simulation s internal states upon seeing a red tomato RoboMary can put her own internal states directly into the states they would be in upon seeing a red tomato In this way without ever seeing a red tomato through her cameras she will know exactly what it is like to see a red tomato citation needed Dennett uses this example as attempt to show us that Mary s all encompassing physical knowledge makes her own internal states as transparent as those of a robot or computer and it is almost straightforward for her to figure out exactly how it feels to see red citation needed Perhaps Mary s failure to learn exactly what seeing red feels like is simply a failure of language or a failure of our ability to describe experiences An alien race with a different method of communication or description might be perfectly able to teach their version of Mary exactly how seeing the color red would feel Perhaps it is simply a uniquely human failing to communicate first person experiences from a third person perspective Dennett suggests that the description might even be possible using English He uses a simpler version of the Mary thought experiment to show how this might work What if Mary was in a room without triangles and was prevented from seeing or making any triangles An English language description of just a few words would be sufficient for her to imagine what it is like to see a triangle she can simply and directly visualize a triangle in her mind Similarly Dennett proposes it is perfectly logically possible that the quale of what it is like to see red could eventually be described in an English language description of millions or billions of words citation needed In Are we explaining consciousness yet 2001 23 Dennett approves of an account of qualia defined as the deep rich collection of individual neural responses that are too fine grained for language to capture For instance a person might have an alarming reaction to yellow because of a yellow car that hit her previously and someone else might have a nostalgic reaction to a comfort food These effects are too individual specific to be captured by English words If one dubs this inevitable residue qualia then qualia are guaranteed to exist but they are just more of the same dispositional properties that have not yet been entered in the catalog 23 Paul Churchland Edit According to Paul Churchland Mary might be considered to be like a feral child Feral children have suffered extreme isolation during childhood Technically when Mary leaves the room she would not have the ability to see or know what the color red is A brain has to learn and develop how to see colors Patterns need to form in the V4 section of the visual cortex These patterns are formed from exposure to wavelengths of light This exposure is needed during the early stages of brain development In Mary s case the identifications and categorizations of color will only be in respect to representations of black and white 24 Gary Drescher Edit In his book Good and Real 2006 25 Gary Drescher compares qualia with gensyms generated symbols in Common Lisp These are objects that Lisp treats as having no properties or components and which can only be identified as equal or not equal to other objects Drescher explains we have no introspective access to whatever internal properties make the red gensym recognizably distinct from the green even though we know the sensation when we experience it 25 Under this interpretation of qualia Drescher responds to the Mary thought experiment by noting that knowing about red related cognitive structures and the dispositions they engender even if that knowledge were implausibly detailed and exhaustive would not necessarily give someone who lacks prior color experience the slightest clue whether the card now being shown is of the color called red This does not however imply that our experience of red is non mechanical on the contrary gensyms are a routine feature of computer programming languages 14 82 David Lewis Edit D K Lewis introduced a hypothesis about types of knowledge and their transmission in qualia cases Lewis agrees that Mary cannot learn what red looks like through her monochrome physicalist studies But he proposes that this does not matter Learning transmits information but experiencing qualia does not transmit information instead it communicates abilities When Mary sees red she does not get any new information She gains new abilities now she can remember what red looks like imagine what other red things might look like and recognize further instances of redness Lewis states that Jackson s thought experiment uses the phenomenal information hypothesis that is that the new knowledge that Mary gains upon seeing red is phenomenal information Lewis then proposes a different ability hypothesis that differentiates between two types of knowledge knowledge that information and knowledge how abilities Normally the two are entangled ordinary learning is also an experience of the subject concerned and people both learn information for instance that Freud was a psychologist and gain ability to recognize images of Freud However in the thought experiment Mary can only use ordinary learning to gain know that knowledge She is prevented from using experience to gain the know how knowledge that would allow her to remember imagine and recognize the color red We have the intuition that Mary has been deprived of some vital data to do with the experience of redness It is also uncontroversial that some things cannot be learned inside the room for example we do not expect Mary to learn how to ski within the room Lewis has articulated that information and ability are potentially different things In this way physicalism is still compatible with the conclusion that Mary gains new knowledge It is also useful for considering other instances of qualia being a bat is an ability so it is know how knowledge 26 Marvin Minsky Edit Marvin Minsky Artificial intelligence researcher Marvin Minsky thinks the problems posed by qualia are essentially issues of complexity or rather of mistaking complexity for simplicity Now a philosophical dualist might then complain You ve described how hurting affects your mind but you still can t express how hurting feels This I maintain is a huge mistake that attempt to reify feeling as an independent entity with an essence that s indescribable As I see it feelings are not strange alien things It is precisely those cognitive changes themselves that constitute what hurting is and this also includes all those clumsy attempts to represent and summarize those changes The big mistake comes from looking for some single simple essence of hurting rather than recognizing that this is the word we use for complex rearrangement of our disposition of resources 27 Michael Tye Edit Michael Tye Michael Tye believes there are no qualia no veils of perception between us and the referents of our thought He describes our experience of an object in the world as transparent By this he means that no matter what private understandings and or misunderstandings we may have of some public entity it is still there before us in reality The idea that qualia intervene between ourselves and their origins he regards as a massive error as he says it is just not credible that visual experiences are