fbpx
Wikipedia

Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica

Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica (English: The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy)[1] often referred to as simply the Principia (/prɪnˈsɪpiə, prɪnˈkɪpiə/), is a book by Isaac Newton that expounds Newton's laws of motion and his law of universal gravitation. The Principia is written in Latin and comprises three volumes, and was first published on 5 July 1687.[2][3]

Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica
Title page of Principia, first edition (1687)
AuthorSir Isaac Newton
Original titlePhilosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica
LanguageNew Latin
Publication date
1687 (1st ed.)
Published in English
1728
LC ClassQA803 .A53
Original text
Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica at Latin Wikisource
TranslationPhilosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica at Wikisource

The Principia is considered one of the most important works in the history of science.[4] The French mathematical physicist Alexis Clairaut assessed it in 1747: "The famous book of Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy marked the epoch of a great revolution in physics. The method followed by its illustrious author Sir Newton ... spread the light of mathematics on a science which up to then had remained in the darkness of conjectures and hypotheses."[5]

A more recent assessment has been that while acceptance of Newton's laws was not immediate, by the end of the century after publication in 1687, "no one could deny that" (out of the Principia) "a science had emerged that, at least in certain respects, so far exceeded anything that had ever gone before that it stood alone as the ultimate exemplar of science generally".[6]

The Principia forms the foundation of classical mechanics. Among other achievements, it explains Johannes Kepler's laws of planetary motion, which Kepler had first obtained empirically. In formulating his physical laws, Newton developed and used mathematical methods now included in the field of calculus, expressing them in the form of geometric propositions about "vanishingly small" shapes.[7] In a revised conclusion to the Principia (see § General Scholium), Newton emphasized the empirical nature of the work with the expression Hypotheses non fingo ("I frame/feign no hypotheses").[8]

After annotating and correcting his personal copy of the first edition,[9] Newton published two further editions, during 1713[10] with errors of the 1687 corrected, and an improved version[11] of 1726.[10]

Contents

Expressed aim and topics covered

 
Sir Isaac Newton (1643–1727) author of the Principia

The Preface of the work states:[12]

... Rational Mechanics will be the sciences of motion resulting from any forces whatsoever, and of the forces required to produce any motion, accurately proposed and demonstrated ... And therefore we offer this work as mathematical principles of his philosophy. For all the difficulty of philosophy seems to consist in this—from the phenomena of motions to investigate the forces of Nature, and then from these forces to demonstrate the other phenomena ...

The Principia deals primarily with massive bodies in motion, initially under a variety of conditions and hypothetical laws of force in both non-resisting and resisting media, thus offering criteria to decide, by observations, which laws of force are operating in phenomena that may be observed. It attempts to cover hypothetical or possible motions both of celestial bodies and of terrestrial projectiles. It explores difficult problems of motions perturbed by multiple attractive forces. Its third and final book deals with the interpretation of observations about the movements of planets and their satellites.

It:

  • shows how astronomical observations prove the inverse square law of gravitation (to an accuracy that was high by the standards of Newton's time);
  • offers estimates of relative masses for the known giant planets and for the Earth and the Sun;
  • defines the very slow motion of the Sun relative to the solar-system barycenter;
  • shows how the theory of gravity can account for irregularities in the motion of the Moon;
  • identifies the oblateness of the shape of the Earth;
  • accounts approximately for marine tides including phenomena of spring and neap tides by the perturbing (and varying) gravitational attractions of the Sun and Moon on the Earth's waters;
  • explains the precession of the equinoxes as an effect of the gravitational attraction of the Moon on the Earth's equatorial bulge; and
  • gives theoretical basis for numerous phenomena about comets and their elongated, near-parabolic orbits.

The opening sections of the Principia contain, in revised and extended form, nearly[13] all of the content of Newton's 1684 tract De motu corporum in gyrum.

The Principia begin with "Definitions"[14] and "Axioms or Laws of Motion",[15] and continues in three books:

Book 1, De motu corporum

Book 1, subtitled De motu corporum (On the motion of bodies) concerns motion in the absence of any resisting medium. It opens with a collection of mathematical lemmas on "the method of first and last ratios",[16] a geometrical form of infinitesimal calculus.[7]

 
Newton's proof of Kepler's second law, as described in the book. If a continuous centripetal force (red arrow) is considered on the planet during its orbit, the area of the triangles defined by the path of the planet will be the same. This is true for any fixed time interval. When the interval tends to zero, the force can be considered instantaneous. (Click image for a detailed description).

The second section establishes relationships between centripetal forces and the law of areas now known as Kepler's second law (Propositions 1–3),[17] and relates circular velocity and radius of path-curvature to radial force[18] (Proposition 4), and relationships between centripetal forces varying as the inverse-square of the distance to the center and orbits of conic-section form (Propositions 5–10).

Propositions 11–31[19] establish properties of motion in paths of eccentric conic-section form including ellipses, and their relation with inverse-square central forces directed to a focus, and include Newton's theorem about ovals (lemma 28).

Propositions 43–45[20] are demonstration that in an eccentric orbit under centripetal force where the apse may move, a steady non-moving orientation of the line of apses is an indicator of an inverse-square law of force.

Book 1 contains some proofs with little connection to real-world dynamics. But there are also sections with far-reaching application to the solar system and universe:

Propositions 57–69[21] deal with the "motion of bodies drawn to one another by centripetal forces". This section is of primary interest for its application to the Solar System, and includes Proposition 66[22] along with its 22 corollaries:[23] here Newton took the first steps in the definition and study of the problem of the movements of three massive bodies subject to their mutually perturbing gravitational attractions, a problem which later gained name and fame (among other reasons, for its great difficulty) as the three-body problem.

Propositions 70–84[24] deal with the attractive forces of spherical bodies. The section contains Newton's proof that a massive spherically symmetrical body attracts other bodies outside itself as if all its mass were concentrated at its centre. This fundamental result, called the Shell theorem, enables the inverse square law of gravitation to be applied to the real solar system to a very close degree of approximation.

Book 2, part 2 of De motu corporum

Part of the contents originally planned for the first book was divided out into a second book, which largely concerns motion through resisting mediums. Just as Newton examined consequences of different conceivable laws of attraction in Book 1, here he examines different conceivable laws of resistance; thus Section 1 discusses resistance in direct proportion to velocity, and Section 2 goes on to examine the implications of resistance in proportion to the square of velocity. Book 2 also discusses (in Section 5) hydrostatics and the properties of compressible fluids; Newton also derives Boyle's law.[25] The effects of air resistance on pendulums are studied in Section 6, along with Newton's account of experiments that he carried out, to try to find out some characteristics of air resistance in reality by observing the motions of pendulums under different conditions. Newton compares the resistance offered by a medium against motions of globes with different properties (material, weight, size). In Section 8, he derives rules to determine the speed of waves in fluids and relates them to the density and condensation (Proposition 48;[26] this would become very important in acoustics). He assumes that these rules apply equally to light and sound and estimates that the speed of sound is around 1088 feet per second and can increase depending on the amount of water in air.[27]

Less of Book 2 has stood the test of time than of Books 1 and 3, and it has been said that Book 2 was largely written to refute a theory of Descartes which had some wide acceptance before Newton's work (and for some time after). According to Descartes's Cartesian theory of vortices, planetary motions were produced by the whirling of fluid vortices that filled interplanetary space and carried the planets along with them.[28] Newton wrote at the end of Book 2[29] his conclusion that the hypothesis of vortices was completely at odds with the astronomical phenomena, and served not so much to explain as to confuse them.

Book 3, De mundi systemate

Book 3, subtitled De mundi systemate (On the system of the world), is an exposition of many consequences of universal gravitation, especially its consequences for astronomy. It builds upon the propositions of the previous books, and applies them with further specificity than in Book 1 to the motions observed in the Solar System. Here (introduced by Proposition 22,[30] and continuing in Propositions 25–35[31]) are developed several of the features and irregularities of the orbital motion of the Moon, especially the variation. Newton lists the astronomical observations on which he relies,[32] and establishes in a stepwise manner that the inverse square law of mutual gravitation applies to Solar System bodies, starting with the satellites of Jupiter[33] and going on by stages to show that the law is of universal application.[34] He also gives starting at Lemma 4[35] and Proposition 40[36] the theory of the motions of comets, for which much data came from John Flamsteed and Edmond Halley, and accounts for the tides,[37] attempting quantitative estimates of the contributions of the Sun[38] and Moon[39] to the tidal motions; and offers the first theory of the precession of the equinoxes.[40] Book 3 also considers the harmonic oscillator in three dimensions, and motion in arbitrary force laws.

In Book 3 Newton also made clear his heliocentric view of the Solar System, modified in a somewhat modern way, since already in the mid-1680s he recognised the "deviation of the Sun" from the centre of gravity of the Solar System.[41] For Newton, "the common centre of gravity of the Earth, the Sun and all the Planets is to be esteem'd the Centre of the World",[42] and that this centre "either is at rest, or moves uniformly forward in a right line".[43] Newton rejected the second alternative after adopting the position that "the centre of the system of the world is immoveable", which "is acknowledg'd by all, while some contend that the Earth, others, that the Sun is fix'd in that centre".[43] Newton estimated the mass ratios Sun:Jupiter and Sun:Saturn,[44] and pointed out that these put the centre of the Sun usually a little way off the common center of gravity, but only a little, the distance at most "would scarcely amount to one diameter of the Sun".[45]

Commentary on the Principia

The sequence of definitions used in setting up dynamics in the Principia is recognisable in many textbooks today. Newton first set out the definition of mass

The quantity of matter is that which arises conjointly from its density and magnitude. A body twice as dense in double the space is quadruple in quantity. This quantity I designate by the name of body or of mass.

This was then used to define the "quantity of motion" (today called momentum), and the principle of inertia in which mass replaces the previous Cartesian notion of intrinsic force. This then set the stage for the introduction of forces through the change in momentum of a body. Curiously, for today's readers, the exposition looks dimensionally incorrect, since Newton does not introduce the dimension of time in rates of changes of quantities.

He defined space and time "not as they are well known to all". Instead, he defined "true" time and space as "absolute"[46] and explained:

Only I must observe, that the vulgar conceive those quantities under no other notions but from the relation they bear to perceptible objects. And it will be convenient to distinguish them into absolute and relative, true and apparent, mathematical and common. ... instead of absolute places and motions, we use relative ones; and that without any inconvenience in common affairs; but in philosophical discussions, we ought to step back from our senses, and consider things themselves, distinct from what are only perceptible measures of them.

To some modern readers it can appear that some dynamical quantities recognised today were used in the Principia but not named. The mathematical aspects of the first two books were so clearly consistent that they were easily accepted; for example, Locke asked Huygens whether he could trust the mathematical proofs, and was assured about their correctness.

However, the concept of an attractive force acting at a distance received a cooler response. In his notes, Newton wrote that the inverse square law arose naturally due to the structure of matter. However, he retracted this sentence in the published version, where he stated that the motion of planets is consistent with an inverse square law, but refused to speculate on the origin of the law. Huygens and Leibniz noted that the law was incompatible with the notion of the aether. From a Cartesian point of view, therefore, this was a faulty theory. Newton's defence has been adopted since by many famous physicists—he pointed out that the mathematical form of the theory had to be correct since it explained the data, and he refused to speculate further on the basic nature of gravity. The sheer number of phenomena that could be organised by the theory was so impressive that younger "philosophers" soon adopted the methods and language of the Principia.

Rules of Reason

Perhaps to reduce the risk of public misunderstanding, Newton included at the beginning of Book 3 (in the second (1713) and third (1726) editions) a section titled "Rules of Reasoning in Philosophy". In the four rules, as they came finally to stand in the 1726 edition, Newton effectively offers a methodology for handling unknown phenomena in nature and reaching towards explanations for them. The four Rules of the 1726 edition run as follows (omitting some explanatory comments that follow each):

  1. We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.
  2. Therefore to the same natural effects we must, as far as possible, assign the same causes.
  3. The qualities of bodies, which admit neither intensification nor remission of degrees, and which are found to belong to all bodies within the reach of our experiments, are to be esteemed the universal qualities of all bodies whatsoever.
  4. In experimental philosophy we are to look upon propositions inferred by general induction from phenomena as accurately or very nearly true, not withstanding any contrary hypothesis that may be imagined, till such time as other phenomena occur, by which they may either be made more accurate, or liable to exceptions.

