fbpx
Wikipedia

Understanding

Understanding is a psychological process related to an abstract or physical object, such as a person, situation, or message whereby one is able to use concepts to model that object. Understanding is a relation between the knower and an object of understanding. Understanding implies abilities and dispositions with respect to an object of knowledge that are sufficient to support intelligent behavior.[1]

Understanding is often, though not always, related to learning concepts, and sometimes also the theory or theories associated with those concepts. However, a person may have a good ability to predict the behavior of an object, animal or system—and therefore may, in some sense, understand it—without necessarily being familiar with the concepts or theories associated with that object, animal, or system in their culture. They may have developed their own distinct concepts and theories, which may be equivalent, better or worse than the recognized standard concepts and theories of their culture. Thus, understanding is correlated with the ability to make inferences.

Definition

Understanding and knowledge are both words without unified definitions [2][3] so Ludwig Wittgenstein looked past a definition of knowledge or understanding and looked at how the words were used in natural language, identifying relevant features in context. [4] It has been suggested that knowledge alone has little value whereas knowing something in context is understanding, [5] which has much higher relative value but it has also been suggested that a state short of knowledge can be termed understanding. [6][7]

Someone's understanding can come from perceived causes [8] or non causal sources, [9] suggesting knowledge being a pillar of where understanding comes from.[10] We can have understanding while lacking corresponding knowledge and have knowledge while lacking the corresponding understanding. [11] Even with knowledge, relevant distinctions or correct conclusion about similar cases may not be made [12][13] suggesting more information about the context would be required, which eludes to different degrees of understanding depending on the context. [10] To understand something implies abilities and dispositions with respect to an object of knowledge that are sufficient to support intelligent behavior. [14]

Understanding could therefore be less demanding than knowledge, because it seems that someone can have understanding of a subject even though they might have been mistaken about that subject. But it is more demanding in that it requires that the internal connections among ones’ beliefs actually be “seen” or “grasped” by the person doing the understanding when found at a deeper level. [10]

Explanatory realism and the propositional model suggests understanding comes from causal propositions [15] but, it has been argued that knowing how the cause might bring an effect is understanding. [16] As understanding is not directed towards a discrete proposition, but involves grasping relations of parts to other parts and perhaps the relations of part to wholes. [17] The relationships grasped helps understanding, but the relationships aren't always causal. [18] So understanding could therefore be expressed by knowledge of dependencies. [16]

Examples

  1. One understands the weather if one is able to predict (e.g. if it is very cloudy, it may rain) and/or give an explanation of some of its features, etc.
  2. A psychiatrist understands another person's anxieties if he/she knows that person's anxieties, their causes, and can give useful advice on how to cope with the anxiety.
  3. One understands a piece of reasoning or an argument if one can consciously reproduce the information content conveyed by the message.
  4. One understands a language to the extent that one can reproduce the information content conveyed by a broad range of spoken utterances or written messages in that language.

Shallow and deep

Someone who has a more sophisticated understanding, more predictively accurate understanding, and/or an understanding that allows them to make explanations that others commonly judge to be better, of something, is said to understand that thing "deeply". Conversely, someone who has a more limited understanding of a thing is said to have a "shallow" understanding. However, the depth of understanding required to usefully participate in an occupation or activity may vary greatly.

For example, consider multiplication of integers. Starting from the most shallow level of understanding, we have (at least) the following possibilities:

  1. A small child may not understand what multiplication is, but may understand that it is a type of mathematics that they will learn when they are older at school. This is "understanding of context"; being able to put an as-yet not-understood concept into some kind of context. Even understanding that a concept is not part of one's current knowledge is, in itself, a type of understanding (see the Dunning–Kruger effect, which is about people who do not have a good understanding of what they do not know).
  2. A slightly older child may understand that multiplication of two integers can be done, at least when the numbers are between 1 and 12, by looking up the two numbers in a times table. They may also be able to memorise and recall the relevant times table in order to answer a multiplication question such as "2 times 4 is what?". This is a simple form of operational understanding; understanding a question well enough to be able to do the operations necessary to be able to find an answer.
  3. A yet older child may understand that multiplication of larger numbers can be done using a different method, such as long multiplication, or using a calculator. This is a more advanced form of operational understanding because it supports answering a wider range of questions of the same type.
  4. A teenager may understand that multiplication is repeated addition, but not understand the broader implications of this. For example, when their teacher refers to multiplying 6 by 3 as "adding up 3 sixes", they may understand that the teacher is talking about two entirely equivalent things. However, they might not understand how to apply this knowledge to implement multiplication as an algorithm on a computer using only addition and looping as basic constructs. This level of understanding is "understanding a definition" (or "understanding the definition" when a concept only has one definition).
  5. A teenager may also understand the mathematical idea of abstracting over individual whole numbers as variables, and how to efficiently (i.e. not via trial-and-error) solve algebraic equations involving multiplication by such variables, such as  . This is "relational understanding"; understanding how multiplication relates to division.
  6. An undergraduate studying mathematics may come to learn that "the integers equipped with multiplication" is merely one example of a range of mathematical structures called monoids, and that theorems about monoids apply equally well to multiplication and other types of monoids.

For the purpose of operating a cash register at McDonald's, a person does not need a very deep understanding of the multiplication involved in calculating the total price of two Big Macs. However, for the purpose of contributing to number theory research, a person would need to have a relatively deep understanding of multiplication — along with other relevant arithmetical concepts such as division and prime numbers.

Assessment

It is possible for a person, or a piece of "intelligent" software, that in reality only has a shallow understanding of a topic, to appear to have a deeper understanding than they actually do, when the right questions are asked of it. The most obvious way this can happen is by memorization of correct answers to known questions, but there are other, more subtle ways that a person or computer can (intentionally or otherwise) deceive somebody about their level of understanding, too. This is particularly a risk with artificial intelligence, in which the ability of a piece of artificial intelligence software to very quickly try out millions of possibilities (attempted solutions, theories, etc.) could create a misleading impression of the real depth of its understanding. Supposed AI software could in fact come up with impressive answers to questions that were difficult for unaided humans to answer, without really understanding the concepts at all, simply by dumbly applying rules very quickly. (However, see the Chinese room argument for a controversial philosophical extension of this argument.)

Examinations are designed to assess students' understanding (and sometimes also other things such as knowledge and writing abilities) without falling prey to these risks. They do this partly by asking multiple different questions about a topic to reduce the risk of measurement error, and partly by forbidding access to reference works and the outside world to reduce the risk of someone else's understanding being passed off as one's own. Because of the faster and more accurate computation and memorization abilities of computers, such tests would arguably often have to be modified if they were to be used to accurately assess the understanding of an artificial intelligence.

Conversely, it is even easier for a person or artificial intelligence to fake a shallower level of understanding than they actually have; they simply need to respond with the same kind of answers that someone with a more limited understanding, or no understanding, would respond with — such as "I don't know", or obviously wrong answers. This is relevant for judges in Turing tests; it is unlikely to be effective to simply ask the respondents to mentally calculate the answer to a very difficult arithmetical question, because the computer is likely to simply dumb itself down and pretend not to know the answer.

As a model

Gregory Chaitin, a noted computer scientist, propounds a view that comprehension is a kind of data compression.[19] In his essay "The Limits of Reason", he argues that understanding something means being able to figure out a simple set of rules that explains it. For example, we understand why day and night exist because we have a simple model—the rotation of the earth—that explains a tremendous amount of data—changes in brightness, temperature, and atmospheric composition of the earth. We have compressed a large amount of information by using a simple model that predicts it. Similarly, we understand the number 0.33333... by thinking of it as one-third. The first way of representing the number requires five concepts ("0", "decimal point", "3", "infinity", "infinity of 3"); but the second way can produce all the data of the first representation, but uses only three concepts ("1", "division", "3"). Chaitin argues that comprehension is this ability to compress data.