systematically misleading in this way 14 46 the only objects of which you are aware are the external ones making up the scene before your eyes 14 47 there are no such things as the qualities of experiences for they are qualities of external surfaces and volumes and films if they are qualities of anything 14 48 He believes we can take our experiences at face value since there is no fear of losing contact with the realness of public objects In Tye s thought there is no question of qualia without information being contained within them it is always an awareness that always representational He characterizes the perception of children as a misperception of referents that are undoubtedly as present for them as they are for grown ups As he puts it they may not know that the house is dilapidated but there is no doubt about their seeing the house After images are dismissed as presenting no problem for the Transparency theory because as he puts it after images being illusory there is nothing that one sees Tye proposes that phenomenal experience has five basic elements for which he has coined the acronym PANIC Poised Abstract Nonconceptual Intentional Content 14 63 It is Poised in the sense that the phenomenal experience is always presented to the understanding whether or not the agent is able to apply a concept to it Tye adds that the experience is maplike in that in most cases it reaches through to the distribution clarification needed of shapes edges volumes etc in the world you may not be reading the map but as with an actual map there is a reliable match with what it is mapping It is Abstract because it is still an open question in a particular case whether you are in touch with a concrete object someone may feel a pain in a left leg when that leg has actually been amputated It is Nonconceptual because a phenomenon can exist although one does not have the concept by which to recognize it Nevertheless it is Intentional in the sense that it represents something again whether or not the particular observer is taking advantage of that fact this is why Tye calls his theory representationalism This last makes it plain that Tye believes that he has retained a direct contact with what produces the phenomena and is therefore not hampered by any trace of a veil of perception 28 Roger Scruton Edit Roger Scruton while sceptical that neurobiology can tell us much about consciousness believes qualia is an incoherent concept and that Wittgenstein s private language argument effectively disproves it Scruton writes The belief that these essentially private features of mental states exist and that they form the introspectible essence of whatever possesses them is grounded in a confusion one that Wittgenstein tried to sweep away in his arguments against the possibility of a private language When you judge that I am in pain it is on the basis of my circumstances and behavior and you could be wrong When I ascribe a pain to myself I don t use any such evidence I don t find out that I am in pain by observation nor can I be wrong But that is not because there is some other fact about my pain accessible only to me which I consult in order to establish what I am feeling For if there were this inner private quality I could misperceive it I could get it wrong and I would have to find out whether I am in pain To describe my inner state I would also have to invent a language intelligible only to me and that Wittgenstein plausibly argues is impossible The conclusion to draw is that I ascribe pain to myself not on the basis of some inner quale but on no basis at all In his book On Human Nature Scruton poses a potential line of criticism to this which is that while Wittgenstein s private language argument does disprove the concept of reference to qualia or the idea that we can talk even to ourselves of their nature it does not disprove their existence altogether Scruton believes that this is a valid criticism and this is why he stops short of actually saying that qualia do not exist and instead merely suggests that we should abandon them as a concept However he quotes Wittgenstein in response Whereof one cannot speak thereof one must be silent 29 Analytical philosophers who are proponents of qualia EditDavid Chalmers Edit David Chalmers David Chalmers formulated the hard problem of consciousness which raised the issue of qualia to a new level of importance and acceptance in the field clarification needed 30 In Chalmers 1995 31 he also argued for what he called the principle of organizational invariance If a system such as one of appropriately configured computer hardware reproduces the functional organization of the brain it will also reproduce the qualia associated with the brain E J Lowe Edit E J Lowe denies that indirect realism in which we have access only to sensory features internal to the brain necessarily implies a Cartesian dualism He agrees with Bertrand Russell that our retinal images that is the distributions across clarification needed our retinas are connected to vague patterns of neural activity in the cortex 32 He defends a version of the causal theory of perception in which a causal path can be traced between the external object and the perception of it He is careful to deny that we do any inferring from the sensory field clarification needed he believes this allows us to found an access to knowledge on that causal connection In a later work he moves closer to the non epistemic argument in that he postulates a wholly non conceptual component of perceptual experience 32 but he refrains from analyzing the relation between the perceptual and the non conceptual More recently he drew attention to the problems that hallucination raises for the direct realist and to their disinclination to enter the discussion on the topic 33 J B Maund Edit This section may need to be rewritten to comply with Wikipedia s quality standards You can help The talk page may contain suggestions September 2014 John Barry Maund an Australian philosopher of perception argues that qualia can be described on two levels a fact that he refers to as dual coding 34 If asked what we see on a television screen there are two varieties of answer that we might give Consider the example of a Movitype screen often used for advertisements and announcements in public places A Movitype screen consists of a matrix or raster as the neuroscientists prefer to call it from the Latin rastrum a rake think of the lines on a TV screen as raked across that is made up of an array of tiny light sources A computer can excite these lights so as to give the impression of letters passing from right to left or even to show moving pictures In describing what we see on such a screen we could adopt the everyday public language and say I saw some sentences followed by a picture of a 7 Up can Although that is a perfectly adequate way of describing the sight nevertheless there is a scientific way of describing it which bears no relation whatsoever to this commonsense description One could ask an electronics engineer to provide us with a computer print out staged across the seconds that we were watching of the point states of the raster of lights This would no doubt be a long and complex document with the state of each tiny light source given its place in the sequence Although such