fbpx
Wikipedia

Hard problem of consciousness

In philosophy of mind, the hard problem of consciousness is to explain why and how humans and other organisms have qualia, phenomenal consciousness, or subjective experiences.[1][2] It is contrasted with the "easy problems" of explaining why and how physical systems give a (healthy) human being the ability to discriminate, to integrate information, and to perform behavioral functions such as watching, listening, speaking (including generating an utterance that appears to refer to personal behaviour or belief), and so forth.[1] The easy problems are amenable to functional explanation—that is, explanations that are mechanistic or behavioral—since each physical system can be explained (at least in principle) purely by reference to the "structure and dynamics" that underpin the phenomenon.[3][4][1]

Proponents of the hard problem argue that it is categorically different from the easy problems since no mechanistic or behavioral explanation could explain the character of an experience, not even in principle. Even after all the relevant functional facts are explicated, they argue, there will still remain a further question: "why is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience?"[1] To bolster their case, proponents of the hard problem frequently turn to various philosophical thought experiments, involving philosophical zombies (which, they claim, are conceivable) or inverted qualia, or the claimed ineffability of colour experiences, or the claimed unknowability of foreign states of consciousness, such as the experience of being a bat.

Chalmers on stage for an Alan Turing Year event at De La Salle University, Manila, 27 March 2012

The terms "hard problem" and "easy problems" were coined by the philosopher David Chalmers in a 1994 talk given at The Science of Consciousness conference held in Tucson, Arizona.[5] The following year, the main talking points of Chalmers' talk were then published in The Journal of Consciousness Studies.[3] The publication gained significant attention from consciousness researchers and became the subject of a special volume of the journal,[6][7] which was later published into a book.[8] In 1996, Chalmers published The Conscious Mind, a book-length treatment of the hard problem, in which he elaborated on his core arguments and responded to counterarguments. His use of the word easy is "tongue-in-cheek".[9] As the cognitive psychologist Steven Pinker puts it, they are about as easy as going to Mars or curing cancer. "That is, scientists more or less know what to look for, and with enough brainpower and funding, they would probably crack it in this century."[10]

The existence of the hard problem is disputed. It has been accepted by some philosophers of mind such as Joseph Levine,[11] Colin McGinn,[12] and Ned Block[13] and cognitive neuroscientists such as Francisco Varela,[14] Giulio Tononi,[15][16] and Christof Koch.[15][16] On the other hand, its existence is denied by other philosophers of mind, such as Daniel Dennett,[17] Massimo Pigliucci,[18] Thomas Metzinger, Patricia Churchland,[19] and Keith Frankish,[20] and by cognitive neuroscientists such as Stanislas Dehaene,[21] Bernard Baars,[22] Anil Seth,[23] and Antonio Damasio.[24] Clinical neurologist and skeptic Steven Novella has dismissed it as "the hard non-problem".[25] According to a 2020 PhilPapers survey, a majority (62.42%) of the philosophers surveyed said they believed that the hard problem is a genuine problem, while 29.72% said that it does not exist.[26]

Overview edit

David Chalmers first formulated the hard problem in his paper "Facing up to the problem of consciousness" (1995)[3] and expanded upon it in The Conscious Mind (1996). His works provoked comment. Some, such as David Lewis and Steven Pinker, have praised Chalmers for his argumentative rigour and "impeccable clarity".[27] Pinker later said, in 2018, "In the end I still think that the hard problem is a meaningful conceptual problem, but agree with Dennett that it is not a meaningful scientific problem. No one will ever get a grant to study whether you are a zombie or whether the same Captain Kirk walks on the deck of the Enterprise and the surface of Zakdorn. And I agree with several other philosophers that it may be futile to hope for a solution at all, precisely because it is a conceptual problem, or, more accurately, a problem with our concepts."[28] Daniel Dennett and Patricia Churchland, among others, believe that the hard problem is best seen as a collection of easy problems that will be solved through further analysis of the brain and behaviour.[29][30]

Consciousness is an ambiguous term. It can be used to mean self consciousness, awareness, the state of being awake, and so on. Chalmers uses Thomas Nagel's definition of consciousness: the feeling of what it is like to be something. Consciousness, in this sense, is synonymous with experience.[31][27]

Chalmers' formulation edit

. . .even when we have explained the performance of all the cognitive and behavioral functions in the vicinity of experience—perceptual discrimination, categorization, internal access, verbal report—there may still remain a further unanswered question: Why is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience?

— David Chalmers, Facing up to the problem of consciousness

The problems of consciousness, Chalmers argues, are of two kinds: the easy problems and the hard problem.

Easy problems edit

The easy problems are amenable to reductive inquiry. They are a logical consequence of lower-level facts about the world, similar to how a clock's ability to tell time is a logical consequence of its clockwork and structure, or a hurricane a logical consequence of the structures and functions of certain weather patterns. A clock, a hurricane, and the easy problems, are all the sum of their parts (as are most things).[27]

The easy problems relevant to consciousness concern mechanistic analysis of the neural processes that accompany behaviour. Examples of these include how sensory systems work, how sensory data is processed in the brain, how that data influences behaviour or verbal reports, the neural basis of thought and emotion, and so on. They are problems that can be analyzed through "structures and functions".[27]

Hard problem edit

The hard problem, in contrast, is the problem of why and how those processes are accompanied by experience.[3] It may further include the question of why these processes are accompanied by this or that particular experience, rather than some other kind of experience. In other words, the hard problem is the problem of explaining why certain mechanisms are accompanied by conscious experience.[27] For example, why should neural processing in the brain lead to the felt sensations of, say, feelings of hunger? And why should those neural firings lead to feelings of hunger rather than some other feeling (such as, for example, feelings of thirst)?

Chalmers argues that it is conceivable that the relevant behaviours associated with hunger, or any other feeling, could occur even in the absence of that feeling. This suggests that experience is irreducible to physical systems such as the brain. This is the topic of the next section.

How the easy and hard problems are related edit

Chalmers believes that the hard problem is irreducible to the easy problems: solving the easy problems will not lead to a solution to the hard problems. This is because the easy problems pertain to the causal structure of the world while the hard problem pertains to consciousness, and facts about consciousness include facts that go beyond mere causal or structural description.

For example, suppose someone were to stub their foot and yelp. In this scenario, the easy problems are mechanistic explanations that involve the activity of the nervous system and brain and its relation to the environment (such as the propagation of nerve signals from the toe to the brain, the processing of that information and how it leads to yelping, and so on). The hard problem is the question of why these mechanisms are accompanied by the feeling of pain, or why these feelings of pain feel the particular way that they do. Chalmers argues that facts about the neural mechanisms of pain, and pain behaviours, do not lead to facts about conscious experience. Facts about conscious experience are, instead, further facts, not derivable from facts about the brain.[27]

 
The hard problem is often illustrated by appealing to the logical possibility of inverted visible spectra. If there is no logical contradiction in supposing that one's colour vision could be inverted, it follows that mechanistic explanations of visual processing do not determine facts about what it is like to see colours.

An explanation for all of the relevant physical facts about neural processing would leave unexplained facts about what it is like to feel pain. This is in part because functions and physical structures of any sort could conceivably exist in the absence of experience. Alternatively, they could exist alongside a different set of experiences. For example, it is logically possible for a perfect replica of Chalmers to have no experience at all, or for it to have a different set of experiences (such as an inverted visible spectrum, so that the blue-yellow red-green axes of its visual field are flipped).

The same cannot be said about clocks, hurricanes, or other physical things. In those cases, a structural or functional description is a complete description. A perfect replica of a clock is a clock, a perfect replica of a hurricane is a hurricane, and so on. The difference is that physical things are nothing more than their physical constituents. For example, water is nothing more than H2O molecules, and understanding everything about H2O molecules is to understand everything there is to know about water. But consciousness is not like this. Knowing everything there is to know about the brain, or any physical system, is not to know everything there is to know about consciousness. Consciousness, then, must not be purely physical.[27]

Implications for physicalism edit

Chalmers's idea contradicts physicalism (sometimes labelled materialism). This is the view that everything that exists is a physical or material thing, so everything can be reduced to microphysical things (such as subatomic particles and the interactions between them). For example, a desk is a physical thing because it is nothing more than a complex arrangement of a large number of subatomic particles interacting in a certain way. According to physicalism, everything, including consciousness, can be explained by appeal to its microphysical constituents. Chalmers's hard problem presents a counterexample to this view, since it suggests that consciousness cannot be reductively explained by appealing to its microphysical constituents. Thus, if the hard problem is a real problem then physicalism must be false, and if physicalism is true then the hard problem must not be a real problem.[citation needed]

Though Chalmers rejects physicalism, he is still a naturalist.[27][importance?]

Historical precedents edit

The hard problem of consciousness has scholarly antecedents considerably earlier than Chalmers. Chalmers himself notes that "a number of thinkers in the recent and distant past" have "recognised the particular difficulties of explaining consciousness."[32] He states that all his original 1996 paper contributed to the discussion was "a catchy name, a minor reformulation of philosophically familiar points".[32]

Among others, thinkers who have made arguments similar to Chalmers' formulation of the hard problem include Isaac Newton,[33] John Locke,[34] Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz,[35][33] John Stuart Mill,[36] and Thomas Henry Huxley.[37][33] Likewise, Asian philosophers like Dharmakirti and Guifeng Zongmi discussed the problem of how consciousness arises from unconscious matter.[33][38][39][40]

Related concepts edit

The mind–body problem edit

The mind–body problem is the problem of how the mind and the body relate. The mind body problem is more general than the hard problem of consciousness, since it is the problem of discovering how the mind and body relate in general, thereby implicating any theoretical framework that broaches the topic. The hard problem, in contrast, is often construed as a problem uniquely faced by physicialist or materialist theories of mind.

"What Is It Like to Be a Bat?" edit

The philosopher Thomas Nagel posited in his 1974 paper "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?" that experiences are essentially subjective (accessible only to the individual undergoing them—i.e., felt only by the one feeling them), while physical states are essentially objective (accessible to multiple individuals). So he argued we have no idea what it could mean to claim that an essentially subjective state just is an essentially non-subjective state (i.e., that a felt state is nothing but a functional state). In other words, we have no idea of what reductivism amounts to.[31] He believes "every subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with a single point of view, and it seems inevitable that an objective, physical theory will abandon that point of view."[31]

Explanatory gap edit

In 1983, the philosopher Joseph Levine proposed that there is an explanatory gap between our understanding of the physical world and our understanding of consciousness.[41]

Levine's disputes that conscious states are reducible to neuronal or brain states. He uses the example of pain (as an example of a conscious state) and its reduction to the firing of c-fibers (a kind of nerve cell). The difficulty is as follows: even if consciousness is physical, it is not clear which physical states correspond to which conscious states. The bridges between the two levels of description will be contingent, rather than necessary. This is significant because in most contexts, relating two scientific levels of descriptions (such as physics and chemistry) is done with the assurance of necessary connections between the two theories (for example, chemistry follows with necessity from physics).[42]

Levine illustrates this with a thought experiment: Suppose that humanity were to encounter an alien species, and suppose it is known that the aliens do not have any c-fibers. Even if one knows this, it is not obvious that the aliens do not feel pain: that would remain an open question. This is because the fact that aliens do not have c-fibers does not entail that they do not feel pain (in other words, feelings of pain do not follow with logical necessity from the firing of c-fibers). Levine thinks such thought experiments demonstrate an explanatory gap between consciousness and the physical world: even if consciousness is reducible to physical things, consciousness cannot be explained in terms of physical things, because the link between physical things and consciousness is contingent link.[42]

Levine does not think that the explanatory gap means that consciousness is not physical; he is open to the idea that the explanatory gap is only an epistemological problem for physicalism.[42] In contrast, Chalmers thinks that the hard problem of consciousness does show that consciousness is not physical.[27]

Philosophical zombies edit

Philosophical zombies are a thought experiment commonly used in discussions of the hard problem.[43][44] They are hypothetical beings physically identical to humans but that lack conscious experience.[45] Philosophers such as Chalmers, Joseph Levine, and Francis Kripke take zombies as impossible within the bounds of nature but possible within the bounds of logic.[46] This would imply that facts about experience are not logically entailed by the "physical" facts. Therefore, consciousness is irreducible. In Chalmers' words, "after God (hypothetically) created the world, he had more work to do."[47] Daniel Dennett, a philosopher of mind, criticised the field's use of "the zombie hunch" which he deems an "embarrassment"[48] that ought to "be dropped like a hot potato".[29]

Knowledge argument edit

The knowledge argument, also known as Mary's Room, is another common thought experiment: A hypothetical neuroscientist named Mary has lived her whole life in a black-and-white room and has never seen colour before. She also happens to know everything there is to know about the brain and colour perception.[49] Chalmers believes[47][page needed] that when Mary sees the colour red for the first time, she gains new knowledge — the knowledge of "what red looks like" — which is distinct from, and irreducible to, her prior physical knowledge of the brain or visual system. A stronger form of the knowledge argument[49] claims not merely that Mary would lack subjective knowledge of "what red looks like," but that she would lack knowledge of an objective fact about the world: namely, "what red looks like," a non-physical fact that can be learned only through direct experience (qualia). Others, such as Thomas Nagel, take a "physicalist" position, disagree with the argument in its stronger and/or weaker forms.[49] For example, Nagel put forward a "speculative proposal" of devising a language that could "explain to a person blind from birth what it is like to see."[31] The knowledge argument implies that such a language could not exist.

Philosophical responses edit

David Chalmers' formulation of the hard problem of consciousness provoked considerable debate within philosophy of mind, as well as scientific research.[42]

 
A diagram showing the relationship between various views concerning the relationship between consciousness and the physical world

The hard problem is considered a problem primarily for physicalist views of the mind (the view that the mind is a physical object or process), since physical explanations tend to be functional, or structural. Because of this, some physicalists have responded to the hard problem by seeking to show that it dissolves upon analysis. Other researchers accept the problem as real and seek to develop a theory of consciousness' place in the world that can solve it, by either modifying physicalism or abandoning it in favour of an alternative ontology (such as panpsychism or dualism). A third response has been to accept the hard problem as real but deny human cognitive faculties can solve it.

PhilPapers is an organization that archives academic philosophy papers and periodically surveys professional philosophers about their views. It can be used to gauge professional attitudes towards the hard problem. As of the 2020 survey results, it seems that the majority of philosophers (62.42%) agree that the hard problem is real, with a substantial minority that disagrees (29.76%).[50]

Attitudes towards physicalism also differ among professionals. In the 2009 PhilPapers survey, 56.5% of philosophers surveyed subscribed to physicalism and 27.1% of philosophers surveyed rejected physicalism. 16.4% fell into the "other" category.[51] In the 2020 PhilPapers survey, 51.93% of philosophers surveyed indicated that they "accept or lean towards" physicalism and 32.08% indicated that they reject physicalism. 6.23% were "agnostic" or "undecided".[50]

Different solutions have been proposed to the hard problem of consciousness. The sections below taxonomizes the various responses to the hard problem. The shape of this taxonomy was first introduced by Chalmers in a 2003 literature review on the topic.[52] The labelling convention of this taxonomy has been incorporated into the technical vocabulary of analytic philosophy, being used by philosophers such as Adrian Boutel,[53] Raamy Majeed,[54] Janet Levin,[55] Pete Mandik & Josh Weisberg,[56] Roberto Pereira,[57] and Helen Yetter-Chappell.[58]

Type-A Materialism edit

Type-A materialism (also known as reductive materialism or a priori physicalism) is view characterized by a commitment to physicalism and a full rejection of the hard problem. By this view, the hard problem either does not exist or is just another easy problem, because every fact about the mind is a fact about the performance of various functions or behaviours. So, once all the relevant functions and behaviours have been accounted for, there will not be any facts left over in need of explanation.[52] Thinkers who subscribe to type-A materialism include Paul and Patricia Churchland, Daniel Dennett, Keith Frankish, and Thomas Metzinger.

