fbpx
Wikipedia

Consciousness

Consciousness, at its simplest, is sentience and awareness of internal and external existence.[1] However, its nature has led to millennia of analyses, explanations and debates by philosophers, theologians, linguists, and scientists. Opinions differ about what exactly needs to be studied or even considered consciousness. In some explanations, it is synonymous with the mind, and at other times, an aspect of mind. In the past, it was one's "inner life", the world of introspection, of private thought, imagination and volition.[2] Today, it often includes any kind of cognition, experience, feeling or perception. It may be awareness, awareness of awareness, or self-awareness either continuously changing or not.[3][4] The disparate range of research, notions and speculations raises a curiosity about whether the right questions are being asked.[5]

Representation of consciousness from the seventeenth century by Robert Fludd, an English Paracelsian physician

Examples of the range of descriptions, definitions or explanations are: simple wakefulness, one's sense of selfhood or soul explored by "looking within"; being a metaphorical "stream" of contents, or being a mental state, mental event or mental process of the brain.

Inter-disciplinary perspectives

Western philosophers since the time of Descartes and Locke have struggled to comprehend the nature of consciousness and how it fits into a larger picture of the world. These questions remain central to both continental and analytic philosophy, in phenomenology and the philosophy of mind, respectively.

Consciousness has also become a significant topic of interdisciplinary research in cognitive science, involving fields such as psychology, linguistics, anthropology,[6] neuropsychology and neuroscience. The primary focus is on understanding what it means biologically and psychologically for information to be present in consciousness—that is, on determining the neural and psychological correlates of consciousness.

In medicine, consciousness is assessed by observing a patient's arousal and responsiveness, and can be seen as a continuum of states ranging from full alertness and comprehension, through disorientation, delirium, loss of meaningful communication, and finally loss of movement in response to painful stimuli.[7] Issues of practical concern include how the presence of consciousness can be assessed in severely ill, comatose, or anesthetized people, and how to treat conditions in which consciousness is impaired or disrupted.[8] The degree of consciousness is measured by standardized behavior observation scales such as the Glasgow Coma Scale.

Etymology

 
John Locke, British Enlightenment philosopher from the 17th century

In the late 20th century, philosophers like Hamlyn, Rorty, and Wilkes have disagreed with Kahn, Hardie and Modrak as to whether Aristotle even had a concept of consciousness. Aristotle does not use any single word or terminology to name the phenomenon; it is used only much later, especially by John Locke. Caston contends that for Aristotle, perceptual awareness was somewhat the same as what modern philosophers call consciousness.[9]

The origin of the modern concept of consciousness is often attributed to Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding, published in 1690.[10] Locke defined consciousness as "the perception of what passes in a man's own mind".[11] His essay influenced the 18th-century view of consciousness, and his definition appeared in Samuel Johnson's celebrated Dictionary (1755).[12] "Consciousness" (French: conscience) is also defined in the 1753 volume of Diderot and d'Alembert's Encyclopédie, as "the opinion or internal feeling that we ourselves have from what we do".[13]

The earliest English language uses of "conscious" and "consciousness" date back, however, to the 1500s. The English word "conscious" originally derived from the Latin conscius (con- "together" and scio "to know"), but the Latin word did not have the same meaning as the English word—it meant "knowing with", in other words, "having joint or common knowledge with another".[14] There were, however, many occurrences in Latin writings of the phrase conscius sibi, which translates literally as "knowing with oneself", or in other words "sharing knowledge with oneself about something". This phrase had the figurative meaning of "knowing that one knows", as the modern English word "conscious" does. In its earliest uses in the 1500s, the English word "conscious" retained the meaning of the Latin conscius. For example, Thomas Hobbes in Leviathan wrote: "Where two, or more men, know of one and the same fact, they are said to be Conscious of it one to another."[15] The Latin phrase conscius sibi, whose meaning was more closely related to the current concept of consciousness, was rendered in English as "conscious to oneself" or "conscious unto oneself". For example, Archbishop Ussher wrote in 1613 of "being so conscious unto myself of my great weakness".[16] Locke's definition from 1690 illustrates that a gradual shift in meaning had taken place.

A related word was conscientia, which primarily means moral conscience. In the literal sense, "conscientia" means knowledge-with, that is, shared knowledge. The word first appears in Latin juridical texts by writers such as Cicero.[17] Here, conscientia is the knowledge that a witness has of the deed of someone else.[18] René Descartes (1596–1650) is generally taken to be the first philosopher to use conscientia in a way that does not fit this traditional meaning.[19] Descartes used conscientia the way modern speakers would use "conscience". In Search after Truth (Regulæ ad directionem ingenii ut et inquisitio veritatis per lumen naturale, Amsterdam 1701) he says "conscience or internal testimony" (conscientiâ, vel interno testimonio).[20][21]

The problem of definition

About forty meanings attributed to the term consciousness can be identified and categorized based on functions and experiences. The prospects for reaching any single, agreed-upon, theory-independent definition of consciousness appear remote.[22]

The dictionary definitions of the word consciousness extend through several centuries and reflect a range of seemingly related meanings, with some differences that have been controversial, such as the distinction between 'inward awareness' and 'perception' of the physical world, or the distinction between 'conscious' and 'unconscious', or the notion of a "mental entity" or "mental activity" that is not physical.

The common usage definitions of consciousness in Webster's Third New International Dictionary (1966 edition, Volume 1, page 482) are as follows:

    • awareness or perception of an inward psychological or spiritual fact; intuitively perceived knowledge of something in one's inner self
    • inward awareness of an external object, state, or fact
    • concerned awareness; INTEREST, CONCERN—often used with an attributive noun [e.g. class consciousness]
  1. the state or activity that is characterized by sensation, emotion, volition, or thought; mind in the broadest possible sense; something in nature that is distinguished from the physical
  2. the totality in psychology of sensations, perceptions, ideas, attitudes, and feelings of which an individual or a group is aware at any given time or within a particular time span—compare STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS
  3. waking life (as that to which one returns after sleep, trance, fever) wherein all one's mental powers have returned . . .
  4. the part of mental life or psychic content in psychoanalysis that is immediately available to the ego—compare PRECONSCIOUS, UNCONSCIOUS

The Cambridge Dictionary defines consciousness as "the state of understanding and realizing something."[23] The Oxford Living Dictionary defines consciousness as "The state of being aware of and responsive to one's surroundings.", "A person's awareness or perception of something." and "The fact of awareness by the mind of itself and the world."[24]

Philosophers have attempted to clarify technical distinctions by using a jargon of their own. The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy in 1998 defines consciousness as follows:

Consciousness—Philosophers have used the term 'consciousness' for four main topics: knowledge in general, intentionality, introspection (and the knowledge it specifically generates) and phenomenal experience... Something within one's mind is 'introspectively conscious' just in case one introspects it (or is poised to do so). Introspection is often thought to deliver one's primary knowledge of one's mental life. An experience or other mental entity is 'phenomenally conscious' just in case there is 'something it is like' for one to have it. The clearest examples are: perceptual experience, such as tastings and seeings; bodily-sensational experiences, such as those of pains, tickles and itches; imaginative experiences, such as those of one's own actions or perceptions; and streams of thought, as in the experience of thinking 'in words' or 'in images'. Introspection and phenomenality seem independent, or dissociable, although this is controversial.[25]

Many philosophers and scientists have been unhappy about the difficulty of producing a definition that does not involve circularity or fuzziness.[26] In The Macmillan Dictionary of Psychology (1989 edition), Stuart Sutherland expressed a skeptical attitude more than a definition:

Consciousness—The having of perceptions, thoughts, and feelings; awareness. The term is impossible to define except in terms that are unintelligible without a grasp of what consciousness means. Many fall into the trap of equating consciousness with self-consciousness—to be conscious it is only necessary to be aware of the external world. Consciousness is a fascinating but elusive phenomenon: it is impossible to specify what it is, what it does, or why it has evolved. Nothing worth reading has been written on it.[26]

A partisan definition such as Sutherland's can hugely affect researchers' assumptions and the direction of their work:

If awareness of the environment . . . is the criterion of consciousness, then even the protozoans are conscious. If awareness of awareness is required, then it is doubtful whether the great apes and human infants are conscious.[27]

Many philosophers have argued that consciousness is a unitary concept that is understood by the majority of people despite the difficulty philosophers have had defining it.[28] Others, though, have argued that the level of disagreement about the meaning of the word indicates that it either means different things to different people (for instance, the objective versus subjective aspects of consciousness), that it encompasses a variety of distinct meanings with no simple element in common,[29] or that we should eliminate this concept from our understanding of the mind, a position known as consciousness semanticism.[30]

Philosophy of mind

Most writers on the philosophy of consciousness have been concerned with defending a particular point of view, and have organized their material accordingly. For surveys, the most common approach is to follow a historical path by associating stances with the philosophers who are most strongly associated with them, for example, Descartes, Locke, Kant, etc. An alternative is to organize philosophical stances according to basic issues.

Coherence of the concept

Philosophers differ from non-philosophers in their intuitions about what consciousness is.[31] While most people have a strong intuition for the existence of what they refer to as consciousness,[28] skeptics argue that this intuition is false, either because the concept of consciousness is intrinsically incoherent, or because our intuitions about it are based in illusions. Gilbert Ryle, for example, argued that traditional understanding of consciousness depends on a Cartesian dualist outlook that improperly distinguishes between mind and body, or between mind and world. He proposed that we speak not of minds, bodies, and the world, but of individuals, or persons, acting in the world. Thus, by speaking of "consciousness" we end up misleading ourselves by thinking that there is any sort of thing as consciousness separated from behavioral and linguistic understandings.[32]

Types

Ned Block argued that discussions on consciousness often failed to properly distinguish phenomenal (P-consciousness) from access (A-consciousness), though these terms had been used before Block.[33] P-consciousness, according to Block, is raw experience: it is moving, colored forms, sounds, sensations, emotions and feelings with our bodies and responses at the center. These experiences, considered independently of any impact on behavior, are called qualia. A-consciousness, on the other hand, is the phenomenon whereby information in our minds is accessible for verbal report, reasoning, and the control of behavior. So, when we perceive, information about what we perceive is access conscious; when we introspect, information about our thoughts is access conscious; when we remember, information about the past is access conscious, and so on. Although some philosophers, such as Daniel Dennett, have disputed the validity of this distinction,[34] others have broadly accepted it. David Chalmers has argued that A-consciousness can in principle be understood in mechanistic terms, but that understanding P-consciousness is much more challenging: he calls this the hard problem of consciousness.[35]

Some philosophers believe that Block's two types of consciousness are not the end of the story. William Lycan, for example, argued in his book Consciousness and Experience that at least eight clearly distinct types of consciousness can be identified (organism consciousness; control consciousness; consciousness of; state/event consciousness; reportability; introspective consciousness; subjective consciousness; self-consciousness)—and that even this list omits several more obscure forms.[36]

There is also debate over whether or not A-consciousness and P-consciousness always coexist or if they can exist separately. Although P-consciousness without A-consciousness is more widely accepted, there have been some hypothetical examples of A without P. Block, for instance, suggests the case of a "zombie" that is computationally identical to a person but without any subjectivity. However, he remains somewhat skeptical concluding "I don't know whether there are any actual cases of A-consciousness without P-consciousness, but I hope I have illustrated their conceptual possibility."[37]

Distinguishing consciousness from its contents

Sam Harris observes: “At the level of your experience, you are not a body of cells, organelles, and atoms; you are consciousness and its ever-changing contents”.[38] Seen in this way, consciousness is a subjectively experienced, ever-present field in which things (the contents of consciousness) come and go.

Christopher Tricker argues that this field of consciousness is symbolised by the mythical bird that opens the Daoist classic the Zhuangzi. This bird’s name is Of a Flock (peng), yet its back is countless thousands of miles across and its wings are like clouds arcing across the heavens. “Like Of a Flock, whose wings arc across the heavens, the wings of your consciousness span to the horizon. At the same time, the wings of every other being’s consciousness span to the horizon. You are of a flock, one bird among kin.”[39]

Mind–body problem

 
Illustration of dualism by René Descartes. Inputs are passed by the sensory organs to the pineal gland and from there to the immaterial spirit.

Mental processes (such as consciousness) and physical processes (such as brain events) seem to be correlated, however the specific nature of the connection is unknown.

The first influential philosopher to discuss this question specifically was Descartes, and the answer he gave is known as Cartesian dualism. Descartes proposed that consciousness resides within an immaterial domain he called res cogitans (the realm of thought), in contrast to the domain of material things, which he called res extensa (the realm of extension).[40] He suggested that the interaction between these two domains occurs inside the brain, perhaps in a small midline structure called the pineal gland.[41]

Although it is widely accepted that Descartes explained the problem cogently, few later philosophers have been happy with his solution, and his ideas about the pineal gland have especially been ridiculed.[42] However, no alternative solution has gained general acceptance. Proposed solutions can be divided broadly into two categories: dualist solutions that maintain Descartes's rigid distinction between the realm of consciousness and the realm of matter but give different answers for how the two realms relate to each other; and monist solutions that maintain that there is really only one realm of being, of which consciousness and matter are both aspects. Each of these categories itself contains numerous variants. The two main types of dualism are substance dualism (which holds that the mind is formed of a distinct type of substance not governed by the laws of physics) and property dualism (which holds that the laws of physics are universally valid but cannot be used to explain the mind). The three main types of monism are physicalism (which holds that the mind consists of matter organized in a particular way), idealism (which holds that only thought or experience truly exists, and matter is merely an illusion), and neutral monism (which holds that both mind and matter are aspects of a distinct essence that is itself identical to neither of them). There are also, however, a large number of idiosyncratic theories that cannot cleanly be assigned to any of these schools of thought.[43]

Since the dawn of Newtonian science with its vision of simple mechanical principles governing the entire universe, some philosophers have been tempted by the idea that consciousness could be explained in purely physical terms. The first influential writer to propose such an idea explicitly was Julien Offray de La Mettrie, in his book Man a Machine (L'homme machine). His arguments, however, were very abstract.[44] The most influential modern physical theories of consciousness are based on psychology and neuroscience. Theories proposed by neuroscientists such as Gerald Edelman[45] and Antonio Damasio,[46] and by philosophers such as Daniel Dennett,[47] seek to explain consciousness in terms of neural events occurring within the brain. Many other neuroscientists, such as Christof Koch,[48] have explored the neural basis of consciousness without attempting to frame all-encompassing global theories. At the same time, computer scientists working in the field of artificial intelligence have pursued the goal of creating digital computer programs that can simulate or embody consciousness.[49]

A few theoretical physicists have argued that classical physics is intrinsically incapable of explaining the holistic aspects of consciousness, but that quantum theory may provide the missing ingredients. Several theorists have therefore proposed quantum mind (QM) theories of consciousness.[50] Notable theories falling into this category include the holonomic brain theory of Karl Pribram and David Bohm, and the Orch-OR theory formulated by Stuart Hameroff and Roger Penrose. Some of these QM theories offer descriptions of phenomenal consciousness, as well as QM interpretations of access consciousness. None of the quantum mechanical theories have been confirmed by experiment. Recent publications by G. Guerreshi, J. Cia, S. Popescu, and H. Briegel[51] could falsify proposals such as those of Hameroff, which rely on quantum entanglement in protein. At the present time many scientists and philosophers consider the arguments for an important role of quantum phenomena to be unconvincing.[52]

Apart from the general question of the "hard problem" of consciousness (which is, roughly speaking, the question of how mental experience can arise from a physical basis[53]), a more specialized question is how to square the subjective notion that we are in control of our decisions (at least in some small measure) with the customary view of causality that subsequent events are caused by prior events. The topic of free will is the philosophical and scientific examination of this conundrum.

Problem of other minds

Many philosophers consider experience to be the essence of consciousness, and believe that experience can only fully be known from the inside, subjectively. But if consciousness is subjective and not visible from the outside, why do the vast majority of people believe that other people are conscious, but rocks and trees are not?[54] This is called the problem of other minds.[55] It is particularly acute for people who believe in the possibility of philosophical zombies, that is, people who think it is possible in principle to have an entity that is physically indistinguishable from a human being and behaves like a human being in every way but nevertheless lacks consciousness.[56] Related issues have also been studied extensively by Greg Littmann of the University of Illinois,[57] and by Colin Allen (a professor at the University of Pittsburgh) regarding the literature and research studying artificial intelligence in androids.[58]

The most commonly given answer is that we attribute consciousness to other people because we see that they resemble us in appearance and behavior; we reason that if they look like us and act like us, they must be like us in other ways, including having experiences of the sort that we do.[59] There are, however, a variety of problems with that explanation. For one thing, it seems to violate the principle of parsimony, by postulating an invisible entity that is not necessary to explain what we observe.[59] Some philosophers, such as Daniel Dennett in a research paper titled "The Unimagined Preposterousness of Zombies", argue that people who give this explanation do not really understand what they are saying.[60] More broadly, philosophers who do not accept the possibility of zombies generally believe that consciousness is reflected in behavior (including verbal behavior), and that we attribute consciousness on the basis of behavior. A more straightforward way of saying this is that we attribute experiences to people because of what they can do, including the fact that they can tell us about their experiences.[61]

Scientific study

For many decades, consciousness as a research topic was avoided by the majority of mainstream scientists, because of a general feeling that a phenomenon defined in subjective terms could not properly be studied using objective experimental methods.[62] In 1975 George Mandler published an influential psychological study which distinguished between slow, serial, and limited conscious processes and fast, parallel and extensive unconscious ones.[63] The Science and Religion Forum[64] 1984 annual conference, 'From Artificial Intelligence to Human Consciousness' identified the nature of consciousness as a matter for investigation; Donald Michie was a keynote speaker. Starting in the 1980s, an expanding community of neuroscientists and psychologists have associated themselves with a field called Consciousness Studies, giving rise to a stream of experimental work published in books,[65] journals such as Consciousness and Cognition, Frontiers in Consciousness Research, Psyche, and the Journal of Consciousness Studies, along with regular conferences organized by groups such as the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness[66] and the Society for Consciousness Studies.

Modern medical and psychological investigations into consciousness are based on psychological experiments (including, for example, the investigation of priming effects using subliminal stimuli), and on case studies of alterations in consciousness produced by trauma, illness, or drugs. Broadly viewed, scientific approaches are based on two core concepts. The first identifies the content of consciousness with the experiences that are reported by human subjects; the second makes use of the concept of consciousness that has been developed by neurologists and other medical professionals who deal with patients whose behavior is impaired. In either case, the ultimate goals are to develop techniques for assessing consciousness objectively in humans as well as other animals, and to understand the neural and psychological mechanisms that underlie it.[48]

Measurement

 
The Necker cube, an ambiguous image

Experimental research on consciousness presents special difficulties, due to the lack of a universally accepted operational definition. In the majority of experiments that are specifically about consciousness, the subjects are human, and the criterion used is verbal report: in other words, subjects are asked to describe their experiences, and their descriptions are treated as observations of the contents of consciousness.[67] For example, subjects who stare continuously at a Necker cube usually report that they experience it "flipping" between two 3D configurations, even though the stimulus itself remains the same.[68] The objective is to understand the relationship between the conscious awareness of stimuli (as indicated by verbal report) and the effects the stimuli have on brain activity and behavior. In several paradigms, such as the technique of response priming, the behavior of subjects is clearly influenced by stimuli for which they report no awareness, and suitable experimental manipulations can lead to increasing priming effects despite decreasing prime identification (double dissociation).[69]

Verbal report is widely considered to be the most reliable indicator of consciousness, but it raises a number of issues.[70] For one thing, if verbal reports are treated as observations, akin to observations in other branches of science, then the possibility arises that they may contain errors—but it is difficult to make sense of the idea that subjects could be wrong about their own experiences, and even more difficult to see how such an error could be detected.[71] Daniel Dennett has argued for an approach he calls heterophenomenology, which means treating verbal reports as stories that may or may not be true, but his ideas about how to do this have not been widely adopted.[72] Another issue with verbal report as a criterion is that it restricts the field of study to humans who have language: this approach cannot be used to study consciousness in other species, pre-linguistic children, or people with types of brain damage that impair language. As a third issue, philosophers who dispute the validity of the Turing test may feel that it is possible, at least in principle, for verbal report to be dissociated from consciousness entirely: a philosophical zombie may give detailed verbal reports of awareness in the absence of any genuine awareness.[73]

Although verbal report is in practice the "gold standard" for ascribing consciousness, it is not the only possible criterion.[70] In medicine, consciousness is assessed as a combination of verbal behavior, arousal, brain activity and purposeful movement. The last three of these can be used as indicators of consciousness when verbal behavior is absent.[74][75] The scientific literature regarding the neural bases of arousal and purposeful movement is very extensive. Their reliability as indicators of consciousness is disputed, however, due to numerous studies showing that alert human subjects can be induced to behave purposefully in a variety of ways in spite of reporting a complete lack of awareness.[69] Studies of the neuroscience of free will have also shown that the experiences that people report when they behave purposefully sometimes do not correspond to their actual behaviors or to the patterns of electrical activity recorded from their brains.[76]

Another approach applies specifically to the study of self-awareness, that is, the ability to distinguish oneself from others. In the 1970s Gordon Gallup developed an operational test for self-awareness, known as the mirror test. The test examines whether animals are able to differentiate between seeing themselves in a mirror versus seeing other animals. The classic example involves placing a spot of coloring on the skin or fur near the individual's forehead and seeing if they attempt to remove it or at least touch the spot, thus indicating that they recognize that the individual they are seeing in the mirror is themselves.[77] Humans (older than 18 months) and other great apes, bottlenose dolphins, orcas, pigeons, European magpies and elephants have all been observed to pass this test.[78]

Neural correlates

 
Schema of the neural processes underlying consciousness, from Christof Koch

A major part of the scientific literature on consciousness consists of studies that examine the relationship between the experiences reported by subjects and the activity that simultaneously takes place in their brains—that is, studies of the neural correlates of consciousness. The hope is to find that activity in a particular part of the brain, or a particular pattern of global brain activity, which will be strongly predictive of conscious awareness. Several brain imaging techniques, such as EEG and fMRI, have been used for physical measures of brain activity in these studies.[79]

Another idea that has drawn attention for several decades is that consciousness is associated with high-frequency (gamma band) oscillations in brain activity. This idea arose from proposals in the 1980s, by Christof von der Malsburg and Wolf Singer, that gamma oscillations could solve the so-called binding problem, by linking information represented in different parts of the brain into a unified experience.[80] Rodolfo Llinás, for example, proposed that consciousness results from recurrent thalamo-cortical resonance where the specific thalamocortical systems (content) and the non-specific (centromedial thalamus) thalamocortical systems (context) interact in the gamma band frequency via synchronous oscillations.[81]

A number of studies have shown that activity in primary sensory areas of the brain is not sufficient to produce consciousness: it is possible for subjects to report a lack of awareness even when areas such as the primary visual cortex (V1) show clear electrical responses to a stimulus.[82] Higher brain areas are seen as more promising, especially the prefrontal cortex, which is involved in a range of higher cognitive functions collectively known as executive functions.[83] There is substantial evidence that a "top-down" flow of neural activity (i.e., activity propagating from the frontal cortex to sensory areas) is more predictive of conscious awareness than a "bottom-up" flow of activity.[84] The prefrontal cortex is not the only candidate area, however: studies by Nikos Logothetis and his colleagues have shown, for example, that visually responsive neurons in parts of the temporal lobe reflect the visual perception in the situation when conflicting visual images are presented to different eyes (i.e., bistable percepts during binocular rivalry).[85] Furthermore, top-down feedback from higher to lower visual brain areas may be weaker or absent in the peripheral visual field, as suggested by some experimental data and theoretical arguments;[86] nevertheless humans can perceive visual inputs in the peripheral visual field arising from bottom-up V1 neural activities.[86][87] Meanwhile, bottom-up V1 activities for the central visual fields can be vetoed, and thus made invisible to perception, by the top-down feedback, when these bottom-up signals are inconsistent with brain's internal model of the visual world.[86][87]

Modulation of neural responses may correlate with phenomenal experiences. In contrast to the raw electrical responses that do not correlate with consciousness, the modulation of these responses by other stimuli correlates surprisingly well with an important aspect of consciousness: namely with the phenomenal experience of stimulus intensity (brightness, contrast). In the research group of Danko Nikolić it has been shown that some of the changes in the subjectively perceived brightness correlated with the modulation of firing rates while others correlated with the modulation of neural synchrony.[88] An fMRI investigation suggested that these findings were strictly limited to the primary visual areas.[89] This indicates that, in the primary visual areas, changes in firing rates and synchrony can be considered as neural correlates of qualia—at least for some type of qualia.

