fbpx
Wikipedia

Philosophy of mind

The Philosophy of mind is a branch of philosophy that deals with the nature of the mind and its relation to the body and the external world.

The mind–body problem is a paradigmatic issue in philosophy of mind, although a number of other issues are addressed, such as the hard problem of consciousness and the nature of particular mental states.[1][2][3] Aspects of the mind that are studied include mental events, mental functions, mental properties, consciousness and its neural correlates, the ontology of the mind, the nature of cognition and of thought, and the relationship of the mind to the body.

Dualism and monism are the two central schools of thought on the mind–body problem, although nuanced views have arisen that do not fit one or the other category neatly.

  • Dualism finds its entry into Western philosophy thanks to René Descartes in the 17th century.[4] Substance dualists like Descartes argue that the mind is an independently existing substance, whereas property dualists maintain that the mind is a group of independent properties that emerge from and cannot be reduced to the brain, but that it is not a distinct substance.[5]
  • Monism is the position that mind and body are ontologically indiscernible entities, not dependent substances. This view was espoused by the 17th-century rationalist Baruch Spinoza.[6] Physicalists argue that only entities postulated by physical theory exist, and that mental processes will eventually be explained in terms of these entities as physical theory continues to evolve. Physicalists maintain various positions on the prospects of reducing mental properties to physical properties (many of whom adopt compatible forms of property dualism),[7][8][9][10][11][12] and the ontological status of such mental properties remains unclear.[11][13][14] Idealists maintain that the mind is all that exists and that the external world is either mental itself, or an illusion created by the mind. Neutral monists such as Ernst Mach and William James argue that events in the world can be thought of as either mental (psychological) or physical depending on the network of relationships into which they enter, and dual-aspect monists such as Spinoza adhere to the position that there is some other, neutral substance, and that both matter and mind are properties of this unknown substance. The most common monisms in the 20th and 21st centuries have all been variations of physicalism; these positions include behaviorism, the type identity theory, anomalous monism and functionalism.[15]

Most modern philosophers of mind adopt either a reductive physicalist or non-reductive physicalist position, maintaining in their different ways that the mind is not something separate from the body.[15] These approaches have been particularly influential in the sciences, especially in the fields of sociobiology, computer science (specifically, artificial intelligence), evolutionary psychology and the various neurosciences.[16][17][18][19] Reductive physicalists assert that all mental states and properties will eventually be explained by scientific accounts of physiological processes and states.[20][21][22] Non-reductive physicalists argue that although the mind is not a separate substance, mental properties supervene on physical properties, or that the predicates and vocabulary used in mental descriptions and explanations are indispensable, and cannot be reduced to the language and lower-level explanations of physical science.[23][24] Continued neuroscientific progress has helped to clarify some of these issues; however, they are far from being resolved. Modern philosophers of mind continue to ask how the subjective qualities and the intentionality of mental states and properties can be explained in naturalistic terms.[25][26]

The problems of physicalist theories of the mind have led some contemporary philosophers to assert that the traditional view of substance dualism should be defended. From this perspective, this theory is coherent, and problems such as "the interaction of mind and body" can be rationally resolved.[27]

Mind–body problem edit

 
René Descartes' illustration of mind/body dualism

The mind–body problem concerns the explanation of the relationship that exists between minds, or mental processes, and bodily states or processes.[1] The main aim of philosophers working in this area is to determine the nature of the mind and mental states/processes, and how—or even if—minds are affected by and can affect the body.

Perceptual experiences depend on stimuli that arrive at our various sensory organs from the external world, and these stimuli cause changes in our mental states, ultimately causing us to feel a sensation, which may be pleasant or unpleasant. Someone's desire for a slice of pizza, for example, will tend to cause that person to move his or her body in a specific manner and in a specific direction to obtain what he or she wants. The question, then, is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to arise out of a lump of gray matter endowed with nothing but electrochemical properties.[15]

A related problem is how someone's propositional attitudes (e.g. beliefs and desires) cause that individual's neurons to fire and muscles to contract. These comprise some of the puzzles that have confronted epistemologists and philosophers of mind from the time of René Descartes.[4]

Dualist solutions to the mind–body problem edit

Dualism is a set of views about the relationship between mind and matter (or body). It begins with the claim that mental phenomena are, in some respects, non-physical.[5] One of the earliest known formulations of mind–body dualism was expressed in the eastern Samkhya and Yoga schools of Hindu philosophy (c. 650 BCE), which divided the world into purusha (mind/spirit) and prakriti (material substance).[28] Specifically, the Yoga Sutra of Patanjali presents an analytical approach to the nature of the mind.

In Western Philosophy, the earliest discussions of dualist ideas are in the writings of Plato who suggested that humans' intelligence (a faculty of the mind or soul) could not be identified with, or explained in terms of, their physical body.[29][30] However, the best-known version of dualism is due to René Descartes (1641), and holds that the mind is a non-extended, non-physical substance, a "res cogitans".[4] Descartes was the first to clearly identify the mind with consciousness and self-awareness, and to distinguish this from the brain, which was the seat of intelligence. He was therefore the first to formulate the mind–body problem in the form in which it still exists today.[4]

Arguments for dualism edit

The most frequently used argument in favor of dualism appeals to the common-sense intuition that conscious experience is distinct from inanimate matter. If asked what the mind is, the average person would usually respond by identifying it with their self, their personality, their soul, or another related entity. They would almost certainly deny that the mind simply is the brain, or vice versa, finding the idea that there is just one ontological entity at play to be too mechanistic or unintelligible.[5] Modern philosophers of mind think that these intuitions are misleading, and that critical faculties, along with empirical evidence from the sciences, should be used to examine these assumptions and determine whether there is any real basis to them.[5]

The mental and the physical seem to have quite different, and perhaps irreconcilable, properties.[31] Mental events have a subjective quality, whereas physical events do not. So, for example, one can reasonably ask what a burnt finger feels like, or what a blue sky looks like, or what nice music sounds like to a person. But it is meaningless, or at least odd, to ask what a surge in the uptake of glutamate in the dorsolateral portion of the prefrontal cortex feels like.

Philosophers of mind call the subjective aspects of mental events "qualia" or "raw feels".[31] There are qualia involved in these mental events that seem particularly difficult to reduce to anything physical. David Chalmers explains this argument by stating that we could conceivably know all the objective information about something, such as the brain states and wavelengths of light involved with seeing the color red, but still not know something fundamental about the situation – what it is like to see the color red.[32]

If consciousness (the mind) can exist independently of physical reality (the brain), one must explain how physical memories are created concerning consciousness. Dualism must therefore explain how consciousness affects physical reality. One possible explanation is that of a miracle, proposed by Arnold Geulincx and Nicolas Malebranche, where all mind–body interactions require the direct intervention of God.

Another argument that has been proposed by C. S. Lewis[33] is the Argument from Reason: if, as monism implies, all of our thoughts are the effects of physical causes, then we have no reason for assuming that they are also the consequent of a reasonable ground. Knowledge, however, is apprehended by reasoning from ground to consequent. Therefore, if monism is correct, there would be no way of knowing this—or anything else—we could not even suppose it, except by a fluke.

The zombie argument is based on a thought experiment proposed by Todd Moody, and developed by David Chalmers in his book The Conscious Mind. The basic idea is that one can imagine one's body, and therefore conceive the existence of one's body, without any conscious states being associated with this body. Chalmers' argument is that it seems possible that such a being could exist because all that is needed is that all and only the things that the physical sciences describe about a zombie must be true of it. Since none of the concepts involved in these sciences make reference to consciousness or other mental phenomena, and any physical entity can be by definition described scientifically via physics, the move from conceivability to possibility is not such a large one.[34] Others such as Dennett have argued that the notion of a philosophical zombie is an incoherent,[35] or unlikely,[36] concept. It has been argued under physicalism that one must either believe that anyone including oneself might be a zombie, or that no one can be a zombie—following from the assertion that one's own conviction about being (or not being) a zombie is a product of the physical world and is therefore no different from anyone else's. This argument has been expressed by Dennett who argues that "Zombies think they are conscious, think they have qualia, think they suffer pains—they are just 'wrong' (according to this lamentable tradition) in ways that neither they nor we could ever discover!"[35] See also the problem of other minds.

Interactionist dualism edit

 
Portrait of René Descartes by Frans Hals (1648)

Interactionist dualism, or simply interactionism, is the particular form of dualism first espoused by Descartes in the Meditations.[4] In the 20th century, its major defenders have been Karl Popper and John Carew Eccles.[37] It is the view that mental states, such as beliefs and desires, causally interact with physical states.[5]

Descartes's argument for this position can be summarized as follows: Seth has a clear and distinct idea of his mind as a thinking thing that has no spatial extension (i.e., it cannot be measured in terms of length, weight, height, and so on). He also has a clear and distinct idea of his body as something that is spatially extended, subject to quantification and not able to think. It follows that mind and body are not identical because they have radically different properties.[4]

Seth's mental states (desires, beliefs, etc.) have causal effects on his body and vice versa: A child touches a hot stove (physical event) which causes pain (mental event) and makes her yell (physical event), this in turn provokes a sense of fear and protectiveness in the caregiver (mental event), and so on.

Descartes' argument depends on the premise that what Seth believes to be "clear and distinct" ideas in his mind are necessarily true. Many contemporary philosophers doubt this.[38][39][40] For example, Joseph Agassi suggests that several scientific discoveries made since the early 20th century have undermined the idea of privileged access to one's own ideas. Freud claimed that a psychologically-trained observer can understand a person's unconscious motivations better than the person himself does. Duhem has shown that a philosopher of science can know a person's methods of discovery better than that person herself does, while Malinowski has shown that an anthropologist can know a person's customs and habits better than the person whose customs and habits they are. He also asserts that modern psychological experiments that cause people to see things that are not there provide grounds for rejecting Descartes' argument, because scientists can describe a person's perceptions better than the person herself can.[41][42]

Other forms of dualism edit

 
Four varieties of dualism. The arrows indicate the direction of the causal interactions. Occasionalism is not shown.
Psychophysical parallelism edit

Psychophysical parallelism, or simply parallelism, is the view that mind and body, while having distinct ontological statuses, do not causally influence one another. Instead, they run along parallel paths (mind events causally interact with mind events and brain events causally interact with brain events) and only seem to influence each other.[43] This view was most prominently defended by Gottfried Leibniz. Although Leibniz was an ontological monist who believed that only one type of substance, the monad, exists in the universe, and that everything is reducible to it, he nonetheless maintained that there was an important distinction between "the mental" and "the physical" in terms of causation. He held that God had arranged things in advance so that minds and bodies would be in harmony with each other. This is known as the doctrine of pre-established harmony.[44]

Occasionalism edit

Occasionalism is the view espoused by Nicholas Malebranche as well as Islamic philosophers such as Abu Hamid Muhammad ibn Muhammad al-Ghazali that asserts all supposedly causal relations between physical events, or between physical and mental events, are not really causal at all. While body and mind are different substances, causes (whether mental or physical) are related to their effects by an act of God's intervention on each specific occasion.[45]

Property dualism edit

Property dualism is the view that the world is constituted of one kind of substance – the physical kind – and there exist two distinct kinds of properties: physical properties and mental properties. It is the view that non-physical, mental properties (such as beliefs, desires and emotions) inhere in some physical bodies (at least, brains). Sub-varieties of property dualism include:

  1. Emergent materialism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way (i.e., in the way that living human bodies are organized), mental properties emerge in a way not fully accountable for by physical laws.[5] These emergent properties have an independent ontological status and cannot be reduced to, or explained in terms of, the physical substrate from which they emerge. They are dependent on the physical properties from which they emerge, but opinions vary as to the coherence of top–down causation, that is, the causal effectiveness of such properties. A form of emergent materialism has been espoused by David Chalmers and the concept has undergone something of a renaissance in recent years,[46] but it was already suggested in the 19th century by William James.
  2. Epiphenomenalism is a doctrine first formulated by Thomas Henry Huxley.[47] It consists of the view that mental phenomena are causally ineffectual, where one or more mental states do not have any influence on physical states or mental phenomena are the effects, but not the causes, of physical phenomena. Physical events can cause other physical and mental events, but mental events cannot cause anything since they are just causally inert by-products (i.e., epiphenomena) of the physical world.[43] This view has been defended by Frank Jackson.[48]
  3. Non-reductive physicalism is the view that mental properties form a separate ontological class to physical properties: mental states (such as qualia) are not reducible to physical states. The ontological stance towards qualia in the case of non-reductive physicalism does not imply that qualia are causally inert; this is what distinguishes it from epiphenomenalism.
  4. Panpsychism is the view that all matter has a mental aspect, or, alternatively, all objects have a unified center of experience or point of view. Superficially, it seems to be a form of property dualism, since it regards everything as having both mental and physical properties. However, some panpsychists say that mechanical behaviour is derived from the primitive mentality of atoms and molecules—as are sophisticated mentality and organic behaviour, the difference being attributed to the presence or absence of complex structure in a compound object. So long as the reduction of non-mental properties to mental ones is in place, panpsychism is not a (strong) form of property dualism; otherwise it is.
Dual aspect theory edit

Dual aspect theory or dual-aspect monism is the view that the mental and the physical are two aspects of, or perspectives on, the same substance. (Thus it is a mixed position, which is monistic in some respects). In modern philosophical writings, the theory's relationship to neutral monism has become somewhat ill-defined, but one proffered distinction says that whereas neutral monism allows the context of a given group of neutral elements and the relationships into which they enter to determine whether the group can be thought of as mental, physical, both, or neither, dual-aspect theory suggests that the mental and the physical are manifestations (or aspects) of some underlying substance, entity or process that is itself neither mental nor physical as normally understood. Various formulations of dual-aspect monism also require the mental and the physical to be complementary, mutually irreducible and perhaps inseparable (though distinct).[49][50][51]

Experiential dualism edit

This is a philosophy of mind that regards the degrees of freedom between mental and physical well-being as not synonymous thus implying an experiential dualism between body and mind. An example of these disparate degrees of freedom is given by Allan Wallace who notes that it is "experientially apparent that one may be physically uncomfortable—for instance, while engaging in a strenuous physical workout—while mentally cheerful; conversely, one may be mentally distraught while experiencing physical comfort".[52] Experiential dualism notes that our subjective experience of merely seeing something in the physical world seems qualitatively different from mental processes like grief that comes from losing a loved one. This philosophy is a proponent of causal dualism, which is defined as the dual ability for mental states and physical states to affect one another. Mental states can cause changes in physical states and vice versa.