This section of Rules for philosophy is followed by a listing of "Phenomena", in which are listed a number of mainly astronomical observations, that Newton used as the basis for inferences later on, as if adopting a consensus set of facts from the astronomers of his time.

Both the "Rules" and the "Phenomena" evolved from one edition of the Principia to the next. Rule 4 made its appearance in the third (1726) edition; Rules 1–3 were present as "Rules" in the second (1713) edition, and predecessors of them were also present in the first edition of 1687, but there they had a different heading: they were not given as "Rules", but rather in the first (1687) edition the predecessors of the three later "Rules", and of most of the later "Phenomena", were all lumped together under a single heading "Hypotheses" (in which the third item was the predecessor of a heavy revision that gave the later Rule 3).

From this textual evolution, it appears that Newton wanted by the later headings "Rules" and "Phenomena" to clarify for his readers his view of the roles to be played by these various statements.

In the third (1726) edition of the Principia, Newton explains each rule in an alternative way and/or gives an example to back up what the rule is claiming. The first rule is explained as a philosophers' principle of economy. The second rule states that if one cause is assigned to a natural effect, then the same cause so far as possible must be assigned to natural effects of the same kind: for example respiration in humans and in animals, fires in the home and in the Sun, or the reflection of light whether it occurs terrestrially or from the planets. An extensive explanation is given of the third rule, concerning the qualities of bodies, and Newton discusses here the generalisation of observational results, with a caution against making up fancies contrary to experiments, and use of the rules to illustrate the observation of gravity and space.

Isaac Newton's statement of the four rules revolutionised the investigation of phenomena. With these rules, Newton could in principle begin to address all of the world's present unsolved mysteries. He was able to use his new analytical method to replace that of Aristotle, and he was able to use his method to tweak and update Galileo's experimental method. The re-creation of Galileo's method has never been significantly changed and in its substance, scientists use it today.[citation needed]

General Scholium

The General Scholium is a concluding essay added to the second edition, 1713 (and amended in the third edition, 1726).[47] It is not to be confused with the General Scholium at the end of Book 2, Section 6, which discusses his pendulum experiments and resistance due to air, water, and other fluids.

Here Newton used the expression hypotheses non fingo, "I formulate no hypotheses",[8] in response to criticisms of the first edition of the Principia. ("Fingo" is sometimes nowadays translated "feign" rather than the traditional "frame," although "feign" does not properly translate "fingo"). Newton's gravitational attraction, an invisible force able to act over vast distances, had led to criticism that he had introduced "occult agencies" into science.[48] Newton firmly rejected such criticisms and wrote that it was enough that the phenomena implied gravitational attraction, as they did; but the phenomena did not so far indicate the cause of this gravity, and it was both unnecessary and improper to frame hypotheses of things not implied by the phenomena: such hypotheses "have no place in experimental philosophy", in contrast to the proper way in which "particular propositions are inferr'd from the phenomena and afterwards rendered general by induction".[49]

Newton also underlined his criticism of the vortex theory of planetary motions, of Descartes, pointing to its incompatibility with the highly eccentric orbits of comets, which carry them "through all parts of the heavens indifferently".

Newton also gave theological argument. From the system of the world, he inferred the existence of a god, along lines similar to what is sometimes called the argument from intelligent or purposive design. It has been suggested that Newton gave "an oblique argument for a unitarian conception of God and an implicit attack on the doctrine of the Trinity".[50][51] The General Scholium does not address or attempt to refute the church doctrine; it simply does not mention Jesus, the Holy Ghost, or the hypothesis of the Trinity.

Publishing the book

Halley and Newton's initial stimulus

In January 1684, Edmond Halley, Christopher Wren and Robert Hooke had a conversation in which Hooke claimed to not only have derived the inverse-square law but also all the laws of planetary motion. Wren was unconvinced, Hooke did not produce the claimed derivation although the others gave him time to do it, and Halley, who could derive the inverse-square law for the restricted circular case (by substituting Kepler's relation into Huygens' formula for the centrifugal force) but failed to derive the relation generally, resolved to ask Newton.[52]

Halley's visits to Newton in 1684 thus resulted from Halley's debates about planetary motion with Wren and Hooke, and they seem to have provided Newton with the incentive and spur to develop and write what became Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. Halley was at that time a Fellow and Council member of the Royal Society in London (positions that in 1686 he resigned to become the Society's paid Clerk).[53] Halley's visit to Newton in Cambridge in 1684 probably occurred in August.[54] When Halley asked Newton's opinion on the problem of planetary motions discussed earlier that year between Halley, Hooke and Wren,[55] Newton surprised Halley by saying that he had already made the derivations some time ago; but that he could not find the papers. (Matching accounts of this meeting come from Halley and Abraham De Moivre to whom Newton confided.) Halley then had to wait for Newton to "find" the results, and in November 1684 Newton sent Halley an amplified version of whatever previous work Newton had done on the subject. This took the form of a 9-page manuscript, De motu corporum in gyrum (Of the motion of bodies in an orbit): the title is shown on some surviving copies, although the (lost) original may have been without a title.

Newton's tract De motu corporum in gyrum, which he sent to Halley in late 1684, derived what is now known as the three laws of Kepler, assuming an inverse square law of force, and generalised the result to conic sections. It also extended the methodology by adding the solution of a problem on the motion of a body through a resisting medium. The contents of De motu so excited Halley by their mathematical and physical originality and far-reaching implications for astronomical theory, that he immediately went to visit Newton again, in November 1684, to ask Newton to let the Royal Society have more of such work.[56] The results of their meetings clearly helped to stimulate Newton with the enthusiasm needed to take his investigations of mathematical problems much further in this area of physical science, and he did so in a period of highly concentrated work that lasted at least until mid-1686.[57]

Newton's single-minded attention to his work generally, and to his project during this time, is shown by later reminiscences from his secretary and copyist of the period, Humphrey Newton. His account tells of Isaac Newton's absorption in his studies, how he sometimes forgot his food, or his sleep, or the state of his clothes, and how when he took a walk in his garden he would sometimes rush back to his room with some new thought, not even waiting to sit before beginning to write it down.[58] Other evidence also shows Newton's absorption in the Principia: Newton for years kept up a regular programme of chemical or alchemical experiments, and he normally kept dated notes of them, but for a period from May 1684 to April 1686, Newton's chemical notebooks have no entries at all.[59] So it seems that Newton abandoned pursuits to which he was formally dedicated, and did very little else for well over a year and a half, but concentrated on developing and writing what became his great work.

The first of the three constituent books was sent to Halley for the printer in spring 1686, and the other two books somewhat later. The complete work, published by Halley at his own financial risk,[60] appeared in July 1687. Newton had also communicated De motu to Flamsteed, and during the period of composition, he exchanged a few letters with Flamsteed about observational data on the planets, eventually acknowledging Flamsteed's contributions in the published version of the Principia of 1687.

Preliminary version

 
Newton's own first edition copy of his Principia, with handwritten corrections for the second edition

The process of writing that first edition of the Principia went through several stages and drafts: some parts of the preliminary materials still survive, while others are lost except for fragments and cross-references in other documents.[61]

Surviving materials show that Newton (up to some time in 1685) conceived his book as a two-volume work. The first volume was to be titled De motu corporum, Liber primus, with contents that later appeared in extended form as Book 1 of the Principia.[citation needed]

A fair-copy draft of Newton's planned second volume De motu corporum, Liber Secundus survives, its completion dated to about the summer of 1685. It covers the application of the results of Liber primus to the Earth, the Moon, the tides, the Solar System, and the universe; in this respect, it has much the same purpose as the final Book 3 of the Principia, but it is written much less formally and is more easily read.[citation needed]

 
Titlepage and frontispiece of the third edition, London, 1726 (John Rylands Library)

It is not known just why Newton changed his mind so radically about the final form of what had been a readable narrative in De motu corporum, Liber Secundus of 1685, but he largely started afresh in a new, tighter, and less accessible mathematical style, eventually to produce Book 3 of the Principia as we know it. Newton frankly admitted that this change of style was deliberate when he wrote that he had (first) composed this book "in a popular method, that it might be read by many", but to "prevent the disputes" by readers who could not "lay aside the[ir] prejudices", he had "reduced" it "into the form of propositions (in the mathematical way) which should be read by those only, who had first made themselves masters of the principles established in the preceding books".[62] The final Book 3 also contained in addition some further important quantitative results arrived at by Newton in the meantime, especially about the theory of the motions of comets, and some of the perturbations of the motions of the Moon.

The result was numbered Book 3 of the Principia rather than Book 2 because in the meantime, drafts of Liber primus had expanded and Newton had divided it into two books. The new and final Book 2 was concerned largely with the motions of bodies through resisting mediums.[63]

But the Liber Secundus of 1685 can still be read today. Even after it was superseded by Book 3 of the Principia, it survived complete, in more than one manuscript. After Newton's death in 1727, the relatively accessible character of its writing encouraged the publication of an English translation in 1728 (by persons still unknown, not authorised by Newton's heirs). It appeared under the English title A Treatise of the System of the World.[64] This had some amendments relative to Newton's manuscript of 1685, mostly to remove cross-references that used obsolete numbering to cite the propositions of an early draft of Book 1 of the Principia. Newton's heirs shortly afterwards published the Latin version in their possession, also in 1728, under the (new) title De Mundi Systemate, amended to update cross-references, citations and diagrams to those of the later editions of the Principia, making it look superficially as if it had been written by Newton after the Principia, rather than before.[65] The System of the World was sufficiently popular to stimulate two revisions (with similar changes as in the Latin printing), a second edition (1731), and a "corrected" reprint[66] of the second edition (1740).

Halley's role as publisher

The text of the first of the three books of the Principia was presented to the Royal Society at the close of April 1686. Hooke made some priority claims (but failed to substantiate them), causing some delay. When Hooke's claim was made known to Newton, who hated disputes, Newton threatened to withdraw and suppress Book 3 altogether, but Halley, showing considerable diplomatic skills, tactfully persuaded Newton to withdraw his threat and let it go forward to publication. Samuel Pepys, as president, gave his imprimatur on 30 June 1686, licensing the book for publication. The Society had just spent its book budget on De Historia piscium,[67] and the cost of publication was borne by Edmund Halley (who was also then acting as publisher of the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society):[68] the book appeared in summer 1687.[69] After Halley had personally financed the publication of Principia, he was informed that the society could no longer afford to provide him the promised annual salary of £50. Instead, Halley was paid with leftover copies of De Historia piscium.[70]

Historical context

Beginnings of the Scientific Revolution

 
Nicolaus Copernicus (1473–1543) formulated a heliocentric (or Sun-centered) model of the universe.

Nicolaus Copernicus had moved the Earth away from the center of the universe with the heliocentric theory for which he presented evidence in his book De revolutionibus orbium coelestium (On the revolutions of the heavenly spheres) published in 1543. Johannes Kepler wrote the book Astronomia nova (A new astronomy) in 1609, setting out the evidence that planets move in elliptical orbits with the Sun at one focus, and that planets do not move with constant speed along this orbit. Rather, their speed varies so that the line joining the centres of the sun and a planet sweeps out equal areas in equal times. To these two laws he added a third a decade later, in his 1619 book Harmonices Mundi (Harmonies of the world). This law sets out a proportionality between the third power of the characteristic distance of a planet from the Sun and the square of the length of its year.

 
Italian physicist Galileo Galilei (1564–1642), a champion of the Copernican model of the universe and a figure in the history of kinematics and classical mechanics

The foundation of modern dynamics was set out in Galileo's book Dialogo sopra i due massimi sistemi del mondo (Dialogue on the two main world systems) where the notion of inertia was implicit and used. In addition, Galileo's experiments with inclined planes had yielded precise mathematical relations between elapsed time and acceleration, velocity or distance for uniform and uniformly accelerated motion of bodies.