Some type-A materialists believe in the reality of phenomenal consciousness but believe it is nothing extra in addition to certain functions or behaviours. This view is sometimes referred to as strong reductionism.[42][52] Other type-A materialists may reject the existence of phenomenal consciousness entirely. This view is referred to as eliminative materialism or illusionism.[59][60][61]

Strong reductionism edit

Many philosophers have disputed that there is a hard problem of consciousness distinct from what Chalmers calls the easy problems of consciousness. Some among them, who are sometimes termed strong reductionists, hold that phenomenal consciousness (i.e., conscious experience) does exist but that it can be fully understood as reducible to the brain.[42]

Broadly, strong reductionists accept that conscious experience is real but argue it can be fully understood in functional terms as an emergent property of the material brain.[42] In contrast to weak reductionists (see above), strong reductionists reject ideas used to support the existence of a hard problem (that the same functional organization could exist without consciousness, or that a blind person who understood vision through a textbook would not know everything about sight) as simply mistaken intuitions.[42][52]

A notable family of strong reductionist accounts are the higher-order theories of consciousness.[62][42] In 2005, the philosopher Peter Carruthers wrote about "recognitional concepts of experience", that is, "a capacity to recognize [a] type of experience when it occurs in one's own mental life," and suggested that such a capacity could explain phenomenal consciousness without positing qualia.[63] On the higher-order view, since consciousness is a representation, and representation is fully functionally analyzable, there is no hard problem of consciousness.[42]

The philosophers Glenn Carruthers and Elizabeth Schier said in 2012 that the main arguments for the existence of a hard problem—philosophical zombies, Mary's room, and Nagel's bats—are only persuasive if one already assumes that "consciousness must be independent of the structure and function of mental states, i.e. that there is a hard problem." Hence, the arguments beg the question. The authors suggest that "instead of letting our conclusions on the thought experiments guide our theories of consciousness, we should let our theories of consciousness guide our conclusions from the thought experiments."[64]

The philosopher Massimo Pigliucci argued in 2013 that the hard problem is misguided, resulting from a "category mistake".[18] He said: "Of course an explanation isn't the same as an experience, but that's because the two are completely independent categories, like colors and triangles. It is obvious that I cannot experience what it is like to be you, but I can potentially have a complete explanation of how and why it is possible to be you."[18]

In 2017, the philosopher Marco Stango, in a paper on John Dewey's approach to the problem of consciousness (which preceded Chalmers' formulation of the hard problem by over half a century), noted that Dewey's approach would see the hard problem as the consequence of an unjustified assumption that feelings and functional behaviors are not the same physical process: "For the Deweyan philosopher, the 'hard problem' of consciousness is a 'conceptual fact' only in the sense that it is a philosophical mistake: the mistake of failing to see that the physical can be had as an episode of immediate sentiency."[65]

The philosopher Thomas Metzinger likens the hard problem of consciousness to vitalism, a formerly widespread view in biology which was not so much solved as abandoned.[66] Brian Jonathan Garrett has also argued that the hard problem suffers from flaws analogous to those of vitalism.[67]

The philosopher Peter Hacker argues that the hard problem is misguided in that it asks how consciousness can emerge from matter, whereas in fact sentience emerges from the evolution of living organisms.[68] He states: "The hard problem isn’t a hard problem at all. The really hard problems are the problems the scientists are dealing with. [...] The philosophical problem, like all philosophical problems, is a confusion in the conceptual scheme."[68] Hacker's critique extends beyond Chalmers and the hard problem and is directed against contemporary philosophy of mind and neuroscience more broadly. Along with the neuroscientist Max Bennett, he has argued that most of contemporary neuroscience remains implicitly dualistic in its conceptualizations and is predicated on the mereological fallacy of ascribing psychological concepts to the brain that can properly be ascribed only to the person as a whole.[69] Hacker further states that "consciousness studies", as it exists today, is "literally a total waste of time" and that "the conception of consciousness which they have is incoherent".[68]

Eliminative materialism / Illusionism edit

Eliminative materialism or eliminativism is the view that many or all of the mental states used in folk psychology (i.e., common-sense ways of discussing the mind) do not, upon scientific examination, correspond to real brain mechanisms.[59] According the 2020 PhilPapers survey, 4.51% of philosophers surveyed subscribe to eliminativism.[50]

While Patricia Churchland and Paul Churchland have famously applied eliminative materialism to propositional attitudes, philosophers including Daniel Dennett, Georges Rey, and Keith Frankish have applied it to qualia or phenomenal consciousness (i.e., conscious experience).[59] On their view, it is mistaken not only to believe there is a hard problem of consciousness, but to believe phenomenal consciousness exists at all.[20][70]

This stance has recently taken on the name of illusionism: the view that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion. The term was popularized by the philosopher Keith Frankish.[60] Frankish argues that "illusionism" is preferable to "eliminativism" for labelling the view that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion. More substantively, Frankish argues that illusionism about phenomenal consciousness is preferable to realism about phenomenal consciousness. He states: "Theories of consciousness typically address the hard problem. They accept that phenomenal consciousness is real and aim to explain how it comes to exist. There is, however, another approach, which holds that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion and aims to explain why it seems to exist."[20] Frankish concludes that illusionism "replaces the hard problem with the illusion problem—the problem of explaining how the illusion of phenomenality arises and why it is so powerful."[20]

The philosopher Daniel Dennett is another prominent figure associated with illusionism. After Frankish published a paper in the Journal of Consciousness Studies titled Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness,[60] Dennett responded with his own paper with the spin-off title Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness.[70] Dennett has been arguing for the illusory status of consciousness since early on in his career. For example, in 1979 he published a paper titled On the Absence of Phenomenology (where he argues for the nonexistence of phenomenal consciousness).[71] Similar ideas have been explicated in his 1991 book Consciousness Explained.[72] Dennett argues that the so-called "hard problem" will be solved in the process of solving what Chalmers terms the "easy problems".[17] He compares consciousness to stage magic and its capability to create extraordinary illusions out of ordinary things.[73] To show how people might be commonly fooled into overstating the accuracy of their introspective abilities, he describes a phenomenon called change blindness, a visual process that involves failure to detect scenery changes in a series of alternating images.[74][page needed] He accordingly argues that consciousness need not be what it seems to be based on introspection. To address the question of the hard problem, or how and why physical processes give rise to experience, Dennett states that the phenomenon of having experience is nothing more than the performance of functions or the production of behavior, which can also be referred to as the easy problems of consciousness.[17] Thus, Dennett argues that the hard problem of experience is included among—not separate from—the easy problems, and therefore they can only be explained together as a cohesive unit.[73]

Elimativists differ on the role they believe intuitive judgement plays in creating the apparent reality of consciousness. The philosopher Jacy Reese Anthis is of the position that this issue is born of an overreliance on intuition, calling philosophical discussions on the topic of consciousness a form of "intuition jousting".[75] But when the issue is tackled with "formal argumentation" and "precise semantics" then the hard problem will dissolve.[75] The philosopher Elizabeth Irvine, in contrast, can be read as having the opposite view, since she argues that phenomenal properties (that is, properties of consciousness) do not exist in our common-sense view of the world. She states that "the hard problem of consciousness may not be a genuine problem for non-philosophers (despite its overwhelming obviousness to philosophers)."[76]

A complete illusionist theory of consciousness must include the description of a mechanism by which the illusion of subjective experience is had and reported by people. Various philosophers and scientists have proposed possible theories.[77] For example, in his book Consciousness and the Social Brain neuroscientist Michael Graziano advocates what he calls attention schema theory, in which our perception of being conscious is merely an error in perception, held by brains which evolved to hold erroneous and incomplete models of their own internal workings, just as they hold erroneous and incomplete models of their own bodies and of the external world.[78][79]

Criticisms edit

The main criticisms of eliminative materialism and illusion hinge on the counterintuitive nature of the view. Arguments of this form are called Moorean Arguments. A Moorean argument seeks to undermine the conclusion of an argument by asserting that the negation of that conclusion is more certain than the premises of the argument.[80]

The roots of the Moorean Argument against illusionism extend back to Augustine of Hippo who stated that he could not be deceived regarding his own existence, since the very act of being deceived secures the existence of a being there to be the recipient of that deception.[note 1][81]

In the Early-Modern era, these arguments were repopularized by René Descartes, who coined the now famous phrase "Je pense, donc je suis" ("I think, therefore I am").[82] Descartes argued that even if he was maximally deceived (because, for example, an evil demon was manipulating all his senses) he would still know with certainty that his mind exists, because the state of being deceived requires a mind as a prerequisite.[83]

This same general argumentative structure is still in use today. For example, in 2002 David Chalmers published an explicitly Moorean argument against illusionism. The argument goes like this: The reality of consciousness is more certain than any theoretical commitments (to, for example, physicalism) that may be motivating the illusionist to deny the existence of consciousness. The reason for this is because we have direct "acquaintance" with consciousness, but we do not have direct acquaintance with anything else (including anything that could inform our beliefs in consciousness being an illusion). In other words: consciousness can be known directly, so the reality of consciousness is more certain than any philosophical or scientific theory that says otherwise.[84] Chalmers concludes that "there is little doubt that something like the Moorean argument is the reason that most people reject illusionism and many find it crazy."[85]

Eliminative materialism and illusionism have been the subject of criticism within the popular press. One highly cited example comes from the philosopher Galen Strawson who wrote an article in the New York Review of Books titled "The Consciousness Deniers". In it, Strawson describes illusionism as the "silliest claim ever made", next to which "every known religious belief is only a little less sensible than the belief that the grass is green."[86] Another notable example comes from Christof Koch (a neuroscientist and one of the leading proponents of Integrated Information Theory) in his popular science book The Feeling of Life Itself. In the early pages of the book, Koch describes eliminativism as the "metaphysical counterpart to Cotard's syndrome, a psychiatric condition in which patients deny being alive."[87] Koch takes the prevalence of eliminativism as evidence that "much of twentieth-century analytic philosophy has gone to the dogs".[88]

Type-B Materialism edit

Type-B Materialism, also known as Weak Reductionism or A Posteriori Physicalism, is the view the hard problem stems from human psychology, and is therefore not indicative of a genuine ontological gap between consciousness and the physical world.[42] Like Type-A Materialists, Type-B Materialists are committed to physicalism. Unlike Type-A Materialists, however, Type-B Materialists do accept inconceivability arguments often cited in support of the hard problem, but with a key caveat: that inconceivability arguments give us insight only into how the human mind tends to conceptualize the relationship between mind and matter, but not into what the true nature of this relationship actually is.[42][52] According to this view, there is a gap between two ways of knowing (introspection and neuroscience) that will not be resolved by understanding all the underlying neurobiology, but still believe that consciousness and neurobiology are one and the same in reality.[42]

While Type-B Materialists all agree that intuitions about the hard problem are psychological rather than ontological in origin, they differ as to whether our intuitions about the hard problem are innate or culturally conditioned. This has been dubbed the "hard-wired/soft-wired distinction."[89][90] In relation to Type-B Materialism, those who believe that our intuitions about the hard problem are innate (and therefore common to all humans) subscribe to the "hard-wired view".[90] Those that believe our intuitions are culturally conditioned subscribe to the "soft-wired view". Unless otherwise specified, the term Type-B Materialism refers to the hard-wired view.[90]

Notable philosophers who subscribe to Type-B Materialism include David Papineau,[91] Joseph Levine,[92] and Janet Levine.[55]

The "hard-wired view" edit

Joseph Levine (who formulated the notion of the explanatory gap) states: "The explanatory gap argument doesn't demonstrate a gap in nature, but a gap in our understanding of nature."[92] He nevertheless contends that full scientific understanding will not close the gap,[42] and that analogous gaps do not exist for other identities in nature, such as that between water and H2O.[93] The philosophers Ned Block and Robert Stalnaker agree that facts about what a conscious experience is like to the one experiencing it cannot be deduced from knowing all the facts about the underlying physiology, but by contrast argue that such gaps of knowledge are also present in many other cases in nature, such as the distinction between water and H2O.[94][13]

To explain why these two ways of knowing (i.e. third-person scientific observation and first-person introspection) yield such different understandings of consciousness, weak reductionists often invoke the phenomenal concepts strategy, which argues the difference stems from our inaccurate phenomenal concepts (i.e., how we think about consciousness), not from the nature of consciousness itself.[95][96] By this view, the hard problem of consciousness stems from a dualism of concepts, not from a dualism of properties or substances.[42]

The "soft-wired view" edit

Some consciousness researchers have argued that the hard problem is a cultural artifact, unique to contemporary Western Culture. This is similar to Type-B Materialism, but it makes the further claim that the psychological facts that cause us to intuit the hard problem are not innate, but culturally conditioned. Notable researchers who hold this view include Anna Wierzbicka,[97] Hakwan Lau and Matthias Michel.[98]

Wierzbicka (who is a linguist) argues that the vocabulary used by consciousness researchers (including words like experience and consciousness) are not universally translatable, and are "parochially English."[97] Weirzbicka calls David Chalmers out by name for using these words, arguing that if philosophers "were to use panhuman concepts expressed in crosstranslatable words" (such as know, think, or feel) then the hard problem would dissolve.[97] David Chalmers has responded to these criticisms by saying that he will not "apologize for using technical terms in an academic article . . . they play a key role in efficient communication in every discipline, including Wierzbicka’s".[90]

Type-C Materialism edit

Type-D Dualism edit

Dualism views consciousness as either a non-physical substance separate from the brain or a non-physical property of the physical brain.[99] Dualism is the view that the mind is irreducible to the physical body.[99] There are multiple dualist accounts of the causal relationship between the mental and the physical, of which interactionism and epiphenomenalism are the most common today. Interactionism posits that the mental and physical causally impact one another, and is associated with the thought of René Descartes (1596–1650).[52] Epiphenomalism holds the mental is causally dependent on the physical, but does not in turn causally impact it.[52]

In contemporary philosophy, interactionism has been defended by philosophers including Martine Nida-Rümelin,[100] while epiphenomenalism has been defended by philosophers including Frank Jackson[101][102] (although Jackson later changed his stance to physicalism).[103] Chalmers has also defended versions of both positions as plausible.[52] Traditional dualists such as Descartes believed the mental and the physical to be two separate substances, or fundamental types of entities (hence "substance dualism"); some more recent dualists, however, accept only one substance, the physical, but state it has both mental and physical properties (hence "property dualism").[99]

Type-E Dualism edit

Type-F Monism edit

Meanwhile, panpsychism and neutral monism, broadly speaking, view consciousness as intrinsic to matter.[52] In its most basic form, panpsychism holds that all physical entities have minds (though its proponents take more qualified positions),[104] while neutral monism, in at least some variations, holds that entities are composed of a substance with mental and physical aspects—and is thus sometimes described as a type of panpsychism.[105]

Forms of panpsychism and neutral monism were defended in the early twentieth century by the psychologist William James,[106][107][note 2] the philosopher Alfred North Whitehead,[107] the physicist Arthur Eddington,[108][109] and the philosopher Bertrand Russell,[104][105] and interest in these views has been revived in recent decades by philosophers including Thomas Nagel,[107] Galen Strawson,[107][110] Philip Goff,[107] and David Chalmers.[104] Chalmers describes his overall view as "naturalistic dualism",[3] but he says panpsychism is in a sense a form of physicalism,[52] as does Strawson.[110] Proponents of panpsychism argue it solves the hard problem of consciousness parsimoniously by making consciousness a fundamental feature of reality.[42][111]

Idealism and cosmopsychism edit

A traditional solution to the hard problem is idealism, according to which consciousness is fundamental and not simply an emergent property of matter. It is claimed that this avoids the hard problem entirely.[112] Objective idealism and cosmopsychism consider mind or consciousness to be the fundamental substance of the universe. Proponents claim that this approach is immune to both the hard problem of consciousness and the combination problem that affects panpsychism.[113][114][115]

From an idealist perspective, matter is a representation or image of mental processes. Supporters suggest that this avoids the problems associated with the materialist view of mind as an emergent property of a physical brain.[116] Critics argue that this then leads to a decombination problem[clarification needed], in terms of explaining individual subjective experience. In response, Bernardo Kastrup claims that nature hints at a mechanism for this in the condition dissociative identity disorder (previously known as Multiple Personality Disorder).[117] Kastrup proposes dissociation as an example from nature showing that multiple minds with their own individual subjective experience could develop within a single universal mind.