a list would give a comprehensive and point by point detailed description of the state of the screen nowhere would it contain mention of English sentences or a 7 Up can This illustrates that there are two ways to describe such a screen 1 the commonsense one which refers to publicly recognizable objects and 2 an accurate point by point account of the actual state of the field that makes no mention of what any passer by would or would not make of it This second description would be non epistemic from the common sense point of view since no objects are mentioned in the print out but perfectly acceptable from the engineer s point of view Note that if one carries this analysis across to human sensing and perceiving this rules out Dennett s claim that all qualiaphiles must regard qualia as ineffable for at this second level they are in principle quite effable indeed it is not ruled out that some neurophysiologist of the future might be able to describe the neural detail of qualia at this level Maund extended his argument with reference to color 35 Color he sees as a dispositional property not an objective one Colors are virtual properties is as if things possessed them Although the naive view attributes them to objects they are intrinsic non relational inner experiences This allows for the facts of difference clarification needed between person and person and also leaves aside the claim that external objects are colored Moreland Perkins Edit In his book Sensing the World 36 Moreland Perkins argues that qualia need not be identified with their objective sources a smell for instance bears no direct resemblance to the molecular shape that gives rise to it nor is a toothache actually in the tooth Like Hobbes he views the process of sensing as complete in itself as he puts it it is not like kicking a football where an external object is required it is more like kicking a kick This explanation evades the Homunculus Objection as adhered to for example by Gilbert Ryle Ryle was unable to entertain this possibility protesting that in effect it explained the having of sensations as the not having of sensations 37 However A J Ayer called this objection very weak as it betrayed an inability to detach the notion of eyes or indeed any sensory organ from the neural sensory experience 38 Howard Robinson and William Robinson Edit Howard Robinson specialized in philosophy of mind He argued against explanations of sensory experience that reduce them to physical origins He never regarded the theory of sense data clarification needed as refuted but set out to refute persuasive objections to it The version of the theory of sense data he defends takes what is before consciousness in perception to be qualia as mental presentations that are causally linked to external entities but which are not physical in themselves needs copy edit He is therefore a dualist one who takes both matter and mind to have real and metaphysically distinct natures One of his articles takes the physicalist to task for ignoring the fact that sensory experience can be entirely free of representational character He cites phosphenes as a stubborn example phosphenes are flashes of light that result either from sudden pressure in the brain as induced for example by intense coughing or through direct physical pressure on the retina and points out that it is counter intuitive to argue that these are not visual experiences on a par with open eye seeing William Robinson no relation takes a similar view in his book Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness 39 He is unusual as a dualist in calling for research programs that investigate the relation of qualia to the brain The problem is so stubborn he says that too many philosophers would prefer to explain it away but he would rather have it explained and does not see why the effort should not be made However he does not expect a straightforward scientific reduction of phenomenal experience to neural architecture he regards this as a forlorn hope The Qualitative Event Realism that Robinson espouses sees phenomenal consciousness as non material events that are caused by brain events but not identical with them He refuses to set aside the vividness and commonness of mental images both visual and aural In this he opposes Daniel Dennett who has difficulty crediting such experience in others He is similar to Moreland Perkins in keeping his investigation wide enough to apply to all the senses Edmond Wright Edit Edmond Wright is a philosopher who considers the inter subjective aspect of perception 40 From John Locke onwards it had been typical to frame perception problems in terms of a single subject S looking at a single entity E with a property p However if we begin with the facts of the differences in sensory registration from person to person coupled with the differences in the criteria we have learned for distinguishing what we together call the same things then a problem arises of how two persons align their differences on these two levels so that they can still get a practical overlap on parts of the real about them and in particular update each other about them needs copy edit Wright was struck by the hearing difference between himself and his son he discovered that his son could hear sounds up to nearly 20 kHz while his range only reached to 14 kHz or so This implies that a difference in qualia could emerge in human action for example the son could warn the father of a high pitched escape of a dangerous gas kept under pressure the sound waves of which would be producing no qualia evidence at all for the father The relevance for language thus becomes critical for an informative statement can best be understood as an updating of a perception and this may involve a radical re selection from the qualia fields viewed as non epistemic even perhaps of the presumed singularity of the referent a fortiori if that referent is the self needs copy edit He distinguishes his view from that of Revonsuo clarification needed who too readily makes his virtual space egocentric importance Wright emphasizes what he asserts is a core feature of communication that in order for an updating to be set up and made possible clarification needed both speaker and hearer have to behave as if they have identified the same singular thing which he notes partakes of the structure of a joke or a story how 40 Wright says that this systematic ambiguity clarification needed seems to opponents of qualia to be a sign of fallacy in the argument as ambiguity is in pure logic whereas on the contrary it is sign in talk about what is perceived of something those speaking to each other have to learn to take advantage of He argues that an important feature of human communication is the degree and character of the faith clarification needed maintained by the participants in the dialogue something that has priority over such virtues of language as sincerity truth and objectivity Indeed he considers that to prioritize them over faith is to move into superstition Erwin Schrodinger Edit Erwin Schrodinger a theoretical physicist and one of the leading pioneers of quantum mechanics also published in the areas of colorimetry and color perception In several of his philosophical writings he defends the notion that qualia are not physical The sensation