Descartes' book of 1644 Principia philosophiae (Principles of philosophy) stated that bodies can act on each other only through contact: a principle that induced people, among them himself, to hypothesize a universal medium as the carrier of interactions such as light and gravity—the aether. Newton was criticized for apparently introducing forces that acted at distance without any medium.[48] Not until the development of particle theory was Descartes' notion vindicated when it was possible to describe all interactions, like the strong, weak, and electromagnetic fundamental interactions, using mediating gauge bosons[71] and gravity through hypothesized gravitons.[72]

Newton's role

Newton had studied these books, or, in some cases, secondary sources based on them, and taken notes entitled Quaestiones quaedam philosophicae (Questions about philosophy) during his days as an undergraduate. During this period (1664–1666) he created the basis of calculus, and performed the first experiments in the optics of colour. At this time, his proof that white light was a combination of primary colours (found via prismatics) replaced the prevailing theory of colours and received an overwhelmingly favourable response, and occasioned bitter disputes with Robert Hooke and others, which forced him to sharpen his ideas to the point where he already composed sections of his later book Opticks by the 1670s in response. Work on calculus is shown in various papers and letters, including two to Leibniz. He became a fellow of the Royal Society and the second Lucasian Professor of Mathematics (succeeding Isaac Barrow) at Trinity College, Cambridge.

Newton's early work on motion

In the 1660s Newton studied the motion of colliding bodies, and deduced that the centre of mass of two colliding bodies remains in uniform motion. Surviving manuscripts of the 1660s also show Newton's interest in planetary motion and that by 1669 he had shown, for a circular case of planetary motion, that the force he called "endeavour to recede" (now called centrifugal force) had an inverse-square relation with distance from the center.[73] After his 1679–1680 correspondence with Hooke, described below, Newton adopted the language of inward or centripetal force. According to Newton scholar J. Bruce Brackenridge, although much has been made of the change in language and difference of point of view, as between centrifugal or centripetal forces, the actual computations and proofs remained the same either way. They also involved the combination of tangential and radial displacements, which Newton was making in the 1660s. The difference between the centrifugal and centripetal points of view, though a significant change of perspective, did not change the analysis.[74] Newton also clearly expressed the concept of linear inertia in the 1660s: for this Newton was indebted to Descartes' work published 1644.[75]

Controversy with Hooke

 
Artist's impression of English polymath Robert Hooke (1635–1703)

Hooke published his ideas about gravitation in the 1660s and again in 1674. He argued for an attracting principle of gravitation in Micrographia of 1665, in a 1666 Royal Society lecture On gravity, and again in 1674, when he published his ideas about the System of the World in somewhat developed form, as an addition to An Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth from Observations.[76] Hooke clearly postulated mutual attractions between the Sun and planets, in a way that increased with nearness to the attracting body, along with a principle of linear inertia. Hooke's statements up to 1674 made no mention, however, that an inverse square law applies or might apply to these attractions. Hooke's gravitation was also not yet universal, though it approached universality more closely than previous hypotheses.[77] Hooke also did not provide accompanying evidence or mathematical demonstration. On these two aspects, Hooke stated in 1674: "Now what these several degrees [of gravitational attraction] are I have not yet experimentally verified" (indicating that he did not yet know what law the gravitation might follow); and as to his whole proposal: "This I only hint at present", "having my self many other things in hand which I would first compleat, and therefore cannot so well attend it" (i.e., "prosecuting this Inquiry").[76]

In November 1679, Hooke began an exchange of letters with Newton, of which the full text is now published.[78] Hooke told Newton that Hooke had been appointed to manage the Royal Society's correspondence,[79] and wished to hear from members about their researches, or their views about the researches of others; and as if to whet Newton's interest, he asked what Newton thought about various matters, giving a whole list, mentioning "compounding the celestial motions of the planets of a direct motion by the tangent and an attractive motion towards the central body", and "my hypothesis of the lawes or causes of springinesse", and then a new hypothesis from Paris about planetary motions (which Hooke described at length), and then efforts to carry out or improve national surveys, the difference of latitude between London and Cambridge, and other items. Newton's reply offered "a fansy of my own" about a terrestrial experiment (not a proposal about celestial motions) which might detect the Earth's motion, by the use of a body first suspended in air and then dropped to let it fall. The main point was to indicate how Newton thought the falling body could experimentally reveal the Earth's motion by its direction of deviation from the vertical, but he went on hypothetically to consider how its motion could continue if the solid Earth had not been in the way (on a spiral path to the centre). Hooke disagreed with Newton's idea of how the body would continue to move.[80] A short further correspondence developed, and towards the end of it Hooke, writing on 6 January 1680 to Newton, communicated his "supposition ... that the Attraction always is in a duplicate proportion to the Distance from the Center Reciprocall, and Consequently that the Velocity will be in a subduplicate proportion to the Attraction and Consequently as Kepler Supposes Reciprocall to the Distance."[81] (Hooke's inference about the velocity was actually incorrect.[82])

In 1686, when the first book of Newton's Principia was presented to the Royal Society, Hooke claimed that Newton had obtained from him the "notion" of "the rule of the decrease of Gravity, being reciprocally as the squares of the distances from the Center". At the same time (according to Edmond Halley's contemporary report) Hooke agreed that "the Demonstration of the Curves generated therby" was wholly Newton's.[78]

A recent assessment about the early history of the inverse square law is that "by the late 1660s", the assumption of an "inverse proportion between gravity and the square of distance was rather common and had been advanced by a number of different people for different reasons".[83] Newton himself had shown in the 1660s that for planetary motion under a circular assumption, force in the radial direction had an inverse-square relation with distance from the center.[73] Newton, faced in May 1686 with Hooke's claim on the inverse square law, denied that Hooke was to be credited as author of the idea, giving reasons including the citation of prior work by others before Hooke.[78] Newton also firmly claimed that even if it had happened that he had first heard of the inverse square proportion from Hooke, which it had not, he would still have some rights to it in view of his mathematical developments and demonstrations, which enabled observations to be relied on as evidence of its accuracy, while Hooke, without mathematical demonstrations and evidence in favour of the supposition, could only guess (according to Newton) that it was approximately valid "at great distances from the center".[78]

The background described above shows there was basis for Newton to deny deriving the inverse square law from Hooke. On the other hand, Newton did accept and acknowledge, in all editions of the Principia, that Hooke (but not exclusively Hooke) had separately appreciated the inverse square law in the Solar System. Newton acknowledged Wren, Hooke and Halley in this connection in the Scholium to Proposition 4 in Book 1.[84] Newton also acknowledged to Halley that his correspondence with Hooke in 1679–80 had reawakened his dormant interest in astronomical matters, but that did not mean, according to Newton, that Hooke had told Newton anything new or original: "yet am I not beholden to him for any light into that business but only for the diversion he gave me from my other studies to think on these things & for his dogmaticalness in writing as if he had found the motion in the Ellipsis, which inclined me to try it ...".[78]) Newton's reawakening interest in astronomy received further stimulus by the appearance of a comet in the winter of 1680/1681, on which he corresponded with John Flamsteed.[85]

In 1759, decades after the deaths of both Newton and Hooke, Alexis Clairaut, mathematical astronomer eminent in his own right in the field of gravitational studies, made his assessment after reviewing what Hooke had published on gravitation. "One must not think that this idea ... of Hooke diminishes Newton's glory", Clairaut wrote; "The example of Hooke" serves "to show what a distance there is between a truth that is glimpsed and a truth that is demonstrated".[86][87]

Location of early edition copies

 
A page from the Principia

It has been estimated that as many as 750 copies[88] of the first edition were printed by the Royal Society, and "it is quite remarkable that so many copies of this small first edition are still in existence ... but it may be because the original Latin text was more revered than read".[89] A survey published in 1953 located 189 surviving copies[90] with nearly 200 further copies located by the most recent survey published in 2020, suggesting that the initial print run was larger than previously thought.[91] However, more recent book historical and bibliographical research has examined those prior claims, and concludes that Macomber's earlier estimation of 500 copies is likely correct.[92]

In 2016, a first edition sold for $3.7 million.[105]

The second edition (1713) were printed in 750 copies, and the third edition (1726) were printed in 1,250 copies.

A facsimile edition (based on the 3rd edition of 1726 but with variant readings from earlier editions and important annotations) was published in 1972 by Alexandre Koyré and I. Bernard Cohen.[10]

Later editions

 
Newton's personal copy of the first edition of Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica, annotated by him for the second edition. Displayed at Cambridge University Library.

Second edition, 1713

 
Second edition opened to title page

Two later editions were published by Newton: Newton had been urged to make a new edition of the Principia since the early 1690s, partly because copies of the first edition had already become very rare and expensive within a few years after 1687.[106] Newton referred to his plans for a second edition in correspondence with Flamsteed in November 1694.[107] Newton also maintained annotated copies of the first edition specially bound up with interleaves on which he could note his revisions; two of these copies still survive,[108] but he had not completed the revisions by 1708. Newton had almost severed connections with one would-be editor, Nicolas Fatio de Duillier, and another, David Gregory seems not to have met with his approval and was also terminally ill, dying in 1708. Nevertheless, reasons were accumulating not to put off the new edition any longer.[109] Richard Bentley, master of Trinity College, persuaded Newton to allow him to undertake a second edition, and in June 1708 Bentley wrote to Newton with a specimen print of the first sheet, at the same time expressing the (unfulfilled) hope that Newton had made progress towards finishing the revisions.[110] It seems that Bentley then realised that the editorship was technically too difficult for him, and with Newton's consent he appointed Roger Cotes, Plumian professor of astronomy at Trinity, to undertake the editorship for him as a kind of deputy (but Bentley still made the publishing arrangements and had the financial responsibility and profit). The correspondence of 1709–1713 shows Cotes reporting to two masters, Bentley and Newton, and managing (and often correcting) a large and important set of revisions to which Newton sometimes could not give his full attention.[111] Under the weight of Cotes' efforts, but impeded by priority disputes between Newton and Leibniz,[112] and by troubles at the Mint,[113] Cotes was able to announce publication to Newton on 30 June 1713.[114] Bentley sent Newton only six presentation copies; Cotes was unpaid; Newton omitted any acknowledgement to Cotes.

Among those who gave Newton corrections for the Second Edition were: Firmin Abauzit, Roger Cotes and David Gregory. However, Newton omitted acknowledgements to some because of the priority disputes. John Flamsteed, the Astronomer Royal, suffered this especially.

The Second Edition was the basis of the first edition to be printed abroad, which appeared in Amsterdam in 1714.

Third edition, 1726

After his serious illness in 1722 and after the appearance of a reprint of the second edition in Amsterdam in 1723, the 80-year-old Newton began to revise once again the Principia in the fall of 1723. The third edition was published 25 March 1726, under the stewardship of Henry Pemberton, M.D., a man of the greatest skill in these matters...; Pemberton later said that this recognition was worth more to him than the two hundred guinea award from Newton.[115]

In 1739–1742, two French priests, Pères Thomas LeSeur and François Jacquier (of the Minim order, but sometimes erroneously identified as Jesuits), produced with the assistance of J.-L. Calandrini an extensively annotated version of the Principia in the 3rd edition of 1726. Sometimes this is referred to as the Jesuit edition: it was much used, and reprinted more than once in Scotland during the 19th century.[116]

Émilie du Châtelet also made a translation of Newton's Principia into French. Unlike LeSeur and Jacquier's edition, hers was a complete translation of Newton's three books and their prefaces. She also included a Commentary section where she fused the three books into a much clearer and easier to understand summary. She included an analytical section where she applied the new mathematics of calculus to Newton's most controversial theories. Previously, geometry was the standard mathematics used to analyse theories. Du Châtelet's translation is the only complete one to have been done in French and hers remains the standard French translation to this day.[117]

Translations

 
Title page to an 1848 copy of The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, translated into English by Andrew Motte

Four full English translations of Newton's Principia have appeared, all based on Newton's 3rd edition of 1726. The first, from 1729, by Andrew Motte,[3] was described by Newton scholar I. Bernard Cohen (in 1968) as "still of enormous value in conveying to us the sense of Newton's words in their own time, and it is generally faithful to the original: clear, and well written".[118] The 1729 version was the basis for several republications, often incorporating revisions, among them a widely used modernised English version of 1934, which appeared under the editorial name of Florian Cajori (though completed and published only some years after his death). Cohen pointed out ways in which the 18th-century terminology and punctuation of the 1729 translation might be confusing to modern readers, but he also made severe criticisms of the 1934 modernised English version, and showed that the revisions had been made without regard to the original, also demonstrating gross errors "that provided the final impetus to our decision to produce a wholly new translation".[119]

The second full English translation, into modern English, is the work that resulted from this decision by collaborating translators I. Bernard Cohen, Anne Whitman, and Julia Budenz; it was published in 1999 with a guide by way of introduction.[120]

The third such translation is due to Ian Bruce, and appears, with many other translations of mathematical works of the 17th and 18th centuries, on his website.[121]

The fourth such translation is due to Charles Leedham-Green, and is published as ``The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Isaac Newton, Translated and Annotated by C.R.Leedham-Green. [122] The main aim of this translation, by a research mathematician, is to be less opaque, and truer to the underlying mathematics and physics, than the Cohen-Whitman-Budenz translation.