However, unlike cartesian dualism or some other systems, experiential dualism does not posit two fundamental substances in reality: mind and matter. Rather, experiential dualism is to be understood as a conceptual framework that gives credence to the qualitative difference between the experience of mental and physical states. Experiential dualism is accepted as the conceptual framework of Madhyamaka Buddhism.

Madhayamaka Buddhism goes further, finding fault with the monist view of physicalist philosophies of mind as well in that these generally posit matter and energy as the fundamental substance of reality. Nonetheless, this does not imply that the cartesian dualist view is correct, rather Madhyamaka regards as error any affirming view of a fundamental substance to reality.

In denying the independent self-existence of all the phenomena that make up the world of our experience, the Madhyamaka view departs from both the substance dualism of Descartes and the substance monism—namely, physicalism—that is characteristic of modern science. The physicalism propounded by many contemporary scientists seems to assert that the real world is composed of physical things-in-themselves, while all mental phenomena are regarded as mere appearances, devoid of any reality in and of themselves. Much is made of this difference between appearances and reality.[52]

Indeed, physicalism, or the idea that matter is the only fundamental substance of reality, is explicitly rejected by Buddhism.

In the Madhyamaka view, mental events are no more or less real than physical events. In terms of our common-sense experience, differences of kind do exist between physical and mental phenomena. While the former commonly have mass, location, velocity, shape, size, and numerous other physical attributes, these are not generally characteristic of mental phenomena. For example, we do not commonly conceive of the feeling of affection for another person as having mass or location. These physical attributes are no more appropriate to other mental events such as sadness, a recalled image from one's childhood, the visual perception of a rose, or consciousness of any sort. Mental phenomena are, therefore, not regarded as being physical, for the simple reason that they lack many of the attributes that are uniquely characteristic of physical phenomena. Thus, Buddhism has never adopted the physicalist principle that regards only physical things as real.[52]

Monist solutions to the mind–body problem edit

In contrast to dualism, monism does not accept any fundamental divisions. The fundamentally disparate nature of reality has been central to forms of eastern philosophies for over two millennia. In Indian and Chinese philosophy, monism is integral to how experience is understood. Today, the most common forms of monism in Western philosophy are physicalist.[15] Physicalistic monism asserts that the only existing substance is physical, in some sense of that term to be clarified by our best science.[53] However, a variety of formulations (see below) are possible. Another form of monism, idealism, states that the only existing substance is mental. Although pure idealism, such as that of George Berkeley, is uncommon in contemporary Western philosophy, a more sophisticated variant called panpsychism, according to which mental experience and properties may be at the foundation of physical experience and properties, has been espoused by some philosophers such as Alfred North Whitehead[54] and David Ray Griffin.[46]

Phenomenalism is the theory that representations (or sense data) of external objects are all that exist. Such a view was briefly adopted by Bertrand Russell and many of the logical positivists during the early 20th century.[55] A third possibility is to accept the existence of a basic substance that is neither physical nor mental. The mental and physical would then both be properties of this neutral substance. Such a position was adopted by Baruch Spinoza[6] and was popularized by Ernst Mach[56] in the 19th century. This neutral monism, as it is called, resembles property dualism.

Physicalistic monisms edit

Behaviorism edit

Behaviorism dominated philosophy of mind for much of the 20th century, especially the first half.[15] In psychology, behaviorism developed as a reaction to the inadequacies of introspectionism.[53] Introspective reports on one's own interior mental life are not subject to careful examination for accuracy and cannot be used to form predictive generalizations. Without generalizability and the possibility of third-person examination, the behaviorists argued, psychology cannot be scientific.[53] The way out, therefore, was to eliminate the idea of an interior mental life (and hence an ontologically independent mind) altogether and focus instead on the description of observable behavior.[57]

Parallel to these developments in psychology, a philosophical behaviorism (sometimes called logical behaviorism) was developed.[53] This is characterized by a strong verificationism, which generally considers unverifiable statements about interior mental life pointless. For the behaviorist, mental states are not interior states on which one can make introspective reports. They are just descriptions of behavior or dispositions to behave in certain ways, made by third parties to explain and predict another's behavior.[58]

Philosophical behaviorism has fallen out of favor since the latter half of the 20th century, coinciding with the rise of cognitivism.[1]

Identity theory edit

Type physicalism (or type-identity theory) was developed by Jack Smart[22] and Ullin Place[59] as a direct reaction to the failure of behaviorism. These philosophers reasoned that, if mental states are something material, but not behavioral, then mental states are probably identical to internal states of the brain. In very simplified terms: a mental state M is nothing other than brain state B. The mental state "desire for a cup of coffee" would thus be nothing more than the "firing of certain neurons in certain brain regions".[22]

 
The classic Identity theory and Anomalous Monism in contrast. For the Identity theory, every token instantiation of a single mental type corresponds (as indicated by the arrows) to a physical token of a single physical type. For anomalous monism, the token–token correspondences can fall outside of the type–type correspondences. The result is token identity.

On the other hand, even granted the above, it does not follow that identity theories of all types must be abandoned. According to token identity theories, the fact that a certain brain state is connected with only one mental state of a person does not have to mean that there is an absolute correlation between types of mental state and types of brain state. The type–token distinction can be illustrated by a simple example: the word "green" contains four types of letters (g, r, e, n) with two tokens (occurrences) of the letter e along with one each of the others. The idea of token identity is that only particular occurrences of mental events are identical with particular occurrences or tokenings of physical events.[60] Anomalous monism (see below) and most other non-reductive physicalisms are token-identity theories.[61] Despite these problems, there is a renewed interest in the type identity theory today, primarily due to the influence of Jaegwon Kim.[22]

Functionalism edit

Functionalism was formulated by Hilary Putnam and Jerry Fodor as a reaction to the inadequacies of the identity theory.[24] Putnam and Fodor saw mental states in terms of an empirical computational theory of the mind.[62] At about the same time or slightly after, D.M. Armstrong and David Kellogg Lewis formulated a version of functionalism that analyzed the mental concepts of folk psychology in terms of functional roles.[63] Finally, Wittgenstein's idea of meaning as use led to a version of functionalism as a theory of meaning, further developed by Wilfrid Sellars and Gilbert Harman. Another one, psychofunctionalism, is an approach adopted by the naturalistic philosophy of mind associated with Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn.

Mental states are characterized by their causal relations with other mental states and with sensory inputs and behavioral outputs. Functionalism abstracts away from the details of the physical implementation of a mental state by characterizing it in terms of non-mental functional properties. For example, a kidney is characterized scientifically by its functional role in filtering blood and maintaining certain chemical balances.[62]

Non-reductive physicalism edit

Non-reductionist philosophers hold firmly to two essential convictions with regard to mind–body relations: 1) Physicalism is true and mental states must be physical states, but 2) All reductionist proposals are unsatisfactory: mental states cannot be reduced to behavior, brain states or functional states.[53] Hence, the question arises whether there can still be a non-reductive physicalism. Donald Davidson's anomalous monism[23] is an attempt to formulate such a physicalism. He "thinks that when one runs across what are traditionally seen as absurdities of Reason, such as akrasia or self-deception, the personal psychology framework is not to be given up in favor of the subpersonal one, but rather must be enlarged or extended so that the rationality set out by the principle of charity can be found elsewhere."[64]

Davidson uses the thesis of supervenience: mental states supervene on physical states, but are not reducible to them. "Supervenience" therefore describes a functional dependence: there can be no change in the mental without some change in the physical–causal reducibility between the mental and physical without ontological reducibility.[65]

Weak emergentism edit

Weak emergentism is a form of "non-reductive physicalism" that involves a layered view of nature, with the layers arranged in terms of increasing complexity and each corresponding to its own special science. Some philosophers [who?] hold that emergent properties causally interact with more fundamental levels, while others maintain that higher-order properties simply supervene over lower levels without direct causal interaction. The latter group therefore holds a less strict, or "weaker", definition of emergentism, which can be rigorously stated as follows: a property P of composite object O is emergent if it is metaphysically impossible for another object to lack property P if that object is composed of parts with intrinsic properties identical to those in O and has those parts in an identical configuration.[citation needed]

Sometimes emergentists use the example of water having a new property when Hydrogen H and Oxygen O combine to form H2O (water). In this example there "emerges" a new property of a transparent liquid that would not have been predicted by understanding hydrogen and oxygen as gases. This is analogous to physical properties of the brain giving rise to a mental state. Emergentists try to solve the notorious mind–body gap this way. One problem for emergentism is the idea of causal closure in the world that does not allow for a mind-to-body causation.[66]

Eliminative materialism edit

If one is a materialist and believes that all aspects of our common-sense psychology will find reduction to a mature cognitive neuroscience, and that non-reductive materialism is mistaken, then one can adopt a final, more radical position: eliminative materialism.

There are several varieties of eliminative materialism, but all maintain that our common-sense "folk psychology" badly misrepresents the nature of some aspect of cognition. Eliminativists such as Patricia and Paul Churchland argue that while folk psychology treats cognition as fundamentally sentence-like, the non-linguistic vector/matrix model of neural network theory or connectionism will prove to be a much more accurate account of how the brain works.[20]

The Churchlands often invoke the fate of other, erroneous popular theories and ontologies that have arisen in the course of history.[20][21] For example, Ptolemaic astronomy served to explain and roughly predict the motions of the planets for centuries, but eventually this model of the solar system was eliminated in favor of the Copernican model. The Churchlands believe the same eliminative fate awaits the "sentence-cruncher" model of the mind in which thought and behavior are the result of manipulating sentence-like states called "propositional attitudes". Sociologist Jacy Reese Anthis argues for eliminative materialism on all faculties of mind, including consciousness, stating, "The deepest mysteries of the mind are within our reach."[67]

Mysterianism edit

Some philosophers take an epistemic approach and argue that the mind–body problem is currently unsolvable, and perhaps will always remain unsolvable to human beings. This is usually termed New mysterianism. Colin McGinn holds that human beings are cognitively closed in regards to their own minds. According to McGinn human minds lack the concept-forming procedures to fully grasp how mental properties such as consciousness arise from their causal basis.[68] An example would be how an elephant is cognitively closed in regards to particle physics.

A more moderate conception has been expounded by Thomas Nagel, which holds that the mind–body problem is currently unsolvable at the present stage of scientific development and that it might take a future scientific paradigm shift or revolution to bridge the explanatory gap. Nagel posits that in the future a sort of "objective phenomenology" might be able to bridge the gap between subjective conscious experience and its physical basis.[69]

Linguistic criticism of the mind–body problem edit

Each attempt to answer the mind–body problem encounters substantial problems. Some philosophers argue that this is because there is an underlying conceptual confusion.[70] These philosophers, such as Ludwig Wittgenstein and his followers in the tradition of linguistic criticism, therefore reject the problem as illusory.[71] They argue that it is an error to ask how mental and biological states fit together. Rather it should simply be accepted that human experience can be described in different ways—for instance, in a mental and in a biological vocabulary. Illusory problems arise if one tries to describe the one in terms of the other's vocabulary or if the mental vocabulary is used in the wrong contexts.[71] This is the case, for instance, if one searches for mental states of the brain. The brain is simply the wrong context for the use of mental vocabulary—the search for mental states of the brain is therefore a category error or a sort of fallacy of reasoning.[71]

Today, such a position is often adopted by interpreters of Wittgenstein such as Peter Hacker.[70] However, Hilary Putnam, the originator of functionalism, has also adopted the position that the mind–body problem is an illusory problem which should be dissolved according to the manner of Wittgenstein.[72]

Naturalism and its problems edit

The thesis of physicalism is that the mind is part of the material (or physical) world. Such a position faces the problem that the mind has certain properties that no other material thing seems to possess. Physicalism must therefore explain how it is possible that these properties can nonetheless emerge from a material thing. The project of providing such an explanation is often referred to as the "naturalization of the mental".[53] Some of the crucial problems that this project attempts to resolve include the existence of qualia and the nature of intentionality.[53]

Qualia edit

Many mental states seem to be experienced subjectively in different ways by different individuals.[32] And it is characteristic of a mental state that it has some experiential quality, e.g. of pain, that it hurts. However, the sensation of pain between two individuals may not be identical, since no one has a perfect way to measure how much something hurts or of describing exactly how it feels to hurt. Philosophers and scientists therefore ask where these experiences come from. The existence of cerebral events, in and of themselves, cannot explain why they are accompanied by these corresponding qualitative experiences. The puzzle of why many cerebral processes occur with an accompanying experiential aspect in consciousness seems impossible to explain.[31]

Yet it also seems to many that science will eventually have to explain such experiences.[53] This follows from an assumption about the possibility of reductive explanations. According to this view, if an attempt can be successfully made to explain a phenomenon reductively (e.g., water), then it can be explained why the phenomenon has all of its properties (e.g., fluidity, transparency).[53] In the case of mental states, this means that there needs to be an explanation of why they have the property of being experienced in a certain way.

The 20th-century German philosopher Martin Heidegger criticized the ontological assumptions underpinning such a reductive model, and claimed that it was impossible to make sense of experience in these terms. This is because, according to Heidegger, the nature of our subjective experience and its qualities is impossible to understand in terms of Cartesian "substances" that bear "properties". Another way to put this is that the very concept of qualitative experience is incoherent in terms of—or is semantically incommensurable with the concept of—substances that bear properties.[73]

This problem of explaining introspective first-person aspects of mental states and consciousness in general in terms of third-person quantitative neuroscience is called the explanatory gap.[74] There are several different views of the nature of this gap among contemporary philosophers of mind. David Chalmers and the early Frank Jackson interpret the gap as ontological in nature; that is, they maintain that qualia can never be explained by science because physicalism is false. There are two separate categories involved and one cannot be reduced to the other.[75] An alternative view is taken by philosophers such as Thomas Nagel and Colin McGinn. According to them, the gap is epistemological in nature. For Nagel, science is not yet able to explain subjective experience because it has not yet arrived at the level or kind of knowledge that is required. We are not even able to formulate the problem coherently.[32] For McGinn, on other hand, the problem is one of permanent and inherent biological limitations. We are not able to resolve the explanatory gap because the realm of subjective experiences is cognitively closed to us in the same manner that quantum physics is cognitively closed to elephants.[76] Other philosophers liquidate the gap as purely a semantic problem. This semantic problem, of course, led to the famous "Qualia Question", which is: Does Red cause Redness?