of colour cannot be accounted for by the physicist s objective picture of light waves Could the physiologist account for it if he had fuller knowledge than he has of the processes in the retina and the nervous processes set up by them in the optical nerve bundles and in the brain I do not think so 41 154 He continues on to remark that subjective experiences do not form a one to one correspondence with stimuli For example light of wavelengths in the neighborhood of 590 nm produces the sensation of yellow whereas exactly the same sensation is produced by mixing red light with wavelength 760 nm with green light at 535 nm From this he concludes that there is no numerical connection with these physical objective characteristics of the waves and the sensations they produce Schrodinger concludes with a proposal of how it is that we might arrive at the mistaken belief that a satisfactory theoretical account of qualitative experience has been or might ever be achieved Scientific theories serve to facilitate the survey of our observations and experimental findings Every scientist knows how difficult it is to remember a moderately extended group of facts before at least some primitive theoretical picture about them has been shaped It is therefore small wonder and by no means to be blamed on the authors of original papers or of text books that after a reasonably coherent theory has been formed they do not describe the bare facts they have found or wish to convey to the reader but clothe them in the terminology of that theory or theories This procedure while very useful for our remembering the fact in a well ordered pattern tends to obliterate the distinction between the actual observations and the theory arisen from them And since the former always are of some sensual quality theories are easily thought to account for sensual qualities which of course they never do 41 163 164 Neuroscientists who state that qualia exist EditGerald Edelman Edit Neuroscientist and Nobel laureate in Physiology Medicine Gerald Edelman in his book Bright Air Brilliant Fire argues 42 One alternative that definitely does not seem feasible is to ignore completely the reality of qualia formulating a theory of consciousness that aims by its descriptions alone to convey to a hypothetical qualia free observer what it is to feel warmth see green and so on In other words this is an attempt to propose a theory based on a kind of God s eye view of consciousness But no scientific theory of whatever kind can be presented without already assuming that observers have sensation as well as perception To assume otherwise is to indulge the errors of theories that attempt syntactical formulations mapped onto objectivist interpretations theories that ignore embodiment as a source of meaning see the Postscript There is no qualia free scientific observer Antonio Damasio Edit Neurologist Antonio Damasio in his book The Feeling Of What Happens states 43 Qualia are the simple sensory qualities to be found in the blueness of the sky or the tone of sound produced by a cello and the fundamental components of the images in the movie metaphor are thus made of qualia Damasio also argues that consciousness is subjective and is different from behavior 43 307 309 The resistance found in some scientific quarters to the use of subjective observations is a revisitation of an old argument between behaviorists who believed that only behaviors not mental experiences could be studied objectively and cognitivists who believed that studying only behavior did not do justice to human complexity The mind and its consciousness are first and foremost private phenomena much as they offer many public signs of their existence to the interested observer The conscious mind and its constituent properties are real entities not illusions and they must be investigated as the personal private subjective experiences that they are The idea that subjective experiences are not scientifically accessible is nonsense Subjective entities require as do objective ones that enough observers undertake rigorous observations according to the same experimental design and they require that those observations be checked for consistency across observers and that they yield some form of measurement Moreover knowledge gathered from subjective observations e g introspective insights can inspire objective experiments and no less importantly subjective experiences can be explained in terms of the available scientific knowledge The idea that the nature of subjective experiences can be grasped effectively by the study of their behavioral correlates is wrong Although both mind and behavior are biological phenomena mind is mind and behavior is behavior Mind and behavior can be correlated and the correlation will become closer as science progresses but in their respective specifications mind and behavior are different This is why in all likelihood I will never know your thoughts unless you tell me and you will never know mine until I tell you Damasio also addresses qualia in his book Self Comes to Mind 44 importance Rodolfo Llinas Edit Neurologist Rodolfo Llinas states in his book I of the Vortex that from a strictly neurological perspective qualia exist and are important to the organism s survival He argues that qualia were important for the evolution of the nervous system of organisms including simple organisms such as insects 45 201 221 There are today two similar beliefs concerning the nature of qualia The first is that qualia represent an epiphenomenon that is not necessary for the acquisition of consciousness Second and somewhat related is the belief that while being the basis for consciousness qualia appeared only in the highest life forms suggesting that qualia represent a recently evolved central function that is present in only the more advanced brains This view relegates the more lowly animals for example ants to a realm characterized by the absence of subjective experiences of any kind It implies that these animals are wired with sets of automatic reflexively organized circuits that provide for survival by maintaining a successful albeit purely reactive interaction with the ongoing external world Although primitive creatures such as ants and cockroaches may be wildly successful for all practical purposes they are biological automatons To me these views lack a proper evolutionary perspective which is perhaps why qualia are given so little overall emphasis in the study of brain function We clearly understand that the functional architecture of the brain is a product of the slow tumblings of evolution and that brain function implements what natural selection has found to be the most beneficial in terms of species survivability What is not often understood is how deeply related qualia truly are to the evolutionary functional structure of the brain One cannot operate without qualia they are properties of mind of monumental importance Llinas argues that qualia are ancient and necessary for an organism s survival and a product of neuronal oscillation He gives the evidence of anesthesia of the brain and subsequent stimulation of limbs to demonstrate that qualia can be turned off by changing only the variable of neuronal oscillation local brain electrical activity while all other connections remain