Dana Densmore and William H. Donahue have published a translation of the work's central argument, published in 1996, along with expansion of included proofs and ample commentary.[123] The book was developed as a textbook for classes at St. John's College and the aim of this translation is to be faithful to the Latin text.[124]

In 2014, British astronaut Tim Peake named his upcoming mission to the International Space Station Principia after the book, in "honour of Britain's greatest scientist".[125] Tim Peake's Principia launched on December 15, 2015 aboard Soyuz TMA-19M.[126]

See also

References

  1. ^ "The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy", Encyclopædia Britannica, London
  2. ^ Among versions of the Principia online: [1].
  3. ^ a b Volume 1 of the 1729 English translation is available as an online scan; limited parts of the 1729 translation (misidentified as based on the 1687 edition) have also been transcribed online.
  4. ^ J. M. Steele, University of Toronto, (review online from Canadian Association of Physicists) 1 April 2010 at the Wayback Machine of N. Guicciardini's "Reading the Principia: The Debate on Newton's Mathematical Methods for Natural Philosophy from 1687 to 1736" (Cambridge UP, 1999), a book which also states (summary before title page) that the "Principia" "is considered one of the masterpieces in the history of science".
  5. ^ (in French) Alexis Clairaut, "Du systeme du monde, dans les principes de la gravitation universelle", in "Histoires (& Memoires) de l'Academie Royale des Sciences" for 1745 (published 1749), at p. 329 (according to a note on p. 329, Clairaut's paper was read at a session of November 1747).
  6. ^ G. E. Smith, "Newton's Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.).
  7. ^ a b The content of infinitesimal calculus in the "Principia" was recognized both in Newton's lifetime and later, among others by the Marquis de l'Hospital, whose 1696 book "Analyse des infiniment petits" (Infinitesimal analysis) stated in its preface, about the "Principia", that "nearly all of it is of this calculus" ("lequel est presque tout de ce calcul"). See also D. T. Whiteside (1970), "The mathematical principles underlying Newton's Principia Mathematica", Journal for the History of Astronomy, vol. 1 (1970), 116–138, especially at p. 120.
  8. ^ a b Or "frame" no hypotheses (as traditionally translated at vol. 2, p. 392, in the 1729 English version).
  9. ^ Newton, Isaac. "Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica (Newton's personally annotated 1st edition)".
  10. ^ a b c [In Latin] Isaac Newton's Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica: the Third edition (1726) with variant readings, assembled and ed. by Alexandre Koyré and I Bernard Cohen with the assistance of Anne Whitman (Cambridge, MA, 1972, Harvard UP).
  11. ^ Hermann, Claudine (2008). "La traduction et les commentaires des Principia de Newton par Émilie du Châtelet". Bibnum. Textes Fondateurs de la Science (in French). doi:10.4000/bibnum.722. S2CID 164354455. translate.google.co.uk : "améliorée"
  12. ^ From Motte's translation of 1729 (at 3rd page of Author's Preface); and see also J. W. Herivel, The background to Newton's "Principia", Oxford University Press, 1965.
  13. ^ The De motu corporum in gyrum article indicates the topics that reappear in the Principia.
  14. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Definitions". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 1.
  15. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Axioms or Laws of Motion". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 19.
  16. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Section I". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 41.
  17. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Section II". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 57.
  18. ^ This relationship between circular curvature, speed and radial force, now often known as Huygens' formula, was independently found by Newton (in the 1660s) and by Huygens in the 1650s: the conclusion was published (without proof) by Huygens in 1673.This was given by Isaac Newton through his Inverse Square Law.
  19. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac; Machin, John (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. pp. 79–153.
  20. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Section IX". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 177.
  21. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Section XI". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 218.
  22. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Section XI, Proposition LXVI". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 234.
  23. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac; Machin, John (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. pp. 239–256.
  24. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Section XII". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume I. B. Motte. p. 263.
  25. ^ Gillispie, Charles Coulston (1960). The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas. Princeton University Press. p. 254. ISBN 0-691-02350-6.
  26. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Proposition 48". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 176.
  27. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Scholium to proposition 50". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 181.
  28. ^ Eric J Aiton, The Cartesian vortex theory, chapter 11 in Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise of astrophysics, Part A: Tycho Brahe to Newton, eds. R Taton & C Wilson, Cambridge (Cambridge University press) 1989; at pp. 207–221.
  29. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Scholium to proposition 53". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 197.
  30. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 252.
  31. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 262.
  32. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "The Phaenomena". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 206.
  33. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 213.
  34. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 220.
  35. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 323.
  36. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 332.
  37. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 255.
  38. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 305.
  39. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 306.
  40. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 320.
  41. ^ See Curtis Wilson, "The Newtonian achievement in astronomy", pages 233–274 in R Taton & C Wilson (eds) (1989) The General History of Astronomy, Volume, 2A', at page 233).
  42. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Proposition 12, Corollary". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 233.
  43. ^ a b Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Proposition 11 & preceding Hypothesis". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 232.
  44. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Proposition 8, Corollary 2". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 228.
  45. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Proposition 12". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. pp. 232–233. Newton's position is seen to go beyond literal Copernican heliocentrism practically to the modern position in regard to the Solar System barycenter (see Barycenter -- Inside or outside the Sun?).
  46. ^ Knudsen, Jens M.; Hjorth, Poul (2012). Elements of Newtonian Mechanics (illustrated ed.). Springer Science & Business Media. p. 30. ISBN 978-3-642-97599-8. Extract of page 30
  47. ^ See online Principia (1729 translation) vol.2, Books 2 & 3, starting at page 387 of volume 2 (1729).
  48. ^ a b Edelglass et al., Matter and Mind, ISBN 0-940262-45-2, p. 54.
  49. ^ See online Principia (1729 translation) vol.2, Books 2 & 3, at page 392 of volume 2 (1729).
  50. ^ Snobelen, Stephen. . Archived from the original on 8 June 2008. Retrieved 31 May 2008.
  51. ^ Ducheyne, Steffen. (PDF). Lias: Sources and Documents Relating to the Early Modern History of Ideas. 33 (2): 223–274. Archived from the original (PDF) on 17 December 2008. Retrieved 19 November 2008.
  52. ^ Paraphrase of 1686 report by Halley, in H. W. Turnbull (ed.), "Correspondence of Isaac Newton", Vol. 2, cited above, pp. 431–448.
  53. ^ 'Cook, 1998': A. Cook, Edmond Halley, Charting the Heavens and the Seas, Oxford University Press 1998, at pp. 147 and 152.
  54. ^ As dated e.g. by D. T. Whiteside, in The Prehistory of the Principia from 1664 to 1686, Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, 45 (1991) 11–61.
  55. ^ Cook, 1998; at p. 147.
  56. ^ Westfall, 1980: R. S. Westfall, Never at Rest: A Biography of Isaac Newton, Cambridge University Press 1980, at p. 404.
  57. ^ Cook, 1998; at p. 151.
  58. ^ Westfall, 1980; at p. 406, also pp. 191–192.
  59. ^ Westfall, 1980; at p. 406, n. 15.
  60. ^ Westfall, 1980; at pp. 153–156.
  61. ^ The fundamental study of Newton's progress in writing the Principia is in I. Bernard Cohen's Introduction to Newton's 'Principia', (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1971), at part 2: "The writing and the first publication of the 'Principia'", pp. 47–142.
  62. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1729). "Introduction to Book 3". The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Volume II. Benjamin Motte. p. 200.
  63. ^ Smith, G. (2008). "Newton's Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta, E.N. Ed. Metaphysics Research Lab, Dept. of Philosophy, Stanford University. Winter 2008. ISSN 1095-5054. Retrieved 21 October 2022.
  64. ^ Newton, Isaac (1728). A Treatise of the System of the World.
  65. ^ I. Bernard Cohen, Introduction to Newton's A Treatise of the System of the World (facsimile of second English edition of 1731), London (Dawsons of Pall Mall) 1969; reprinted in A Treatise of the System of the World, Dover Phoenix Editions, 2004, ISBN 0-486-43880-5.
  66. ^ Newton, Sir Isaac (1740). The System of the World: Demonstrated in an Easy and Popular Manner. Being a Proper Introduction to the Most Sublime Philosophy. By the Illustrious Sir Isaac Newton. Translated into English. A "corrected" reprint of the second edition.
  67. ^ Richard Westfall (1980), Never at Rest, p. 453, ISBN 0-521-27435-4.
  68. ^ Clerk, Halley's (29 October 2013). "Halley and the Principia". Halley's Log. Retrieved 7 December 2019.
  69. ^ . Museumoflondon.org.uk. Archived from the original on 31 March 2012. Retrieved 16 March 2012.
  70. ^ Bill Bryson (2004). A Short History of Nearly Everything. Random House, Inc. p. 74. ISBN 978-0-385-66004-4.
  71. ^ The Henryk Niewodniczanski Institute of Nuclear Physics. "Particle Physics and Astrophysics Research". {{cite web}}: Missing or empty |url= (help)
  72. ^ Rovelli, Carlo (2000). "Notes for a brief history of quantum gravity". arXiv:gr-qc/0006061.
  73. ^ a b D. T. Whiteside, "The pre-history of the 'Principia' from 1664 to 1686", Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, 45 (1991), pages 11–61; especially at 13–20. [2].
  74. ^ See J. Bruce Brackenridge, "The key to Newton's dynamics: the Kepler problem and the Principia", (University of California Press, 1995), especially at pages 20–21.
  75. ^ See page 10 in D. T. Whiteside, "Before the Principia: the maturing of Newton's thoughts on dynamical astronomy, 1664–1684", Journal for the History of Astronomy, i (1970), pages 5–19.
  76. ^ a b Hooke's 1674 statement in "An Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth from Observations", is available in online facsimile here.
  77. ^ See page 239 in Curtis Wilson (1989), "The Newtonian achievement in astronomy", ch. 13 (pages 233–274) in "Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise of astrophysics: 2A: Tycho Brahe to Newton", CUP 1989.
  78. ^ a b c d e H. W. Turnbull (ed.), Correspondence of Isaac Newton, Vol. 2 (1676–1687), (Cambridge University Press, 1960), giving the Hooke-Newton correspondence (of November 1679 to January 1679/80) at pp. 297–314, and the 1686 correspondence over Hooke's priority claim at pp. 431–448.
  79. ^ "Correspondence", vol. 2 already cited, at p. 297.
  80. ^ Several commentators have followed Hooke in calling Newton's spiral path mistaken, or even a "blunder", but there are also the following facts: (a) that Hooke left out of account Newton's specific statement that the motion resulted from dropping "a heavy body suspended in the Air" (i.e. a resisting medium), see Newton to Hooke, 28 November 1679, document #236 at page 301, "Correspondence", vol. 2 cited above, and compare Hooke's report to the Royal Society on 11 December 1679, where Hooke reported the matter "supposing no resistance", see D Gjertsen, "Newton Handbook" (1986), at page 259); and (b) that Hooke's reply of 9 December 1679 to Newton considered the cases of motion both with and without air resistance: The resistance-free path was what Hooke called an 'elliptueid'; but a line in Hooke's diagram showing the path for his case of air resistance was, though elongated, also another inward-spiralling path ending at the Earth's centre: Hooke wrote "where the Medium ... has a power of impeding and destroying its motion the curve in wch it would move would be some what like the Line AIKLMNOP &c and ... would terminate in the center C". Hooke's path including air resistance was therefore to this extent like Newton's (see "Correspondence", vol. 2, cited above, at pages 304–306, document #237, with accompanying figure). The diagrams are also available online: see Curtis Wilson, chapter 13 in "Planetary Astronomy from the Renaissance to the Rise of Astrophysics, Part A, Tycho Brahe to Newton", (Cambridge UP 1989), at page 241 showing Newton's 1679 diagram with spiral, and extract of his letter; also at page 242 showing Hooke's 1679 diagram including two paths, closed curve and spiral. Newton pointed out in his later correspondence over the priority claim that the descent in a spiral "is true in a resisting medium such as our air is", see "Correspondence", vol. 2 cited above, at page 433, document #286.
  81. ^ See page 309 in "Correspondence of Isaac Newton", Vol. 2 cited above, at document #239.
  82. ^ See Curtis Wilson (1989) at page 244.
  83. ^ See "Meanest foundations and nobler superstructures: Hooke, Newton and the 'Compounding of the Celestiall Motions of the Planetts'", Ofer Gal, 2003 at page 9.
  84. ^ See for example the 1729 English translation of the 'Principia', at page 66.
  85. ^ R. S. Westfall, "Never at Rest", 1980, at pages 391–292.
  86. ^ The second extract is quoted and translated in W. W. Rouse Ball, "An Essay on Newton's 'Principia'" (London and New York: Macmillan, 1893), at page 69.
  87. ^ The original statements by Clairaut (in French) are found (with orthography here as in the original) in "Explication abregée du systême du monde, et explication des principaux phénomenes astronomiques tirée des Principes de M. Newton" (1759), at Introduction (section IX), page 6: "Il ne faut pas croire que cette idée ... de Hook diminue la gloire de M. Newton", [and] "L'exemple de Hook" [serves] "à faire voir quelle distance il y a entre une vérité entrevue & une vérité démontrée".
  88. ^ California Institute of Technology (10 November 2020). "News Release 10-NOV-2020 - Hundreds of copies of Newton's Principia found in new census - Findings suggest that Isaac Newton's 17th-century masterpiece was more widely read". EurekAlert!. Retrieved 11 November 2020.
  89. ^ Henry P. Macomber, "Census of Owners of 1687 First, and 1726 Presentation Edition of Newton's 'Principia'", The Papers of the Bibliographical Society of America, volume 47 (1953), pages 269–300, at page 269.
  90. ^ Macomber, op. cit., page 270.
  91. ^ Feingold, Mordechai and Svorenčík, Andrej (2020) A preliminary census of copies of the first edition of Newton's Principia (1687). Annals of Science, 77 (3), pages 253-348.
  92. ^ Dean, Jason W. and Cumby, Jamie (2021) Principles of Principia: Some Notes on the Print Run for the First Edition. The Book Collector, 70 (3), pages 418-435.
  93. ^ Newton, Isaac. "Philosophiæ naturalis principia mathematica". Cambridge Digital Library. Retrieved 3 July 2013.
  94. ^ Newton, Isaac (1687). "Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica" (in Latin). Swem Library: Jussu Societatis Regiae ac Typis Josephi Streater. Archived from the original on 15 December 2012.
  95. ^ "Principia mystery annotations: We're pretty sure whodunit — but what was he thinking?". 4 March 2020.
  96. ^ "Special Collections & University Archives". stanford.edu.
  97. ^ "The Crawford collection at the Royal Observatory Edinburgh". The Royal Observatory, Edinburgh. Retrieved 3 July 2013.
  98. ^ "Newton's book back in Uppsala University Library". Uppsala University. Retrieved 10 May 2014.
  99. ^ "Beautiful Science: Ideas that Changed the World – Astronomy". Retrieved 2 January 2016.
  100. ^ "A scientific gem: Isaac Newton (1643-1727)". Retrieved 5 July 2016.
  101. ^ Lork, Tim (December 2021). "Chapter 22: Principia".
  102. ^ "Echoes from the Vault". Echoes from the Vault. Retrieved 6 November 2017.
  103. ^ "Annotated first edition copy of Newton's Principia". University of Sydney Library. University of Sydney. Retrieved 17 April 2019.
  104. ^ Westrin, Stefan (2 September 2012). "Boktjuven på Vasa". Arbetarbladet (in Swedish). Retrieved 20 June 2020.
  105. ^ Rawlinson, Kevin (15 December 2016). "Isaac Newton masterwork becomes most expensive science book sold". The Guardian. Retrieved 19 December 2016.
  106. ^ The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol.4, Cambridge University Press 1967, at pp.519, n.2.
  107. ^ The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol.4, Cambridge University press 1967, at p.42.
  108. ^ I Bernard Cohen, Introduction to the Principia, Cambridge 1971.
  109. ^ Richard S. Westfall. Never at Rest: A Biography of Isaac Newton. Cambridge U. Press. 1980 ISBN 0-521-23143-4, at p. 699.
  110. ^ The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 4, Cambridge University press 1967, at pp. 518–520.
  111. ^ The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 5, Cambridge University press 1975. Bentley's letter to Newton of October 1709 (at pp. 7–8) describes Cotes' perhaps unenviable position in relation to his master Bentley: "You need not be so shy of giving Mr. Cotes too much trouble: he has more esteem for you, and obligations to you, than to think that trouble too grievous: but however he does it at my Orders, to whom he owes more than that."
  112. ^ Westfall, pp. 712–716.
  113. ^ Westfall, pp. 751–760.
  114. ^ Westfall, p. 750.
  115. ^ Westfall, p. 802.
  116. ^ [In Latin] Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica volume 1 of a facsimile of a reprint (1833) of the 3rd (1726) edition, as annotated in 1740–42 by Thomas LeSeur & François Jacquier, with the assistance of J-L Calandrini.
  117. ^ See "Translating Newton's 'Principia': The Marquise du Châtelet's Revisions and Additions for a French Audience". Author: Judith P. Zinsser. Source: Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, Vol. 55, No. 2 (May 2001), pp. 227–245.
  118. ^ I Bernard Cohen (1968), "Introduction" (at page i) to (facsimile) reprint of 1729 English translation of Newton's "Principia" (London (1968), Dawsons of Pall Mall).
  119. ^ See pages 29–37 in I. Bernard Cohen (1999), "A Guide to Newton's Principia", published as an introduction to Isaac Newton: The Principia, Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, a new translation by I Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman, University of California Press, 1999.
  120. ^ Isaac Newton: The Principia, Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, a new translation by I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman, preceded by "A Guide to Newton's Principia" by I. Bernard Cohen, University of California Press, 1999, ISBN 978-0-520-08816-0, ISBN 978-0-520-08817-7.
  121. ^ Ian Bruce http://www.17centurymaths.com.
  122. ^ C.R. Leedham-Green, editor, The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (CUP; 2021) ISBN 978-1107020658
  123. ^ Dana Densmore and William H. Donahue, Newton's Principia: The Central Argument: Translation, Notes, and Expanded Proofs (Green Lion Press; 3rd edition, 2003) ISBN 978-1-888009-23-1, 978-1-888009-23-1
  124. ^ Densmore and Donahue, pp. xv–xvi.
  125. ^ Ghosh, Pallab (17 July 2014). "Tim Peake mission name pays tribute to Isaac Newton". BBC News.
  126. ^ "Roscosmos Announces New Soyuz/Progress Launch Dates". NASA. 9 June 2015.

