fbpx
Wikipedia

Scientific method

The scientific method is an empirical method for acquiring knowledge that has characterized the development of science since at least the 17th century. (For notable practitioners in previous centuries, see history of scientific method.)

The scientific method is often represented as an ongoing process. This diagram represents one variant, and there are many others.

The scientific method involves careful observation coupled with rigorous scepticism, because cognitive assumptions can distort the interpretation of the observation. Scientific inquiry includes creating a hypothesis through inductive reasoning, testing it through experiments and statistical analysis, and adjusting or discarding the hypothesis based on the results.

The above mentioned are principles of the scientific method, a definitive series of steps applicable to all scientific enterprises.[1][2][3]

Although procedures vary from one field of inquiry to another, the underlying process is frequently the same. The process in the scientific method involves making conjectures (hypothetical explanations), deriving predictions from the hypotheses as logical consequences, and then carrying out experiments or empirical observations based on those predictions.[a][4] A hypothesis is a conjecture based on knowledge obtained while seeking answers to the question. The hypothesis might be very specific or it might be broad. Scientists then test hypotheses by conducting experiments or studies. A scientific hypothesis must be falsifiable, implying that it is possible to identify a possible outcome of an experiment or observation that conflicts with predictions deduced from the hypothesis; otherwise, the hypothesis cannot be meaningfully tested.[5]

The purpose of an experiment is to determine whether observations[A][a][b] agree or disagree with hypothesis.[6][b]

Though the scientific method is often presented as a fixed sequence of steps, it represents rather a set of general principles.[7] Not all steps take place in every scientific inquiry (nor to the same degree), and they are not always in the same order.[8][9]

History

Important debates in the history of science concern scepticism that anything can be known for sure (such as views of Francisco Sanches), rationalism (especially as advocated by René Descartes), inductivism, empiricism (as argued for by Francis Bacon, then rising to particular prominence with Robert Hooke,[10][11] Isaac Newton and his followers), and hypothetico-deductivism, which came to the fore in the early 19th century.

The term "scientific method" emerged in the 19th century, as a result of significant institutional development of science emerged and terminologies established clear boundaries between science and non-science, such as "scientist" and "pseudoscience", appeared.[12] Throughout the 1830s and 1850s, when Baconianism was popular, naturalists like William Whewell, John Herschel, John Stuart Mill engaged in debates over "induction" and "facts" and were focused on how to generate knowledge.[12] In the late 19th and early 20th centuries, a debate over realism vs. antirealism was conducted as powerful scientific theories extended beyond the realm of the observable.[13]

Problem-solving via scientific method

The term "scientific method" came into popular use in the twentieth century; Dewey's 1910 book, How We Think, inspired popular guidelines,[14] appearing in dictionaries and science textbooks, although there was little consensus over its meaning.[12] Although there was growth through the middle of the twentieth century, by the 1960s and 1970s numerous influential philosophers of science such as Thomas Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend had questioned the universality of the "scientific method" and in doing so largely replaced the notion of science as a homogeneous and universal method with that of it being a heterogeneous and local practice.[12] In particular, Paul Feyerabend, in the 1975 first edition of his book Against Method, argued against there being any universal rules of science;[13] Popper 1963,[15] Gauch 2003,[7] and Tow 2010[16] disagree with Feyerabend's claim; problem solvers, and researchers are to be prudent with their resources during their inquiry.[B][c]

Later stances include physicist Lee Smolin's 2013 essay "There Is No Scientific Method",[24] in which he espouses two ethical principles,[e] and historian of science Daniel Thurs' chapter in the 2015 book Newton's Apple and Other Myths about Science, which concluded that the scientific method is a myth or, at best, an idealization.[25] As myths are beliefs,[26] they are subject to the narrative fallacy as Taleb points out.[27] Philosophers Robert Nola and Howard Sankey, in their 2007 book Theories of Scientific Method, said that debates over the scientific method continue, and argued that Feyerabend, despite the title of Against Method, accepted certain rules of method and attempted to justify those rules with a meta methodology.[28] Staddon (2017) argues it is a mistake to try following rules in the absence of an algorithmic scientific method; in that case, "science is best understood through examples".[f] But algorithmic methods, such as disproof of existing theory by experiment have been used since Alhacen (1027) Book of Optics,[b] and Galileo (1638) Two New Sciences,[30] and The Assayer[31] still stand as scientific method. They contradict Feyerabend's stance. [C][D]

The ubiquitous element in the scientific method is empiricism. This is in opposition to stringent forms of rationalism: the scientific method embodies the position that reason alone cannot solve a particular scientific problem. A strong formulation of the scientific method is not always aligned with a form of empiricism in which the empirical data is put forward in the form of experience or other abstracted forms of knowledge; in current scientific practice, however, the use of scientific modelling and reliance on abstract typologies and theories is normally accepted. The scientific method counters claims that revelation, political or religious dogma, appeals to tradition, commonly held beliefs, common sense, or currently held theories pose the only possible means of demonstrating truth.[35][17][16]

Different early expressions of empiricism and the scientific method can be found throughout history, for instance with the ancient Stoics, Epicurus,[36] Alhazen,[E] Avicenna, Al-Biruni,[38][39] Roger Bacon, and William of Ockham. From the 16th century onwards, experiments were advocated by Francis Bacon, and performed by Giambattista della Porta,[40] Johannes Kepler,[41][i] and Galileo Galilei.[j] There was particular development aided by theoretical works by Francisco Sanches,[42] John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume.

A sea voyage from America to Europe afforded C. S. Peirce the distance to clarify his ideas,[F] gradually resulting in the hypothetico-deductive model.[43] Formulated in the 20th century, the model has undergone significant revision since first proposed (for a more formal discussion, see § Elements of the scientific method).

Overview

The scientific method is the process by which science is carried out.[44] As in other areas of inquiry, science (through the scientific method) can build on previous knowledge, and can unify understanding of its topics of study over time.[k] This model can be seen to underlie the scientific revolution.[46]

The overall process involves making conjectures (hypotheses), deriving predictions from them as logical consequences, and then carrying out experiments based on those predictions to determine whether the original conjecture was correct.[4] However, there are difficulties in a formulaic statement of method. Though the scientific method is often presented as a fixed sequence of steps, these actions are better considered as general principles.[8] Not all steps take place in every scientific inquiry (nor to the same degree), and they are not always done in the same order. As noted by scientist and philosopher William Whewell (1794–1866), "invention, sagacity, [and] genius"[9] are required at every step.

Factors of scientific inquiry

There are different ways of outlining the basic method used for scientific inquiry. The scientific community and philosophers of science generally agree on the following classification of method components. These methodological elements and organization of procedures tend to be more characteristic of experimental sciences than social sciences. Nonetheless, the cycle of formulating hypotheses, testing and analyzing the results, and formulating new hypotheses, will resemble the cycle described below.The scientific method is an iterative, cyclical process through which information is continually revised.[47][48] It is generally recognized to develop advances in knowledge through the following elements, in varying combinations or contributions:[49][50]

  • Characterizations (observations, definitions, and measurements of the subject of inquiry)
  • Hypotheses (theoretical, hypothetical explanations of observations and measurements of the subject)
  • Predictions (inductive and deductive reasoning from the hypothesis or theory)
  • Experiments (tests of all of the above)

Each element of the scientific method is subject to peer review for possible mistakes. These activities do not describe all that scientists do but apply mostly to experimental sciences (e.g., physics, chemistry, biology, and psychology). The elements above are often taught in the educational system as "the scientific method".[A]

The scientific method is not a single recipe: it requires intelligence, imagination, and creativity.[51] In this sense, it is not a mindless set of standards and procedures to follow but is rather an ongoing cycle, constantly developing more useful, accurate, and comprehensive models and methods. For example, when Einstein developed the Special and General Theories of Relativity, he did not in any way refute or discount Newton's Principia. On the contrary, if the astronomically massive, the feather-light, and the extremely fast are removed from Einstein's theories – all phenomena Newton could not have observed – Newton's equations are what remain. Einstein's theories are expansions and refinements of Newton's theories and, thus, increase confidence in Newton's work.

An iterative,[48] pragmatic[35] scheme of the four points above is sometimes offered as a guideline for proceeding:[52]

  1. Define a question
  2. Gather information and resources (observe)
  3. Form an explanatory hypothesis
  4. Test the hypothesis by performing an experiment and collecting data in a reproducible manner
  5. Analyze the data
  6. Interpret the data and draw conclusions that serve as a starting point for a new hypothesis
  7. Publish results
  8. Retest (frequently done by other scientists)

The iterative cycle inherent in this step-by-step method goes from point 3 to 6 and back to 3 again.

While this schema outlines a typical hypothesis/testing method,[53] many philosophers, historians, and sociologists of science, including Paul Feyerabend,[l] claim that such descriptions of scientific method have little relation to the ways that science is actually practiced.

Elements of the scientific method

The basic elements of the scientific method are illustrated by the following example (which occurred from 1944 to 1953) from the discovery of the structure of DNA (marked with   and indented).

Characterizations

  In 1950, it was known that genetic inheritance had a mathematical description, starting with the studies of Gregor Mendel, and that DNA contained genetic information (Oswald Avery's transforming principle).[55] But the mechanism of storing genetic information (i.e., genes) in DNA was unclear. Researchers in Bragg's laboratory at Cambridge University made X-ray diffraction pictures of various molecules, starting with crystals of salt, and proceeding to more complicated substances. Using clues painstakingly assembled over decades, beginning with its chemical composition, it was determined that it should be possible to characterize the physical structure of DNA, and the X-ray images would be the vehicle.[56]

The scientific method depends upon increasingly sophisticated characterizations of the subjects of investigation. (The subjects can also be called unsolved problems or the unknowns.)[A] For example, Benjamin Franklin conjectured, correctly, that St. Elmo's fire was electrical in nature, but it has taken a long series of experiments and theoretical changes to establish this. While seeking the pertinent properties of the subjects, careful thought may also entail some definitions and observations; the observations often demand careful measurements and/or counting.

The question can refer to the explanation of a specific observation,[A] as in "Why is the sky blue?" but can also be open-ended, as in "How can I design a drug to cure this particular disease?" This stage frequently involves finding and evaluating evidence from previous experiments, personal scientific observations or assertions, as well as the work of other scientists. If the answer is already known, a different question that builds on the evidence can be posed. When applying the scientific method to research, determining a good question can be very difficult and it will affect the outcome of the investigation.[57]

The systematic, careful collection of measurements or counts of relevant quantities is often the critical difference between pseudo-sciences, such as alchemy, and science, such as chemistry or biology. Scientific measurements are usually tabulated, graphed, or mapped, and statistical manipulations, such as correlation and regression, performed on them. The measurements might be made in a controlled setting, such as a laboratory, or made on more or less inaccessible or unmanipulatable objects such as stars or human populations. The measurements often require specialized scientific instruments such as thermometers, spectroscopes, particle accelerators, or voltmeters, and the progress of a scientific field is usually intimately tied to their invention and improvement.

 
Precession of the perihelion – exaggerated in the case of Mercury, but observed in the case of S2's apsidal precession around Sagittarius A*[58]

The characterization element can require extended and extensive study, even centuries. It took thousands of years of measurements, from the Chaldean, Indian, Persian, Greek, Arabic, and European astronomers, to fully record the motion of planet Earth. Newton was able to include those measurements into the consequences of his laws of motion. But the perihelion of the planet Mercury's orbit exhibits a precession that cannot be fully explained by Newton's laws of motion (see diagram to the right), as Leverrier pointed out in 1859. The observed difference for Mercury's precession between Newtonian theory and observation was one of the things that occurred to Albert Einstein as a possible early test of his theory of General relativity. His relativistic calculations matched observation much more closely than did Newtonian theory. The difference is approximately 43 arc-seconds per century.

I am not accustomed to saying anything with certainty after only one or two observations.

— Andreas Vesalius, (1546)[59]

Uncertainty

Measurements in scientific work are also usually accompanied by estimates of their uncertainty.[60] The uncertainty is often estimated by making repeated measurements of the desired quantity. Uncertainties may also be calculated by consideration of the uncertainties of the individual underlying quantities used. Counts of things, such as the number of people in a nation at a particular time, may also have an uncertainty due to data collection limitations. Or counts may represent a sample of desired quantities, with an uncertainty that depends upon the sampling method used and the number of samples taken.

Definition

The scientific definition of a term sometimes differs substantially from its natural language usage. For example, mass and weight overlap in meaning in common discourse, but have distinct meanings in mechanics. Scientific quantities are often characterized by their units of measure which can later be described in terms of conventional physical units when communicating the work.

New theories are sometimes developed after realizing certain terms have not previously been sufficiently clearly defined. For example, Albert Einstein's first paper on relativity begins by defining simultaneity and the means for determining length. These ideas were skipped over by Isaac Newton with, "I do not define time, space, place and motion, as being well known to all." Einstein's paper then demonstrates that they (viz., absolute time and length independent of motion) were approximations. Francis Crick cautions us that when characterizing a subject, however, it can be premature to define something when it remains ill-understood.[61] In Crick's study of consciousness, he actually found it easier to study awareness in the visual system, rather than to study free will, for example. His cautionary example was the gene; the gene was much more poorly understood before Watson and Crick's pioneering discovery of the structure of DNA; it would have been counterproductive to spend much time on the definition of the gene, before them.

Hypothesis development

  Linus Pauling proposed that DNA might be a triple helix.[62][63] This hypothesis was also considered by Francis Crick and James D. Watson but discarded. When Watson and Crick learned of Pauling's hypothesis, they understood from existing data that Pauling was wrong.[64] and that Pauling would soon admit his difficulties with that structure.

A hypothesis is a suggested explanation of a phenomenon, or alternately a reasoned proposal suggesting a possible correlation between or among a set of phenomena.

Normally hypotheses have the form of a mathematical model. Sometimes, but not always, they can also be formulated as existential statements, stating that some particular instance of the phenomenon being studied has some characteristic and causal explanations, which have the general form of universal statements, stating that every instance of the phenomenon has a particular characteristic.

Scientists are free to use whatever resources they have – their own creativity, ideas from other fields, inductive reasoning, Bayesian inference, and so on – to imagine possible explanations for a phenomenon under study. Albert Einstein once observed that "there is no logical bridge between phenomena and their theoretical principles."[65][m] Charles Sanders Peirce, borrowing a page from Aristotle (Prior Analytics, 2.25)[67] described the incipient stages of inquiry, instigated by the "irritation of doubt" to venture a plausible guess, as abductive reasoning.[32]: II, p.290  The history of science is filled with stories of scientists claiming a "flash of inspiration", or a hunch, which then motivated them to look for evidence to support or refute their idea. Michael Polanyi made such creativity the centerpiece of his discussion of methodology.

William Glen observes that[68]

the success of a hypothesis, or its service to science, lies not simply in its perceived "truth", or power to displace, subsume or reduce a predecessor idea, but perhaps more in its ability to stimulate the research that will illuminate ... bald suppositions and areas of vagueness.

— William Glen, The Mass-Extinction Debates

In general, scientists tend to look for theories that are "elegant" or "beautiful". Scientists often use these terms to refer to a theory that is following the known facts but is nevertheless relatively simple and easy to handle. Occam's Razor serves as a rule of thumb for choosing the most desirable amongst a group of equally explanatory hypotheses.

To minimize the confirmation bias that results from entertaining a single hypothesis, strong inference emphasizes the need for entertaining multiple alternative hypotheses.[69]

Predictions from the hypothesis

  James D. Watson, Francis Crick, and others hypothesized that DNA had a helical structure. This implied that DNA's X-ray diffraction pattern would be 'x shaped'.[70][71] This prediction followed from the work of Cochran, Crick and Vand[72] (and independently by Stokes). The Cochran-Crick-Vand-Stokes theorem provided a mathematical explanation for the empirical observation that diffraction from helical structures produces x-shaped patterns. In their first paper, Watson and Crick also noted that the double helix structure they proposed provided a simple mechanism for DNA replication, writing, "It has not escaped our notice that the specific pairing we have postulated immediately suggests a possible copying mechanism for the genetic material".[73]

Any useful hypothesis will enable predictions, by reasoning including deductive reasoning.[n] It might predict the outcome of an experiment in a laboratory setting or the observation of a phenomenon in nature. The prediction can also be statistical and deal only with probabilities.

It is essential that the outcome of testing such a prediction be currently unknown. Only in this case does a successful outcome increase the probability that the hypothesis is true. If the outcome is already known, it is called a consequence and should have already been considered while formulating the hypothesis.

If the predictions are not accessible by observation or experience, the hypothesis is not yet testable and so will remain to that extent unscientific in a strict sense. A new technology or theory might make the necessary experiments feasible. For example, while a hypothesis on the existence of other intelligent species may be convincing with scientifically based speculation, no known experiment can test this hypothesis. Therefore, science itself can have little to say about the possibility. In the future, a new technique may allow for an experimental test and the speculation would then become part of accepted science.

For example, Einstein's theory of general relativity makes several specific predictions about the observable structure of spacetime, such as that light bends in a gravitational field, and that the amount of bending depends in a precise way on the strength of that gravitational field. Arthur Eddington's observations made during a 1919 solar eclipse supported General Relativity rather than Newtonian gravitation.[74]

Experiments

  Watson and Crick showed an initial (and incorrect) proposal for the structure of DNA to a team from King's College LondonRosalind Franklin, Maurice Wilkins, and Raymond Gosling. Franklin immediately spotted the flaws which concerned the water content. Later Watson saw Franklin's photo 51, a detailed X-ray diffraction image, which showed an X-shape[75][22] and was able to confirm the structure was helical.[21][76][c]

Once predictions are made, they can be sought by experiments. If the test results contradict the predictions, the hypotheses which entailed them are called into question and become less tenable. Sometimes the experiments are conducted incorrectly or are not very well designed when compared to a crucial experiment. If the experimental results confirm the predictions, then the hypotheses are considered more likely to be correct, but might still be wrong and continue to be subject to further testing. The experimental control is a technique for dealing with observational error. This technique uses the contrast between multiple samples, or observations, or populations, under differing conditions, to see what varies or what remains the same. We vary the conditions for the acts of measurement, to help isolate what has changed. Mill's canons can then help us figure out what the important factor is.[77] Factor analysis is one technique for discovering the important factor in an effect.

Depending on the predictions, the experiments can have different shapes. It could be a classical experiment in a laboratory setting, a double-blind study or an archaeological excavation. Even taking a plane from New York to Paris is an experiment that tests the aerodynamical hypotheses used for constructing the plane.

These institutions thereby reduce the research function to a cost/benefit,[60] which is expressed as money, and the time and attention of the researchers to be expended,[60] in exchange for a report to their constituents.[78] Current large instruments, such as CERN's Large Hadron Collider (LHC),[79] or LIGO,[80] or the National Ignition Facility (NIF),[81] or the International Space Station (ISS),[82] or the James Webb Space Telescope (JWST),[83][84] entail expected costs of billions of dollars, and timeframes extending over decades. These kinds of institutions affect public policy, on a national or even international basis, and the researchers would require shared access to such machines and their adjunct infrastructure.[o][85]

Scientists assume an attitude of openness and accountability on the part of those experimenting. Detailed record-keeping is essential, to aid in recording and reporting on the experimental results, and supports the effectiveness and integrity of the procedure. They will also assist in reproducing the experimental results, likely by others. Traces of this approach can be seen in the work of Hipparchus (190–120 BCE), when determining a value for the precession of the Earth, while controlled experiments can be seen in the works of al-Battani (853–929 CE)[86] and Alhazen (965–1039 CE).[87][p][q][g]

Evaluation and improvement

  Watson and Crick then produced their model, using this information along with the previously known information about DNA's composition, especially Chargaff's rules of base pairing.[23] After considerable fruitless experimentation, being discouraged by their superior from continuing, and numerous false starts,[90][91][92] Watson and Crick were able to infer the essential structure of DNA by concrete modeling of the physical shapes of the nucleotides which comprise it.[23][93][94] They were guided by the bond lengths which had been deduced by Linus Pauling and by Rosalind Franklin's X-ray diffraction images.

The scientific method is iterative. At any stage, it is possible to refine its accuracy and precision, so that some consideration will lead the scientist to repeat an earlier part of the process. Failure to develop an interesting hypothesis may lead a scientist to re-define the subject under consideration. Failure of a hypothesis to produce interesting and testable predictions may lead to reconsideration of the hypothesis or of the definition of the subject. Failure of an experiment to produce interesting results may lead a scientist to reconsider the experimental method, the hypothesis, or the definition of the subject.