Cognitive psychologist Donald D. Hoffman uses a mathematical model based around conscious agents, within a fundamentally conscious universe, to support conscious realism as a description of nature—one that falls within the objective idealism approaches to the hard problem: "The objective world, i.e., the world whose existence does not depend on the perceptions of a particular conscious agent, consists entirely of conscious agents."[118]

David Chalmers calls this form of idealism one of "the handful of promising approaches to the mind–body problem."[119]

New mysterianism edit

New mysterianism, most significantly associated with the philosopher Colin McGinn, proposes that the human mind, in its current form, will not be able to explain consciousness.[120][12] McGinn draws on Noam Chomsky's distinction between problems, which are in principle solvable, and mysteries, which human cognitive faculties are unequipped to ever understand, and places the mind–body problem in the latter category.[120] His position is that a naturalistic explanation does exist but that the human mind is cognitively closed to it due to its limited range of intellectual abilities.[120] He cites Jerry Fodor's concept of the modularity of mind in support of cognitive closure.[120]

While in McGinn's strong form, new mysterianism states that the relationship between consciousness and the material world can never be understood by the human mind, there are also weaker forms that argue it cannot be understood within existing paradigms but that advances in science or philosophy may open the way to other solutions (see above).[42] The ideas of Thomas Nagel and Joseph Levine fall into the second category.[42] Steven Pinker has also endorsed this weaker version of the view, summarizing it as follows:[10]

And then there is the theory put forward by philosopher Colin McGinn that our vertigo when pondering the Hard Problem is itself a quirk of our brains. The brain is a product of evolution, and just as animal brains have their limitations, we have ours. Our brains can't hold a hundred numbers in memory, can't visualize seven-dimensional space and perhaps can't intuitively grasp why neural information processing observed from the outside should give rise to subjective experience on the inside. This is where I place my bet, though I admit that the theory could be demolished when an unborn genius—a Darwin or Einstein of consciousness—comes up with a flabbergasting new idea that suddenly makes it all clear to us.

Commentary on the problem's explanatory targets edit

Philosopher Raamy Majeed argued in 2016 that the hard problem is associated with two "explanatory targets":[54]

  1. [PQ] Physical processing gives rise to experiences with a phenomenal character.
  2. [Q] Our phenomenal qualities are thus-and-so.

The first fact concerns the relationship between the physical and the phenomenal (i.e., how and why are some physical states felt states), whereas the second concerns the very nature of the phenomenal itself (i.e., what does the felt state feel like?).

Wolfgang Fasching argues that the hard problem is not about qualia, but about the what-it-is-like-ness of experience in Nagel's sense—about the givenness of phenomenal contents:

Today there is a strong tendency to simply equate consciousness with the qualia. Yet there is clearly something not quite right about this. The "itchiness of itches" and the "hurtfulness of pain" are qualities we are conscious of. So philosophy of mind tends to treat consciousness as if it consisted simply of the contents of consciousness (the phenomenal qualities), while it really is precisely consciousness of contents, the very givenness of whatever is subjectively given. And therefore the problem of consciousness does not pertain so much to some alleged "mysterious, nonpublic objects", i.e. objects that seem to be only "visible" to the respective subject, but rather to the nature of "seeing" itself (and in today’s philosophy of mind astonishingly little is said about the latter).[121]

Relationship to scientific frameworks edit

Most neuroscientists and cognitive scientists believe that Chalmers' alleged "hard problem" will be solved, or be shown to not be a real problem, in the course of the solution of the so-called "easy problems", although a significant minority disagrees.[10][122][better source needed]

Neural correlates of consciousness edit

Since 1990, researchers including the molecular biologist Francis Crick and the neuroscientist Christof Koch have made significant progress toward identifying which neurobiological events occur concurrently to the experience of subjective consciousness.[123] These postulated events are referred to as neural correlates of consciousness or NCCs. However, this research arguably addresses the question of which neurobiological mechanisms are linked to consciousness but not the question of why they should give rise to consciousness at all, the latter being the hard problem of consciousness as Chalmers formulated it. In "On the Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness", Chalmers said he is confident that, granting the principle that something such as what he terms global availability can be used as an indicator of consciousness, the neural correlates will be discovered "in a century or two".[124] Nevertheless, he stated regarding their relationship to the hard problem of consciousness:

One can always ask why these processes of availability should give rise to consciousness in the first place. As yet we cannot explain why they do so, and it may well be that full details about the processes of availability will still fail to answer this question. Certainly, nothing in the standard methodology I have outlined answers the question; that methodology assumes a relation between availability and consciousness, and therefore does nothing to explain it. [...] So the hard problem remains. But who knows: Somewhere along the line we may be led to the relevant insights that show why the link is there, and the hard problem may then be solved.[124]

The neuroscientist and Nobel laureate Eric Kandel wrote that locating the NCCs would not solve the hard problem, but rather one of the so-called easy problems to which the hard problem is contrasted.[125] Kandel went on to note Crick and Koch's suggestion that once the binding problem—understanding what accounts for the unity of experience—is solved, it will be possible to solve the hard problem empirically.[125] However, neuroscientist Anil Seth argued that emphasis on the so-called hard problem is a distraction from what he calls the "real problem": understanding the neurobiology underlying consciousness, namely the neural correlates of various conscious processes.[23] This more modest goal is the focus of most scientists working on consciousness.[125] Psychologist Susan Blackmore believes, by contrast, that the search for the neural correlates of consciousness is futile and itself predicated on an erroneous belief in the hard problem of consciousness.[126]

Integrated information theory edit

Integrated information theory (IIT), developed by the neuroscientist and psychiatrist Giulio Tononi in 2004 and more recently also advocated by Koch, is one of the most discussed models of consciousness in neuroscience and elsewhere.[127][128] The theory proposes an identity between consciousness and integrated information, with the latter item (denoted as Φ) defined mathematically and thus in principle measurable.[128][129] The hard problem of consciousness, write Tononi and Koch, may indeed be intractable when working from matter to consciousness.[16] However, because IIT inverts this relationship and works from phenomenological axioms to matter, they say it could be able to solve the hard problem.[16] In this vein, proponents have said the theory goes beyond identifying human neural correlates and can be extrapolated to all physical systems. Tononi wrote (along with two colleagues):

While identifying the "neural correlates of consciousness" is undoubtedly important, it is hard to see how it could ever lead to a satisfactory explanation of what consciousness is and how it comes about. As will be illustrated below, IIT offers a way to analyze systems of mechanisms to determine if they are properly structured to give rise to consciousness, how much of it, and of which kind.[130]

As part of a broader critique of IIT, Michael Cerullo suggested that the theory's proposed explanation is in fact for what he dubs (following Scott Aaronson) the "Pretty Hard Problem" of methodically inferring which physical systems are conscious—but would not solve Chalmers' hard problem.[128] "Even if IIT is correct," he argues, "it does not explain why integrated information generates (or is) consciousness."[128] Chalmers agrees that IIT, if correct, would solve the "Pretty Hard Problem" rather than the hard problem.[131]

Global workspace theory edit

Global workspace theory (GWT) is a cognitive architecture and theory of consciousness proposed by the cognitive psychologist Bernard Baars in 1988.[132] Baars explains the theory with the metaphor of a theater, with conscious processes represented by an illuminated stage.[132] This theater integrates inputs from a variety of unconscious and otherwise autonomous networks in the brain and then broadcasts them to unconscious networks (represented in the metaphor by a broad, unlit "audience").[132] The theory has since been expanded upon by other scientists including cognitive neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene.[133]

In his original paper outlining the hard problem of consciousness, Chalmers discussed GWT as a theory that only targets one of the "easy problems" of consciousness.[3] In particular, he said GWT provided a promising account of how information in the brain could become globally accessible, but argued that "now the question arises in a different form: why should global accessibility give rise to conscious experience? As always, this bridging question is unanswered."[3] J. W. Dalton similarly criticized GWT on the grounds that it provides, at best, an account of the cognitive function of consciousness, and fails to explain its experiential aspect.[134] By contrast, A. C. Elitzur argued: "While [GWT] does not address the 'hard problem', namely, the very nature of consciousness, it constrains any theory that attempts to do so and provides important insights into the relation between consciousness and cognition."[135]

For his part, Baars writes (along with two colleagues) that there is no hard problem of explaining qualia over and above the problem of explaining causal functions, because qualia are entailed by neural activity and themselves causal.[22] Dehaene, in his 2014 book Consciousness and the Brain, rejected the concept of qualia and argued that Chalmers' "easy problems" of consciousness are actually the hard problems.[21] He further stated that the "hard problem" is based only upon ill-defined intuitions that are continually shifting as understanding evolves:[21]

Once our intuitions are educated by cognitive neuroscience and computer simulations, Chalmers' hard problem will evaporate. The hypothetical concept of qualia, pure mental experience, detached from any information-processing role, will be viewed as a peculiar idea of the prescientific era, much like vitalism... [Just as science dispatched vitalism] the science of consciousness will keep eating away at the hard problem of consciousness until it vanishes.

Meta-problem edit

In 2018, Chalmers highlighted what he calls the "meta-problem of consciousness", another problem related to the hard problem of consciousness:[77]

The meta-problem of consciousness is (to a first approximation) the problem of explaining why we think that there is a [hard] problem of consciousness.

In his "second approximation", he says it is the problem of explaining the behavior of "phenomenal reports", and the behavior of expressing a belief that there is a hard problem of consciousness.[77]

Explaining its significance, he says:[77]

Although the meta-problem is strictly speaking an easy problem, it is deeply connected to the hard problem. We can reasonably hope that a solution to the meta-problem will shed significant light on the hard problem. A particularly strong line holds that a solution to the meta-problem will solve or dissolve the hard problem. A weaker line holds that it will not remove the hard problem, but it will constrain the form of a solution.

In other words, the 'strong line' holds that the solution to the meta-problem would provide an explanation of our beliefs about consciousness that is independent of consciousness. That would debunk our beliefs about consciousness, in the same way that explaining beliefs about god in evolutionary terms may provide arguments against theism itself.[136]

In popular culture edit

British playwright Sir Tom Stoppard's play The Hard Problem, first produced in 2015, is named after the hard problem of consciousness, which Stoppard defines as having "subjective First Person experiences".[137]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ "But, without any delusive representations of images or phantasms, I am most certain that I am, and that I know and delight in this. In respect to these truths I am not at all afraid of the arguments of the Academians, who say, What if you are deceived? For if I am deceived, I am. For he who is not, cannot be deceived..."
  2. ^ There has been debate over how best to characterize James' position. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states: "James’s commitment to panpsychism remains somewhat controversial, since he also advanced a cogent set of objections against a version of the view, which he labelled the 'mind dust' theory, in chapter six of The Principles of Psychology ([1890] 1981). These objections are the inspiration for the so-called 'combination problem', around which much of the twenty first century literature on panpsychism focuses."