Religious perspectives

Cognition helps us gain knowledge which can affect our level of understanding or 'right view' as expressed in buddhism. Understanding also is seen in the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit helping an individual with their insight into God's providence.

See also

References

  1. ^ Bereiter, Carl. . Archived from the original on 2006-02-25.
  2. ^ Zagzebski, Linda (2017), "What is Knowledge?", The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, pp. 92–116, doi:10.1002/9781405164863.ch3, ISBN 978-1-4051-6486-3, S2CID 158886670, retrieved 2021-11-28
  3. ^ Târziu, Gabriel (2021-04-01). "How Do We Obtain Understanding with the Help of Explanations?". Axiomathes. 31 (2): 173–197. doi:10.1007/s10516-020-09488-6. ISSN 1572-8390. S2CID 218947045.
  4. ^ Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty, remark 42
  5. ^ Pritchard, Duncan (2008-08-12). "Knowing the Answer, Understanding and Epistemic Value". Grazer Philosophische Studien. 77 (1): 325–339. doi:10.1163/18756735-90000852. hdl:20.500.11820/522fbeba-15b2-46d0-8019-4647e795642c. ISSN 1875-6735.
  6. ^ Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (2003-08-21). The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-44228-2.
  7. ^ Elgin, Catherine Z. (2017-09-29). True Enough. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-03653-5.
  8. ^ Lipton, Peter (2003-10-04). Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-54827-9.
  9. ^ Kitcher, Philip (1985-11-01). "Two Approaches to Explanation". The Journal of Philosophy. 82 (11): 632–639. doi:10.2307/2026419. JSTOR 2026419.
  10. ^ a b c Grimm, Stephen R. (2014), Fairweather, Abrol (ed.), "Understanding as Knowledge of Causes", Virtue Epistemology Naturalized: Bridges Between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, Synthese Library, Cham: Springer International Publishing, vol. 366, pp. 329–345, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-04672-3_19, ISBN 978-3-319-04672-3, retrieved 2021-11-28
  11. ^ Pritchard, Duncan (2009). "Knowledge, Understanding and Epistemic Value". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements. 64: 19–43. doi:10.1017/S1358246109000046. hdl:20.500.11820/0ef91ebb-b9f0-44e9-88d6-08afe5e96cc0. ISSN 1755-3555. S2CID 170647127.
  12. ^ Hills, Alison (2009-10-01). "Moral Testimony and Moral Epistemology". Ethics. 120 (1): 94–127. doi:10.1086/648610. ISSN 0014-1704. S2CID 144361023.
  13. ^ Hills, Alison (2010-04-29). The Beloved Self: Morality and the Challenge from Egoism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-921330-6.
  14. ^ Bereiter, Carl (2005-04-11). Education and Mind in the Knowledge Age. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-64479-6.
  15. ^ Kim, Jaegwon (1994). "Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence". Philosophical Issues. 5: 51–69. doi:10.2307/1522873. ISSN 1533-6077. JSTOR 1522873.
  16. ^ a b Grimm, Stephen R. (2014), Fairweather, Abrol (ed.), "Understanding as Knowledge of Causes", Virtue Epistemology Naturalized: Bridges Between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, Synthese Library, Cham: Springer International Publishing, vol. 366, pp. 329–345, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-04672-3_19, ISBN 978-3-319-04672-3, retrieved 2021-11-28
  17. ^ Zagzebski, Linda (2008-07-08). On Epistemology. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-534-25234-2.
  18. ^ Ruben, David-Hillel; Ruben, Director of New York University in London and Professor of Philosophy at the School of Oriental and African Studies David-Hillel (2003). Action and Its Explanation. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-823588-0.
  19. ^ Chaitin, Gregory (2006), (PDF), Scientific American, 294 (3): 74–81, Bibcode:2006SciAm.294c..74C, doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0306-74, PMID 16502614, archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-03-04