By 1027, Alhazen, based on his measurements of the refraction of light, was able to deduce that outer space was less dense than air, that is: "the body of the heavens is rarer than the body of air".[34] In 1079 Ibn Mu'adh's Treatise On Twilight was able to infer that Earth's atmosphere was 50 miles thick, based on atmospheric refraction of the sun's rays.[r]

Other scientists may start their own research and enter the process at any stage. They might adopt the characterization and formulate their own hypothesis, or they might adopt the hypothesis and deduce their own predictions. Often the experiment is not done by the person who made the prediction, and the characterization is based on experiments done by someone else. Published results of experiments can also serve as a hypothesis predicting their own reproducibility.

Confirmation

Science is a social enterprise, and scientific work tends to be accepted by the scientific community when it has been confirmed. Crucially, experimental and theoretical results must be reproduced by others within the scientific community. Researchers have given their lives for this vision; Georg Wilhelm Richmann was killed by ball lightning (1753) when attempting to replicate the 1752 kite-flying experiment of Benjamin Franklin.[96]

If an experiment cannot be repeated to produce the same results, this implies that the original results might have been in error. As a result, it is common for a single experiment to be performed multiple times, especially when there are uncontrolled variables or other indications of experimental error. For significant or surprising results, other scientists may also attempt to replicate the results for themselves, especially if those results would be important to their own work.[97] Replication has become a contentious issue in social and biomedical science where treatments are administered to groups of individuals. Typically an experimental group gets the treatment, such as a drug, and the control group gets a placebo. John Ioannidis in 2005 pointed out that the method being used has led to many findings that cannot be replicated.[98]

The process of peer review involves the evaluation of the experiment by experts, who typically give their opinions anonymously. Some journals request that the experimenter provide lists of possible peer reviewers, especially if the field is highly specialized. Peer review does not certify the correctness of the results, only that, in the opinion of the reviewer, the experiments themselves were sound (based on the description supplied by the experimenter). If the work passes peer review, which occasionally may require new experiments requested by the reviewers, it will be published in a peer-reviewed scientific journal. The specific journal that publishes the results indicates the perceived quality of the work.[s]

Scientists typically are careful in recording their data, a requirement promoted by Ludwik Fleck (1896–1961) and others.[99] Though not typically required, they might be requested to supply this data to other scientists who wish to replicate their original results (or parts of their original results), extending to the sharing of any experimental samples that may be difficult to obtain.[100] To protect against bad science and fraudulent data, government research-granting agencies such as the National Science Foundation, and science journals, including Nature and Science, have a policy that researchers must archive their data and methods so that other researchers can test the data and methods and build on the research that has gone before. Scientific data archiving can be done at several national archives in the U.S. or the World Data Center.

Scientific inquiry

Scientific inquiry generally aims to obtain knowledge in the form of testable explanations[19][18] that scientists can use to predict the results of future experiments. This allows scientists to gain a better understanding of the topic under study, and later to use that understanding to intervene in its causal mechanisms (such as to cure disease). The better an explanation is at making predictions, the more useful it frequently can be, and the more likely it will continue to explain a body of evidence better than its alternatives. The most successful explanations – those that explain and make accurate predictions in a wide range of circumstances – are often called scientific theories.[A]

Most experimental results do not produce large changes in human understanding; improvements in theoretical scientific understanding typically result from a gradual process of development over time, sometimes across different domains of science.[101] Scientific models vary in the extent to which they have been experimentally tested and for how long, and in their acceptance in the scientific community. In general, explanations become accepted over time as evidence accumulates on a given topic, and the explanation in question proves more powerful than its alternatives at explaining the evidence. Often subsequent researchers re-formulate the explanations over time, or combined explanations to produce new explanations.

Tow sees the scientific method in terms of an evolutionary algorithm applied to science and technology.[16]

Properties of scientific inquiry

Scientific knowledge is closely tied to empirical findings and can remain subject to falsification if new experimental observations are incompatible with what is found. That is, no theory can ever be considered final since new problematic evidence might be discovered. If such evidence is found, a new theory may be proposed, or (more commonly) it is found that modifications to the previous theory are sufficient to explain the new evidence. The strength of a theory relates to how long it has persisted without major alteration to its core principles.

Theories can also become subsumed by other theories. For example, Newton's laws explained thousands of years of scientific observations of the planets almost perfectly. However, these laws were then determined to be special cases of a more general theory (relativity), which explained both the (previously unexplained) exceptions to Newton's laws and predicted and explained other observations such as the deflection of light by gravity. Thus, in certain cases independent, unconnected, scientific observations can be connected, unified by principles of increasing explanatory power.[102][103]

Since new theories might be more comprehensive than what preceded them, and thus be able to explain more than previous ones, successor theories might be able to meet a higher standard by explaining a larger body of observations than their predecessors.[102] For example, the theory of evolution explains the diversity of life on Earth, how species adapt to their environments, and many other patterns observed in the natural world;[104][105] its most recent major modification was unification with genetics to form the modern evolutionary synthesis. In subsequent modifications, it has also subsumed aspects of many other fields such as biochemistry and molecular biology.[16]

Beliefs and biases

 
Flying gallop as shown by this painting (Théodore Géricault, 1821) is falsified; see below.
 
Muybridge's photographs of The Horse in Motion, 1878, were used to answer the question of whether all four feet of a galloping horse are ever off the ground at the same time. This demonstrates a use of photography as an experimental tool in science.

Scientific methodology often directs that hypotheses be tested in controlled conditions wherever possible. This is frequently possible in certain areas, such as in the biological sciences, and more difficult in other areas, such as in astronomy.

The practice of experimental control and reproducibility can have the effect of diminishing the potentially harmful effects of circumstance, and to a degree, personal bias. For example, pre-existing beliefs can alter the interpretation of results, as in confirmation bias; this is a heuristic that leads a person with a particular belief to see things as reinforcing their belief, even if another observer might disagree (in other words, people tend to observe what they expect to observe).[26]

[T]he action of thought is excited by the irritation of doubt, and ceases when belief is attained.

— C.S. Peirce, How to Make Our Ideas Clear (1877)[32]

A historical example is the belief that the legs of a galloping horse are splayed at the point when none of the horse's legs touch the ground, to the point of this image being included in paintings by its supporters. However, the first stop-action pictures of a horse's gallop by Eadweard Muybridge showed this to be false, and that the legs are instead gathered together.[106]

Another important human bias that plays a role is a preference for new, surprising statements (see Appeal to novelty), which can result in a search for evidence that the new is true.[107] Poorly attested beliefs can be believed and acted upon via a less rigorous heuristic.[108]

Goldhaber and Nieto published in 2010 the observation that if theoretical structures with "many closely neighboring subjects are described by connecting theoretical concepts, then the theoretical structure acquires a robustness which makes it increasingly hard – though certainly never impossible – to overturn".[103] When a narrative is constructed its elements become easier to believe.[109][27]

Fleck (1979), p. 27 notes "Words and ideas are originally phonetic and mental equivalences of the experiences coinciding with them. ... Such proto-ideas are at first always too broad and insufficiently specialized. ... Once a structurally complete and closed system of opinions consisting of many details and relations has been formed, it offers enduring resistance to anything that contradicts it". Sometimes, these relations have their elements assumed a priori, or contain some other logical or methodological flaw in the process that ultimately produced them. Donald M. MacKay has analyzed these elements in terms of limits to the accuracy of measurement and has related them to instrumental elements in a category of measurement.[t]

Models of scientific inquiry

The classical model of scientific inquiry derives from Aristotle,[110] who distinguished the forms of approximate and exact reasoning, set out the threefold scheme of abductive, deductive, and inductive inference, and also treated the compound forms such as reasoning by analogy.

The hypothetico-deductive model or method is a proposed description of the scientific method. Here, predictions from the hypothesis are central: if one assumes the hypothesis to be true, what consequences follow? If a subsequent empirical investigation does not demonstrate that these consequences or predictions correspond to the observable world, the hypothesis can be concluded to be false.

In 1877,[49] Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) characterized inquiry in general not as the pursuit of truth per se but as the struggle to move from irritating, inhibitory doubts born of surprises, disagreements, and the like, and to reach a secure belief, the belief being that on which one is prepared to act. He framed scientific inquiry as part of a broader spectrum and as spurred, like inquiry generally, by actual doubt, not mere verbal or hyperbolic doubt, which he held to be fruitless.[u]

Communication and community

Frequently the scientific method is employed not only by a single person but also by several people cooperating directly or indirectly. Such cooperation can be regarded as an important element of a scientific community. Various standards of scientific methodology are used within such an environment.

Scientific journals use a process of peer review, in which scientists' manuscripts are submitted by editors of scientific journals to (usually one to three, and usually anonymous) fellow scientists familiar with the field for evaluation. In certain journals, the journal itself selects the referees; while in others (especially journals that are extremely specialized), the manuscript author might recommend referees. The referees may or may not recommend publication, or they might recommend publication with suggested modifications, or sometimes, publication in another journal. This standard is practiced to various degrees by different journals and can have the effect of keeping the literature free of obvious errors and generally improve the quality of the material, especially in the journals that use the standard most rigorously. The peer-review process can have limitations when considering research outside the conventional scientific paradigm: problems of "groupthink" can interfere with open and fair deliberation of some new research.[113]

Researchers sometimes practice scientific data archiving, such as in compliance with the policies of government funding agencies and scientific journals. In these cases, detailed records of their experimental procedures, raw data, statistical analyses, and source code can be preserved to provide evidence of the methodology and practice of the procedure and assist in any potential future attempts to reproduce the result. These procedural records may also assist in the conception of new experiments to test the hypothesis, and may prove useful to engineers who might examine the potential practical applications of a discovery.

When additional information is needed before a study can be reproduced, the author of the study might be asked to provide it. They might provide it, or if the author refuses to share data, appeals can be made to the journal editors who published the study or to the institution which funded the research.

Since a scientist cannot record everything that took place in an experiment, facts selected for their apparent relevance are reported. This may lead, unavoidably, to problems later if some supposedly irrelevant feature is questioned. For example, Heinrich Hertz did not report the size of the room used to test Maxwell's equations, which later turned out to account for a small deviation in the results. The problem is that parts of the theory itself need to be assumed to select and report the experimental conditions. The observations are hence sometimes described as being 'theory-laden'.

Science of complex systems

Science applied to complex systems can involve elements such as transdisciplinarity, systems theory, control theory, and scientific modelling. The Santa Fe Institute studies such systems;[85] Murray Gell-Mann interconnects these topics with message passing.[114][16]

Some biological systems, such those involved in proprioception, have been fruitfully modeled by engineering techniques.[115][116]

In general, the scientific method may be difficult to apply stringently to diverse, interconnected systems and large data sets. In particular, practices used within Big data, such as predictive analytics, may be considered to be at odds with the scientific method,[117] as some of the data may have been stripped of the parameters which might be material in alternative hypotheses for an explanation; thus the stripped data would only serve to support the null hypothesis in the predictive analytics application. Fleck (1979), pp. 38–50 notes "a scientific discovery remains incomplete without considerations of the social practices that condition it".[118]

Philosophy and sociology of science

Analytical philosophy

Philosophy of science looks at the underpinning logic of the scientific method, at what separates science from non-science, and the ethic that is implicit in science. There are basic assumptions, derived from philosophy by at least one prominent scientist,[C][119] that form the base of the scientific method – namely, that reality is objective and consistent, that humans have the capacity to perceive reality accurately, and that rational explanations exist for elements of the real world.[119] These assumptions from methodological naturalism form a basis on which science may be grounded. Logical positivist, empiricist, falsificationist, and other theories have criticized these assumptions and given alternative accounts of the logic of science, but each has also itself been criticized.

Thomas Kuhn examined the history of science in his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, and found that the actual method used by scientists differed dramatically from the then-espoused method. His observations of science practice are essentially sociological and do not speak to how science is or can be practiced in other times and other cultures.

Norwood Russell Hanson, Imre Lakatos and Thomas Kuhn have done extensive work on the "theory-laden" character of observation. Hanson (1958) first coined the term for the idea that all observation is dependent on the conceptual framework of the observer, using the concept of gestalt to show how preconceptions can affect both observation and description.[120] He opens Chapter 1 with a discussion of the Golgi bodies and their initial rejection as an artefact of staining technique, and a discussion of Brahe and Kepler observing the dawn and seeing a "different" sunrise despite the same physiological phenomenon.[i][v] Kuhn[121] and Feyerabend[122] acknowledge the pioneering significance of Hanson's work.

Post-modernism and science wars

Paul Feyerabend similarly examined the history of science, and was led to deny that science is genuinely a methodological process. In his book Against Method he argues that scientific progress is not the result of applying any particular method. In essence, he says that for any specific method or norm of science, one can find a historic episode where violating it has contributed to the progress of science. Thus, if believers in the scientific method wish to express a single universally valid rule, Feyerabend jokingly suggests, it should be 'anything goes'.[123] However, this is uneconomic.[B] Criticisms such as Feyerabend's led to the strong programme, a radical approach to the sociology of science.

The postmodernist critiques of science have themselves been the subject of intense controversy. This ongoing debate, known as the science wars, is the result of conflicting values and assumptions between the postmodernist and realist camps. Whereas postmodernists assert that scientific knowledge is simply another discourse (this term has special meaning in this context) and not representative of any form of fundamental truth, realists in the scientific community maintain that scientific knowledge does reveal real and fundamental truths about reality. Many books have been written by scientists which take on this problem and challenge the assertions of the postmodernists while defending science as a legitimate method of deriving truth.[124]

Anthropology and sociology

In anthropology and sociology, following the field research in an academic scientific laboratory by Latour and Woolgar, Karin Knorr Cetina has conducted a comparative study of two scientific fields (namely high energy physics and molecular biology) to conclude that the epistemic practices and reasonings within both scientific communities are different enough to introduce the concept of "epistemic cultures", in contradiction with the idea that a so-called "scientific method" is unique and a unifying concept.[125] Comparing 'epistemic cultures' with Fleck 1935, Thought collectives, (denkkollektiven): Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einfǖhrung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv[126]Fleck (1979), p. xxvii recognizes that facts have lifetimes, flourishing only after incubation periods. His selected question for investigation (1934) was "HOW, THEN, DID THIS EMPIRICAL FACT ORIGINATE AND IN WHAT DOES IT CONSIST?".[127] But by Fleck 1979, p.27, the thought collectives within the respective fields will have to settle on common specialized terminology, publish their results and further intercommunicate with their colleagues using the common terminology, in order to progress.[128]

Relationship with mathematics

Science is the process of gathering, comparing, and evaluating proposed models against observables. A model can be a simulation, mathematical or chemical formula, or set of proposed steps. Science is like mathematics in that researchers in both disciplines try to distinguish what is known from what is unknown at each stage of discovery. Models, in both science and mathematics, need to be internally consistent and also ought to be falsifiable (capable of disproof). In mathematics, a statement need not yet be proved; at such a stage, that statement would be called a conjecture. But when a statement has attained mathematical proof, that statement gains a kind of immortality which is highly prized by mathematicians, and for which some mathematicians devote their lives.[129]

Mathematical work and scientific work can inspire each other.[31] For example, the technical concept of time arose in science, and timelessness was a hallmark of a mathematical topic. But today, the Poincaré conjecture has been proved using time as a mathematical concept in which objects can flow (see Ricci flow).

Nevertheless, the connection between mathematics and reality (and so science to the extent it describes reality) remains obscure. Eugene Wigner's paper, The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences, is a very well-known account of the issue from a Nobel Prize-winning physicist. In fact, some observers (including some well-known mathematicians such as Gregory Chaitin, and others such as Lakoff and Núñez) have suggested that mathematics is the result of practitioner bias and human limitation (including cultural ones), somewhat like the post-modernist view of science.

George Pólya's work on problem solving,[130] the construction of mathematical proofs, and heuristic[131][132] show that the mathematical method and the scientific method differ in detail, while nevertheless resembling each other in using iterative or recursive steps.

In Pólya's view, understanding involves restating unfamiliar definitions in your own words, resorting to geometrical figures, and questioning what we know and do not know already; analysis, which Pólya takes from Pappus,[133] involves free and heuristic construction of plausible arguments, working backward from the goal, and devising a plan for constructing the proof; synthesis is the strict Euclidean exposition of step-by-step details[134] of the proof; review involves reconsidering and re-examining the result and the path taken to it.

Building on Pólya's work, Imre Lakatos argued that mathematicians actually use contradiction, criticism, and revision as principles for improving their work.[135][w] In like manner to science, where truth is sought, but certainty is not found, in Proofs and Refutations, what Lakatos tried to establish was that no theorem of informal mathematics is final or perfect. This means that we should not think that a theorem is ultimately true, only that no counterexample has yet been found. Once a counterexample, i.e. an entity contradicting/not explained by the theorem is found, we adjust the theorem, possibly extending the domain of its validity. This is a continuous way our knowledge accumulates, through the logic and process of proofs and refutations. (However, if axioms are given for a branch of mathematics, this creates a logical system —Wittgenstein 1921 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 5.13; Lakatos claimed that proofs from such a system were tautological, i.e. internally logically true, by rewriting forms, as shown by Poincaré, who demonstrated the technique of transforming tautologically true forms (viz. the Euler characteristic) into or out of forms from homology,[136] or more abstractly, from homological algebra.[137])[138][w]

Lakatos proposed an account of mathematical knowledge based on Polya's idea of heuristics. In Proofs and Refutations, Lakatos gave several basic rules for finding proofs and counterexamples to conjectures. He thought that mathematical 'thought experiments' are a valid way to discover mathematical conjectures and proofs.[140]

Gauss, when asked how he came about his theorems, once replied "durch planmässiges Tattonieren" (through systematic palpable experimentation).[141]

Relationship with statistics

When the scientific method employs statistics as a key part of its arsenal, there are mathematical and practical issues that can have a deleterious effect on the reliability of the output of scientific methods. This is described in a popular 2005 scientific paper "Why Most Published Research Findings Are False" by John Ioannidis, which is considered foundational to the field of metascience.[142] Much research in metascience seeks to identify poor use of statistics and improve its use.[x][y]

The particular points raised are statistical ("The smaller the studies conducted in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true" and "The greater the flexibility in designs, definitions, outcomes, and analytical modes in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true.") and economical ("The greater the financial and other interests and prejudices in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true" and "The hotter a scientific field (with more scientific teams involved), the less likely the research findings are to be true.") Hence: "Most research findings are false for most research designs and for most fields" and "As shown, the majority of modern biomedical research is operating in areas with very low pre- and poststudy probability for true findings." However: "Nevertheless, most new discoveries will continue to stem from hypothesis-generating research with low or very low pre-study odds," which means that *new* discoveries will come from research that, when that research started, had low or very low odds (a low or very low chance) of succeeding. Hence, if the scientific method is used to expand the frontiers of knowledge, research into areas that are outside the mainstream will yield the newest discoveries.