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d Chalmers, David (1995). "Facing up to the problem of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2 (3): 200–219.
  2. ^ Harnad, Stevan (1995). "Why and how we are not zombies". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 1: 164–167. See also Harnad, Stevan (April 2000). "How/why the mind–body problem is hard". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 7 (4): 54–61.
  3. ^ a b c d e f g Chalmers, David (1995). "Facing up to the problem of consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2 (3): 200–219.
  4. ^ See Cooney's foreword to the reprint of Chalmers' paper: Brian Cooney, ed. (1999). "Chapter 27: Facing up to the problem of consciousness". The place of mind. Cengage Learning. pp. 382 ff. ISBN 978-0534528256.
  5. ^ Problem of Consciousness (Tuscan 1994)
  6. ^ JCS vol. 4, pp. 3-46, 1997
  7. ^ Chalmers, David (1997). "Moving forward on the problem of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (1): 3–46.
  8. ^ Shear, Jonathan (1997). Explaining Consciousness: The Hard Problem. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262692212.
  9. ^ "Episode 83, The David Chalmers Interview (Part I - Consciousness)". The Panpsycast Philosophy Podcast. 19 July 2020. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
  10. ^ a b c Pinker, Steven (29 January 2007). "The Brain: The Mystery of Consciousness". Time. Retrieved 19 December 2018.
  11. ^ Levine, Joseph (2009-01-15). "The Explanatory Gap". The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind: 281–291. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0017. ISBN 978-0199262618.
  12. ^ a b McGinn, Colin (20 February 2012). "All machine and no ghost?". New Statesman. Retrieved 27 March 2012.
  13. ^ a b Block, Ned (2002). "The Harder Problem of Consciousness". The Journal of Philosophy. 99 (8): 391–425. doi:10.2307/3655621. JSTOR 3655621. S2CID 111383062.
  14. ^ Varela, F.J. (1 April 1996). "Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 3 (4): 330–349.
  15. ^ a b Tononi, Giulio; Boly, Melanie; Massimini, Marcello; Koch, Christof (July 2016). "Integrated information theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 17 (7): 450–461. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.44. PMID 27225071. S2CID 21347087.
  16. ^ a b c d Tononi, Giulio; Koch, Christof (March 2015). "Consciousness: here, there and everywhere?". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 370 (1668): 20140167. doi:10.1098/rstb.2014.0167. PMC 4387509. PMID 25823865.
  17. ^ a b c Dennett, Daniel C. (2013). "The tuned deck". Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 310 ff. ISBN 978-0393240689. and also "Commentary on Chalmers": Dennett, Daniel C. (1996). "Facing backwards on the problem of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 3 (1): 4–6.
  18. ^ a b c Massimo Pigliucci (2013). "What hard problem?" (PDF). Philosophy Now (99).
  19. ^ Churchland, Patricia (1996). "The Hornswoggle Problem" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 3 (5–6): 402–408. Retrieved 10 January 2021.
  20. ^ a b c d Frankish, Keith (2016). "Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23 (11–12): 11–39. Retrieved 20 December 2018.
  21. ^ a b c Dehaene, Stanislas (2014). Consciousness and the brain: deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. Viking Adult. pp. 259–266. ISBN 978-0670025435.
  22. ^ a b Edelman, Gerald; Gally, Joseph; Baars, Bernard (2011). "Biology of Consciousness". Frontiers in Psychology. 2 (4): 4. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00004. PMC 3111444. PMID 21713129.
  23. ^ a b Seth, Anil (November 2016). "The real problem". Aeon. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  24. ^ Sean Carroll (29 April 2019). "Sean Carroll's Mindscape". Preposterousuniverse.com (Podcast). Sean Carroll. Event occurs at 1:04.46. I'm just saying that the idea of a hard problem that you cannot transpose, I think is wrong.
  25. ^ "Psychological Scales. The Hard Problem of Consciousness". arabpsychology.com. Retrieved 2023-10-29.
  26. ^ "PhilPapers Survey 2020". survey2020.philpeople.org. Retrieved 2022-05-26.
  27. ^ a b c d e f g h i Chalmers, David (1996). The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. xii–xiii, 95–106, backcover.
  28. ^ Pinker, Steven (2018). Enlightenment Now. Viking. p. 481. ISBN 9780525427575.
  29. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel; commentary on T. Moody, O. Flanagan and T. Polger. "The Unimagined Preposterous of Zombies", Journal of Consciousness Studies vol. 2, no. 4, 1995, pp. 322–326.
  30. ^ Churchland, Patricia Smith (2005). "A neurophilosophical slant on consciousness research". Cortical Function: A View from the Thalamus. Progress in Brain Research. Vol. 149. pp. 285–293. doi:10.1016/S0079-6123(05)49020-2. ISBN 9780444516794. PMID 16226591.
  31. ^ a b c d Nagel, Thomas (October 1974). "What is it like to be a bat?". The Philosophical Review. 83 (4): 435–450. doi:10.2307/2183914. JSTOR 2183914. S2CID 49125889.
  32. ^ a b Chalmers, David (January 1997). "Moving forward on the problem of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (1): 3–46.
  33. ^ a b c d Chalmers, David (2020). "Is the hard problem of consciousness universal?" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 27 (5–6): 227–257. Retrieved 22 February 2022.
  34. ^ Locke, John (1722). The works of John Locke: in three volumes. Vol. 1. London: Printed for A. Churchill, and A. Manship, and sold by W. Taylor in Pater-noster-Row. p. 293.
  35. ^ Leibniz, Monadology, 17, as quoted by Aranyosi, Istvan (2004). "Chalmers's zombie arguments" (PDF) (draft ed.). Central European University Personal Pages.
  36. ^ Mill, John Stuart. A System of Logic (1843), Book V, Chapter V, section 3
  37. ^ Huxley, Thomas Henry; Youmans, William Jay (1868). The elements of physiology and hygiene: a text-book for educational institutions. New York: D. Appleton and company. p. 178.
  38. ^ Arnold, Dan (2021). "Philosophy of Mind's "Hard Problem" in Light of Buddhist Idealism". In Emmanuel, Steven M. (ed.). Philosophy's Big Questions: Comparing Buddhist and Western Approaches. New York: Columbia University Press. pp. 97–128. ISBN 978-0231174879.
  39. ^ Bryan Van Norden, Buddhism Comes to China, retrieved 2021-12-29
  40. ^ Tiwald, Justin; Van Norden, Bryan W. eds. (2005), Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, p. 101. Hackett Publishing.
  41. ^ Levine, J. 1983. “Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap”. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64: 354–361.
  42. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r Weisberg, Josh. "The Hard Problem of Consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  43. ^ Seager, William. "Are Zombies Logically Possible?". www.utsc.utoronto.ca. Retrieved 2020-09-03.
  44. ^ Kaszniak, Alfred W.; Scott, Andrew C. (2007). "Zombie Killer". Association of Scientific Studies of Consciousness. S2CID 14891432.
  45. ^ Polger, Tom. "Zombies: Entry". host.uniroma3.it. Retrieved 2020-09-03.
  46. ^ Kirk, Robert (2019), "Zombies", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-09-03
  47. ^ a b David Chalmers (1996) The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, pp. 153–56. Oxford University Press, New York, ISBN 0-19-511789-1 (Pbk.)
  48. ^ Dennett, Daniel (1999), "The Zombie Hunch: Extinction of an Intuition?", Royal Institute of Philosophy Millennial Lecture
  49. ^ a b c Martine Nida-Rümelin; Donnchadh O Conaill (2019). "Qualia: The Knowledge Argument". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2020-09-03.
  50. ^ a b c Bourget, David; Chalmers, David J. (2020). "Philosophers on Philosophy: The 2020 PhilPapers Survey". Philosophers' Imprint.
  51. ^ Bourget, David; Chalmers, David J. (2014). "What Do Philosophers Believe?". Philosophical Studies. 170 (3): 465–500. doi:10.1007/s11098-013-0259-7. S2CID 254936498.
  52. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Chalmers, David (2003). "Consciousness and its Place in Nature". In Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (eds.). Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 102–142. doi:10.1002/9780470998762.ch5. ISBN 9780470998762.
  53. ^ Boutel, Adrian (2013). "How to be a Type-C Physicalist". Philosophical Studies. 164 (2): 301–320. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-9854-2. S2CID 254941872.
  54. ^ a b Majeed, Raamy (September 2016). "The hard problem & its explanatory targets". Ratio. 29 (3): 298–311. doi:10.1111/rati.12103.
  55. ^ a b Levin, Janet (2008). "Taking Type-B Materialism Seriously". Mind and Language. 23 (4): 402–425. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2008.00349.x.
  56. ^ Mandik, Pete; Weisberg, Josh (2008). Wrenn, Chase (ed.). Type-Q Materialism. Peter Lang Publishing Group.
  57. ^ Pereira, Roberto Horácio Sá (2016). "In Defence of Type-A Materialism". Diametros. 49 (49): 68–83. doi:10.13153/diam.49.2016.921.
  58. ^ Yetter-Chappell, Helen (2017). "Dissolving Type-B Physicalism". Philosophical Perspectives. 31 (1): 469–498. doi:10.1111/phpe.12099.
  59. ^ a b c Ramsey, William (2019). "Eliminative Materialism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 April 2019.
  60. ^ a b c Frankish, K. (2016). "Illusionism as a theory of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23 (11–12): 11–39.
  61. ^ Dennett, D. (2016). "Illusionism as an obvious default theory of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23 (11–12): 65–72.
  62. ^ Carruthers, Peter (2016). "Higher-order theories of consciousness". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  63. ^ Carruthers, Peter (2005). "Phenomenal concepts and higher-order experiments". Consciousness: essays from a higher-order perspective. Oxford University Press. pp. 79 ff. ISBN 978-0191535048.
  64. ^ Carruthers, Glenn; Schier, Elizabeth (2012). "Dissolving the hard problem of consciousness" (PDF). Consciousness Online fourth conference. Retrieved 7 July 2014.
  65. ^ Stango, Marco (Summer 2017). "A Deweyan assessment of three major tendencies in philosophy of consciousness". Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 53 (3): 466–490. doi:10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.53.3.06. S2CID 148690536.
  66. ^ Harris, Sam. "Making Sense #96". SamHarris.org. Sam Harris. Retrieved 27 August 2020. (25.45) TM:I think it will not be a mystery. Life is not a mystery anymore, but a hundred and fifty years ago many people thought that this is an irreducible mystery. (25:57) Harris:So you're not a fan anymore, if you ever were, of the framing by David Chalmers of the Hard Problem of Consciousness? Metzinger: No, that's so boring. I mean, that's last century. I mean, you know, we all respect Dave [Chalmers], and we know he is very smart and has got a very fast mind, no debate about that. But conceivability arguments are just very, very weak. If you have an ill-defined folk psychological umbrella term like "consciousness", then you can pull off all kinds of scenarios and zombie thought experiments. It doesn't really… It helped to clarify some issues in the mid 90's, but the consciousness community has listened to this and just moved on. I mean nobody of the serious researchers in the field thinks about this anymore, but it has taken on like a folkloristic life of its own. A lot of people talk about the Hard Problem who wouldn't be able to state what it consists in now.
  67. ^ Garrett, Brian Jonathan (May 2006). "What the History of Vitalism Teaches Us About Consciousness and the 'Hard Problem'". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 72 (3): 576–588. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00584.x.
  68. ^ a b c Hacker, Peter (2010). "Hacker's challenge". The Philosophers' Magazine. 51 (51): 23–32. doi:10.5840/tpm2010517.
  69. ^ Schaal, David W. (2005). "Naming Our Concerns About Neuroscience: A Review of Bennett and Hacker's Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience". Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior. 84 (3): 683–692. doi:10.1901/jeab.2005.83-05. PMC 1389787. PMID 16596986.
  70. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel (2016). "Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23 (11–12): 65–72.
  71. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (1979). "On the Absence of Phenomenology". In Gustafson, Donald F.; Tapscott, Bangs L. (eds.). Body, Mind, and Method. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 93–113.
  72. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Penguin Books.
  73. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel C. (2003). "Explaining the 'magic' of consciousness". Journal of Cultural and Evolutionary Psychology. 1 (1): 7–19. doi:10.1556/jcep.1.2003.1.2. S2CID 144560246.
  74. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company. ISBN 978-0316180658.
  75. ^ a b Anthis, Jacy (2022). "Consciousness Semanticism: A Precise Eliminativist Theory of Consciousness". Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures 2021. Studies in Computational Intelligence. Vol. 1032. pp. 20–41. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-96993-6_3. ISBN 978-3-030-96992-9. Retrieved 7 August 2022.
  76. ^ Irvine, Elizabeth (2013). Consciousness as a scientific concept: a philosophy of science perspective. Studies in brain and mind. Vol. 5. Dordrecht; New York: Springer-Verlag. p. 167. ISBN 9789400751729.
  77. ^ a b c d Chalmers, David (2018). "The Meta-Problem of Consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 25 (9–10): 6–61. Retrieved 6 February 2019.
  78. ^ Graziano, Michael (2013). Consciousness and the social brain. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0190263195.
  79. ^ Michael Graziano (10 July 2015). "Build-a-brain". aeon.co. Retrieved 19 April 2018.
  80. ^ Scarfone, Matthew (2022). "Using and Abusing Moorean Arguments". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 8 (1): 52–71. doi:10.1017/apa.2020.47. S2CID 239672728.
  81. ^ Augustine of Hippo. "Book 11, Chapter 26". City of God.
  82. ^ Descartes, René (1637). "4". Discourse on the Method.
  83. ^ Descartes, René (1641). "Second Meditation". Meditations on First Philosophy.
  84. ^ Chalmers, David (2020). "Debunking Arguments for Illusionism". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 27 (5–6): 258–281.
  85. ^ Chalmers, David (2002). "Debunking Arguments for Illusionism". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 27 (5–6): 258–281.
  86. ^ Strawson, G. (2018). "The Consciousness Deniers". The New York Review of Books.
  87. ^ Koch, Christof (2019). The Feeling of Life Itself: Why Consciousness is Everywhere But Can't be Computed. MIT Press. p. 2.
  88. ^ Koch, Christof (2019). The Feeling of Life Itself: Why Consciousness is Everywhere But Can't be Computed. MIT Press. p. 3.
  89. ^ Balmer, A. (2020). "Soft-Wired Illusionism vs. the Meta-Problem of Consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 27 (5–6): 26–37.
  90. ^ a b c d Chalmers, David (2020). "Is the Hard Problem of Consciousness Universal?". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 27 (5–6): 227–257.
  91. ^ Papineau, D. (2019). "Response to Chalmers' 'The Meta-Problem of Consciousness'". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 26 (9–10): 173–181.
  92. ^ a b J. Levine, "Conceivability, Identity, and the Explanatory Gap" in Stuart R. Hameroff, Alfred W. Kaszniak and David Chalmers (eds.), Towards a Science of Consciousness III: The Third Tucson Discussions and Debates, The MIT Press, 1999,. pp 3–12.
  93. ^ Gennaro, Rocco J. "Consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  94. ^ Block, Ned; Stalnaker, Robert (1999). "Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the Explanatory Gap" (PDF). The Philosophical Review. 108 (1): 1–46. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.693.2421. doi:10.2307/2998259. JSTOR 2998259.
  95. ^ Stoljar, Daniel (2005). "Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts". Mind & Language. 20 (5): 469–494. doi:10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00296.x.
  96. ^ Chalmers, David (2006). "Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap" (PDF). In Alter, Torin; Walter, Sven (eds.). Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195171655. Retrieved 27 March 2019.
  97. ^ a b c Wierzbicka, A. (2019). "From 'Consciousness' to 'I Think, I Feel, I Know': A Commentary on David Chalmers". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 26 (9–10): 257–269.
  98. ^ Lau, Hakwan; Michel, Matthias (2019). "A Socio-Historical Take on the Meta-Problem of Consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 26 (9–10): 136–147.
  99. ^ a b c Calef, Scott (2014). "Dualism and Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 February 2019.
  100. ^ Nida-Rümelin, Martine (2006). "Dualist Emergentism" (PDF). In McLaughlin, Brian; Cohen, Jonathan (eds.). Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind (1st ed.). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-405-11761-6. Retrieved 1 February 2019.
  101. ^ Jackson, Frank (1982). "Epiphenomenal Qualia". The Philosophical Quarterly. 32 (127): 127–136. doi:10.2307/2960077. JSTOR 2960077.
  102. ^ Jackson, Frank (1986). "What Mary Didn't Know". The Journal of Philosophy. 83 (5): 291–295. doi:10.2307/2026143. JSTOR 2026143. S2CID 19000667.
  103. ^ Jackson, Frank (2003). "Mind and Illusion". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements. 53: 251–271. doi:10.1017/S1358246100008365. S2CID 170304272. Retrieved 6 February 2019.
  104. ^ a b c Chalmers, David (2016). "Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism". In Bruntrup, Godehard; Jaskolla, Ludwig (eds.). Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 19–47. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199359943.003.0002. ISBN 9780199359967.
  105. ^ a b Stubenberg, Leopold (2016). "Neutral monism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
  106. ^ Koch, Christof (January 2014). "Is Consciousness Universal?". Scientific American. doi:10.1038/scientificamericanmind0114-26. Retrieved 13 September 2018.
  107. ^ a b c d e Goff, Philip; Seager, William; Allen-Hermanson, Sean (2017). "Panpsychism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
  108. ^ Brüntrup, Godehard; Jaskolla, Ludwig (2016). "Introduction". In Bruntrup, Godehard; Jaskolla, Ludwig (eds.). Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 1–16. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199359943.003.0001. ISBN 9780199359967.
  109. ^ Skrbina, David. "Panpsychism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 February 2019.
  110. ^ a b Strawson, Galen (2006). "Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 13 (10/11): 3–31. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
  111. ^ Goff, Philip (2017). "The Case for Panpsychism". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 3 October 2018.
  112. ^ Kastrup, Bernardo (2018). "The Universe in Consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 25 (5–6): 125–155.
  113. ^ Shani, Itay; Keppler, Joachim (2018). "Beyond combination: how cosmic consciousness grounds ordinary experience". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 4 (3): 390–410. doi:10.1017/apa.2018.30. S2CID 125246376.
  114. ^ Shani, Itay (2015). "Cosmopsychism: A holistic approach to the metaphysics of experience". Philosophical Papers. 44 (3): 389–437. doi:10.1080/05568641.2015.1106709. S2CID 146624784.
  115. ^ Albahari, Miri (2019). "Perennial Idealism: A Mystical Solution to the Mind–Body Problem". Philosophers' Imprint. 19 (44): 1–37. S2CID 211538796.
  116. ^ Kastrup, Bernardo (2018). "Conflating abstraction with empirical observation: The false mind-matter dichotomy". Constructivist Foundations. 13 (3).
  117. ^ Kastrup, Bernardo (2019). Analytic Idealism: A consciousness-only ontology (PhD Thesis). Radboud University Nijmegen.
  118. ^ Hoffman, Donald D. (2008). "Conscious Realism and the Mind–Body Problem". Mind and Matter. 6 (1): 87–121. S2CID 3175512.
  119. ^ Chalmers, David J. (2020). "Idealism and the Mind–Body Problem" (PDF). In Seager, William (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Panpsychism. Routledge. ISBN 978-1138817135. Retrieved 2 December 2019. Overall, I think cosmic idealism is the most promising version of idealism, and is about as promising as any version of panpsychism. It should be on the list of the handful of promising approaches to the mind–body problem.
  120. ^ a b c d McGinn, Colin (1989). "Can We Solve the Mind–Body Problem?". Mind. 98 (391): 349–366. doi:10.1093/mind/XCVIII.391.349. JSTOR 2254848.
  121. ^ Fasching, W. Prakāśa. "A few reflections on the Advaitic understanding of consciousness as presence and its relevance for philosophy of mind." Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09690-2
  122. ^ Dennett, Daniel (2014). "The Hard Problem". Edge.org. Retrieved 11 April 2019.
  123. ^ Koch, Christof; Massimini, Marcello; Boly, Melanie; Tononi, Giulio (April 2016). "Neural correlates of consciousness: Progress and problems". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 17 (5): 307–321. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.22. PMID 27094080. S2CID 5395332. Retrieved 14 April 2018.
  124. ^ a b Chalmers, David (1998). "On the Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness" (PDF). In Hameroff, Stuart; Kaszniak, Alfred; Scott, Alwyn (eds.). Toward a Science of Consciousness II. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262082624. Retrieved 17 April 2018.
  125. ^ a b c Kandel Eric R. (2007). In search of memory: The emergence of a new science of mind. W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 380–382. ISBN 978-0393329377.
  126. ^ Blackmore, Susan (2014). "The Neural Correlates of Consciousness". Edge.org. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  127. ^ Krohn, Stephan; Ostwald, Dirk (2017). "Computing integrated information". Neuroscience of Consciousness. 2017 (1): nix017. doi:10.1093/nc/nix017. PMC 6007153. PMID 30042849.
  128. ^ a b c d Cerullo, Michael A. (September 2015). Kording, Konrad P. (ed.). "The Problem with Phi: A Critique of Integrated Information Theory". PLOS Computational Biology. 11 (9): e1004286. Bibcode:2015PLSCB..11E4286C. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1004286. PMC 4574706. PMID 26378789.
  129. ^ Mørch, Hedda Hassel (2017). "The Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  130. ^ Oizumi, Masafumi; Albantakis, Larissa; Tononi, Giulio (May 2014). "From the Phenomenology to the Mechanisms of Consciousness: Integrated Information Theory 3.0". PLOS Computational Biology. 10 (5): e1003588. Bibcode:2014PLSCB..10E3588O. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003588. PMC 4014402. PMID 24811198.
  131. ^ Mindt, Garrett (2017). "The Problem with the 'Information' in Integrated Information Theory" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 24 (7–8): 130–154. Retrieved 22 February 2022.
  132. ^ a b c Baars, Bernard J. (2005). "Global workspace theory of consciousness: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience". The Boundaries of Consciousness: Neurobiology and Neuropathology. Progress in Brain Research. Vol. 150. pp. 45–53. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.456.2829. doi:10.1016/S0079-6123(05)50004-9. ISBN 9780444518514. PMID 16186014.
  133. ^ Dehaene, Stanislas; Naccache, Lionel (2001). "Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: basic evidence and a workspace framework" (PDF). Cognition. 79 (1–2): 1–37. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00123-2. PMID 11164022. S2CID 1762431. Retrieved 5 April 2019.
  134. ^ Dalton, J. W. (1997). "The unfinished theatre". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (4): 316–318.
  135. ^ Elitzur, Avshalom C. (1997). "Why don't we know what Mary knows? Baars' reversing the problem of qualia". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (4): 319–324.
  136. ^ The Meta-Problem of Consciousness | Professor David Chalmers | Talks at Google, retrieved 2022-01-11
  137. ^ Stoppard, Tom (28 January 2015). "First Person". Programme notes. London: Royal National Theatre.