intact He argues for an oscillatory electrical origin of qualia or important aspects of them 45 202 207 Vilayanur Ramachandran Edit Vilayanur S Ramachandran Vilayanur S Ramachandran and William Hirstein 46 proposed three laws of qualia with a fourth later added which are functional criteria that need to be fulfilled in order for certain neural events to be associated with qualia by philosophers of the mind Qualia are irrevocable and indubitable You don t say maybe it is red but I can visualize it as green if I want to An explicit neural representation of red is created that invariably and automatically reports this to higher brain centres Once the representation is created what can be done with it is open ended You have the luxury of choice e g if you have the percept of an apple you can use it to tempt Adam to keep the doctor away bake a pie or just to eat Even though the representation at the input level is immutable and automatic the output is potentially infinite This isn t true for say a spinal reflex arc where the output is also inevitable and automatic Indeed a paraplegic can even have an erection and ejaculate without an orgasm Short term memory The input invariably creates a representation that persists in short term memory long enough to allow time for choice of output Without this component again you get just a reflex arc Attention Qualia and attention are closely linked You need attention to fulfill criterion number two to choose A study of circuits involved in attention therefore will shed much light on the riddle of qualia 47 These authors approach qualia from an empirical perspective and not as a logical or philosophical problem They wonder how qualia evolved They consider a skeptical point of view in which since the objective scientific description of the world is complete without qualia it is nonsense to ask the question of why they evolved or what qualia are for But they rule out such an option Based on the parsimony principle of Occam s razor one could accept epiphenomenalism and deny qualia since they are not necessary for a description of the functioning of the brain However they argue that Occam s razor is not useful for scientific discovery 46 For example the discovery of relativity in physics was not the product of accepting Occam s razor but rather of rejecting it and asking the question of whether a deeper generalization not required by the currently available data was true and would allow for unexpected predictions Most scientific discoveries arise these authors argue from ontologically promiscuous conjectures that do not come from current data The authors then point out that skepticism might be justified in the philosophical field but that science is the wrong place for such skepticism Such skeptical questions might include asking if your red is not my green or if we can be logically certain that we are not dreaming Science these authors assert deals with what is probably true beyond reasonable doubt not with what can be known with complete and absolute certainty The authors say that most neuroscientists and even most psychologists dispute the very existence of the problem of qualia 46 Roger Orpwood Edit Roger Orpwood an engineer who studies neural mechanisms proposed a neurobiological model that gives rise to qualia and ultimately consciousness Advancements in cognitive and computational neuroscience necessitate study of the mind and qualia from a scientific perspective Orpwood does not deny the existence of qualia nor does he debate its physical or non physical existence He suggests that qualia are created through the neurobiological mechanism of re entrant feedback in cortical systems 48 49 Orpwood first addresses the issue of information One unsolved aspect of qualia is the concept of the fundamental information clarification needed involved in creating the experience He does not take a position on the metaphysics of the information underlying the experience of qualia nor does he state what information actually is but he does say that information is of two types the information structure and information message Information structures are defined by the physical vehicles and structural biological patterns that encode information That encoded information is the information message a source that describes what that information is The neural mechanism or network receives input information structures completes a designated instructional task firing of the neuron or network and outputs a modified information structure to downstream regions The information message is the purpose and meaning of the information structure and causally exists as a result of that particular information structure Modification of the information structure changes the meaning of the information message but the message itself cannot be directly altered Local cortical networks can receive feedback from their own output information structures This form of local feedback continuously cycles part of the network s output structures as its next input information structure Since the output structure must represent the information message derived from the input structure each consecutive cycle that is fed back represents the output structure the network just generated As the network of mechanisms cannot recognize the information message but only the input information structure the network is unaware that it is representing its own previous outputs The neural mechanisms are merely completing their instructional tasks and outputting any recognizable clarification needed information structures Orpwood proposes that these local networks come into an attractor state that consistently outputs exactly the same information structure as the input structure Instead of only representing the information message derived from the input structure the network will now represent its own output and thereby its own information message As the input structures are fed back the network identifies the previous information structure as being a previous representation of the information message As Orpwood writes Once an attractor state has been established the output of a network is a representation of its own identity to the network 49 4 Orpwood explains the neurobiological manifestation of qualia as representations of the network s own output structures by which it represents its own information message This is particular to networks of pyramidal neurons Although computational neuroscience still has much to investigate regarding pyramidal neurons their complex circuitry is unusual The complexity of pyramidal neuron networks in a species is directly related to the increase in that species s functional capabilities 50 When human pyramidal networks are compared with other primate species and with species with less intricate behavioral and social interactions the complexity of these neural networks drastically decline needs copy edit These networks are also more complex compared to in frontal brain regions These regions are often associated with weasel words conscious assessment and modification of one s immediate environment often referred to as executive functions One needs sensory input to gain information from the environment Perception of that input is necessary in order to navigate and modify interactions with the environment