In 2013, the perturbational complexity index (PCI) was proposed, a measure of the algorithmic complexity of the electrophysiological response of the cortex to transcranial magnetic stimulation. This measure was shown to be higher in individuals that are awake, in REM sleep or in a locked-in state than in those who are in deep sleep or in a vegetative state,[90] making it potentially useful as a quantitative assessment of consciousness states.

Assuming that not only humans but even some non-mammalian species are conscious, a number of evolutionary approaches to the problem of neural correlates of consciousness open up. For example, assuming that birds are conscious—a common assumption among neuroscientists and ethologists due to the extensive cognitive repertoire of birds—there are comparative neuroanatomical ways to validate some of the principal, currently competing, mammalian consciousness–brain theories. The rationale for such a comparative study is that the avian brain deviates structurally from the mammalian brain. So how similar are they? What homologues can be identified? The general conclusion from the study by Butler, et al.,[91] is that some of the major theories for the mammalian brain [92][93][94] also appear to be valid for the avian brain. The structures assumed to be critical for consciousness in mammalian brains have homologous counterparts in avian brains. Thus the main portions of the theories of Crick and Koch,[92] Edelman and Tononi,[93] and Cotterill [94] seem to be compatible with the assumption that birds are conscious. Edelman also differentiates between what he calls primary consciousness (which is a trait shared by humans and non-human animals) and higher-order consciousness as it appears in humans alone along with human language capacity.[93] Certain aspects of the three theories, however, seem less easy to apply to the hypothesis of avian consciousness. For instance, the suggestion by Crick and Koch that layer 5 neurons of the mammalian brain have a special role, seems difficult to apply to the avian brain, since the avian homologues have a different morphology. Likewise, the theory of Eccles[95][96] seems incompatible, since a structural homologue/analogue to the dendron has not been found in avian brains. The assumption of an avian consciousness also brings the reptilian brain into focus. The reason is the structural continuity between avian and reptilian brains, meaning that the phylogenetic origin of consciousness may be earlier than suggested by many leading neuroscientists.

Joaquin Fuster of UCLA has advocated the position of the importance of the prefrontal cortex in humans, along with the areas of Wernicke and Broca, as being of particular importance to the development of human language capacities neuro-anatomically necessary for the emergence of higher-order consciousness in humans.[97]

A study in 2016 looked at lesions in specific areas of the brainstem that were associated with coma and vegetative states. A small region of the rostral dorsolateral pontine tegmentum in the brainstem was suggested to drive consciousness through functional connectivity with two cortical regions, the left ventral anterior insular cortex, and the pregenual anterior cingulate cortex. These three regions may work together as a triad to maintain consciousness.[98]

Models

A wide range of empirical theories of consciousness have been proposed.[99][100][101] Adrian Doerig and colleagues list 13 notable theories,[101] while Anil Seth and Tim Bayne list 22 notable theories.[100]

Integrated information theory (IIT) postulates that consciousness resides in the information being processed and arises once the information reaches a certain level of complexity.[citation needed]

Orchestrated objective reduction (Orch OR) postulates that consciousness originates at the quantum level inside neurons. The mechanism is held to be a quantum process called objective reduction that is orchestrated by cellular structures called microtubules. However the details of the mechanism would go beyond current quantum theory.[102]

In 2011, Graziano and Kastner[103] proposed the "attention schema" theory of awareness. In that theory, specific cortical areas, notably in the superior temporal sulcus and the temporo-parietal junction, are used to build the construct of awareness and attribute it to other people. The same cortical machinery is also used to attribute awareness to oneself. Damage to these cortical regions can lead to deficits in consciousness such as hemispatial neglect. In the attention schema theory, the value of explaining the feature of awareness and attributing it to a person is to gain a useful predictive model of that person's attentional processing. Attention is a style of information processing in which a brain focuses its resources on a limited set of interrelated signals. Awareness, in this theory, is a useful, simplified schema that represents attentional states. To be aware of X is explained by constructing a model of one's attentional focus on X.

The entropic brain is a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs. The theory suggests that the brain in primary states such as rapid eye movement (REM) sleep, early psychosis and under the influence of psychedelic drugs, is in a disordered state; normal waking consciousness constrains some of this freedom and makes possible metacognitive functions such as internal self-administered reality testing and self-awareness.[104][105][106][107] Criticism has included questioning whether the theory has been adequately tested.[108]

In 2017, work by David Rudrauf and colleagues, including Karl Friston, applied the active inference paradigm to consciousness, a model of how sensory data is integrated with priors in a process of projective transformation. The authors argue that, while their model identifies a key relationship between computation and phenomenology, it does not completely solve the hard problem of consciousness or completely close the explanatory gap.[109]

Biological function and evolution

Opinions are divided as to where in biological evolution consciousness emerged and about whether or not consciousness has any survival value. Some argue that consciousness is a byproduct of evolution. It has been argued that consciousness emerged (i) exclusively with the first humans, (ii) exclusively with the first mammals, (iii) independently in mammals and birds, or (iv) with the first reptiles.[110] Other authors date the origins of consciousness to the first animals with nervous systems or early vertebrates in the Cambrian over 500 million years ago.[111] Donald Griffin suggests in his book Animal Minds a gradual evolution of consciousness.[112] Each of these scenarios raises the question of the possible survival value of consciousness.

Thomas Henry Huxley defends in an essay titled On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and its History an epiphenomenalist theory of consciousness according to which consciousness is a causally inert effect of neural activity—"as the steam-whistle which accompanies the work of a locomotive engine is without influence upon its machinery".[113] To this William James objects in his essay Are We Automata? by stating an evolutionary argument for mind-brain interaction implying that if the preservation and development of consciousness in the biological evolution is a result of natural selection, it is plausible that consciousness has not only been influenced by neural processes, but has had a survival value itself; and it could only have had this if it had been efficacious.[114][115] Karl Popper develops in the book The Self and Its Brain a similar evolutionary argument.[116]

Regarding the primary function of conscious processing, a recurring idea in recent theories is that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities and information-processing that would otherwise be independent.[117] This has been called the integration consensus. Another example has been proposed by Gerald Edelman called dynamic core hypothesis which puts emphasis on reentrant connections that reciprocally link areas of the brain in a massively parallel manner.[118] Edelman also stresses the importance of the evolutionary emergence of higher-order consciousness in humans from the historically older trait of primary consciousness which humans share with non-human animals (see Neural correlates section above). These theories of integrative function present solutions to two classic problems associated with consciousness: differentiation and unity. They show how our conscious experience can discriminate between a virtually unlimited number of different possible scenes and details (differentiation) because it integrates those details from our sensory systems, while the integrative nature of consciousness in this view easily explains how our experience can seem unified as one whole despite all of these individual parts. However, it remains unspecified which kinds of information are integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated without consciousness. Nor is it explained what specific causal role conscious integration plays, nor why the same functionality cannot be achieved without consciousness. Obviously not all kinds of information are capable of being disseminated consciously (e.g., neural activity related to vegetative functions, reflexes, unconscious motor programs, low-level perceptual analyses, etc.) and many kinds of information can be disseminated and combined with other kinds without consciousness, as in intersensory interactions such as the ventriloquism effect.[119] Hence it remains unclear why any of it is conscious. For a review of the differences between conscious and unconscious integrations, see the article of Ezequiel Morsella.[119]

As noted earlier, even among writers who consider consciousness to be well-defined, there is widespread dispute about which animals other than humans can be said to possess it.[120] Edelman has described this distinction as that of humans possessing higher-order consciousness while sharing the trait of primary consciousness with non-human animals (see previous paragraph). Thus, any examination of the evolution of consciousness is faced with great difficulties. Nevertheless, some writers have argued that consciousness can be viewed from the standpoint of evolutionary biology as an adaptation in the sense of a trait that increases fitness.[121] In his article "Evolution of consciousness", John Eccles argued that special anatomical and physical properties of the mammalian cerebral cortex gave rise to consciousness ("[a] psychon ... linked to [a] dendron through quantum physics").[122] Bernard Baars proposed that once in place, this "recursive" circuitry may have provided a basis for the subsequent development of many of the functions that consciousness facilitates in higher organisms.[123] Peter Carruthers has put forth one such potential adaptive advantage gained by conscious creatures by suggesting that consciousness allows an individual to make distinctions between appearance and reality.[124] This ability would enable a creature to recognize the likelihood that their perceptions are deceiving them (e.g. that water in the distance may be a mirage) and behave accordingly, and it could also facilitate the manipulation of others by recognizing how things appear to them for both cooperative and devious ends.

Other philosophers, however, have suggested that consciousness would not be necessary for any functional advantage in evolutionary processes.[125][126] No one has given a causal explanation, they argue, of why it would not be possible for a functionally equivalent non-conscious organism (i.e., a philosophical zombie) to achieve the very same survival advantages as a conscious organism. If evolutionary processes are blind to the difference between function F being performed by conscious organism O and non-conscious organism O*, it is unclear what adaptive advantage consciousness could provide.[127] As a result, an exaptive explanation of consciousness has gained favor with some theorists that posit consciousness did not evolve as an adaptation but was an exaptation arising as a consequence of other developments such as increases in brain size or cortical rearrangement.[111] Consciousness in this sense has been compared to the blind spot in the retina where it is not an adaption of the retina, but instead just a by-product of the way the retinal axons were wired.[128] Several scholars including Pinker, Chomsky, Edelman, and Luria have indicated the importance of the emergence of human language as an important regulative mechanism of learning and memory in the context of the development of higher-order consciousness (see Neural correlates section above).

Altered states

 
A Buddhist monk meditating

There are some brain states in which consciousness seems to be absent, including dreamless sleep or coma. There are also a variety of circumstances that can change the relationship between the mind and the world in less drastic ways, producing what are known as altered states of consciousness. Some altered states occur naturally; others can be produced by drugs or brain damage.[129] Altered states can be accompanied by changes in thinking, disturbances in the sense of time, feelings of loss of control, changes in emotional expression, alternations in body image and changes in meaning or significance.[130]

The two most widely accepted altered states are sleep and dreaming. Although dream sleep and non-dream sleep appear very similar to an outside observer, each is associated with a distinct pattern of brain activity, metabolic activity, and eye movement; each is also associated with a distinct pattern of experience and cognition. During ordinary non-dream sleep, people who are awakened report only vague and sketchy thoughts, and their experiences do not cohere into a continuous narrative. During dream sleep, in contrast, people who are awakened report rich and detailed experiences in which events form a continuous progression, which may however be interrupted by bizarre or fantastic intrusions.[131][failed verification] Thought processes during the dream state frequently show a high level of irrationality. Both dream and non-dream states are associated with severe disruption of memory: it usually disappears in seconds during the non-dream state, and in minutes after awakening from a dream unless actively refreshed.[132]

Research conducted on the effects of partial epileptic seizures on consciousness found that patients who have partial epileptic seizures experience altered states of consciousness.[133][134] In partial epileptic seizures, consciousness is impaired or lost while some aspects of consciousness, often automated behaviors, remain intact. Studies found that when measuring the qualitative features during partial epileptic seizures, patients exhibited an increase in arousal and became absorbed in the experience of the seizure, followed by difficulty in focusing and shifting attention.

A variety of psychoactive drugs, including alcohol, have notable effects on consciousness.[135] These range from a simple dulling of awareness produced by sedatives, to increases in the intensity of sensory qualities produced by stimulants, cannabis, empathogens–entactogens such as MDMA ("Ecstasy"), or most notably by the class of drugs known as psychedelics.[129] LSD, mescaline, psilocybin, dimethyltryptamine, and others in this group can produce major distortions of perception, including hallucinations; some users even describe their drug-induced experiences as mystical or spiritual in quality. The brain mechanisms underlying these effects are not as well understood as those induced by use of alcohol,[135] but there is substantial evidence that alterations in the brain system that uses the chemical neurotransmitter serotonin play an essential role.[136]

There has been some research into physiological changes in yogis and people who practise various techniques of meditation. Some research with brain waves during meditation has reported differences between those corresponding to ordinary relaxation and those corresponding to meditation. It has been disputed, however, whether there is enough evidence to count these as physiologically distinct states of consciousness.[137]

The most extensive study of the characteristics of altered states of consciousness was made by psychologist Charles Tart in the 1960s and 1970s. Tart analyzed a state of consciousness as made up of a number of component processes, including exteroception (sensing the external world); interoception (sensing the body); input-processing (seeing meaning); emotions; memory; time sense; sense of identity; evaluation and cognitive processing; motor output; and interaction with the environment.[138][self-published source] Each of these, in his view, could be altered in multiple ways by drugs or other manipulations. The components that Tart identified have not, however, been validated by empirical studies. Research in this area has not yet reached firm conclusions, but a recent questionnaire-based study identified eleven significant factors contributing to drug-induced states of consciousness: experience of unity; spiritual experience; blissful state; insightfulness; disembodiment; impaired control and cognition; anxiety; complex imagery; elementary imagery; audio-visual synesthesia; and changed meaning of percepts.[139]

Medical aspects

The medical approach to consciousness is scientifically oriented. It derives from a need to treat people whose brain function has been impaired as a result of disease, brain damage, toxins, or drugs. In medicine, conceptual distinctions are considered useful to the degree that they can help to guide treatments. The medical approach focuses mostly on the amount of consciousness a person has: in medicine, consciousness is assessed as a "level" ranging from coma and brain death at the low end, to full alertness and purposeful responsiveness at the high end.[140]

Consciousness is of concern to patients and physicians, especially neurologists and anesthesiologists. Patients may have disorders of consciousness or may need to be anesthetized for a surgical procedure. Physicians may perform consciousness-related interventions such as instructing the patient to sleep, administering general anesthesia, or inducing medical coma.[140] Also, bioethicists may be concerned with the ethical implications of consciousness in medical cases of patients such as the Karen Ann Quinlan case,[141] while neuroscientists may study patients with impaired consciousness in hopes of gaining information about how the brain works.[142]

Assessment

In medicine, consciousness is examined using a set of procedures known as neuropsychological assessment.[74] There are two commonly used methods for assessing the level of consciousness of a patient: a simple procedure that requires minimal training, and a more complex procedure that requires substantial expertise. The simple procedure begins by asking whether the patient is able to move and react to physical stimuli. If so, the next question is whether the patient can respond in a meaningful way to questions and commands. If so, the patient is asked for name, current location, and current day and time. A patient who can answer all of these questions is said to be "alert and oriented times four" (sometimes denoted "A&Ox4" on a medical chart), and is usually considered fully conscious.[143]

The more complex procedure is known as a neurological examination, and is usually carried out by a neurologist in a hospital setting. A formal neurological examination runs through a precisely delineated series of tests, beginning with tests for basic sensorimotor reflexes, and culminating with tests for sophisticated use of language. The outcome may be summarized using the Glasgow Coma Scale, which yields a number in the range 3–15, with a score of 3 to 8 indicating coma, and 15 indicating full consciousness. The Glasgow Coma Scale has three subscales, measuring the best motor response (ranging from "no motor response" to "obeys commands"), the best eye response (ranging from "no eye opening" to "eyes opening spontaneously") and the best verbal response (ranging from "no verbal response" to "fully oriented"). There is also a simpler pediatric version of the scale, for children too young to be able to use language.[140]

In 2013, an experimental procedure was developed to measure degrees of consciousness, the procedure involving stimulating the brain with a magnetic pulse, measuring resulting waves of electrical activity, and developing a consciousness score based on the complexity of the brain activity.[144]

Disorders

Medical conditions that inhibit consciousness are considered disorders of consciousness.[145] This category generally includes minimally conscious state and persistent vegetative state, but sometimes also includes the less severe locked-in syndrome and more severe chronic coma.[145][146] Differential diagnosis of these disorders is an active area of biomedical research.[147][148][149] Finally, brain death results in possible irreversible disruption of consciousness.[145] While other conditions may cause a moderate deterioration (e.g., dementia and delirium) or transient interruption (e.g., grand mal and petit mal seizures) of consciousness, they are not included in this category.

Disorder Description
Locked-in syndrome The patient has awareness, sleep-wake cycles, and meaningful behavior (viz., eye-movement), but is isolated due to quadriplegia and pseudobulbar palsy.
Minimally conscious state The patient has intermittent periods of awareness and wakefulness and displays some meaningful behavior.
Persistent vegetative state The patient has sleep-wake cycles, but lacks awareness and only displays reflexive and non-purposeful behavior.
Chronic coma The patient lacks awareness and sleep-wake cycles and only displays reflexive behavior.
Brain death The patient lacks awareness, sleep-wake cycles, and brain-mediated reflexive behavior.

Medical experts increasingly view anosognosia as a disorder of consciousness.[150] Anosognosia a Greek-derived term meaning "unawareness of disease". This is a condition in which patients are disabled in some way, most commonly as a result of a stroke, but either misunderstand the nature of the problem or deny that there is anything wrong with them.[151] The most frequently occurring form is seen in people who have experienced a stroke damaging the parietal lobe in the right hemisphere of the brain, giving rise to a syndrome known as hemispatial neglect, characterized by an inability to direct action or attention toward objects located to the left with respect to their bodies. Patients with hemispatial neglect are often paralyzed on the left side of the body, but sometimes deny being unable to move. When questioned about the obvious problem, the patient may avoid giving a direct answer, or may give an explanation that doesn't make sense. Patients with hemispatial neglect may also fail to recognize paralyzed parts of their bodies: one frequently mentioned case is of a man who repeatedly tried to throw his own paralyzed right leg out of the bed he was lying in, and when asked what he was doing, complained that somebody had put a dead leg into the bed with him. An even more striking type of anosognosia is Anton–Babinski syndrome, a rarely occurring condition in which patients become blind but claim to be able to see normally, and persist in this claim in spite of all evidence to the contrary.[152]

Outside human adults

In children

Of the eight types of consciousness in the Lycan classification, some are detectable in utero and others develop years after birth. Psychologist and educator William Foulkes studied children's dreams and concluded that prior to the shift in cognitive maturation that humans experience during ages five to seven,[153] children lack the Lockean consciousness that Lycan had labeled "introspective consciousness" and that Foulkes labels "self-reflection."[154] In a 2020 paper, Katherine Nelson and Robyn Fivush use "autobiographical consciousness" to label essentially the same faculty, and agree with Foulkes on the timing of this faculty's acquisition. Nelson and Fivush contend that "language is the tool by which humans create a new, uniquely human form of consciousness, namely, autobiographical consciousness."[155] Julian Jaynes had staked out these positions decades earlier.[156][157] Citing the developmental steps that lead the infant to autobiographical consciousness, Nelson and Fivush point to the acquisition of "theory of mind," calling theory of mind "necessary for autobiographical consciousness" and defining it as "understanding differences between one's own mind and others' minds in terms of beliefs, desires, emotions and thoughts." They write, "The hallmark of theory of mind, the understanding of false belief, occurs ... at five to six years of age."[158]

In animals

The topic of animal consciousness is beset by a number of difficulties. It poses the problem of other minds in an especially severe form, because non-human animals, lacking the ability to express human language, cannot tell humans about their experiences.[159] Also, it is difficult to reason objectively about the question, because a denial that an animal is conscious is often taken to imply that it does not feel, its life has no value, and that harming it is not morally wrong. Descartes, for example, has sometimes been blamed for mistreatment of animals due to the fact that he believed only humans have a non-physical mind.[160] Most people have a strong intuition that some animals, such as cats and dogs, are conscious, while others, such as insects, are not; but the sources of this intuition are not obvious, and are often based on personal interactions with pets and other animals they have observed.[159]

 
Thomas Nagel argues that while a human might be able to imagine what it is like to be a bat by taking "the bat's point of view", it would still be impossible "to know what it is like for a bat to be a bat." (Townsend's big-eared bat pictured).