Role of chance in discovery

Somewhere between 33% and 50% of all scientific discoveries are estimated to have been stumbled upon, rather than sought out. This may explain why scientists so often express that they were lucky.[144] Louis Pasteur is credited with the famous saying that "Luck favours the prepared mind", but some psychologists have begun to study what it means to be 'prepared for luck' in the scientific context. Research is showing that scientists are taught various heuristics that tend to harness chance and the unexpected.[144][145] This is what Nassim Nicholas Taleb calls "Anti-fragility"; while some systems of investigation are fragile in the face of human error, human bias, and randomness, the scientific method is more than resistant or tough – it actually benefits from such randomness in many ways (it is anti-fragile). Taleb believes that the more anti-fragile the system, the more it will flourish in the real world.[146]

Psychologist Kevin Dunbar says the process of discovery often starts with researchers finding bugs in their experiments. These unexpected results lead researchers to try to fix what they think is an error in their method. Eventually, the researcher decides the error is too persistent and systematic to be a coincidence. The highly controlled, cautious, and curious aspects of the scientific method are thus what make it well suited for identifying such persistent systematic errors. At this point, the researcher will begin to think of theoretical explanations for the error, often seeking the help of colleagues across different domains of expertise.[144][145]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b See, for example, Galileo Galilei (1638). His thought experiments disprove Aristotle's physics of falling bodies.
  2. ^ a b c Book of Optics (circa 1027) After anatomical investigation of the human eye, and an exhaustive study of human visual perception, Alhacen characterizes the first postulate of Euclid's Optics as 'superfluous and useless' (Book I, [6.54] —thereby overturning Euclid's, Ptolemy's, and Galen's emission theory of vision, using logic and deduction from experiment. He showed Euclid's first postulate of Optics to be hypothetical only, and fails to account for his experiments.), and deduces that light must enter the eye, in order for us to see. He describes the camera obscura as part of this investigation.
  3. ^ a b The goal shifts: after observing the x-ray diffraction pattern of DNA,[21][22] and as time was of the essence,[18] Watson and Crick realize that fastest way to discover DNA's structure was not by mathematical analysis,[17] but by building physical models.[23]
  4. ^ Thus echoing Popper (1963), p. viii
  5. ^ Smolin espouses ethical principles: 1) "we agree to tell the truth and we agree to be governed by rational argument from public evidence". 2) ..."when the evidence is not sufficient to decide from rational argument, whether one point of view is right or another point of view is right, we agree to encourage competition and diversification"...[d]
  6. ^ Staddon, John (2017) Scientific Method: How science works, fails to work or pretends to work Taylor and Francis.[29]
  7. ^ a b Book of Optics Book Seven, Chapter Two [2.1] p.220: — light travels through transparent bodies, such as air, water, glass, transparent stones, in straight lines. "Indeed, this is observable by means of experiment".[89]
  8. ^ The full title translation is from Voelkel (2001), p. 60.
  9. ^ a b Kepler was driven to this experiment after observing the partial solar eclipse at Graz, July 10, 1600. He used Tycho Brahe's method of observation, which was to project the image of the Sun on a piece of paper through a pinhole aperture, instead of looking directly at the Sun. He disagreed with Brahe's conclusion that total eclipses of the Sun were impossible because there were historical accounts of total eclipses. Instead, he deduced that the size of the aperture controls the sharpness of the projected image (the larger the aperture, the more accurate the image – this fact is now fundamental for optical system design). Voelkel (2001), p. 61, notes that Kepler's 1604 experiments produced the first correct account of vision and the eye, because he realized he could not accurately write about astronomical observation by ignoring the eye. Smith (2004), p. 192 recounts how Kepler used Giambattista della Porta's water-filled glass spheres to model the eye, and using an aperture to represent the entrance pupil of the eye, showed that the entire scene at the entrance pupil-focused on a single point of the rear of the glass sphere (representing the retina of the eye). This completed Kepler's investigation of the optical train, as it satisfied his application to astronomy.
  10. ^ ...an experimental approach was advocated by Galileo in 1638 with the publication of Two New Sciences.[30]
  11. ^ The topics of study, as expressed in the vocabulary of its scientists, are approached by a "single unified method".[14]: pp.8, 13, 33–35, 60  The topics are unified by its predicates, in a system of expressions. The unification process was formalized by Jacques Herbrand in 1930.[45]
  12. ^ "no opinion, however absurd and incredible, can be imagined, which has not been maintained by some of the philosophers". —Descartes[54]
  13. ^ "A leap is involved in all thinking" —John Dewey[66]
  14. ^ From the hypothesis, deduce valid forms using modus ponens, or using modus tollens. Avoid invalid forms such as affirming the consequent.
  15. ^ The machinery of the mind can only transform knowledge, but never originate it, unless it be fed with facts of observation. —C.S. Peirce[32]
  16. ^ "And this [experiment using a camera obscura] can be tried anytime".[88]
  17. ^ Book of Optics Book II [3.52] to [3.66] Summary p.444 for Alhazen's experiments on color; pp.343—394 for his physiological experiments on the eye[87]
  18. ^ The Sun's rays are still visible at twilight in the morning and evening due to atmospheric refraction even when the depression angle of the sun is 18° below the horizon.[95]
  19. ^ In Two New Sciences, there are three 'reviewers': Simplicio, Sagredo, and Salviati, who serve as foil, antagonist, and protagonist. Galileo speaks for himself only briefly. But Einstein's 1905 papers were not peer-reviewed before their publication.
  20. ^ The scientific method requires testing and validation a posteriori before ideas are accepted.[60]
  21. ^ "What one does not in the least doubt one should not pretend to doubt; but a man should train himself to doubt," said Peirce in a brief intellectual autobiography.[111] Peirce held that actual, genuine doubt originates externally, usually in surprise, but also that it is to be sought and cultivated, "provided only that it be the weighty and noble metal itself, and no counterfeit nor paper substitute".[112]
  22. ^ Brahe and Kepler are two different observers, intersubjectivity validates Hanson.
  23. ^ a b Stillwell's review (p. 381) of Poincaré's efforts on the Euler characteristic notes that it took five iterations for Poincaré to arrive at the Poincaré homology sphere.[139]
  24. ^ For example, see misuse of p-values.
  25. ^ Regarding the Misuse of t-Tests[143]

Notes: Problem-solving via scientific method

  1. ^ a b c d e In the inquiry-based education paradigm, the stage of "characterization, observation, definition, ..." is more briefly summed up under the rubric of a Question. The question at some stage might be as basic as the 5Ws, or is this answer true?, or who else might know this?, or can I ask them?, and so forth. The questions of the inquirer spiral until the goal is reached.
  2. ^ a b Peirce (1899) First rule of logic (F.R.L)[17] Paragraph 1.136: From the first rule of logic, if we truly desire the goal of the inquiry we are not to waste our resources.[18][19]Terence Tao states the concept thus:[20]

    ...true or false, we still have to make choices. You know, just because time is a limited resource. Attention is a limited resource. Money is a limited resource. So, these are always important questions.

    [20]
  3. ^ a b Never fail to recognize an idea... .— C. S. Peirce, ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE LOGIC OF SCIENCE, SECOND PAPER. —HOW TO MAKE OUR IDEAS CLEAR. Popular Science Monthly Volume 12, January 1878, p.286[32]
  4. ^ Twenty-three hundred years ago, Aristotle proposed that a vacuum did not exist in nature; thirteen hundred years later, Alhazen disproved Aristotle's hypothesis, using experiments on refraction,[33] thus deducing the existence of outer space.[34]
  5. ^ Alhazen argued the importance of forming questions and subsequently testing them: "How does light travel through transparent bodies? Light travels through transparent bodies in straight lines only... We have explained this exhaustively in our Book of Optics.[g] But let us now mention something to prove this convincingly: the fact that light travels in straight lines is clearly observed in the lights which enter into dark rooms through holes.... [T]he entering light will be clearly observable in the dust which fills the air.[37]
    • He demonstrated his conjecture that "light travels through transparent bodies in straight lines only" by placing a straight stick or a taut thread next to the light beam, as quoted in Sambursky (1975), p. 136 to prove that light travels in a straight line.
    • David Hockney cites Alhazen several times as the likely source for the portraiture technique using the camera obscura, which Hockney rediscovered with the aid of an optical suggestion from Charles M. Falco. Kitab al-Manazir, which is Alhazen's Book of Optics, at that time denoted Opticae Thesaurus, Alhazen Arabis, was translated from Arabic into Latin for European use as early as 1270. Hockney cites Friedrich Risner's 1572 Basle edition of Opticae Thesaurus. Hockney quotes Alhazen as the first clear description of the camera obscura.[35]
  6. ^ Distancing oneself from the problem is one technique for solving problems[32]