This suggests that frontal regions containing more complex pyramidal networks are associated with an increased perceptive capacity how As perception is necessary for conscious thought to occur citation needed and since qualia derive from clarification needed consciousness of some perception qualia may be specific to the functional capacity of clarification needed pyramidal networks non sequitur For this reason Orpwood believes that the mechanisms of re entrant feedback may not only create qualia but also be the foundation to consciousness Other issues EditIndeterminacy Edit A criticism similar to Nietzsche s criticism of Kant s thing in itself applies also to qualia Qualia are unobservable in others and unquantifiable in us We cannot possibly be sure when discussing individual qualia that we are even discussing the same phenomena Thus any discussion of them is of indeterminate value as descriptions of qualia are necessarily of indeterminate accuracy citation needed Qualia like things in themselves have no publicly demonstrable properties This along with the impossibility of being sure that we are communicating about the same qualia makes them of indeterminate value and definition in any philosophy in which proof relies upon precise definition citation needed On the other hand qualia could be considered akin to Kantian phenomena since they are held to be seemings of appearances Revonsuo clarification needed however considers that within neurophysiological inquiry a definition vague at the level of the fields clarification needed may become possible just as we can define a television picture at the level of liquid crystal pixels non sequitur Causal efficacy Edit Whether qualia or consciousness can play any causal role in the physical world remains an open question Epiphenomenalism acknowledges the existence of qualia while denying them any causal power The position has been criticized by a number of philosophers a if only because our own consciousness seem to be causally active 54 In order to avoid epiphenomenalism one who believes that qualia are nonphysical would need to embrace something like interactionist dualism or perhaps emergentism the claim that there are as yet unknown causal relations between the mental and physical This in turn would imply that qualia can be detected by an external agency clarification needed through their causal powers Epistemological issues Edit Examples of qualia might include the pain of a headache the taste of wine or the redness of an evening sky But such examples prejudge a central debate on qualia citation needed Suppose someone wants to know the nature of the liquid crystal pixels on a television screen those tiny elements that make up the picture It would not suffice as an answer to say that they are the redness of an evening sky as it appears on the screen this would ignore their real character Relying on a list like the one above assumes that we must tie sensations to both the notion of given objects in the world the head wine an evening sky and to the properties with which we characterize the experiences themselves redness for example Nor is it satisfactory to print a little red square as at the top of this article for since each person has a slightly different registration of the light rays 55 it confusingly suggests that we all have the same response how Imagine in a television shop seeing a red square on twenty screens at once each slightly different something of vital importance would be overlooked if a single example were to be taken as defining them all further explanation needed Yet it has been argued whether or not identification with the external object should still be the core of a correct approach to sensation for there are many who state the definition thus because they regard the link with external reality as crucial needs copy edit If sensations are defined as raw feels this threatens the reliability of knowledge because if one sees them as neurophysiological happenings in the brain it is difficult to understand how they could have any connection to entities whether in the body or the external world John McDowell for example declared that to countenance qualia as a bare presence prevents us ever gaining a certain ground for our knowledge 56 The issue is epistemological it would appear that access to knowledge is blocked if one allows the existence of qualia as fields in which only virtual constructs are before clarification needed the mind His reason is that it ambiguous puts the entities about which we require knowledge behind a veil of perception an occult field of appearance which leaves us ignorant of the reality presumed to be beyond it He is convinced that such uncertainty propels needs copy edit into the dangerous regions of relativism and solipsism These constitute an ethical argument against qualia being something going on in the brain clarification needed and these implications are probably largely responsible for the fact that in the 20th century it was regarded as not only freakish but also dangerously misguided to uphold the notion of sensations as going on inside the head citation needed The argument was usually strengthened with mockery at the very idea of redness being in the brain 57 How can there be red neurons in the brain Viewing sensations as raw feels implies that initially they have not yet to carry on the metaphor been cooked that is unified into things and persons which is something the mind does after the sensation has responded to the blank input that response driven by motivation that is initially by pain and pleasure and subsequently when memories have been implanted by desire and fear needs copy edit Such a raw feel state has been called non epistemic In support of this view the theorists who cite a range of empirical facts for example There are brain damaged persons known as agnosics literally not knowing who still have vivid visual sensations but are quite unable to identify any entity before them including parts of their own body There is also the similar predicament of persons formerly blind who are given sight for the first time And consider what it is a newborn baby experiences German physicist Hermann von Helmholtz proposed an experiment to demonstrate the non epistemic nature of qualia His instructions were to stand in front of a familiar landscape turn your back on it bend down and look at the landscape between your legs you will find it difficult in the upside down view to recognize what you found familiar before 58 These examples suggest the reality of a bare presence that is knowledgeless sensation that is no more than evidence Supporters of the non epistemic theory thus regard sensations as only data in the sense that they are given Latin datum given and fundamentally involuntary which is a good reason for not regarding them as basically mental why In the 20th century they were called sense data by the proponents of qualia but this led to the confusion that they carried with them reliable proofs of objective causal origins For instance one supporter of qualia was happy to speak of the redness and bulginess of a cricket ball as a typical sense datum 59 though not all of them were happy to define qualia by their relation to external entities 60 The modern argument centers on how we learn