External links

understanding, this, article, about, psychological, process, other, uses, disambiguation, understand, redirects, here, other, uses, understand, disambiguation, psychological, process, related, abstract, physical, object, such, person, situation, message, where. This article is about the psychological process For other uses see Understanding disambiguation Understand redirects here For other uses see Understand disambiguation Understanding is a psychological process related to an abstract or physical object such as a person situation or message whereby one is able to use concepts to model that object Understanding is a relation between the knower and an object of understanding Understanding implies abilities and dispositions with respect to an object of knowledge that are sufficient to support intelligent behavior 1 Understanding is often though not always related to learning concepts and sometimes also the theory or theories associated with those concepts However a person may have a good ability to predict the behavior of an object animal or system and therefore may in some sense understand it without necessarily being familiar with the concepts or theories associated with that object animal or system in their culture They may have developed their own distinct concepts and theories which may be equivalent better or worse than the recognized standard concepts and theories of their culture Thus understanding is correlated with the ability to make inferences Contents 1 Definition 2 Examples 3 Shallow and deep 4 Assessment 5 As a model 6 Religious perspectives 7 See also 8 References 9 External linksDefinition EditUnderstanding and knowledge are both words without unified definitions 2 3 so Ludwig Wittgenstein looked past a definition of knowledge or understanding and looked at how the words were used in natural language identifying relevant features in context 4 It has been suggested that knowledge alone has little value whereas knowing something in context is understanding 5 which has much higher relative value but it has also been suggested that a state short of knowledge can be termed understanding 6 7 Someone s understanding can come from perceived causes 8 or non causal sources 9 suggesting knowledge being a pillar of where understanding comes from 10 We can have understanding while lacking corresponding knowledge and have knowledge while lacking the corresponding understanding 11 Even with knowledge relevant distinctions or correct conclusion about similar cases may not be made 12 13 suggesting more information about the context would be required which eludes to different degrees of understanding depending on the context 10 To understand something implies abilities and dispositions with respect to an object of knowledge that are sufficient to support intelligent behavior 14 Understanding could therefore be less demanding than knowledge because it seems that someone can have understanding of a subject even though they might have been mistaken about that subject But it is more demanding in that it requires that the internal connections among ones beliefs actually be seen or grasped by the person doing the understanding when found at a deeper level 10 Explanatory realism and the propositional model suggests understanding comes from causal propositions 15 but it has been argued that knowing how the cause might bring an effect is understanding 16 As understanding is not directed towards a discrete proposition but involves grasping relations of parts to other parts and perhaps the relations of part to wholes 17 The relationships grasped helps understanding but the relationships aren t always causal 18 So understanding could therefore be expressed by knowledge of dependencies 16 Examples EditOne understands the weather if one is able to predict e g if it is very cloudy it may rain and or give an explanation of some of its features etc A psychiatrist understands another person s anxieties if he she knows that person s anxieties their causes and can give useful advice on how to cope with the anxiety One understands a piece of reasoning or an argument if one can consciously reproduce the information content conveyed by the message One understands a language to the extent that one can reproduce the information content conveyed by a broad range of spoken utterances or written messages in that language Shallow and deep EditSomeone who has a more sophisticated understanding more predictively accurate understanding and or an understanding that allows them to make explanations that others commonly judge to be better of something is said to understand that thing deeply Conversely someone who has a more limited understanding of a thing is said to have a shallow understanding However the depth of understanding required to usefully participate in an occupation or activity may vary greatly For example consider multiplication of integers Starting from the most shallow level of understanding we have at least the following possibilities A small child may not understand what multiplication is but may understand that it is a type of mathematics that they will learn