Intentionality edit

 
John Searle—one of the most influential philosophers of mind, proponent of biological naturalism (Berkeley 2002)

Intentionality is the capacity of mental states to be directed towards (about) or be in relation with something in the external world.[26] This property of mental states entails that they have contents and semantic referents and can therefore be assigned truth values. When one tries to reduce these states to natural processes there arises a problem: natural processes are not true or false, they simply happen.[77] It would not make any sense to say that a natural process is true or false. But mental ideas or judgments are true or false, so how then can mental states (ideas or judgments) be natural processes? The possibility of assigning semantic value to ideas must mean that such ideas are about facts. Thus, for example, the idea that Herodotus was a historian refers to Herodotus and to the fact that he was a historian. If the fact is true, then the idea is true; otherwise, it is false. But where does this relation come from? In the brain, there are only electrochemical processes and these seem not to have anything to do with Herodotus.[25]

Philosophy of perception edit

Philosophy of perception is concerned with the nature of perceptual experience and the status of perceptual objects, in particular how perceptual experience relates to appearances and beliefs about the world. The main contemporary views within philosophy of perception include naive realism, enactivism and representational views.[2][3][78]

 
A phrenological mapping of the brainphrenology was among the first attempts to correlate mental functions with specific parts of the brain although it is now widely discredited.

Philosophy of mind and science edit

Humans are corporeal beings and, as such, they are subject to examination and description by the natural sciences. Since mental processes are intimately related to bodily processes (e.g., embodied cognition theory of mind), the descriptions that the natural sciences furnish of human beings play an important role in the philosophy of mind.[1] There are many scientific disciplines that study processes related to the mental. The list of such sciences includes: biology, computer science, cognitive science, cybernetics, linguistics, medicine, pharmacology, and psychology.[79]

Neurobiology edit

The theoretical background of biology, as is the case with modern natural sciences in general, is fundamentally materialistic. The objects of study are, in the first place, physical processes, which are considered to be the foundations of mental activity and behavior.[80] The increasing success of biology in the explanation of mental phenomena can be seen by the absence of any empirical refutation of its fundamental presupposition: "there can be no change in the mental states of a person without a change in brain states."[79]

Within the field of neurobiology, there are many subdisciplines that are concerned with the relations between mental and physical states and processes:[80] Sensory neurophysiology investigates the relation between the processes of perception and stimulation.[81] Cognitive neuroscience studies the correlations between mental processes and neural processes.[81] Neuropsychology describes the dependence of mental faculties on specific anatomical regions of the brain.[81] Lastly, evolutionary biology studies the origins and development of the human nervous system and, in as much as this is the basis of the mind, also describes the ontogenetic and phylogenetic development of mental phenomena beginning from their most primitive stages.[79] Evolutionary biology furthermore places tight constraints on any philosophical theory of the mind, as the gene-based mechanism of natural selection does not allow any giant leaps in the development of neural complexity or neural software but only incremental steps over long time periods.[82]

 
Since the 1980s, sophisticated neuroimaging procedures, such as fMRI (above), have furnished increasing knowledge about the workings of the human brain, shedding light on ancient philosophical problems.

The methodological breakthroughs of the neurosciences, in particular the introduction of high-tech neuroimaging procedures, has propelled scientists toward the elaboration of increasingly ambitious research programs: one of the main goals is to describe and comprehend the neural processes which correspond to mental functions (see: neural correlate).[80] Several groups are inspired by these advances.

Computer science edit

Computer science concerns itself with the automatic processing of information (or at least with physical systems of symbols to which information is assigned) by means of such things as computers.[83] From the beginning, computer programmers have been able to develop programs that permit computers to carry out tasks for which organic beings need a mind. A simple example is multiplication. It is not clear whether computers could be said to have a mind. Could they, someday, come to have what we call a mind? This question has been propelled into the forefront of much philosophical debate because of investigations in the field of artificial intelligence (AI).

Within AI, it is common to distinguish between a modest research program and a more ambitious one: this distinction was coined by John Searle in terms of a weak AI and strong AI. The exclusive objective of "weak AI", according to Searle, is the successful simulation of mental states, with no attempt to make computers become conscious or aware, etc. The objective of strong AI, on the contrary, is a computer with consciousness similar to that of human beings.[84] The program of strong AI goes back to one of the pioneers of computation Alan Turing. As an answer to the question "Can computers think?", he formulated the famous Turing test.[85] Turing believed that a computer could be said to "think" when, if placed in a room by itself next to another room that contained a human being and with the same questions being asked of both the computer and the human being by a third party human being, the computer's responses turned out to be indistinguishable from those of the human. Essentially, Turing's view of machine intelligence followed the behaviourist model of the mind—intelligence is as intelligence does. The Turing test has received many criticisms, among which the most famous is probably the Chinese room thought experiment formulated by Searle.[84]

The question about the possible sensitivity (qualia) of computers or robots still remains open. Some computer scientists believe that the specialty of AI can still make new contributions to the resolution of the "mind–body problem". They suggest that based on the reciprocal influences between software and hardware that takes place in all computers, it is possible that someday theories can be discovered that help us to understand the reciprocal influences between the human mind and the brain (wetware).[86]

Psychology edit

Psychology is the science that investigates mental states directly. It uses generally empirical methods to investigate concrete mental states like joy, fear or obsessions. Psychology investigates the laws that bind these mental states to each other or with inputs and outputs to the human organism.[87]

An example of this is the psychology of perception. Scientists working in this field have discovered general principles of the perception of forms. A law of the psychology of forms says that objects that move in the same direction are perceived as related to each other.[79] This law describes a relation between visual input and mental perceptual states. However, it does not suggest anything about the nature of perceptual states. The laws discovered by psychology are compatible with all the answers to the mind–body problem already described.

Cognitive science edit

Cognitive science is the interdisciplinary scientific study of the mind and its processes. It examines what cognition is, what it does, and how it works. It includes research on intelligence and behavior, especially focusing on how information is represented, processed, and transformed (in faculties such as perception, language, memory, reasoning, and emotion) within nervous systems (human or other animals) and machines (e.g. computers). Cognitive science consists of multiple research disciplines, including psychology, artificial intelligence, philosophy, neuroscience, linguistics, anthropology, sociology, and education.[88] It spans many levels of analysis, from low-level learning and decision mechanisms to high-level logic and planning; from neural circuitry to modular brain organization. Over the years, cognitive science has evolved from a representational and information processing approach to explaining the mind to embrace an embodied perspective of it. Accordingly, bodily processes play a significant role in the acquisition, development, and shaping of cognitive capabilities.[89] For instance, Rowlands (2012) argues that cognition is enactive, embodied, embedded, affective and (potentially) extended. The position is taken that the "classical sandwich" of cognition sandwiched between perception and action is artificial; cognition has to be seen as a product of a strongly coupled interaction that cannot be divided this way.[90][91]

Near-death research edit

In the field of near-death research, the following phenomenon, among others, occurs: For example, during some brain operations the brain is artificially and measurably deactivated. Nevertheless, some patients report during this phase that they have perceived what is happening in their surroundings, that is, that they have had consciousness. Patients also report experiences during a cardiac arrest. There is the following problem: As soon as the brain is no longer supplied with blood and thus with oxygen after a cardiac arrest, the brain ceases its normal operation after about 15 seconds, that is, the brain falls into a state of unconsciousness.[92]

Philosophy of mind in the continental tradition edit

Most of the discussion in this article has focused on one style or tradition of philosophy in modern Western culture, usually called analytic philosophy (sometimes described as Anglo-American philosophy).[93] Many other schools of thought exist, however, which are sometimes subsumed under the broad (and vague) label of continental philosophy.[93] In any case, though topics and methods here are numerous, in relation to the philosophy of mind the various schools that fall under this label (phenomenology, existentialism, etc.) can globally be seen to differ from the analytic school in that they focus less on language and logical analysis alone but also take in other forms of understanding human existence and experience. With reference specifically to the discussion of the mind, this tends to translate into attempts to grasp the concepts of thought and perceptual experience in some sense that does not merely involve the analysis of linguistic forms.[93]

Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, first published in 1781 and presented again with major revisions in 1787, represents a significant intervention into what will later become known as the philosophy of mind. Kant's first critique is generally recognized as among the most significant works of modern philosophy in the West. Kant is a figure whose influence is marked in both continental and analytic/Anglo-American philosophy. Kant's work develops an in-depth study of transcendental consciousness, or the life of the mind as conceived through the universal categories of understanding.

In Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's Philosophy of Mind (frequently translated as Philosophy of Spirit or Geist),[94] the third part of his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel discusses three distinct types of mind: the "subjective mind/spirit", the mind of an individual; the "objective mind/spirit", the mind of society and of the State; and the "Absolute mind/spirit", the position of religion, art, and philosophy. See also Hegel's The Phenomenology of Spirit. Nonetheless, Hegel's work differs radically from the style of Anglo-American philosophy of mind.

In 1896, Henri Bergson made in Matter and Memory "Essay on the relation of body and spirit" a forceful case for the ontological difference of body and mind by reducing the problem to the more definite one of memory, thus allowing for a solution built on the empirical test case of aphasia.

In modern times, the two main schools that have developed in response or opposition to this Hegelian tradition are phenomenology and existentialism. Phenomenology, founded by Edmund Husserl, focuses on the contents of the human mind (see noema) and how processes shape our experiences.[95] Existentialism, a school of thought founded upon the work of Søren Kierkegaard, focuses on Human predicament and how people deal with the situation of being alive. Existential-phenomenology represents a major branch of continental philosophy (they are not contradictory), rooted in the work of Husserl but expressed in its fullest forms in the work of Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. See Heidegger's Being and Time, Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Perception, Sartre's Being and Nothingness, and Simone de Beauvoir's The Second Sex.

Topics related to philosophy of mind edit

There are countless subjects that are affected by the ideas developed in the philosophy of mind. Clear examples of this are the nature of death and its definitive character, the nature of emotion, of perception and of memory. Questions about what a person is and what his or her identity have to do with the philosophy of mind. There are two subjects that, in connection with the philosophy of the mind, have aroused special attention: free will and the self.[1]

Free will edit

In the context of philosophy of mind, the problem of free will takes on renewed intensity. This is the case for materialistic determinists.[1] According to this position, natural laws completely determine the course of the material world. Mental states, and therefore the will as well, would be material states, which means human behavior and decisions would be completely determined by natural laws. Some take this reasoning a step further: people cannot determine by themselves what they want and what they do. Consequently, they are not free.[96]

This argumentation is rejected, on the one hand, by the compatibilists. Those who adopt this position suggest that the question "Are we free?" can only be answered once we have determined what the term "free" means. The opposite of "free" is not "caused" but "compelled" or "coerced". It is not appropriate to identify freedom with indetermination. A free act is one where the agent could have done otherwise if it had chosen otherwise. In this sense a person can be free even though determinism is true.[96] The most important compatibilist in the history of the philosophy was David Hume.[97] More recently, this position is defended, for example, by Daniel Dennett.[98]

On the other hand, there are also many incompatibilists who reject the argument because they believe that the will is free in a stronger sense called libertarianism.[96] These philosophers affirm the course of the world is either a) not completely determined by natural law where natural law is intercepted by physically independent agency,[99] b) determined by indeterministic natural law only, or c) determined by indeterministic natural law in line with the subjective effort of physically non-reducible agency.[100] Under Libertarianism, the will does not have to be deterministic and, therefore, it is potentially free. Critics of the second proposition (b) accuse the incompatibilists of using an incoherent concept of freedom. They argue as follows: if our will is not determined by anything, then we desire what we desire by pure chance. And if what we desire is purely accidental, we are not free. So if our will is not determined by anything, we are not free.[96]