under the regime of motivation definition needed to interpret sensory evidence in terms of things persons and selves through a continuing process of feedback The definition of qualia inevitably brings with it philosophical and neurophysiological presuppositions The question of what qualia can be raises profound issues in the philosophy of mind since some materialists want to deny their existence altogether on the other hand if they are accepted they cannot be easily accounted for as they raise the difficult problem of consciousness There are committed dualists such as Richard L Amoroso or John Hagelin who believe that the mental and the material are two distinct aspects of physical reality like the distinction between the classical and quantum regimes 61 In contrast there are direct realists for whom qualia are unscientific as there appears to be no way of making them fit within the modern scientific picture and there are committed proselytizers for a final truth who reject them as forcing knowledge out of reach See also Edit Philosophy portalBinding problem Unanswered question in the study of consciousness Blockhead thought experiment philosophical thought experiment about a computer which has been programmed with all possible sentences in a natural language so as to be able to pass the Turing test despite lacking intelligencePages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Chinese room Thought experiment on artificial intelligence by John Searle Explanatory gap Inability to describe conscious experiences in solely physical or structural terms Feeling Conscious subjective experience of emotion Form constant Recurringly observed geometric pattern Further facts Philosophy idea Hard problem of consciousness Philosophical concept first stated by David Chalmers in 1995 Ideasthesia Phenomenon in which concepts evoke sensory experiences Knowledge argument Thought experiment Mind body problem Open question in philosophy of how abstract minds interact with physical bodies Open individualism Philosophical concept Philosophical zombie Thought experiment in philosophy Process philosophy Philosophical approach Self awareness Capacity for introspection and individuation as a subject Self reference Sentence idea or formula that refers to itself Subjectivity Philosophical concept related to consciousness agency personhood reality and truth Synesthesia Neurological condition involving the crossing of senses Vertiginous question philosophical question of all the subjects of experience out there why is this one the one corresponding to the human being referred to as me the one whose experiences are live Pages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallbackNotes Edit Epiphenomenalism has few friends It has been deemed thoughtless and incoherent Taylor 1927 51 unintelligible Benecke 1901 52 truly incredible McLaughlin 1994 53 References Edit Kriegel Uriah 2014 Current Controversies In Philosophy of Mind New York Taylor amp Francis p 201 ISBN 978 0415530866 a b Dennett Daniel 1985 11 21 Quining Qualia Oxford University Press Retrieved 2020 05 19 Dennett D 2002 Quining qualia In Chalmers D ed Philosophy of mind Classical and contemporary readings Oxford University Press pp 226 246 Dennett D 2015 Why and how does consciousness seem the way it seems In Metzinger T Windt J eds Open mind Mind Group pp 387 398 Damasio A 1999 The feeling of what happens Harcourt Brace Edelman G Gally J Baars B 2011 Biology of consciousness Frontiers In Psychology 2 4 1 6 Edelman G 1992 Bright air brilliant fire BasicBooks Edelman G 2003 Naturalizing consciousness A theoretical framework Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 100 9 5520 5524 Koch C 2019 The feeling of life itself The MIT Press Llinas R 2003 I of the Vortex MIT Press pp 202 207 Oizumi M Albantakis L Tononi G 2014 From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness Integrated information theory 3 0 PLOS Computational Biology 10 e1003588 Overgaard M Mogensen J Kirkeby Hinrup A eds 2021 Beyond neural correlates of consciousness Routledge Taylor amp Francis Ramachandran V Hirstein W 1997 Three laws of qualia What neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness qualia and the self Journal of consciousness studies 4 5 6 429 458 Tononi G Boly M Massimini M Koch C 2016 Integrated information theory From consciousness to its physical substrate Nature Reviews Neuroscience 17 450 461 Eliasmith Chris 2004 05 11 qualia Philosophy Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind Canada University of Waterloo Retrieved 2010 12 03 Peirce C S Writings Chronological Edition Vol 1 pp 477 478 Qualia The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2018 a b c Lewis C I 1929 Mind and the World Order Outline of a theory of knowledge New York Charles Scribner s Sons p 121 a b Jackson Frank 1982 Epiphenomenal Qualia PDF The Philosophical Quarterly 32 127 127 136 doi 10 2307 2960077 JSTOR 2960077 Retrieved August 7 2019 Kripke Saul Identity and Necessity 1971 Kripke Saul A 1972 Naming and Necessity Semantics of Natural Language Dordrecht Springer Netherlands pp 253 355 ISBN 978 90 277 0310 1 retrieved 2023 04 26 Levy Neil 1 January 2014 The value of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 21 1 2 127 138 PMC 4001209 PMID 24791144 Shepherd J 2018 Consciousness and Moral Status Routledge Taylor amp Francis group Jackson Frank 1982 Feigl H 1958 Broad C D 1925 2021 Qualia The Knowledge Argument 1 History of the underlying ideas Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Qualia knowledge Stanford U a b Nagel Thomas October 1974 What is it like to be a bat The Philosophical Review 83 4 435 450 doi 10 2307 2183914 JSTOR 2183914 a b c d e f g Tye Michael 2000 Consciousness Color and Content Cambridge MA MIT Press Locke John 1975 1689 Essay Concerning Human Understanding title not cited Oxford Oxford University Press II xxxii 15 full citation needed a b Inverted qualia Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Retrieved 2010 12 03 via Plato stanford edu a b Hardin C L 1987 Qualia and materialism Closing the explanatory gap Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 2 281 298 doi 10 2307 2107629 JSTOR 2107629 Stratton George M 1896 Some preliminary experiments on vision PDF Psychological Review Slater A M ed 1999 Perceptual Development Visual auditory and speech perception in infancy East Sussex Psychology Press ISBN 978 0863778513 via Google Books a b Dennett D C 20 October 1992 Consciousness Explained 1st ed Back Bay Books ISBN 978 0316180665 Joseph Levine Conceivability Identity and the Explanatory Gap Cognet mit edu 2000 09 26 Archived from the original on 2010 08 31 Retrieved 2010 12 03 Dennett D C 1988 Quining qualia In Marcel A J Bisiach E eds Consciousness in Contemporary Science Clarendon Press Oxford University Press pp 42 77 Ungerleider L G 3 November 1995 Functional brain imaging studies of cortical mechanisms for memory Science 270 5237 769 775 Bibcode 1995Sci 270 769U doi 10 1126 science 270 5237 769 PMID 7481764 S2CID 37665998 a b Dennett D C April 2001 Are we explaining consciousness yet Cognition 79 1 2 221 237 doi 10 1016 s0010 0277 00 00130 x PMID 11164029 S2CID 2235514 Churchland Paul 2004 Knowing qualia A reply to Jackson with postscript 1997 In Ludlow Peter Nagasawa Yujin