External links edit

hard, problem, consciousness, other, uses, hard, problem, disambiguation, philosophy, mind, hard, problem, consciousness, explain, humans, other, organisms, have, qualia, phenomenal, consciousness, subjective, experiences, contrasted, with, easy, problems, exp. For other uses see Hard problem disambiguation In philosophy of mind the hard problem of consciousness is to explain why and how humans and other organisms have qualia phenomenal consciousness or subjective experiences 1 2 It is contrasted with the easy problems of explaining why and how physical systems give a healthy human being the ability to discriminate to integrate information and to perform behavioral functions such as watching listening speaking including generating an utterance that appears to refer to personal behaviour or belief and so forth 1 The easy problems are amenable to functional explanation that is explanations that are mechanistic or behavioral since each physical system can be explained at least in principle purely by reference to the structure and dynamics that underpin the phenomenon 3 4 1 Proponents of the hard problem argue that it is categorically different from the easy problems since no mechanistic or behavioral explanation could explain the character of an experience not even in principle Even after all the relevant functional facts are explicated they argue there will still remain a further question why is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience 1 To bolster their case proponents of the hard problem frequently turn to various philosophical thought experiments involving philosophical zombies which they claim are conceivable or inverted qualia or the claimed ineffability of colour experiences or the claimed unknowability of foreign states of consciousness such as the experience of being a bat Chalmers on stage for an Alan Turing Year event at De La Salle University Manila 27 March 2012The terms hard problem and easy problems were coined by the philosopher David Chalmers in a 1994 talk given at The Science of Consciousness conference held in Tucson Arizona 5 The following year the main talking points of Chalmers talk were then published in The Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 The publication gained significant attention from consciousness researchers and became the subject of a special volume of the journal 6 7 which was later published into a book 8 In 1996 Chalmers published The Conscious Mind a book length treatment of the hard problem in which he elaborated on his core arguments and responded to counterarguments His use of the word easy is tongue in cheek 9 As the cognitive psychologist Steven Pinker puts it they are about as easy as going to Mars or curing cancer That is scientists more or less know what to look for and with enough brainpower and funding they would probably crack it in this century 10 The existence of the hard problem is disputed It has been accepted by some philosophers of mind such as Joseph Levine 11 Colin McGinn 12 and Ned Block 13 and cognitive neuroscientists such as Francisco Varela 14 Giulio Tononi 15 16 and Christof Koch 15 16 On the other hand its existence is denied by other philosophers of mind such as Daniel Dennett 17 Massimo Pigliucci 18 Thomas Metzinger Patricia Churchland 19 and Keith Frankish 20 and by cognitive neuroscientists such as Stanislas Dehaene 21 Bernard Baars 22 Anil Seth 23 and Antonio Damasio 24 Clinical neurologist and skeptic Steven Novella has dismissed it as the hard non problem 25 According to a 2020 PhilPapers survey a majority 62 42 of the philosophers surveyed said they believed that the hard problem is a genuine problem while 29 72 said that it does not exist 26 Contents 1 Overview 1 1 Chalmers formulation 1 1 1 Easy problems 1 1 2 Hard problem 1 1 3 How the easy and hard problems are related 1 1 4 Implications for physicalism 1 2 Historical precedents 1 3 Related concepts 1 3 1 The mind body problem 1 3 2 What Is It Like to Be a Bat 1 3 3 Explanatory gap 1 3 4 Philosophical zombies 1 3 5 Knowledge argument 2 Philosophical responses 2 1 Type A Materialism 2 1 1 Strong reductionism 2 1 2 Eliminative materialism Illusionism 2 1 2 1 Criticisms 2 2 Type B Materialism 2 2 1 The hard wired view 2 2 2 The soft wired view 2 3 Type C Materialism 2 4 Type D Dualism 2 5 Type E Dualism 2 6 Type F Monism 2 6 1 Idealism and cosmopsychism 2 7 New mysterianism 2 8 Commentary on the problem s explanatory targets 3 Relationship to scientific frameworks 3 1 Neural correlates of consciousness 3 2 Integrated information theory 3 3 Global workspace theory 4 Meta problem 5 In popular culture 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 External linksOverview editDavid Chalmers first formulated the hard problem in his paper Facing up to the problem of consciousness 1995 3 and expanded upon it in The Conscious Mind 1996 His works provoked comment Some such as David Lewis and Steven Pinker have praised Chalmers for his argumentative rigour and impeccable clarity 27 Pinker later said in 2018 In the end I still think that the hard problem is a meaningful conceptual problem but agree with Dennett that it is not a meaningful scientific problem No one will ever get a grant to study whether you are a zombie or whether the same Captain Kirk walks on the deck of the Enterprise and the surface of Zakdorn And I agree with several other philosophers that it may be futile to hope for a solution at all precisely because it is a conceptual problem or more accurately a problem with our concepts 28 Daniel Dennett and Patricia Churchland among others believe that the hard problem is best seen as a collection of easy problems that will be solved through further analysis of the brain and behaviour 29 30 Consciousness is an ambiguous term It can be used to mean self consciousness awareness the state of being awake and so on Chalmers uses Thomas Nagel s definition of consciousness the feeling of what it is like to be something Consciousness in this sense is synonymous with experience 31 27 Chalmers formulation edit even when we have explained the performance of all the cognitive and behavioral functions in the vicinity of experience perceptual discrimination categorization internal access verbal report there may still remain a further unanswered question Why is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience David Chalmers Facing up to the problem of consciousness The problems of consciousness Chalmers argues are of two kinds the easy problems and the hard problem Easy problems edit The easy problems are amenable to reductive inquiry They are a logical consequence of lower level facts about the world similar to how a clock s ability to tell time is a logical consequence of its clockwork and structure or a hurricane a logical consequence of the structures and functions of certain weather patterns A clock a hurricane and the easy problems are all the sum of their parts as are most things 27 The easy problems relevant to consciousness concern mechanistic analysis of the neural processes that accompany behaviour Examples of these include how sensory systems work how sensory data is processed in the brain how that data influences behaviour or verbal reports the neural basis of thought and emotion and so on They are problems that can be analyzed through structures and functions 27 Hard problem edit The hard problem in contrast is the problem of why and how those processes are accompanied by experience 3 It may further include the question of why these processes are accompanied by this or that particular experience rather than some other kind of experience In other words the hard problem is the problem of explaining why certain mechanisms are accompanied by conscious experience 27 For example why should neural processing in the brain lead to the felt sensations of say feelings of hunger And why should those neural firings lead to feelings of hunger rather than some other feeling such as for example feelings of thirst Chalmers argues that it is conceivable that the relevant behaviours associated with hunger or any other feeling could occur even in the absence of that feeling This suggests that experience is irreducible to physical systems such as the brain This is the topic of the next section How the easy and hard problems are related edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed September 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Chalmers believes that the hard problem is irreducible to the easy problems solving the easy problems will not lead to a solution to the hard problems This is because the easy problems pertain to the causal structure of the world while the hard problem pertains to consciousness and facts about consciousness include facts that go beyond mere causal or structural description For example suppose someone were to stub their foot and yelp In this scenario the easy problems are mechanistic explanations that involve the activity of the nervous system and brain and its relation to the environment such as the propagation of nerve signals from the toe to the brain the processing of that information and how it leads to yelping and so on The hard problem is the question of why these mechanisms are accompanied by the feeling of pain or why these feelings of pain feel the particular way that they do Chalmers argues that facts about the neural mechanisms of pain and pain behaviours do not lead to facts about conscious experience Facts about conscious experience are instead further facts not derivable from facts about the brain 27 nbsp The hard problem is often illustrated by appealing to the logical possibility of inverted visible spectra If there is no logical contradiction in supposing that one s colour vision could be inverted it follows that mechanistic explanations of visual processing do not determine facts about what it is like to see colours An explanation for all of the relevant physical facts about neural processing would leave unexplained facts about what it is like to feel pain This is in part because functions and physical structures of any sort could conceivably exist in the absence of experience Alternatively they could exist alongside a different set of experiences For example it is logically possible for a perfect replica of Chalmers to have no experience at all or for it to have a different set of experiences such as an inverted visible spectrum so that the blue yellow red green axes of its visual field are flipped The same cannot be said about clocks hurricanes or other physical things In those cases a structural or functional description is a complete description A perfect replica of a clock is a clock a perfect replica of a hurricane is a hurricane and so on The difference is that physical things are nothing more than their physical constituents For example water is nothing more than H2O molecules and understanding everything about H2O molecules is to understand everything there is to know about water But consciousness is not like this Knowing everything there is to know about the brain or any physical system is not to know everything there is to know about consciousness Consciousness then must not be purely physical 27 Implications for physicalism edit See also Physicalism Chalmers s idea contradicts physicalism sometimes labelled materialism This is the view that everything that exists is a physical or material thing so everything can be reduced to microphysical things such as subatomic particles and the interactions between them For example a desk is a physical thing because it is nothing more than a complex arrangement of a large number of subatomic particles interacting in a certain way According to physicalism everything including consciousness can be explained by appeal to its microphysical constituents Chalmers s hard problem presents a counterexample to this view since it suggests that consciousness cannot be reductively explained by appealing to its microphysical constituents Thus if the hard problem is a real problem then physicalism must be false and if physicalism is true then the hard problem must not be a real problem citation needed Though Chalmers rejects physicalism he is still a naturalist 27 importance Historical precedents edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Hard problem of consciousness The hard problem of consciousness has scholarly antecedents considerably earlier than Chalmers Chalmers himself notes that a number of thinkers in the recent and distant past have recognised the particular difficulties of explaining consciousness 32 He states that all his original 1996 paper contributed to the discussion was a catchy name a minor reformulation of philosophically familiar points 32 Among others thinkers who have made arguments similar to Chalmers formulation of the hard problem include Isaac Newton 33 John Locke 34 Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 35 33 John Stuart Mill 36 and Thomas Henry Huxley 37 33 Likewise Asian philosophers like Dharmakirti and Guifeng Zongmi discussed the problem of how consciousness arises from unconscious matter 33 38 39 40 Related concepts edit The mind body problem edit Main article Mind body problem The mind body problem is the problem of how the mind and the body relate The mind body problem is more general than the hard problem of consciousness since it is the problem of discovering how the mind and body relate in general thereby implicating any theoretical framework that broaches the topic The hard problem in contrast is often construed as a problem uniquely faced by physicialist or materialist theories of mind What Is It Like to Be a Bat edit Main article What Is It Like to Be a Bat The philosopher Thomas Nagel posited in his 1974 paper What Is It Like to Be a Bat that experiences are essentially subjective accessible only to the individual undergoing them i e felt only by the one feeling them while physical states are essentially objective accessible to multiple individuals So he argued we have no idea what it could mean to claim that an essentially subjective state just is an essentially non subjective state i e that a felt state is nothing but a functional state In other words we have no idea of what reductivism amounts to 31 He believes every subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with a single point of view and it seems inevitable that an objective physical theory will abandon that point of view 31 Explanatory gap edit Main article Explanatory gap See also Reductionism In 1983 the philosopher Joseph Levine proposed that there is an explanatory gap between our understanding of the physical world and our understanding of consciousness 41 Levine s disputes that conscious states are reducible to neuronal or brain states He uses the example of pain as an example of a conscious state and its reduction to the firing of c fibers a kind of nerve cell The difficulty is as follows even if consciousness is physical it is not clear which physical states correspond to which conscious states The bridges between the two levels of description will be contingent rather than necessary This is significant because in most contexts relating two scientific levels of descriptions such as physics and chemistry is done with the assurance of necessary connections between the two theories for example chemistry follows with necessity from physics 42 Levine illustrates this with a thought experiment Suppose that humanity were to encounter an alien species and suppose it is known that the aliens do not have any c fibers Even if one knows this it is not obvious that the aliens do not feel pain that would remain an open question This is because the fact that aliens do not have c fibers does not entail that they do not feel pain in other words feelings of pain do not follow with logical necessity from the firing of c fibers Levine thinks such thought experiments demonstrate an explanatory gap between consciousness and the physical world even if consciousness is reducible to physical things consciousness cannot be explained in terms of physical things because the link between physical things and consciousness is contingent link 42 Levine does not think that the explanatory gap means that consciousness is not physical he is open to the idea that the explanatory gap is only an epistemological problem for physicalism 42 In contrast Chalmers thinks that the hard problem of consciousness does show that consciousness is not physical 27 Philosophical zombies edit Main article Philosophical zombie Philosophical zombies are a thought experiment commonly used in discussions of the hard problem 43 44 They are hypothetical beings physically identical to humans but that lack conscious experience 45 Philosophers such as Chalmers Joseph Levine and Francis Kripke take zombies as impossible within the bounds of nature but possible within the bounds of logic 46 This would imply that facts about experience are not logically entailed by the physical facts Therefore consciousness is irreducible In Chalmers words after God hypothetically created the world he had more work to do 47 Daniel Dennett a philosopher of mind criticised the field s use of the zombie hunch which he deems an embarrassment 48 that ought to be dropped like a hot potato 29 Knowledge argument edit Main article Knowledge argument The knowledge argument also known as Mary s Room is another common thought experiment A hypothetical neuroscientist named Mary has lived her whole life in a black and white room and has never seen colour before She also happens to know everything there is to know about the brain and colour perception 49 Chalmers believes 47 page needed that when Mary sees the colour red for the first time she gains new knowledge the knowledge of what red looks like which is distinct from and irreducible to her prior physical knowledge of the brain or visual system A stronger form of the knowledge argument 49 claims not merely that Mary would lack subjective knowledge of what red looks like but that she would lack knowledge of an objective fact about the world namely what red looks like a non physical fact that can be learned only through direct experience qualia Others such as Thomas Nagel take a physicalist position disagree with the argument in its stronger and or weaker forms 49 For example Nagel put forward a speculative proposal of devising a language that could explain to a person blind from birth what it is like to see 31 The knowledge argument implies that such a language could not exist Philosophical responses editDavid Chalmers formulation of the hard problem of consciousness provoked considerable debate within philosophy of mind as well as scientific research 42 nbsp A diagram showing the relationship between various views concerning the relationship between consciousness and the physical worldThe hard problem is considered a problem primarily for physicalist views of the mind the view that the mind is a physical object or process since physical explanations tend to be functional or structural Because of this some physicalists have responded to the hard problem by seeking to show that it dissolves upon analysis Other researchers accept the problem as real and seek to develop a theory of consciousness place in the world that can solve it by either modifying physicalism or abandoning it in favour of an alternative ontology such as panpsychism or dualism A third response has been to accept the hard problem as real but deny human cognitive faculties can solve it