Self edit

The philosophy of mind also has important consequences for the concept of "self". If by "self" or "I" one refers to an essential, immutable nucleus of the person, some modern philosophers of mind, such as Daniel Dennett believe that no such thing exists. According to Dennett and other contemporaries, the self is considered an illusion.[101] The idea of a self as an immutable essential nucleus derives from the idea of an immaterial soul. Such an idea is unacceptable to modern philosophers with physicalist orientations and their general skepticism of the concept of "self" as postulated by David Hume, who could never catch himself not doing, thinking or feeling anything.[102] However, in the light of empirical results from developmental psychology, developmental biology and neuroscience, the idea of an essential inconstant, material nucleus—an integrated representational system distributed over changing patterns of synaptic connections—seems reasonable.[103]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f Kim, Jaegwan (1995). "Emergent properties". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 240. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
  2. ^ a b Siegel, S.: The Contents of Visual Experience. New York: Oxford University Press. 2010.
  3. ^ a b Macpherson, F. & Haddock, A., editors, Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
  4. ^ a b c d e f Descartes, René (1998). Discourse on Method and Meditations on First Philosophy. Hacket Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-87220-421-8.
  5. ^ a b c d e f Hart, W.D. (1996) "Dualism", in Samuel Guttenplan (org) A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell, Oxford, 265–7.
  6. ^ a b Spinoza, Baruch (1670) Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (A Theologico-Political Treatise).
  7. ^ Schneider, Susan (2013). "Non-Reductive Physicalism and the Mind Problem1". Noûs. 47 (1): 135–153. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00847.x. ISSN 0029-4624.
  8. ^ DePaul, Michael; Baltimore, Joseph A. (2013). "Type Physicalism and Causal Exclusion". Journal of Philosophical Research. 38: 405–418. doi:10.5840/jpr20133821. ISSN 1053-8364.
  9. ^ S. C. Gibb; E. J. Lowe; R. D. Ingthorsson (21 March 2013). Mental Causation and Ontology. OUP Oxford. p. 58. ISBN 978-0-19-165255-4.
  10. ^ Demircioglu, Erhan (2011). "Supervenience And Reductive Physicalism". European Journal of Analytic Philosophy. 7 (1): 25–35.
  11. ^ a b Francescotti, Robert. "Supervenience and Mind". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. from the original on 2014-07-17. Retrieved 2014-08-10.
  12. ^ Gibb, Sophie (2010). "Closure Principles and the Laws of Conservation of Energy and Momentum". Dialectica. 64 (3): 363–384. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.2010.01237.x. ISSN 0012-2017. S2CID 55120533. See also Dempsey, L. P. (2012). "Consciousness, Supervenience, and Identity: Marras and Kim on the Efficacy of Conscious Experience". Dialogue. 51 (3): 373–395. doi:10.1017/s0012217312000662. S2CID 147060838. See also Baltimore, J. A. (2010). "Defending the piggyback principle against Shapiro and Sober's empirical approach". Dialectica. 175 (2): 151–168. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9467-2. S2CID 13314992.
  13. ^ McLaughlin, Brian; Bennett, Karen (2014). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Supervenience". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). Retrieved 2014-08-10.
  14. ^ Megill, Jason (2012). "A Defense of Emergence". Axiomathes. 23 (4): 597–615. doi:10.1007/s10516-012-9203-2. ISSN 1122-1151. S2CID 170226477.
  15. ^ a b c d e Kim, J., "Mind–Body Problem", Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Ted Honderich (ed.). Oxford:Oxford University Press. 1995.
  16. ^ Pinel, J. Psychobiology, (1990) Prentice Hall, Inc. ISBN 88-15-07174-1
  17. ^ LeDoux, J. (2002) The Synaptic Self: How Our Brains Become Who We Are, New York:Viking Penguin. ISBN 88-7078-795-8
  18. ^ Russell, S. and Norvig, P. Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach, New Jersey:Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-103805-2
  19. ^ Dawkins, R. The Selfish Gene (1976) Oxford:Oxford University Press. ISBN
  20. ^ a b c Churchland, Patricia (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind–Brain. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-03116-5.
  21. ^ a b Churchland, Paul (1981). "Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes". Journal of Philosophy. 78 (2): 67–90. doi:10.2307/2025900. JSTOR 2025900.
  22. ^ a b c d Smart, J.J.C. (1956). "Sensations and Brain Processes". Philosophical Review.
  23. ^ a b Donald Davidson (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-924627-4.
  24. ^ a b Putnam, Hilary (1967). "Psychological Predicates", in W. H. Capitan and D. D. Merrill, eds., Art, Mind and Religion (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.)
  25. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel (1998). The intentional stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-54053-7.
  26. ^ a b Searle, John (2001). Intentionality. A Paper on the Philosophy of Mind. Frankfurt a. M.: Nachdr. Suhrkamp. ISBN 978-3-518-28556-5.
  27. ^ Mousavirad, Seyyed Jaaber (2023-11-29). "Coherence of Substance Dualism". International Philosophical Quarterly. 63 (1): 33–42. doi:10.5840/ipq20231114214.
  28. ^ Sri Swami Sivananda. . Archived from the original on May 15, 2006.
  29. ^ Plato (1995). E.A. Duke; W.F. Hicken; W.S.M. Nicoll; D.B. Robinson; J.C.G. Strachan (eds.). Phaedo. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-1-4065-4150-2.
  30. ^ Robinson, H. (1983): "Aristotelian dualism", Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 1, 123–44.
  31. ^ a b c Jackson, F. (1982) "Epiphenomenal Qualia." Reprinted in Chalmers, David ed. :2002. Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press.
  32. ^ a b c Nagel, T. (1974). "What is it like to be a bat?" (PDF). Philosophical Review. 83 (4): 435–456. doi:10.2307/2183914. JSTOR 2183914.
  33. ^ Lewis, C.S (1947). Miracles. New York : W. Morrow & Co. ISBN 978-0-688-17369-2.
  34. ^ Chalmers, David (1997). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511789-9.
  35. ^ a b Dennett, Daniel (1995). . Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2: 322–6. Archived from the original on 2017-05-15. Retrieved 2017-04-27.
  36. ^ Dennett, Daniel (1991). Consciousness Explained. Little, Brown and Co. p. 95. ISBN 978-0-316-18065-8.
  37. ^ Popper, Karl & Eccles, John (2002). The Self and Its Brain. Springer Verlag. ISBN 978-3-492-21096-6.
  38. ^ Dennett D., (1991), Consciousness Explained, Boston: Little, Brown & Company
  39. ^ Stich, S., (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (Bradford)
  40. ^ Ryle, G., 1949, The Concept of Mind, New York: Barnes and Noble
  41. ^ Agassi, J. (1975). Privileged Access; Science in Flux, Boston Stidues in the Philosophy of Science, 80. Dordrecht: Reidel.
  42. ^ Agassi, J. (1997). La Scienza in Divenire. Rome: Armando.
  43. ^ a b Robinson, Howard (2003-08-19). "Dualism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition). Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved 2006-09-25.
  44. ^ Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1714). Monadology. ISBN 978-0-87548-030-5.
  45. ^ Schmaltz, Tad (2002). "Nicolas Malebranche". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2002 Edition). Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved 2006-09-25.
  46. ^ a b Chalmers, David (1996). The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511789-9.
  47. ^ Huxley, T. H. [1874] "On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and its History", The Fortnightly Review, n.s.16:555–580. Reprinted in Method and Results: Essays by Thomas H. Huxley (New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1898).
  48. ^ Jackson, Frank (1986). "What Mary didn't know". Journal of Philosophy. 83 (5): 291–295. doi:10.2307/2026143. JSTOR 2026143. S2CID 19000667.
  49. ^ Atmanspacher, H (2012). "Dual-aspect monism a la Pauli and Jung". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 19 (9–10): 96–120.
  50. ^ Velmans, M (2012). "Reflexive Monism: psychophysical relations among mind, matter and consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 19 (9–10): 143–165. from the original on 2017-11-11.
  51. ^ Leopold Stubenberg. "Neutral Monism and the Dual Aspect Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  52. ^ a b c Wallace, Allen (1999). Consciousness At The Crossroads: Conversations With The Dalai Lama On Brain Science And Buddhism. Snow Lion. ISBN 978-0-545-22720-9.
  53. ^ a b c d e f g h i Stoljar, Daniel (2005). "Physicalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2005 Edition). Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. Retrieved 2006-09-24.
  54. ^ Cf. Michel Weber and Anderson Weekes (eds.), Process Approaches to Consciousness in Psychology, Neuroscience, and Philosophy of Mind (Whitehead Psychology Nexus Studies II) 2015-04-08 at the Wayback Machine, Albany, New York, State University of New York Press, 2009.
  55. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1918) Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, London: Longmans, Green.
  56. ^ Mach, Ernst (1959) [1886]. Die Analyse der Empfindungen und das Verhältnis des Physischen zum Psychischen [The Analysis of Sensations and the Relation of Physical to the Psychical] (Fifth ed.). New York: Dover.
  57. ^ Skinner, B.F. (1972). Beyond Freedom & Dignity. New York: Bantam/Vintage Books. ISBN 978-0-553-14372-0.
  58. ^ Ryle, Gilbert (1949). The Concept of Mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press. ISBN 978-0-226-73295-4.
  59. ^ Place, Ullin (1956). "Is Consciousness a Brain Process?". British Journal of Psychology. 47 (1): 44–50. doi:10.1111/j.2044-8295.1956.tb00560.x. PMID 13304279. S2CID 36940527.
  60. ^ Smart, J.J.C, "Identity Theory", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2002 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  61. ^ Davidson, D. (2001). Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-88-7078-832-7.
  62. ^ a b Block, Ned. "What is functionalism" in Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, 2 vols. Vol 1. (Cambridge: Harvard, 1980).
  63. ^ Armstrong, D., 1968, A Materialist Theory of the Mind, Routledge.
  64. ^ Di Francesco M. & Marraffa M. (2013). "The Unconscious, consciousness, and the Self illusion" (PDF). Dialogues in Philosophy, Mental and Neuro Sciences. 6 (1): 10–22. (PDF) from the original on 2017-03-03.
  65. ^ Stanton, W.L. (1983). "Supervenience and Psychological Law in Anomalous Monism". Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 64: 72–9. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.1983.tb00185.x.
  66. ^ Jaegwon Kim, Philosophy of Mind, Westview Press; 2 edition (July 8, 2005) ISBN 0-8133-4269-4
  67. ^ Anthis, Jacy (2022). "Consciousness Semanticism: A Precise Eliminativist Theory of Consciousness". Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures 2021. Studies in Computational Intelligence. Vol. 1032. pp. 20–41. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-96993-6_3. ISBN 978-3-030-96992-9. Retrieved 7 August 2022.
  68. ^ McGinn, Colin. "Can We Solve the Mind–Body Problem?" 2016-12-26 at the Wayback Machine, Mind, New Series, Vol. 98, No. 391, July 1989 (pp. 349–366), p. 350.
    • Reprinted in O'Connor, Timothy and Robb, David. "Colin McGinn, Can We Solve the Mind–Body Problem?", Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings. Routledge, 2003, p. 438ff.
  69. ^ "Hard problem of Consciousness" 2015-04-20 at the Wayback Machine, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Josh Weisberg
  70. ^ a b Hacker, Peter (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Blackwel Pub. ISBN 978-1-4051-0838-6.
  71. ^ a b c Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1954). Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-631-14660-5.
  72. ^ Putnam, Hilary (2000). The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body, and World. New York: Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-10286-5.
  73. ^ Hubert Dreyfus, "Critique of Descartes I" (recorded lecture), University of California at Berkeley, Sept. 18, 2007.
  74. ^ Joseph Levine, Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap, in: Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 64, no. 4, October, 1983, 354–361
  75. ^ Jackson, F. (1986) "What Mary didn't Know", Journal of Philosophy, 83, 5, pp. 291–295.
  76. ^ McGinn, C. "Can the Mind-Body Problem Be Solved", Mind, New Series, Volume 98, Issue 391, pp. 349–366. a (online) 2007-09-28 at the Wayback Machine
  77. ^ Fodor, Jerry (1993). Psychosemantics. The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-06106-3.
  78. ^ Siegel, S. (2011)."The Contents of Perception", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/perception-contents/.
  79. ^ a b c d Pinker, S. (1997) How the Mind Works. tr. It: Come Funziona la Mente. Milan:Mondadori, 2000. ISBN 88-04-49908-7
  80. ^ a b c Bear, M. F. et al. Eds. (1995). Neuroscience: Exploring The Brain. Baltimore, Maryland, Williams and Wilkins. ISBN 0-7817-3944-6
  81. ^ a b c Pinel, J.P.J (1997). Psychobiology. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-88-15-07174-3.
  82. ^ Metzinger, Thomas (2003). Being No One – The Self Model Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge: MIT Press. pp. 349–366. ISBN 978-0-262-13417-0.
  83. ^ Sipser, M. (1998). Introduction to the Theory of Computation. Boston, Mass.: PWS Publishing Co. ISBN 978-0-534-94728-6.
  84. ^ a b Searle, John (1980). "Minds, Brains and Programs" (PDF). The Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 3 (3): 417–424. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00005756. S2CID 55303721.
  85. ^ Turing, Alan (October 1950), "Computing Machinery and Intelligence", Mind, LIX (236): 433–460, doi:10.1093/mind/LIX.236.433, ISSN 0026-4423
  86. ^ Russell, S. & Norvig, R. (1995). Artificial Intelligence:A Modern Approach. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, Inc. ISBN 978-0-13-103805-9.
  87. ^ "Encyclopedia of Psychology". 2019-03-07. from the original on 2008-05-13.
  88. ^ Thagard, Paul, Cognitive Science, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
  89. ^ Calvo, Paco; Gomila, Toni (2008). Handbook of Cognitive Science: An Embodied Approach. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-08-091487-9.
  90. ^ Mark Rowlands (2010). "Chapter 3: The mind embedded". The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. MIT Press. pp. 51 ff. ISBN 978-0-262-01455-7.
  91. ^ Dave Ward; Mog Stapleton (2012). "Es are good. Cognition as enacted, embodied, embedded, affective and extended". In Fabio Paglieri (ed.). Consciousness in Interaction: The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness. John Benjamins Publishing. pp. 89 ff. ISBN 978-90-272-1352-5. On-line version here 2014-04-10 at the Wayback Machine.
  92. ^ J. M. Luce: Chronic disorders of consciousness following coma: Part one: medical issues. In: Chest. Band 144, Nummer 4, Oktober 2013, S. 1381–1387, doi:10.1378/chest.13-0395, PMID 24081351 (Review).
  93. ^ a b c Dummett, M. (2001). Origini della Filosofia Analitica. Einaudi. ISBN 978-88-06-15286-4.
  94. ^ Hegel, G.W.F (1983). Phenomenology of Spirit. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-503169-0., translated by A.V. Miller with analysis of the text and foreword by J. N. Findlay (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) ISBN 0-19-824597-1 .
  95. ^ Husserl, Edmund (2008). Logische Untersuchungen. Akademie Verlag Berlin. ISBN 978-3-05-004391-3. trans.: Giovanni Piana. Milan: EST. ISBN 88-428-0949-7
  96. ^ a b c d "Philosopher Ted Honderich's Determinism web resource". from the original on 2008-05-16.
  97. ^ Russell, Paul, Freedom and Moral Sentiment: Hume's Way of Naturalizing Responsibility Oxford University Press: New York & Oxford, 1995.
  98. ^ Dennett, Daniel (1984). The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Cambridge MA: Bradford Books–MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-54042-1.
  99. ^ Descartes, René (1649). Passions of the Soul. Hackett Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-87220-035-7.
  100. ^ Kane, Robert (2009). "Libertarianism". Philosophical Studies. 144 (1): 39. doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9365-y. S2CID 262782420.
  101. ^ Dennett, C. & Hofstadter, D.R. (1981). The Mind's I. Bantam Books. ISBN 978-0-553-01412-9.
  102. ^ Searle, John (1 November 2004). Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press Inc, USA. ISBN 978-0-19-515733-8.
  103. ^ LeDoux, Joseph (2002). The Synaptic Self. New York: Viking Penguin. ISBN 978-88-7078-795-5.

Further reading edit

  • The London Philosophy Study Guide 2009-09-23 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject: Philosophy of Mind 2020-06-15 at the Wayback Machine
  • Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, 1980), p. 120, 125.
  • Pedro Jesús Teruel, Mente, cerebro y antropología en Kant (Madrid, 2008). ISBN 978-84-309-4688-4.
  • David J. Ungs, Better than one; how we each have two minds (London, 2004). ISBN 978-1-78220-173-1
  • Alfred North Whitehead Science and the Modern World (1925; reprinted London, 1985), pp. 68–70.
  • Edwin Burtt The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science, 2nd ed. (London, 1932), pp. 318–19.
  • Felix Deutsch (ed.) On the Mysterious Leap from the Mind to the Body (New York, 1959).
  • Herbert Feigl The "Mental" and the "Physical": The Essay and a Postscript (1967), in H. Feigl et al., (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Minneapolis, 1958), Vol. 2, pp. 370–497, at p. 373.
  • Nap Mabaquiao, Jr., (with foreword by Tim Crane). Manila: De La Salle University Publishing House, 2012.
  • Celia Green The Lost Cause: Causation and the Mind–Body Problem. (Oxford: Oxford Forum, 2003). Applies a sceptical view on causality to the problems of interactionism.
  • Gyatso, Geshe Kelsang Gyatso, Understanding the Mind: The Nature and Power of the Mind, Tharpa Publications (2nd. ed., 1997) ISBN 978-0-948006-78-4
  • Gerhard Medicus (2017). Being Human – Bridging the Gap between the Sciences of Body and Mind, Berlin VWB
  • Scott Robert Sehon, . Cambridge: MIT University Press, 2005.