Philosophers who consider subjective experience the essence of consciousness also generally believe, as a correlate, that the existence and nature of animal consciousness can never rigorously be known. Thomas Nagel spelled out this point of view in an influential essay titled What Is it Like to Be a Bat?. He said that an organism is conscious "if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism—something it is like for the organism"; and he argued that no matter how much we know about an animal's brain and behavior, we can never really put ourselves into the mind of the animal and experience its world in the way it does itself.[161] Other thinkers, such as Douglas Hofstadter, dismiss this argument as incoherent.[162] Several psychologists and ethologists have argued for the existence of animal consciousness by describing a range of behaviors that appear to show animals holding beliefs about things they cannot directly perceive—Donald Griffin's 2001 book Animal Minds reviews a substantial portion of the evidence.[112]

On July 7, 2012, eminent scientists from different branches of neuroscience gathered at the University of Cambridge to celebrate the Francis Crick Memorial Conference, which deals with consciousness in humans and pre-linguistic consciousness in nonhuman animals. After the conference, they signed in the presence of Stephen Hawking, the 'Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness', which summarizes the most important findings of the survey:

"We decided to reach a consensus and make a statement directed to the public that is not scientific. It's obvious to everyone in this room that animals have consciousness, but it is not obvious to the rest of the world. It is not obvious to the rest of the Western world or the Far East. It is not obvious to the society."[163]

"Convergent evidence indicates that non-human animals ..., including all mammals and birds, and other creatures, ... have the necessary neural substrates of consciousness and the capacity to exhibit intentional behaviors."[164]

In artifacts

The idea of an artifact made conscious is an ancient theme of mythology, appearing for example in the Greek myth of Pygmalion, who carved a statue that was magically brought to life, and in medieval Jewish stories of the Golem, a magically animated homunculus built of clay.[165] However, the possibility of actually constructing a conscious machine was probably first discussed by Ada Lovelace, in a set of notes written in 1842 about the Analytical Engine invented by Charles Babbage, a precursor (never built) to modern electronic computers. Lovelace was essentially dismissive of the idea that a machine such as the Analytical Engine could think in a humanlike way. She wrote:

It is desirable to guard against the possibility of exaggerated ideas that might arise as to the powers of the Analytical Engine. ... The Analytical Engine has no pretensions whatever to originate anything. It can do whatever we know how to order it to perform. It can follow analysis; but it has no power of anticipating any analytical relations or truths. Its province is to assist us in making available what we are already acquainted with.[166]

One of the most influential contributions to this question was an essay written in 1950 by pioneering computer scientist Alan Turing, titled Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Turing disavowed any interest in terminology, saying that even "Can machines think?" is too loaded with spurious connotations to be meaningful; but he proposed to replace all such questions with a specific operational test, which has become known as the Turing test.[167] To pass the test, a computer must be able to imitate a human well enough to fool interrogators. In his essay Turing discussed a variety of possible objections, and presented a counterargument to each of them. The Turing test is commonly cited in discussions of artificial intelligence as a proposed criterion for machine consciousness; it has provoked a great deal of philosophical debate. For example, Daniel Dennett and Douglas Hofstadter argue that anything capable of passing the Turing test is necessarily conscious,[168] while David Chalmers argues that a philosophical zombie could pass the test, yet fail to be conscious.[169] A third group of scholars have argued that with technological growth once machines begin to display any substantial signs of human-like behavior then the dichotomy (of human consciousness compared to human-like consciousness) becomes passé and issues of machine autonomy begin to prevail even as observed in its nascent form within contemporary industry and technology.[57][58] Jürgen Schmidhuber argues that consciousness is the result of compression.[170] As an agent sees representation of itself recurring in the environment, the compression of this representation can be called consciousness.

 
John Searle in December 2005

In a lively exchange over what has come to be referred to as "the Chinese room argument", John Searle sought to refute the claim of proponents of what he calls "strong artificial intelligence (AI)" that a computer program can be conscious, though he does agree with advocates of "weak AI" that computer programs can be formatted to "simulate" conscious states. His own view is that consciousness has subjective, first-person causal powers by being essentially intentional due to the way human brains function biologically; conscious persons can perform computations, but consciousness is not inherently computational the way computer programs are. To make a Turing machine that speaks Chinese, Searle imagines a room with one monolingual English speaker (Searle himself, in fact), a book that designates a combination of Chinese symbols to be output paired with Chinese symbol input, and boxes filled with Chinese symbols. In this case, the English speaker is acting as a computer and the rulebook as a program. Searle argues that with such a machine, he would be able to process the inputs to outputs perfectly without having any understanding of Chinese, nor having any idea what the questions and answers could possibly mean. If the experiment were done in English, since Searle knows English, he would be able to take questions and give answers without any algorithms for English questions, and he would be effectively aware of what was being said and the purposes it might serve. Searle would pass the Turing test of answering the questions in both languages, but he is only conscious of what he is doing when he speaks English. Another way of putting the argument is to say that computer programs can pass the Turing test for processing the syntax of a language, but that the syntax cannot lead to semantic meaning in the way strong AI advocates hoped.[171][172]

In the literature concerning artificial intelligence, Searle's essay has been second only to Turing's in the volume of debate it has generated.[173] Searle himself was vague about what extra ingredients it would take to make a machine conscious: all he proposed was that what was needed was "causal powers" of the sort that the brain has and that computers lack. But other thinkers sympathetic to his basic argument have suggested that the necessary (though perhaps still not sufficient) extra conditions may include the ability to pass not just the verbal version of the Turing test, but the robotic version,[174] which requires grounding the robot's words in the robot's sensorimotor capacity to categorize and interact with the things in the world that its words are about, Turing-indistinguishably from a real person. Turing-scale robotics is an empirical branch of research on embodied cognition and situated cognition.[175]

In 2014, Victor Argonov has suggested a non-Turing test for machine consciousness based on machine's ability to produce philosophical judgments.[176] He argues that a deterministic machine must be regarded as conscious if it is able to produce judgments on all problematic properties of consciousness (such as qualia or binding) having no innate (preloaded) philosophical knowledge on these issues, no philosophical discussions while learning, and no informational models of other creatures in its memory (such models may implicitly or explicitly contain knowledge about these creatures' consciousness). However, this test can be used only to detect, but not refute the existence of consciousness. A positive result proves that machine is conscious but a negative result proves nothing. For example, absence of philosophical judgments may be caused by lack of the machine's intellect, not by absence of consciousness.

Stream of consciousness

William James is usually credited with popularizing the idea that human consciousness flows like a stream, in his Principles of Psychology of 1890.

According to James, the "stream of thought" is governed by five characteristics:[177]

  1. Every thought tends to be part of a personal consciousness.
  2. Within each personal consciousness thought is always changing.
  3. Within each personal consciousness thought is sensibly continuous.
  4. It always appears to deal with objects independent of itself.
  5. It is interested in some parts of these objects to the exclusion of others.

A similar concept appears in Buddhist philosophy, expressed by the Sanskrit term Citta-saṃtāna, which is usually translated as mindstream or "mental continuum". Buddhist teachings describe that consciousness manifests moment to moment as sense impressions and mental phenomena that are continuously changing.[178] The teachings list six triggers that can result in the generation of different mental events.[178] These triggers are input from the five senses (seeing, hearing, smelling, tasting or touch sensations), or a thought (relating to the past, present or the future) that happen to arise in the mind. The mental events generated as a result of these triggers are: feelings, perceptions and intentions/behaviour. The moment-by-moment manifestation of the mind-stream is said to happen in every person all the time. It even happens in a scientist who analyses various phenomena in the world, or analyses the material body including the organ brain.[178] The manifestation of the mindstream is also described as being influenced by physical laws, biological laws, psychological laws, volitional laws, and universal laws.[178] The purpose of the Buddhist practice of mindfulness is to understand the inherent nature of the consciousness and its characteristics.[179]

Narrative form

In the West, the primary impact of the idea has been on literature rather than science: "stream of consciousness as a narrative mode" means writing in a way that attempts to portray the moment-to-moment thoughts and experiences of a character. This technique perhaps had its beginnings in the monologues of Shakespeare's plays and reached its fullest development in the novels of James Joyce and Virginia Woolf, although it has also been used by many other noted writers.[180]

Here, for example, is a passage from Joyce's Ulysses about the thoughts of Molly Bloom:

Yes because he never did a thing like that before as ask to get his breakfast in bed with a couple of eggs since the City Arms hotel when he used to be pretending to be laid up with a sick voice doing his highness to make himself interesting for that old faggot Mrs Riordan that he thought he had a great leg of and she never left us a farthing all for masses for herself and her soul greatest miser ever was actually afraid to lay out 4d for her methylated spirit telling me all her ailments she had too much old chat in her about politics and earthquakes and the end of the world let us have a bit of fun first God help the world if all the women were her sort down on bathingsuits and lownecks of course nobody wanted her to wear them I suppose she was pious because no man would look at her twice I hope Ill never be like her a wonder she didnt want us to cover our faces but she was a welleducated woman certainly and her gabby talk about Mr Riordan here and Mr Riordan there I suppose he was glad to get shut of her.[181]

Spiritual approaches

To most philosophers, the word "consciousness" connotes the relationship between the mind and the world. To writers on spiritual or religious topics, it frequently connotes the relationship between the mind and God, or the relationship between the mind and deeper truths that are thought to be more fundamental than the physical world. The mystical psychiatrist Richard Maurice Bucke, author of the 1901 book Cosmic Consciousness: A Study in the Evolution of the Human Mind, distinguished between three types of consciousness: 'Simple Consciousness', awareness of the body, possessed by many animals; 'Self Consciousness', awareness of being aware, possessed only by humans; and 'Cosmic Consciousness', awareness of the life and order of the universe, possessed only by humans who are enlightened.[182] Many more examples could be given, such as the various levels of spiritual consciousness presented by Prem Saran Satsangi and Stuart Hameroff.[183]

Another thorough account of the spiritual approach is Ken Wilber's 1977 book The Spectrum of Consciousness, a comparison of western and eastern ways of thinking about the mind. Wilber described consciousness as a spectrum with ordinary awareness at one end, and more profound types of awareness at higher levels.[184]