PhilPapers is an organization that archives academic philosophy papers and periodically surveys professional philosophers about their views It can be used to gauge professional attitudes towards the hard problem As of the 2020 survey results it seems that the majority of philosophers 62 42 agree that the hard problem is real with a substantial minority that disagrees 29 76 50 Attitudes towards physicalism also differ among professionals In the 2009 PhilPapers survey 56 5 of philosophers surveyed subscribed to physicalism and 27 1 of philosophers surveyed rejected physicalism 16 4 fell into the other category 51 In the 2020 PhilPapers survey 51 93 of philosophers surveyed indicated that they accept or lean towards physicalism and 32 08 indicated that they reject physicalism 6 23 were agnostic or undecided 50 Different solutions have been proposed to the hard problem of consciousness The sections below taxonomizes the various responses to the hard problem The shape of this taxonomy was first introduced by Chalmers in a 2003 literature review on the topic 52 The labelling convention of this taxonomy has been incorporated into the technical vocabulary of analytic philosophy being used by philosophers such as Adrian Boutel 53 Raamy Majeed 54 Janet Levin 55 Pete Mandik amp Josh Weisberg 56 Roberto Pereira 57 and Helen Yetter Chappell 58 Type A Materialism edit Further information Reductive materialism and A priori physicalism Type A materialism also known as reductive materialism or a priori physicalism is view characterized by a commitment to physicalism and a full rejection of the hard problem By this view the hard problem either does not exist or is just another easy problem because every fact about the mind is a fact about the performance of various functions or behaviours So once all the relevant functions and behaviours have been accounted for there will not be any facts left over in need of explanation 52 Thinkers who subscribe to type A materialism include Paul and Patricia Churchland Daniel Dennett Keith Frankish and Thomas Metzinger Some type A materialists believe in the reality of phenomenal consciousness but believe it is nothing extra in addition to certain functions or behaviours This view is sometimes referred to as strong reductionism 42 52 Other type A materialists may reject the existence of phenomenal consciousness entirely This view is referred to as eliminative materialism or illusionism 59 60 61 Strong reductionism edit Many philosophers have disputed that there is a hard problem of consciousness distinct from what Chalmers calls the easy problems of consciousness Some among them who are sometimes termed strong reductionists hold that phenomenal consciousness i e conscious experience does exist but that it can be fully understood as reducible to the brain 42 Broadly strong reductionists accept that conscious experience is real but argue it can be fully understood in functional terms as an emergent property of the material brain 42 In contrast to weak reductionists see above strong reductionists reject ideas used to support the existence of a hard problem that the same functional organization could exist without consciousness or that a blind person who understood vision through a textbook would not know everything about sight as simply mistaken intuitions 42 52 A notable family of strong reductionist accounts are the higher order theories of consciousness 62 42 In 2005 the philosopher Peter Carruthers wrote about recognitional concepts of experience that is a capacity to recognize a type of experience when it occurs in one s own mental life and suggested that such a capacity could explain phenomenal consciousness without positing qualia 63 On the higher order view since consciousness is a representation and representation is fully functionally analyzable there is no hard problem of consciousness 42 The philosophers Glenn Carruthers and Elizabeth Schier said in 2012 that the main arguments for the existence of a hard problem philosophical zombies Mary s room and Nagel s bats are only persuasive if one already assumes that consciousness must be independent of the structure and function of mental states i e that there is a hard problem Hence the arguments beg the question The authors suggest that instead of letting our conclusions on the thought experiments guide our theories of consciousness we should let our theories of consciousness guide our conclusions from the thought experiments 64 The philosopher Massimo Pigliucci argued in 2013 that the hard problem is misguided resulting from a category mistake 18 He said Of course an explanation isn t the same as an experience but that s because the two are completely independent categories like colors and triangles It is obvious that I cannot experience what it is like to be you but I can potentially have a complete explanation of how and why it is possible to be you 18 In 2017 the philosopher Marco Stango in a paper on John Dewey s approach to the problem of consciousness which preceded Chalmers formulation of the hard problem by over half a century noted that Dewey s approach would see the hard problem as the consequence of an unjustified assumption that feelings and functional behaviors are not the same physical process For the Deweyan philosopher the hard problem of consciousness is a conceptual fact only in the sense that it is a philosophical mistake the mistake of failing to see that the physical can be had as an episode of immediate sentiency 65 The philosopher Thomas Metzinger likens the hard problem of consciousness to vitalism a formerly widespread view in biology which was not so much solved as abandoned 66 Brian Jonathan Garrett has also argued that the hard problem suffers from flaws analogous to those of vitalism 67 The philosopher Peter Hacker argues that the hard problem is misguided in that it asks how consciousness can emerge from matter whereas in fact sentience emerges from the evolution of living organisms 68 He states The hard problem isn t a hard problem at all The really hard problems are the problems the scientists are dealing with The philosophical problem like all philosophical problems is a confusion in the conceptual scheme 68 Hacker s critique extends beyond Chalmers and the hard problem and is directed against contemporary philosophy of mind and neuroscience more broadly Along with the neuroscientist Max Bennett he has argued that most of contemporary neuroscience remains implicitly dualistic in its conceptualizations and is predicated on the mereological fallacy of ascribing psychological concepts to the brain that can properly be ascribed only to the person as a whole 69 Hacker further states that consciousness studies as it exists today is literally a total waste of time and that the conception of consciousness which they have is incoherent 68 Eliminative materialism Illusionism edit Main article Eliminative materialism Eliminative materialism or eliminativism is the view that many or all of the mental states used in folk psychology i e common sense ways of discussing the mind do not upon scientific examination correspond to real brain mechanisms 59 According the 2020 PhilPapers survey 4 51 of philosophers surveyed subscribe to eliminativism 50 While Patricia Churchland and Paul Churchland have famously applied eliminative materialism to propositional attitudes philosophers including Daniel Dennett Georges Rey and Keith Frankish have applied it to qualia or phenomenal consciousness i e conscious experience 59 On their view it is mistaken not only to believe there is a hard problem of consciousness but to believe phenomenal consciousness exists at all 20 70 This stance has recently taken on the name of illusionism the view that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion The term was popularized by the philosopher Keith Frankish 60 Frankish argues that illusionism is preferable to eliminativism for labelling the view that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion More substantively Frankish argues that illusionism about phenomenal consciousness is preferable to realism about phenomenal consciousness He states Theories of consciousness typically address the hard problem They accept that phenomenal consciousness is real and aim to explain how it comes to exist There is however another approach which holds that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion and aims to explain why it seems to exist 20 Frankish concludes that illusionism replaces the hard problem with the illusion problem the problem of explaining how the illusion of phenomenality arises and why it is so powerful 20 The philosopher Daniel Dennett is another prominent figure associated with illusionism After Frankish published a paper in the Journal of Consciousness Studies titled Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness 60 Dennett responded with his own paper with the spin off title Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness 70 Dennett has been arguing for the illusory status of consciousness since early on in his career For example in 1979 he published a paper titled On the Absence of Phenomenology where he argues for the nonexistence of phenomenal consciousness 71 Similar ideas have been explicated in his 1991 book Consciousness Explained 72 Dennett argues that the so called hard problem will be solved in the process of solving what Chalmers terms the easy problems 17 He compares consciousness to stage magic and its capability to create extraordinary illusions out of ordinary things 73 To show how people might be commonly fooled into overstating the accuracy of their introspective abilities he describes a phenomenon called change blindness a visual process that involves failure to detect scenery changes in a series of alternating images 74 page needed He accordingly argues that consciousness need not be what it seems to be based on introspection To address the question of the hard problem or how and why physical processes give rise to experience Dennett states that the phenomenon of having experience is nothing more than the performance of functions or the production of behavior which can also be referred to as the easy problems of consciousness 17 Thus Dennett argues that the hard problem of experience is included among not separate from the easy problems and therefore they can only be explained together as a cohesive unit 73 Elimativists differ on the role they believe intuitive judgement plays in creating the apparent reality of consciousness The philosopher Jacy Reese Anthis is of the position that this issue is born of an overreliance on intuition calling philosophical discussions on the topic of consciousness a form of intuition jousting 75 But when the issue is tackled with formal argumentation and precise semantics then the hard problem will dissolve 75 The philosopher Elizabeth Irvine in contrast can be read as having the opposite view since she argues that phenomenal properties that is properties of consciousness do not exist in our common sense view of the world She states that the hard problem of consciousness may not be a genuine problem for non philosophers despite its overwhelming obviousness to philosophers 76 A complete illusionist theory of consciousness must include the description of a mechanism by which the illusion of subjective experience is had and reported by people Various philosophers and scientists have proposed possible theories 77 For example in his book Consciousness and the Social Brain neuroscientist Michael Graziano advocates what he calls attention schema theory in which our perception of being conscious is merely an error in perception held by brains which evolved to hold erroneous and incomplete models of their own internal workings just as they hold erroneous and incomplete models of their own bodies and of the external world 78 79 Criticisms edit The main criticisms of eliminative materialism and illusion hinge on the counterintuitive nature of the view Arguments of this form are called Moorean Arguments A Moorean argument seeks to undermine the conclusion of an argument by asserting that the negation of that conclusion is more certain than the premises of the argument 80 The roots of the Moorean Argument against illusionism extend back to Augustine of Hippo who stated that he could not be deceived regarding his own existence since the very act of being deceived secures the existence of a being there to be the recipient of that deception note 1 81 nbsp Wikisource has original text related to this article Descartes Discourse on the Method Part 4 In the Early Modern era these arguments were repopularized by Rene Descartes who coined the now famous phrase Je pense donc je suis I think therefore I am 82 Descartes argued that even if he was maximally deceived because for example an evil demon was manipulating all his senses he would still know with certainty that his mind exists because the state of being deceived requires a mind as a prerequisite 83 This same general argumentative structure is still in use today For example in 2002 David Chalmers published an explicitly Moorean argument against illusionism The argument goes like this The reality of consciousness is more certain than any theoretical commitments to for example physicalism that may be motivating the illusionist to deny the existence of consciousness The reason for this is because we have direct acquaintance with consciousness but we do not have direct acquaintance with anything else including anything that could inform our beliefs in consciousness being an illusion In other words consciousness can be known directly so the reality of consciousness is more certain than any philosophical or scientific theory that says otherwise 84 Chalmers concludes that there is little doubt that something like the Moorean argument is the reason that most people reject illusionism and many find it crazy 85 Eliminative materialism and illusionism have been the subject of criticism within the popular press One highly cited example comes from the philosopher Galen Strawson who wrote an article in the New York Review of Books titled The Consciousness Deniers In it Strawson describes illusionism as the silliest claim ever made next to which every known religious belief is only a little less sensible than the belief that the grass is green 86 Another notable example comes from Christof Koch a neuroscientist and one of the leading proponents of Integrated Information Theory in his popular science book The Feeling of Life Itself In the early pages of the book Koch describes eliminativism as the metaphysical counterpart to Cotard s syndrome a psychiatric condition in which patients deny being alive 87 Koch takes the prevalence of eliminativism as evidence that much of twentieth century analytic philosophy has gone to the dogs 88 Type B Materialism edit Further information Phenomenal concept strategy and A posteriori physicalism Type B Materialism also known as Weak Reductionism or A Posteriori Physicalism is the view the hard problem stems from human psychology and is therefore not indicative of a genuine ontological gap between consciousness and the physical world 42 Like Type A Materialists Type B Materialists are committed to physicalism Unlike Type A Materialists however Type B Materialists do accept inconceivability arguments often cited in support of the hard problem but with a key caveat that inconceivability arguments give us insight only into how the human mind tends to conceptualize the relationship between mind and matter but not into what the true nature of this relationship actually is 42 52 According to this view there is a gap between two ways of knowing introspection and neuroscience that will not be resolved by understanding all the underlying neurobiology but still believe that consciousness and neurobiology are one and the same in reality 42 While Type B Materialists all agree that intuitions about the hard problem are psychological rather than ontological in origin they differ as to whether our intuitions about the hard problem are innate or culturally conditioned This has been dubbed the hard wired soft wired distinction 89 90 In relation to Type B Materialism those who believe that our intuitions about the hard problem are innate and therefore common to all humans subscribe to the hard wired view 90 Those that believe our intuitions are culturally conditioned subscribe to the soft wired view Unless otherwise specified the term Type B Materialism refers to the hard wired view 90 Notable philosophers who subscribe to Type B Materialism include David Papineau 91 Joseph Levine 92 and Janet Levine 55 The hard wired view edit Joseph Levine who formulated the notion of the explanatory gap states The explanatory gap argument doesn t demonstrate a gap in nature but a gap in our understanding of nature 92 He nevertheless contends that full scientific understanding will not close the gap 42 and that analogous gaps do not exist for other identities in nature such as that between water and H2O 93 The philosophers Ned Block and Robert Stalnaker agree that facts about what a conscious experience is like to the one experiencing it cannot be deduced from knowing all the facts about the underlying physiology but by contrast argue that such gaps of knowledge are also present in many other cases in nature such as the distinction between water and H2O 94 13 To explain why these two ways of knowing i e third person scientific observation and first person introspection yield such different understandings of consciousness weak reductionists often invoke the phenomenal concepts strategy which argues the difference stems from our inaccurate phenomenal concepts i e how we think about consciousness not from the nature of consciousness itself 95 96 By this view the hard problem of consciousness stems from a dualism of concepts not from a dualism of properties or substances 42 The soft wired view edit Some consciousness researchers have argued that the hard problem is a cultural artifact unique to contemporary Western Culture This is similar to Type B Materialism but it makes the further claim that the psychological facts that cause us to intuit the hard problem are not innate but culturally conditioned Notable researchers who hold this view include Anna Wierzbicka 97 Hakwan Lau and Matthias Michel 98 Wierzbicka who is a linguist argues that the vocabulary used by consciousness researchers including words like experience and consciousness are not universally translatable and are parochially English 97 Weirzbicka calls David Chalmers out by name for using these words arguing that if philosophers were to use panhuman concepts expressed in crosstranslatable words such as know think or feel then the hard problem would dissolve 97 David Chalmers has responded to these criticisms by saying that he will not apologize for using technical terms in an academic article they play a key role in efficient communication in every discipline including Wierzbicka s 90 Type C Materialism edit This section needs expansion with See talk page You can help by adding to it June 2023 Type D Dualism edit Main articles Dualism philosophy of mind Interactionism philosophy of mind and Epiphenomenalism Dualism views consciousness as either a non physical substance separate from the brain or a non physical property of the physical brain 99 Dualism is the view that the mind is irreducible to the physical body 99 There are multiple dualist accounts of the causal relationship between