External links edit

  • Philosophy of mind at PhilPapers
  • Philosophy of mind at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • "Theory of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Guide to Philosophy of Mind, compiled by David Chalmers.
  • , compiled by David Chalmers (Editor) & David Bourget (Assistant Editor).
  • , edited by Chris Eliasmith.
  • , by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners.
  • A list of online papers on consciousness and philosophy of mind, compiled by David Chalmers
  • , from the Indian Psychology series by Swami Veda Bharati.
  • [1] Gerhard Medicus: Being Human – Bridging the Gap between the Sciences of Body and Mind, Berlin 2017 VWB

philosophy, mind, confused, with, theory, mind, branch, philosophy, that, deals, with, nature, mind, relation, body, external, world, mind, body, problem, paradigmatic, issue, philosophy, mind, although, number, other, issues, addressed, such, hard, problem, c. Not to be confused with Theory of mind The Philosophy of mind is a branch of philosophy that deals with the nature of the mind and its relation to the body and the external world The mind body problem is a paradigmatic issue in philosophy of mind although a number of other issues are addressed such as the hard problem of consciousness and the nature of particular mental states 1 2 3 Aspects of the mind that are studied include mental events mental functions mental properties consciousness and its neural correlates the ontology of the mind the nature of cognition and of thought and the relationship of the mind to the body Dualism and monism are the two central schools of thought on the mind body problem although nuanced views have arisen that do not fit one or the other category neatly Dualism finds its entry into Western philosophy thanks to Rene Descartes in the 17th century 4 Substance dualists like Descartes argue that the mind is an independently existing substance whereas property dualists maintain that the mind is a group of independent properties that emerge from and cannot be reduced to the brain but that it is not a distinct substance 5 Monism is the position that mind and body are ontologically indiscernible entities not dependent substances This view was espoused by the 17th century rationalist Baruch Spinoza 6 Physicalists argue that only entities postulated by physical theory exist and that mental processes will eventually be explained in terms of these entities as physical theory continues to evolve Physicalists maintain various positions on the prospects of reducing mental properties to physical properties many of whom adopt compatible forms of property dualism 7 8 9 10 11 12 and the ontological status of such mental properties remains unclear 11 13 14 Idealists maintain that the mind is all that exists and that the external world is either mental itself or an illusion created by the mind Neutral monists such as Ernst Mach and William James argue that events in the world can be thought of as either mental psychological or physical depending on the network of relationships into which they enter and dual aspect monists such as Spinoza adhere to the position that there is some other neutral substance and that both matter and mind are properties of this unknown substance The most common monisms in the 20th and 21st centuries have all been variations of physicalism these positions include behaviorism the type identity theory anomalous monism and functionalism 15 Most modern philosophers of mind adopt either a reductive physicalist or non reductive physicalist position maintaining in their different ways that the mind is not something separate from the body 15 These approaches have been particularly influential in the sciences especially in the fields of sociobiology computer science specifically artificial intelligence evolutionary psychology and the various neurosciences 16 17 18 19 Reductive physicalists assert that all mental states and properties will eventually be explained by scientific accounts of physiological processes and states 20 21 22 Non reductive physicalists argue that although the mind is not a separate substance mental properties supervene on physical properties or that the predicates and vocabulary used in mental descriptions and explanations are indispensable and cannot be reduced to the language and lower level explanations of physical science 23 24 Continued neuroscientific progress has helped to clarify some of these issues however they are far from being resolved Modern philosophers of mind continue to ask how the subjective qualities and the intentionality of mental states and properties can be explained in naturalistic terms 25 26 The problems of physicalist theories of the mind have led some contemporary philosophers to assert that the traditional view of substance dualism should be defended From this perspective this theory is coherent and problems such as the interaction of mind and body can be rationally resolved 27 Contents 1 Mind body problem 1 1 Dualist solutions to the mind body problem 1 1 1 Arguments for dualism 1 1 2 Interactionist dualism 1 1 3 Other forms of dualism 1 1 3 1 Psychophysical parallelism 1 1 3 2 Occasionalism 1 1 3 3 Property dualism 1 1 3 4 Dual aspect theory 1 1 3 5 Experiential dualism 1 2 Monist solutions to the mind body problem 1 2 1 Physicalistic monisms 1 2 1 1 Behaviorism 1 2 1 2 Identity theory 1 2 1 3 Functionalism 1 2 1 4 Non reductive physicalism 1 2 1 5 Weak emergentism 1 2 1 6 Eliminative materialism 1 3 Mysterianism 1 4 Linguistic criticism of the mind body problem 1 5 Naturalism and its problems 1 5 1 Qualia 1 5 2 Intentionality 2 Philosophy of perception 3 Philosophy of mind and science 3 1 Neurobiology 3 2 Computer science 3 3 Psychology 3 4 Cognitive science 3 5 Near death research 4 Philosophy of mind in the continental tradition 5 Topics related to philosophy of mind 5 1 Free will 5 2 Self 6 See also 7 References 8 Further reading 9 External linksMind body problem editMain article Mind body problem nbsp Rene Descartes illustration of mind body dualism The mind body problem concerns the explanation of the relationship that exists between minds or mental processes and bodily states or processes 1 The main aim of philosophers working in this area is to determine the nature of the mind and mental states processes and how or even if minds are affected by and can affect the body Perceptual experiences depend on stimuli that arrive at our various sensory organs from the external world and these stimuli cause changes in our mental states ultimately causing us to feel a sensation which may be pleasant or unpleasant Someone s desire for a slice of pizza for example will tend to cause that person to move his or her body in a specific manner and in a specific direction to obtain what he or she wants The question then is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to arise out of a lump of gray matter endowed with nothing but electrochemical properties 15 A related problem is how someone s propositional attitudes e g beliefs and desires cause that individual s neurons to fire and muscles to contract These comprise some of the puzzles that have confronted epistemologists and philosophers of mind from the time of Rene Descartes 4 Dualist solutions to the mind body problem edit See also Mind in eastern philosophy Dualism is a set of views about the relationship between mind and matter or body It begins with the claim that mental phenomena are in some respects non physical 5 One of the earliest known formulations of mind body dualism was expressed in the eastern Samkhya and Yoga schools of Hindu philosophy c 650 BCE which divided the world into purusha mind spirit and prakriti material substance 28 Specifically the Yoga Sutra of Patanjali presents an analytical approach to the nature of the mind In Western Philosophy the earliest discussions of dualist ideas are in the writings of Plato who suggested that humans intelligence a faculty of the mind or soul could not be identified with or explained in terms of their physical body 29 30 However the best known version of dualism is due to Rene Descartes 1641 and holds that the mind is a non extended non physical substance a res cogitans 4 Descartes was the first to clearly identify the mind with consciousness and self awareness and to distinguish this from the brain which was the seat of intelligence He was therefore the first to formulate the mind body problem in the form in which it still exists today 4 Arguments for dualism edit The most frequently used argument in favor of dualism appeals to the common sense intuition that conscious experience is distinct from inanimate matter If asked what the mind is the average person would usually respond by identifying it with their self their personality their soul or another related entity They would almost certainly deny that the mind simply is the brain or vice versa finding the idea that there is just one ontological entity at play to be too mechanistic or unintelligible 5 Modern philosophers of mind think that these intuitions are misleading and that critical faculties along with empirical evidence from the sciences should be used to examine these assumptions and determine whether there is any real basis to them 5 The mental and the physical seem to have quite different and perhaps irreconcilable properties 31 Mental events have a subjective quality whereas physical events do not So for example one can reasonably ask what a burnt finger feels like or what a blue sky looks like or what nice music sounds like to a person But it is meaningless or at least odd to ask what a surge in the uptake of glutamate in the dorsolateral portion of the prefrontal cortex feels like Philosophers of mind call the subjective aspects of mental events qualia or raw feels 31 There are qualia involved in these mental events that seem particularly difficult to reduce to anything physical David Chalmers explains this argument by stating that we could conceivably know all the objective information about something such as the brain states and wavelengths of light involved with seeing the color red but still not know something fundamental about the situation what it is like to see the color red 32 If consciousness the mind can exist independently of physical reality the brain one must explain how physical memories are created concerning consciousness Dualism must therefore explain how consciousness affects physical reality One possible explanation is that of a miracle proposed by Arnold Geulincx and Nicolas Malebranche where all mind body interactions require the direct intervention of God Another argument that has been proposed by C S Lewis 33 is the Argument from Reason if as monism implies all of our thoughts are the effects of physical causes then we have no reason for assuming that they are also the consequent of a reasonable ground Knowledge however is apprehended by reasoning from ground to consequent Therefore if monism is correct there would be no way of knowing this or anything else we could not even suppose it except by a fluke The zombie argument is based on a thought experiment proposed by Todd Moody and developed by David Chalmers in his book The Conscious Mind The basic idea is that one can imagine one s body and therefore conceive the existence of one s body without any conscious states being associated with this body Chalmers argument is that it seems possible that such a being could exist because all that is needed is that all and only the things that the physical sciences describe about a zombie must be true of it Since none of the concepts involved in these sciences make reference to consciousness or other mental phenomena and any physical entity can be by definition described scientifically via physics the move from conceivability to possibility is not such a large one 34 Others such as Dennett have argued that the notion of a philosophical zombie is an incoherent 35 or unlikely 36 concept It has been argued under physicalism that one must either believe that anyone including oneself might be a zombie or that no one can be a zombie following from the assertion that one s own conviction about being or not being a zombie is a product of the physical world and is therefore no different from anyone else s This argument has been expressed by Dennett who argues that Zombies think they are conscious think they have qualia think they suffer pains they are just wrong according to this lamentable tradition in ways that neither they nor we could ever discover 35 See also the problem of other minds Interactionist dualism edit nbsp Portrait of Rene Descartes by Frans Hals 1648 Interactionist dualism or simply interactionism is the particular form of dualism first espoused by Descartes in the Meditations 4 In the 20th century its major defenders have been Karl Popper and John Carew Eccles 37 It is the view that mental states such as beliefs and desires causally interact with physical states 5 Descartes s argument for this position can be summarized as follows Seth has a clear and distinct idea of his mind as a thinking thing that has no spatial extension i e it cannot be measured in terms of length weight height and so on He also has a clear and distinct idea of his body as something that is spatially extended subject to quantification and not able to think It follows that mind and body are not identical because they have radically different properties 4 Seth s mental states desires beliefs etc have causal effects on his body and vice versa A child touches a hot stove physical event which causes pain mental event and makes her yell physical event this in turn provokes a sense of fear and protectiveness in the caregiver mental event and so on Descartes argument depends on the premise that what Seth believes to be clear and distinct ideas in his mind are necessarily true Many contemporary philosophers doubt this 38 39 40 For example Joseph Agassi suggests that several scientific discoveries made since the early 20th century have undermined the idea of privileged access to one s own ideas Freud claimed that a psychologically trained observer can understand a person s unconscious motivations better than the person himself does Duhem has shown that a philosopher of science can know a person s methods of discovery better than that person herself does while Malinowski has shown that an anthropologist can know a person s customs and habits better than the person whose customs and habits they are He also asserts that modern psychological experiments that cause people to see things that are not there provide grounds for rejecting Descartes argument because scientists can describe a person s perceptions better than the person herself can 41 42 Other forms of dualism edit nbsp Four varieties of dualism The arrows indicate the direction of the causal interactions Occasionalism is not shown Psychophysical parallelism edit Psychophysical parallelism or simply parallelism is the view that mind and body while having distinct ontological statuses do not causally influence one another Instead they run along parallel paths mind events causally interact with mind events and brain events causally interact with brain events and only seem to influence each other 43 This view was most prominently defended by Gottfried Leibniz Although Leibniz was an ontological monist who believed that only one type of substance the monad exists in the universe and that everything is reducible to it he nonetheless maintained that there was an important distinction between the mental and the physical in terms of causation He held that God had arranged things in advance so that minds and bodies would be in harmony with each other This is known as the doctrine of pre established harmony 44 Occasionalism edit Occasionalism is the view espoused by Nicholas Malebranche as well as Islamic philosophers such as Abu Hamid Muhammad ibn Muhammad al Ghazali that asserts all supposedly causal relations between physical events or between physical and mental events are not really causal at all While body and mind are different substances causes whether mental or physical are related to their effects by an act of God s intervention on each specific occasion 45 Property dualism edit Property dualism is the view that the world is constituted of one kind of substance the physical kind and there exist two distinct kinds of properties physical properties and mental properties It is the view that non physical mental properties such as beliefs desires and emotions inhere in some physical bodies at least brains Sub varieties of property dualism include Emergent materialism asserts that when matter is organized in the appropriate way i e in the way that living human bodies are organized mental properties emerge in a way not fully accountable for by physical laws 5 These emergent properties have an independent ontological status and cannot be reduced to or explained in terms of the physical substrate from which they emerge They are dependent on the physical properties from which they emerge but opinions vary as to the coherence of top down causation that is the causal effectiveness of such properties A form of emergent materialism has been espoused by David Chalmers and the concept has undergone something of a renaissance in recent years 46 but it was already suggested in the 19th century by William James Epiphenomenalism is a doctrine first formulated by Thomas Henry Huxley 47 It consists of the view that mental phenomena are causally ineffectual where one or more mental states do not have any influence on physical states or mental phenomena are the effects but not the causes of physical phenomena Physical events can cause other physical and mental events but mental events cannot cause anything since they are just causally inert by products i e epiphenomena of the physical world 43 This view has been defended by Frank Jackson 48 Non reductive physicalism is the view that mental properties form a separate ontological class to physical properties mental states such as qualia are not reducible to physical states The ontological stance towards qualia in the case of non reductive physicalism does not imply that qualia are causally inert this is what distinguishes it from epiphenomenalism Panpsychism is the view that all matter has a mental aspect or alternatively all objects have a unified center of experience or point of view Superficially it seems to be a form of property dualism since