Further reading

  • Miller, Laura, Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science (University of Virginia Press, 2018) online review
  • Alexandre Koyré, Newtonian studies (London: Chapman and Hall, 1965).
  • I. Bernard Cohen, Introduction to Newton's Principia (Harvard University Press, 1971).
  • Richard S. Westfall, Force in Newton's physics; the science of dynamics in the seventeenth century (New York: American Elsevier, 1971).
  • S. Chandrasekhar, Newton's Principia for the common reader (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995).
  • Guicciardini, N., 2005, "Philosophia Naturalis..." in Grattan-Guinness, I., ed., Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics. Elsevier: 59–87.
  • Andrew Janiak, Newton as Philosopher (Cambridge University Press, 2008).
  • François De Gandt, Force and geometry in Newton's Principia trans. Curtis Wilson (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, c1995).
  • Steffen Ducheyne, The main Business of Natural Philosophy: Isaac Newton's Natural-Philosophical Methodology (Dordrecht e.a.: Springer, 2012).
  • John Herivel, The background to Newton's Principia; a study of Newton's dynamical researches in the years 1664–84 (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1965).
  • Brian Ellis, "The Origin and Nature of Newton's Laws of Motion" in Beyond the Edge of Certainty, ed. R. G. Colodny. (Pittsburgh: University Pittsburgh Press, 1965), 29–68.
  • E.A. Burtt, Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science (Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Company, 1954).
  • Colin Pask, Magnificent Principia: Exploring Isaac Newton's Masterpiece (New York: Prometheus Books, 2013).

External links

Latin versions

First edition (1687)

  • High resolution digitised version of Newton's own copy of the first edition, with annotations.
  • Cambridge University, Cambridge Digital Library High resolution digitised version of Newton's own copy of the first edition, interleaved with blank pages for his annotations and corrections.
  • 1687: Newton's Principia, first edition (1687, in Latin). High-resolution presentation of the Gunnerus Library copy.
  • 1687: Newton's Principia, first edition (1687, in Latin).
  • Project Gutenberg.
  • ETH-Bibliothek Zürich. From the library of Gabriel Cramer.
  • Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica From the Rare Book and Special Collection Division at the Library of Congress

Second edition (1713)

  • ETH-Bibliothek Zürich.
  • ETH-Bibliothek Zürich (pirated Amsterdam reprint of 1723).
  • Philosophiæ naturalis principia mathematica (Adv.b.39.2), a 1713 edition with annotations by Newton in the collections of Cambridge University Library and fully digitised in Cambridge Digital Library

Third edition (1726)

  • ETH-Bibliothek Zürich.

Later Latin editions

  • Principia (in Latin, annotated). 1833 Glasgow reprint (volume 1) with Books 1 and 2 of the Latin edition annotated by Leseur, Jacquier and Calandrini 1739–42 (described above).
  • Archive.org (1871 reprint of the 1726 edition)

English translations

  • Andrew Motte, 1729, first English translation of third edition (1726)
    • WikiSource, Partial
    • Google books, vol. 1 with Book 1.
    • Internet Archive, vol. 2 with Books 2 and 3. (Book 3 starts at p.200.) (Google's metadata wrongly labels this vol. 1).
    • Partial HTML
  • Robert Thorpe 1802 translation
  • N. W. Chittenden, ed., 1846 "American Edition" a partly modernised English version, largely the Motte translation of 1729.
    • Wikisource
    • Archive.org #1
    • Archive.org #2
    • eBooks@Adelaide eBooks@Adelaide
  • Percival Frost 1863 translation with interpolations Archive.org
  • Florian Cajori 1934 modernisation of 1729 Motte and 1802 Thorpe translations
  • Ian Bruce has made a complete translation of the third edition, with notes, on his website.
  • Charles Leedham-Green 2021 has published a complete and heavily annotated translation. Cambridge; Cambridge University Press.