the mental and the physical of which interactionism and epiphenomenalism are the most common today Interactionism posits that the mental and physical causally impact one another and is associated with the thought of Rene Descartes 1596 1650 52 Epiphenomalism holds the mental is causally dependent on the physical but does not in turn causally impact it 52 In contemporary philosophy interactionism has been defended by philosophers including Martine Nida Rumelin 100 while epiphenomenalism has been defended by philosophers including Frank Jackson 101 102 although Jackson later changed his stance to physicalism 103 Chalmers has also defended versions of both positions as plausible 52 Traditional dualists such as Descartes believed the mental and the physical to be two separate substances or fundamental types of entities hence substance dualism some more recent dualists however accept only one substance the physical but state it has both mental and physical properties hence property dualism 99 Type E Dualism edit This section needs expansion with See talk page You can help by adding to it June 2023 Type F Monism edit Main articles Panpsychism and Neutral monism Meanwhile panpsychism and neutral monism broadly speaking view consciousness as intrinsic to matter 52 In its most basic form panpsychism holds that all physical entities have minds though its proponents take more qualified positions 104 while neutral monism in at least some variations holds that entities are composed of a substance with mental and physical aspects and is thus sometimes described as a type of panpsychism 105 Forms of panpsychism and neutral monism were defended in the early twentieth century by the psychologist William James 106 107 note 2 the philosopher Alfred North Whitehead 107 the physicist Arthur Eddington 108 109 and the philosopher Bertrand Russell 104 105 and interest in these views has been revived in recent decades by philosophers including Thomas Nagel 107 Galen Strawson 107 110 Philip Goff 107 and David Chalmers 104 Chalmers describes his overall view as naturalistic dualism 3 but he says panpsychism is in a sense a form of physicalism 52 as does Strawson 110 Proponents of panpsychism argue it solves the hard problem of consciousness parsimoniously by making consciousness a fundamental feature of reality 42 111 Idealism and cosmopsychism edit Main article Idealism A traditional solution to the hard problem is idealism according to which consciousness is fundamental and not simply an emergent property of matter It is claimed that this avoids the hard problem entirely 112 Objective idealism and cosmopsychism consider mind or consciousness to be the fundamental substance of the universe Proponents claim that this approach is immune to both the hard problem of consciousness and the combination problem that affects panpsychism 113 114 115 From an idealist perspective matter is a representation or image of mental processes Supporters suggest that this avoids the problems associated with the materialist view of mind as an emergent property of a physical brain 116 Critics argue that this then leads to a decombination problem clarification needed in terms of explaining individual subjective experience In response Bernardo Kastrup claims that nature hints at a mechanism for this in the condition dissociative identity disorder previously known as Multiple Personality Disorder 117 Kastrup proposes dissociation as an example from nature showing that multiple minds with their own individual subjective experience could develop within a single universal mind Cognitive psychologist Donald D Hoffman uses a mathematical model based around conscious agents within a fundamentally conscious universe to support conscious realism as a description of nature one that falls within the objective idealism approaches to the hard problem The objective world i e the world whose existence does not depend on the perceptions of a particular conscious agent consists entirely of conscious agents 118 David Chalmers calls this form of idealism one of the handful of promising approaches to the mind body problem 119 New mysterianism edit Main article New mysterianism New mysterianism most significantly associated with the philosopher Colin McGinn proposes that the human mind in its current form will not be able to explain consciousness 120 12 McGinn draws on Noam Chomsky s distinction between problems which are in principle solvable and mysteries which human cognitive faculties are unequipped to ever understand and places the mind body problem in the latter category 120 His position is that a naturalistic explanation does exist but that the human mind is cognitively closed to it due to its limited range of intellectual abilities 120 He cites Jerry Fodor s concept of the modularity of mind in support of cognitive closure 120 While in McGinn s strong form new mysterianism states that the relationship between consciousness and the material world can never be understood by the human mind there are also weaker forms that argue it cannot be understood within existing paradigms but that advances in science or philosophy may open the way to other solutions see above 42 The ideas of Thomas Nagel and Joseph Levine fall into the second category 42 Steven Pinker has also endorsed this weaker version of the view summarizing it as follows 10 And then there is the theory put forward by philosopher Colin McGinn that our vertigo when pondering the Hard Problem is itself a quirk of our brains The brain is a product of evolution and just as animal brains have their limitations we have ours Our brains can t hold a hundred numbers in memory can t visualize seven dimensional space and perhaps can t intuitively grasp why neural information processing observed from the outside should give rise to subjective experience on the inside This is where I place my bet though I admit that the theory could be demolished when an unborn genius a Darwin or Einstein of consciousness comes up with a flabbergasting new idea that suddenly makes it all clear to us Commentary on the problem s explanatory targets edit Philosopher Raamy Majeed argued in 2016 that the hard problem is associated with two explanatory targets 54 PQ Physical processing gives rise to experiences with a phenomenal character Q Our phenomenal qualities are thus and so The first fact concerns the relationship between the physical and the phenomenal i e how and why are some physical states felt states whereas the second concerns the very nature of the phenomenal itself i e what does the felt state feel like Wolfgang Fasching argues that the hard problem is not about qualia but about the what it is like ness of experience in Nagel s sense about the givenness of phenomenal contents Today there is a strong tendency to simply equate consciousness with the qualia Yet there is clearly something not quite right about this The itchiness of itches and the hurtfulness of pain are qualities we are conscious of So philosophy of mind tends to treat consciousness as if it consisted simply of the contents of consciousness the phenomenal qualities while it really is precisely consciousness of contents the very givenness of whatever is subjectively given And therefore the problem of consciousness does not pertain so much to some alleged mysterious nonpublic objects i e objects that seem to be only visible to the respective subject but rather to the nature of seeing itself and in today s philosophy of mind astonishingly little is said about the latter 121 Relationship to scientific frameworks editMost neuroscientists and cognitive scientists believe that Chalmers alleged hard problem will be solved or be shown to not be a real problem in the course of the solution of the so called easy problems although a significant minority disagrees 10 122 better source needed Neural correlates of consciousness edit Further information Neural correlates of consciousness Since 1990 researchers including the molecular biologist Francis Crick and the neuroscientist Christof Koch have made significant progress toward identifying which neurobiological events occur concurrently to the experience of subjective consciousness 123 These postulated events are referred to as neural correlates of consciousness or NCCs However this research arguably addresses the question of which neurobiological mechanisms are linked to consciousness but not the question of why they should give rise to consciousness at all the latter being the hard problem of consciousness as Chalmers formulated it In On the Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness Chalmers said he is confident that granting the principle that something such as what he terms global availability can be used as an indicator of consciousness the neural correlates will be discovered in a century or two 124 Nevertheless he stated regarding their relationship to the hard problem of consciousness One can always ask why these processes of availability should give rise to consciousness in the first place As yet we cannot explain why they do so and it may well be that full details about the processes of availability will still fail to answer this question Certainly nothing in the standard methodology I have outlined answers the question that methodology assumes a relation between availability and consciousness and therefore does nothing to explain it So the hard problem remains But who knows Somewhere along the line we may be led to the relevant insights that show why the link is there and the hard problem may then be solved 124 The neuroscientist and Nobel laureate Eric Kandel wrote that locating the NCCs would not solve the hard problem but rather one of the so called easy problems to which the hard problem is contrasted 125 Kandel went on to note Crick and Koch s suggestion that once the binding problem understanding what accounts for the unity of experience is solved it will be possible to solve the hard problem empirically 125 However neuroscientist Anil Seth argued that emphasis on the so called hard problem is a distraction from what he calls the real problem understanding the neurobiology underlying consciousness namely the neural correlates of various conscious processes 23 This more modest goal is the focus of most scientists working on consciousness 125 Psychologist Susan Blackmore believes by contrast that the search for the neural correlates of consciousness is futile and itself predicated on an erroneous belief in the hard problem of consciousness 126 Integrated information theory edit Further information Integrated information theory Integrated information theory IIT developed by the neuroscientist and psychiatrist Giulio Tononi in 2004 and more recently also advocated by Koch is one of the most discussed models of consciousness in neuroscience and elsewhere 127 128 The theory proposes an identity between consciousness and integrated information with the latter item denoted as F defined mathematically and thus in principle measurable 128 129 The hard problem of consciousness write Tononi and Koch may indeed be intractable when working from matter to consciousness 16 However because IIT inverts this relationship and works from phenomenological axioms to matter they say it could be able to solve the hard problem 16 In this vein proponents have said the theory goes beyond identifying human neural correlates and can be extrapolated to all physical systems Tononi wrote along with two colleagues While identifying the neural correlates of consciousness is undoubtedly important it is hard to see how it could ever lead to a satisfactory explanation of what consciousness is and how it comes about As will be illustrated below IIT offers a way to analyze systems of mechanisms to determine if they are properly structured to give rise to consciousness how much of it and of which kind 130 As part of a broader critique of IIT Michael Cerullo suggested that the theory s proposed explanation is in fact for what he dubs following Scott Aaronson the Pretty Hard Problem of methodically inferring which physical systems are conscious but would not solve Chalmers hard problem 128 Even if IIT is correct he argues it does not explain why integrated information generates or is consciousness 128 Chalmers agrees that IIT if correct would solve the Pretty Hard Problem rather than the hard problem 131 Global workspace theory edit Further information Global workspace theory Global workspace theory GWT is a cognitive architecture and theory of consciousness proposed by the cognitive psychologist Bernard Baars in 1988 132 Baars explains the theory with the metaphor of a theater with conscious processes represented by an illuminated stage 132 This theater integrates inputs from a variety of unconscious and otherwise autonomous networks in the brain and then broadcasts them to unconscious networks represented in the metaphor by a broad unlit audience 132 The theory has since been expanded upon by other scientists including cognitive neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene 133 In his original paper outlining the hard problem of consciousness Chalmers discussed GWT as a theory that only targets one of the easy problems of consciousness 3 In particular he said GWT provided a promising account of how information in the brain could become globally accessible but argued that now the question arises in a different form why should global accessibility give rise to conscious experience As always this bridging question is unanswered 3 J W Dalton similarly criticized GWT on the grounds that it provides at best an account of the cognitive function of consciousness and fails to explain its experiential aspect 134 By contrast A C Elitzur argued While GWT does not address the hard problem namely the very nature of consciousness it constrains any theory that attempts to do so and provides important insights into the relation between consciousness and cognition 135 For his part Baars writes along with two colleagues that there is no hard problem of explaining qualia over and above the problem of explaining causal functions because qualia are entailed by neural activity and themselves causal 22 Dehaene in his 2014 book Consciousness and the Brain rejected the concept of qualia and argued that Chalmers easy problems of consciousness are actually the hard problems 21 He further stated that the hard problem is based only upon ill defined intuitions that are continually shifting as understanding evolves 21 Once our intuitions are educated by cognitive neuroscience and computer simulations Chalmers hard problem will evaporate The hypothetical concept of qualia pure mental experience detached from any information processing role will be viewed as a peculiar idea of the prescientific era much like vitalism Just as science dispatched vitalism the science of consciousness will keep eating away at the hard problem of consciousness until it vanishes Meta problem editIn 2018 Chalmers highlighted what he calls the meta problem of consciousness another problem related to the hard problem of consciousness 77 The meta problem of consciousness is to a first approximation the problem of explaining why we think that there is a hard problem of consciousness In his second approximation he says it is the problem of explaining the behavior of phenomenal reports and the behavior of expressing a belief that there is a hard problem of consciousness 77 Explaining its significance he says 77 Although the meta problem is strictly speaking an easy problem it is deeply connected to the hard problem We can reasonably hope that a solution to the meta problem will shed significant light on the hard problem A particularly strong line holds that a solution to the meta problem will solve or dissolve the hard problem A weaker line holds that it will not remove the hard problem but it will constrain the form of a solution In other words the strong line holds that the solution to the meta problem would provide an explanation of our beliefs about consciousness that is independent of consciousness That would debunk our beliefs about consciousness in the same way that explaining beliefs about god in evolutionary terms may provide arguments against theism itself 136 In popular culture editBritish playwright Sir Tom Stoppard s play The Hard Problem first produced in 2015 is named after the hard problem of consciousness which Stoppard defines as having subjective First Person experiences 137 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portalAnimal consciousness Artificial consciousness Binding problem Blindsight Chinese room Cogito ergo sum Cryonics Free will Ideasthesia Introspection Knowledge by acquaintance List of unsolved problems in biology Mind body problem Phenomenalism Philosophy of self Primary secondary quality distinction Problem of mental causation Problem of other minds Vertiginous question Von Neumann Wigner interpretationNotes edit But without any delusive representations of images or phantasms I am most certain that I am and that I know and delight in this In respect to these truths I am not at all afraid of the arguments of the Academians who say What if you are deceived For if I am deceived I am For he who is not cannot be deceived There has been debate over how best to characterize James position The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states James s commitment to panpsychism remains somewhat controversial since he also advanced a cogent set of objections against a version of the view which he labelled the mind dust theory in chapter six of The Principles of Psychology 1890 1981 These objections are the inspiration for the so called combination problem around which much of the twenty first century literature on panpsychism focuses References edit a b c d Chalmers David 1995 Facing up to the problem of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 3 200 219 Harnad Stevan 1995 Why and how we are not zombies Journal of Consciousness Studies 1 164 167 See also Harnad Stevan April 2000 How why the mind body problem is hard Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 4 54 61 a b c d e f g Chalmers David 1995 Facing up to the problem of consciousness PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 3 200 219 See Cooney s foreword to the reprint of Chalmers paper Brian Cooney ed 1999 Chapter 27 Facing up to the problem of consciousness The place of mind Cengage Learning pp 382 ff ISBN 978 0534528256 Problem of Consciousness Tuscan 1994 JCS vol 4 pp 3 46 1997 Chalmers David 1997 Moving forward on the problem of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 1 3 46 Shear Jonathan 1997 Explaining Consciousness The Hard Problem MIT Press ISBN 978 0262692212 Episode 83 The David Chalmers Interview Part I Consciousness The Panpsycast Philosophy Podcast 19 July 2020 Retrieved 2020 09 05 a b c Pinker Steven 29 January 2007 The Brain The Mystery of Consciousness Time Retrieved 19 December 2018 Levine Joseph 2009 01 15 The Explanatory Gap The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind 281 291 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199262618 003 0017 ISBN 978 0199262618 a b McGinn Colin 20 February 2012 All machine and no ghost New Statesman Retrieved 27 March 2012 a b Block Ned 2002 The Harder Problem of Consciousness The Journal of Philosophy 99 8 391 425 doi 10 2307 3655621 JSTOR 3655621 S2CID 111383062 Varela F J 1 April 1996 Neurophenomenology a methodological remedy for the hard problem Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 