it regards everything as having both mental and physical properties However some panpsychists say that mechanical behaviour is derived from the primitive mentality of atoms and molecules as are sophisticated mentality and organic behaviour the difference being attributed to the presence or absence of complex structure in a compound object So long as the reduction of non mental properties to mental ones is in place panpsychism is not a strong form of property dualism otherwise it is Dual aspect theory edit Dual aspect theory or dual aspect monism is the view that the mental and the physical are two aspects of or perspectives on the same substance Thus it is a mixed position which is monistic in some respects In modern philosophical writings the theory s relationship to neutral monism has become somewhat ill defined but one proffered distinction says that whereas neutral monism allows the context of a given group of neutral elements and the relationships into which they enter to determine whether the group can be thought of as mental physical both or neither dual aspect theory suggests that the mental and the physical are manifestations or aspects of some underlying substance entity or process that is itself neither mental nor physical as normally understood Various formulations of dual aspect monism also require the mental and the physical to be complementary mutually irreducible and perhaps inseparable though distinct 49 50 51 Experiential dualism edit This is a philosophy of mind that regards the degrees of freedom between mental and physical well being as not synonymous thus implying an experiential dualism between body and mind An example of these disparate degrees of freedom is given by Allan Wallace who notes that it is experientially apparent that one may be physically uncomfortable for instance while engaging in a strenuous physical workout while mentally cheerful conversely one may be mentally distraught while experiencing physical comfort 52 Experiential dualism notes that our subjective experience of merely seeing something in the physical world seems qualitatively different from mental processes like grief that comes from losing a loved one This philosophy is a proponent of causal dualism which is defined as the dual ability for mental states and physical states to affect one another Mental states can cause changes in physical states and vice versa However unlike cartesian dualism or some other systems experiential dualism does not posit two fundamental substances in reality mind and matter Rather experiential dualism is to be understood as a conceptual framework that gives credence to the qualitative difference between the experience of mental and physical states Experiential dualism is accepted as the conceptual framework of Madhyamaka Buddhism Madhayamaka Buddhism goes further finding fault with the monist view of physicalist philosophies of mind as well in that these generally posit matter and energy as the fundamental substance of reality Nonetheless this does not imply that the cartesian dualist view is correct rather Madhyamaka regards as error any affirming view of a fundamental substance to reality In denying the independent self existence of all the phenomena that make up the world of our experience the Madhyamaka view departs from both the substance dualism of Descartes and the substance monism namely physicalism that is characteristic of modern science The physicalism propounded by many contemporary scientists seems to assert that the real world is composed of physical things in themselves while all mental phenomena are regarded as mere appearances devoid of any reality in and of themselves Much is made of this difference between appearances and reality 52 Indeed physicalism or the idea that matter is the only fundamental substance of reality is explicitly rejected by Buddhism In the Madhyamaka view mental events are no more or less real than physical events In terms of our common sense experience differences of kind do exist between physical and mental phenomena While the former commonly have mass location velocity shape size and numerous other physical attributes these are not generally characteristic of mental phenomena For example we do not commonly conceive of the feeling of affection for another person as having mass or location These physical attributes are no more appropriate to other mental events such as sadness a recalled image from one s childhood the visual perception of a rose or consciousness of any sort Mental phenomena are therefore not regarded as being physical for the simple reason that they lack many of the attributes that are uniquely characteristic of physical phenomena Thus Buddhism has never adopted the physicalist principle that regards only physical things as real 52 Monist solutions to the mind body problem edit In contrast to dualism monism does not accept any fundamental divisions The fundamentally disparate nature of reality has been central to forms of eastern philosophies for over two millennia In Indian and Chinese philosophy monism is integral to how experience is understood Today the most common forms of monism in Western philosophy are physicalist 15 Physicalistic monism asserts that the only existing substance is physical in some sense of that term to be clarified by our best science 53 However a variety of formulations see below are possible Another form of monism idealism states that the only existing substance is mental Although pure idealism such as that of George Berkeley is uncommon in contemporary Western philosophy a more sophisticated variant called panpsychism according to which mental experience and properties may be at the foundation of physical experience and properties has been espoused by some philosophers such as Alfred North Whitehead 54 and David Ray Griffin 46 Phenomenalism is the theory that representations or sense data of external objects are all that exist Such a view was briefly adopted by Bertrand Russell and many of the logical positivists during the early 20th century 55 A third possibility is to accept the existence of a basic substance that is neither physical nor mental The mental and physical would then both be properties of this neutral substance Such a position was adopted by Baruch Spinoza 6 and was popularized by Ernst Mach 56 in the 19th century This neutral monism as it is called resembles property dualism Physicalistic monisms edit Behaviorism edit Main article Behaviorism Behaviorism dominated philosophy of mind for much of the 20th century especially the first half 15 In psychology behaviorism developed as a reaction to the inadequacies of introspectionism 53 Introspective reports on one s own interior mental life are not subject to careful examination for accuracy and cannot be used to form predictive generalizations Without generalizability and the possibility of third person examination the behaviorists argued psychology cannot be scientific 53 The way out therefore was to eliminate the idea of an interior mental life and hence an ontologically independent mind altogether and focus instead on the description of observable behavior 57 Parallel to these developments in psychology a philosophical behaviorism sometimes called logical behaviorism was developed 53 This is characterized by a strong verificationism which generally considers unverifiable statements about interior mental life pointless For the behaviorist mental states are not interior states on which one can make introspective reports They are just descriptions of behavior or dispositions to behave in certain ways made by third parties to explain and predict another s behavior 58 Philosophical behaviorism has fallen out of favor since the latter half of the 20th century coinciding with the rise of cognitivism 1 Identity theory edit Main article Type physicalism Type physicalism or type identity theory was developed by Jack Smart 22 and Ullin Place 59 as a direct reaction to the failure of behaviorism These philosophers reasoned that if mental states are something material but not behavioral then mental states are probably identical to internal states of the brain In very simplified terms a mental state M is nothing other than brain state B The mental state desire for a cup of coffee would thus be nothing more than the firing of certain neurons in certain brain regions 22 nbsp The classic Identity theory and Anomalous Monism in contrast For the Identity theory every token instantiation of a single mental type corresponds as indicated by the arrows to a physical token of a single physical type For anomalous monism the token token correspondences can fall outside of the type type correspondences The result is token identity On the other hand even granted the above it does not follow that identity theories of all types must be abandoned According to token identity theories the fact that a certain brain state is connected with only one mental state of a person does not have to mean that there is an absolute correlation between types of mental state and types of brain state The type token distinction can be illustrated by a simple example the word green contains four types of letters g r e n with two tokens occurrences of the letter e along with one each of the others The idea of token identity is that only particular occurrences of mental events are identical with particular occurrences or tokenings of physical events 60 Anomalous monism see below and most other non reductive physicalisms are token identity theories 61 Despite these problems there is a renewed interest in the type identity theory today primarily due to the influence of Jaegwon Kim 22 Functionalism edit Main article Functionalism philosophy of mind Functionalism was formulated by Hilary Putnam and Jerry Fodor as a reaction to the inadequacies of the identity theory 24 Putnam and Fodor saw mental states in terms of an empirical computational theory of the mind 62 At about the same time or slightly after D M Armstrong and David Kellogg Lewis formulated a version of functionalism that analyzed the mental concepts of folk psychology in terms of functional roles 63 Finally Wittgenstein s idea of meaning as use led to a version of functionalism as a theory of meaning further developed by Wilfrid Sellars and Gilbert Harman Another one psychofunctionalism is an approach adopted by the naturalistic philosophy of mind associated with Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn Mental states are characterized by their causal relations with other mental states and with sensory inputs and behavioral outputs Functionalism abstracts away from the details of the physical implementation of a mental state by characterizing it in terms of non mental functional properties For example a kidney is characterized scientifically by its functional role in filtering blood and maintaining certain chemical balances 62 Non reductive physicalism edit Main article Physicalism Non reductionist philosophers hold firmly to two essential convictions with regard to mind body relations 1 Physicalism is true and mental states must be physical states but 2 All reductionist proposals are unsatisfactory mental states cannot be reduced to behavior brain states or functional states 53 Hence the question arises whether there can still be a non reductive physicalism Donald Davidson s anomalous monism 23 is an attempt to formulate such a physicalism He thinks that when one runs across what are traditionally seen as absurdities of Reason such as akrasia or self deception the personal psychology framework is not to be given up in favor of the subpersonal one but rather must be enlarged or extended so that the rationality set out by the principle of charity can be found elsewhere 64 Davidson uses the thesis of supervenience mental states supervene on physical states but are not reducible to them Supervenience therefore describes a functional dependence there can be no change in the mental without some change in the physical causal reducibility between the mental and physical without ontological reducibility 65 Weak emergentism edit Main article Emergentism Weak emergentism is a form of non reductive physicalism that involves a layered view of nature with the layers arranged in terms of increasing complexity and each corresponding to its own special science Some philosophers who hold that emergent properties causally interact with more fundamental levels while others maintain that higher order properties simply supervene over lower levels without direct causal interaction The latter group therefore holds a less strict or weaker definition of emergentism which can be rigorously stated as follows a property P of composite object O is emergent if it is metaphysically impossible for another object to lack property P if that object is composed of parts with intrinsic properties identical to those in O and has those parts in an identical configuration citation needed Sometimes emergentists use the example of water having a new property when Hydrogen H and Oxygen O combine to form H2O water In this example there emerges a new property of a transparent liquid that would not have been predicted by understanding hydrogen and oxygen as gases This is analogous to physical properties of the brain giving rise to a mental state Emergentists try to solve the notorious mind body gap this way One problem for emergentism is the idea of causal closure in the world that does not allow for a mind to body causation 66 Eliminative materialism edit Main article Eliminative materialism If one is a materialist and believes that all aspects of our common sense psychology will find reduction to a mature cognitive neuroscience and that non reductive materialism is mistaken then one can adopt a final more radical position eliminative materialism There are several varieties of eliminative materialism but all maintain that our common sense folk psychology badly misrepresents the nature of some aspect of cognition Eliminativists such as Patricia and Paul Churchland argue that while folk psychology treats cognition as fundamentally sentence like the non linguistic vector matrix model of neural network theory or connectionism will prove to be a much more accurate account of how the brain works 20 The Churchlands often invoke the fate of other erroneous popular theories and ontologies that have arisen in the course of history 20 21 For example Ptolemaic astronomy served to explain and roughly predict the motions of the planets for centuries but eventually this model of the solar system was eliminated in favor of the Copernican model The Churchlands believe the same eliminative fate awaits the sentence cruncher model of the mind in which thought and behavior are the result of manipulating sentence like states called propositional attitudes Sociologist Jacy Reese Anthis argues for eliminative materialism on all faculties of mind including consciousness stating The deepest mysteries of the mind are within our reach 67 Mysterianism edit Main article New mysterianism Some philosophers take an epistemic approach and argue that the mind body problem is currently unsolvable and perhaps will always remain unsolvable to human beings This is usually termed New mysterianism Colin McGinn holds that human beings are cognitively closed in regards to their own minds According to McGinn human minds lack the concept forming procedures to fully grasp how mental properties such as consciousness arise from their causal basis 68 An example would be how an elephant is cognitively closed in regards to particle physics A more moderate conception has been expounded by Thomas Nagel which holds that the mind body problem is currently unsolvable at the present stage of scientific development and that it might take a future scientific paradigm shift or revolution to bridge the explanatory gap Nagel posits that in the future a sort of objective phenomenology might be able to bridge the gap between subjective conscious experience and its physical basis 69 Linguistic criticism of the mind body problem edit Each attempt to answer the mind body problem encounters substantial problems Some philosophers argue that this is because there is an underlying conceptual confusion 70 These philosophers such as Ludwig Wittgenstein and his followers in the tradition of linguistic criticism therefore reject the problem as illusory 71 They argue that it is an error to ask how mental and biological states fit together Rather it should simply be accepted that human experience can be described in different ways for instance in a mental and in a biological vocabulary Illusory problems arise if one tries to describe the one in terms of the other s vocabulary or if the mental vocabulary is used in the wrong contexts 71 This is the case for instance if one searches for mental states of the brain The brain is simply the wrong context for the use of mental vocabulary the search for mental states of the brain is therefore a category error or a sort of fallacy of reasoning 71 Today such a position is often adopted by interpreters of Wittgenstein such as Peter Hacker 70 However Hilary Putnam the originator of functionalism has also adopted the position that the mind body problem is an illusory problem which should be dissolved according to the manner of Wittgenstein 72 Naturalism and its problems edit The thesis of physicalism is that the mind is part of the material or physical world Such a position faces the problem that the mind has certain properties that no other material thing seems to possess Physicalism must therefore explain how it is possible that these properties can nonetheless emerge from a material thing The project of providing such an explanation is often referred to as the naturalization of the mental 53 Some of the crucial problems that this project attempts to resolve include the existence of qualia and the nature of intentionality 53 Qualia edit Main article Qualia Many mental states seem to be experienced subjectively in different ways by different individuals 32 And it is characteristic of a mental state that it has some experiential quality e g of pain that it hurts However the sensation of pain between two individuals may not be identical since no one has a perfect way to measure how much something hurts or of describing exactly how it feels to hurt Philosophers and scientists therefore ask where these experiences come from The existence of cerebral events in and of themselves cannot explain why they are