See also

References

  1. ^ "consciousness". Merriam-Webster. Retrieved June 4, 2012.
  2. ^ Jaynes, Julian (2000) [1976]. (PDF). Houghton Mifflin. ISBN 0-618-05707-2. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2019-08-07. Retrieved 2019-10-16.
  3. ^ Rochat, Philippe (2003). "Five levels of self-awareness as they unfold early in life" (PDF). Consciousness and Cognition. 12 (4): 717–731. doi:10.1016/s1053-8100(03)00081-3. PMID 14656513. S2CID 10241157. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  4. ^ P.A. Guertin (2019). "A novel concept introducing the idea of continuously changing levels of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research. 10 (6): 406–412.
  5. ^ Hacker, P.M.S. (2012). "The Sad and Sorry History of Consciousness: being, among other things, a challenge to the "consciousness-studies community"" (PDF). Royal Institute of Philosophy. supplementary volume 70. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  6. ^ Cohen A.P., Rapport N. (1995). Questions of Consciousness. London: Routledge. ISBN 9781134804696.
  7. ^ Güven Güzeldere (1997). Ned Block; Owen Flanagan; Güven Güzeldere (eds.). The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical debates. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 1–67.
  8. ^ J.J. Fins; N.D. Schiff; K.M. Foley (2007). "Late recovery from the minimally conscious state: ethical and policy implications". Neurology. 68 (4): 304–307. doi:10.1212/01.wnl.0000252376.43779.96. PMID 17242341. S2CID 32561349.
  9. ^ Caston, Victor (2002). "Aristotle on Consciousness". Mind (PDF). Oxford University Press. p. 751. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  10. ^ Locke, John. . Australia: University of Adelaide. Archived from the original on May 8, 2018. Retrieved August 20, 2010.
  11. ^ "Science & Technology: consciousness". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved August 20, 2010.
  12. ^ Samuel Johnson (1756). A Dictionary of the English Language. Knapton.
  13. ^ Jaucourt, Louis, chevalier de. "Consciousness." The Encyclopedia of Diderot & d'Alembert Collaborative Translation Project. Translated by Scott St. Louis. Ann Arbor: Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan Library, 2014. Originally published as "Conscience," Encyclopédie ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, 3:902 (Paris, 1753).
  14. ^ C. S. Lewis (1990). "Ch. 8: Conscience and conscious". Studies in words. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-39831-2.
  15. ^ Thomas Hobbes (1904). Leviathan: or, The Matter, Forme & Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiasticall and Civill. University Press. p. 39. ISBN 9783932392382.
  16. ^ James Ussher, Charles Richard Elrington (1613). The whole works, Volume 2. Hodges and Smith. p. 417.
  17. ^ Barbara Cassin (2014). Dictionary of Untranslatables. A Philosophical Lexicon. Princeton University Press. p. 176. ISBN 978-0-691-13870-1.
  18. ^ G. Molenaar (1969). "Seneca's Use of the Term Conscientia". Mnemosyne. 22 (2): 170–180. doi:10.1163/156852569x00670.
  19. ^ Boris Hennig (2007). "Cartesian Conscientia". British Journal for the History of Philosophy. 15 (3): 455–484. doi:10.1080/09608780701444915. S2CID 218603781.
  20. ^ Charles Adam, Paul Tannery (eds.), Oeuvres de Descartes X, 524 (1908).
  21. ^ Sara Heinämaa; Vili Lähteenmäki; Pauliina Remes, eds. (2007). Consciousness: from perception to reflection in the history of philosophy. Springer. pp. 205–206. ISBN 978-1-4020-6081-6.
  22. ^ Vimal, RLP; Sansthana, DA (2010). "On the Quest of Defining Consciousness" (PDF). Mind and Matter. 8 (1): 93–121.
  23. ^ "CONSCIOUSNESS – meaning in the Cambridge English Dictionary". dictionary.cambridge.org.
  24. ^ . Oxford Dictionaries – English. Archived from the original on September 25, 2016.
  25. ^ Edward Craig (1998). "Consciousness". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-18707-7.
  26. ^ a b Stuart Sutherland (1989). "Consciousness". Macmillan Dictionary of Psychology. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-333-38829-7.
  27. ^ Thomas, Garth J. (1967). "Consciousness". Encyclopaedia Britannica. Vol. 6. p. 366.
  28. ^ a b Michael V. Antony (2001). "Is consciousness ambiguous?". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 8: 19–44.
  29. ^ Max Velmans (2009). "How to define consciousness—and how not to define consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 16: 139–156.
  30. ^ Anthis, Jacy (2022). "Consciousness Semanticism: A Precise Eliminativist Theory of Consciousness". Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures 2021. Studies in Computational Intelligence. 1032: 20–41. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-96993-6_3. ISBN 978-3-030-96992-9. Retrieved 7 August 2022.
  31. ^ Justin Sytsma; Edouard Machery (2010). "Two conceptions of subjective experience" (PDF). Philosophical Studies. 151 (2): 299–327. doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9439-x. S2CID 2444730. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  32. ^ Gilbert Ryle (1949). The Concept of Mind. University of Chicago Press. pp. 156–163. ISBN 978-0-226-73296-1.
  33. ^ Ned Block (1998). "On a confusion about a function of consciousness". In N. Block; O. Flanagan; G. Guzeldere (eds.). The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. MIT Press. pp. 375–415. ISBN 978-0-262-52210-6.
  34. ^ Daniel Dennett (2004). Consciousness Explained. Penguin. p. 375. ISBN 978-0-7139-9037-9.
  35. ^ David Chalmers (1995). . Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2: 200–219. Archived from the original on 2005-03-08.
  36. ^ William Lycan (1996). Consciousness and Experience. MIT Press. pp. 1–4. ISBN 978-0-262-12197-2.
  37. ^ Block N (1995). (PDF). Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 18 (2): 272–284. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00038486. S2CID 41023484. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-02-10.
  38. ^ Harris, S. (12 October 2011). The mystery of consciousness. Sam Harris. https://www.samharris.org/blog/the-mystery-of-consciousness
  39. ^ Tricker, C. (2022). The cicada and the bird. The usefulness of a useless philosophy. Chuang Tzu's ancient wisdom translated for modern life. Page 52. (Google Books)
  40. ^ Dy, Manuel B. Jr. (2001). Philosophy of Man: selected readings. Goodwill Trading Co. p. 97. ISBN 978-971-12-0245-3.
  41. ^ "Descartes and the Pineal Gland". Stanford University. November 5, 2008. Retrieved 2010-08-22.
  42. ^ Gert-Jan Lokhorst. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Descartes and the pineal gland". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition).
  43. ^ William Jaworski (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction. John Wiley and Sons. pp. 5–11. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
  44. ^ Julien Offray de La Mettrie (1996). Ann Thomson (ed.). Machine man and other writings. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-47849-6.
  45. ^ Gerald Edelman (1993). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-00764-6.
  46. ^ Antonio Damasio (1999). The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt Press. ISBN 978-0-15-601075-7.
  47. ^ Daniel Dennett (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little & Company. ISBN 978-0-316-18066-5.
  48. ^ a b Christof Koch (2004). The Quest for Consciousness. Englewood, CO: Roberts & Company. ISBN 978-0-9747077-0-9.
  49. ^ Ron Sun and Stan Franklin, Computational models of consciousness: A taxonomy and some examples. In: P.D. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, and E. Thompson (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness, pp. 151–174. Cambridge University Press, New York. 2007
  50. ^ Quantum Approaches to Consciousness. Stanford University. December 25, 2011.
  51. ^ Cai, J.; Popescu, S.; Briegel, H. (2010). "Persistent dynamic entanglement from classical motion: How bio-molecular machines can generate non-trivial quantum states". Physical Review E. 82 (2): 021921. arXiv:0809.4906. Bibcode:2010PhRvE..82b1921C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevE.82.021921. PMID 20866851. S2CID 23336691.
  52. ^ John Searle (1997). The Mystery of Consciousness. The New York Review of Books. pp. 53–88. ISBN 978-0-940322-06-6.
  53. ^ Rocco J. Gennaro (2011). "§4.4 The hard problem of consciousness". The Consciousness Paradox: Consciousness, Concepts, and Higher-Order Thoughts. MIT Press. p. 75. ISBN 978-0-262-01660-5.
  54. ^ Knobe J (2008). "Can a Robot, an Insect or God Be Aware?". Scientific American Mind. 19 (6): 68–71. doi:10.1038/scientificamericanmind1208-68.
  55. ^ Alec Hyslop (1995). Other Minds. Springer. pp. 5–14. ISBN 978-0-7923-3245-9.
  56. ^ Robert Kirk. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Zombies". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition).
  57. ^ a b The Culture and Philosophy of Ridley Scott, Greg Littmann, pp. 133–144, Lexington Books (2013).
  58. ^ a b Moral Machines, Wendell Wallach and Colin Allen, 288 pages, Oxford University Press, USA (June 3, 2010), ISBN 0-19-973797-5.
  59. ^ a b Alec Hyslop (1995). "The analogical inference to other minds". Other Minds. Springer. pp. 41–70. ISBN 978-0-7923-3245-9.
  60. ^ Daniel Dennett (1995). "The unimagined preposterousness of zombies". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2: 322–325.
  61. ^ Stevan Harnad (1995). "Why and how we are not zombies". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 1: 164–167.
  62. ^ Horst Hendriks-Jansen (1996). Catching ourselves in the act: situated activity, interactive emergence, evolution, and human thought. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. p. 114. ISBN 978-0-262-08246-4.
  63. ^ Mandler, G. "Consciousness: Respectable, useful, and probably necessary". In R. Solso (Ed.) Information processing and cognition: NJ: LEA.
  64. ^ "Science and Religion Forum". 2021. from the original on 2016-11-03.
  65. ^ Mandler, G. Consciousness recovered: Psychological functions and origins of thought. Philadelphia: John Benjamins. 2002
  66. ^ Stuart Hameroff; Alfred Kaszniak; David Chalmers (1999). "Preface". Toward a Science of Consciousness III: The Third Tucson Discussions and Debates. MIT Press. pp. xix–xx. ISBN 978-0-262-58181-3.
  67. ^ Bernard Baars (1993). A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press. pp. 15–18. ISBN 978-0-521-42743-2.
  68. ^ Paul Rooks; Jane Wilson (2000). Perception: Theory, Development, and Organization. Psychology Press. pp. 25–26. ISBN 978-0-415-19094-7.
  69. ^ a b Thomas Schmidt; Dirk Vorberg (2006). "Criteria for unconscious cognition: Three types of dissociation". Perception and Psychophysics. 68 (3): 489–504. doi:10.3758/bf03193692. PMID 16900839.
  70. ^ a b Arnaud Destrebecqz; Philippe Peigneux (2006). "Methods for studying unconscious learning". In Steven Laureys (ed.). The Boundaries of Consciousness: Neurobiology and Neuropathology. Elsevier. pp. 69–80. ISBN 978-0-444-52876-6.
  71. ^ Daniel Dennett (1992). "Quining qualia". In A. Marcel; E. Bisiach (eds.). Consciousness in Modern Science. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-852237-9. Retrieved 2011-10-31.
  72. ^ Daniel Dennett (2003). "Who's on first? Heterophenomenology explained". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 10: 19–30.
  73. ^ David Chalmers (1996). "Ch. 3: Can consciousness be reductively explained?". The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511789-9.
  74. ^ a b J.T. Giacino; C.M. Smart (2007). "Recent advances in behavioral assessment of individuals with disorders of consciousness". Current Opinion in Neurology. 20 (6): 614–619. doi:10.1097/WCO.0b013e3282f189ef. PMID 17992078. S2CID 7097163.
  75. ^ Christof Koch (October 2017). "How to Make a Consciousness Meter". Scientific American. 317 (5): 28–33. Bibcode:2017SciAm.317e..28K. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican1117-28. PMID 29565878.
  76. ^ Patrick Haggard (2008). "Human volition: towards a neuroscience of will". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 9 (12): 934–946. doi:10.1038/nrn2497. PMID 19020512. S2CID 1495720.
  77. ^ Gordon Gallup (1970). "Chimpanzees: Self recognition". Science. 167 (3914): 86–87. Bibcode:1970Sci...167...86G. doi:10.1126/science.167.3914.86. PMID 4982211. S2CID 145295899.
  78. ^ David Edelman; Anil Seth (2009). "Animal consciousness: a synthetic approach". Trends in Neurosciences. 32 (9): 476–484. doi:10.1016/j.tins.2009.05.008. PMID 19716185. S2CID 13323524.
  79. ^ Christof Koch (2004). The Quest for Consciousness. Englewood, CO: Roberts & Company. pp. 16–19. ISBN 978-0-9747077-0-9.
  80. ^ Wolf Singer (2007). "Binding by synchrony". Scholarpedia. 2 (12): 1657. Bibcode:2007SchpJ...2.1657S. doi:10.4249/scholarpedia.1657.
  81. ^ Rodolfo Llinás (2002). I of the vortex: from neurons to self. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-62163-2.
  82. ^ Koch, The Quest for Consciousness, pp. 105–116
  83. ^ Baldauf, D.; Desimone, R. (2014-04-25). "Neural Mechanisms of Object-Based Attention". Science. 344 (6182): 424–427. Bibcode:2014Sci...344..424B. doi:10.1126/science.1247003. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 24763592. S2CID 34728448.
  84. ^ Francis Crick; Christof Koch (2003). (PDF). Nature Neuroscience. 6 (2): 119–126. doi:10.1038/nn0203-119. PMID 12555104. S2CID 13960489. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2012-05-22.
  85. ^ Koch, The Quest for Consciousness, pp. 269–286
  86. ^ a b c Zhaoping, Li (2019-10-01). "A new framework for understanding vision from the perspective of the primary visual cortex". Current Opinion in Neurobiology. Computational Neuroscience. 58: 1–10. doi:10.1016/j.conb.2019.06.001. ISSN 0959-4388. PMID 31271931. S2CID 195806018.
  87. ^ a b Zhaoping, Li (2020-07-30). "The Flip Tilt Illusion: Visible in Peripheral Vision as Predicted by the Central-Peripheral Dichotomy". i-Perception. 11 (4): 2041669520938408. doi:10.1177/2041669520938408. ISSN 2041-6695. PMC 7401056. PMID 32782769.
  88. ^ Biederlack J.; Castelo-Branco M.; Neuenschwander S.; Wheeler D.W.; Singer W.; Nikolić D. (2006). "Brightness induction: Rate enhancement and neuronal synchronization as complementary codes". Neuron. 52 (6): 1073–1083. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2006.11.012. PMID 17178409. S2CID 16732916.
  89. ^ Williams Adrian L.; Singh Krishna D.; Smith Andrew T. (2003). "Surround modulation measured with functional MRI in the human visual cortex". Journal of Neurophysiology. 89 (1): 525–533. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.137.1066. doi:10.1152/jn.00048.2002. PMID 12522199.
  90. ^ Adenauer G. Casali; Olivia Gosseries; Mario Rosanova; Mélanie Boly; Simone Sarasso; Karina R. Casali; Silvia Casarotto; Marie-Aurélie Bruno; Steven Laureys; Giulio Tononi; Marcello Massimini (14 August 2013). "A Theoretically based index of consciousness independent of sensory processing and behavior". Science Translational Medicine. 5 (198): 198ra105. doi:10.1126/scitranslmed.3006294. hdl:2268/171542. PMID 23946194. S2CID 8686961.
  91. ^ Ann B. Butler; Paul R. Manger; B.I.B Lindahl; Peter Århem (2005). "Evolution of the neural basis of consciousness: a bird-mammal comparison". BioEssays. 27 (9): 923–936. doi:10.1002/bies.20280. PMID 16108067.
  92. ^ a b Francis Crick and Christof Koch (1995). "Are we aware of neural activity in primary visual cortex?". Nature. 375 (6527): 121–123. Bibcode:1995Natur.375..121C. doi:10.1038/375121a0. PMID 7753166. S2CID 4262990.
  93. ^ a b c Gerald M. Edelman and Giulio Tononi (2000). A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-01376-0.
  94. ^ a b Rodney M.J. Cotterill (2001). "Cooperation of the basal ganglia, cerebellum, sensory cerebrum and hippocampus: possible implications for cognition, consciousness, intelligence and creativity". Progress in Neurobiology. 64 (1): 1–33. doi:10.1016/s0301-0082(00)00058-7. PMID 11250060. S2CID 206054149.
  95. ^ J.C. Eccles (1982). "Animal consciousness and human self-consciousness". Experientia. 38 (12): 1384–1391. doi:10.1007/bf01955747. PMID 7151952. S2CID 35174442.
  96. ^ John Eccles (1990). "A unitary hypothesis of mind-brain interaction in the cerebral cortex". Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B. 240 (1299): 433–451. Bibcode:1990RSPSB.240..433E. doi:10.1098/rspb.1990.0047. PMID 2165613. S2CID 23188208.
  97. ^ Joaquin Fuster, The Prefrontal Cortex, Second Edition.
  98. ^ Fischer, David B.; Boes, Aaron D.; Demertzi, Athena; Evrard, Henry C.; Laureys, Steven; Edlow, Brian L.; Liu, Hesheng; Saper, Clifford B.; Pascual-Leone, Alvaro; Fox, Michael D.; Geerling, Joel C. (2016-12-06). "A human brain network derived from coma-causing brainstem lesions". Neurology. 87 (23): 2427–2434. doi:10.1212/WNL.0000000000003404. ISSN 0028-3878. PMC 5177681. PMID 27815400.
  99. ^ Northoff, Georg; Lamme, Victor (2020). "Neural signs and mechanisms of consciousness: Is there a potential convergence of theories of consciousness in sight?". Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews. 118: 568–587. doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.07.019. PMID 32783969. S2CID 221084519.
  100. ^ a b Seth, Anil K.; Bayne, Tim (2022). "Theories of consciousness" (PDF). Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 23 (7): 439–452. doi:10.1038/s41583-022-00587-4. PMID 35505255. S2CID 242810797.
  101. ^ a b Doerig, Adrian; Schurger, Aaron; Herzog, Michael H. (2021). "Hard criteria for empirical theories of consciousness". Cognitive Neuroscience. 12 (2): 41–62. doi:10.1080/17588928.2020.1772214. PMID 32663056. S2CID 220529998.
  102. ^ Michael Brooks; "Interview: Cosmic thoughts", New Scientist, November 2022. pp.46-9.
  103. ^ Graziano, M.S.A.; Kastner, S (2011). "Human consciousness and its relationship to social neuroscience: A novel hypothesis". Cog. Neurosci. 2 (2): 98–113. doi:10.1080/17588928.2011.565121. PMC 3223025. PMID 22121395.
  104. ^ Carhart-Harris, R. L.; Friston, K. J.; Barker, Eric L. (20 June 2019). "REBUS and the Anarchic Brain: Toward a Unified Model of the Brain Action of Psychedelics". Pharmacological Reviews. 71 (3): 316–344. doi:10.1124/pr.118.017160. PMC 6588209. PMID 31221820.
  105. ^ Carhart-Harris, Robin L. (November 2018). "The entropic brain – revisited". Neuropharmacology. 142: 167–178. doi:10.1016/j.neuropharm.2018.03.010. PMID 29548884. S2CID 4483591.
  106. ^ Carhart-Harris, Robin L.; Leech, Robert; Hellyer, Peter J.; Shanahan, Murray; Feilding, Amanda; Tagliazucchi, Enzo; Chialvo, Dante R.; Nutt, David (2014). "The entropic brain: a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 8: 20. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00020. PMC 3909994. PMID 24550805.
  107. ^ "Entropy as More than Chaos in the Brain: Expanding Field, Expanding Minds". 2018-06-22.
  108. ^ Papo, David (30 August 2016). "Commentary: The entropic brain: a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 10: 423. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2016.00423. PMC 5004455. PMID 27624312.
  109. ^ David Rudrauf; Daniel Bennequin; Isabela Granic; Gregory Landini; Karl Friston; Kenneth Williford (2017). "A Mathematical Model of Embodied Consciousness". Journal of Theoretical Biology. 428 (1): 106–131. Bibcode:2017JThBi.428..106R. doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2017.05.032. PMID 28554611.
  110. ^ Peter Århem; B.I.B. Lindahl; Paul R. Manger; Ann B. Butler (2008). "On the origin of consciousness—some amniote scenarios". In Hans Liljenström; Peter Århem (eds.). Consciousness Transitions: Phylogenetic, Ontogenetic, and Physiological Aspects. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-444-52977-0.
  111. ^ a b Feinberg, TE; Mallatt, J (October 2013). "The evolutionary and genetic origins of consciousness in the Cambrian Period over 500 million years ago". Frontiers in Psychology. 4: 667. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00667. PMC 3790330. PMID 24109460.
  112. ^ a b Donald Griffin (2001). Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-30865-4.
  113. ^ T.H. Huxley (1874). "On the hypothesis that animals are automata, and its history". The Fortnightly Review. 16 (253): 555–580. Bibcode:1874Natur..10..362.. doi:10.1038/010362a0.
  114. ^ W. James (1879). "Are we automata?". Mind. 4 (13): 1–22. doi:10.1093/mind/os-4.13.1.
  115. ^ B.I.B. Lindahl (1997). "Consciousness and biological evolution". Journal of Theoretical Biology. 187 (4): 613–629. Bibcode:1997JThBi.187..613L. doi:10.1006/jtbi.1996.0394. PMID 9299304.
  116. ^ Karl R. Popper, John C. Eccles (1977). The Self and Its Brain. Springer International. ISBN 978-0-387-08307-0.
  117. ^ Bernard Baars (January 2002). "The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 6 (1): 47–52. doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01819-2. PMID 11849615. S2CID 6386902.
  118. ^ Seth, Anil; Eugene Izhikevich; George Reeke; Gerald Edelman (2006). "Theories and measures of consciousness: An extended framework". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 103 (28): 10799–10804. Bibcode:2006PNAS..10310799S. doi:10.1073/pnas.0604347103. PMC 1487169. PMID 16818879.
  119. ^ a b Ezequiel Morsella (2005). (PDF). Psychological Review. 112 (4): 1000–1021. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.112.4.1000. PMID 16262477. S2CID 2298524. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-11-18.
  120. ^ S. Budiansky (1998). If a Lion Could Talk: Animal Intelligence and the Evolution of Consciousness. The Free Press. ISBN 978-0-684-83710-9.
  121. ^ S. Nichols; T. Grantham (2000). (PDF). Philosophy of Science. 67 (4): 648–670. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.515.9722. doi:10.1086/392859. S2CID 16484193. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-08-13. Retrieved 2017-10-25.
  122. ^ John Eccles (1992). "Evolution of consciousness". Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 89 (16): 7320–7324. Bibcode:1992PNAS...89.7320E. doi:10.1073/pnas.89.16.7320. PMC 49701. PMID 1502142.
  123. ^ Bernard Baars (1993). A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42743-2.
  124. ^ Carruthers, Peter (2004). Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  125. ^ Owen Flanagan; T.W. Polger (1995). "Zombies and the function of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2: 313–321.
  126. ^ Rosenthal, David (2008). "Consciousness and its function". Neuropsychologia. 46 (3): 829–840. doi:10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2007.11.012. PMID 18164042. S2CID 7791431.
  127. ^ Stevan Harnad (2002). "Turing indistinguishability and the Blind Watchmaker". In J.H. Fetzer (ed.). Consciousness Evolving. John Benjamins. Retrieved 2011-10-26.
  128. ^ Zack Robinson; Corey J. Maley; Gualtiero Piccinini (2015). "Is Consciousness a Spandrel?". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (2): 365–383. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.10. S2CID 170892645.
  129. ^ a b Vaitl, Dieter (2005). (PDF). Psychological Bulletin. 131 (1): 98–127. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.131.1.98. PMID 15631555. S2CID 6909813. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-10-22.
  130. ^ Schacter, Daniel; Gilbert, Daniel; Wegner, Daniel (2011). Psychology 2nd Ed. New York: Worth Publishers. p. 190. ISBN 978-1-4292-3719-2. Retrieved 27 October 2020.
  131. ^ Coenen, Anton (2010). "Subconscious Stimulus Recognition and Processing During Sleep" (PDF). Psyche. 16–2. (PDF) from the original on 2017-06-11.
  132. ^ Hobson, J. Allan; Pace-Schott, Edward F.; Stickgold, Robert (2003). "Dreaming and the brain: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states". In Pace-Schott, Edward F.; Solms, Mark; Blagrove, Mark; Harnad, Stevan (eds.). Sleep and Dreaming: Scientific Advances and Reconsiderations. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-00869-3. (PDF) from the original on 2021-08-10.
  133. ^ Johanson M.; Valli K.; Revonsuo A.; Wedlund J. (2008). "Content analysis of subjective experiences in partial epileptic seizures". Epilepsy & Behavior. 12 (1): 170–182. doi:10.1016/j.yebeh.2007.10.002. PMID 18086461. S2CID 28276470.
  134. ^ Johanson M.; Valli K.; Revonsuo A.; et al. (2008). "Alterations in the contents of consciousness in partial epileptic seizures". Epilepsy & Behavior. 13 (2): 366–371. doi:10.1016/j.yebeh.2008.04.014. PMID 18522873. S2CID 24473529.
  135. ^ a b Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV (DSM-IV-TR ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association. 31 July 1994. ISBN 978-0-89042-025-6.
  136. ^ Lyvers, Michael (2003). "The neurochemistry of psychedelic experiences" (PDF). ePublications@bond.
  137. ^ M. Murphy; S. Donovan; E. Taylor (1997). The Physical and Psychological Effects of Meditation: A Review of Contemporary Research With a Comprehensive Bibliography, 1931–1996. Institute of Noetic Sciences.
  138. ^ Tart, Charles (2001). "Ch. 2: The components of consciousness". States of Consciousness. IUniverse.com. ISBN 978-0-595-15196-7. Retrieved 5 October 2011.
  139. ^ Studerus, Erich; Gamma, Alex; Vollenweider, Franz X. (2010). Bell, Vaughan (ed.). "Psychometric evaluation of the altered states of consciousness rating scale (OAV)". PLOS One. 5 (8): e12412. Bibcode:2010PLoSO...512412S. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0012412. PMC 2930851. PMID 20824211.
  140. ^ a b c Hal Blumenfeld (2009). "The neurological examination of consciousness". In Steven Laureys; Giulio Tononi (eds.). The Neurology of Consciousness: Cognitive Neuroscience and Neuropathology. Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-374168-4.
  141. ^ Kinney HC, Korein J, Panigrahy A, Dikkes P, Goode R (26 May 1994). (PDF). N Engl J Med. 330 (21): 1469–1475. doi:10.1056/NEJM199405263302101. PMID 8164698. S2CID 5112573. Archived from the original (PDF) on 18 November 2020.
  142. ^ Koch, The Quest for Consciousness, pp. 216–226
  143. ^ V. Mark Durand; David H. Barlow (2009). Essentials of Abnormal Psychology. Cengage Learning. pp. 74–75. ISBN 978-0-495-59982-1. Note: A patient who can additionally describe the current situation may be referred to as "oriented times four".
  144. ^ Neergaard, Lauren (August 14, 2013). . Associated Press through NBC News. Archived from the original on August 16, 2013. Retrieved March 2, 2022.
  145. ^ a b c Bernat JL (8 Apr 2006). "Chronic disorders of consciousness". Lancet. 367 (9517): 1181–1192. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(06)68508-5. PMID 16616561. S2CID 13550675.
  146. ^ Bernat JL (20 Jul 2010). "The natural history of chronic disorders of consciousness". Neurology. 75 (3): 206–207. doi:10.1212/WNL.0b013e3181e8e960. PMID 20554939. S2CID 30959964.
  147. ^ Coleman MR, Davis MH, Rodd JM, Robson T, Ali A, Owen AM, Pickard JD (September 2009). "Towards the routine use of brain imaging to aid the clinical diagnosis of disorders of consciousness". Brain. 132 (9): 2541–2552. doi:10.1093/brain/awp183. PMID 19710182.
  148. ^ Monti MM, Vanhaudenhuyse A, Coleman MR, Boly M, Pickard JD, Tshibanda L, Owen AM, Laureys S (18 Feb 2010). (PDF). N Engl J Med. 362 (7): 579–589. doi:10.1056/NEJMoa0905370. PMID 20130250. S2CID 13358991. Archived from the original (PDF) on 24 February 2019.
  149. ^ Seel RT, Sherer M, Whyte J, Katz DI, Giacino JT, Rosenbaum AM, Hammond FM, Kalmar K, Pape TL, et al. (December 2010). "Assessment scales for disorders of consciousness: evidence-based recommendations for clinical practice and research". Arch Phys Med Rehabil. 91 (12): 1795–1813. doi:10.1016/j.apmr.2010.07.218. PMID 21112421.
  150. ^ Prigatano, George P. (2009). "Anosognosia: clinical and ethical considerations". Current Opinion in Neurology. 22 (6): 606–611. doi:10.1097/WCO.0b013e328332a1e7. PMID 19809315. S2CID 40751848.
  151. ^ George P. Prigatano; Daniel Schacter (1991). "Introduction". In George Prigatano; Daniel Schacter (eds.). Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury: Clinical and Theoretical Issues. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–16. ISBN 978-0-19-505941-0.
  152. ^ Kenneth M. Heilman (1991). "Anosognosia: possible neuropsychological mechanisms". In George Prigatano; Daniel Schacter (eds.). Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury: Clinical and Theoretical Issues. Oxford University Press. pp. 53–62. ISBN 978-0-19-505941-0.
  153. ^ Arnold J. Sameroff; Marshall M. Haith, eds. (1996). The Five to Seven Year Shift: The Age of Reason and Responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  154. ^ Foulkes, David (1999). Children's Dreaming and the Development of Consciousness. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. p. 13. In defining 'consciousness' as a self-reflective act, psychology loses much of the glamour and mystery of other areas of consciousness-study, but it also can proceed on a workaday basis without becoming paralyzed in pure abstraction.
  155. ^ Nelson, Katherine; Fivush, Robin (2020). "The Development of Autobiographical Memory, Autobiographical Narratives, and Autobiographical Consciousness". Psychological Reports. 123 (1): 74. doi:10.1177/0033294119852574. PMID 31142189. S2CID 169038149.
  156. ^ Jaynes, Julian (2000) [1976]. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Houghton Mifflin. p. 447. ISBN 0-618-05707-2. Consciousness is based on language.... Consciousness is not the same as cognition and should be sharply distinguished from it.
  157. ^ Jaynes, Julian (2000) [1976]. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Houghton Mifflin. p. 450. ISBN 0-618-05707-2. The basic connotative definition of consciousness is thus an analog 'I' narratizing in a functional mind-space. The denotative definition is, as it was for Descartes, Locke, and Hume, what is introspectable.
  158. ^ Nelson, Katherine; Fivush, Robin (2020). "The Development of Autobiographical Memory, Autobiographical Narratives, and Autobiographical Consciousness". Psychological Reports. 123 (1): 80–83. doi:10.1177/0033294119852574. PMID 31142189. S2CID 169038149.
  159. ^ a b Colin Allen. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Animal consciousness". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition).
  160. ^ Peter Carruthers (1999). "Sympathy and subjectivity". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 77 (4): 465–482. doi:10.1080/00048409912349231.
  161. ^ Thomas Nagel (1991). "Ch. 12 What is it like to be a bat?". Mortal Questions. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-40676-5.
  162. ^ Douglas Hofstadter (1981). "Reflections on What Is It Like to Be a Bat?". In Douglas Hofstadter; Daniel Dennett (eds.). The Mind's I. Basic Books. pp. 403–414. ISBN 978-0-7108-0352-8.
  163. ^ Animal Consciousness Officially Recognized by Leading Panel of Neuroscientists. 3 September 2012. Archived from the original on 2021-10-28 – via YouTube.
  164. ^ "Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness" (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  165. ^ Moshe Idel (1990). Golem: Jewish Magical and Mystical Traditions on the Artificial Anthropoid. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-0160-6. Note: In many stories the Golem was mindless, but some gave it emotions or thoughts.
  166. ^ Ada Lovelace. "Sketch of The Analytical Engine, Note G".
  167. ^ Stuart Shieber (2004). The Turing Test : Verbal Behavior as the Hallmark of Intelligence. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-69293-9.
  168. ^ Daniel Dennett; Douglas Hofstadter (1985). The Mind's I. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-553-34584-1.
  169. ^ David Chalmers (1997). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511789-9.
  170. ^ Jürgen Schmidhuber (2009). Driven by Compression Progress: A Simple Principle Explains Essential Aspects of Subjective Beauty, Novelty, Surprise, Interestingness, Attention, Curiosity, Creativity, Art, Science, Music, Jokes. arXiv:0812.4360. Bibcode:2008arXiv0812.4360S.
  171. ^ John R. Searle (1990). "Is the brain's mind a computer program" (PDF). Scientific American. 262 (1): 26–31. Bibcode:1990SciAm.262a..26S. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0190-26. PMID 2294583. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  172. ^ The Chinese Room Argument. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  173. ^ John Searle; et al. (1980). "Minds, brains, and programs". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 3 (3): 417–457. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.83.5248. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00005756. S2CID 55303721.
  174. ^ Graham Oppy; David Dowe (2011). "The Turing test". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition).
  175. ^ Margaret Wilson (2002). "Six views of embodied cognition". Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 9 (4): 625–636. doi:10.3758/BF03196322. PMID 12613670.
  176. ^ Victor Argonov (2014). "Experimental Methods for Unraveling the Mind-body Problem: The Phenomenal Judgment Approach". Journal of Mind and Behavior. 35: 51–70.
  177. ^ William James (1890). The Principles of Psychology, Volume 1. H. Holt. p. 225.
  178. ^ a b c d Karunamuni N.D. (May 2015). "The Five-Aggregate Model of the Mind". SAGE Open. 5 (2): 215824401558386. doi:10.1177/2158244015583860.
  179. ^ Dzogchen Rinpoche (2007). "Taming the mindstream". In Doris Wolter (ed.). Losing the Clouds, Gaining the Sky: Buddhism and the Natural Mind. Wisdom Publications. pp. 81–92. ISBN 978-0-86171-359-2.
  180. ^ Robert Humphrey (1954). Stream of Consciousness in the Modern Novel. University of California Press. pp. 23–49. ISBN 978-0-520-00585-3.
  181. ^ James Joyce (1990). Ulysses. BompaCrazy.com. p. 620.
  182. ^ Richard Maurice Bucke (1905). Cosmic Consciousness: A Study in the Evolution of the Human Mind. Innes & Sons. pp. 1–2.
  183. ^ Satsangi, Prem Saran and Hameroff, Stuart (2016) Consciousness: Integrating Eastern and Western Perspectives New Age Books. ISBN 978-81-7822-493-0
  184. ^ Ken Wilber (2002). The Spectrum of Consciousness. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 3–16. ISBN 978-81-208-1848-4.