References

  1. ^ Newton, Issac (1999) [1726 (3rd ed.)]. Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica [Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy]. The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Translated by Cohen, I. Bernard; Whitman, Anne; Budenz, Julia. Includes "A Guide to Newton's Principia" by I. Bernard Cohen, pp. 1–370. (The Principia itself is on pp. 371–946). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. 791–796 ("Rules of Reasoning in Philosophy"); see also Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica#Rules of Reason. ISBN 978-0-520-08817-7.
  2. ^ , Oxford Dictionaries: British and World English, 2016, archived from the original on 2016-06-20, retrieved 2016-05-28
  3. ^ Oxford English Dictionary (3rd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2014. from the original on 2023-11-29. Retrieved 2018-05-31 – via OED Online.
  4. ^ a b Peirce, Charles Sanders (1908). "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God" . Hibbert Journal. 7: 90–112 – via Wikisource. with added notes. Reprinted with previously unpublished part, Collected Papers v. 6, paragraphs 452–85, The Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 434–450, and elsewhere. N.B. 435.30 'living institution': Hibbert J. mis-transcribed 'living institution': ("constitution" for "institution")
  5. ^ Popper (1959), p. 273.
  6. ^ Smith (2001b), Book I, [6.54] pp.372,408.
  7. ^ a b Gauch (2003), p. 3: "The scientific method 'is often misrepresented as a fixed sequence of steps,' rather than being seen for what it truly is, 'a highly variable and creative process' (AAAS 2000:18). The claim here is that science has general principles that must be mastered to increase productivity and enhance perspective, not that these principles provide a simple and automated sequence of steps to follow."
  8. ^ a b Gauch (2003), p. 3.
  9. ^ a b William Whewell, History of Inductive Science (1837), and in Philosophy of Inductive Science (1840)
  10. ^ Inwood, Stephen (2003). The Forgotten Genius : The biography of Robert Hooke (1635–1703). San Francisco: MacAdam/Cage Pub. pp. 112–116. ISBN 978-1-931561-56-3. OCLC 53006741.
  11. ^ Hooke, Robert (1705). "First general: The present state of natural philosophy and wherein it is deficient". In Waller, Richard (ed.). The posthumous works of Robert Hooke, M.D. S.R.S. Geom. Prof. Gresh. etc.
  12. ^ a b c d Thurs (2011).
  13. ^ a b Achinstein, Peter (2004). "General Introduction". Science Rules: A Historical Introduction to Scientific Methods. Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 1–5. ISBN 978-0-8018-7943-2.
  14. ^ a b Cowles (2020), p. 264
  15. ^ Popper (1963). (PDF). pp. 312–365. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-10-13. claims that Trial and error is a universal method.
  16. ^ a b c d e Tow, David Hunter (11 September 2010). The Future of Life: A Unified Theory of Evolution. Future of Life Series. Future of Life Media (published 2010). p. 262. Retrieved 2016-12-11. On further examination, however, the scientific method bears a striking similarity to the larger process of evolution itself. [...] Of great significance is the evolutionary algorithm, which uses a simplified subset of the process of natural evolution applied to find the solution to problems that are too complex to solve by traditional analytic methods. In essence, it is a process of accelerated and rigorous trial and error building on previous knowledge to refine an existing hypothesis, or discarding it altogether to find a better model. [...] The evolutionary algorithm is a technique derived from the evolution of knowledge processing applied within the context of science and technology, itself an outcome of evolution. The scientific method continues to evolve through adaptive reward, trial and error, and application of the method to itself.
  17. ^ a b c Peirce, Charles S. (1899). . Collected Papers. v. 1. paragraphs 135–140. Archived from the original on 2012-01-06. Retrieved 2012-01-06. ... in order to learn, one must desire to learn ...
  18. ^ a b c Peirce, Charles S. (1902), Carnegie application, see MS L75.329330, from Draft D 2011-05-24 at the Wayback Machine of Memoir 27: "Consequently, to discover is simply to expedite an event that would occur sooner or later, if we had not troubled ourselves to make the discovery. Consequently, the art of discovery is purely a question of economics. The economics of research is, so far as logic is concerned, the leading doctrine concerning the art of discovery. Consequently, the conduct of abduction, which is chiefly a question of heuretic and is the first question of heuretic, is to be governed by economical considerations."
  19. ^ a b Peirce, Charles S., Carnegie application (L75, 1902), New Elements of Mathematics v. 4, pp. 37–38: "For it is not sufficient that a hypothesis should be a justifiable one. Any hypothesis that explains the facts is justified critically. But among justifiable hypotheses we have to select that one which is suitable for being tested by experiment."
  20. ^ a b Steven Strogatz THE JOY OF WHY (1 Feb 2024) What Makes for ‘Good’ Mathematics? An interview of Terence Tao.
  21. ^ a b McElheny (2004), p. 52: Friday, January 30, 1953. Tea time — Franklin confronts Watson and his paper – "Of course it [Pauling's pre-print] is wrong. DNA is not a helix." However, Watson then visits Wilkins' office, sees photo 51, and immediately recognizes the diffraction pattern of a helical structure. But additional questions remained, requiring additional iterations of their research. For example, the number of strands in the backbone of the helix (Crick suspected 2 strands, but cautioned Watson to examine that more critically), the location of the base pairs (inside the backbone or outside the backbone), etc. One key point was that they realized that the quickest way to reach a result was not to continue a mathematical analysis, but to build a physical model. Later that evening — Watson urges Wilkins to begin model-building immediately. But Wilkins agrees to do so only after Franklin's departure.
  22. ^ a b Cynthia Wolberger (2021) Photograph 51 explained
  23. ^ a b c McElheny (2004), pp. 57–59: Saturday, February 28, 1953 — Watson found the base-pairing mechanism which explained Chargaff's rules using his cardboard models.
  24. ^ Smolin, Lee (May 2013). "There is No Scientific Method". from the original on 2016-08-07. Retrieved 2016-06-07.
  25. ^ Thurs, Daniel P. (2015), "That the scientific method accurately reflects what scientists actually do", in Numbers, Ronald L.; Kampourakis, Kostas (eds.), Newton's Apple and Other Myths about Science, Harvard University Press, pp. 210–218, ISBN 978-0-674-91547-3, from the original on 2023-11-29, retrieved 2020-10-20, It's probably best to get the bad news out of the way first, the so-called scientific method is a myth. ... If typical formulations were accurate, the only location true science would be taking place in would be grade-school classrooms.
  26. ^ a b Mark Snyder (1984) When Belief Creates Reality 2021-08-24 at the Wayback Machine Advances in Experimental Social Psychology Volume 18, 1984, Pages 247-305
  27. ^ a b Taleb (2007), p. 72 lists ways to avoid the narrative fallacy and confirmation bias; the narrative fallacy being a substitute for explanation.
  28. ^ Nola, Robert; Sankey, Howard (2007). Theories of Scientific Method: An Introduction. Philosophy and science. Vol. 2. Montréal: McGill–Queen's University Press. pp. 1, 300. doi:10.4324/9781315711959. ISBN 9780773533448. OCLC 144602109. There is a large core of people who think there is such a thing as a scientific method that can be justified, although not all agree as to what this might be. But there are also a growing number of people who think that there is no method to be justified. For some, the whole idea is yesteryear's debate, the continuation of which can be summed up as yet more of the proverbial 'flogging a dead horse'. We beg to differ. ... We shall claim that Feyerabend did endorse various scientific values, did accept rules of method (on a certain understanding of what these are), and did attempt to justify them using a meta methodology somewhat akin to the principle of reflective equilibrium.
  29. ^ Staddon, John (16 September 2020). "Staddon, John (Sep 2020) Whatever Happened to History of Science?" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2021-08-27. Retrieved 2021-08-27.
  30. ^ a b Galileo Galilei (1638).
  31. ^ a b "Philosophy [i.e., physics] is written in this grand book – I mean the universe – which stands continually open to our gaze, but it cannot be understood unless one first learns to comprehend the language and interpret the characters in which it is written. It is written in the language of mathematics, and its characters are triangles, circles, and other geometrical figures, without which it is humanly impossible to understand a single word of it; without these, one is wandering around in a dark labyrinth." – Galileo Galilei, Il Saggiatore (The Assayer, 1623), as translated by Stillman Drake (1957), Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo pp. 237–238, as quoted by di Francia (1981), p. 10.
  32. ^ a b c d e Peirce, Charles Sanders (1877). "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" . Popular Science Monthly. 12: 286–302 – via Wikisource.
  33. ^ Alhacen (c.1035) Treatise on Light (رسالة في الضوء) as cited in Shmuel Sambursky, ed. (1975) Physical thought from the Presocratics to the quantum physicists : an anthology, p.137
  34. ^ a b Smith (2010) Book 7, [4.28] p.270
  35. ^ a b c Hockney (2006), p. 240: "Truth is sought for its own sake. And those who are engaged upon the quest for anything for its own sake are not interested in other things. Finding the truth is difficult, and the road to it is rough." – Alhazen (Ibn Al-Haytham 965 – c. 1040) Critique of Ptolemy, translated by S. Pines, Actes X Congrès internationale d'histoire des sciences, Vol I Ithaca 1962, as quoted in Sambursky (1975), p. 139. (This quotation is from Alhazen's critique of Ptolemy's books Almagest, Planetary Hypotheses, and Ptolemy's Theory of Visual Perception: An English Translation of the Optics. Translated by A. Mark Smith. American Philosophical Society. 1996. ISBN 9780871698629. from the original on 2023-11-29. Retrieved 2021-11-27.)
  36. ^ Elizabeth Asmis (1985) Epicurus' Scientific Method. Cornell University Press
  37. ^ Alhazen, Treatise on Light (رسالة في الضوء), translated into English from German by M. Schwarz, from "Abhandlung über das Licht" 2019-12-30 at the Wayback Machine, J. Baarmann (editor and translator from Arabic to German, 1882) Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenländischen Gesellschaft Vol 36 as quoted in Sambursky (1975), p. 136.
  38. ^ Alikuzai (2013), p. 154.
  39. ^ Rozhanskaya & Levinova (1996).
  40. ^ (PDF). The optics of Giovan Battista della Porta (1535–1615): A Reassessment Workshop at Technical University of Berlin, 24–25 October 2014. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-05-27.
  41. ^ Kepler, Johannes (1604) Ad Vitellionem paralipomena, quibus astronomiae pars opticae traditur (Supplements to Witelo, in which the optical part of astronomy is treated)[h] as cited in Smith, A. Mark (June 2004). "What Is the History of Medieval Optics Really about?". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 148 (2): 180–194. JSTOR 1558283. PMID 15338543.
  42. ^ Sanches (1988).
  43. ^ Godfrey-Smith (2003), p. 236.
  44. ^ Gauch (2003), p. xv: "The thesis of this book, as outlined in Chapter One, is that there are general principles applicable to all the sciences."
  45. ^ Maribel Fernández (Dec 2007) Unification Algorithms
  46. ^ Lindberg (2007), pp. 2–3: "There is a danger that must be avoided. ... If we wish to do justice to the historical enterprise, we must take the past for what it was. And that means we must resist the temptation to scour the past for examples or precursors of modern science. ...My concern will be with the beginnings of scientific theories, the methods by which they were formulated, and the uses to which they were put; ... "
  47. ^ Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2009). Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-30062-7. from the original on 2023-11-29. Retrieved 2020-05-09.
  48. ^ a b Brody (1993), p. 10 calls this an epistemic cycle; these cycles can occur at high levels of abstraction.
  49. ^ a b Peirce, Charles Sanders (1877). "The Fixation of Belief" . Popular Science Monthly. 12: 1–15 – via Wikisource..
  50. ^ Peirce, Charles S., Collected Papers v. 5, in paragraph 582, from 1898: "... [rational] inquiry of every type, fully carried out, has the vital power of self-correction and of growth. This is a property so deeply saturating its inmost nature that it may truly be said that there is but one thing needful for learning the truth, and that is a hearty and active desire to learn what is true."
  51. ^ Einstein & Infeld (1938), p. 92: "To raise new questions, new possibilities, to regard old problems from a new angle, requires creative imagination and marks real advance in science."
  52. ^ Crawford S, Stucki L (1990). "Peer review and the changing research record". Journal of the American Society for Information Science. 41 (3): 223–228. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1097-4571(199004)41:3<223::AID-ASI14>3.0.CO;2-3.
  53. ^ Gauch (2003), esp. chapters 5–8.
  54. ^ René Descartes (1637) Discourse on the Method/Part 2 Archived 2021-09-01 at the Wayback Machine Part II
  55. ^ McCarty (1985), p. 252.
  56. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 34.
  57. ^ Schuster, Daniel P.; Powers, William J., eds. (2005). "Ch. 1". Translational and Experimental Clinical Research. Lippincott Williams & Wilkins. ISBN 9780781755658. from the original on 2023-11-29. Retrieved 2021-11-27. This chapter also discusses the different types of research questions and how they are produced.
  58. ^ "ESO Telescope Sees Star Dance Around Supermassive Black Hole, Proves Einstein Right". Science Release. European Southern Observatory. 16 April 2020. from the original on 2020-05-15. Retrieved 2020-04-17.
  59. ^ Andreas Vesalius, Epistola, Rationem, Modumque Propinandi Radicis Chynae Decocti (1546), p. 141. Quoted and translated in C.D. O'Malley, Andreas Vesalius of Brussels, (1964), p. 116. As quoted by Bynum & Porter (2005), p. 597: "Andreas Vesalius"
  60. ^ a b c d MacKay, Donald M. (1969). Information, Mechanism, and Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 1–4. ISBN 0-262-63032-X. Invariably one came up against fundamental physical limits to the accuracy of measurement. ... The art of physical measurement seemed to be a matter of compromise, of choosing between reciprocally related uncertainties. ... Multiplying together the conjugate pairs of uncertainty limits mentioned, however, I found that they formed invariant products of not one but two distinct kinds. ... The first group of limits were calculable a priori from a specification of the instrument. The second group could be calculated only a posteriori from a specification of what was done with the instrument. ... In the first case each unit [of information] would add one additional dimension (conceptual category), whereas in the second each unit would add one additional atomic fact.
  61. ^ Crick, Francis (1994), The Astonishing Hypothesis ISBN 0-684-19431-7 p. 20
  62. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 40: October 1951 — "That's what a helix should look like!" Crick exclaimed in delight (This is the Cochran-Crick-Vand-Stokes theory of the transform of a helix).
  63. ^ Judson (1979), p. 157. "'The structure that we propose is a three-chain structure, each chain being a helix' – Linus Pauling"
  64. ^ McElheny (2004), pp. 49–50: January 28, 1953 — Watson read Pauling's pre-print, and realized that in Pauling's model, DNA's phosphate groups had to be un-ionized. But DNA is an acid, which contradicts Pauling's model.
  65. ^ Einstein, Albert (1949). The World as I See It. New York: Philosophical Library. pp. 24–28.
  66. ^ Dewey (1910), p. 26
  67. ^ Aristotle (trans. 1853) Prior Analytics 2.25 Archived 2021-09-10 at the Wayback Machine via Wikisource
  68. ^ Glen (1994), pp. 37–38.
  69. ^ Platt, John R. (16 October 1964). "Strong Inference". Science. 146 (3642): 347–. Bibcode:1964Sci...146..347P. doi:10.1126/science.146.3642.347. PMID 17739513.
  70. ^ Judson (1979), pp. 137–138: "Watson did enough work on Tobacco mosaic virus to produce the diffraction pattern for a helix, per Crick's work on the transform of a helix."
  71. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 43: June 1952 — Watson had succeeded in getting X-ray pictures of TMV showing a diffraction pattern consistent with the transform of a helix.
  72. ^ Cochran W, Crick FHC and Vand V. (1952) "The Structure of Synthetic Polypeptides. I. The Transform of Atoms on a Helix", Acta Crystallogr., 5, 581–586.
  73. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 68: Nature April 25, 1953.
  74. ^ In March 1917, the Royal Astronomical Society announced that on May 29, 1919, the occasion of a total eclipse of the sun would afford favorable conditions for testing Einstein's General theory of relativity. One expedition, to Sobral, Ceará, Brazil, and Eddington's expedition to the island of Principe yielded a set of photographs, which, when compared to photographs taken at Sobral and at Greenwich Observatory showed that the deviation of light was measured to be 1.69 arc-seconds, as compared to Einstein's desk prediction of 1.75 arc-seconds. – Antonina Vallentin (1954), Einstein, as quoted by Samuel Rapport and Helen Wright (1965), Physics, New York: Washington Square Press, pp. 294–295.
  75. ^ "The Secret of Photo 51". NOVA. PBS. from the original on 2017-08-31. Retrieved 2017-09-11.
  76. ^ Watson (1968), p. 167: "The instant I saw the picture my mouth fell open and my pulse began to race." Page 168 shows the X-shaped pattern of the B-form of DNA, clearly indicating crucial details of its helical structure to Watson and Crick.
  77. ^ Mill, John Stuart, "A System of Logic", University Press of the Pacific, Honolulu, 2002, ISBN 1-4102-0252-6.
  78. ^ National Science Foundation (NSF) (2021) NSF Reports 2021-08-17 at the Wayback Machine and News 2021-08-20 at the Wayback Machine
  79. ^ "LHC long term schedule". lhc-commissioning.web.cern.ch. from the original on 2020-04-25. Retrieved 2021-08-22. (2021)
  80. ^ "ligo.caltech.edu (1999) Laser Interferometer Gravitational-Wave Observatory". from the original on 2021-09-01. Retrieved 2021-08-30.
  81. ^ "NIF (2021) What Is the National Ignition Facility?". from the original on 2017-07-31. Retrieved 2021-08-22.
  82. ^ "ISS (2021) International Space Station". 12 January 2015. from the original on 2005-09-07. Retrieved 2021-08-22.
  83. ^ "JWST (2021) WEBB Space Telescope". from the original on 2012-01-04. Retrieved 2021-08-22.
  84. ^ James Webb Space Telescope (JWST) (12 Nov 2021) James Webb Space Telescope Deployment Sequence (Nominal) 2021-12-23 at the Wayback Machine highlights the predictions from launch to day+29,
  85. ^ a b "James (2003) "Complex Systems Theory?"" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2021-04-18. Retrieved 2018-05-27.
  86. ^ al-Battani, De Motu Stellarum translation from Arabic to Latin in 1116, as cited by E. S. Kennedy, A Survey of Islamic Astronomical Tables, (Transactions of the American Philosophical Society, New Series, 46, 2), Philadelphia, 1956, pp. 10–11, 32–34.
  87. ^ a b Smith (2001b).
  88. ^ Smith (2001b), Book I [6.86] p.379.
  89. ^ Smith (2010), p. 220 Book Seven covers refraction.
  90. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 53: The weekend (January 31 – February 1) — After seeing photo 51, Watson informed Bragg of the X-ray diffraction image of DNA in B form. Bragg permitted them to restart their research on DNA (that is, model building).
  91. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 54: Sunday, February 8, 1953 — Maurice Wilkes gave Watson and Crick permission to work on models, as Wilkes would not be building models until Franklin left DNA research.
  92. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 56: Jerry Donohue, on sabbatical from Pauling's lab and visiting Cambridge, advises Watson that the textbook form of the base pairs was incorrect for DNA base pairs; rather, the keto form of the base pairs should be used instead. This form allowed the bases' hydrogen bonds to pair 'unlike' with 'unlike', rather than to pair 'like' with 'like', as Watson was inclined to model, based on the textbook statements. On February 27, 1953, Watson was convinced enough to make cardboard models of the nucleotides in their keto form.
  93. ^ Watson (1968), pp. 194–197: "Suddenly I became aware that an adenine-thymine pair held together by two hydrogen bonds was identical in shape to a guanine-cytosine pair held together by at least two hydrogen bonds. ..."
  94. ^ McElheny (2004), p. 57: Saturday, February 28, 1953 — Watson tried 'like with like' and admitted these base pairs didn't have hydrogen bonds that line up. But after trying 'unlike with unlike', and getting Jerry Donohue's approval, the base pairs turned out to be identical in shape (as Watson stated above in his 1968 Double Helix memoir quoted above). Watson now felt confident enough to inform Crick. (Of course, 'unlike with unlike' increases the number of possible codons, if this scheme were a genetic code.)
  95. ^ Goldstein, Bernard R. (1977) Ibn Mu'adh's "(1079) Treatise On Twilight and the Height of the Atmosphere 2022-09-21 at the Wayback Machine" Archive for History of Exact Sciences Vol. 17, No. 2 (21.VII.1977), pp. 97-118 (22 pages) JSTOR. (Treatise On Twilight was printed by F Risner in Opticae Thesaurus (1572) as Liber de crepusculis, but attributed to Alhazen rather than Ibn Mu'adh.)
  96. ^ Krider, E. Philip (January 2006). "Benjamin Franklin and lightning rods". Physics Today. 59 (1): 42. Bibcode:2006PhT....59a..42K. doi:10.1063/1.2180176. S2CID 110623159. On 6 August 1753, the Swedish scientist Georg Wilhelm Richmann was electrocuted in St. Petersburg ...
  97. ^ "Reconstruction of Galileo Galilei's experiment – the inclined plane" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2014-04-29. Retrieved 2014-04-28.
  98. ^ Ioannidis, John P. A. (August 2005). "Why most published research findings are false". PLOS Medicine. 2 (8): e124. doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124. PMC 1182327. PMID 16060722.
  99. ^ Fleck (1979), pp. xxvii–xxviii.
  100. ^ "NIH Data Sharing Policy 2012-05-13 at the Wayback Machine."
  101. ^ Stanovich, Keith E. (2007). How to Think Straight About Psychology. Boston: Pearson Education. p. 123
  102. ^ a b Brody (1993), pp. 44–45.
  103. ^ a b Goldhaber & Nieto (2010), p. 942.
  104. ^ Hall, B.K.; Hallgrímsson, B., eds. (2008). Strickberger's Evolution (4th ed.). Jones & Bartlett. p. 762. ISBN 978-0-7637-0066-9.
  105. ^ Cracraft, J.; Donoghue, M.J., eds. (2005). Assembling the tree of life. Oxford University Press. p. 592. ISBN 978-0-19-517234-8. from the original on 2023-11-29. Retrieved 2020-10-20.
  106. ^ Needham & Wang (1954), p. 166 shows how the 'flying gallop' image propagated from China to the West.
  107. ^ Goldhaber & Nieto (2010), p. 940.
  108. ^ Ronald R. Sims (2003). Ethics and corporate social responsibility: Why giants fall. p. 21: "'A myth is a belief given uncritical acceptance by members of a group ...' – Weiss, Business Ethics p. 15."
  109. ^ Lakatos (1976), pp. 1–19.
  110. ^ Aristotle (1938). "Prior Analytics". Aristotle, Volume 1. Loeb Classical Library. Translated by Hugh Tredennick. London: William Heinemann. pp. 181–531.
  111. ^ Ketner, Kenneth Laine (2009). "Charles Sanders Peirce: Interdisciplinary Scientist". The Logic of Interdisciplinarity. By Peirce, Charles S. Bisanz, Elize (ed.). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
  112. ^ Peirce, Charles S. (October 1905). "Issues of Pragmaticism". The Monist. Vol. XV, no. 4. pp. 481–499, see p. 484, and p. 491. Reprinted in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 438–463, see 443 and 451.
  113. ^ Brown, C. (2005) Overcoming Barriers to Use of Promising Research Among Elite Middle East Policy Groups, Journal of Social Behaviour and Personality, Select Press.
  114. ^ David Mermin (September 1994). "A "Virtuosically Adaptive" System As Seen By A "Marginally Adaptive" One (Review of The Quark and the Jaguar, by Murray Gell-Mann (1994))". Physics Today. 47 (9): 89. doi:10.1063/1.2808634.
    Murray Gell-Mann (11 May 2016). What the Quark and Jaguar is about. Archived from the original on 2021-12-11 – via Youtube.
  115. ^ Poppele RE, Bowman RJ (January 1970). "Quantitative description of linear behavior of mammalian muscle spindles". Journal of Neurophysiology. 33 (1): 59–72. doi:10.1152/jn.1970.33.1.59. PMID 4243791.
  116. ^ Blum KP, Lamotte D'Incamps B, Zytnicki D, Ting LH (September 2017). Ayers J (ed.). "Force encoding in muscle spindles during stretch of passive muscle". PLOS Computational Biology. 13 (9): e1005767. Bibcode:2017PLSCB..13E5767B. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1005767. PMC 5634630. PMID 28945740.
  117. ^ Anderson, Chris (2008) The End of Theory: The Data Deluge Makes the Scientific Method Obsolete 2021-05-02 at the Wayback Machine. Wired Magazine 16.07
  118. ^ Ludwik Fleck (1979) Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact 2021-08-26 at the Wayback Machine
  119. ^ a b Einstein, Albert (1936, 1956) One may say "the eternal mystery of the world is its comprehensibility." From the article "Physics and Reality" (1936), reprinted in Out of My Later Years (1956). 'It is one of the great realizations of Immanuel Kant that the setting up of a real external world would be senseless without this comprehensibility.'
  120. ^ Hanson, Norwood (1958), Patterns of Discovery, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-05197-2
  121. ^ Kuhn, Thomas S. (2009). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. p. 113. ISBN 978-1-4432-5544-8.
  122. ^ Feyerabend, Paul K (1960) "Patterns of Discovery" The Philosophical Review (1960) vol. 69 (2) pp. 247–252
  123. ^ Feyerabend, Paul K., Against Method, Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge, 1st published, 1975. Reprinted, Verso, London, 1978.
  124. ^ For example:
    • Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and Its Quarrels with Science, The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997
    • Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals' Abuse of Science, Picador. 1999
    • The Sokal Hoax: The Sham That Shook the Academy, University of Nebraska Press, 2000 ISBN 0-8032-7995-7
    • A House Built on Sand: Exposing Postmodernist Myths About Science, Oxford University Press, 2000
    • Intellectual Impostures, Economist Books, 2003
  125. ^ Knorr-Cetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures: how the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-25893-8. OCLC 39539508.
  126. ^ As cited in Fleck (1979), p. 27, Fleck (1979), pp. 38–50
  127. ^ Fleck (1979), p. xxviii
  128. ^ Fleck (1979), p. 27
  129. ^ Pólya (1957), p. 131 in the section on 'Modern heuristic': "When we are working intensively, we feel keenly the progress of our work; we are elated when our progress is rapid, we are depressed when it is slow."
  130. ^ "If you can't solve a problem, then there is an easier problem you can solve: find it." —Pólya (1957), p. 114
  131. ^ George Pólya (1954), Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning Volume I: Induction and Analogy in Mathematics.
  132. ^ George Pólya (1954), Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning Volume II: Patterns of Plausible Reasoning.
  133. ^ Pólya (1957), p. 142.
  134. ^ Pólya (1957), p. 144.
  135. ^ Lakatos (1976) documents the development, by generations of mathematicians, of Euler's formula for polyhedra.
  136. ^ H.S.M. Coxeter (1973) Regular Polytopes ISBN 9780486614809, Chapter IX "Poincaré's proof of Euler's formula"
  137. ^ "Charles A. Weibel (ca. 1995) History of Homological Algebra" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2021-09-06. Retrieved 2021-08-28.
  138. ^ Henri Poincaré, Sur l’analysis situs, Comptes rendusde l’Academie des Sciences 115 (1892), 633–636. as cited by Lakatos (1976), p. 162
  139. ^ John Stillwell, reviewer (Apr 2014). Notices of the AMS. 61 (4), pp. 378–383, on Jeremy Gray's (2013) Henri Poincaré: A Scientific Biography (PDF 2021-07-04 at the Wayback Machine).
  140. ^ Lakatos (1976), p. 55.
  141. ^ Mackay (1991), p. 100.
  142. ^ Ioannidis, John P.A. (1 August 2005). "Why Most Published Research Findings Are False". PLOS Medicine. 2 (8): e124. doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124. ISSN 1549-1277. PMC 1182327. PMID 16060722.
  143. ^ Schaefer, Carl F (May 1984). "Regarding the Misuse of t Tests". Anesthesiology. 60 (5): 505. doi:10.1097/00000542-198405000-00026. PMID 6711862. from the original on 2021-08-29. Retrieved 2021-08-29.
  144. ^ a b c Dunbar, K., & Fugelsang, J. (2005). Causal thinking in science: How scientists and students interpret the unexpected. In M.E. Gorman, R.D. Tweney, D. Gooding & A. Kincannon (Eds.), Scientific and Technical Thinking (pp. 57–79). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
  145. ^ a b Oliver, J.E. (1991). "Ch 2". The incomplete guide to the art of discovery. New York: Columbia University Press. ISBN 9780231076203.
  146. ^ Taleb, Nassim N. . Archived from the original on 2013-05-07.

Sources

Further reading

  • Bauer, Henry H., Scientific Literacy and the Myth of the Scientific Method, University of Illinois Press, Champaign, IL, 1992
  • Beveridge, William I.B., The Art of Scientific Investigation, Heinemann, Melbourne, Australia, 1950.
  • Bernstein, Richard J., Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis, University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, PA, 1983.
  • Brody, Baruch A. and Capaldi, Nicholas, Science: Men, Methods, Goals: A Reader: Methods of Physical Science 2023-04-13 at the Wayback Machine, W.A. Benjamin, 1968
  • Brody, Baruch A. and Grandy, Richard E., Readings in the Philosophy of Science, 2nd edition, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1989.
  • Burks, Arthur W., Chance, Cause, Reason: An Inquiry into the Nature of Scientific Evidence, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1977.
  • Chalmers, Alan, What Is This Thing Called Science?. Queensland University Press and Open University Press, 1976.
  • Crick, Francis (1988), What Mad Pursuit: A Personal View of Scientific Discovery, New York: Basic Books, ISBN 978-0-465-09137-9.
  • Crombie, A.C. (1953), Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100–1700, Oxford: Clarendon
  • Earman, John (ed.), Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations: Essays in the Philosophy of Science, University of California Press, Berkeley & Los Angeles, CA, 1992.
  • Fraassen, Bas C. van, The Scientific Image, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1980.
  • Franklin, James (2009), What Science Knows: And How It Knows It, New York: Encounter Books, ISBN 978-1-59403-207-3.
  • Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Reason in the Age of Science, Frederick G. Lawrence (trans.), MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1981.
  • Giere, Ronald N. (ed.), Cognitive Models of Science, vol. 15 in 'Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN, 1992.
  • Hacking, Ian, Representing and Intervening, Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983.
  • Heisenberg, Werner, Physics and Beyond, Encounters and Conversations, A.J. Pomerans (trans.), Harper and Row, New York, 1971, pp. 63–64.
  • Holton, Gerald, Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein, 1st edition 1973, revised edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1988.
  • Karin Knorr Cetina, Knorr Cetina, Karin (1999). Epistemic cultures: how the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-25894-5.
  • Kuhn, Thomas S., The Essential Tension, Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1977.
  • Latour, Bruno, Science in Action, How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1987.
  • Losee, John, A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1972. 2nd edition, 1980.
  • Maxwell, Nicholas, The Comprehensibility of the Universe: A New Conception of Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998. Paperback 2003.
  • Maxwell, Nicholas, Understanding Scientific Progress 2018-02-20 at the Wayback Machine, Paragon House, St. Paul, Minnesota, 2017.
  • McComas, William F., ed. (1998). (PDF). The Nature of Science in Science Education. Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 53–70. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-07-01.
  • Misak, Cheryl J., Truth and the End of Inquiry, A Peircean Account of Truth, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1991.
  • Oreskes, Naomi, "Masked Confusion: A trusted source of health information misleads the public by prioritizing rigor over reality", Scientific American, vol. 329, no. 4 (November 2023), pp. 90–91.
  • Piattelli-Palmarini, Massimo (ed.), Language and Learning, The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1980.
  • Popper, Karl R., Unended Quest, An Intellectual Autobiography, Open Court, La Salle, IL, 1982.
  • Putnam, Hilary, Renewing Philosophy, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1992.
  • Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1979.
  • Salmon, Wesley C., Four Decades of Scientific Explanation, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN, 1990.
  • Shimony, Abner, Search for a Naturalistic World View: Vol. 1, Scientific Method and Epistemology, Vol. 2, Natural Science and Metaphysics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993.
  • Thagard, Paul, Conceptual Revolutions, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1992.
  • Ziman, John (2000). Real Science: what it is, and what it means. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