accompanied by these corresponding qualitative experiences The puzzle of why many cerebral processes occur with an accompanying experiential aspect in consciousness seems impossible to explain 31 Yet it also seems to many that science will eventually have to explain such experiences 53 This follows from an assumption about the possibility of reductive explanations According to this view if an attempt can be successfully made to explain a phenomenon reductively e g water then it can be explained why the phenomenon has all of its properties e g fluidity transparency 53 In the case of mental states this means that there needs to be an explanation of why they have the property of being experienced in a certain way The 20th century German philosopher Martin Heidegger criticized the ontological assumptions underpinning such a reductive model and claimed that it was impossible to make sense of experience in these terms This is because according to Heidegger the nature of our subjective experience and its qualities is impossible to understand in terms of Cartesian substances that bear properties Another way to put this is that the very concept of qualitative experience is incoherent in terms of or is semantically incommensurable with the concept of substances that bear properties 73 This problem of explaining introspective first person aspects of mental states and consciousness in general in terms of third person quantitative neuroscience is called the explanatory gap 74 There are several different views of the nature of this gap among contemporary philosophers of mind David Chalmers and the early Frank Jackson interpret the gap as ontological in nature that is they maintain that qualia can never be explained by science because physicalism is false There are two separate categories involved and one cannot be reduced to the other 75 An alternative view is taken by philosophers such as Thomas Nagel and Colin McGinn According to them the gap is epistemological in nature For Nagel science is not yet able to explain subjective experience because it has not yet arrived at the level or kind of knowledge that is required We are not even able to formulate the problem coherently 32 For McGinn on other hand the problem is one of permanent and inherent biological limitations We are not able to resolve the explanatory gap because the realm of subjective experiences is cognitively closed to us in the same manner that quantum physics is cognitively closed to elephants 76 Other philosophers liquidate the gap as purely a semantic problem This semantic problem of course led to the famous Qualia Question which is Does Red cause Redness Intentionality edit Main article Intentionality nbsp John Searle one of the most influential philosophers of mind proponent of biological naturalism Berkeley 2002 Intentionality is the capacity of mental states to be directed towards about or be in relation with something in the external world 26 This property of mental states entails that they have contents and semantic referents and can therefore be assigned truth values When one tries to reduce these states to natural processes there arises a problem natural processes are not true or false they simply happen 77 It would not make any sense to say that a natural process is true or false But mental ideas or judgments are true or false so how then can mental states ideas or judgments be natural processes The possibility of assigning semantic value to ideas must mean that such ideas are about facts Thus for example the idea that Herodotus was a historian refers to Herodotus and to the fact that he was a historian If the fact is true then the idea is true otherwise it is false But where does this relation come from In the brain there are only electrochemical processes and these seem not to have anything to do with Herodotus 25 Philosophy of perception editMain article Philosophy of perception Philosophy of perception is concerned with the nature of perceptual experience and the status of perceptual objects in particular how perceptual experience relates to appearances and beliefs about the world The main contemporary views within philosophy of perception include naive realism enactivism and representational views 2 3 78 nbsp A phrenological mapping of the brain phrenology was among the first attempts to correlate mental functions with specific parts of the brain although it is now widely discredited Philosophy of mind and science editHumans are corporeal beings and as such they are subject to examination and description by the natural sciences Since mental processes are intimately related to bodily processes e g embodied cognition theory of mind the descriptions that the natural sciences furnish of human beings play an important role in the philosophy of mind 1 There are many scientific disciplines that study processes related to the mental The list of such sciences includes biology computer science cognitive science cybernetics linguistics medicine pharmacology and psychology 79 Neurobiology edit Main article Neuroscience The theoretical background of biology as is the case with modern natural sciences in general is fundamentally materialistic The objects of study are in the first place physical processes which are considered to be the foundations of mental activity and behavior 80 The increasing success of biology in the explanation of mental phenomena can be seen by the absence of any empirical refutation of its fundamental presupposition there can be no change in the mental states of a person without a change in brain states 79 Within the field of neurobiology there are many subdisciplines that are concerned with the relations between mental and physical states and processes 80 Sensory neurophysiology investigates the relation between the processes of perception and stimulation 81 Cognitive neuroscience studies the correlations between mental processes and neural processes 81 Neuropsychology describes the dependence of mental faculties on specific anatomical regions of the brain 81 Lastly evolutionary biology studies the origins and development of the human nervous system and in as much as this is the basis of the mind also describes the ontogenetic and phylogenetic development of mental phenomena beginning from their most primitive stages 79 Evolutionary biology furthermore places tight constraints on any philosophical theory of the mind as the gene based mechanism of natural selection does not allow any giant leaps in the development of neural complexity or neural software but only incremental steps over long time periods 82 nbsp Since the 1980s sophisticated neuroimaging procedures such as fMRI above have furnished increasing knowledge about the workings of the human brain shedding light on ancient philosophical problems The methodological breakthroughs of the neurosciences in particular the introduction of high tech neuroimaging procedures has propelled scientists toward the elaboration of increasingly ambitious research programs one of the main goals is to describe and comprehend the neural processes which correspond to mental functions see neural correlate 80 Several groups are inspired by these advances Computer science edit Main article Computer science Computer science concerns itself with the automatic processing of information or at least with physical systems of symbols to which information is assigned by means of such things as computers 83 From the beginning computer programmers have been able to develop programs that permit computers to carry out tasks for which organic beings need a mind A simple example is multiplication It is not clear whether computers could be said to have a mind Could they someday come to have what we call a mind This question has been propelled into the forefront of much philosophical debate because of investigations in the field of artificial intelligence AI Within AI it is common to distinguish between a modest research program and a more ambitious one this distinction was coined by John Searle in terms of a weak AI and strong AI The exclusive objective of weak AI according to Searle is the successful simulation of mental states with no attempt to make computers become conscious or aware etc The objective of strong AI on the contrary is a computer with consciousness similar to that of human beings 84 The program of strong AI goes back to one of the pioneers of computation Alan Turing As an answer to the question Can computers think he formulated the famous Turing test 85 Turing believed that a computer could be said to think when if placed in a room by itself next to another room that contained a human being and with the same questions being asked of both the computer and the human being by a third party human being the computer s responses turned out to be indistinguishable from those of the human Essentially Turing s view of machine intelligence followed the behaviourist model of the mind intelligence is as intelligence does The Turing test has received many criticisms among which the most famous is probably the Chinese room thought experiment formulated by Searle 84 The question about the possible sensitivity qualia of computers or robots still remains open Some computer scientists believe that the specialty of AI can still make new contributions to the resolution of the mind body problem They suggest that based on the reciprocal influences between software and hardware that takes place in all computers it is possible that someday theories can be discovered that help us to understand the reciprocal influences between the human mind and the brain wetware 86 Psychology edit Main article Psychology Psychology is the science that investigates mental states directly It uses generally empirical methods to investigate concrete mental states like joy fear or obsessions Psychology investigates the laws that bind these mental states to each other or with inputs and outputs to the human organism 87 An example of this is the psychology of perception Scientists working in this field have discovered general principles of the perception of forms A law of the psychology of forms says that objects that move in the same direction are perceived as related to each other 79 This law describes a relation between visual input and mental perceptual states However it does not suggest anything about the nature of perceptual states The laws discovered by psychology are compatible with all the answers to the mind body problem already described Cognitive science edit Cognitive science is the interdisciplinary scientific study of the mind and its processes It examines what cognition is what it does and how it works It includes research on intelligence and behavior especially focusing on how information is represented processed and transformed in faculties such as perception language memory reasoning and emotion within nervous systems human or other animals and machines e g computers Cognitive science consists of multiple research disciplines including psychology artificial intelligence philosophy neuroscience linguistics anthropology sociology and education 88 It spans many levels of analysis from low level learning and decision mechanisms to high level logic and planning from neural circuitry to modular brain organization Over the years cognitive science has evolved from a representational and information processing approach to explaining the mind to embrace an embodied perspective of it Accordingly bodily processes play a significant role in the acquisition development and shaping of cognitive capabilities 89 For instance Rowlands 2012 argues that cognition is enactive embodied embedded affective and potentially extended The position is taken that the classical sandwich of cognition sandwiched between perception and action is artificial cognition has to be seen as a product of a strongly coupled interaction that cannot be divided this way 90 91 Near death research edit Main article Near death studies In the field of near death research the following phenomenon among others occurs For example during some brain operations the brain is artificially and measurably deactivated Nevertheless some patients report during this phase that they have perceived what is happening in their surroundings that is that they have had consciousness Patients also report experiences during a cardiac arrest There is the following problem As soon as the brain is no longer supplied with blood and thus with oxygen after a cardiac arrest the brain ceases its normal operation after about 15 seconds that is the brain falls into a state of unconsciousness 92 Philosophy of mind in the continental tradition editMost of the discussion in this article has focused on one style or tradition of philosophy in modern Western culture usually called analytic philosophy sometimes described as Anglo American philosophy 93 Many other schools of thought exist however which are sometimes subsumed under the broad and vague label of continental philosophy 93 In any case though topics and methods here are numerous in relation to the philosophy of mind the various schools that fall under this label phenomenology existentialism etc can globally be seen to differ from the analytic school in that they focus less on language and logical analysis alone but also take in other forms of understanding human existence and experience With reference specifically to the discussion of the mind this tends to translate into attempts to grasp the concepts of thought and perceptual experience in some sense that does not merely involve the analysis of linguistic forms 93 Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason first published in 1781 and presented again with major revisions in 1787 represents a significant intervention into what will later become known as the philosophy of mind Kant s first critique is generally recognized as among the most significant works of modern philosophy in the West Kant is a figure whose influence is marked in both continental and analytic Anglo American philosophy Kant s work develops an in depth study of transcendental consciousness or the life of the mind as conceived through the universal categories of understanding In Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel s Philosophy of Mind frequently translated as Philosophy of Spirit or Geist 94 the third part of his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences Hegel discusses three distinct types of mind the subjective mind spirit the mind of an individual the objective mind spirit the mind of society and of the State and the Absolute mind spirit the position of religion art and philosophy See also Hegel s The Phenomenology of Spirit Nonetheless Hegel s work differs radically from the style of Anglo American philosophy of mind In 1896 Henri Bergson made in Matter and Memory Essay on the relation of body and spirit a forceful case for the ontological difference of body and mind by reducing the problem to the more definite one of memory thus allowing for a solution built on the empirical test case of aphasia In modern times the two main schools that have developed in response or opposition to this Hegelian tradition are phenomenology and existentialism Phenomenology founded by Edmund Husserl focuses on the contents of the human mind see noema and how processes shape our experiences 95 Existentialism a school of thought founded upon the work of Soren Kierkegaard focuses on Human predicament and how people deal with the situation of being alive Existential phenomenology represents a major branch of continental philosophy they are not contradictory rooted in the work of Husserl but expressed in its fullest forms in the work of Martin Heidegger Jean Paul Sartre Simone de Beauvoir and Maurice Merleau Ponty See Heidegger s Being and Time Merleau Ponty s Phenomenology of Perception Sartre s Being and Nothingness and Simone de Beauvoir s The Second Sex Topics related to philosophy of mind editThere are countless subjects that are affected by the ideas developed in the philosophy of mind Clear examples of this are the nature of death and its definitive character the nature of emotion of perception and of memory Questions about what a person is and what his or her identity have to do with the philosophy of mind There are two subjects that in connection with the philosophy of the mind have aroused special attention free will and the self 1 Free will edit Main article Free will In the context of philosophy of mind the problem of free will takes on renewed intensity This is the case for materialistic determinists 1 According to this position natural laws completely determine the course of the material world Mental states and therefore the will as well would be material states which means human behavior and decisions would be completely determined by natural laws Some take this reasoning a step further people cannot determine by themselves what they want and what they do Consequently they are not free 96 This argumentation is rejected on the one hand by the compatibilists Those who adopt this position suggest that the question Are we free can only be answered once we have determined what the term free means The opposite of free is not caused but compelled or coerced It is not appropriate to identify freedom with indetermination A free act is one where the agent could have done otherwise if it had chosen otherwise In this sense a person can be free even though determinism is true 96 The most important compatibilist in the history of the philosophy was David Hume 97 More recently this position is defended for example by Daniel Dennett 98 On the other hand there are also many incompatibilists who reject the argument because they believe that the will is free in a stronger sense called libertarianism 96 These philosophers affirm the course of the world is either a not completely determined by natural law where natural law is intercepted by physically independent agency 99 b determined by indeterministic natural law only or c determined by indeterministic natural law in line with the subjective effort of physically non reducible agency 100 Under Libertarianism the will does not have to be deterministic and therefore it is potentially free Critics of the second proposition b accuse the incompatibilists of using an incoherent concept of freedom They argue as follows if our will is not determined by anything then we desire what we desire by pure chance And if what we desire is purely accidental we are not free So if