Further reading

External links

consciousness, this, article, about, other, uses, disambiguation, conscious, disambiguation, confused, with, conscientiousness, conscience, simplest, sentience, awareness, internal, external, existence, however, nature, millennia, analyses, explanations, debat. This article is about Consciousness For other uses see Consciousness disambiguation and Conscious disambiguation Not to be confused with Conscientiousness or Conscience Consciousness at its simplest is sentience and awareness of internal and external existence 1 However its nature has led to millennia of analyses explanations and debates by philosophers theologians linguists and scientists Opinions differ about what exactly needs to be studied or even considered consciousness In some explanations it is synonymous with the mind and at other times an aspect of mind In the past it was one s inner life the world of introspection of private thought imagination and volition 2 Today it often includes any kind of cognition experience feeling or perception It may be awareness awareness of awareness or self awareness either continuously changing or not 3 4 The disparate range of research notions and speculations raises a curiosity about whether the right questions are being asked 5 Representation of consciousness from the seventeenth century by Robert Fludd an English Paracelsian physician Examples of the range of descriptions definitions or explanations are simple wakefulness one s sense of selfhood or soul explored by looking within being a metaphorical stream of contents or being a mental state mental event or mental process of the brain Contents 1 Inter disciplinary perspectives 2 Etymology 3 The problem of definition 4 Philosophy of mind 4 1 Coherence of the concept 4 2 Types 4 3 Distinguishing consciousness from its contents 4 4 Mind body problem 4 5 Problem of other minds 5 Scientific study 5 1 Measurement 5 2 Neural correlates 5 3 Models 5 4 Biological function and evolution 5 5 Altered states 6 Medical aspects 6 1 Assessment 6 2 Disorders 7 Outside human adults 7 1 In children 7 2 In animals 7 3 In artifacts 8 Stream of consciousness 8 1 Narrative form 9 Spiritual approaches 10 See also 11 References 12 Further reading 13 External linksInter disciplinary perspectives EditWestern philosophers since the time of Descartes and Locke have struggled to comprehend the nature of consciousness and how it fits into a larger picture of the world These questions remain central to both continental and analytic philosophy in phenomenology and the philosophy of mind respectively Consciousness has also become a significant topic of interdisciplinary research in cognitive science involving fields such as psychology linguistics anthropology 6 neuropsychology and neuroscience The primary focus is on understanding what it means biologically and psychologically for information to be present in consciousness that is on determining the neural and psychological correlates of consciousness In medicine consciousness is assessed by observing a patient s arousal and responsiveness and can be seen as a continuum of states ranging from full alertness and comprehension through disorientation delirium loss of meaningful communication and finally loss of movement in response to painful stimuli 7 Issues of practical concern include how the presence of consciousness can be assessed in severely ill comatose or anesthetized people and how to treat conditions in which consciousness is impaired or disrupted 8 The degree of consciousness is measured by standardized behavior observation scales such as the Glasgow Coma Scale Etymology Edit John Locke British Enlightenment philosopher from the 17th century In the late 20th century philosophers like Hamlyn Rorty and Wilkes have disagreed with Kahn Hardie and Modrak as to whether Aristotle even had a concept of consciousness Aristotle does not use any single word or terminology to name the phenomenon it is used only much later especially by John Locke Caston contends that for Aristotle perceptual awareness was somewhat the same as what modern philosophers call consciousness 9 The origin of the modern concept of consciousness is often attributed to Locke s Essay Concerning Human Understanding published in 1690 10 Locke defined consciousness as the perception of what passes in a man s own mind 11 His essay influenced the 18th century view of consciousness and his definition appeared in Samuel Johnson s celebrated Dictionary 1755 12 Consciousness French conscience is also defined in the 1753 volume of Diderot and d Alembert s Encyclopedie as the opinion or internal feeling that we ourselves have from what we do 13 The earliest English language uses of conscious and consciousness date back however to the 1500s The English word conscious originally derived from the Latin conscius con together and scio to know but the Latin word did not have the same meaning as the English word it meant knowing with in other words having joint or common knowledge with another 14 There were however many occurrences in Latin writings of the phrase conscius sibi which translates literally as knowing with oneself or in other words sharing knowledge with oneself about something This phrase had the figurative meaning of knowing that one knows as the modern English word conscious does In its earliest uses in the 1500s the English word conscious retained the meaning of the Latin conscius For example Thomas Hobbes in Leviathan wrote Where two or more men know of one and the same fact they are said to be Conscious of it one to another 15 The Latin phrase conscius sibi whose meaning was more closely related to the current concept of consciousness was rendered in English as conscious to oneself or conscious unto oneself For example Archbishop Ussher wrote in 1613 of being so conscious unto myself of my great weakness 16 Locke s definition from 1690 illustrates that a gradual shift in meaning had taken place A related word was conscientia which primarily means moral conscience In the literal sense conscientia means knowledge with that is shared knowledge The word first appears in Latin juridical texts by writers such as Cicero 17 Here conscientia is the knowledge that a witness has of the deed of someone else 18 Rene Descartes 1596 1650 is generally taken to be the first philosopher to use conscientia in a way that does not fit this traditional meaning 19 Descartes used conscientia the way modern speakers would use conscience In Search after Truth Regulae ad directionem ingenii ut et inquisitio veritatis per lumen naturale Amsterdam 1701 he says conscience or internal testimony conscientia vel interno testimonio 20 21 The problem of definition EditAbout forty meanings attributed to the term consciousness can be identified and categorized based on functions and experiences The prospects for reaching any single agreed upon theory independent definition of consciousness appear remote 22 The dictionary definitions of the word consciousness extend through several centuries and reflect a range of seemingly related meanings with some differences that have been controversial such as the distinction between inward awareness and perception of the physical world or the distinction between conscious and unconscious or the notion of a mental entity or mental activity that is not physical The common usage definitions of consciousness in Webster s Third New International Dictionary 1966 edition Volume 1 page 482 are as follows awareness or perception of an inward psychological or spiritual fact intuitively perceived knowledge of something in one s inner self inward awareness of an external object state or fact concerned awareness INTEREST CONCERN often used with an attributive noun e g class consciousness the state or activity that is characterized by sensation emotion volition or thought mind in the broadest possible sense something in nature that is distinguished from the physical the totality in psychology of sensations perceptions ideas attitudes and feelings of which an individual or a group is aware at any given time or within a particular time span compare STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS waking life as that to which one returns after sleep trance fever wherein all one s mental powers have returned the part of mental life or psychic content in psychoanalysis that is immediately available to the ego compare PRECONSCIOUS UNCONSCIOUSThe Cambridge Dictionary defines consciousness as the state of understanding and realizing something 23 The Oxford Living Dictionary defines consciousness as The state of being aware of and responsive to one s surroundings A person s awareness or perception of something and The fact of awareness by the mind of itself and the world 24 Philosophers have attempted to clarify technical distinctions by using a jargon of their own The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy in 1998 defines consciousness as follows Consciousness Philosophers have used the term consciousness for four main topics knowledge in general intentionality introspection and the knowledge it specifically generates and phenomenal experience Something within one s mind is introspectively conscious just in case one introspects it or is poised to do so Introspection is often thought to deliver one s primary knowledge of one s mental life An experience or other mental entity is phenomenally conscious just in case there is something it is like for one to have it The clearest examples are perceptual experience such as tastings and seeings bodily sensational experiences such as those of pains tickles and itches imaginative experiences such as those of one s own actions or perceptions and streams of thought as in the experience of thinking in words or in images Introspection and phenomenality seem independent or dissociable although this is controversial 25 Many philosophers and scientists have been unhappy about the difficulty of producing a definition that does not involve circularity or fuzziness 26 In The Macmillan Dictionary of Psychology 1989 edition Stuart Sutherland expressed a skeptical attitude more than a definition Consciousness The having of perceptions thoughts and feelings awareness The term is impossible to define except in terms that are unintelligible without a grasp of what consciousness means Many fall into the trap of equating consciousness with self consciousness to be conscious it is only necessary to be aware of the external world Consciousness is a fascinating but elusive phenomenon it is impossible to specify what it is what it does or why it has evolved Nothing worth reading has been written on it 26 A partisan definition such as Sutherland s can hugely affect researchers assumptions and the direction of their work If awareness of the environment is the criterion of consciousness then even the protozoans are conscious If awareness of awareness is required then it is doubtful whether the great apes and human infants are conscious 27 Many philosophers have argued that consciousness is a unitary concept that is understood by the majority of people despite the difficulty philosophers have had defining it 28 Others though have argued that the level of disagreement about the meaning of the word indicates that it either means different things to different people for instance the objective versus subjective aspects of consciousness that it encompasses a variety of distinct meanings with no simple element in common 29 or that we should eliminate this concept from our understanding of the mind a position known as consciousness semanticism 30 Philosophy of mind EditMost writers on the philosophy of consciousness have been concerned with defending a particular point of view and have organized their material accordingly For surveys the most common approach is to follow a historical path by associating stances with the philosophers who are most strongly associated with them for example Descartes Locke Kant etc An alternative is to organize philosophical stances according to basic issues Coherence of the concept Edit Philosophers differ from non philosophers in their intuitions about what consciousness is 31 While most people have a strong intuition for the existence of what they refer to as consciousness 28 skeptics argue that this intuition is false either because the concept of consciousness is intrinsically incoherent or because our intuitions about it are based in illusions Gilbert Ryle for example argued that traditional understanding of consciousness depends on a Cartesian dualist outlook that improperly distinguishes between mind and body or between mind and world He proposed that we speak not of minds bodies and the world but of individuals or persons acting in the world Thus by speaking of consciousness we end up misleading ourselves by thinking that there is any sort of thing as consciousness separated from behavioral and linguistic understandings 32 Types Edit Ned Block argued that discussions on consciousness often failed to properly distinguish phenomenal P consciousness from access A consciousness though these terms had been used before Block 33 P consciousness according to Block is raw experience it is moving colored forms sounds sensations emotions and feelings with our bodies and responses at the center These experiences considered independently of any impact on behavior are called qualia A consciousness on the other hand is the phenomenon whereby information in our minds is accessible for verbal report reasoning and the control of behavior So when we perceive information about what we perceive is access conscious when we introspect information about our thoughts is access conscious when we remember information about the past is access conscious and so on Although some philosophers such as Daniel Dennett have disputed the validity of this distinction 34 others have broadly accepted it David Chalmers has argued that A consciousness can in principle be understood in mechanistic terms but that understanding P consciousness is much more challenging he calls this the hard problem of consciousness 35 Some philosophers believe that Block s two types of consciousness are not the end of the story William Lycan for example argued in his book Consciousness and Experience that at least eight clearly distinct types of consciousness can be identified organism consciousness control consciousness consciousness of state event consciousness reportability introspective consciousness subjective consciousness self consciousness and that even this list omits several more obscure forms 36 There is also debate over whether or not A consciousness and P consciousness always coexist or if they can exist separately Although P consciousness without A consciousness is more widely accepted there have been some hypothetical examples of A without P Block for instance suggests the case of a zombie that is computationally identical to a person but without any subjectivity However he remains somewhat skeptical concluding I don t know whether there are any actual cases of A consciousness without P consciousness but I hope I have illustrated their conceptual possibility 37 Distinguishing consciousness from its contents Edit Sam Harris observes At the level of your experience you are not a body of cells organelles and atoms you are consciousness and its ever changing contents 38 Seen in this way consciousness is a subjectively experienced ever present field in which things the contents of consciousness come and go Christopher Tricker argues that this field of consciousness is symbolised by the mythical bird that opens the Daoist classic the Zhuangzi This bird s name is Of a Flock peng 鵬 yet its back is countless thousands of miles across and its wings are like clouds arcing across the heavens Like Of a Flock whose wings arc across the heavens the wings of your consciousness span to the horizon At the same time the wings of every other being s consciousness span to the horizon You are of a flock one bird among kin 39 Mind body problem Edit Main article Mind body problem Illustration of dualism by Rene Descartes Inputs are passed by the sensory organs to the pineal gland and from there to the immaterial spirit Mental processes such as consciousness and physical processes such as brain events seem to be correlated however the specific nature of the connection is unknown The first influential philosopher to discuss this question specifically was Descartes and the answer he gave is known as Cartesian dualism Descartes proposed that consciousness resides within an immaterial domain he called res cogitans the realm of thought in contrast to the domain of material things which he called res extensa the realm of extension 40 He suggested that the interaction between these two domains occurs inside the brain perhaps in a small midline structure called the pineal gland 41 Although it is widely accepted that Descartes explained the problem cogently few later philosophers have been happy with his solution and his ideas about the pineal gland have especially been ridiculed 42 However no alternative solution has gained general acceptance Proposed solutions can be divided broadly into two categories dualist solutions that maintain Descartes s rigid distinction between the realm of consciousness and the realm of matter but give different answers for how the two realms relate to each other and monist solutions that maintain that there is really only one realm of being of which consciousness and matter are both aspects Each of these categories itself contains numerous variants The two main types of dualism are substance dualism which holds that the mind is formed of a distinct type of substance not governed by the laws of physics and property dualism which holds that the laws of physics are universally valid but cannot be used to explain the mind The three main types of monism are physicalism which holds that the mind consists of matter organized in a particular way idealism which holds that only thought or experience truly exists and matter is merely an illusion and neutral monism which holds that both mind and matter are aspects of a distinct essence that is itself identical to neither of them There are also however a large number of idiosyncratic theories that cannot cleanly be assigned to any of these schools of thought 43 Since the dawn of Newtonian science with its vision of simple mechanical principles governing the entire universe some philosophers have been tempted by the idea that consciousness could be explained in purely physical terms The first influential writer to propose such an idea explicitly was Julien Offray de La Mettrie in his book Man a Machine L homme machine His arguments however were very abstract 44 The most influential modern physical theories of consciousness are based on psychology and neuroscience Theories proposed by neuroscientists such as Gerald Edelman 45 and Antonio Damasio 46 and by philosophers such as Daniel Dennett 47 seek to explain consciousness in terms of neural events occurring within the brain Many other neuroscientists such as Christof Koch 48 have explored the neural basis of consciousness without attempting to frame all encompassing global theories At the same time computer scientists working in the field of artificial intelligence have pursued the goal of creating digital computer programs that can simulate or embody consciousness 49 A few theoretical physicists have argued that classical physics is intrinsically incapable of explaining the holistic aspects of consciousness but that quantum theory may provide the missing ingredients Several theorists have therefore proposed quantum mind QM theories of consciousness 50 Notable theories falling into this category include the holonomic brain theory of Karl Pribram and David Bohm and the Orch OR theory formulated by Stuart Hameroff and Roger Penrose Some of these QM theories offer descriptions of phenomenal consciousness as well as QM interpretations of access consciousness None of the quantum mechanical theories have been confirmed by experiment Recent publications by G Guerreshi J Cia S Popescu and H Briegel 51 could falsify proposals such as those of Hameroff which rely on quantum entanglement in protein At the present time many scientists and philosophers consider the arguments for an important role of quantum phenomena to be unconvincing 52 Apart from the general question of the hard problem of consciousness which is roughly speaking the question of how mental experience can arise from a physical basis 53 a more specialized question is how to square the subjective notion that we are in control of our decisions at least in some small measure with the customary view of causality that subsequent events are caused by prior events The topic of free will is the philosophical and scientific examination of this conundrum Problem of other minds Edit Main article Problem of other minds Many philosophers consider experience to be the essence of consciousness and believe that experience can only fully be known from the inside subjectively But if consciousness is subjective and not visible from the outside why do the vast majority of people believe that other people are conscious but rocks and trees are not 54 This is called the problem of other minds 55 It is particularly acute for people who believe in the possibility of philosophical zombies that is people who think it is possible in principle to have an entity that is physically indistinguishable from a human being and behaves like a human being in every way but nevertheless lacks consciousness 56 Related issues have also been studied extensively by Greg Littmann of the University of Illinois 57 and by Colin Allen a professor at the University of Pittsburgh regarding the literature and research studying artificial intelligence in androids 58 The most commonly given answer is that we attribute consciousness to other people because we see that they resemble us in appearance and behavior we reason that if they look like us and act like us they must be like us in other ways including having experiences of the sort that we do 59 There are however a variety of problems with that explanation For one thing it seems to violate the principle of parsimony by postulating an invisible entity that is not necessary to explain what we observe 59 Some philosophers such as Daniel Dennett in a research paper titled The Unimagined Preposterousness of Zombies argue that people who give this explanation do not really understand what they are saying 60 More broadly philosophers who do not accept the possibility of zombies generally believe that consciousness is reflected in behavior including verbal behavior and that we attribute consciousness on the basis of behavior A more straightforward way of saying this is that we attribute experiences to people because of what they can do including the fact that they can tell us about their experiences 61 Scientific study EditFor many decades consciousness as a research topic was avoided by the majority of mainstream scientists because of a general feeling that a phenomenon defined in subjective terms could not properly be studied using objective experimental methods 62 In 1975 George Mandler published an influential psychological study which distinguished between slow serial and limited conscious processes and fast parallel and extensive unconscious ones 63 The Science and Religion Forum 64 1984 annual conference From Artificial Intelligence to Human Consciousness identified the nature of consciousness as a matter for investigation Donald Michie was a keynote speaker Starting in the 1980s an expanding community of neuroscientists and psychologists have associated themselves with a field called Consciousness Studies giving rise to a stream of experimental work published in books 65 journals such as Consciousness and Cognition Frontiers in Consciousness Research Psyche and the Journal of Consciousness Studies along with regular conferences organized by groups such as the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness 66 and the Society for Consciousness Studies Modern medical and psychological investigations into consciousness are based on psychological experiments including for example the investigation of priming effects using subliminal stimuli and on case studies of alterations in consciousness produced by trauma illness or drugs Broadly viewed scientific approaches are based on two core concepts The first identifies the content of consciousness with the experiences that are reported by human subjects the second makes use of the concept of consciousness that has been developed by neurologists and other medical professionals who deal with patients whose behavior is impaired In either case the ultimate goals are to develop techniques for assessing consciousness objectively in humans as well as other animals and to understand the neural and psychological mechanisms that underlie it 48 Measurement Edit The Necker cube an ambiguous image Experimental research on consciousness presents special difficulties due to the lack of a universally accepted operational definition In the majority of experiments that are specifically about consciousness the subjects are human and the criterion used is verbal report in other words subjects are asked to describe their experiences and their descriptions are treated as observations of the contents of consciousness 67 For example subjects who stare continuously at a Necker cube usually report that they experience it flipping between two 3D configurations even though the stimulus itself remains the same 68 The objective is to understand the relationship between the conscious awareness of stimuli as indicated by verbal report and the effects the stimuli have on brain activity and behavior In several paradigms such as the technique of response priming the behavior of subjects is clearly influenced by stimuli for which they report no awareness and suitable experimental manipulations can lead to increasing priming effects despite decreasing prime identification double dissociation 69 Verbal report is widely considered to be the most reliable indicator of consciousness but it raises a