when they are older at school This is understanding of context being able to put an as yet not understood concept into some kind of context Even understanding that a concept is not part of one s current knowledge is in itself a type of understanding see the Dunning Kruger effect which is about people who do not have a good understanding of what they do not know A slightly older child may understand that multiplication of two integers can be done at least when the numbers are between 1 and 12 by looking up the two numbers in a times table They may also be able to memorise and recall the relevant times table in order to answer a multiplication question such as 2 times 4 is what This is a simple form of operational understanding understanding a question well enough to be able to do the operations necessary to be able to find an answer A yet older child may understand that multiplication of larger numbers can be done using a different method such as long multiplication or using a calculator This is a more advanced form of operational understanding because it supports answering a wider range of questions of the same type A teenager may understand that multiplication is repeated addition but not understand the broader implications of this For example when their teacher refers to multiplying 6 by 3 as adding up 3 sixes they may understand that the teacher is talking about two entirely equivalent things However they might not understand how to apply this knowledge to implement multiplication as an algorithm on a computer using only addition and looping as basic constructs This level of understanding is understanding a definition or understanding the definition when a concept only has one definition A teenager may also understand the mathematical idea of abstracting over individual whole numbers as variables and how to efficiently i e not via trial and error solve algebraic equations involving multiplication by such variables such as 2 x 6 displaystyle 2x 6 This is relational understanding understanding how multiplication relates to division An undergraduate studying mathematics may come to learn that the integers equipped with multiplication is merely one example of a range of mathematical structures called monoids and that theorems about monoids apply equally well to multiplication and other types of monoids For the purpose of operating a cash register at McDonald s a person does not need a very deep understanding of the multiplication involved in calculating the total price of two Big Macs However for the purpose of contributing to number theory research a person would need to have a relatively deep understanding of multiplication along with other relevant arithmetical concepts such as division and prime numbers Assessment EditIt is possible for a person or a piece of intelligent software that in reality only has a shallow understanding of a topic to appear to have a deeper understanding than they actually do when the right questions are asked of it The most obvious way this can happen is by memorization of correct answers to known questions but there are other more subtle ways that a person or computer can intentionally or otherwise deceive somebody about their level of understanding too This is particularly a risk with artificial intelligence in which the ability of a piece of artificial intelligence software to very quickly try out millions of possibilities attempted solutions theories etc could create a misleading impression of the real depth of its understanding Supposed AI software could in fact come up with impressive answers to questions that were difficult for unaided humans to answer without really understanding the concepts at all simply by dumbly applying rules very quickly However see the Chinese room argument for a controversial philosophical extension of this argument Examinations are designed to assess students understanding and sometimes also other things such as knowledge and writing abilities without falling prey to these risks They do this partly by asking multiple different questions about a topic to reduce the risk of measurement error and partly by forbidding access to reference works and the outside world to reduce the risk of someone else s understanding being passed off as one s own Because of the faster and more accurate computation and memorization abilities of computers such tests would arguably often have to be modified if they were to be used to accurately assess the understanding of an artificial intelligence Conversely it is even easier for a person or artificial intelligence to fake a shallower level of understanding than they actually have they simply need to respond with the same kind of answers that someone with a more limited understanding or no understanding would respond with such as I don t know or obviously wrong answers This is relevant for judges in Turing tests it is unlikely to be effective to simply ask the respondents to mentally calculate the answer to a very difficult arithmetical question because the computer is likely to simply dumb itself down and pretend not to know the answer As a model EditGregory Chaitin