External links

scientific, method, other, uses, disambiguation, scientific, research, redirects, here, publisher, scientific, research, publishing, broader, coverage, this, topic, research, this, article, require, copy, editing, grammar, style, cohesion, tone, spelling, assi. For other uses see Scientific method disambiguation Scientific research redirects here For the publisher see Scientific Research Publishing For broader coverage of this topic see Research This article may require copy editing for grammar style cohesion tone or spelling You can assist by editing it January 2024 Learn how and when to remove this template message The scientific method is an empirical method for acquiring knowledge that has characterized the development of science since at least the 17th century For notable practitioners in previous centuries see history of scientific method The scientific method is often represented as an ongoing process This diagram represents one variant and there are many others The scientific method involves careful observation coupled with rigorous scepticism because cognitive assumptions can distort the interpretation of the observation Scientific inquiry includes creating a hypothesis through inductive reasoning testing it through experiments and statistical analysis and adjusting or discarding the hypothesis based on the results The above mentioned are principles of the scientific method a definitive series of steps applicable to all scientific enterprises 1 2 3 Although procedures vary from one field of inquiry to another the underlying process is frequently the same The process in the scientific method involves making conjectures hypothetical explanations deriving predictions from the hypotheses as logical consequences and then carrying out experiments or empirical observations based on those predictions a 4 A hypothesis is a conjecture based on knowledge obtained while seeking answers to the question The hypothesis might be very specific or it might be broad Scientists then test hypotheses by conducting experiments or studies A scientific hypothesis must be falsifiable implying that it is possible to identify a possible outcome of an experiment or observation that conflicts with predictions deduced from the hypothesis otherwise the hypothesis cannot be meaningfully tested 5 The purpose of an experiment is to determine whether observations A a b agree or disagree with hypothesis 6 b Though the scientific method is often presented as a fixed sequence of steps it represents rather a set of general principles 7 Not all steps take place in every scientific inquiry nor to the same degree and they are not always in the same order 8 9 Contents 1 History 1 1 Problem solving via scientific method 2 Overview 2 1 Factors of scientific inquiry 3 Elements of the scientific method 3 1 Characterizations 3 1 1 Uncertainty 3 1 2 Definition 3 2 Hypothesis development 3 3 Predictions from the hypothesis 3 4 Experiments 3 5 Evaluation and improvement 3 6 Confirmation 4 Scientific inquiry 4 1 Properties of scientific inquiry 4 2 Beliefs and biases 5 Models of scientific inquiry 6 Communication and community 7 Science of complex systems 8 Philosophy and sociology of science 8 1 Analytical philosophy 8 2 Post modernism and science wars 8 3 Anthropology and sociology 9 Relationship with mathematics 9 1 Relationship with statistics 9 2 Role of chance in discovery 10 See also 11 Notes 11 1 Notes Problem solving via scientific method 12 References 13 Sources 14 Further reading 15 External linksHistoryMain article History of scientific method See also Timeline of the history of the scientific methodImportant debates in the history of science concern scepticism that anything can be known for sure such as views of Francisco Sanches rationalism especially as advocated by Rene Descartes inductivism empiricism as argued for by Francis Bacon then rising to particular prominence with Robert Hooke 10 11 Isaac Newton and his followers and hypothetico deductivism which came to the fore in the early 19th century The term scientific method emerged in the 19th century as a result of significant institutional development of science emerged and terminologies established clear boundaries between science and non science such as scientist and pseudoscience appeared 12 Throughout the 1830s and 1850s when Baconianism was popular naturalists like William Whewell John Herschel John Stuart Mill engaged in debates over induction and facts and were focused on how to generate knowledge 12 In the late 19th and early 20th centuries a debate over realism vs antirealism was conducted as powerful scientific theories extended beyond the realm of the observable 13 Problem solving via scientific method See also Notes Problem solving via scientific method The term scientific method came into popular use in the twentieth century Dewey s 1910 book How We Think inspired popular guidelines 14 appearing in dictionaries and science textbooks although there was little consensus over its meaning 12 Although there was growth through the middle of the twentieth century by the 1960s and 1970s numerous influential philosophers of science such as Thomas Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend had questioned the universality of the scientific method and in doing so largely replaced the notion of science as a homogeneous and universal method with that of it being a heterogeneous and local practice 12 In particular Paul Feyerabend in the 1975 first edition of his book Against Method argued against there being any universal rules of science 13 Popper 1963 15 Gauch 2003 7 and Tow 2010 16 disagree with Feyerabend s claim problem solvers and researchers are to be prudent with their resources during their inquiry B c Later stances include physicist Lee Smolin s 2013 essay There Is No Scientific Method 24 in which he espouses two ethical principles e and historian of science Daniel Thurs chapter in the 2015 book Newton s Apple and Other Myths about Science which concluded that the scientific method is a myth or at best an idealization 25 As myths are beliefs 26 they are subject to the narrative fallacy as Taleb points out 27 Philosophers Robert Nola and Howard Sankey in their 2007 book Theories of Scientific Method said that debates over the scientific method continue and argued that Feyerabend despite the title of Against Method accepted certain rules of method and attempted to justify those rules with a meta methodology 28 Staddon 2017 argues it is a mistake to try following rules in the absence of an algorithmic scientific method in that case science is best understood through examples f But algorithmic methods such as disproof of existing theory by experiment have been used since Alhacen 1027 Book of Optics b and Galileo 1638 Two New Sciences 30 and The Assayer 31 still stand as scientific method They contradict Feyerabend s stance C D The ubiquitous element in the scientific method is empiricism This is in opposition to stringent forms of rationalism the scientific method embodies the position that reason alone cannot solve a particular scientific problem A strong formulation of the scientific method is not always aligned with a form of empiricism in which the empirical data is put forward in the form of experience or other abstracted forms of knowledge in current scientific practice however the use of scientific modelling and reliance on abstract typologies and theories is normally accepted The scientific method counters claims that revelation political or religious dogma appeals to tradition commonly held beliefs common sense or currently held theories pose the only possible means of demonstrating truth 35 17 16 Different early expressions of empiricism and the scientific method can be found throughout history for instance with the ancient Stoics Epicurus 36 Alhazen E Avicenna Al Biruni 38 39 Roger Bacon and William of Ockham From the 16th century onwards experiments were advocated by Francis Bacon and performed by Giambattista della Porta 40 Johannes Kepler 41 i and Galileo Galilei j There was particular development aided by theoretical works by Francisco Sanches 42 John Locke George Berkeley and David Hume A sea voyage from America to Europe afforded C S Peirce the distance to clarify his ideas F gradually resulting in the hypothetico deductive model 43 Formulated in the 20th century the model has undergone significant revision since first proposed for a more formal discussion see Elements of the scientific method OverviewThe scientific method is the process by which science is carried out 44 As in other areas of inquiry science through the scientific method can build on previous knowledge and can unify understanding of its topics of study over time k This model can be seen to underlie the scientific revolution 46 The overall process involves making conjectures hypotheses deriving predictions from them as logical consequences and then carrying out experiments based on those predictions to determine whether the original conjecture was correct 4 However there are difficulties in a formulaic statement of method Though the scientific method is often presented as a fixed sequence of steps these actions are better considered as general principles 8 Not all steps take place in every scientific inquiry nor to the same degree and they are not always done in the same order As noted by scientist and philosopher William Whewell 1794 1866 invention sagacity and genius 9 are required at every step Factors of scientific inquiry There are different ways of outlining the basic method used for scientific inquiry The scientific community and philosophers of science generally agree on the following classification of method components These methodological elements and organization of procedures tend to be more characteristic of experimental sciences than social sciences Nonetheless the cycle of formulating hypotheses testing and analyzing the results and formulating new hypotheses will resemble the cycle described below The scientific method is an iterative cyclical process through which information is continually revised 47 48 It is generally recognized to develop advances in knowledge through the following elements in varying combinations or contributions 49 50 Characterizations observations definitions and measurements of the subject of inquiry Hypotheses theoretical hypothetical explanations of observations and measurements of the subject Predictions inductive and deductive reasoning from the hypothesis or theory Experiments tests of all of the above Each element of the scientific method is subject to peer review for possible mistakes These activities do not describe all that scientists do but apply mostly to experimental sciences e g physics chemistry biology and psychology The elements above are often taught in the educational system as the scientific method A The scientific method is not a single recipe it requires intelligence imagination and creativity 51 In this sense it is not a mindless set of standards and procedures to follow but is rather an ongoing cycle constantly developing more useful accurate and comprehensive models and methods For example when Einstein developed the Special and General Theories of Relativity he did not in any way refute or discount Newton s Principia On the contrary if the astronomically massive the feather light and the extremely fast are removed from Einstein s theories all phenomena Newton could not have observed Newton s equations are what remain Einstein s theories are expansions and refinements of Newton s theories and thus increase confidence in Newton s work An iterative 48 pragmatic 35 scheme of the four points above is sometimes offered as a guideline for proceeding 52 Define a question Gather information and resources observe Form an explanatory hypothesis Test the hypothesis by performing an experiment and collecting data in a reproducible manner Analyze the data Interpret the data and draw conclusions that serve as a starting point for a new hypothesis Publish results Retest frequently done by other scientists The iterative cycle inherent in this step by step method goes from point 3 to 6 and back to 3 again While this schema outlines a typical hypothesis testing method 53 many philosophers historians and sociologists of science including Paul Feyerabend l claim that such descriptions of scientific method have little relation to the ways that science is actually practiced Elements of the scientific methodThe basic elements of the scientific method are illustrated by the following example which occurred from 1944 to 1953 from the discovery of the structure of DNA marked with nbsp and indented Characterizations nbsp In 1950 it was known that genetic inheritance had a mathematical description starting with the studies of Gregor Mendel and that DNA contained genetic information Oswald Avery s transforming principle 55 But the mechanism of storing genetic information i e genes in DNA was unclear Researchers in Bragg s laboratory at Cambridge University made X ray diffraction pictures of various molecules starting with crystals of salt and proceeding to more complicated substances Using clues painstakingly assembled over decades beginning with its chemical composition it was determined that it should be possible to characterize the physical structure of DNA and the X ray images would be the vehicle 56 The scientific method depends upon increasingly sophisticated characterizations of the subjects of investigation The subjects can also be called unsolved problems or the unknowns A For example Benjamin Franklin conjectured correctly that St Elmo s fire was electrical in nature but it has taken a long series of experiments and theoretical changes to establish this While seeking the pertinent properties of the subjects careful thought may also entail some definitions and observations the observations often demand careful measurements and or counting The question can refer to the explanation of a specific observation A as in Why is the sky blue but can also be open ended as in How can I design a drug to cure this particular disease This stage frequently involves finding and evaluating evidence from previous experiments personal scientific observations or assertions as well as the work of other scientists If the answer is already known a different question that builds on the evidence can be posed When applying the scientific method to research determining a good question can be very difficult and it will affect the outcome of the investigation 57 The systematic careful collection of measurements or counts of relevant quantities is often the critical difference between pseudo sciences such as alchemy and science such as chemistry or biology Scientific measurements are usually tabulated graphed or mapped and statistical manipulations such as correlation and regression performed on them The measurements might be made in a controlled setting such as a laboratory or made on more or less inaccessible or unmanipulatable objects such as stars or human populations The measurements often require specialized scientific instruments such as thermometers spectroscopes particle accelerators or voltmeters and the progress of a scientific field is usually intimately tied to their invention and improvement nbsp Precession of the perihelion exaggerated in the case of Mercury but observed in the case of S2 s apsidal precession around Sagittarius A 58 The characterization element can require extended and extensive study even centuries It took thousands of years of measurements from the Chaldean Indian Persian Greek Arabic and European astronomers to fully record the motion of planet Earth Newton was able to include those measurements into the consequences of his laws of motion But the perihelion of the planet Mercury s orbit exhibits a precession that cannot be fully explained by Newton s laws of motion see diagram to the right as Leverrier pointed out in 1859 The observed difference for Mercury s precession between Newtonian theory and observation was one of the things that occurred to Albert Einstein as a possible early test of his theory of General relativity His relativistic calculations matched observation much more closely than did Newtonian theory The difference is approximately 43 arc seconds per century I am not accustomed to saying anything with certainty after only one or two observations Andreas Vesalius 1546 59 Uncertainty Measurements in scientific work are also usually accompanied by estimates of their uncertainty 60 The uncertainty is often estimated by making repeated measurements of the desired quantity Uncertainties may also be calculated by consideration of the uncertainties of the individual underlying quantities used Counts of things such as the number of people in a nation at a particular time may also have an uncertainty due to data collection limitations Or counts may represent a sample of desired quantities with an uncertainty that depends upon the sampling method used and the number of samples taken Definition The scientific definition of a term sometimes differs substantially from its natural language usage For example mass and weight overlap in meaning in common discourse but have distinct meanings in mechanics Scientific quantities are often characterized by their units of measure which can later be described in terms of conventional physical units when communicating the work New theories are sometimes developed after realizing certain terms have not previously been sufficiently clearly defined For example Albert Einstein s first paper on relativity begins by defining simultaneity and the means for determining length These ideas were skipped over by Isaac Newton with I do not define time space place and motion as being well known to all Einstein s paper then demonstrates that they viz absolute time and length independent of motion were approximations Francis Crick cautions us that when characterizing a subject however it can be premature to define something when it remains ill understood 61 In Crick s study of consciousness he actually found it easier to study awareness in the visual system rather than to study free will for example His cautionary example was the gene the gene was much more poorly understood before Watson and Crick s pioneering discovery of the structure of DNA it would have been counterproductive to spend much time on the definition of the gene before them Hypothesis development Main article Hypothesis formation nbsp Linus Pauling proposed that DNA might be a triple helix 62 63 This hypothesis was also considered by Francis Crick and James D Watson but discarded When Watson and Crick learned of Pauling s hypothesis they understood from existing data that Pauling was wrong 64 and that Pauling would soon admit his difficulties with that structure A hypothesis is a suggested explanation of a phenomenon or alternately a reasoned proposal suggesting a possible correlation between or among a set of phenomena Normally hypotheses have the form of a mathematical model Sometimes but not always they can also be formulated as existential statements stating that some particular instance of the phenomenon being studied has some characteristic and causal explanations which have the general form of universal statements stating that every instance of the phenomenon has a particular characteristic Scientists are free to use whatever resources they have their own creativity ideas from other fields inductive reasoning Bayesian inference and so on to imagine possible explanations for a phenomenon under study Albert Einstein once observed that there is no logical bridge between phenomena and their theoretical principles 65 m Charles Sanders Peirce borrowing a page from Aristotle Prior Analytics 2 25 67 described the incipient stages of inquiry instigated by the irritation of doubt to venture a plausible guess as abductive reasoning 32 II p 290 The history of science is filled with stories of scientists claiming a flash of inspiration or a hunch which then motivated them to look for evidence to support or refute their idea Michael Polanyi made such creativity the centerpiece of his discussion of methodology William Glen observes that 68 the success of a hypothesis or its service to science lies not simply in its perceived truth or power to displace subsume or reduce a predecessor idea but perhaps more in its ability to stimulate the research that will illuminate bald suppositions and areas of vagueness William Glen The Mass Extinction Debates In general scientists tend to look for theories that are elegant or beautiful Scientists often use these terms to refer to a theory that is following the known facts but is nevertheless relatively simple and easy to handle Occam s Razor serves as a rule of thumb for choosing the most desirable amongst a group of equally explanatory hypotheses To minimize the confirmation bias that results from entertaining a single hypothesis strong inference emphasizes the need for entertaining multiple alternative hypotheses 69 Predictions from the hypothesis Further information Prediction Science nbsp James D Watson Francis Crick and others hypothesized that DNA had a helical structure This implied that DNA s X ray diffraction pattern would be x shaped 70 71 This prediction followed from the work of Cochran Crick and Vand 72 and independently by Stokes The Cochran Crick Vand Stokes theorem provided a mathematical explanation for the empirical observation that diffraction from helical structures produces x shaped patterns In their first paper Watson and Crick also noted that the double helix structure they proposed provided a simple mechanism for DNA replication writing It has not escaped our notice that the specific pairing we have postulated immediately suggests a possible copying mechanism for the genetic material 73 Any useful hypothesis will enable predictions by reasoning including deductive reasoning n It might predict the outcome of an experiment in a laboratory setting or the observation of a phenomenon in nature The prediction can also be statistical and deal only with probabilities It is essential that the outcome of testing such a prediction be currently unknown Only in this case does a successful outcome increase the probability that the hypothesis is true If the outcome is already known it is called a consequence and should have already been considered while formulating the hypothesis If the predictions are not accessible by observation or experience the hypothesis is not yet testable and so will remain to that extent unscientific in a strict sense A new technology or theory might make the necessary experiments feasible For example while a hypothesis on the existence of other intelligent species may be convincing with scientifically based speculation no known experiment can test this hypothesis Therefore science itself can have little to say about the possibility In the future a new technique may allow for an experimental test and the speculation would then become part of accepted science For example Einstein s theory of general relativity makes several specific predictions about the observable structure of spacetime such as that light bends in a gravitational field and that the amount of bending depends in a precise way on the strength of that gravitational field Arthur Eddington s observations made during a 1919 solar eclipse supported General Relativity rather than Newtonian gravitation 74 Experiments Main article Experiment nbsp Watson and Crick showed an initial and incorrect proposal for the structure of DNA to a team from King s College London Rosalind Franklin Maurice Wilkins and Raymond Gosling Franklin immediately spotted the flaws which concerned the water content Later Watson saw Franklin s photo 51 a detailed X ray diffraction image which showed an X shape 75 22 and was able to confirm the structure was helical 21 76 c Once predictions are made they can be sought by experiments If the test results contradict the predictions the hypotheses which entailed them are called into question and become less tenable Sometimes the experiments are conducted incorrectly or are not very well designed when compared to a crucial experiment If the experimental results confirm the predictions then the hypotheses are considered more likely to be correct but might still be wrong and continue to be subject to further testing The experimental control is a technique for dealing with observational error This technique uses the contrast between multiple samples or observations or populations under differing conditions to see what varies or what remains the same We vary the conditions for the acts of measurement to help isolate what has changed Mill s canons can then help us figure out what the important factor is 77 Factor analysis is one technique for discovering the important factor in an effect Depending on the predictions the experiments can have different shapes It could be a classical experiment in a laboratory setting a double blind study or an archaeological excavation Even taking a plane from New York to Paris is an experiment that tests the aerodynamical hypotheses used for constructing the plane These institutions thereby reduce the research function to a cost benefit 60 which is expressed as money and the time and attention of the researchers to be expended 60 in exchange for a report to their constituents 78 Current large instruments such as CERN s Large Hadron Collider LHC 79 or LIGO 80 or the National Ignition Facility NIF 81 or the International Space Station ISS 82 or the James Webb Space Telescope JWST 83 84 entail expected costs of billions of dollars and timeframes extending over decades These kinds of institutions affect public policy on a national or even international basis and the researchers would require shared access to such machines and their adjunct infrastructure o 85 Scientists assume an attitude of openness and accountability on the part of those experimenting Detailed record keeping is essential to aid in recording and reporting on the experimental