number of issues 70 For one thing if verbal reports are treated as observations akin to observations in other branches of science then the possibility arises that they may contain errors but it is difficult to make sense of the idea that subjects could be wrong about their own experiences and even more difficult to see how such an error could be detected 71 Daniel Dennett has argued for an approach he calls heterophenomenology which means treating verbal reports as stories that may or may not be true but his ideas about how to do this have not been widely adopted 72 Another issue with verbal report as a criterion is that it restricts the field of study to humans who have language this approach cannot be used to study consciousness in other species pre linguistic children or people with types of brain damage that impair language As a third issue philosophers who dispute the validity of the Turing test may feel that it is possible at least in principle for verbal report to be dissociated from consciousness entirely a philosophical zombie may give detailed verbal reports of awareness in the absence of any genuine awareness 73 Although verbal report is in practice the gold standard for ascribing consciousness it is not the only possible criterion 70 In medicine consciousness is assessed as a combination of verbal behavior arousal brain activity and purposeful movement The last three of these can be used as indicators of consciousness when verbal behavior is absent 74 75 The scientific literature regarding the neural bases of arousal and purposeful movement is very extensive Their reliability as indicators of consciousness is disputed however due to numerous studies showing that alert human subjects can be induced to behave purposefully in a variety of ways in spite of reporting a complete lack of awareness 69 Studies of the neuroscience of free will have also shown that the experiences that people report when they behave purposefully sometimes do not correspond to their actual behaviors or to the patterns of electrical activity recorded from their brains 76 Another approach applies specifically to the study of self awareness that is the ability to distinguish oneself from others In the 1970s Gordon Gallup developed an operational test for self awareness known as the mirror test The test examines whether animals are able to differentiate between seeing themselves in a mirror versus seeing other animals The classic example involves placing a spot of coloring on the skin or fur near the individual s forehead and seeing if they attempt to remove it or at least touch the spot thus indicating that they recognize that the individual they are seeing in the mirror is themselves 77 Humans older than 18 months and other great apes bottlenose dolphins orcas pigeons European magpies and elephants have all been observed to pass this test 78 Neural correlates Edit Schema of the neural processes underlying consciousness from Christof Koch A major part of the scientific literature on consciousness consists of studies that examine the relationship between the experiences reported by subjects and the activity that simultaneously takes place in their brains that is studies of the neural correlates of consciousness The hope is to find that activity in a particular part of the brain or a particular pattern of global brain activity which will be strongly predictive of conscious awareness Several brain imaging techniques such as EEG and fMRI have been used for physical measures of brain activity in these studies 79 Another idea that has drawn attention for several decades is that consciousness is associated with high frequency gamma band oscillations in brain activity This idea arose from proposals in the 1980s by Christof von der Malsburg and Wolf Singer that gamma oscillations could solve the so called binding problem by linking information represented in different parts of the brain into a unified experience 80 Rodolfo Llinas for example proposed that consciousness results from recurrent thalamo cortical resonance where the specific thalamocortical systems content and the non specific centromedial thalamus thalamocortical systems context interact in the gamma band frequency via synchronous oscillations 81 A number of studies have shown that activity in primary sensory areas of the brain is not sufficient to produce consciousness it is possible for subjects to report a lack of awareness even when areas such as the primary visual cortex V1 show clear electrical responses to a stimulus 82 Higher brain areas are seen as more promising especially the prefrontal cortex which is involved in a range of higher cognitive functions collectively known as executive functions 83 There is substantial evidence that a top down flow of neural activity i e activity propagating from the frontal cortex to sensory areas is more predictive of conscious awareness than a bottom up flow of activity 84 The prefrontal cortex is not the only candidate area however studies by Nikos Logothetis and his colleagues have shown for example that visually responsive neurons in parts of the temporal lobe reflect the visual perception in the situation when conflicting visual images are presented to different eyes i e bistable percepts during binocular rivalry 85 Furthermore top down feedback from higher to lower visual brain areas may be weaker or absent in the peripheral visual field as suggested by some experimental data and theoretical arguments 86 nevertheless humans can perceive visual inputs in the peripheral visual field arising from bottom up V1 neural activities 86 87 Meanwhile bottom up V1 activities for the central visual fields can be vetoed and thus made invisible to perception by the top down feedback when these bottom up signals are inconsistent with brain s internal model of the visual world 86 87 Modulation of neural responses may correlate with phenomenal experiences In contrast to the raw electrical responses that do not correlate with consciousness the modulation of these responses by other stimuli correlates surprisingly well with an important aspect of consciousness namely with the phenomenal experience of stimulus intensity brightness contrast In the research group of Danko Nikolic it has been shown that some of the changes in the subjectively perceived brightness correlated with the modulation of firing rates while others correlated with the modulation of neural synchrony 88 An fMRI investigation suggested that these findings were strictly limited to the primary visual areas 89 This indicates that in the primary visual areas changes in firing rates and synchrony can be considered as neural correlates of qualia at least for some type of qualia In 2013 the perturbational complexity index PCI was proposed a measure of the algorithmic complexity of the electrophysiological response of the cortex to transcranial magnetic stimulation This measure was shown to be higher in individuals that are awake in REM sleep or in a locked in state than in those who are in deep sleep or in a vegetative state 90 making it potentially useful as a quantitative assessment of consciousness states Assuming that not only humans but even some non mammalian species are conscious a number of evolutionary approaches to the problem of neural correlates of consciousness open up For example assuming that birds are conscious a common assumption among neuroscientists and ethologists due to the extensive cognitive repertoire of birds there are comparative neuroanatomical ways to validate some of the principal currently competing mammalian consciousness brain theories The rationale for such a comparative study is that the avian brain deviates structurally from the mammalian brain So how similar are they What homologues can be identified The general conclusion from the study by Butler et al 91 is that some of the major theories for the mammalian brain 92 93 94 also appear to be valid for the avian brain The structures assumed to be critical for consciousness in mammalian brains have homologous counterparts in avian brains Thus the main portions of the theories of Crick and Koch 92 Edelman and Tononi 93 and Cotterill 94 seem to be compatible with the assumption that birds are conscious Edelman also differentiates between what he calls primary consciousness which is a trait shared by humans and non human animals and higher order consciousness as it appears in humans alone along with human language capacity 93 Certain aspects of the three theories however seem less easy to apply to the hypothesis of avian consciousness For instance the suggestion by Crick and Koch that layer 5 neurons of the mammalian brain have a special role seems difficult to apply to the avian brain since the avian homologues have a different morphology Likewise the theory of Eccles 95 96 seems incompatible since a structural homologue analogue to the dendron has not been found in avian brains The assumption of an avian consciousness also brings the reptilian brain into focus The reason is the structural continuity between avian and reptilian brains meaning that the phylogenetic origin of consciousness may be earlier than suggested by many leading neuroscientists Joaquin Fuster of UCLA has advocated the position of the importance of the prefrontal cortex in humans along with the areas of Wernicke and Broca as being of particular importance to the development of human language capacities neuro anatomically necessary for the emergence of higher order consciousness in humans 97 A study in 2016 looked at lesions in specific areas of the brainstem that were associated with coma and vegetative states A small region of the rostral dorsolateral pontine tegmentum in the brainstem was suggested to drive consciousness through functional connectivity with two cortical regions the left ventral anterior insular cortex and the pregenual anterior cingulate cortex These three regions may work together as a triad to maintain consciousness 98 Models Edit This section is missing information about global workspace theory Please expand the section to include this information Further details may exist on the talk page January 2023 Further information Models of consciousness A wide range of empirical theories of consciousness have been proposed 99 100 101 Adrian Doerig and colleagues list 13 notable theories 101 while Anil Seth and Tim Bayne list 22 notable theories 100 Integrated information theory IIT postulates that consciousness resides in the information being processed and arises once the information reaches a certain level of complexity citation needed Orchestrated objective reduction Orch OR postulates that consciousness originates at the quantum level inside neurons The mechanism is held to be a quantum process called objective reduction that is orchestrated by cellular structures called microtubules However the details of the mechanism would go beyond current quantum theory 102 In 2011 Graziano and Kastner 103 proposed the attention schema theory of awareness In that theory specific cortical areas notably in the superior temporal sulcus and the temporo parietal junction are used to build the construct of awareness and attribute it to other people The same cortical machinery is also used to attribute awareness to oneself Damage to these cortical regions can lead to deficits in consciousness such as hemispatial neglect In the attention schema theory the value of explaining the feature of awareness and attributing it to a person is to gain a useful predictive model of that person s attentional processing Attention is a style of information processing in which a brain focuses its resources on a limited set of interrelated signals Awareness in this theory is a useful simplified schema that represents attentional states To be aware of X is explained by constructing a model of one s attentional focus on X The entropic brain is a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs The theory suggests that the brain in primary states such as rapid eye movement REM sleep early psychosis and under the influence of psychedelic drugs is in a disordered state normal waking consciousness constrains some of this freedom and makes possible metacognitive functions such as internal self administered reality testing and self awareness 104 105 106 107 Criticism has included questioning whether the theory has been adequately tested 108 In 2017 work by David Rudrauf and colleagues including Karl Friston applied the active inference paradigm to consciousness a model of how sensory data is integrated with priors in a process of projective transformation The authors argue that while their model identifies a key relationship between computation and phenomenology it does not completely solve the hard problem of consciousness or completely close the explanatory gap 109 Biological function and evolution Edit Opinions are divided as to where in biological evolution consciousness emerged and about whether or not consciousness has any survival value Some argue that consciousness is a byproduct of evolution It has been argued that consciousness emerged i exclusively with the first humans ii exclusively with the first mammals iii independently in mammals and birds or iv with the first reptiles 110 Other authors date the origins of consciousness to the first animals with nervous systems or early vertebrates in the Cambrian over 500 million years ago 111 Donald Griffin suggests in his book Animal Minds a gradual evolution of consciousness 112 Each of these scenarios raises the question of the possible survival value of consciousness Thomas Henry Huxley defends in an essay titled On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata and its History an epiphenomenalist theory of consciousness according to which consciousness is a causally inert effect of neural activity as the steam whistle which accompanies the work of a locomotive engine is without influence upon its machinery 113 To this William James objects in his essay Are We Automata by stating an evolutionary argument for mind brain interaction implying that if the preservation and development of consciousness in the biological evolution is a result of natural selection it is plausible that consciousness has not only been influenced by neural processes but has had a survival value itself and it could only have had this if it had been efficacious 114 115 Karl Popper develops in the book The Self and Its Brain a similar evolutionary argument 116 Regarding the primary function of conscious processing a recurring idea in recent theories is that phenomenal states somehow integrate neural activities and information processing that would otherwise be independent 117 This has been called the integration consensus Another example has been proposed by Gerald Edelman called dynamic core hypothesis which puts emphasis on reentrant connections that reciprocally link areas of the brain in a massively parallel manner 118 Edelman also stresses the importance of the evolutionary emergence of higher order consciousness in humans from the historically older trait of primary consciousness which humans share with non human animals see Neural correlates section above These theories of integrative function present solutions to two classic problems associated with consciousness differentiation and unity They show how our conscious experience can discriminate between a virtually unlimited number of different possible scenes and details differentiation because it integrates those details from our sensory systems while the integrative nature of consciousness in this view easily explains how our experience can seem unified as one whole despite all of these individual parts However it remains unspecified which kinds of information are integrated in a conscious manner and which kinds can be integrated without consciousness Nor is it explained what specific causal role conscious integration plays nor why the same functionality cannot be achieved without consciousness Obviously not all kinds of information are capable of being disseminated consciously e g neural activity related to vegetative functions reflexes unconscious motor programs low level perceptual analyses etc and many kinds of information can be disseminated and combined with other kinds without consciousness as in intersensory interactions such as the ventriloquism effect 119 Hence it remains unclear why any of it is conscious For a review of the differences between conscious and unconscious integrations see the article of Ezequiel Morsella 119 As noted earlier even among writers who consider consciousness to be well defined there is widespread dispute about which animals other than humans can be said to possess it 120 Edelman has described this distinction as that of humans possessing higher order consciousness while sharing the trait of primary consciousness with non human animals see previous paragraph Thus any examination of the evolution of consciousness is faced with great difficulties Nevertheless some writers have argued that consciousness can be viewed from the standpoint of evolutionary biology as an adaptation in the sense of a trait that increases fitness 121 In his article Evolution of consciousness John Eccles argued that special anatomical and physical properties of the mammalian cerebral cortex gave rise to consciousness a psychon linked to a dendron through quantum physics 122 Bernard Baars proposed that once in place this recursive circuitry may have provided a basis for the subsequent development of many of the functions that consciousness facilitates in higher organisms 123 Peter Carruthers has put forth one such potential adaptive advantage gained by conscious creatures by suggesting that consciousness allows an individual to make distinctions between appearance and reality 124 This ability would enable a creature to recognize the likelihood that their perceptions are deceiving them e g that water in the distance may be a mirage and behave accordingly and it could also facilitate the manipulation of others by recognizing how things appear to them for both cooperative and devious ends Other philosophers however have suggested that consciousness would not be necessary for any functional advantage in evolutionary processes 125 126 No one has given a causal explanation they argue of why it would not be possible for a functionally equivalent non conscious organism i e a philosophical zombie to achieve the very same survival advantages as a conscious organism If evolutionary processes are blind to the difference between function F being performed by conscious organism O and non conscious organism O it is unclear what adaptive advantage consciousness could provide 127 As a result an exaptive explanation of consciousness has gained favor with some theorists that posit consciousness did not evolve as an adaptation but was an exaptation arising as a consequence of other developments such as increases in brain size or cortical rearrangement 111 Consciousness in this sense has been compared to the blind spot in the retina where it is not an adaption of the retina but instead just a by product of the way the retinal axons were wired 128 Several scholars including Pinker Chomsky Edelman and Luria have indicated the importance of the emergence of human language as an important regulative mechanism of learning and memory in the context of the development of higher order consciousness see Neural correlates section above Altered states Edit A Buddhist monk meditating Main article Altered state of consciousness There are some brain states in which consciousness seems to be absent including dreamless sleep or coma There are also a variety of circumstances that can change the relationship between the mind and the world in less drastic ways producing what are known as altered states of consciousness Some altered states occur naturally others can be produced by drugs or brain damage 129 Altered states can be accompanied by changes in thinking disturbances in the sense of time feelings of loss of control changes in emotional expression alternations in body image and changes in meaning or significance 130 The two most widely accepted altered states are sleep and dreaming Although dream sleep and non dream sleep appear very similar to an outside observer each is associated with a distinct pattern of brain activity metabolic activity and eye movement each is also associated with a distinct pattern of experience and cognition During ordinary non dream sleep people who are awakened report only vague and sketchy thoughts and their experiences do not cohere into a continuous narrative During dream sleep in contrast people who are awakened report rich and detailed experiences in which events form a continuous progression which may however be interrupted by bizarre or fantastic intrusions 131 failed verification Thought processes during the dream state frequently show a high level of irrationality Both dream and non dream states are associated with severe disruption of memory it usually disappears in seconds during the non dream state and in minutes after awakening from a dream unless actively refreshed 132 Research conducted on the effects of partial epileptic seizures on consciousness found that patients who have partial epileptic seizures experience altered states of consciousness 133 134 In partial epileptic seizures consciousness is impaired or lost while some aspects of consciousness often automated behaviors remain intact Studies found that when measuring the qualitative features during partial epileptic seizures patients exhibited an increase in arousal and became absorbed in the experience of the seizure followed by difficulty in focusing and shifting attention A variety of psychoactive drugs including alcohol have notable effects on consciousness 135 These range from a simple dulling of awareness produced by sedatives to increases in the intensity of sensory qualities produced by stimulants cannabis empathogens entactogens such as MDMA Ecstasy or most notably by the class of drugs known as psychedelics 129 LSD mescaline psilocybin dimethyltryptamine and others in this group can produce major distortions of perception including hallucinations some users even describe their drug induced experiences as mystical or spiritual in quality The brain mechanisms underlying these effects are not as well understood as those induced by use of alcohol 135 but there is substantial evidence that alterations in the brain system that uses the chemical neurotransmitter serotonin play an essential role 136 There has been some research into physiological changes in yogis and people who practise various techniques of meditation Some research with brain waves during meditation has reported differences between those corresponding to ordinary relaxation and those corresponding to meditation It has been disputed however whether there is enough evidence to count these as physiologically distinct states of consciousness 137 The most extensive study of the characteristics of altered states of consciousness was made by psychologist Charles Tart in the 1960s and 1970s Tart analyzed a state of consciousness as made up of a number of component processes including exteroception sensing the external world interoception sensing the body input processing seeing meaning emotions memory time sense sense of identity evaluation and cognitive processing motor output and interaction with the environment 138 self published source Each of these in his view could be altered in multiple ways by drugs or other manipulations The components that Tart identified have not however been validated by empirical studies Research in this area has not yet reached firm conclusions but a recent questionnaire based study identified eleven significant factors contributing to drug induced states of consciousness experience of unity spiritual experience blissful state insightfulness disembodiment impaired control and cognition anxiety complex imagery elementary imagery audio visual synesthesia and changed meaning of percepts 139 Medical aspects EditThe medical approach to consciousness is scientifically oriented It derives from a need to treat people whose brain function has been impaired as a result of disease brain damage toxins or drugs In medicine conceptual distinctions are considered useful to the degree that they can help to guide treatments The medical approach focuses mostly on the amount of consciousness a person has in medicine consciousness is assessed as a level ranging from coma and brain death at the low end to full alertness and purposeful responsiveness at the high end 140 Consciousness is of concern to patients and physicians especially neurologists and anesthesiologists Patients may have disorders of consciousness or may need to be anesthetized for a surgical procedure Physicians may perform consciousness related interventions such as instructing the patient to sleep administering general anesthesia or inducing medical coma 140 Also bioethicists may be concerned with the ethical implications of consciousness in medical cases of patients such as the Karen Ann Quinlan case 141 while neuroscientists may study patients with impaired consciousness in hopes of gaining information about how the brain works 142 Assessment Edit In medicine consciousness is examined using a set of procedures known as neuropsychological assessment 74 There are two commonly used methods for assessing the level of consciousness of a patient a simple procedure that requires minimal training and a more complex procedure that requires substantial expertise The simple procedure begins by asking whether the patient is able to move and react to physical stimuli If so the next question is whether the patient can respond in a meaningful way to questions and commands If so the patient is asked for name current location and current day and time A patient who can answer all of these questions is said to be alert and oriented times four sometimes denoted A amp Ox4 on a medical chart and is usually considered fully conscious 143 The more complex procedure is known as a neurological examination and is usually carried out by a neurologist in a hospital setting A formal neurological