a noted computer scientist propounds a view that comprehension is a kind of data compression 19 In his essay The Limits of Reason he argues that understanding something means being able to figure out a simple set of rules that explains it For example we understand why day and night exist because we have a simple model the rotation of the earth that explains a tremendous amount of data changes in brightness temperature and atmospheric composition of the earth We have compressed a large amount of information by using a simple model that predicts it Similarly we understand the number 0 33333 by thinking of it as one third The first way of representing the number requires five concepts 0 decimal point 3 infinity infinity of 3 but the second way can produce all the data of the first representation but uses only three concepts 1 division 3 Chaitin argues that comprehension is this ability to compress data Religious perspectives EditCognition helps us gain knowledge which can affect our level of understanding or right view as expressed in buddhism Understanding also is seen in the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit helping an individual with their insight into God s providence See also Edit Psychology portalActive listening Awareness Binah Kabbalah Chinese room Communication Concept Epistemology Hermeneutic circle Informational listening Ishin denshin Lie to children List of language disorders Meaning linguistics Natural language understanding Mental model Nous Perception ThoughtReferences Edit Bereiter Carl Education and mind in the Knowledge Age Archived from the original on 2006 02 25 Zagzebski Linda 2017 What is Knowledge The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology John Wiley amp Sons Ltd pp 92 116 doi 10 1002 9781405164863 ch3 ISBN 978 1 4051 6486 3 S2CID 158886670 retrieved 2021 11 28 Tarziu Gabriel 2021 04 01 How Do We Obtain Understanding with the Help of Explanations Axiomathes 31 2 173 197 doi 10 1007 s10516 020 09488 6 ISSN 1572 8390 S2CID 218947045 Ludwig Wittgenstein On Certainty remark 42 Pritchard Duncan 2008 08 12 Knowing the Answer Understanding and Epistemic Value Grazer Philosophische Studien 77 1 325 339 doi 10 1163 18756735 90000852 hdl 20 500 11820 522fbeba 15b2 46d0 8019 4647e795642c ISSN 1875 6735 Kvanvig Jonathan L 2003 08 21 The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 44228 2 Elgin Catherine Z 2017 09 29 True Enough MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 03653 5 Lipton Peter 2003 10 04 Inference to the Best Explanation Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 54827 9 Kitcher Philip 1985 11 01 Two Approaches to Explanation The Journal of Philosophy 82 11 632 639 doi 10 2307 2026419 JSTOR 2026419 a b c Grimm Stephen R 2014 Fairweather Abrol ed Understanding as Knowledge of Causes Virtue Epistemology Naturalized Bridges Between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science Synthese Library Cham Springer International Publishing vol 366 pp 329 345 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 04672 3 19 ISBN 978 3 319 04672 3 retrieved 2021 11 28 Pritchard Duncan 2009 Knowledge Understanding and Epistemic Value Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 64 19 43 doi 10 1017 S1358246109000046 hdl 20 500 11820 0ef91ebb b9f0 44e9 88d6 08afe5e96cc0 ISSN 1755 3555 S2CID 170647127 Hills Alison 2009 10 01 Moral Testimony and Moral Epistemology Ethics 120 1 94 127 doi 10 1086 648610 ISSN 0014 1704 S2CID 144361023 Hills Alison 2010 04 29 The Beloved Self Morality and the Challenge from Egoism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 921330 6 Bereiter Carl 2005 04 11 Education and Mind in the Knowledge Age Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 64479 6 Kim Jaegwon 1994 Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence Philosophical Issues 5 51 69 doi 10 2307 1522873 ISSN 1533 6077 JSTOR 1522873 a b Grimm Stephen R 2014 Fairweather Abrol ed Understanding as Knowledge of Causes Virtue Epistemology Naturalized Bridges Between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science Synthese Library Cham Springer International Publishing vol 366 pp 329 345 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 04672 3 19 ISBN 978 3 319 04672 3 retrieved 2021 11 28 Zagzebski Linda 2008 07 08 On Epistemology Cengage Learning ISBN 978 0 534 25234 2 Ruben David Hillel Ruben Director of New York University in London and Professor of Philosophy at the School of Oriental and African Studies David Hillel 2003 Action and Its Explanation Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 823588 0 Chaitin Gregory 2006 The Limits Of Reason PDF Scientific American 294 3 74 81 Bibcode 2006SciAm 294c 74C doi 10 1038 scientificamerican0306 74 PMID 16502614 archived from the original PDF on 2016 03 04External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Understanding Look up understanding in Wiktionary the free dictionary Understanding at PhilPapers Understanding in Epistemology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Understanding amp oldid 1130841692, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.