Other links

  • David R. Wilkins of the School of Mathematics at Trinity College, Dublin has transcribed a few sections into TeX and METAPOST and made the source, as well as a formatted PDF available at Extracts from the Works of Isaac Newton.

philosophiæ, naturalis, principia, mathematica, whitehead, russell, work, mathematical, logic, principia, mathematica, english, mathematical, principles, natural, philosophy, often, referred, simply, principia, book, isaac, newton, that, expounds, newton, laws. For Whitehead and Russell s work on mathematical logic see Principia Mathematica Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica English The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy 1 often referred to as simply the Principia p r ɪ n ˈ s ɪ p i e p r ɪ n ˈ k ɪ p i e is a book by Isaac Newton that expounds Newton s laws of motion and his law of universal gravitation The Principia is written in Latin and comprises three volumes and was first published on 5 July 1687 2 3 Philosophiae Naturalis Principia MathematicaTitle page of Principia first edition 1687 AuthorSir Isaac NewtonOriginal titlePhilosophiae Naturalis Principia MathematicaLanguageNew LatinPublication date1687 1st ed Published in English1728LC ClassQA803 A53Original textPhilosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica at Latin WikisourceTranslationPhilosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica at WikisourceWikisource has original text related to this article The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy 1729 The Principia is considered one of the most important works in the history of science 4 The French mathematical physicist Alexis Clairaut assessed it in 1747 The famous book of Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy marked the epoch of a great revolution in physics The method followed by its illustrious author Sir Newton spread the light of mathematics on a science which up to then had remained in the darkness of conjectures and hypotheses 5 A more recent assessment has been that while acceptance of Newton s laws was not immediate by the end of the century after publication in 1687 no one could deny that out of the Principia a science had emerged that at least in certain respects so far exceeded anything that had ever gone before that it stood alone as the ultimate exemplar of science generally 6 The Principia forms the foundation of classical mechanics Among other achievements it explains Johannes Kepler s laws of planetary motion which Kepler had first obtained empirically In formulating his physical laws Newton developed and used mathematical methods now included in the field of calculus expressing them in the form of geometric propositions about vanishingly small shapes 7 In a revised conclusion to the Principia see General Scholium Newton emphasized the empirical nature of the work with the expression Hypotheses non fingo I frame feign no hypotheses 8 After annotating and correcting his personal copy of the first edition 9 Newton published two further editions during 1713 10 with errors of the 1687 corrected and an improved version 11 of 1726 10 Contents 1 Contents 1 1 Expressed aim and topics covered 1 2 Book 1 De motu corporum 1 3 Book 2 part 2 of De motu corporum 1 4 Book 3 De mundi systemate 1 5 Commentary on the Principia 2 Rules of Reason 2 1 General Scholium 3 Publishing the book 3 1 Halley and Newton s initial stimulus 3 2 Preliminary version 3 3 Halley s role as publisher 4 Historical context 4 1 Beginnings of the Scientific Revolution 4 2 Newton s role 4 3 Newton s early work on motion 4 4 Controversy with Hooke 5 Location of early edition copies 6 Later editions 6 1 Second edition 1713 6 2 Third edition 1726 6 3 Translations 7 See also 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External links 10 1 Latin versions 10 2 English translations 10 3 Other linksContents EditExpressed aim and topics covered Edit Sir Isaac Newton 1643 1727 author of the Principia The Preface of the work states 12 Rational Mechanics will be the sciences of motion resulting from any forces whatsoever and of the forces required to produce any motion accurately proposed and demonstrated And therefore we offer this work as mathematical principles of his philosophy For all the difficulty of philosophy seems to consist in this from the phenomena of motions to investigate the forces of Nature and then from these forces to demonstrate the other phenomena The Principia deals primarily with massive bodies in motion initially under a variety of conditions and hypothetical laws of force in both non resisting and resisting media thus offering criteria to decide by observations which laws of force are operating in phenomena that may be observed It attempts to cover hypothetical or possible motions both of celestial bodies and of terrestrial projectiles It explores difficult problems of motions perturbed by multiple attractive forces Its third and final book deals with the interpretation of observations about the movements of planets and their satellites It shows how astronomical observations prove the inverse square law of gravitation to an accuracy that was high by the standards of Newton s time offers estimates of relative masses for the known giant planets and for the Earth and the Sun defines the very slow motion of the Sun relative to the solar system barycenter shows how the theory of gravity can account for irregularities in the motion of the Moon identifies the oblateness of the shape of the Earth accounts approximately for marine tides including phenomena of spring and neap tides by the perturbing and varying gravitational attractions of the Sun and Moon on the Earth s waters explains the precession of the equinoxes as an effect of the gravitational attraction of the Moon on the Earth s equatorial bulge and gives theoretical basis for numerous phenomena about comets and their elongated near parabolic orbits The opening sections of the Principia contain in revised and extended form nearly 13 all of the content of Newton s 1684 tract De motu corporum in gyrum The Principia begin with Definitions 14 and Axioms or Laws of Motion 15 and continues in three books Book 1 De motu corporum Edit Book 1 subtitled De motu corporum On the motion of bodies concerns motion in the absence of any resisting medium It opens with a collection of mathematical lemmas on the method of first and last ratios 16 a geometrical form of infinitesimal calculus 7 Newton s proof of Kepler s second law as described in the book If a continuous centripetal force red arrow is considered on the planet during its orbit the area of the triangles defined by the path of the planet will be the same This is true for any fixed time interval When the interval tends to zero the force can be considered instantaneous Click image for a detailed description The second section establishes relationships between centripetal forces and the law of areas now known as Kepler s second law Propositions 1 3 17 and relates circular velocity and radius of path curvature to radial force 18 Proposition 4 and relationships between centripetal forces varying as the inverse square of the distance to the center and orbits of conic section form Propositions 5 10 Propositions 11 31 19 establish properties of motion in paths of eccentric conic section form including ellipses and their relation with inverse square central forces directed to a focus and include Newton s theorem about ovals lemma 28 Propositions 43 45 20 are demonstration that in an eccentric orbit under centripetal force where the apse may move a steady non moving orientation of the line of apses is an indicator of an inverse square law of force Book 1 contains some proofs with little connection to real world dynamics But there are also sections with far reaching application to the solar system and universe Propositions 57 69 21 deal with the motion of bodies drawn to one another by centripetal forces This section is of primary interest for its application to the Solar System and includes Proposition 66 22 along with its 22 corollaries 23 here Newton took the first steps in the definition and study of the problem of the movements of three massive bodies subject to their mutually perturbing gravitational attractions a problem which later gained name and fame among other reasons for its great difficulty as the three body problem Propositions 70 84 24 deal with the attractive forces of spherical bodies The section contains Newton s proof that a massive spherically symmetrical body attracts other bodies outside itself as if all its mass were concentrated at its centre This fundamental result called the Shell theorem enables the inverse square law of gravitation to be applied to the real solar system to a very close degree of approximation Book 2 part 2 of De motu corporum Edit Part of the contents originally planned for the first book was divided out into a second book which largely concerns motion through resisting mediums Just as Newton examined consequences of different conceivable laws of attraction in Book 1 here he examines different conceivable laws of resistance thus Section 1 discusses resistance in direct proportion to velocity and Section 2 goes on to examine the implications of resistance in proportion to the square of velocity Book 2 also discusses in Section 5 hydrostatics and the properties of compressible fluids Newton also derives Boyle s law 25 The effects of air resistance on pendulums are studied in Section 6 along with Newton s account of experiments that he carried out to try to find out some characteristics of air resistance in reality by observing the motions of pendulums under different conditions Newton compares the resistance offered by a medium against motions of globes with different properties material weight size In Section 8 he derives rules to determine the speed of waves in fluids and relates them to the density and condensation Proposition 48 26 this would become very important in acoustics He assumes that these rules apply equally to light and sound and estimates that the speed of sound is around 1088 feet per second and can increase depending on the amount of water in air 27 Less of Book 2 has stood the test of time than of Books 1 and 3 and it has been said that Book 2 was largely written to refute a theory of Descartes which had some wide acceptance before Newton s work and for some time after According to Descartes s Cartesian theory of vortices planetary motions were produced by the whirling of fluid vortices that filled interplanetary space and carried the planets along with them 28 Newton wrote at the end of Book 2 29 his conclusion that the hypothesis of vortices was completely at odds with the astronomical phenomena and served not so much to explain as to confuse them Book 3 De mundi systemate Edit Book 3 subtitled De mundi systemate On the system of the world is an exposition of many consequences of universal gravitation especially its consequences for astronomy It builds upon the propositions of the previous books and applies them with further specificity than in Book 1 to the motions observed in the Solar System Here introduced by Proposition 22 30 and continuing in Propositions 25 35 31 are developed several of the features and irregularities of the orbital motion of the Moon especially the variation Newton lists the astronomical observations on which he relies 32 and establishes in a stepwise manner that the inverse square law of mutual gravitation applies to Solar System bodies starting with the satellites of Jupiter 33 and going on by stages to show that the law is of universal application 34 He also gives starting at Lemma 4 35 and Proposition 40 36 the theory of the motions of comets for which much data came from John Flamsteed and Edmond Halley and accounts for the tides 37 attempting quantitative estimates of the contributions of the Sun 38 and Moon 39 to the tidal motions and offers the first theory of the precession of the equinoxes 40 Book 3 also considers the harmonic oscillator in three dimensions and motion in arbitrary force laws In Book 3 Newton also made clear his heliocentric view of the Solar System modified in a somewhat modern way since already in the mid 1680s he recognised the deviation of the Sun from the centre of gravity of the Solar System 41 For Newton the common centre of gravity of the Earth the Sun and all the Planets is to be esteem d the Centre of the World 42 and that this centre either is at rest or moves uniformly forward in a right line 43 Newton rejected the second alternative after adopting the position that the centre of the system of the world is immoveable which is acknowledg d by all while some contend that the Earth others that the Sun is fix d in that centre 43 Newton estimated the mass ratios Sun Jupiter and Sun Saturn 44 and pointed out that these put the centre of the Sun usually a little way off the common center of gravity but only a little the distance at most would scarcely amount to one diameter of the Sun 45 Commentary on the Principia Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica news newspapers books scholar JSTOR July 2018 Learn how and when to remove this template message The sequence of definitions used in setting up dynamics in the Principia is recognisable in many textbooks today Newton first set out the definition of mass The quantity of matter is that which arises conjointly from its density and magnitude A body twice as dense in double the space is quadruple in quantity This quantity I designate by the name of body or of mass This was then used to define the quantity of motion today called momentum and the principle of inertia in which mass replaces the previous Cartesian notion of intrinsic force This then set the stage for the introduction of forces through the change in momentum of a body Curiously for today s readers the exposition looks dimensionally incorrect since Newton does not introduce the dimension of time in rates of changes of quantities He defined space and time not as they are well known to all Instead he defined true time and space as absolute 46 and explained Only I must observe that the vulgar conceive those quantities under no other notions but from the relation they bear to perceptible objects And it will be convenient to distinguish them into absolute and relative true and apparent mathematical and common instead of absolute places and motions we use relative ones and that without any inconvenience in common affairs but in philosophical discussions we ought to step back from our senses and consider things themselves distinct from what are only perceptible measures of them To some modern readers it can appear that some dynamical quantities recognised today were used in the Principia but not named The mathematical aspects of the first two books were so clearly consistent that they were easily accepted for example Locke asked Huygens whether he could trust the mathematical proofs and was assured about their correctness However the concept of an attractive force acting at a distance received a cooler response In his notes Newton wrote that the inverse square law arose naturally due to the structure of matter However he retracted this sentence in the published version where he stated that the motion of planets is consistent with an inverse square law but refused to speculate on the origin of the law Huygens and Leibniz noted that the law was incompatible with the notion of the aether From a Cartesian point of view therefore this was a faulty theory Newton s defence has been adopted since by many famous physicists he pointed out that the mathematical form of the theory had to be correct since it explained the data and he refused to speculate further on the basic nature of gravity The sheer number of phenomena that could be organised by the theory was so impressive that younger philosophers soon adopted the methods and language of the Principia Rules of Reason EditSee also s The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy 1846 BookIII Rules Perhaps to reduce the risk of public misunderstanding Newton included at the beginning of Book 3 in the second 1713 and third 1726 editions a section titled Rules of Reasoning in Philosophy In the four rules as they came finally to stand in the 1726 edition Newton effectively offers