4 330 349 a b Tononi Giulio Boly Melanie Massimini Marcello Koch Christof July 2016 Integrated information theory from consciousness to its physical substrate Nature Reviews Neuroscience 17 7 450 461 doi 10 1038 nrn 2016 44 PMID 27225071 S2CID 21347087 a b c d Tononi Giulio Koch Christof March 2015 Consciousness here there and everywhere Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences 370 1668 20140167 doi 10 1098 rstb 2014 0167 PMC 4387509 PMID 25823865 a b c Dennett Daniel C 2013 The tuned deck Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking W W Norton amp Company pp 310 ff ISBN 978 0393240689 and also Commentary on Chalmers Dennett Daniel C 1996 Facing backwards on the problem of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 1 4 6 a b c Massimo Pigliucci 2013 What hard problem PDF Philosophy Now 99 Churchland Patricia 1996 The Hornswoggle Problem PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 5 6 402 408 Retrieved 10 January 2021 a b c d Frankish Keith 2016 Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 11 12 11 39 Retrieved 20 December 2018 a b c Dehaene Stanislas 2014 Consciousness and the brain deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts Viking Adult pp 259 266 ISBN 978 0670025435 a b Edelman Gerald Gally Joseph Baars Bernard 2011 Biology of Consciousness Frontiers in Psychology 2 4 4 doi 10 3389 fpsyg 2011 00004 PMC 3111444 PMID 21713129 a b Seth Anil November 2016 The real problem Aeon Retrieved 22 April 2018 Sean Carroll 29 April 2019 Sean Carroll s Mindscape Preposterousuniverse com Podcast Sean Carroll Event occurs at 1 04 46 I m just saying that the idea of a hard problem that you cannot transpose I think is wrong Psychological Scales The Hard Problem of Consciousness arabpsychology com Retrieved 2023 10 29 PhilPapers Survey 2020 survey2020 philpeople org Retrieved 2022 05 26 a b c d e f g h i Chalmers David 1996 The Conscious Mind New York Oxford University Press pp xii xiii 95 106 backcover Pinker Steven 2018 Enlightenment Now Viking p 481 ISBN 9780525427575 a b Dennett Daniel commentary on T Moody O Flanagan and T Polger The Unimagined Preposterous of Zombies Journal of Consciousness Studies vol 2 no 4 1995 pp 322 326 Churchland Patricia Smith 2005 A neurophilosophical slant on consciousness research Cortical Function A View from the Thalamus Progress in Brain Research Vol 149 pp 285 293 doi 10 1016 S0079 6123 05 49020 2 ISBN 9780444516794 PMID 16226591 a b c d Nagel Thomas October 1974 What is it like to be a bat The Philosophical Review 83 4 435 450 doi 10 2307 2183914 JSTOR 2183914 S2CID 49125889 a b Chalmers David January 1997 Moving forward on the problem of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 1 3 46 a b c d Chalmers David 2020 Is the hard problem of consciousness universal PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 27 5 6 227 257 Retrieved 22 February 2022 Locke John 1722 The works of John Locke in three volumes Vol 1 London Printed for A Churchill and A Manship and sold by W Taylor in Pater noster Row p 293 Leibniz Monadology 17 as quoted by Aranyosi Istvan 2004 Chalmers s zombie arguments PDF draft ed Central European University Personal Pages Mill John Stuart A System of Logic 1843 Book V Chapter V section 3 Huxley Thomas Henry Youmans William Jay 1868 The elements of physiology and hygiene a text book for educational institutions New York D Appleton and company p 178 Arnold Dan 2021 Philosophy of Mind s Hard Problem in Light of Buddhist Idealism In Emmanuel Steven M ed Philosophy s Big Questions Comparing Buddhist and Western Approaches New York Columbia University Press pp 97 128 ISBN 978 0231174879 Bryan Van Norden Buddhism Comes to China retrieved 2021 12 29 Tiwald Justin Van Norden Bryan W eds 2005 Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy p 101 Hackett Publishing Levine J 1983 Materialism and qualia the explanatory gap Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 354 361 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r Weisberg Josh The Hard Problem of Consciousness Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Seager William Are Zombies Logically Possible www utsc utoronto ca Retrieved 2020 09 03 Kaszniak Alfred W Scott Andrew C 2007 Zombie Killer Association of Scientific Studies of Consciousness S2CID 14891432 Polger Tom Zombies Entry host uniroma3 it Retrieved 2020 09 03 Kirk Robert 2019 Zombies in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2020 09 03 a b David Chalmers 1996 The Conscious Mind In Search of a Fundamental Theory pp 153 56 Oxford University Press New York ISBN 0 19 511789 1 Pbk Dennett Daniel 1999 The Zombie Hunch Extinction of an Intuition Royal Institute of Philosophy Millennial Lecture a b c Martine Nida Rumelin Donnchadh O Conaill 2019 Qualia The Knowledge Argument In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2020 09 03 a b c Bourget David Chalmers David J 2020 Philosophers on Philosophy The 2020 PhilPapers Survey Philosophers Imprint Bourget David Chalmers David J 2014 What Do Philosophers Believe Philosophical Studies 170 3 465 500 doi 10 1007 s11098 013 0259 7 S2CID 254936498 a b c d e f g h i j Chalmers David 2003 Consciousness and its Place in Nature In Stich Stephen P Warfield Ted A eds Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind Malden MA Blackwell pp 102 142 doi 10 1002 9780470998762 ch5 ISBN 9780470998762 Boutel Adrian 2013 How to be a Type C Physicalist Philosophical Studies 164 2 301 320 doi 10 1007 s11098 012 9854 2 S2CID 254941872 a b Majeed Raamy September 2016 The hard problem amp its explanatory targets Ratio 29 3 298 311 doi 10 1111 rati 12103 a b Levin Janet 2008 Taking Type B Materialism Seriously Mind and Language 23 4 402 425 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0017 2008 00349 x Mandik Pete Weisberg Josh 2008 Wrenn Chase ed Type Q Materialism Peter Lang Publishing Group Pereira Roberto Horacio Sa 2016 In Defence of Type A Materialism Diametros 49 49 68 83 doi 10 13153 diam 49 2016 921 Yetter Chappell Helen 2017 Dissolving Type B Physicalism Philosophical Perspectives 31 1 469 498 doi 10 1111 phpe 12099 a b c Ramsey William 2019 Eliminative Materialism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 1 April 2019 a b c Frankish K 2016 Illusionism as a theory of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 11 12 11 39 Dennett D 2016 Illusionism as an obvious default theory of consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 11 12 65 72 Carruthers Peter 2016 Higher order theories of consciousness Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Carruthers Peter 2005 Phenomenal concepts and higher order experiments Consciousness essays from a higher order perspective Oxford University Press pp 79 ff ISBN 978 0191535048 Carruthers Glenn Schier Elizabeth 2012 Dissolving the hard problem of consciousness PDF Consciousness Online fourth conference Retrieved 7 July 2014 Stango Marco Summer 2017 A Deweyan assessment of three major tendencies in philosophy of consciousness Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society 53 3 466 490 doi 10 2979 trancharpeirsoc 53 3 06 S2CID 148690536 Harris Sam Making Sense 96 SamHarris org Sam Harris Retrieved 27 August 2020 25 45 TM I think it will not be a mystery Life is not a mystery anymore but a hundred and fifty years ago many people thought that this is an irreducible mystery 25 57 Harris So you re not a fan anymore if you ever were of the framing by David Chalmers of the Hard Problem of Consciousness Metzinger No that s so boring I mean that s last century I mean you know we all respect Dave Chalmers and we know he is very smart and has got a very fast mind no debate about that But conceivability arguments are just very very weak If you have an ill defined folk psychological umbrella term like consciousness then you can pull off all kinds of scenarios and zombie thought experiments It doesn t really It helped to clarify some issues in the mid 90 s but the consciousness community has listened to this and just moved on I mean nobody of the serious researchers in the field thinks about this anymore but it has taken on like a folkloristic life of its own A lot of people talk about the Hard Problem who wouldn t be able to state what it consists in now Garrett Brian Jonathan May 2006 What the History of Vitalism Teaches Us About Consciousness and the Hard Problem Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 3 576 588 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2006 tb00584 x a b c Hacker Peter 2010 Hacker s challenge The Philosophers Magazine 51 51 23 32 doi 10 5840 tpm2010517 Schaal David W 2005 Naming Our Concerns About Neuroscience A Review of Bennett and Hacker s Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 84 3 683 692 doi 10 1901 jeab 2005 83 05 PMC 1389787 PMID 16596986 a b Dennett Daniel 2016 Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 11 12 65 72 Dennett Daniel C 1979 On the Absence of Phenomenology In Gustafson Donald F Tapscott Bangs L eds Body Mind and Method Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 93 113 Dennett Daniel C 1991 Consciousness Explained Penguin Books a b Dennett Daniel C 2003 Explaining the magic of consciousness Journal of Cultural and Evolutionary Psychology 1 1 7 19 doi 10 1556 jcep 1 2003 1 2 S2CID 144560246 Dennett Daniel C 1991 Consciousness explained Boston Little Brown and Company ISBN 978 0316180658 a b Anthis Jacy 2022 Consciousness Semanticism A Precise Eliminativist Theory of Consciousness Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures 2021 Studies in Computational Intelligence Vol 1032 pp 20 41 doi 10 1007 978 3 030 96993 6 3 ISBN 978 3 030 96992 9 Retrieved 7 August 2022 Irvine Elizabeth 2013 Consciousness as a scientific concept a philosophy of science perspective Studies in brain and mind Vol 5 Dordrecht New York Springer Verlag p 167 ISBN 9789400751729 a b c d Chalmers David 2018 The Meta Problem of Consciousness PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 25 9 10 6 61 Retrieved 6 February 2019 Graziano Michael 2013 Consciousness and the social brain Oxford New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0190263195 Michael Graziano 10 July 2015 Build a brain aeon co Retrieved 19 April 2018 Scarfone Matthew 2022 Using and Abusing Moorean Arguments Journal of the American Philosophical Association 8 1 52 71 doi 10 1017 apa 2020 47 S2CID 239672728 Augustine of Hippo Book 11 Chapter 26 City of God Descartes Rene 1637 4 Discourse on the Method Descartes Rene 1641 Second Meditation Meditations on First Philosophy Chalmers David 2020 Debunking Arguments for Illusionism Journal of Consciousness Studies 27 5 6 258 281 Chalmers David 2002 Debunking Arguments for Illusionism Journal of Consciousness Studies 27 5 6 258 281 Strawson G 2018 The Consciousness Deniers The New York Review of Books Koch Christof 2019 The Feeling of Life Itself Why Consciousness is Everywhere But Can t be Computed MIT Press p 2 Koch Christof 2019 The Feeling of Life Itself Why Consciousness is Everywhere But Can t be Computed MIT Press p 3 Balmer A 2020 Soft Wired Illusionism vs the Meta Problem of Consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 27 5 6 26 37 a b c d Chalmers David 2020 Is the Hard Problem of Consciousness Universal Journal of Consciousness Studies 27 5 6 227 257 Papineau D 2019 Response to Chalmers The Meta Problem of Consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 9 10 173 181 a b J Levine Conceivability Identity and the Explanatory Gap in Stuart R Hameroff Alfred W Kaszniak and David Chalmers eds Towards a Science of Consciousness III The Third Tucson Discussions and Debates The MIT Press 1999 pp 3 12 Gennaro Rocco J Consciousness Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Block Ned Stalnaker Robert 1999 Conceptual Analysis Dualism and the Explanatory Gap PDF The Philosophical Review 108 1 1 46 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 693 2421 doi 10 2307 2998259 JSTOR 2998259 Stoljar Daniel 2005 Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts Mind amp Language 20 5 469 494 doi 10 1111 j 0268 1064 2005 00296 x Chalmers David 2006 Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap PDF In Alter Torin Walter Sven eds Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195171655 Retrieved 27 March 2019 a b c Wierzbicka A 2019 From Consciousness to I Think I Feel I Know A Commentary on David Chalmers Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 9 10 257 269 Lau Hakwan Michel Matthias 2019 A Socio Historical Take on the Meta Problem of Consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 9 10 136 147 a b c Calef Scott 2014 Dualism and Mind Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 8 February 2019 Nida Rumelin Martine 2006 Dualist Emergentism PDF In McLaughlin Brian Cohen Jonathan eds Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind 1st ed Malden MA Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 1 405 11761 6 Retrieved 1 February 2019 Jackson Frank 1982 Epiphenomenal Qualia The Philosophical Quarterly 32 127 127 136 doi 10 2307 2960077 JSTOR 2960077 Jackson Frank 1986 What Mary Didn t Know The Journal of Philosophy 83 5 291 295 doi 10 2307 2026143 JSTOR 2026143 S2CID 19000667 Jackson Frank 2003 Mind and Illusion Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 53 251 271 doi 10 1017 S1358246100008365 S2CID 170304272 Retrieved 6 February 2019 a b c Chalmers David 2016 Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism In Bruntrup Godehard Jaskolla Ludwig eds Panpsychism Contemporary Perspectives Oxford UK Oxford University Press pp 19 47 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199359943 003 0002 ISBN 9780199359967 a b Stubenberg Leopold 2016 Neutral monism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 15 September 2018 Koch Christof January 2014 Is Consciousness Universal Scientific American doi 10 1038 scientificamericanmind0114 26 Retrieved 13 September 2018 a b c d e Goff Philip Seager William Allen Hermanson Sean 2017 Panpsychism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 15 September 2018 Bruntrup Godehard Jaskolla Ludwig 2016 Introduction In Bruntrup Godehard Jaskolla Ludwig eds Panpsychism Contemporary Perspectives Oxford UK Oxford University Press pp 1 16 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199359943 003 0001 ISBN 9780199359967 Skrbina David Panpsychism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 8 February 2019 a b Strawson Galen 2006 Realistic monism Why physicalism entails panpsychism PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 10 11 3 31 Retrieved 15 September 2018 Goff Philip 2017 The Case for Panpsychism Philosophy Now Retrieved 3 October 2018 Kastrup Bernardo 2018 The Universe in Consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 25 5 6 125 155 Shani Itay Keppler Joachim 2018 Beyond combination how cosmic consciousness grounds ordinary experience Journal of the American Philosophical Association 4 3 390 410 doi 10 1017 apa 2018 30 S2CID 125246376 Shani Itay 2015 Cosmopsychism A holistic approach to the metaphysics of experience Philosophical Papers 44 3 389 437 doi 10 1080 05568641 2015 1106709 S2CID 146624784 Albahari Miri 2019 Perennial Idealism A Mystical Solution to the Mind Body Problem Philosophers Imprint 19 44 1 37 S2CID 211538796 Kastrup Bernardo 2018 Conflating abstraction with empirical observation The false mind matter dichotomy Constructivist Foundations 13 3 Kastrup Bernardo 2019 Analytic Idealism A consciousness only ontology PhD Thesis Radboud University Nijmegen Hoffman Donald D 2008 Conscious Realism and the Mind Body Problem Mind and Matter 6 1 87 121 S2CID 3175512 Chalmers David J 2020 Idealism and the Mind Body Problem PDF In Seager William ed The Routledge Handbook of Panpsychism Routledge ISBN 978 1138817135 Retrieved 2 December 2019 Overall I think cosmic idealism is the most promising version of idealism and is about as promising as any version of panpsychism It should be on the list of the handful of promising approaches to the mind body problem a b c d McGinn Colin 1989 Can We Solve the Mind Body Problem Mind 98 391 349 366 doi 10 1093 mind XCVIII 391 349 JSTOR 2254848 Fasching W Prakasa A few reflections on the Advaitic understanding of consciousness as presence and its relevance for philosophy of mind Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 2020 https doi org 10 1007 s11097 020 09690 2 Dennett Daniel 2014 The Hard Problem Edge org Retrieved 11 April 2019 Koch Christof Massimini Marcello Boly Melanie Tononi Giulio April 2016 Neural correlates of consciousness Progress and problems Nature Reviews Neuroscience 17 5 307 321 doi 10 1038 nrn 2016 22 PMID 27094080 S2CID 5395332 Retrieved 14 April 2018 a b Chalmers David 1998 On the Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness PDF In Hameroff Stuart Kaszniak Alfred Scott Alwyn eds Toward a Science of Consciousness II Cambridge MA MIT Press ISBN 9780262082624 Retrieved 17 April 2018 a b c Kandel Eric R 2007 In search of memory The emergence of a new science of mind W W Norton amp Company pp 380 382 ISBN 978 0393329377 Blackmore Susan 2014 The Neural Correlates of Consciousness Edge org Retrieved 22 April 2018 Krohn Stephan Ostwald Dirk 2017 Computing integrated information Neuroscience of Consciousness 2017 1 nix017 doi 10 1093 nc nix017 PMC 6007153 PMID 30042849 a b c d Cerullo Michael A September 2015 Kording Konrad P ed The Problem with Phi A Critique of Integrated Information Theory PLOS Computational Biology 11 9 e1004286 Bibcode 2015PLSCB 11E4286C doi 10 1371 journal pcbi 1004286 PMC 4574706 PMID 26378789 Morch Hedda Hassel 2017 The Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness Philosophy Now Retrieved 22 April 2018 Oizumi Masafumi Albantakis Larissa Tononi Giulio May 2014 From the Phenomenology to the Mechanisms of Consciousness Integrated Information Theory 3 0 PLOS Computational Biology 10 5 e1003588 Bibcode 2014PLSCB 10E3588O doi 10 1371 journal pcbi 1003588 PMC 4014402 PMID 24811198 Mindt Garrett 2017 The Problem with the Information in Integrated Information Theory PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 24 7 8 130 154 Retrieved 22 February 2022 a b c Baars Bernard J 2005 Global workspace theory of consciousness Toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience The Boundaries of Consciousness Neurobiology and Neuropathology Progress in Brain Research Vol 150 pp 45 53 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 456 2829 doi 10 1016 S0079 6123 05 50004 9 ISBN 9780444518514 PMID 16186014 Dehaene Stanislas Naccache Lionel 2001 Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness basic evidence and a workspace framework PDF Cognition 79 1 2 1 37 doi 10 1016 S0010 0277 00 00123 2 PMID 11164022 S2CID 1762431 Retrieved 5 April 2019 Dalton J W 1997 The unfinished theatre Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 4 316 318 Elitzur Avshalom C 1997 Why don t we know what Mary knows Baars reversing the problem of qualia Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 4 319 324 The Meta Problem of Consciousness Professor David Chalmers Talks at Google retrieved 2022 01 11 Stoppard Tom 28 January 2015 First Person Programme notes London Royal National Theatre External links editWeisberg Josh The hard problem of consciousness Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Hard problem of consciousness amp oldid 1218443338, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.