Stoljar Daniel eds There s Something about Mary Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 163 178 a b Drescher G 2006 Good and Real Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 81 82 ISBN 978 0262042338 via Google Books Lewis D K 2004 What experience teaches In Ludlow Peter Nagasawa Yujin Stoljar Daniel eds There s Something about Mary Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 77 103 Edge interview with Marvin Minsky Edge org Edge Foundation Inc 1998 02 26 Retrieved 2010 12 03 Tye M 1991 The Imagery Debate Cambridge MA MIT Press Tye M 1995 Ten Problems of Consciousness A representational theory of the phenomenal mind Cambridge MA MIT Press Scruton Roger 2017 On Human Nature Kind Amy Qualia Internet Encyclopedia of Philoshopy Retrieved 6 November 2022 Chalmers D 1995 Absent qualia fading qualia dancing qualia In Metzinger Thomas ed Conscious Experience Imprint Academic free copy available from qualia on consc net a b Lowe E J 1996 Subjects of Experience Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 101 Lowe E J 2008 Illusions and hallucinations as evidence for sense data In Wright Edmond ed The Case for Qualia Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 59 72 ISBN 978 0262731881 via Google Books Maund J B September 1975 The representative theory of perception Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 1 41 55 doi 10 1080 00455091 1975 10716096 S2CID 146937154 Maund J B 1995 Colours Their nature and representation Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521472739 via Google Books Maund J B 2003 Perception Chesham Acumen Pub Ltd Perkins Moreland 1983 Sensing the World Indianapolis IN Hackett Pub Co ISBN 978 0915145751 via Archive org Ryle G 1949 The Concept of Mind London Hutchinson p 215 Ayer A J 1957 The Problem of Knowledge Harmondsworth Penguin Books p 107 Robinson William 2004 Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness Cambridge Cambridge University Press a b Wright Edmond ed 2008 The Case for Qualia publisher s abstract Cambridge MA MIT Press Wright Edmond 2005 11 16 Narrative Perception Language and Faith Basingstoke Palgrave Macmillan Retrieved 2010 12 03 a b Schrodinger Erwin 2001 1958 What is Life The physical aspects of the living cell reprint ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521427081 Edelman G 1992 Bright air brilliant fire On the matter of mind Basic Books p 115 a b Damasio A 1999 The feeling of what happens Heineman Damasio A 2010 Self comes to mind Constructing the conscious brain Knopf Doubleday Publishing a b Llinas R 2002 I of the Vortex From neurons to self The MIT Press a b c Ramachandran V S Hirstein W 1 May 1997 Three laws of qualia What neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 5 6 429 457 also available from Three laws of qualia PDF imprint co uk Ramachandran V S Hirstein W 1 December 2001 Synaesthesia a window into perception thought and language Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 12 3 34 Orpwood Roger D December 2007 Neurobiological mechanisms underlying qualia Journal of Integrative Neuroscience 06 4 523 540 doi 10 1142 s0219635207001696 PMID 18181267 Orpwood Roger D June 2010 Perceptual qualia and local network behavior in the cerebral cortex Journal of Integrative Neuroscience 09 2 123 152 doi 10 1142 s021963521000241x PMID 20589951 a b Orpwood Roger D 2013 Qualia could arise from information processing in local cortical networks Frontiers in Psychology 4 121 doi 10 3389 fpsyg 2013 00121 PMC 3596736 PMID 23504586 Elston G N 1 November 2003 Cortex cognition and the cell New insights into the pyramidal neuron and prefrontal function Cerebral Cortex 13 11 1124 1138 doi 10 1093 cercor bhg093 PMID 14576205 Taylor A 1927 Plato The man and his work New York MacVeagh p 198 Benecke E C 1900 1901 On the aspect theory of the relation of mind to body Aristotelian Society Proceedings n s 1 18 44 doi 10 1093 aristotelian 1 1 18 McLaughlin B 1994 Guttenplan S ed Epiphenomenalism a Companion to the Philosophy of Mind Oxford Blackwell pp 277 288 Georgiev Danko D 2017 Quantum Information and Consciousness A gentle introduction Boca Raton FL CRC Press p 362 doi 10 1201 9780203732519 ISBN 978 1138104488 OCLC 1003273264 Zbl 1390 81001 Georgiev Danko D 2020 Inner privacy of conscious experiences and quantum information BioSystems 187 104051 arXiv 2001 00909 doi 10 1016 j biosystems 2019 104051 PMID 31629783 S2CID 204813557 Hardin C L 1988 Color for Philosophers Indianapolis IN Hackett Pub Co ISBN 0872200396 via Google Books McDowell John 1994 Mind and World Cambridge MA Harvard University Press p 42 Roberson Gwendolyn E Wallace Mark T Schirillo James A October 2001 The sensorimotor contingency of multisensory localization correlates with the conscious percept of spatial unity Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 5 1001 1002 doi 10 1017 S0140525X0154011X Warren Richard M Warren Roslyn P eds 1968 Helmholtz on Perception Its physiology and development New York John Wiley amp Sons p 178 Price Hubert H 1932 Perception London Methuen p 32 Sellars Roy Wood 1922 Evolutionary Naturalism Chicago amp London Open Court Pub Co Amoroso Richard L 2010 Complementarity of Mind amp Body Realizing the dream of Descartes Einstein amp Eccles New York Nova Science Publishers Other references Edit various authors 2007 03 19 Chalmers David ed Online collection of papers on qualia Archived from the original on 2007 03 19 via Archive org a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint uses authors parameter link Lormand Eric Qualia Now showing at a theatre near you response to D Dennett University of Michigan Dennett Daniel Quining qualia Cognitive Studies Tufts University Ramachandran V S Hirstein W Three laws of qualia PDF imprint co uk biological perspective Gregory Richard Brainy mind qualia and the sensation of time Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind Alter Torin The Knowledge Argument Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind article University of Rome Archived from the original on 2012 12 03 Retrieved 2007 01 22 Robinson William Qualia realism Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind article University of Rome Archived from the original on 2012 12 03 Retrieved 2007 01 22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Byrne Alex 2020 Inverted qualia Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article Stanford U Tye Michael 2021 Qualia Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article Stanford U Nida Rumelin Martine 2021 Qualia The knowledge argument Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article Stanford U Further reading EditMroczko Wasowicz A Nikolic D 2014 Semantic mechanisms may be responsible for developing synesthesia PDF Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8 509 doi 10 3389 fnhum 2014 00509 PMC 4137691 PMID 25191239 External links Edit Look up qualia in Wiktionary the free dictionary Wikibooks has a book on the topic of Consciousness Studies Qualia Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy article University of Tennessee ISSN 2161 0002 Qualia Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2021 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Qualia amp oldid 1152023930, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.