a methodology for handling unknown phenomena in nature and reaching towards explanations for them The four Rules of the 1726 edition run as follows omitting some explanatory comments that follow each We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances Therefore to the same natural effects we must as far as possible assign the same causes The qualities of bodies which admit neither intensification nor remission of degrees and which are found to belong to all bodies within the reach of our experiments are to be esteemed the universal qualities of all bodies whatsoever In experimental philosophy we are to look upon propositions inferred by general induction from phenomena as accurately or very nearly true not withstanding any contrary hypothesis that may be imagined till such time as other phenomena occur by which they may either be made more accurate or liable to exceptions This section of Rules for philosophy is followed by a listing of Phenomena in which are listed a number of mainly astronomical observations that Newton used as the basis for inferences later on as if adopting a consensus set of facts from the astronomers of his time Both the Rules and the Phenomena evolved from one edition of the Principia to the next Rule 4 made its appearance in the third 1726 edition Rules 1 3 were present as Rules in the second 1713 edition and predecessors of them were also present in the first edition of 1687 but there they had a different heading they were not given as Rules but rather in the first 1687 edition the predecessors of the three later Rules and of most of the later Phenomena were all lumped together under a single heading Hypotheses in which the third item was the predecessor of a heavy revision that gave the later Rule 3 From this textual evolution it appears that Newton wanted by the later headings Rules and Phenomena to clarify for his readers his view of the roles to be played by these various statements In the third 1726 edition of the Principia Newton explains each rule in an alternative way and or gives an example to back up what the rule is claiming The first rule is explained as a philosophers principle of economy The second rule states that if one cause is assigned to a natural effect then the same cause so far as possible must be assigned to natural effects of the same kind for example respiration in humans and in animals fires in the home and in the Sun or the reflection of light whether it occurs terrestrially or from the planets An extensive explanation is given of the third rule concerning the qualities of bodies and Newton discusses here the generalisation of observational results with a caution against making up fancies contrary to experiments and use of the rules to illustrate the observation of gravity and space Isaac Newton s statement of the four rules revolutionised the investigation of phenomena With these rules Newton could in principle begin to address all of the world s present unsolved mysteries He was able to use his new analytical method to replace that of Aristotle and he was able to use his method to tweak and update Galileo s experimental method The re creation of Galileo s method has never been significantly changed and in its substance scientists use it today citation needed General Scholium Edit Main article General Scholium The General Scholium is a concluding essay added to the second edition 1713 and amended in the third edition 1726 47 It is not to be confused with the General Scholium at the end of Book 2 Section 6 which discusses his pendulum experiments and resistance due to air water and other fluids Here Newton used the expression hypotheses non fingo I formulate no hypotheses 8 in response to criticisms of the first edition of the Principia Fingo is sometimes nowadays translated feign rather than the traditional frame although feign does not properly translate fingo Newton s gravitational attraction an invisible force able to act over vast distances had led to criticism that he had introduced occult agencies into science 48 Newton firmly rejected such criticisms and wrote that it was enough that the phenomena implied gravitational attraction as they did but the phenomena did not so far indicate the cause of this gravity and it was both unnecessary and improper to frame hypotheses of things not implied by the phenomena such hypotheses have no place in experimental philosophy in contrast to the proper way in which particular propositions are inferr d from the phenomena and afterwards rendered general by induction 49 Newton also underlined his criticism of the vortex theory of planetary motions of Descartes pointing to its incompatibility with the highly eccentric orbits of comets which carry them through all parts of the heavens indifferently Newton also gave theological argument From the system of the world he inferred the existence of a god along lines similar to what is sometimes called the argument from intelligent or purposive design It has been suggested that Newton gave an oblique argument for a unitarian conception of God and an implicit attack on the doctrine of the Trinity 50 51 The General Scholium does not address or attempt to refute the church doctrine it simply does not mention Jesus the Holy Ghost or the hypothesis of the Trinity Publishing the book EditThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2020 Learn how and when to remove this template message Halley and Newton s initial stimulus Edit In January 1684 Edmond Halley Christopher Wren and Robert Hooke had a conversation in which Hooke claimed to not only have derived the inverse square law but also all the laws of planetary motion Wren was unconvinced Hooke did not produce the claimed derivation although the others gave him time to do it and Halley who could derive the inverse square law for the restricted circular case by substituting Kepler s relation into Huygens formula for the centrifugal force but failed to derive the relation generally resolved to ask Newton 52 Halley s visits to Newton in 1684 thus resulted from Halley s debates about planetary motion with Wren and Hooke and they seem to have provided Newton with the incentive and spur to develop and write what became Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica Halley was at that time a Fellow and Council member of the Royal Society in London positions that in 1686 he resigned to become the Society s paid Clerk 53 Halley s visit to Newton in Cambridge in 1684 probably occurred in August 54 When Halley asked Newton s opinion on the problem of planetary motions discussed earlier that year between Halley Hooke and Wren 55 Newton surprised Halley by saying that he had already made the derivations some time ago but that he could not find the papers Matching accounts of this meeting come from Halley and Abraham De Moivre to whom Newton confided Halley then had to wait for Newton to find the results and in November 1684 Newton sent Halley an amplified version of whatever previous work Newton had done on the subject This took the form of a 9 page manuscript De motu corporum in gyrum Of the motion of bodies in an orbit the title is shown on some surviving copies although the lost original may have been without a title Newton s tract De motu corporum in gyrum which he sent to Halley in late 1684 derived what is now known as the three laws of Kepler assuming an inverse square law of force and generalised the result to conic sections It also extended the methodology by adding the solution of a problem on the motion of a body through a resisting medium The contents of De motu so excited Halley by their mathematical and physical originality and far reaching implications for astronomical theory that he immediately went to visit Newton again in November 1684 to ask Newton to let the Royal Society have more of such work 56 The results of their meetings clearly helped to stimulate Newton with the enthusiasm needed to take his investigations of mathematical problems much further in this area of physical science and he did so in a period of highly concentrated work that lasted at least until mid 1686 57 Newton s single minded attention to his work generally and to his project during this time is shown by later reminiscences from his secretary and copyist of the period Humphrey Newton His account tells of Isaac Newton s absorption in his studies how he sometimes forgot his food or his sleep or the state of his clothes and how when he took a walk in his garden he would sometimes rush back to his room with some new thought not even waiting to sit before beginning to write it down 58 Other evidence also shows Newton s absorption in the Principia Newton for years kept up a regular programme of chemical or alchemical experiments and he normally kept dated notes of them but for a period from May 1684 to April 1686 Newton s chemical notebooks have no entries at all 59 So it seems that Newton abandoned pursuits to which he was formally dedicated and did very little else for well over a year and a half but concentrated on developing and writing what became his great work The first of the three constituent books was sent to Halley for the printer in spring 1686 and the other two books somewhat later The complete work published by Halley at his own financial risk 60 appeared in July 1687 Newton had also communicated De motu to Flamsteed and during the period of composition he exchanged a few letters with Flamsteed about observational data on the planets eventually acknowledging Flamsteed s contributions in the published version of the Principia of 1687 Preliminary version Edit Newton s own first edition copy of his Principia with handwritten corrections for the second edition The process of writing that first edition of the Principia went through several stages and drafts some parts of the preliminary materials still survive while others are lost except for fragments and cross references in other documents 61 Surviving materials show that Newton up to some time in 1685 conceived his book as a two volume work The first volume was to be titled De motu corporum Liber primus with contents that later appeared in extended form as Book 1 of the Principia citation needed A fair copy draft of Newton s planned second volume De motu corporum Liber Secundus survives its completion dated to about the summer of 1685 It covers the application of the results of Liber primus to the Earth the Moon the tides the Solar System and the universe in this respect it has much the same purpose as the final Book 3 of the Principia but it is written much less formally and is more easily read citation needed Titlepage and frontispiece of the third edition London 1726 John Rylands Library It is not known just why Newton changed his mind so radically about the final form of what had been a readable narrative in De motu corporum Liber Secundus of 1685 but he largely started afresh in a new tighter and less accessible mathematical style eventually to produce Book 3 of the Principia as we know it Newton frankly admitted that this change of style was deliberate when he wrote that he had first composed this book in a popular method that it might be read by many but to prevent the disputes by readers who could not lay aside the ir prejudices he had reduced it into the form of propositions in the mathematical way which should be read by those only who had first made themselves masters of the principles established in the preceding books 62 The final Book 3 also contained in addition some further important quantitative results arrived at by Newton in the meantime especially about the theory of the motions of comets and some of the perturbations of the motions of the Moon The result was numbered Book 3 of the Principia rather than Book 2 because in the meantime drafts of Liber primus had expanded and Newton had divided it into two books The new and final Book 2 was concerned largely with the motions of bodies through resisting mediums 63 But the Liber Secundus of 1685 can still be read today Even after it was superseded by Book 3 of the Principia it survived complete in more than one manuscript After Newton s death in 1727 the relatively accessible character of its writing encouraged the publication of an English translation in 1728 by persons still unknown not authorised by Newton s heirs It appeared under the English title A Treatise of the System of the World 64 This had some amendments relative to Newton s manuscript of 1685 mostly to remove cross references that used obsolete numbering to cite the propositions of an early draft of Book 1 of the Principia Newton s heirs shortly afterwards published the Latin version in their possession also in 1728 under the new title De Mundi Systemate amended to update cross references citations and diagrams to those of the later editions of the Principia making it look superficially as if it had been written by Newton after the Principia rather than before 65 The System of the World was sufficiently popular to stimulate two revisions with similar changes as in the Latin printing a second edition 1731 and a corrected reprint 66 of the second edition 1740 Halley s role as publisher Edit The text of the first of the three books of the Principia was presented to the Royal Society at the close of April 1686 Hooke made some priority claims but failed to substantiate them causing some delay When Hooke s claim was made known to Newton who hated disputes Newton threatened to withdraw and suppress Book 3 altogether but Halley showing considerable diplomatic skills tactfully persuaded Newton to withdraw his threat and let it go forward to publication Samuel Pepys as president gave his imprimatur on 30 June 1686 licensing the book for publication The Society had just spent its book budget on De Historia piscium 67 and the cost of publication was borne by Edmund Halley who was also then acting as publisher of the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society 68 the book appeared in summer 1687 69 After Halley had personally financed the publication of Principia he was informed that the society could no longer afford to provide him the promised annual salary of 50 Instead Halley was paid with leftover copies of De Historia piscium 70 Historical context EditFurther information History of gravitational theory Beginnings of the Scientific Revolution Edit Nicolaus Copernicus 1473 1543 formulated a heliocentric or Sun centered model of the universe Nicolaus Copernicus had moved the Earth away from the center of the universe with the heliocentric theory for which he presented evidence in his book De revolutionibus orbium coelestium On the revolutions of the heavenly spheres published in 1543 Johannes Kepler wrote the book Astronomia nova A new astronomy in 1609 setting out the evidence that planets move in elliptical orbits with the Sun at one focus and that planets do not move with constant speed along this orbit Rather their speed varies so that the line joining the centres of the sun and a planet sweeps out equal areas in equal times To these two laws he added a third a decade later in his 1619 book Harmonices Mundi Harmonies of the world This law sets out a proportionality between the third power of the characteristic distance of a planet from the Sun and the square of the length of its year Italian physicist Galileo Galilei 1564 1642 a champion of the Copernican model of the universe and a figure in the history of kinematics and classical mechanicsThe foundation of modern dynamics was set out in Galileo s book Dialogo sopra i due massimi sistemi del mondo Dialogue on the two main world systems where the notion of inertia was implicit and used In addition Galileo s experiments with inclined planes had yielded precise mathematical relations between elapsed time and acceleration velocity or distance for uniform and uniformly accelerated motion of bodies Descartes book of 1644 Principia philosophiae Principles of philosophy stated that bodies can act on each other only through contact a principle that induced people among them himself to hypothesize a universal medium as the carrier of interactions such as light and gravity the aether Newton was criticized for apparently introducing forces that acted at distance without any medium 48 Not until the development of particle theory was Descartes notion vindicated