results and supports the effectiveness and integrity of the procedure They will also assist in reproducing the experimental results likely by others Traces of this approach can be seen in the work of Hipparchus 190 120 BCE when determining a value for the precession of the Earth while controlled experiments can be seen in the works of al Battani 853 929 CE 86 and Alhazen 965 1039 CE 87 p q g Evaluation and improvement nbsp Watson and Crick then produced their model using this information along with the previously known information about DNA s composition especially Chargaff s rules of base pairing 23 After considerable fruitless experimentation being discouraged by their superior from continuing and numerous false starts 90 91 92 Watson and Crick were able to infer the essential structure of DNA by concrete modeling of the physical shapes of the nucleotides which comprise it 23 93 94 They were guided by the bond lengths which had been deduced by Linus Pauling and by Rosalind Franklin s X ray diffraction images The scientific method is iterative At any stage it is possible to refine its accuracy and precision so that some consideration will lead the scientist to repeat an earlier part of the process Failure to develop an interesting hypothesis may lead a scientist to re define the subject under consideration Failure of a hypothesis to produce interesting and testable predictions may lead to reconsideration of the hypothesis or of the definition of the subject Failure of an experiment to produce interesting results may lead a scientist to reconsider the experimental method the hypothesis or the definition of the subject By 1027 Alhazen based on his measurements of the refraction of light was able to deduce that outer space was less dense than air that is the body of the heavens is rarer than the body of air 34 In 1079 Ibn Mu adh s Treatise On Twilight was able to infer that Earth s atmosphere was 50 miles thick based on atmospheric refraction of the sun s rays r Other scientists may start their own research and enter the process at any stage They might adopt the characterization and formulate their own hypothesis or they might adopt the hypothesis and deduce their own predictions Often the experiment is not done by the person who made the prediction and the characterization is based on experiments done by someone else Published results of experiments can also serve as a hypothesis predicting their own reproducibility Confirmation Main article Reproducibility Science is a social enterprise and scientific work tends to be accepted by the scientific community when it has been confirmed Crucially experimental and theoretical results must be reproduced by others within the scientific community Researchers have given their lives for this vision Georg Wilhelm Richmann was killed by ball lightning 1753 when attempting to replicate the 1752 kite flying experiment of Benjamin Franklin 96 If an experiment cannot be repeated to produce the same results this implies that the original results might have been in error As a result it is common for a single experiment to be performed multiple times especially when there are uncontrolled variables or other indications of experimental error For significant or surprising results other scientists may also attempt to replicate the results for themselves especially if those results would be important to their own work 97 Replication has become a contentious issue in social and biomedical science where treatments are administered to groups of individuals Typically an experimental group gets the treatment such as a drug and the control group gets a placebo John Ioannidis in 2005 pointed out that the method being used has led to many findings that cannot be replicated 98 The process of peer review involves the evaluation of the experiment by experts who typically give their opinions anonymously Some journals request that the experimenter provide lists of possible peer reviewers especially if the field is highly specialized Peer review does not certify the correctness of the results only that in the opinion of the reviewer the experiments themselves were sound based on the description supplied by the experimenter If the work passes peer review which occasionally may require new experiments requested by the reviewers it will be published in a peer reviewed scientific journal The specific journal that publishes the results indicates the perceived quality of the work s Scientists typically are careful in recording their data a requirement promoted by Ludwik Fleck 1896 1961 and others 99 Though not typically required they might be requested to supply this data to other scientists who wish to replicate their original results or parts of their original results extending to the sharing of any experimental samples that may be difficult to obtain 100 To protect against bad science and fraudulent data government research granting agencies such as the National Science Foundation and science journals including Nature and Science have a policy that researchers must archive their data and methods so that other researchers can test the data and methods and build on the research that has gone before Scientific data archiving can be done at several national archives in the U S or the World Data Center Scientific inquiryScientific inquiry generally aims to obtain knowledge in the form of testable explanations 19 18 that scientists can use to predict the results of future experiments This allows scientists to gain a better understanding of the topic under study and later to use that understanding to intervene in its causal mechanisms such as to cure disease The better an explanation is at making predictions the more useful it frequently can be and the more likely it will continue to explain a body of evidence better than its alternatives The most successful explanations those that explain and make accurate predictions in a wide range of circumstances are often called scientific theories A Most experimental results do not produce large changes in human understanding improvements in theoretical scientific understanding typically result from a gradual process of development over time sometimes across different domains of science 101 Scientific models vary in the extent to which they have been experimentally tested and for how long and in their acceptance in the scientific community In general explanations become accepted over time as evidence accumulates on a given topic and the explanation in question proves more powerful than its alternatives at explaining the evidence Often subsequent researchers re formulate the explanations over time or combined explanations to produce new explanations Tow sees the scientific method in terms of an evolutionary algorithm applied to science and technology 16 Properties of scientific inquiry Scientific knowledge is closely tied to empirical findings and can remain subject to falsification if new experimental observations are incompatible with what is found That is no theory can ever be considered final since new problematic evidence might be discovered If such evidence is found a new theory may be proposed or more commonly it is found that modifications to the previous theory are sufficient to explain the new evidence The strength of a theory relates to how long it has persisted without major alteration to its core principles Theories can also become subsumed by other theories For example Newton s laws explained thousands of years of scientific observations of the planets almost perfectly However these laws were then determined to be special cases of a more general theory relativity which explained both the previously unexplained exceptions to Newton s laws and predicted and explained other observations such as the deflection of light by gravity Thus in certain cases independent unconnected scientific observations can be connected unified by principles of increasing explanatory power 102 103 Since new theories might be more comprehensive than what preceded them and thus be able to explain more than previous ones successor theories might be able to meet a higher standard by explaining a larger body of observations than their predecessors 102 For example the theory of evolution explains the diversity of life on Earth how species adapt to their environments and many other patterns observed in the natural world 104 105 its most recent major modification was unification with genetics to form the modern evolutionary synthesis In subsequent modifications it has also subsumed aspects of many other fields such as biochemistry and molecular biology 16 Beliefs and biases nbsp Flying gallop as shown by this painting Theodore Gericault 1821 is falsified see below nbsp Muybridge s photographs of The Horse in Motion 1878 were used to answer the question of whether all four feet of a galloping horse are ever off the ground at the same time This demonstrates a use of photography as an experimental tool in science Scientific methodology often directs that hypotheses be tested in controlled conditions wherever possible This is frequently possible in certain areas such as in the biological sciences and more difficult in other areas such as in astronomy The practice of experimental control and reproducibility can have the effect of diminishing the potentially harmful effects of circumstance and to a degree personal bias For example pre existing beliefs can alter the interpretation of results as in confirmation bias this is a heuristic that leads a person with a particular belief to see things as reinforcing their belief even if another observer might disagree in other words people tend to observe what they expect to observe 26 T he action of thought is excited by the irritation of doubt and ceases when belief is attained C S Peirce How to Make Our Ideas Clear 1877 32 A historical example is the belief that the legs of a galloping horse are splayed at the point when none of the horse s legs touch the ground to the point of this image being included in paintings by its supporters However the first stop action pictures of a horse s gallop by Eadweard Muybridge showed this to be false and that the legs are instead gathered together 106 Another important human bias that plays a role is a preference for new surprising statements see Appeal to novelty which can result in a search for evidence that the new is true 107 Poorly attested beliefs can be believed and acted upon via a less rigorous heuristic 108 Goldhaber and Nieto published in 2010 the observation that if theoretical structures with many closely neighboring subjects are described by connecting theoretical concepts then the theoretical structure acquires a robustness which makes it increasingly hard though certainly never impossible to overturn 103 When a narrative is constructed its elements become easier to believe 109 27 Fleck 1979 p 27 notes Words and ideas are originally phonetic and mental equivalences of the experiences coinciding with them Such proto ideas are at first always too broad and insufficiently specialized Once a structurally complete and closed system of opinions consisting of many details and relations has been formed it offers enduring resistance to anything that contradicts it Sometimes these relations have their elements assumed a priori or contain some other logical or methodological flaw in the process that ultimately produced them Donald M MacKay has analyzed these elements in terms of limits to the accuracy of measurement and has related them to instrumental elements in a category of measurement t Models of scientific inquiryMain article Models of scientific inquiryThe classical model of scientific inquiry derives from Aristotle 110 who distinguished the forms of approximate and exact reasoning set out the threefold scheme of abductive deductive and inductive inference and also treated the compound forms such as reasoning by analogy The hypothetico deductive model or method is a proposed description of the scientific method Here predictions from the hypothesis are central if one assumes the hypothesis to be true what consequences follow If a subsequent empirical investigation does not demonstrate that these consequences or predictions correspond to the observable world the hypothesis can be concluded to be false In 1877 49 Charles Sanders Peirce 1839 1914 characterized inquiry in general not as the pursuit of truth per se but as the struggle to move from irritating inhibitory doubts born of surprises disagreements and the like and to reach a secure belief the belief being that on which one is prepared to act He framed scientific inquiry as part of a broader spectrum and as spurred like inquiry generally by actual doubt not mere verbal or hyperbolic doubt which he held to be fruitless u Communication and communitySee also Scientific community and Scholarly communication Frequently the scientific method is employed not only by a single person but also by several people cooperating directly or indirectly Such cooperation can be regarded as an important element of a scientific community Various standards of scientific methodology are used within such an environment Scientific journals use a process of peer review in which scientists manuscripts are submitted by editors of scientific journals to usually one to three and usually anonymous fellow scientists familiar with the field for evaluation In certain journals the journal itself selects the referees while in others especially journals that are extremely specialized the manuscript author might recommend referees The referees may or may not recommend publication or they might recommend publication with suggested modifications or sometimes publication in another journal This standard is practiced to various degrees by different journals and can have the effect of keeping the literature free of obvious errors and generally improve the quality of the material especially in the journals that use the standard most rigorously The peer review process can have limitations when considering research outside the conventional scientific paradigm problems of groupthink can interfere with open and fair deliberation of some new research 113 Researchers sometimes practice scientific data archiving such as in compliance with the policies of government funding agencies and scientific journals In these cases detailed records of their experimental procedures raw data statistical analyses and source code can be preserved to provide evidence of the methodology and practice of the procedure and assist in any potential future attempts to reproduce the result These procedural records may also assist in the conception of new experiments to test the hypothesis and may prove useful to engineers who might examine the potential practical applications of a discovery When additional information is needed before a study can be reproduced the author of the study might be asked to provide it They might provide it or if the author refuses to share data appeals can be made to the journal editors who published the study or to the institution which funded the research Since a scientist cannot record everything that took place in an experiment facts selected for their apparent relevance are reported This may lead unavoidably to problems later if some supposedly irrelevant feature is questioned For example Heinrich Hertz did not report the size of the room used to test Maxwell s equations which later turned out to account for a small deviation in the results The problem is that parts of the theory itself need to be assumed to select and report the experimental conditions The observations are hence sometimes described as being theory laden Science of complex systemsScience applied to complex systems can involve elements such as transdisciplinarity systems theory control theory and scientific modelling The Santa Fe Institute studies such systems 85 Murray Gell Mann interconnects these topics with message passing 114 16 Some biological systems such those involved in proprioception have been fruitfully modeled by engineering techniques 115 116 In general the scientific method may be difficult to apply stringently to diverse interconnected systems and large data sets In particular practices used within Big data such as predictive analytics may be considered to be at odds with the scientific method 117 as some of the data may have been stripped of the parameters which might be material in alternative hypotheses for an explanation thus the stripped data would only serve to support the null hypothesis in the predictive analytics application Fleck 1979 pp 38 50 notes a scientific discovery remains incomplete without considerations of the social practices that condition it 118 Philosophy and sociology of scienceSee also Philosophy of science and Sociology of scientific knowledge Analytical philosophy Philosophy of science looks at the underpinning logic of the scientific method at what separates science from non science and the ethic that is implicit in science There are basic assumptions derived from philosophy by at least one prominent scientist C 119 that form the base of the scientific method namely that reality is objective and consistent that humans have the capacity to perceive reality accurately and that rational explanations exist for elements of the real world 119 These assumptions from methodological naturalism form a basis on which science may be grounded Logical positivist empiricist falsificationist and other theories have criticized these assumptions and given alternative accounts of the logic of science but each has also itself been criticized Thomas Kuhn examined the history of science in his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and found that the actual method used by scientists differed dramatically from the then espoused method His observations of science practice are essentially sociological and do not speak to how science is or can be practiced in other times and other cultures Norwood Russell Hanson Imre Lakatos and Thomas Kuhn have done extensive work on the theory laden character of observation Hanson 1958 first coined the term for the idea that all observation is dependent on the conceptual framework of the observer using the concept of gestalt to show how preconceptions can affect both observation and description 120 He opens Chapter 1 with a discussion of the Golgi bodies and their initial rejection as an artefact of staining technique and a discussion of Brahe and Kepler observing the dawn and seeing a different sunrise despite the same physiological phenomenon i v Kuhn 121 and Feyerabend 122 acknowledge the pioneering significance of Hanson s work Post modernism and science wars Paul Feyerabend similarly examined the history of science and was led to deny that science is genuinely a methodological process In his book Against Method he argues that scientific progress is not the result of applying any particular method In essence he says that for any specific method or norm of science one can find a historic episode where violating it has contributed to the progress of science Thus if believers in the scientific method wish to express a single universally valid rule Feyerabend jokingly suggests it should be anything goes 123 However this is uneconomic B Criticisms such as Feyerabend s led to the strong programme a radical approach to the sociology of science The postmodernist critiques of science have themselves been the subject of intense controversy This ongoing debate known as the science wars is the result of conflicting values and assumptions between the postmodernist and realist camps Whereas postmodernists assert that scientific knowledge is simply another discourse this term has special meaning in this context and not representative of any form of fundamental truth realists in the scientific community maintain that scientific knowledge does reveal real and fundamental truths about reality Many books have been written by scientists which take on this problem and challenge the assertions of the postmodernists while defending science as a legitimate method of deriving truth 124 Anthropology and sociology In anthropology and sociology following the field research in an academic scientific laboratory by Latour and Woolgar Karin Knorr Cetina has conducted a comparative study of two scientific fields namely high energy physics and molecular biology to conclude that the epistemic practices and reasonings within both scientific communities are different enough to introduce the concept of epistemic cultures in contradiction with the idea that a so called scientific method is unique and a unifying concept 125 Comparing epistemic cultures with Fleck 1935 Thought collectives denkkollektiven Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache Einfǖhrung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv 126 Fleck 1979 p xxvii recognizes that facts have lifetimes flourishing only after incubation periods His selected question for investigation 1934 was HOW THEN DID THIS EMPIRICAL FACT ORIGINATE AND IN WHAT DOES IT CONSIST 127 But by Fleck 1979 p 27 the thought collectives within the respective fields will have to settle on common specialized terminology publish their results and further intercommunicate with their colleagues using the common terminology in order to progress 128 See also Cognitive revolution and Perceptual control theory The methodology of modeling and PCT as modelRelationship with mathematicsScience is the process of gathering comparing and evaluating proposed models against observables A model can be a simulation mathematical or chemical formula or set of proposed steps Science is like mathematics in that researchers in both disciplines try to distinguish what is known from what is unknown at each stage of discovery Models in both science and mathematics need to be internally consistent and also ought to be falsifiable capable of disproof In mathematics a statement need not yet be proved at such a stage that statement would be called a conjecture But when a statement has attained mathematical proof that statement gains a kind of immortality which is highly prized by mathematicians and for which some mathematicians devote their lives 129 Mathematical work and scientific work can inspire each other 31 For example the technical concept of time arose in science and timelessness was a hallmark of a mathematical topic But today the Poincare conjecture has been proved using time as a mathematical concept in which objects can flow see Ricci flow Nevertheless the connection between mathematics and reality and so science to the extent it describes reality remains obscure Eugene Wigner s paper The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences is a very well known account of the issue from a Nobel Prize winning physicist In fact some observers including some well known mathematicians such as Gregory Chaitin and others such as Lakoff and Nunez have suggested that mathematics is the result of practitioner bias and human limitation including cultural ones somewhat like the post modernist view of science George Polya s work on problem solving 130 the construction of mathematical proofs and heuristic 131 132 show that the mathematical method and the scientific method differ in detail while nevertheless resembling each other in using iterative or recursive steps Mathematical method Scientific method1 Understanding Characterization from experience and observation2 Analysis Hypothesis a proposed explanation3 Synthesis Deduction prediction from the hypothesis4 Review Extend Test and experimentIn Polya s view understanding involves restating unfamiliar definitions in your own words resorting to geometrical figures and questioning what we know and do not know already analysis which Polya takes from Pappus 133 involves free and heuristic construction of plausible arguments working backward from the goal and devising a plan for constructing the proof synthesis is the strict Euclidean exposition of step by step details 134 of the proof review involves reconsidering and re examining the result and the path taken to it Building on Polya s work Imre Lakatos argued that mathematicians actually use contradiction criticism and revision as principles for improving their work 135 w In like manner to science where truth is sought but certainty is not found in Proofs and Refutations what Lakatos tried to establish was that no theorem of informal mathematics is final or perfect This means that we should not think that a theorem is ultimately true only that no counterexample has yet been found Once a counterexample i e an entity contradicting not explained by the theorem is found we adjust the theorem possibly extending the domain of its validity This is a continuous way our knowledge accumulates through the logic and process of proofs and refutations However if axioms are given for a branch of mathematics this creates a logical system Wittgenstein 1921 Tractatus Logico Philosophicus 5 13 Lakatos claimed that proofs from such a system were tautological i e internally logically true by rewriting forms as shown by Poincare who demonstrated the technique of transforming tautologically true forms viz the Euler characteristic into or out of forms from homology 136 or more abstractly from homological algebra 137 138 w Lakatos proposed an account of mathematical knowledge based on Polya s idea of heuristics In Proofs and Refutations Lakatos gave several basic rules for finding proofs and counterexamples to conjectures He thought that mathematical thought experiments are a valid way to discover mathematical conjectures and proofs 140 Gauss when asked how he came about his theorems once replied durch planmassiges Tattonieren through systematic palpable experimentation 141 Relationship with statistics When the scientific method employs statistics as a key part of its arsenal there are mathematical and practical issues that can have a deleterious effect on the reliability of the output of scientific methods This is described in a popular 2005 scientific paper Why Most