examination runs through a precisely delineated series of tests beginning with tests for basic sensorimotor reflexes and culminating with tests for sophisticated use of language The outcome may be summarized using the Glasgow Coma Scale which yields a number in the range 3 15 with a score of 3 to 8 indicating coma and 15 indicating full consciousness The Glasgow Coma Scale has three subscales measuring the best motor response ranging from no motor response to obeys commands the best eye response ranging from no eye opening to eyes opening spontaneously and the best verbal response ranging from no verbal response to fully oriented There is also a simpler pediatric version of the scale for children too young to be able to use language 140 In 2013 an experimental procedure was developed to measure degrees of consciousness the procedure involving stimulating the brain with a magnetic pulse measuring resulting waves of electrical activity and developing a consciousness score based on the complexity of the brain activity 144 Disorders Edit Medical conditions that inhibit consciousness are considered disorders of consciousness 145 This category generally includes minimally conscious state and persistent vegetative state but sometimes also includes the less severe locked in syndrome and more severe chronic coma 145 146 Differential diagnosis of these disorders is an active area of biomedical research 147 148 149 Finally brain death results in possible irreversible disruption of consciousness 145 While other conditions may cause a moderate deterioration e g dementia and delirium or transient interruption e g grand mal and petit mal seizures of consciousness they are not included in this category Disorder DescriptionLocked in syndrome The patient has awareness sleep wake cycles and meaningful behavior viz eye movement but is isolated due to quadriplegia and pseudobulbar palsy Minimally conscious state The patient has intermittent periods of awareness and wakefulness and displays some meaningful behavior Persistent vegetative state The patient has sleep wake cycles but lacks awareness and only displays reflexive and non purposeful behavior Chronic coma The patient lacks awareness and sleep wake cycles and only displays reflexive behavior Brain death The patient lacks awareness sleep wake cycles and brain mediated reflexive behavior Medical experts increasingly view anosognosia as a disorder of consciousness 150 Anosognosia a Greek derived term meaning unawareness of disease This is a condition in which patients are disabled in some way most commonly as a result of a stroke but either misunderstand the nature of the problem or deny that there is anything wrong with them 151 The most frequently occurring form is seen in people who have experienced a stroke damaging the parietal lobe in the right hemisphere of the brain giving rise to a syndrome known as hemispatial neglect characterized by an inability to direct action or attention toward objects located to the left with respect to their bodies Patients with hemispatial neglect are often paralyzed on the left side of the body but sometimes deny being unable to move When questioned about the obvious problem the patient may avoid giving a direct answer or may give an explanation that doesn t make sense Patients with hemispatial neglect may also fail to recognize paralyzed parts of their bodies one frequently mentioned case is of a man who repeatedly tried to throw his own paralyzed right leg out of the bed he was lying in and when asked what he was doing complained that somebody had put a dead leg into the bed with him An even more striking type of anosognosia is Anton Babinski syndrome a rarely occurring condition in which patients become blind but claim to be able to see normally and persist in this claim in spite of all evidence to the contrary 152 Outside human adults EditIn children Edit See also Theory of mind Of the eight types of consciousness in the Lycan classification some are detectable in utero and others develop years after birth Psychologist and educator William Foulkes studied children s dreams and concluded that prior to the shift in cognitive maturation that humans experience during ages five to seven 153 children lack the Lockean consciousness that Lycan had labeled introspective consciousness and that Foulkes labels self reflection 154 In a 2020 paper Katherine Nelson and Robyn Fivush use autobiographical consciousness to label essentially the same faculty and agree with Foulkes on the timing of this faculty s acquisition Nelson and Fivush contend that language is the tool by which humans create a new uniquely human form of consciousness namely autobiographical consciousness 155 Julian Jaynes had staked out these positions decades earlier 156 157 Citing the developmental steps that lead the infant to autobiographical consciousness Nelson and Fivush point to the acquisition of theory of mind calling theory of mind necessary for autobiographical consciousness and defining it as understanding differences between one s own mind and others minds in terms of beliefs desires emotions and thoughts They write The hallmark of theory of mind the understanding of false belief occurs at five to six years of age 158 In animals Edit Main article Animal consciousness The topic of animal consciousness is beset by a number of difficulties It poses the problem of other minds in an especially severe form because non human animals lacking the ability to express human language cannot tell humans about their experiences 159 Also it is difficult to reason objectively about the question because a denial that an animal is conscious is often taken to imply that it does not feel its life has no value and that harming it is not morally wrong Descartes for example has sometimes been blamed for mistreatment of animals due to the fact that he believed only humans have a non physical mind 160 Most people have a strong intuition that some animals such as cats and dogs are conscious while others such as insects are not but the sources of this intuition are not obvious and are often based on personal interactions with pets and other animals they have observed 159 Thomas Nagel argues that while a human might be able to imagine what it is like to be a bat by taking the bat s point of view it would still be impossible to know what it is like for a bat to be a bat Townsend s big eared bat pictured Philosophers who consider subjective experience the essence of consciousness also generally believe as a correlate that the existence and nature of animal consciousness can never rigorously be known Thomas Nagel spelled out this point of view in an influential essay titled What Is it Like to Be a Bat He said that an organism is conscious if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism something it is like for the organism and he argued that no matter how much we know about an animal s brain and behavior we can never really put ourselves into the mind of the animal and experience its world in the way it does itself 161 Other thinkers such as Douglas Hofstadter dismiss this argument as incoherent 162 Several psychologists and ethologists have argued for the existence of animal consciousness by describing a range of behaviors that appear to show animals holding beliefs about things they cannot directly perceive Donald Griffin s 2001 book Animal Minds reviews a substantial portion of the evidence 112 On July 7 2012 eminent scientists from different branches of neuroscience gathered at the University of Cambridge to celebrate the Francis Crick Memorial Conference which deals with consciousness in humans and pre linguistic consciousness in nonhuman animals After the conference they signed in the presence of Stephen Hawking the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness which summarizes the most important findings of the survey We decided to reach a consensus and make a statement directed to the public that is not scientific It s obvious to everyone in this room that animals have consciousness but it is not obvious to the rest of the world It is not obvious to the rest of the Western world or the Far East It is not obvious to the society 163 Convergent evidence indicates that non human animals including all mammals and birds and other creatures have the necessary neural substrates of consciousness and the capacity to exhibit intentional behaviors 164 In artifacts Edit Main article Artificial consciousness The idea of an artifact made conscious is an ancient theme of mythology appearing for example in the Greek myth of Pygmalion who carved a statue that was magically brought to life and in medieval Jewish stories of the Golem a magically animated homunculus built of clay 165 However the possibility of actually constructing a conscious machine was probably first discussed by Ada Lovelace in a set of notes written in 1842 about the Analytical Engine invented by Charles Babbage a precursor never built to modern electronic computers Lovelace was essentially dismissive of the idea that a machine such as the Analytical Engine could think in a humanlike way She wrote It is desirable to guard against the possibility of exaggerated ideas that might arise as to the powers of the Analytical Engine The Analytical Engine has no pretensions whatever to originate anything It can do whatever we know how to order it to perform It can follow analysis but it has no power of anticipating any analytical relations or truths Its province is to assist us in making available what we are already acquainted with 166 One of the most influential contributions to this question was an essay written in 1950 by pioneering computer scientist Alan Turing titled Computing Machinery and Intelligence Turing disavowed any interest in terminology saying that even Can machines think is too loaded with spurious connotations to be meaningful but he proposed to replace all such questions with a specific operational test which has become known as the Turing test 167 To pass the test a computer must be able to imitate a human well enough to fool interrogators In his essay Turing discussed a variety of possible objections and presented a counterargument to each of them The Turing test is commonly cited in discussions of artificial intelligence as a proposed criterion for machine consciousness it has provoked a great deal of philosophical debate For example Daniel Dennett and Douglas Hofstadter argue that anything capable of passing the Turing test is necessarily conscious 168 while David Chalmers argues that a philosophical zombie could pass the test yet fail to be conscious 169 A third group of scholars have argued that with technological growth once machines begin to display any substantial signs of human like behavior then the dichotomy of human consciousness compared to human like consciousness becomes passe and issues of machine autonomy begin to prevail even as observed in its nascent form within contemporary industry and technology 57 58 Jurgen Schmidhuber argues that consciousness is the result of compression 170 As an agent sees representation of itself recurring in the environment the compression of this representation can be called consciousness John Searle in December 2005 In a lively exchange over what has come to be referred to as the Chinese room argument John Searle sought to refute the claim of proponents of what he calls strong artificial intelligence AI that a computer program can be conscious though he does agree with advocates of weak AI that computer programs can be formatted to simulate conscious states His own view is that consciousness has subjective first person causal powers by being essentially intentional due to the way human brains function biologically conscious persons can perform computations but consciousness is not inherently computational the way computer programs are To make a Turing machine that speaks Chinese Searle imagines a room with one monolingual English speaker Searle himself in fact a book that designates a combination of Chinese symbols to be output paired with Chinese symbol input and boxes filled with Chinese symbols In this case the English speaker is acting as a computer and the rulebook as a program Searle argues that with such a machine he would be able to process the inputs to outputs perfectly without having any understanding of Chinese nor having any idea what the questions and answers could possibly mean If the experiment were done in English since Searle knows English he would be able to take questions and give answers without any algorithms for English questions and he would be effectively aware of what was being said and the purposes it might serve Searle would pass the Turing test of answering the questions in both languages but he is only conscious of what he is doing when he speaks English Another way of putting the argument is to say that computer programs can pass the Turing test for processing the syntax of a language but that the syntax cannot lead to semantic meaning in the way strong AI advocates hoped 171 172 In the literature concerning artificial intelligence Searle s essay has been second only to Turing s in the volume of debate it has generated 173 Searle himself was vague about what extra ingredients it would take to make a machine conscious all he proposed was that what was needed was causal powers of the sort that the brain has and that computers lack But other thinkers sympathetic to his basic argument have suggested that the necessary though perhaps still not sufficient extra conditions may include the ability to pass not just the verbal version of the Turing test but the robotic version 174 which requires grounding the robot s words in the robot s sensorimotor capacity to categorize and interact with the things in the world that its words are about Turing indistinguishably from a real person Turing scale robotics is an empirical branch of research on embodied cognition and situated cognition 175 In 2014 Victor Argonov has suggested a non Turing test for machine consciousness based on machine s ability to produce philosophical judgments 176 He argues that a deterministic machine must be regarded as conscious if it is able to produce judgments on all problematic properties of consciousness such as qualia or binding having no innate preloaded philosophical knowledge on these issues no philosophical discussions while learning and no informational models of other creatures in its memory such models may implicitly or explicitly contain knowledge about these creatures consciousness However this test can be used only to detect but not refute the existence of consciousness A positive result proves that machine is conscious but a negative result proves nothing For example absence of philosophical judgments may be caused by lack of the machine s intellect not by absence of consciousness Stream of consciousness EditMain article Stream of consciousness psychology William James is usually credited with popularizing the idea that human consciousness flows like a stream in his Principles of Psychology of 1890 According to James the stream of thought is governed by five characteristics 177 Every thought tends to be part of a personal consciousness Within each personal consciousness thought is always changing Within each personal consciousness thought is sensibly continuous It always appears to deal with objects independent of itself It is interested in some parts of these objects to the exclusion of others A similar concept appears in Buddhist philosophy expressed by the Sanskrit term Citta saṃtana which is usually translated as mindstream or mental continuum Buddhist teachings describe that consciousness manifests moment to moment as sense impressions and mental phenomena that are continuously changing 178 The teachings list six triggers that can result in the generation of different mental events 178 These triggers are input from the five senses seeing hearing smelling tasting or touch sensations or a thought relating to the past present or the future that happen to arise in the mind The mental events generated as a result of these triggers are feelings perceptions and intentions behaviour The moment by moment manifestation of the mind stream is said to happen in every person all the time It even happens in a scientist who analyses various phenomena in the world or analyses the material body including the organ brain 178 The manifestation of the mindstream is also described as being influenced by physical laws biological laws psychological laws volitional laws and universal laws 178 The purpose of the Buddhist practice of mindfulness is to understand the inherent nature of the consciousness and its characteristics 179 Narrative form Edit In the West the primary impact of the idea has been on literature rather than science stream of consciousness as a narrative mode means writing in a way that attempts to portray the moment to moment thoughts and experiences of a character This technique perhaps had its beginnings in the monologues of Shakespeare s plays and reached its fullest development in the novels of James Joyce and Virginia Woolf although it has also been used by many other noted writers 180 Here for example is a passage from Joyce s Ulysses about the thoughts of Molly Bloom Yes because he never did a thing like that before as ask to get his breakfast in bed with a couple of eggs since the City Arms hotel when he used to be pretending to be laid up with a sick voice doing his highness to make himself interesting for that old faggot Mrs Riordan that he thought he had a great leg of and she never left us a farthing all for masses for herself and her soul greatest miser ever was actually afraid to lay out 4d for her methylated spirit telling me all her ailments she had too much old chat in her about politics and earthquakes and the end of the world let us have a bit of fun first God help the world if all the women were her sort down on bathingsuits and lownecks of course nobody wanted her to wear them I suppose she was pious because no man would look at her twice I hope Ill never be like her a wonder she didnt want us to cover our faces but she was a welleducated woman certainly and her gabby talk about Mr Riordan here and Mr Riordan there I suppose he was glad to get shut of her 181 Spiritual approaches EditFurther information Higher consciousness To most philosophers the word consciousness connotes the relationship between the mind and the world To writers on spiritual or religious topics it frequently connotes the relationship between the mind and God or the relationship between the mind and deeper truths that are thought to be more fundamental than the physical world The mystical psychiatrist Richard Maurice Bucke author of the 1901 book Cosmic Consciousness A Study in the Evolution of the Human Mind distinguished between three types of consciousness Simple Consciousness awareness of the body possessed by many animals Self Consciousness awareness of being aware possessed only by humans and Cosmic Consciousness awareness of the life and order of the universe possessed only by humans who are enlightened 182 Many more examples could be given such as the various levels of spiritual consciousness presented by Prem Saran Satsangi and Stuart Hameroff 183 Another thorough account of the spiritual approach is Ken Wilber s 1977 book The Spectrum of Consciousness a comparison of western and eastern ways of thinking about the mind Wilber described consciousness as a spectrum with ordinary awareness at one end and more profound types of awareness at higher levels 184 See also Edit Medicine portal Philosophy portalChaitanya consciousness Pure consciousness in Hindu philosophy Models of consciousness Ideas for a scientific mechanism underlying consciousness Plant perception paranormal A pseudoscientific theory Sakshi Witness Pure awareness in Hindu philosophy Vertiginous question On the uniqueness of a person s consciousness RealityReferences Edit consciousness Merriam Webster Retrieved June 4 2012 Jaynes Julian 2000 1976 The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind PDF Houghton Mifflin ISBN 0 618 05707 2 Archived from the original PDF on 2019 08 07 Retrieved 2019 10 16 Rochat Philippe 2003 Five levels of self awareness as they unfold early in life PDF Consciousness and Cognition 12 4 717 731 doi 10 1016 s1053 8100 03 00081 3 PMID 14656513 S2CID 10241157 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 P A Guertin 2019 A novel concept introducing the idea of continuously changing levels of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Exploration amp Research 10 6 406 412 Hacker P M S 2012 The Sad and Sorry History of Consciousness being among other things a challenge to the consciousness studies community PDF Royal Institute of Philosophy supplementary volume 70 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Cohen A P Rapport N 1995 Questions of Consciousness London Routledge ISBN 9781134804696 Guven Guzeldere 1997 Ned Block Owen Flanagan Guven Guzeldere eds The Nature of Consciousness Philosophical debates Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 1 67 J J Fins N D Schiff K M Foley 2007 Late recovery from the minimally conscious state ethical and policy implications Neurology 68 4 304 307 doi 10 1212 01 wnl 0000252376 43779 96 PMID 17242341 S2CID 32561349 Caston Victor 2002 Aristotle on Consciousness Mind PDF Oxford University Press p 751 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Locke John An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Chapter XXVII Australia University of Adelaide Archived from the original on May 8 2018 Retrieved August 20 2010 Science amp Technology consciousness Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved August 20 2010 Samuel Johnson 1756 A Dictionary of the English Language Knapton Jaucourt Louis chevalier de Consciousness The Encyclopedia of Diderot amp d Alembert Collaborative Translation Project Translated by Scott St Louis Ann Arbor Michigan Publishing University of Michigan Library 2014 Originally published as Conscience Encyclopedie ou Dictionnaire raisonne des sciences des arts et des metiers 3 902 Paris 1753 C S Lewis 1990 Ch 8 Conscience and conscious Studies in words Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 39831 2 Thomas Hobbes 1904 Leviathan or The Matter Forme amp Power of a Commonwealth Ecclesiasticall and Civill University Press p 39 ISBN 9783932392382 James Ussher Charles Richard Elrington 1613 The whole works Volume 2 Hodges and Smith p 417 Barbara Cassin 2014 Dictionary of Untranslatables A Philosophical Lexicon Princeton University Press p 176 ISBN 978 0 691 13870 1 G Molenaar 1969 Seneca s Use of the Term Conscientia Mnemosyne 22 2 170 180 doi 10 1163 156852569x00670 Boris Hennig 2007 Cartesian Conscientia British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 3 455 484 doi 10 1080 09608780701444915 S2CID 218603781 Charles Adam Paul Tannery eds Oeuvres de Descartes X 524 1908 Sara Heinamaa Vili Lahteenmaki Pauliina Remes eds 2007 Consciousness from perception to reflection in the history of philosophy Springer pp 205 206 ISBN 978 1 4020 6081 6 Vimal RLP Sansthana DA 2010 On the Quest of Defining Consciousness PDF Mind and Matter 8 1 93 121 CONSCIOUSNESS meaning in the Cambridge English Dictionary dictionary cambridge org consciousness Definition of consciousness in English by Oxford Dictionaries Oxford Dictionaries English Archived from the original on September 25 2016 Edward Craig 1998 Consciousness Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 18707 7 a b Stuart Sutherland 1989 Consciousness Macmillan Dictionary of Psychology Macmillan ISBN 978 0 333 38829 7 Thomas Garth J 1967 Consciousness Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 6 p 366 a b Michael V Antony 2001 Is consciousness ambiguous Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 19 44 Max Velmans 2009 How to define consciousness and how not to define consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 16 139 156 Anthis Jacy 2022 Consciousness Semanticism A Precise Eliminativist Theory of Consciousness Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures 2021 Studies in Computational Intelligence 1032 20 41 doi 10 1007 978 3 030 96993 6 3 ISBN 978 3 030 96992 9 Retrieved 7 August 2022 Justin Sytsma Edouard Machery 2010 Two conceptions of subjective experience PDF Philosophical Studies 151 2 299 327 doi 10 1007 s11098 009 9439 x S2CID 2444730 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Gilbert Ryle 1949 The Concept of Mind University of Chicago Press pp 156 163 ISBN 978 0 226 73296 1 Ned Block 1998 On a confusion about a function of consciousness In N Block O Flanagan G Guzeldere eds The Nature of Consciousness Philosophical Debates MIT Press pp 375 415 ISBN 978 0 262 52210 6 Daniel Dennett 2004 Consciousness Explained Penguin p 375 ISBN 978 0 7139 9037 9 David Chalmers 1995 Facing up to the problem of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 200 219 Archived from the original on 2005 03 08 William Lycan 1996 Consciousness and Experience MIT Press pp 1 4 ISBN 978 0 262 12197 2 Block N 1995 How many concepts of consciousness PDF Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 2 272 284 doi 10 1017 s0140525x00038486 S2CID 41023484 Archived from the original PDF on 2020 02 10 Harris S 12 October 2011 The mystery of consciousness Sam Harris https www samharris org blog the mystery of consciousness Tricker C 2022 The cicada and the bird The usefulness of a useless philosophy Chuang Tzu s ancient wisdom translated for modern life Page 52 Google Books Dy Manuel B Jr 2001 Philosophy of Man selected readings Goodwill Trading Co p 97 ISBN 978 971 12 0245 3 Descartes and the Pineal Gland Stanford University November 5 2008 Retrieved 2010 08 22 Gert Jan Lokhorst Edward N Zalta ed Descartes and the pineal gland Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition William Jaworski 2011 Philosophy of Mind A Comprehensive Introduction John Wiley and Sons pp 5 11 ISBN 978 1 4443 3367 1 Julien Offray de La Mettrie 1996 Ann Thomson ed Machine man and other writings Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 47849 6 Gerald Edelman 