our will is not determined by anything we are not free 96 Self edit Main article Philosophy of self The philosophy of mind also has important consequences for the concept of self If by self or I one refers to an essential immutable nucleus of the person some modern philosophers of mind such as Daniel Dennett believe that no such thing exists According to Dennett and other contemporaries the self is considered an illusion 101 The idea of a self as an immutable essential nucleus derives from the idea of an immaterial soul Such an idea is unacceptable to modern philosophers with physicalist orientations and their general skepticism of the concept of self as postulated by David Hume who could never catch himself not doing thinking or feeling anything 102 However in the light of empirical results from developmental psychology developmental biology and neuroscience the idea of an essential inconstant material nucleus an integrated representational system distributed over changing patterns of synaptic connections seems reasonable 103 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal Artificial philosophy Animal consciousness Artificial consciousness Collective intentionality Computational theory of mind Embodied cognition Intension Intention Outline of human intelligence Outline of thought Theory of mind in animalsReferences edit a b c d e f Kim Jaegwan 1995 Emergent properties In Honderich Ted ed Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press p 240 ISBN 978 0 19 866132 0 a b Siegel S The Contents of Visual Experience New York Oxford University Press 2010 a b Macpherson F amp Haddock A editors Disjunctivism Perception Action Knowledge Oxford Oxford University Press 2008 a b c d e f Descartes Rene 1998 Discourse on Method and Meditations on First Philosophy Hacket Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 87220 421 8 a b c d e f Hart W D 1996 Dualism in Samuel Guttenplan org A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind Blackwell Oxford 265 7 a b Spinoza Baruch 1670 Tractatus Theologico Politicus A Theologico Political Treatise Schneider Susan 2013 Non Reductive Physicalism and the Mind Problem1 Nous 47 1 135 153 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0068 2011 00847 x ISSN 0029 4624 DePaul Michael Baltimore Joseph A 2013 Type Physicalism and Causal Exclusion Journal of Philosophical Research 38 405 418 doi 10 5840 jpr20133821 ISSN 1053 8364 S C Gibb E J Lowe R D Ingthorsson 21 March 2013 Mental Causation and Ontology OUP Oxford p 58 ISBN 978 0 19 165255 4 Demircioglu Erhan 2011 Supervenience And Reductive Physicalism European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 7 1 25 35 a b Francescotti Robert Supervenience and Mind The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy ISSN 2161 0002 Archived from the original on 2014 07 17 Retrieved 2014 08 10 Gibb Sophie 2010 Closure Principles and the Laws of Conservation of Energy and Momentum Dialectica 64 3 363 384 doi 10 1111 j 1746 8361 2010 01237 x ISSN 0012 2017 S2CID 55120533 See also Dempsey L P 2012 Consciousness Supervenience and Identity Marras and Kim on the Efficacy of Conscious Experience Dialogue 51 3 373 395 doi 10 1017 s0012217312000662 S2CID 147060838 See also Baltimore J A 2010 Defending the piggyback principle against Shapiro and Sober s empirical approach Dialectica 175 2 151 168 doi 10 1007 s11229 009 9467 2 S2CID 13314992 McLaughlin Brian Bennett Karen 2014 Edward N Zalta ed Supervenience The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2014 Edition Retrieved 2014 08 10 Megill Jason 2012 A Defense of Emergence Axiomathes 23 4 597 615 doi 10 1007 s10516 012 9203 2 ISSN 1122 1151 S2CID 170226477 a b c d e Kim J Mind Body Problem Oxford Companion to Philosophy Ted Honderich ed Oxford Oxford University Press 1995 Pinel J Psychobiology 1990 Prentice Hall Inc ISBN 88 15 07174 1 LeDoux J 2002 The Synaptic Self How Our Brains Become Who We Are New York Viking Penguin ISBN 88 7078 795 8 Russell S and Norvig P Artificial Intelligence A Modern Approach New Jersey Prentice Hall ISBN 0 13 103805 2 Dawkins R The Selfish Gene 1976 Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN a b c Churchland Patricia 1986 Neurophilosophy Toward a Unified Science of the Mind Brain MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 03116 5 a b Churchland Paul 1981 Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes Journal of Philosophy 78 2 67 90 doi 10 2307 2025900 JSTOR 2025900 a b c d Smart J J C 1956 Sensations and Brain Processes Philosophical Review a b Donald Davidson 1980 Essays on Actions and Events Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 924627 4 a b Putnam Hilary 1967 Psychological Predicates in W H Capitan and D D Merrill eds Art Mind and Religion Pittsburgh University of Pittsburgh Press a b Dennett Daniel 1998 The intentional stance Cambridge Mass MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 54053 7 a b Searle John 2001 Intentionality A Paper on the Philosophy of Mind Frankfurt a M Nachdr Suhrkamp ISBN 978 3 518 28556 5 Mousavirad Seyyed Jaaber 2023 11 29 Coherence of Substance Dualism International Philosophical Quarterly 63 1 33 42 doi 10 5840 ipq20231114214 Sri Swami Sivananda Sankhya Hindu philosophy The Sankhya Archived from the original on May 15 2006 Plato 1995 E A Duke W F Hicken W S M Nicoll D B Robinson J C G Strachan eds Phaedo Clarendon Press ISBN 978 1 4065 4150 2 Robinson H 1983 Aristotelian dualism Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 1 123 44 a b c Jackson F 1982 Epiphenomenal Qualia Reprinted in Chalmers David ed 2002 Philosophy of Mind Classical and Contemporary Readings Oxford University Press a b c Nagel T 1974 What is it like to be a bat PDF Philosophical Review 83 4 435 456 doi 10 2307 2183914 JSTOR 2183914 Lewis C S 1947 Miracles New York W Morrow amp Co ISBN 978 0 688 17369 2 Chalmers David 1997 The Conscious Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511789 9 a b Dennett Daniel 1995 The unimagined preposterousness of zombies Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 322 6 Archived from the original on 2017 05 15 Retrieved 2017 04 27 Dennett Daniel 1991 Consciousness Explained Little Brown and Co p 95 ISBN 978 0 316 18065 8 Popper Karl amp Eccles John 2002 The Self and Its Brain Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 492 21096 6 Dennett D 1991 Consciousness Explained Boston Little Brown amp Company Stich S 1983 From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science Cambridge MA MIT Press Bradford Ryle G 1949 The Concept of Mind New York Barnes and Noble Agassi J 1975 Privileged Access Science in Flux Boston Stidues in the Philosophy of Science 80 Dordrecht Reidel Agassi J 1997 La Scienza in Divenire Rome Armando a b Robinson Howard 2003 08 19 Dualism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2003 Edition Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University Retrieved 2006 09 25 Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm 1714 Monadology ISBN 978 0 87548 030 5 Schmaltz Tad 2002 Nicolas Malebranche The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2002 Edition Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University Retrieved 2006 09 25 a b Chalmers David 1996 The Conscious Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511789 9 Huxley T H 1874 On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata and its History The Fortnightly Review n s 16 555 580 Reprinted in Method and Results Essays by Thomas H Huxley New York D Appleton and Company 1898 Jackson Frank 1986 What Mary didn t know Journal of Philosophy 83 5 291 295 doi 10 2307 2026143 JSTOR 2026143 S2CID 19000667 Atmanspacher H 2012 Dual aspect monism a la Pauli and Jung Journal of Consciousness Studies 19 9 10 96 120 Velmans M 2012 Reflexive Monism psychophysical relations among mind matter and consciousness Journal of Consciousness Studies 19 9 10 143 165 Archived from the original on 2017 11 11 Leopold Stubenberg Neutral Monism and the Dual Aspect Theory Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b c Wallace Allen 1999 Consciousness At The Crossroads Conversations With The Dalai Lama On Brain Science And Buddhism Snow Lion ISBN 978 0 545 22720 9 a b c d e f g h i Stoljar Daniel 2005 Physicalism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2005 Edition Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University Retrieved 2006 09 24 Cf Michel Weber and Anderson Weekes eds Process Approaches to Consciousness in Psychology Neuroscience and Philosophy of Mind Whitehead Psychology Nexus Studies II Archived 2015 04 08 at the Wayback Machine Albany New York State University of New York Press 2009 Russell Bertrand 1918 Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays London Longmans Green Mach Ernst 1959 1886 Die Analyse der Empfindungen und das Verhaltnis des Physischen zum Psychischen The Analysis of Sensations and the Relation of Physical to the Psychical Fifth ed New York Dover Skinner B F 1972 Beyond Freedom amp Dignity New York Bantam Vintage Books ISBN 978 0 553 14372 0 Ryle Gilbert 1949 The Concept of Mind Chicago Chicago University Press ISBN 978 0 226 73295 4 Place Ullin 1956 Is Consciousness a Brain Process British Journal of Psychology 47 1 44 50 doi 10 1111 j 2044 8295 1956 tb00560 x PMID 13304279 S2CID 36940527 Smart J J C Identity Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2002 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Davidson D 2001 Subjective Intersubjective Objective Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 88 7078 832 7 a b Block Ned What is functionalism in Readings in Philosophy of Psychology 2 vols Vol 1 Cambridge Harvard 1980 Armstrong D 1968 A Materialist Theory of the Mind Routledge Di Francesco M amp Marraffa M 2013 The Unconscious consciousness and the Self illusion PDF Dialogues in Philosophy Mental and Neuro Sciences 6 1 10 22 Archived PDF from the original on 2017 03 03 Stanton W L 1983 Supervenience and Psychological Law in Anomalous Monism Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 72 9 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0114 1983 tb00185 x Jaegwon Kim Philosophy of Mind Westview Press 2 edition July 8 2005 ISBN 0 8133 4269 4 Anthis Jacy 2022 Consciousness Semanticism A Precise Eliminativist Theory of Consciousness Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures 2021 Studies in Computational Intelligence Vol 1032 pp 20 41 doi 10 1007 978 3 030 96993 6 3 ISBN 978 3 030 96992 9 Retrieved 7 August 2022 McGinn Colin Can We Solve the Mind Body Problem Archived 2016 12 26 at the Wayback Machine Mind New Series Vol 98 No 391 July 1989 pp 349 366 p 350 Reprinted in O Connor Timothy and Robb David Colin McGinn Can We Solve the Mind Body Problem Philosophy of Mind Contemporary Readings Routledge 2003 p 438ff Hard problem of Consciousness Archived 2015 04 20 at the Wayback Machine The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Josh Weisberg a b Hacker Peter 2003 Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience Blackwel Pub ISBN 978 1 4051 0838 6 a b c Wittgenstein Ludwig 1954 Philosophical Investigations New York Macmillan ISBN 978 0 631 14660 5 Putnam Hilary 2000 The Threefold Cord Mind Body and World New York Columbia University Press ISBN 978 0 231 10286 5 Hubert Dreyfus Critique of Descartes I recorded lecture University of California at Berkeley Sept 18 2007 Joseph Levine Materialism and Qualia The Explanatory Gap in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly vol 64 no 4 October 1983 354 361 Jackson F 1986 What Mary didn t Know Journal of Philosophy 83 5 pp 291 295 McGinn C Can the Mind Body Problem Be Solved Mind New Series Volume 98 Issue 391 pp 349 366 a online Archived 2007 09 28 at the Wayback Machine Fodor Jerry 1993 Psychosemantics The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind Cambridge MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 06106 3 Siegel S 2011 The Contents of Perception The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2011 Edition Edward N Zalta ed URL http plato stanford edu archives win2011 entries perception contents a b c d Pinker S 1997 How the Mind Works tr It Come Funziona la Mente Milan Mondadori 2000 ISBN 88 04 49908 7 a b c Bear M F et al Eds 1995 Neuroscience Exploring The Brain Baltimore Maryland Williams and Wilkins ISBN 0 7817 3944 6 a b c Pinel J P J 1997 Psychobiology Prentice Hall ISBN 978 88 15 07174 3 Metzinger Thomas 2003 Being No One The Self Model Theory of Subjectivity Cambridge MIT Press pp 349 366 ISBN 978 0 262 13417 0 Sipser M 1998 Introduction to the Theory of Computation Boston Mass PWS Publishing Co ISBN 978 0 534 94728 6 a b Searle John 1980 Minds Brains and Programs PDF The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 3 417 424 doi 10 1017 S0140525X00005756 S2CID 55303721 Turing Alan October 1950 Computing Machinery and Intelligence Mind LIX 236 433 460 doi 10 1093 mind LIX 236 433 ISSN 0026 4423 Russell S amp Norvig R 1995 Artificial Intelligence A Modern Approach New Jersey Prentice Hall Inc ISBN 978 0 13 103805 9 Encyclopedia of Psychology 2019 03 07 Archived from the original on 2008 05 13 Thagard Paul Cognitive Science The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2008 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Calvo Paco Gomila Toni 2008 Handbook of Cognitive Science An Embodied Approach Elsevier ISBN 978 0 08 091487 9 Mark Rowlands 2010 Chapter 3 The mind embedded The new science of the mind From extended mind to embodied phenomenology MIT Press pp 51 ff ISBN 978 0 262 01455 7 Dave Ward Mog Stapleton 2012 Es are good Cognition as enacted embodied embedded affective and extended In Fabio Paglieri ed Consciousness in Interaction The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness John Benjamins Publishing pp 89 ff ISBN 978 90 272 1352 5 On line version here Archived 2014 04 10 at the Wayback Machine J M Luce Chronic disorders of consciousness following coma Part one medical issues In Chest Band 144 Nummer 4 Oktober 2013 S 1381 1387 doi 10 1378 chest 13 0395 PMID 24081351 Review a b c Dummett M 2001 Origini della Filosofia Analitica Einaudi ISBN 978 88 06 15286 4 Hegel G W F 1983 Phenomenology of Spirit Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 503169 0 translated by A V Miller with analysis of the text and foreword by J N Findlay Oxford Clarendon Press 1977 ISBN 0 19 824597 1 Husserl Edmund 2008 Logische Untersuchungen Akademie Verlag Berlin ISBN 978 3 05 004391 3 trans Giovanni Piana Milan EST ISBN 88 428 0949 7 a b c d Philosopher Ted Honderich s Determinism web resource Archived from the original on 2008 05 16 Russell Paul Freedom and Moral Sentiment Hume s Way of Naturalizing Responsibility Oxford University Press New York amp Oxford 1995 Dennett Daniel 1984 The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting Cambridge MA Bradford Books MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 54042 1 Descartes Rene 1649 Passions of the Soul Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 87220 035 7 Kane Robert 2009 Libertarianism Philosophical Studies 144 1 39 doi 10 1007 s11098 009 9365 y S2CID 262782420 Dennett C amp Hofstadter D R 1981 The Mind s I Bantam Books ISBN 978 0 553 01412 9 Searle John 1 November 2004 Mind A Brief Introduction Oxford University Press Inc USA ISBN 978 0 19 515733 8 LeDoux Joseph 2002 The Synaptic Self New York Viking Penguin ISBN 978 88 7078 795 5 Further reading editThe London Philosophy Study Guide Archived 2009 09 23 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read depending on the student s familiarity with the subject Philosophy of Mind Archived 2020 06 15 at the Wayback Machine Richard Rorty Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature Princeton 1980 p 120 125 Pedro Jesus Teruel Mente cerebro y antropologia en Kant Madrid 2008 ISBN 978 84 309 4688 4 David J Ungs Better than one how we each have two minds London 2004 ISBN 978 1 78220 173 1 Alfred North Whitehead Science and the Modern World 1925 reprinted London 1985 pp 68 70 Edwin Burtt The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science 2nd ed London 1932 pp 318 19 Felix Deutsch ed On the Mysterious Leap from the Mind to the Body New York 1959 Herbert Feigl The Mental and the Physical The Essay and a Postscript 1967 in H Feigl et al eds Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Minneapolis 1958 Vol 2 pp 370 497 at p 373 Nap Mabaquiao Jr Mind Science and Computation with foreword by Tim Crane Manila De La Salle University Publishing House 2012 Celia Green The Lost Cause Causation and the Mind Body Problem Oxford Oxford Forum 2003 Applies a sceptical view on causality to the problems of interactionism Gyatso Geshe Kelsang Gyatso Understanding the Mind The Nature and Power of the Mind Tharpa Publications 2nd ed 1997 ISBN 978 0 948006 78 4 Gerhard Medicus Being Human Bridging the Gap between the Sciences of Body and Mind Berlin 2015 VWB Gerhard Medicus 2017 Being Human Bridging the Gap between the Sciences of Body and Mind Berlin VWB Scott Robert Sehon Teleological Realism Mind Agency and Explanation Cambridge MIT University Press 2005 External links edit nbsp Wikibooks has a book on the topic of Consciousness Studies nbsp Look up philosophy of mind in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Philosophy of mind nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Philosophy of mind Library resources about Philosophy of mind Resources in your library Resources in other libraries Philosophy of mind at PhilPapers Philosophy of mind at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Theory of Mind Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Guide to Philosophy of Mind compiled by David Chalmers MindPapers A Bibliography of the Philosophy of Mind and the Science of Consciousness compiled by David Chalmers Editor amp David Bourget Assistant Editor Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind edited by Chris Eliasmith An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind by Paul Newall aimed at beginners A list of online papers on consciousness and philosophy of mind compiled by David Chalmers Mind Field The Playground of Gods from the Indian Psychology series by Swami Veda Bharati 1 Gerhard Medicus Being Human Bridging the Gap between the Sciences of Body and Mind Berlin 2017 VWB Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Philosophy of mind amp oldid 1220680086, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.