Published Research Findings Are False by John Ioannidis which is considered foundational to the field of metascience 142 Much research in metascience seeks to identify poor use of statistics and improve its use x y The particular points raised are statistical The smaller the studies conducted in a scientific field the less likely the research findings are to be true and The greater the flexibility in designs definitions outcomes and analytical modes in a scientific field the less likely the research findings are to be true and economical The greater the financial and other interests and prejudices in a scientific field the less likely the research findings are to be true and The hotter a scientific field with more scientific teams involved the less likely the research findings are to be true Hence Most research findings are false for most research designs and for most fields and As shown the majority of modern biomedical research is operating in areas with very low pre and poststudy probability for true findings However Nevertheless most new discoveries will continue to stem from hypothesis generating research with low or very low pre study odds which means that new discoveries will come from research that when that research started had low or very low odds a low or very low chance of succeeding Hence if the scientific method is used to expand the frontiers of knowledge research into areas that are outside the mainstream will yield the newest discoveries Role of chance in discovery Main article Role of chance in scientific discoveries Somewhere between 33 and 50 of all scientific discoveries are estimated to have been stumbled upon rather than sought out This may explain why scientists so often express that they were lucky 144 Louis Pasteur is credited with the famous saying that Luck favours the prepared mind but some psychologists have begun to study what it means to be prepared for luck in the scientific context Research is showing that scientists are taught various heuristics that tend to harness chance and the unexpected 144 145 This is what Nassim Nicholas Taleb calls Anti fragility while some systems of investigation are fragile in the face of human error human bias and randomness the scientific method is more than resistant or tough it actually benefits from such randomness in many ways it is anti fragile Taleb believes that the more anti fragile the system the more it will flourish in the real world 146 Psychologist Kevin Dunbar says the process of discovery often starts with researchers finding bugs in their experiments These unexpected results lead researchers to try to fix what they think is an error in their method Eventually the researcher decides the error is too persistent and systematic to be a coincidence The highly controlled cautious and curious aspects of the scientific method are thus what make it well suited for identifying such persistent systematic errors At this point the researcher will begin to think of theoretical explanations for the error often seeking the help of colleagues across different domains of expertise 144 145 See alsoEmpirical limits in science Idea that knowledge comes only mainly from sensory experiencePages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets Evidence based practices Pragmatic methodologyPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets Methodology Study of research methods Metascience Scientific study of science Quantitative research All procedures for the numerical representation of empirical facts Research transparency Scientific law Statement based on repeated empirical observations that describes some natural phenomenon Testability Extent to which truthness or falseness of a hypothesis declaration can be tested Timeline of the history of scientific methodNotes a b See for example Galileo Galilei 1638 His thought experiments disprove Aristotle s physics of falling bodies a b c Book of Optics circa 1027 After anatomical investigation of the human eye and an exhaustive study of human visual perception Alhacen characterizes the first postulate of Euclid s Optics as superfluous and useless Book I 6 54 thereby overturning Euclid s Ptolemy s and Galen s emission theory of vision using logic and deduction from experiment He showed Euclid s first postulate of Optics to be hypothetical only and fails to account for his experiments and deduces that light must enter the eye in order for us to see He describes the camera obscura as part of this investigation a b The goal shifts after observing the x ray diffraction pattern of DNA 21 22 and as time was of the essence 18 Watson and Crick realize that fastest way to discover DNA s structure was not by mathematical analysis 17 but by building physical models 23 Thus echoing Popper 1963 p viii Smolin espouses ethical principles 1 we agree to tell the truth and we agree to be governed by rational argument from public evidence 2 when the evidence is not sufficient to decide from rational argument whether one point of view is right or another point of view is right we agree to encourage competition and diversification d Staddon John 2017 Scientific Method How science works fails to work or pretends to work Taylor and Francis 29 a b Book of Optics Book Seven Chapter Two 2 1 p 220 light travels through transparent bodies such as air water glass transparent stones in straight lines Indeed this is observable by means of experiment 89 The full title translation is from Voelkel 2001 p 60 a b Kepler was driven to this experiment after observing the partial solar eclipse at Graz July 10 1600 He used Tycho Brahe s method of observation which was to project the image of the Sun on a piece of paper through a pinhole aperture instead of looking directly at the Sun He disagreed with Brahe s conclusion that total eclipses of the Sun were impossible because there were historical accounts of total eclipses Instead he deduced that the size of the aperture controls the sharpness of the projected image the larger the aperture the more accurate the image this fact is now fundamental for optical system design Voelkel 2001 p 61 notes that Kepler s 1604 experiments produced the first correct account of vision and the eye because he realized he could not accurately write about astronomical observation by ignoring the eye Smith 2004 p 192 recounts how Kepler used Giambattista della Porta s water filled glass spheres to model the eye and using an aperture to represent the entrance pupil of the eye showed that the entire scene at the entrance pupil focused on a single point of the rear of the glass sphere representing the retina of the eye This completed Kepler s investigation of the optical train as it satisfied his application to astronomy an experimental approach was advocated by Galileo in 1638 with the publication of Two New Sciences 30 The topics of study as expressed in the vocabulary of its scientists are approached by a single unified method 14 pp 8 13 33 35 60 The topics are unified by its predicates in a system of expressions The unification process was formalized by Jacques Herbrand in 1930 45 no opinion however absurd and incredible can be imagined which has not been maintained by some of the philosophers Descartes 54 A leap is involved in all thinking John Dewey 66 From the hypothesis deduce valid forms using modus ponens or using modus tollens Avoid invalid forms such as affirming the consequent The machinery of the mind can only transform knowledge but never originate it unless it be fed with facts of observation C S Peirce 32 And this experiment using a camera obscura can be tried anytime 88 Book of Optics Book II 3 52 to 3 66 Summary p 444 for Alhazen s experiments on color pp 343 394 for his physiological experiments on the eye 87 The Sun s rays are still visible at twilight in the morning and evening due to atmospheric refraction even when the depression angle of the sun is 18 below the horizon 95 In Two New Sciences there are three reviewers Simplicio Sagredo and Salviati who serve as foil antagonist and protagonist Galileo speaks for himself only briefly But Einstein s 1905 papers were not peer reviewed before their publication The scientific method requires testing and validation a posteriori before ideas are accepted 60 What one does not in the least doubt one should not pretend to doubt but a man should train himself to doubt said Peirce in a brief intellectual autobiography 111 Peirce held that actual genuine doubt originates externally usually in surprise but also that it is to be sought and cultivated provided only that it be the weighty and noble metal itself and no counterfeit nor paper substitute 112 Brahe and Kepler are two different observers intersubjectivity validates Hanson a b Stillwell s review p 381 of Poincare s efforts on the Euler characteristic notes that it took five iterations for Poincare to arrive at the Poincare homology sphere 139 For example see misuse of p values Regarding the Misuse of t Tests 143 Notes Problem solving via scientific method a b c d e In the inquiry based education paradigm the stage of characterization observation definition is more briefly summed up under the rubric of a Question The question at some stage might be as basic as the 5Ws or is this answer true or who else might know this or can I ask them and so forth The questions of the inquirer spiral until the goal is reached a b Peirce 1899 First rule of logic F R L 17 Paragraph 1 136 From the first rule of logic if we truly desire the goal of the inquiry we are not to waste our resources 18 19 Terence Tao states the concept thus 20 true or false we still have to make choices You know just because time is a limited resource Attention is a limited resource Money is a limited resource So these are always important questions 20 a b Never fail to recognize an idea C S Peirce ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE LOGIC OF SCIENCE SECOND PAPER HOW TO MAKE OUR IDEAS CLEAR Popular Science Monthly Volume 12 January 1878 p 286 32 Twenty three hundred years ago Aristotle proposed that a vacuum did not exist in nature thirteen hundred years later Alhazen disproved Aristotle s hypothesis using experiments on refraction 33 thus deducing the existence of outer space 34 Alhazen argued the importance of forming questions and subsequently testing them How does light travel through transparent bodies Light travels through transparent bodies in straight lines only We have explained this exhaustively in our Book of Optics g But let us now mention something to prove this convincingly the fact that light travels in straight lines is clearly observed in the lights which enter into dark rooms through holes T he entering light will be clearly observable in the dust which fills the air 37 He demonstrated his conjecture that light travels through transparent bodies in straight lines only by placing a straight stick or a taut thread next to the light beam as quoted in Sambursky 1975 p 136 to prove that light travels in a straight line David Hockney cites Alhazen several times as the likely source for the portraiture technique using the camera obscura which Hockney rediscovered with the aid of an optical suggestion from Charles M Falco Kitab al Manazir which is Alhazen s Book of Optics at that time denoted Opticae Thesaurus Alhazen Arabis was translated from Arabic into Latin for European use as early as 1270 Hockney cites Friedrich Risner s 1572 Basle edition of Opticae Thesaurus Hockney quotes Alhazen as the first clear description of the camera obscura 35 Distancing oneself from the problem is one technique for solving problems 32 References Newton Issac 1999 1726 3rd ed Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy The Principia Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Translated by Cohen I Bernard Whitman Anne Budenz Julia Includes A Guide to Newton s Principia by I Bernard Cohen pp 1 370 The Principia itself is on pp 371 946 Berkeley CA University of California Press 791 796 Rules of Reasoning in Philosophy see also Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica Rules of Reason ISBN 978 0 520 08817 7 scientific method Oxford Dictionaries British and World English 2016 archived from the original on 2016 06 20 retrieved 2016 05 28 Oxford English Dictionary 3rd ed Oxford Oxford University Press 2014 Archived from the original on 2023 11 29 Retrieved 2018 05 31 via OED Online a b Peirce Charles Sanders 1908 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God Hibbert Journal 7 90 112 via Wikisource with added notes Reprinted with previously unpublished part Collected Papers v 6 paragraphs 452 85 The Essential Peirce v 2 pp 434 450 and elsewhere N B 435 30 living institution Hibbert J mis transcribed living institution constitution for institution Popper 1959 p 273 Smith 2001b Book I 6 54 pp 372 408 a b Gauch 2003 p 3 The scientific method is often misrepresented as a fixed sequence of steps rather than being seen for what it truly is a highly variable and creative process AAAS 2000 18 The claim here is that science has general principles that must be mastered to increase productivity and enhance perspective not that these principles provide a simple and automated sequence of steps to follow a b Gauch 2003 p 3 a b William Whewell History of Inductive Science 1837 and in Philosophy of Inductive Science 1840 Inwood Stephen 2003 The Forgotten Genius The biography of Robert Hooke 1635 1703 San Francisco MacAdam Cage Pub pp 112 116 ISBN 978 1 931561 56 3 OCLC 53006741 Hooke Robert 1705 First general The present state of natural philosophy and wherein it is deficient In Waller Richard ed The posthumous works of Robert Hooke M D S R S Geom Prof Gresh etc a b c d Thurs 2011 a b Achinstein Peter 2004 General Introduction Science Rules A Historical Introduction to Scientific Methods Johns Hopkins University Press pp 1 5 ISBN 978 0 8018 7943 2 a b Cowles 2020 p 264 Popper 1963 Conjectures and Refutations PDF pp 312 365 Archived from the original PDF on 2017 10 13 claims that Trial and error is a universal method a b c d e Tow David Hunter 11 September 2010 The Future of Life A Unified Theory of Evolution Future of Life Series Future of Life Media published 2010 p 262 Retrieved 2016 12 11 On further examination however the scientific method bears a striking similarity to the larger process of evolution itself Of great significance is the evolutionary algorithm which uses a simplified subset of the process of natural evolution applied to find the solution to problems that are too complex to solve by traditional analytic methods In essence it is a process of accelerated and rigorous trial and error building on previous knowledge to refine an existing hypothesis or discarding it altogether to find a better model The evolutionary algorithm is a technique derived from the evolution of knowledge processing applied within the context of science and technology itself an outcome of evolution The scientific method continues to evolve through adaptive reward trial and error and application of the method to itself a b c Peirce Charles S 1899 F R L First Rule of Logic Collected Papers v 1 paragraphs 135 140 Archived from the original on 2012 01 06 Retrieved 2012 01 06 in order to learn one must desire to learn a b c Peirce Charles S 1902 Carnegie application see MS L75 329330 from Draft D Archived 2011 05 24 at the Wayback Machine of Memoir 27 Consequently to discover is simply to expedite an event that would occur sooner or later if we had not troubled ourselves to make the discovery Consequently the art of discovery is purely a question of economics The economics of research is so far as logic is concerned the leading doctrine concerning the art of discovery Consequently the conduct of abduction which is chiefly a question of heuretic and is the first question of heuretic is to be governed by economical considerations a b Peirce Charles S Carnegie application L75 1902 New Elements of Mathematics v 4 pp 37 38 For it is not sufficient that a hypothesis should be a justifiable one Any hypothesis that explains the facts is justified critically But among justifiable hypotheses we have to select that one which is suitable for being tested by experiment a b Steven Strogatz THE JOY OF WHY 1 Feb 2024 What Makes for Good Mathematics An interview of Terence Tao a b McElheny 2004 p 52 Friday January 30 1953 Tea time Franklin confronts Watson and his paper Of course it Pauling s pre print is wrong DNA is not a helix However Watson then visits Wilkins office sees photo 51 and immediately recognizes the diffraction pattern of a helical structure But additional questions remained requiring additional iterations of their research For example the number of strands in the backbone of the helix Crick suspected 2 strands but cautioned Watson to examine that more critically the location of the base pairs inside the backbone or outside the backbone etc One key point was that they realized that the quickest way to reach a result was not to continue a mathematical analysis but to build a physical model Later that evening Watson urges Wilkins to begin model building immediately But Wilkins agrees to do so only after Franklin s departure a b Cynthia Wolberger 2021 Photograph 51 explained a b c McElheny 2004 pp 57 59 Saturday February 28 1953 Watson found the base pairing mechanism which explained Chargaff s rules using his cardboard models Smolin Lee May 2013 There is No Scientific Method Archived from the original on 2016 08 07 Retrieved 2016 06 07 Thurs Daniel P 2015 That the scientific method accurately reflects what scientists actually do in Numbers Ronald L Kampourakis Kostas eds Newton s Apple and Other Myths about Science Harvard University Press pp 210 218 ISBN 978 0 674 91547 3 archived from the original on 2023 11 29 retrieved 2020 10 20 It s probably best to get the bad news out of the way first the so called scientific method is a myth If typical formulations were accurate the only location true science would be taking place in would be grade school classrooms a b Mark Snyder 1984 When Belief Creates Reality Archived 2021 08 24 at the Wayback Machine Advances in Experimental Social Psychology Volume 18 1984 Pages 247 305 a b Taleb 2007 p 72 lists ways to avoid the narrative fallacy and confirmation bias the narrative fallacy being a substitute for explanation Nola Robert Sankey Howard 2007 Theories of Scientific Method An Introduction Philosophy and science Vol 2 Montreal McGill Queen s University Press pp 1 300 doi 10 4324 9781315711959 ISBN 9780773533448 OCLC 144602109 There is a large core of people who think there is such a thing as a scientific method that can be justified although not all agree as to what this might be But there are also a growing number of people who think that there is no method to be justified For some the whole idea is yesteryear s debate the continuation of which can be summed up as yet more of the proverbial flogging a dead horse We beg to differ We shall claim that Feyerabend did endorse various scientific values did accept rules of method on a certain understanding of what these are and did attempt to justify them using a meta methodology somewhat akin to the principle of reflective equilibrium Staddon John 16 September 2020 Staddon John Sep 2020 Whatever Happened to History of Science PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2021 08 27 Retrieved 2021 08 27 a b Galileo Galilei 1638 a b Philosophy i e physics is written in this grand book I mean the universe which stands continually open to our gaze but it cannot be understood unless one first learns to comprehend the language and interpret the characters in which it is written It is written in the language of mathematics and its characters are triangles circles and other geometrical figures without which it is humanly impossible to understand a single word of it without these one is wandering around in a dark labyrinth Galileo Galilei Il Saggiatore The Assayer 1623 as translated by Stillman Drake 1957 Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo pp 237 238 as quoted by di Francia 1981 p 10 a b c d e Peirce Charles Sanders 1877 How to Make Our Ideas Clear Popular Science Monthly 12 286 302 via Wikisource Alhacen c 1035 Treatise on Light رسالة في الضوء as cited in Shmuel Sambursky ed 1975 Physical thought from the Presocratics to the quantum physicists an anthology p 137 a b Smith 2010 Book 7 4 28 p 270 a b c Hockney 2006 p 240 Truth is sought for its own sake And those who are engaged upon the quest for anything for its own sake are not interested in other things Finding the truth is difficult and the road to it is rough Alhazen Ibn Al Haytham 965 c 1040 Critique of Ptolemy translated by S Pines Actes X Congres internationale d histoire des sciences Vol I Ithaca 1962 as quoted in Sambursky 1975 p 139 This quotation is from Alhazen s critique of Ptolemy s books Almagest Planetary Hypotheses and Ptolemy s Theory of Visual Perception An English Translation of the Optics Translated by A Mark Smith American Philosophical Society 1996 ISBN 9780871698629 Archived from the original on 2023 11 29 Retrieved 2021 11 27 Elizabeth Asmis 1985 Epicurus Scientific Method Cornell University Press Alhazen Treatise on Light رسالة في الضوء translated into English from German by M Schwarz from Abhandlung uber das Licht Archived 2019 12 30 at the Wayback Machine J Baarmann editor and translator from Arabic to German 1882 Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenlandischen Gesellschaft Vol 36 as quoted in Sambursky 1975 p 136 Alikuzai 2013 p 154 Rozhanskaya amp Levinova 1996 various papers PDF The optics of Giovan Battista della Porta 1535 1615 A Reassessment Workshop at Technical University of Berlin 24 25 October 2014 Archived from the original PDF on 2018 05 27 Kepler Johannes 1604 Ad Vitellionem paralipomena quibus astronomiae pars opticae traditur Supplements to Witelo in which the optical part of astronomy is treated h as cited in Smith A Mark June 2004 What Is the History of Medieval Optics Really about Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 148 2 180 194 JSTOR 1558283 PMID 15338543 Sanches 1988 Godfrey Smith 2003 p 236 Gauch 2003 p xv The thesis of this book as outlined in Chapter One is that there are general principles applicable to all the sciences Maribel Fernandez Dec 2007 Unification Algorithms Lindberg 2007 pp 2 3 There is a danger that must be avoided If we wish to do justice to the historical enterprise we must take the past for what it was And that means we must resist the temptation to scour the past for examples or precursors of modern science My concern will be with the beginnings of scientific theories the methods by which they were formulated and the uses to which they were put Godfrey Smith Peter 2009 Theory and Reality An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 30062 7 Archived from the original on 2023 11 29 Retrieved 2020 05 09 a b Brody 1993 p 10 calls this an epistemic cycle these cycles can occur at high levels of abstraction a b Peirce Charles Sanders 1877 The Fixation of Belief Popular Science Monthly 12 1 15 via Wikisource Peirce Charles S Collected Papers v 5 in paragraph 582 from 1898 rational inquiry of every type fully carried out has the vital power of self correction and of growth This is a property so deeply saturating its inmost nature that it may truly be said that there is but one thing needful for learning the truth and that is a hearty and active desire to learn what is true Einstein amp Infeld 1938 p 92 To raise new questions new possibilities to regard old problems from a new angle requires creative imagination and marks real advance in science Crawford S Stucki L 1990 Peer review and the changing research record Journal of the American Society for Information Science 41 3 223 228 doi 10 1002 SICI 1097 4571 199004 41 3 lt 223 AID ASI14 gt 3 0 CO 2 3 Gauch 2003 esp chapters 5 8 Rene Descartes 1637 Discourse on the Method Part 2 Archived 2021 09 01 at the Wayback Machine Part II McCarty 1985 p 252 McElheny 2004 p 34 Schuster Daniel P Powers William J eds 2005 Ch 1 Translational and Experimental Clinical Research Lippincott Williams amp Wilkins ISBN 9780781755658 Archived from the original on 2023 11 29 Retrieved 2021 11 27 This chapter also discusses the different types of research questions and how they are produced ESO Telescope Sees Star Dance Around Supermassive Black Hole Proves Einstein Right Science Release European Southern Observatory 16 April 2020 Archived from the original on 2020 05 15 Retrieved 2020 04 17 Andreas Vesalius Epistola Rationem Modumque Propinandi Radicis Chynae Decocti 1546 p 141 Quoted and translated in C D O Malley Andreas Vesalius of Brussels 1964 p 116 As quoted by Bynum amp Porter 2005 p 597 Andreas Vesalius a b c d MacKay Donald M 1969 Information Mechanism and Meaning Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 1 4 ISBN 0 262 63032 X Invariably one came up against fundamental physical limits to the accuracy of measurement The art of physical measurement seemed to be a matter of compromise of choosing between reciprocally related uncertainties Multiplying together the conjugate pairs of uncertainty limits mentioned however I found that they formed invariant products of not one but two distinct kinds The first group of limits were calculable a priori from a specification of the instrument The second group could be calculated only a posteriori from a specification of what was done with the instrument In the first case each unit of information would add one additional dimension conceptual category whereas in the second each unit would add one additional atomic fact Crick Francis 1994 The Astonishing Hypothesis ISBN 0 684 19431 7 p 20 McElheny 2004 p 40 October 1951 That s what a helix should look like Crick exclaimed in delight This is the Cochran Crick Vand Stokes theory of the transform of a helix Judson 1979 p 157 The structure that we propose is a three chain structure each chain being a helix Linus Pauling McElheny 2004 pp 49 50 January 28 1953 Watson read Pauling s pre print and realized that in