1993 Bright Air Brilliant Fire On the Matter of the Mind Basic Books ISBN 978 0 465 00764 6 Antonio Damasio 1999 The Feeling of What Happens Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness New York Harcourt Press ISBN 978 0 15 601075 7 Daniel Dennett 1991 Consciousness Explained Boston Little amp Company ISBN 978 0 316 18066 5 a b Christof Koch 2004 The Quest for Consciousness Englewood CO Roberts amp Company ISBN 978 0 9747077 0 9 Ron Sun and Stan Franklin Computational models of consciousness A taxonomy and some examples In P D Zelazo M Moscovitch and E Thompson eds The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness pp 151 174 Cambridge University Press New York 2007 Quantum Approaches to Consciousness Stanford University December 25 2011 Cai J Popescu S Briegel H 2010 Persistent dynamic entanglement from classical motion How bio molecular machines can generate non trivial quantum states Physical Review E 82 2 021921 arXiv 0809 4906 Bibcode 2010PhRvE 82b1921C doi 10 1103 PhysRevE 82 021921 PMID 20866851 S2CID 23336691 John Searle 1997 The Mystery of Consciousness The New York Review of Books pp 53 88 ISBN 978 0 940322 06 6 Rocco J Gennaro 2011 4 4 The hard problem of consciousness The Consciousness Paradox Consciousness Concepts and Higher Order Thoughts MIT Press p 75 ISBN 978 0 262 01660 5 Knobe J 2008 Can a Robot an Insect or God Be Aware Scientific American Mind 19 6 68 71 doi 10 1038 scientificamericanmind1208 68 Alec Hyslop 1995 Other Minds Springer pp 5 14 ISBN 978 0 7923 3245 9 Robert Kirk Edward N Zalta ed Zombies Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2009 Edition a b The Culture and Philosophy of Ridley Scott Greg Littmann pp 133 144 Lexington Books 2013 a b Moral Machines Wendell Wallach and Colin Allen 288 pages Oxford University Press USA June 3 2010 ISBN 0 19 973797 5 a b Alec Hyslop 1995 The analogical inference to other minds Other Minds Springer pp 41 70 ISBN 978 0 7923 3245 9 Daniel Dennett 1995 The unimagined preposterousness of zombies Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 322 325 Stevan Harnad 1995 Why and how we are not zombies Journal of Consciousness Studies 1 164 167 Horst Hendriks Jansen 1996 Catching ourselves in the act situated activity interactive emergence evolution and human thought Massachusetts Institute of Technology p 114 ISBN 978 0 262 08246 4 Mandler G Consciousness Respectable useful and probably necessary In R Solso Ed Information processing and cognition NJ LEA Science and Religion Forum 2021 Archived from the original on 2016 11 03 Mandler G Consciousness recovered Psychological functions and origins of thought Philadelphia John Benjamins 2002 Stuart Hameroff Alfred Kaszniak David Chalmers 1999 Preface Toward a Science of Consciousness III The Third Tucson Discussions and Debates MIT Press pp xix xx ISBN 978 0 262 58181 3 Bernard Baars 1993 A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness Cambridge University Press pp 15 18 ISBN 978 0 521 42743 2 Paul Rooks Jane Wilson 2000 Perception Theory Development and Organization Psychology Press pp 25 26 ISBN 978 0 415 19094 7 a b Thomas Schmidt Dirk Vorberg 2006 Criteria for unconscious cognition Three types of dissociation Perception and Psychophysics 68 3 489 504 doi 10 3758 bf03193692 PMID 16900839 a b Arnaud Destrebecqz Philippe Peigneux 2006 Methods for studying unconscious learning In Steven Laureys ed The Boundaries of Consciousness Neurobiology and Neuropathology Elsevier pp 69 80 ISBN 978 0 444 52876 6 Daniel Dennett 1992 Quining qualia In A Marcel E Bisiach eds Consciousness in Modern Science Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 852237 9 Retrieved 2011 10 31 Daniel Dennett 2003 Who s on first Heterophenomenology explained Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 19 30 David Chalmers 1996 Ch 3 Can consciousness be reductively explained The Conscious Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511789 9 a b J T Giacino C M Smart 2007 Recent advances in behavioral assessment of individuals with disorders of consciousness Current Opinion in Neurology 20 6 614 619 doi 10 1097 WCO 0b013e3282f189ef PMID 17992078 S2CID 7097163 Christof Koch October 2017 How to Make a Consciousness Meter Scientific American 317 5 28 33 Bibcode 2017SciAm 317e 28K doi 10 1038 scientificamerican1117 28 PMID 29565878 Patrick Haggard 2008 Human volition towards a neuroscience of will Nature Reviews Neuroscience 9 12 934 946 doi 10 1038 nrn2497 PMID 19020512 S2CID 1495720 Gordon Gallup 1970 Chimpanzees Self recognition Science 167 3914 86 87 Bibcode 1970Sci 167 86G doi 10 1126 science 167 3914 86 PMID 4982211 S2CID 145295899 David Edelman Anil Seth 2009 Animal consciousness a synthetic approach Trends in Neurosciences 32 9 476 484 doi 10 1016 j tins 2009 05 008 PMID 19716185 S2CID 13323524 Christof Koch 2004 The Quest for Consciousness Englewood CO Roberts amp Company pp 16 19 ISBN 978 0 9747077 0 9 Wolf Singer 2007 Binding by synchrony Scholarpedia 2 12 1657 Bibcode 2007SchpJ 2 1657S doi 10 4249 scholarpedia 1657 Rodolfo Llinas 2002 I of the vortex from neurons to self MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 62163 2 Koch The Quest for Consciousness pp 105 116 Baldauf D Desimone R 2014 04 25 Neural Mechanisms of Object Based Attention Science 344 6182 424 427 Bibcode 2014Sci 344 424B doi 10 1126 science 1247003 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 24763592 S2CID 34728448 Francis Crick Christof Koch 2003 A framework for consciousness PDF Nature Neuroscience 6 2 119 126 doi 10 1038 nn0203 119 PMID 12555104 S2CID 13960489 Archived from the original PDF on 2012 05 22 Koch The Quest for Consciousness pp 269 286 a b c Zhaoping Li 2019 10 01 A new framework for understanding vision from the perspective of the primary visual cortex Current Opinion in Neurobiology Computational Neuroscience 58 1 10 doi 10 1016 j conb 2019 06 001 ISSN 0959 4388 PMID 31271931 S2CID 195806018 a b Zhaoping Li 2020 07 30 The Flip Tilt Illusion Visible in Peripheral Vision as Predicted by the Central Peripheral Dichotomy i Perception 11 4 2041669520938408 doi 10 1177 2041669520938408 ISSN 2041 6695 PMC 7401056 PMID 32782769 Biederlack J Castelo Branco M Neuenschwander S Wheeler D W Singer W Nikolic D 2006 Brightness induction Rate enhancement and neuronal synchronization as complementary codes Neuron 52 6 1073 1083 doi 10 1016 j neuron 2006 11 012 PMID 17178409 S2CID 16732916 Williams Adrian L Singh Krishna D Smith Andrew T 2003 Surround modulation measured with functional MRI in the human visual cortex Journal of Neurophysiology 89 1 525 533 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 137 1066 doi 10 1152 jn 00048 2002 PMID 12522199 Adenauer G Casali Olivia Gosseries Mario Rosanova Melanie Boly Simone Sarasso Karina R Casali Silvia Casarotto Marie Aurelie Bruno Steven Laureys Giulio Tononi Marcello Massimini 14 August 2013 A Theoretically based index of consciousness independent of sensory processing and behavior Science Translational Medicine 5 198 198ra105 doi 10 1126 scitranslmed 3006294 hdl 2268 171542 PMID 23946194 S2CID 8686961 Ann B Butler Paul R Manger B I B Lindahl Peter Arhem 2005 Evolution of the neural basis of consciousness a bird mammal comparison BioEssays 27 9 923 936 doi 10 1002 bies 20280 PMID 16108067 a b Francis Crick and Christof Koch 1995 Are we aware of neural activity in primary visual cortex Nature 375 6527 121 123 Bibcode 1995Natur 375 121C doi 10 1038 375121a0 PMID 7753166 S2CID 4262990 a b c Gerald M Edelman and Giulio Tononi 2000 A Universe of Consciousness How Matter Becomes Imagination Basic Books ISBN 978 0 465 01376 0 a b Rodney M J Cotterill 2001 Cooperation of the basal ganglia cerebellum sensory cerebrum and hippocampus possible implications for cognition consciousness intelligence and creativity Progress in Neurobiology 64 1 1 33 doi 10 1016 s0301 0082 00 00058 7 PMID 11250060 S2CID 206054149 J C Eccles 1982 Animal consciousness and human self consciousness Experientia 38 12 1384 1391 doi 10 1007 bf01955747 PMID 7151952 S2CID 35174442 John Eccles 1990 A unitary hypothesis of mind brain interaction in the cerebral cortex Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 240 1299 433 451 Bibcode 1990RSPSB 240 433E doi 10 1098 rspb 1990 0047 PMID 2165613 S2CID 23188208 Joaquin Fuster The Prefrontal Cortex Second Edition Fischer David B Boes Aaron D Demertzi Athena Evrard Henry C Laureys Steven Edlow Brian L Liu Hesheng Saper Clifford B Pascual Leone Alvaro Fox Michael D Geerling Joel C 2016 12 06 A human brain network derived from coma causing brainstem lesions Neurology 87 23 2427 2434 doi 10 1212 WNL 0000000000003404 ISSN 0028 3878 PMC 5177681 PMID 27815400 Northoff Georg Lamme Victor 2020 Neural signs and mechanisms of consciousness Is there a potential convergence of theories of consciousness in sight Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 118 568 587 doi 10 1016 j neubiorev 2020 07 019 PMID 32783969 S2CID 221084519 a b Seth Anil K Bayne Tim 2022 Theories of consciousness PDF Nature Reviews Neuroscience 23 7 439 452 doi 10 1038 s41583 022 00587 4 PMID 35505255 S2CID 242810797 a b Doerig Adrian Schurger Aaron Herzog Michael H 2021 Hard criteria for empirical theories of consciousness Cognitive Neuroscience 12 2 41 62 doi 10 1080 17588928 2020 1772214 PMID 32663056 S2CID 220529998 Michael Brooks Interview Cosmic thoughts New Scientist November 2022 pp 46 9 Graziano M S A Kastner S 2011 Human consciousness and its relationship to social neuroscience A novel hypothesis Cog Neurosci 2 2 98 113 doi 10 1080 17588928 2011 565121 PMC 3223025 PMID 22121395 Carhart Harris R L Friston K J Barker Eric L 20 June 2019 REBUS and the Anarchic Brain Toward a Unified Model of the Brain Action of Psychedelics Pharmacological Reviews 71 3 316 344 doi 10 1124 pr 118 017160 PMC 6588209 PMID 31221820 Carhart Harris Robin L November 2018 The entropic brain revisited Neuropharmacology 142 167 178 doi 10 1016 j neuropharm 2018 03 010 PMID 29548884 S2CID 4483591 Carhart Harris Robin L Leech Robert Hellyer Peter J Shanahan Murray Feilding Amanda Tagliazucchi Enzo Chialvo Dante R Nutt David 2014 The entropic brain a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8 20 doi 10 3389 fnhum 2014 00020 PMC 3909994 PMID 24550805 Entropy as More than Chaos in the Brain Expanding Field Expanding Minds 2018 06 22 Papo David 30 August 2016 Commentary The entropic brain a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10 423 doi 10 3389 fnhum 2016 00423 PMC 5004455 PMID 27624312 David Rudrauf Daniel Bennequin Isabela Granic Gregory Landini Karl Friston Kenneth Williford 2017 A Mathematical Model of Embodied Consciousness Journal of Theoretical Biology 428 1 106 131 Bibcode 2017JThBi 428 106R doi 10 1016 j jtbi 2017 05 032 PMID 28554611 Peter Arhem B I B Lindahl Paul R Manger Ann B Butler 2008 On the origin of consciousness some amniote scenarios In Hans Liljenstrom Peter Arhem eds Consciousness Transitions Phylogenetic Ontogenetic and Physiological Aspects Elsevier ISBN 978 0 444 52977 0 a b Feinberg TE Mallatt J October 2013 The evolutionary and genetic origins of consciousness in the Cambrian Period over 500 million years ago Frontiers in Psychology 4 667 doi 10 3389 fpsyg 2013 00667 PMC 3790330 PMID 24109460 a b Donald Griffin 2001 Animal Minds Beyond Cognition to Consciousness University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 30865 4 T H Huxley 1874 On the hypothesis that animals are automata and its history The Fortnightly Review 16 253 555 580 Bibcode 1874Natur 10 362 doi 10 1038 010362a0 W James 1879 Are we automata Mind 4 13 1 22 doi 10 1093 mind os 4 13 1 B I B Lindahl 1997 Consciousness and biological evolution Journal of Theoretical Biology 187 4 613 629 Bibcode 1997JThBi 187 613L doi 10 1006 jtbi 1996 0394 PMID 9299304 Karl R Popper John C Eccles 1977 The Self and Its Brain Springer International ISBN 978 0 387 08307 0 Bernard Baars January 2002 The conscious access hypothesis Origins and recent evidence Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6 1 47 52 doi 10 1016 S1364 6613 00 01819 2 PMID 11849615 S2CID 6386902 Seth Anil Eugene Izhikevich George Reeke Gerald Edelman 2006 Theories and measures of consciousness An extended framework Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 103 28 10799 10804 Bibcode 2006PNAS 10310799S doi 10 1073 pnas 0604347103 PMC 1487169 PMID 16818879 a b Ezequiel Morsella 2005 The function of phenomenal states Supramodular Interaction Theory PDF Psychological Review 112 4 1000 1021 doi 10 1037 0033 295X 112 4 1000 PMID 16262477 S2CID 2298524 Archived from the original PDF on 2020 11 18 S Budiansky 1998 If a Lion Could Talk Animal Intelligence and the Evolution of Consciousness The Free Press ISBN 978 0 684 83710 9 S Nichols T Grantham 2000 Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness PDF Philosophy of Science 67 4 648 670 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 515 9722 doi 10 1086 392859 S2CID 16484193 Archived from the original PDF on 2017 08 13 Retrieved 2017 10 25 John Eccles 1992 Evolution of consciousness Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 89 16 7320 7324 Bibcode 1992PNAS 89 7320E doi 10 1073 pnas 89 16 7320 PMC 49701 PMID 1502142 Bernard Baars 1993 A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 42743 2 Carruthers Peter 2004 Phenomenal Consciousness A Naturalistic Theory Cambridge Cambridge University Press Owen Flanagan T W Polger 1995 Zombies and the function of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 313 321 Rosenthal David 2008 Consciousness and its function Neuropsychologia 46 3 829 840 doi 10 1016 j neuropsychologia 2007 11 012 PMID 18164042 S2CID 7791431 Stevan Harnad 2002 Turing indistinguishability and the Blind Watchmaker In J H Fetzer ed Consciousness Evolving John Benjamins Retrieved 2011 10 26 Zack Robinson Corey J Maley Gualtiero Piccinini 2015 Is Consciousness a Spandrel Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 2 365 383 doi 10 1017 apa 2014 10 S2CID 170892645 a b Vaitl Dieter 2005 Psychobiology of altered states of consciousness PDF Psychological Bulletin 131 1 98 127 doi 10 1037 0033 2909 131 1 98 PMID 15631555 S2CID 6909813 Archived from the original PDF on 2020 10 22 Schacter Daniel Gilbert Daniel Wegner Daniel 2011 Psychology 2nd Ed New York Worth Publishers p 190 ISBN 978 1 4292 3719 2 Retrieved 27 October 2020 Coenen Anton 2010 Subconscious Stimulus Recognition and Processing During Sleep PDF Psyche 16 2 Archived PDF from the original on 2017 06 11 Hobson J Allan Pace Schott Edward F Stickgold Robert 2003 Dreaming and the brain Toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states In Pace Schott Edward F Solms Mark Blagrove Mark Harnad Stevan eds Sleep and Dreaming Scientific Advances and Reconsiderations Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 00869 3 Archived PDF from the original on 2021 08 10 Johanson M Valli K Revonsuo A Wedlund J 2008 Content analysis of subjective experiences in partial epileptic seizures Epilepsy amp Behavior 12 1 170 182 doi 10 1016 j yebeh 2007 10 002 PMID 18086461 S2CID 28276470 Johanson M Valli K Revonsuo A et al 2008 Alterations in the contents of consciousness in partial epileptic seizures Epilepsy amp Behavior 13 2 366 371 doi 10 1016 j yebeh 2008 04 014 PMID 18522873 S2CID 24473529 a b Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders DSM IV DSM IV TR ed Washington DC American Psychiatric Association 31 July 1994 ISBN 978 0 89042 025 6 Lyvers Michael 2003 The neurochemistry of psychedelic experiences PDF ePublications bond M Murphy S Donovan E Taylor 1997 The Physical and Psychological Effects of Meditation A Review of Contemporary Research With a Comprehensive Bibliography 1931 1996 Institute of Noetic Sciences Tart Charles 2001 Ch 2 The components of consciousness States of Consciousness IUniverse com ISBN 978 0 595 15196 7 Retrieved 5 October 2011 Studerus Erich Gamma Alex Vollenweider Franz X 2010 Bell Vaughan ed Psychometric evaluation of the altered states of consciousness rating scale OAV PLOS One 5 8 e12412 Bibcode 2010PLoSO 512412S doi 10 1371 journal pone 0012412 PMC 2930851 PMID 20824211 a b c Hal Blumenfeld 2009 The neurological examination of consciousness In Steven Laureys Giulio Tononi eds The Neurology of Consciousness Cognitive Neuroscience and Neuropathology Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 374168 4 Kinney HC Korein J Panigrahy A Dikkes P Goode R 26 May 1994 Neuropathological findings in the brain of Karen Ann Quinlan the role of the thalamus in the persistent vegetative state PDF N Engl J Med 330 21 1469 1475 doi 10 1056 NEJM199405263302101 PMID 8164698 S2CID 5112573 Archived from the original PDF on 18 November 2020 Koch The Quest for Consciousness pp 216 226 V Mark Durand David H Barlow 2009 Essentials of Abnormal Psychology Cengage Learning pp 74 75 ISBN 978 0 495 59982 1 Note A patient who can additionally describe the current situation may be referred to as oriented times four Neergaard Lauren August 14 2013 New tool peeks into brain to measure consciousness Associated Press through NBC News Archived from the original on August 16 2013 Retrieved March 2 2022 a b c Bernat JL 8 Apr 2006 Chronic disorders of consciousness Lancet 367 9517 1181 1192 doi 10 1016 S0140 6736 06 68508 5 PMID 16616561 S2CID 13550675 Bernat JL 20 Jul 2010 The natural history of chronic disorders of consciousness Neurology 75 3 206 207 doi 10 1212 WNL 0b013e3181e8e960 PMID 20554939 S2CID 30959964 Coleman MR Davis MH Rodd JM Robson T Ali A Owen AM Pickard JD September 2009 Towards the routine use of brain imaging to aid the clinical diagnosis of disorders of consciousness Brain 132 9 2541 2552 doi 10 1093 brain awp183 PMID 19710182 Monti MM Vanhaudenhuyse A Coleman MR Boly M Pickard JD Tshibanda L Owen AM Laureys S 18 Feb 2010 Willful modulation of brain activity in disorders of consciousness PDF N Engl J Med 362 7 579 589 doi 10 1056 NEJMoa0905370 PMID 20130250 S2CID 13358991 Archived from the original PDF on 24 February 2019 Seel RT Sherer M Whyte J Katz DI Giacino JT Rosenbaum AM Hammond FM Kalmar K Pape TL et al December 2010 Assessment scales for disorders of consciousness evidence based recommendations for clinical practice and research Arch Phys Med Rehabil 91 12 1795 1813 doi 10 1016 j apmr 2010 07 218 PMID 21112421 Prigatano George P 2009 Anosognosia clinical and ethical considerations Current Opinion in Neurology 22 6 606 611 doi 10 1097 WCO 0b013e328332a1e7 PMID 19809315 S2CID 40751848 George P Prigatano Daniel Schacter 1991 Introduction In George Prigatano Daniel Schacter eds Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury Clinical and Theoretical Issues Oxford University Press pp 3 16 ISBN 978 0 19 505941 0 Kenneth M Heilman 1991 Anosognosia possible neuropsychological mechanisms In George Prigatano Daniel Schacter eds Awareness of Deficit After Brain Injury Clinical and Theoretical Issues Oxford University Press pp 53 62 ISBN 978 0 19 505941 0 Arnold J Sameroff Marshall M Haith eds 1996 The Five to Seven Year Shift The Age of Reason and Responsibility Chicago University of Chicago Press Foulkes David 1999 Children s Dreaming and the Development of Consciousness Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press p 13 In defining consciousness as a self reflective act psychology loses much of the glamour and mystery of other areas of consciousness study but it also can proceed on a workaday basis without becoming paralyzed in pure abstraction Nelson Katherine Fivush Robin 2020 The Development of Autobiographical Memory Autobiographical Narratives and Autobiographical Consciousness Psychological Reports 123 1 74 doi 10 1177 0033294119852574 PMID 31142189 S2CID 169038149 Jaynes Julian 2000 1976 The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind Houghton Mifflin p 447 ISBN 0 618 05707 2 Consciousness is based on language Consciousness is not the same as cognition and should be sharply distinguished from it Jaynes Julian 2000 1976 The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind Houghton Mifflin p 450 ISBN 0 618 05707 2 The basic connotative definition of consciousness is thus an analog I narratizing in a functional mind space The denotative definition is as it was for Descartes Locke and Hume what is introspectable Nelson Katherine Fivush Robin 2020 The Development of Autobiographical Memory Autobiographical Narratives and Autobiographical Consciousness Psychological Reports 123 1 80 83 doi 10 1177 0033294119852574 PMID 31142189 S2CID 169038149 a b Colin Allen Edward N Zalta ed Animal consciousness Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition Peter Carruthers 1999 Sympathy and subjectivity Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 4 465 482 doi 10 1080 00048409912349231 Thomas Nagel 1991 Ch 12 What is it like to be a bat Mortal Questions Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 40676 5 Douglas Hofstadter 1981 Reflections on What Is It Like to Be a Bat In Douglas Hofstadter Daniel Dennett eds The Mind s I Basic Books pp 403 414 ISBN 978 0 7108 0352 8 Animal Consciousness Officially Recognized by Leading Panel of Neuroscientists 3 September 2012 Archived from the original on 2021 10 28 via YouTube Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Moshe Idel 1990 Golem Jewish Magical and Mystical Traditions on the Artificial Anthropoid SUNY Press ISBN 978 0 7914 0160 6 Note In many stories the Golem was mindless but some gave it emotions or thoughts Ada Lovelace Sketch of The Analytical Engine Note G Stuart Shieber 2004 The Turing Test Verbal Behavior as the Hallmark of Intelligence MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 69293 9 Daniel Dennett Douglas Hofstadter 1985 The Mind s I Basic Books ISBN 978 0 553 34584 1 David Chalmers 1997 The Conscious Mind In Search of a Fundamental Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511789 9 Jurgen Schmidhuber 2009 Driven by Compression Progress A Simple Principle Explains Essential Aspects of Subjective Beauty Novelty Surprise Interestingness Attention Curiosity Creativity Art Science Music Jokes arXiv 0812 4360 Bibcode 2008arXiv0812 4360S John R Searle 1990 Is the brain s mind a computer program PDF Scientific American 262 1 26 31 Bibcode 1990SciAm 262a 26S doi 10 1038 scientificamerican0190 26 PMID 2294583 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 The Chinese Room Argument Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 John Searle et al 1980 Minds brains and programs Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 3 417 457 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 83 5248 doi 10 1017 S0140525X00005756 S2CID 55303721 Graham Oppy David Dowe 2011 The Turing test Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2011 Edition Margaret Wilson 2002 Six views of embodied cognition Psychonomic Bulletin amp Review 9 4 625 636 doi 10 3758 BF03196322 PMID 12613670 Victor Argonov 2014 Experimental Methods for Unraveling the Mind body Problem The Phenomenal Judgment Approach Journal of Mind and Behavior 35 51 70 William James 1890 The Principles of Psychology Volume 1 H Holt p 225 a b c d Karunamuni N D May 2015 The Five Aggregate Model of the Mind SAGE Open 5 2 215824401558386 doi 10 1177 2158244015583860 Dzogchen Rinpoche 2007 Taming the mindstream In Doris Wolter ed Losing the Clouds Gaining the Sky Buddhism and the Natural Mind Wisdom Publications pp 81 92 ISBN 978 0 86171 359 2 Robert Humphrey 1954 Stream of Consciousness in the Modern Novel University of California Press pp 23 49 ISBN 978 0 520 00585 3 James Joyce 1990 Ulysses BompaCrazy com p 620 Richard Maurice Bucke 1905 Cosmic Consciousness A Study in the Evolution of the Human Mind Innes amp Sons pp 1 2 Satsangi Prem Saran and Hameroff Stuart 2016 Consciousness Integrating Eastern and Western Perspectives New Age Books ISBN 978 81 7822 493 0 Ken Wilber 2002 The Spectrum of Consciousness Motilal Banarsidass pp 3 16 ISBN 978 81 208 1848 4 Further reading EditChalmers David 1996 The Conscious Mind In Search of a Fundamental Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511789 9 Dehaene Stanislas 2014 Consciousness and the Brain Deciphering How the Brain Codes Our Thoughts Viking Press ISBN 978 0670025435 Dennett Daniel 1991 Consciousness Explained Little Brown and Company ISBN 9780316439480 Frankish Keith 2021 Consciousness The Basics Routledge ISBN 9781138655980 Harley Trevor 2021 The Science of Consciousness Waking Sleeping and Dreaming Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 9781316408889 ISBN 978 1 107 56330 8 S2CID 233977060 Irvine Elizabeth 2013 Consciousness as a Scientific Concept A Philosophy of Science Perspective Dordrecht Netherlands Springer doi 10 1007 978 94 007 5173 6 ISBN 978 94 007 5172 9 Koch Christof 2019 The Feeling of Life Itself Why Consciousness Is Widespread but Can t Be Computed MIT Press ISBN 9780262042819 Overgaard Morten Mogensen Jesper Kirkeby Hinrup Asger eds 2021 Beyond Neural Correlates of Consciousness Routledge ISBN 9781138637986 Prinz Jesse 2012 The Conscious Brain How Attention Engenders Experience Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780195314595 001 0001 ISBN 9780195314595 Schneider Susan Velmans Max eds 2017 The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness 2nd ed Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 0 470 67406 2 Seth Anil 2021 Being You A New Science of Consciousness Penguin Random House ISBN 9781524742874 Thompson Evan 2014 Waking Dreaming Being Self and Consciousness in Neuroscience Meditation and Philosophy Columbia University Press ISBN 9780231136952 Zelazo Philip David Moscovitch Morris Thompson Evan eds 2007 The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 CBO9780511816789 ISBN 978 0 521 67412 6 External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Consciousness Wikimedia Commons has media related to Consciousness The dictionary definition of consciousness at Wiktionary Consciousness Studies at Wikibooks Gulick Robert Van Consciousness In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Consciousness Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Consciousness amp oldid 1153023358, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.