Pauling s model DNA s phosphate groups had to be un ionized But DNA is an acid which contradicts Pauling s model Einstein Albert 1949 The World as I See It New York Philosophical Library pp 24 28 Dewey 1910 p 26 Aristotle trans 1853 Prior Analytics 2 25 Archived 2021 09 10 at the Wayback Machine via Wikisource Glen 1994 pp 37 38 Platt John R 16 October 1964 Strong Inference Science 146 3642 347 Bibcode 1964Sci 146 347P doi 10 1126 science 146 3642 347 PMID 17739513 Judson 1979 pp 137 138 Watson did enough work on Tobacco mosaic virus to produce the diffraction pattern for a helix per Crick s work on the transform of a helix McElheny 2004 p 43 June 1952 Watson had succeeded in getting X ray pictures of TMV showing a diffraction pattern consistent with the transform of a helix Cochran W Crick FHC and Vand V 1952 The Structure of Synthetic Polypeptides I The Transform of Atoms on a Helix Acta Crystallogr 5 581 586 McElheny 2004 p 68 Nature April 25 1953 In March 1917 the Royal Astronomical Society announced that on May 29 1919 the occasion of a total eclipse of the sun would afford favorable conditions for testing Einstein s General theory of relativity One expedition to Sobral Ceara Brazil and Eddington s expedition to the island of Principe yielded a set of photographs which when compared to photographs taken at Sobral and at Greenwich Observatory showed that the deviation of light was measured to be 1 69 arc seconds as compared to Einstein s desk prediction of 1 75 arc seconds Antonina Vallentin 1954 Einstein as quoted by Samuel Rapport and Helen Wright 1965 Physics New York Washington Square Press pp 294 295 The Secret of Photo 51 NOVA PBS Archived from the original on 2017 08 31 Retrieved 2017 09 11 Watson 1968 p 167 The instant I saw the picture my mouth fell open and my pulse began to race Page 168 shows the X shaped pattern of the B form of DNA clearly indicating crucial details of its helical structure to Watson and Crick Mill John Stuart A System of Logic University Press of the Pacific Honolulu 2002 ISBN 1 4102 0252 6 National Science Foundation NSF 2021 NSF Reports Archived 2021 08 17 at the Wayback Machine and News Archived 2021 08 20 at the Wayback Machine LHC long term schedule lhc commissioning web cern ch Archived from the original on 2020 04 25 Retrieved 2021 08 22 2021 ligo caltech edu 1999 Laser Interferometer Gravitational Wave Observatory Archived from the original on 2021 09 01 Retrieved 2021 08 30 NIF 2021 What Is the National Ignition Facility Archived from the original on 2017 07 31 Retrieved 2021 08 22 ISS 2021 International Space Station 12 January 2015 Archived from the original on 2005 09 07 Retrieved 2021 08 22 JWST 2021 WEBB Space Telescope Archived from the original on 2012 01 04 Retrieved 2021 08 22 James Webb Space Telescope JWST 12 Nov 2021 James Webb Space Telescope Deployment Sequence Nominal Archived 2021 12 23 at the Wayback Machine highlights the predictions from launch to day 29 a b James 2003 Complex Systems Theory PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2021 04 18 Retrieved 2018 05 27 al Battani De Motu Stellarum translation from Arabic to Latin in 1116 as cited by E S Kennedy A Survey of Islamic Astronomical Tables Transactions of the American Philosophical Society New Series 46 2 Philadelphia 1956 pp 10 11 32 34 a b Smith 2001b Smith 2001b Book I 6 86 p 379 Smith 2010 p 220 Book Seven covers refraction McElheny 2004 p 53 The weekend January 31 February 1 After seeing photo 51 Watson informed Bragg of the X ray diffraction image of DNA in B form Bragg permitted them to restart their research on DNA that is model building McElheny 2004 p 54 Sunday February 8 1953 Maurice Wilkes gave Watson and Crick permission to work on models as Wilkes would not be building models until Franklin left DNA research McElheny 2004 p 56 Jerry Donohue on sabbatical from Pauling s lab and visiting Cambridge advises Watson that the textbook form of the base pairs was incorrect for DNA base pairs rather the keto form of the base pairs should be used instead This form allowed the bases hydrogen bonds to pair unlike with unlike rather than to pair like with like as Watson was inclined to model based on the textbook statements On February 27 1953 Watson was convinced enough to make cardboard models of the nucleotides in their keto form Watson 1968 pp 194 197 Suddenly I became aware that an adenine thymine pair held together by two hydrogen bonds was identical in shape to a guanine cytosine pair held together by at least two hydrogen bonds McElheny 2004 p 57 Saturday February 28 1953 Watson tried like with like and admitted these base pairs didn t have hydrogen bonds that line up But after trying unlike with unlike and getting Jerry Donohue s approval the base pairs turned out to be identical in shape as Watson stated above in his 1968 Double Helix memoir quoted above Watson now felt confident enough to inform Crick Of course unlike with unlike increases the number of possible codons if this scheme were a genetic code Goldstein Bernard R 1977 Ibn Mu adh s 1079 Treatise On Twilight and the Height of the Atmosphere Archived 2022 09 21 at the Wayback Machine Archive for History of Exact Sciences Vol 17 No 2 21 VII 1977 pp 97 118 22 pages JSTOR Treatise On Twilight was printed by F Risner in Opticae Thesaurus 1572 as Liber de crepusculis but attributed to Alhazen rather than Ibn Mu adh Krider E Philip January 2006 Benjamin Franklin and lightning rods Physics Today 59 1 42 Bibcode 2006PhT 59a 42K doi 10 1063 1 2180176 S2CID 110623159 On 6 August 1753 the Swedish scientist Georg Wilhelm Richmann was electrocuted in St Petersburg Reconstruction of Galileo Galilei s experiment the inclined plane PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2014 04 29 Retrieved 2014 04 28 Ioannidis John P A August 2005 Why most published research findings are false PLOS Medicine 2 8 e124 doi 10 1371 journal pmed 0020124 PMC 1182327 PMID 16060722 Fleck 1979 pp xxvii xxviii NIH Data Sharing Policy Archived 2012 05 13 at the Wayback Machine Stanovich Keith E 2007 How to Think Straight About Psychology Boston Pearson Education p 123 a b Brody 1993 pp 44 45 a b Goldhaber amp Nieto 2010 p 942 Hall B K Hallgrimsson B eds 2008 Strickberger s Evolution 4th ed Jones amp Bartlett p 762 ISBN 978 0 7637 0066 9 Cracraft J Donoghue M J eds 2005 Assembling the tree of life Oxford University Press p 592 ISBN 978 0 19 517234 8 Archived from the original on 2023 11 29 Retrieved 2020 10 20 Needham amp Wang 1954 p 166 shows how the flying gallop image propagated from China to the West Goldhaber amp Nieto 2010 p 940 Ronald R Sims 2003 Ethics and corporate social responsibility Why giants fall p 21 A myth is a belief given uncritical acceptance by members of a group Weiss Business Ethics p 15 Lakatos 1976 pp 1 19 Aristotle 1938 Prior Analytics Aristotle Volume 1 Loeb Classical Library Translated by Hugh Tredennick London William Heinemann pp 181 531 Ketner Kenneth Laine 2009 Charles Sanders Peirce Interdisciplinary Scientist The Logic of Interdisciplinarity By Peirce Charles S Bisanz Elize ed Berlin Akademie Verlag Peirce Charles S October 1905 Issues of Pragmaticism The Monist Vol XV no 4 pp 481 499 see p 484 and p 491 Reprinted in Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 438 463 see 443 and 451 Brown C 2005 Overcoming Barriers to Use of Promising Research Among Elite Middle East Policy Groups Journal of Social Behaviour and Personality Select Press David Mermin September 1994 A Virtuosically Adaptive System As Seen By A Marginally Adaptive One Review of The Quark and the Jaguar by Murray Gell Mann 1994 Physics Today 47 9 89 doi 10 1063 1 2808634 Murray Gell Mann 11 May 2016 What theQuark and Jaguaris about Archived from the original on 2021 12 11 via Youtube Poppele RE Bowman RJ January 1970 Quantitative description of linear behavior of mammalian muscle spindles Journal of Neurophysiology 33 1 59 72 doi 10 1152 jn 1970 33 1 59 PMID 4243791 Blum KP Lamotte D Incamps B Zytnicki D Ting LH September 2017 Ayers J ed Force encoding in muscle spindles during stretch of passive muscle PLOS Computational Biology 13 9 e1005767 Bibcode 2017PLSCB 13E5767B doi 10 1371 journal pcbi 1005767 PMC 5634630 PMID 28945740 Anderson Chris 2008 The End of Theory The Data Deluge Makes the Scientific Method Obsolete Archived 2021 05 02 at the Wayback Machine Wired Magazine 16 07 Ludwik Fleck 1979 Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact Archived 2021 08 26 at the Wayback Machine a b Einstein Albert 1936 1956 One may say the eternal mystery of the world is its comprehensibility From the article Physics and Reality 1936 reprinted in Out of My Later Years 1956 It is one of the great realizations of Immanuel Kant that the setting up of a real external world would be senseless without this comprehensibility Hanson Norwood 1958 Patterns of Discovery Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 05197 2 Kuhn Thomas S 2009 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Chicago IL University of Chicago Press p 113 ISBN 978 1 4432 5544 8 Feyerabend Paul K 1960 Patterns of Discovery The Philosophical Review 1960 vol 69 2 pp 247 252 Feyerabend Paul K Against Method Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge 1st published 1975 Reprinted Verso London 1978 For example Higher Superstition The Academic Left and Its Quarrels with Science The Johns Hopkins University Press 1997 Fashionable Nonsense Postmodern Intellectuals Abuse of Science Picador 1999 The Sokal Hoax The Sham That Shook the Academy University of Nebraska Press 2000 ISBN 0 8032 7995 7 A House Built on Sand Exposing Postmodernist Myths About Science Oxford University Press 2000 Intellectual Impostures Economist Books 2003 Knorr Cetina K 1999 Epistemic cultures how the sciences make knowledge Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 25893 8 OCLC 39539508 As cited in Fleck 1979 p 27 Fleck 1979 pp 38 50 Fleck 1979 p xxviii Fleck 1979 p 27 Polya 1957 p 131 in the section on Modern heuristic When we are working intensively we feel keenly the progress of our work we are elated when our progress is rapid we are depressed when it is slow If you can t solve a problem then there is an easier problem you can solve find it Polya 1957 p 114 George Polya 1954 Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning Volume I Induction and Analogy in Mathematics George Polya 1954 Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning Volume II Patterns of Plausible Reasoning Polya 1957 p 142 Polya 1957 p 144 Lakatos 1976 documents the development by generations of mathematicians of Euler s formula for polyhedra H S M Coxeter 1973 Regular Polytopes ISBN 9780486614809 Chapter IX Poincare s proof of Euler s formula Charles A Weibel ca 1995 History of Homological Algebra PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2021 09 06 Retrieved 2021 08 28 Henri Poincare Sur l analysis situs Comptes rendusde l Academie des Sciences 115 1892 633 636 as cited by Lakatos 1976 p 162 John Stillwell reviewer Apr 2014 Notices of the AMS 61 4 pp 378 383 on Jeremy Gray s 2013 Henri Poincare A Scientific Biography PDF Archived 2021 07 04 at the Wayback Machine Lakatos 1976 p 55 Mackay 1991 p 100 Ioannidis John P A 1 August 2005 Why Most Published Research Findings Are False PLOS Medicine 2 8 e124 doi 10 1371 journal pmed 0020124 ISSN 1549 1277 PMC 1182327 PMID 16060722 Schaefer Carl F May 1984 Regarding the Misuse of t Tests Anesthesiology 60 5 505 doi 10 1097 00000542 198405000 00026 PMID 6711862 Archived from the original on 2021 08 29 Retrieved 2021 08 29 a b c Dunbar K amp Fugelsang J 2005 Causal thinking in science How scientists and students interpret the unexpected In M E Gorman R D Tweney D Gooding amp A Kincannon Eds Scientific and Technical Thinking pp 57 79 Mahwah NJ Lawrence Erlbaum Associates a b Oliver J E 1991 Ch 2 The incomplete guide to the art of discovery New York Columbia University Press ISBN 9780231076203 Taleb Nassim N Antifragility or The Property Of Disorder Loving Systems Archived from the original on 2013 05 07 SourcesRozhanskaya Mariam Levinova I S 1996 Statics In Rushdi Rashid ed Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science Psychology Press pp 274 298 ISBN 978 0 415 12411 9 Alikuzai Hamid Wahed 2013 A Concise History of Afghanistan in 25 Volumes Vol 1 Trafford Publishing ISBN 978 1 4907 1446 2 Archived from the original on 2023 11 29 Retrieved 2023 06 03 Born Max 1949 Natural Philosophy of Cause and Chance Peter Smith also published by Dover 1964 From the Waynflete Lectures 1948 On the web N B the web version does not have the 3 addenda by Born 1950 1964 in which he notes that all knowledge is subjective Born then proposes a solution in Appendix 3 1964 Brody Thomas A 1993 Luis de la Pena Peter E Hodgson eds The Philosophy Behind Physics Berlin New York Springer Verlag ISBN 978 0 387 55914 8 archived from the original on 2023 11 29 retrieved 2020 05 09 Bruno Leonard C 1989 The Landmarks of Science Facts on File ISBN 978 0 8160 2137 6 Bynum W F Porter Roy 2005 Oxford Dictionary of Scientific Quotations Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 858409 4 Cowles Henry M 2020 The Scientific Method An Evolution of Thinking from Darwin to Dewey Cambridge MA Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674976191 Reviewed in Riskin Jessica 2 July 2020 Just Use Your Thinking Pump The New York Review of Books Vol LXVII no 11 pp 48 50 Archived from the original on 2020 06 24 Retrieved 2020 06 24 Dales Richard C 1973 The Scientific Achievement of the Middle Ages The Middle Ages Series University of Pennsylvania Press ISBN 978 0 8122 1057 6 Dewey John 1910 How we think Boston D C Heath and Company OCLC 194219 Public domain in the US 236 pages di Francia G Toraldo 1981 The Investigation of the Physical World Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 29925 1 Einstein Albert Infeld Leopold 1938 The Evolution of Physics from early concepts to relativity and quanta New York Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 0 671 20156 2 Feynman Richard 1965 The Character of Physical Law Cambridge M I T Press ISBN 978 0 262 56003 0 Fleck Ludwik 1979 Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact Univ of Chicago ISBN 978 0 226 25325 1 written in German 1935 Entstehung und Entwickelung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache Einfuhrung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollectiv English translation by Thaddeus J Trenn and Fred Bradley 1979 Archived 2023 04 06 at the Wayback Machine Edited by Thaddeus J Trenn and Robert K Merton Foreword by Robert K Merton Galileo Galilei 1638 Discorsi e Dimonstrazioni Matematiche intorno a due nuoue scienze Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Relating to Two New Sciences in Italian and Latin Leiden House of Elzevir English translation Galileo Galilei 2003 1914 by Macmillan Dialogues concerning two new sciences Translated by Henry Crew amp Alfonso de Salvio reprint ed New York Dover ISBN 978 0 486 60099 4 Additional publication information is from the collection of first editions of the Library of Congress surveyed by Bruno 1989 pp 261 264 Gauch Hugh G Jr 2003 Scientific Method in Practice Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 01708 4 archived from the original on 2023 11 29 retrieved 2020 05 09 Glen William ed 1994 The Mass Extinction Debates How Science Works in a Crisis Stanford CA Stanford University Press ISBN 978 0 8047 2285 8 Godfrey Smith Peter 2003 Theory and Reality An introduction to the philosophy of science University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 30063 4 Goldhaber Alfred Scharff Nieto Michael Martin January March 2010 Photon and graviton mass limits Rev Mod Phys 82 1 939 979 arXiv 0809 1003 Bibcode 2010RvMP 82 939G doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 82 939 S2CID 14395472 Hockney David 2006 Secret Knowledge rediscovering the lost techniques of the old masters expanded ed Penguin Publishing ISBN 0 14 200512 6 Jevons William Stanley 1874 The Principles of Science A Treatise on Logic and Scientific Method Dover Publications ISBN 978 1 4304 8775 3 1877 1879 Reprinted with a foreword by Ernst Nagel New York 1958 Judson Horace Freeland 1979 The Eighth Day of Creation Simon and Schuster ISBN 0 671 22540 5 Kuhn Thomas S 1961 The Function of Measurement in Modern Physical Science Isis 52 2 161 193 doi 10 1086 349468 JSTOR 228678 S2CID 144294881 Lakatos Imre 1976 John Worrall Elie Zahar eds Proofs and Refutations Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 29038 8 Lindberg David C 2007 The Beginnings of Western Science University of Chicago Press 2nd edition 2007 Mackay Alan L ed 1991 Dictionary of Scientific Quotations London IOP Publishing Ltd ISBN 978 0 7503 0106 0 McCarty Maclyn 1985 The Transforming Principle Discovering that genes are made of DNA New York W W Norton ISBN 978 0 393 30450 3 Memoir of a researcher in the Avery MacLeod McCarty experiment McElheny Victor K 2004 Watson amp DNA Making a scientific revolution Basic Books ISBN 978 0 7382 0866 4 Moulton Forest Ray Schifferes Justus J eds 1960 The Autobiography of Science 2nd ed Doubleday Needham Joseph Wang Ling 王玲 1954 Science and Civilisation in ChinaVol 1 Introductory Orientations Cambridge University Press Newton Isaac 1999 1687 1713 1726 Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 08817 7 Third edition From I Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman s 1999 translation Orsted Hans Christian 1997 Selected Scientific Works of Hans Christian Orsted Princeton ISBN 978 0 691 04334 0 Translated to English by Karen Jelved Andrew D Jackson and Ole Knudsen translators 1997 Peirce C S see Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography Poincare Henri 1905 Science and Hypothesis London Walter Scott Publishing archived from the original on 2007 09 29 retrieved 2007 08 01 via The Mead Project Polya George 1957 How to Solve It 2nd ed Princeton University Press OCLC 4140462 Polya George 2009 Reprint Ishi Press International ISBN 978 4 87187 830 2 OCLC 706968824 Popper Karl R 1959 1934 The Logic of Scientific Discovery English ed Popper Karl R 1963 Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge Routledge ISBN 0 415 28594 1 Popper Karl R 2005 1959 English ed The Logic of Scientific Discovery PDF Taylor amp Francis e Library ISBN 0 203 99462 0 archived from the original PDF on 2013 07 22 Sambursky Shmuel ed 1975 Physical Thought from the Presocratics to the Quantum Physicists Pica Press ISBN 978 0 87663 712 8 Reviewed in Hoffmann Banesh 1976 Because it s there Man s struggle to understand Nature Physics Today 29 2 51 53 Bibcode 1976PhT 29b 51S doi 10 1063 1 3023315 Sanches Francisco 1988 1581 Limbrick Elaine Thomson Douglas eds That Nothing is Known Quod nihil scitur Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 35077 8 OCLC 462156333 Critical edition Smith A Mark 2001a Alhacen s Theory of Visual Perception A Critical Edition with English Translation and Commentary of the First Three Books of Alhacen s De aspectibus the Medieval Latin Version of Ibn al Haytham s Kitab al Manaẓir Volume One Introduction and Latin text Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 91 4 1 337 doi 10 2307 3657358 JSTOR 3657358 Smith A Mark 2001b Alhacen s Theory of Visual Perception A Critical Edition with English Translation and Commentary of the First Three Books of Alhacen s De aspectibus the Medieval Latin Version of Ibn al Haytham s Kitab al Manaẓir Volume Two English translation Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 91 5 339 819 doi 10 2307 3657357 JSTOR 3657357 Smith A Mark 2010 ALHACEN ON REFRACTION A Critical Edition with English Translation and Commentary of Book 7 of Alhacen s De Aspectibus Volume One Introduction and Latin Text Volume Two English Translation Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 100 3 JSTOR 20787647 Thurs Daniel 2011 12 Scientific Methods In Shank Michael Numbers Ronald Harrison Peter eds Wrestling with Nature From Omens to Science Chicago University of Chicago Press pp 307 336 ISBN 978 0 226 31783 0 Taleb Nassim Nicholas 2007 The Black Swan Random House ISBN 978 1 4000 6351 2 Voelkel James R 2001 Johannes Kepler and the New Astronomy Oxford University Press Watson James D 1968 The Double Helix New York Atheneum Library of Congress card number 68 16217 Further readingBauer Henry H Scientific Literacy and the Myth of the Scientific Method University of Illinois Press Champaign IL 1992 Beveridge William I B The Art of Scientific Investigation Heinemann Melbourne Australia 1950 Bernstein Richard J Beyond Objectivism and Relativism Science Hermeneutics and Praxis University of Pennsylvania Press Philadelphia PA 1983 Brody Baruch A and Capaldi Nicholas Science Men Methods Goals A Reader Methods of Physical Science Archived 2023 04 13 at the Wayback Machine W A Benjamin 1968 Brody Baruch A and Grandy Richard E Readings in the Philosophy of Science 2nd edition Prentice Hall Englewood Cliffs NJ 1989 Burks Arthur W Chance Cause Reason An Inquiry into the Nature of Scientific Evidence University of Chicago Press Chicago IL 1977 Chalmers Alan What Is This Thing Called Science Queensland University Press and Open University Press 1976 Crick Francis 1988 What Mad Pursuit A Personal View of Scientific Discovery New York Basic Books ISBN 978 0 465 09137 9 Crombie A C 1953 Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100 1700 Oxford Clarendon Earman John ed Inference Explanation and Other Frustrations Essays in the Philosophy of Science University of California Press Berkeley amp Los Angeles CA 1992 Fraassen Bas C van The Scientific Image Oxford University Press Oxford 1980 Franklin James 2009 What Science Knows And How It Knows It New York Encounter Books ISBN 978 1 59403 207 3 Gadamer Hans Georg Reason in the Age of Science Frederick G Lawrence trans MIT Press Cambridge MA 1981 Giere Ronald N ed Cognitive Models of Science vol 15 in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science University of Minnesota Press Minneapolis MN 1992 Hacking Ian Representing and Intervening Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1983 Heisenberg Werner Physics and Beyond Encounters and Conversations A J Pomerans trans Harper and Row New York 1971 pp 63 64 Holton Gerald Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought Kepler to Einstein 1st edition 1973 revised edition Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1988 Karin Knorr Cetina Knorr Cetina Karin 1999 Epistemic cultures how the sciences make knowledge Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 25894 5 Kuhn Thomas S The Essential Tension Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change University of Chicago Press Chicago IL 1977 Latour Bruno Science in Action How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1987 Losee John A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Oxford University Press Oxford 1972 2nd edition 1980 Maxwell Nicholas The Comprehensibility of the Universe A New Conception of Science Oxford University Press Oxford 1998 Paperback 2003 Maxwell Nicholas Understanding Scientific Progress Archived 2018 02 20 at the Wayback Machine Paragon House St Paul Minnesota 2017 McComas William F ed 1998 The Principal Elements of the Nature of Science Dispelling the Myths PDF The Nature of Science in Science Education Netherlands Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 53 70 Archived from the original PDF on 2014 07 01 Misak Cheryl J Truth and the End of Inquiry A Peircean Account of Truth Oxford University Press Oxford 1991 Oreskes Naomi Masked Confusion A trusted source of health information misleads the public by prioritizing rigor over reality Scientific American vol 329 no 4 November 2023 pp 90 91 Piattelli Palmarini Massimo ed Language and Learning The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1980 Popper Karl R Unended Quest An Intellectual Autobiography Open Court La Salle IL 1982 Putnam Hilary Renewing Philosophy Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1992 Rorty Richard Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature Princeton University Press Princeton NJ 1979 Salmon Wesley C Four Decades of Scientific Explanation University of Minnesota Press Minneapolis MN 1990 Shimony Abner Search for a Naturalistic World View Vol 1 Scientific Method and Epistemology Vol 2 Natural Science and Metaphysics Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1993 Thagard Paul Conceptual Revolutions Princeton University Press Princeton NJ 1992 Ziman John 2000 Real Science what it is and what it means Cambridge Cambridge University Press External links nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Scientific method nbsp Wikibooks has a book on the topic of The Scientific Method nbsp Wikiversity has learning resources about Thinking Scientifically Andersen Anne Hepburn Brian Scientific Method In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Confirmation and Induction Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Scientific method at PhilPapers Scientific method at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project An Introduction to Science Scientific Thinking and a scientific method Archived 2018 01 01 at the Wayback Machine by Steven D Schafersman Introduction to the scientific method at the University of Rochester The scientific method from a philosophical perspective Theory ladenness by Paul Newall at The Galilean Library Lecture on Scientific Method by Greg Anderson archived 28 April 2006 Using the scientific method for designing science fair projects Scientific Methods an online book by Richard D Jarrard Richard Feynman on the Key to Science one minute three seconds from the Cornell Lectures Lectures on the Scientific Method by Nick Josh Karean Kevin Padian Michael Shermer and Richard Dawkins archived 21 January 2013 How Do We Know What Is True animated video 2 52 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Scientific method amp oldid 1203286379, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.