when it was possible to describe all interactions like the strong weak and electromagnetic fundamental interactions using mediating gauge bosons 71 and gravity through hypothesized gravitons 72 Newton s role Edit Newton had studied these books or in some cases secondary sources based on them and taken notes entitled Quaestiones quaedam philosophicae Questions about philosophy during his days as an undergraduate During this period 1664 1666 he created the basis of calculus and performed the first experiments in the optics of colour At this time his proof that white light was a combination of primary colours found via prismatics replaced the prevailing theory of colours and received an overwhelmingly favourable response and occasioned bitter disputes with Robert Hooke and others which forced him to sharpen his ideas to the point where he already composed sections of his later book Opticks by the 1670s in response Work on calculus is shown in various papers and letters including two to Leibniz He became a fellow of the Royal Society and the second Lucasian Professor of Mathematics succeeding Isaac Barrow at Trinity College Cambridge Newton s early work on motion Edit In the 1660s Newton studied the motion of colliding bodies and deduced that the centre of mass of two colliding bodies remains in uniform motion Surviving manuscripts of the 1660s also show Newton s interest in planetary motion and that by 1669 he had shown for a circular case of planetary motion that the force he called endeavour to recede now called centrifugal force had an inverse square relation with distance from the center 73 After his 1679 1680 correspondence with Hooke described below Newton adopted the language of inward or centripetal force According to Newton scholar J Bruce Brackenridge although much has been made of the change in language and difference of point of view as between centrifugal or centripetal forces the actual computations and proofs remained the same either way They also involved the combination of tangential and radial displacements which Newton was making in the 1660s The difference between the centrifugal and centripetal points of view though a significant change of perspective did not change the analysis 74 Newton also clearly expressed the concept of linear inertia in the 1660s for this Newton was indebted to Descartes work published 1644 75 Controversy with Hooke Edit Artist s impression of English polymath Robert Hooke 1635 1703 Hooke published his ideas about gravitation in the 1660s and again in 1674 He argued for an attracting principle of gravitation in Micrographia of 1665 in a 1666 Royal Society lecture On gravity and again in 1674 when he published his ideas about the System of the World in somewhat developed form as an addition to An Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth from Observations 76 Hooke clearly postulated mutual attractions between the Sun and planets in a way that increased with nearness to the attracting body along with a principle of linear inertia Hooke s statements up to 1674 made no mention however that an inverse square law applies or might apply to these attractions Hooke s gravitation was also not yet universal though it approached universality more closely than previous hypotheses 77 Hooke also did not provide accompanying evidence or mathematical demonstration On these two aspects Hooke stated in 1674 Now what these several degrees of gravitational attraction are I have not yet experimentally verified indicating that he did not yet know what law the gravitation might follow and as to his whole proposal This I only hint at present having my self many other things in hand which I would first compleat and therefore cannot so well attend it i e prosecuting this Inquiry 76 In November 1679 Hooke began an exchange of letters with Newton of which the full text is now published 78 Hooke told Newton that Hooke had been appointed to manage the Royal Society s correspondence 79 and wished to hear from members about their researches or their views about the researches of others and as if to whet Newton s interest he asked what Newton thought about various matters giving a whole list mentioning compounding the celestial motions of the planets of a direct motion by the tangent and an attractive motion towards the central body and my hypothesis of the lawes or causes of springinesse and then a new hypothesis from Paris about planetary motions which Hooke described at length and then efforts to carry out or improve national surveys the difference of latitude between London and Cambridge and other items Newton s reply offered a fansy of my own about a terrestrial experiment not a proposal about celestial motions which might detect the Earth s motion by the use of a body first suspended in air and then dropped to let it fall The main point was to indicate how Newton thought the falling body could experimentally reveal the Earth s motion by its direction of deviation from the vertical but he went on hypothetically to consider how its motion could continue if the solid Earth had not been in the way on a spiral path to the centre Hooke disagreed with Newton s idea of how the body would continue to move 80 A short further correspondence developed and towards the end of it Hooke writing on 6 January 1680 to Newton communicated his supposition that the Attraction always is in a duplicate proportion to the Distance from the Center Reciprocall and Consequently that the Velocity will be in a subduplicate proportion to the Attraction and Consequently as Kepler Supposes Reciprocall to the Distance 81 Hooke s inference about the velocity was actually incorrect 82 In 1686 when the first book of Newton s Principia was presented to the Royal Society Hooke claimed that Newton had obtained from him the notion of the rule of the decrease of Gravity being reciprocally as the squares of the distances from the Center At the same time according to Edmond Halley s contemporary report Hooke agreed that the Demonstration of the Curves generated therby was wholly Newton s 78 A recent assessment about the early history of the inverse square law is that by the late 1660s the assumption of an inverse proportion between gravity and the square of distance was rather common and had been advanced by a number of different people for different reasons 83 Newton himself had shown in the 1660s that for planetary motion under a circular assumption force in the radial direction had an inverse square relation with distance from the center 73 Newton faced in May 1686 with Hooke s claim on the inverse square law denied that Hooke was to be credited as author of the idea giving reasons including the citation of prior work by others before Hooke 78 Newton also firmly claimed that even if it had happened that he had first heard of the inverse square proportion from Hooke which it had not he would still have some rights to it in view of his mathematical developments and demonstrations which enabled observations to be relied on as evidence of its accuracy while Hooke without mathematical demonstrations and evidence in favour of the supposition could only guess according to Newton that it was approximately valid at great distances from the center 78 The background described above shows there was basis for Newton to deny deriving the inverse square law from Hooke On the other hand Newton did accept and acknowledge in all editions of the Principia that Hooke but not exclusively Hooke had separately appreciated the inverse square law in the Solar System Newton acknowledged Wren Hooke and Halley in this connection in the Scholium to Proposition 4 in Book 1 84 Newton also acknowledged to Halley that his correspondence with Hooke in 1679 80 had reawakened his dormant interest in astronomical matters but that did not mean according to Newton that Hooke had told Newton anything new or original yet am I not beholden to him for any light into that business but only for the diversion he gave me from my other studies to think on these things amp for his dogmaticalness in writing as if he had found the motion in the Ellipsis which inclined me to try it 78 Newton s reawakening interest in astronomy received further stimulus by the appearance of a comet in the winter of 1680 1681 on which he corresponded with John Flamsteed 85 In 1759 decades after the deaths of both Newton and Hooke Alexis Clairaut mathematical astronomer eminent in his own right in the field of gravitational studies made his assessment after reviewing what Hooke had published on gravitation One must not think that this idea of Hooke diminishes Newton s glory Clairaut wrote The example of Hooke serves to show what a distance there is between a truth that is glimpsed and a truth that is demonstrated 86 87 Location of early edition copies Edit A page from the Principia It has been estimated that as many as 750 copies 88 of the first edition were printed by the Royal Society and it is quite remarkable that so many copies of this small first edition are still in existence but it may be because the original Latin text was more revered than read 89 A survey published in 1953 located 189 surviving copies 90 with nearly 200 further copies located by the most recent survey published in 2020 suggesting that the initial print run was larger than previously thought 91 However more recent book historical and bibliographical research has examined those prior claims and concludes that Macomber s earlier estimation of 500 copies is likely correct 92 Cambridge University Library has Newton s own copy of the first edition with handwritten notes for the second edition 93 The Earl Gregg Swem Library at the College of William amp Mary has a first edition copy of the Principia 94 Throughout are Latin annotations written by Thomas S Savage These handwritten notes are currently being researched at The College 95 The Frederick E Brasch Collection of Newton and Newtoniana in Stanford University also has a first edition of the Principia 96 A first edition forms part of the Crawford Collection housed at the Royal Observatory Edinburgh 97 The Uppsala University Library owns a first edition copy which was stolen in the 1960s and returned to the library in 2009 98 The Folger Shakespeare Library in Washington D C owns a first edition as well as a 1713 second edition The Huntington Library in San Marino California owns Isaac Newton s personal copy with annotations in Newton s own hand 99 The Bodmer Library in Switzerland keeps a copy of the original edition that was owned by Leibniz It contains handwritten notes by Leibniz in particular concerning the controversy of who first formulated calculus although he published it later Newton argued that he developed it earlier 100 The Iron Library in Switzerland holds a first edition copy that was formerly in the library of the physicist Ernst Mach 101 The University of St Andrews Library holds both variants of the first edition as well as copies of the 1713 and 1726 editions 102 The Fisher Library in the University of Sydney has a first edition copy annotated by a mathematician of uncertain identity and corresponding notes from Newton himself 103 The Linda Hall Library holds the first edition as well as a copy of the 1713 and 1726 editions The Teleki Bolyai Library of Targu Mureș holds a 2 line imprint first edition One book is also located at Vasaskolan Gavle in Sweden 104 Dalhousie University has a copy as part of the William I Morse collection McGill University in Montreal has the copy once owned by Sir William Osler The University of Toronto has a copy in the Thomas Fisher Rare Book Collection In 2016 a first edition sold for 3 7 million 105 The second edition 1713 were printed in 750 copies and the third edition 1726 were printed in 1 250 copies A facsimile edition based on the 3rd edition of 1726 but with variant readings from earlier editions and important annotations was published in 1972 by Alexandre Koyre and I Bernard Cohen 10 Later editions Edit Newton s personal copy of the first edition of Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica annotated by him for the second edition Displayed at Cambridge University Library Second edition 1713 Edit Second edition opened to title page Two later editions were published by Newton Newton had been urged to make a new edition of the Principia since the early 1690s partly because copies of the first edition had already become very rare and expensive within a few years after 1687 106 Newton referred to his plans for a second edition in correspondence with Flamsteed in November 1694 107 Newton also maintained annotated copies of the first edition specially bound up with interleaves on which he could note his revisions two of these copies still survive 108 but he had not completed the revisions by 1708 Newton had almost severed connections with one would be editor Nicolas Fatio de Duillier and another David Gregory seems not to have met with his approval and was also terminally ill dying in 1708 Nevertheless reasons were accumulating not to put off the new edition any longer 109 Richard Bentley master of Trinity College persuaded Newton to allow him to undertake a second edition and in June 1708 Bentley wrote to Newton with a specimen print of the first sheet at the same time expressing the unfulfilled hope that Newton had made progress towards finishing the revisions 110 It seems that Bentley then realised that the editorship was technically too difficult for him and with Newton s consent he appointed Roger Cotes Plumian professor of astronomy at Trinity to undertake the editorship for him as a kind of deputy but Bentley still made the publishing arrangements and had the financial responsibility and profit The correspondence of 1709 1713 shows Cotes reporting to two masters Bentley and Newton and managing and often correcting a large and important set of revisions to which Newton sometimes could not give his full attention 111 Under the weight of Cotes efforts but impeded by priority disputes between Newton and Leibniz 112 and by troubles at the Mint 113 Cotes was able to announce publication to Newton on 30 June 1713 114 Bentley sent Newton only six presentation copies Cotes was unpaid Newton omitted any acknowledgement to Cotes Among those who gave Newton corrections for the Second Edition were Firmin Abauzit Roger Cotes and David Gregory However Newton omitted acknowledgements to some because of the priority disputes John Flamsteed the Astronomer Royal suffered this especially The Second Edition was the basis of the first edition to be printed abroad which appeared in Amsterdam in 1714 Third edition 1726 Edit After his serious illness in 1722 and after the appearance of a reprint of the second edition in Amsterdam in 1723 the 80 year old Newton began to revise once again the Principia in the fall of 1723 The third edition was published 25 March 1726 under the stewardship of Henry Pemberton M D a man of the greatest skill in these matters Pemberton later said that this recognition was worth more to him than the two hundred guinea award from Newton 115 In 1739 1742 two French priests Peres Thomas LeSeur and Francois Jacquier of the Minim order but sometimes erroneously identified as Jesuits produced with the assistance of J L Calandrini an extensively annotated version of the Principia in the 3rd edition of 1726 Sometimes this is referred to as the Jesuit edition it was much used and reprinted more than once in Scotland during the 19th century 116 Emilie du Chatelet also made a translation of Newton s Principia into French Unlike LeSeur and Jacquier s edition hers was a complete translation of Newton s three books and their prefaces She also included a Commentary section where she fused the three books into a much clearer and easier to understand summary She included an analytical section where she applied the new mathematics of calculus to Newton s most controversial theories Previously geometry was the standard mathematics used to analyse theories Du Chatelet s translation is the only complete one to have been done in French and hers remains the standard French translation to this day 117 Translations Edit Title page to an 1848 copy of The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy translated into English by Andrew Motte Four full English translations of Newton s Principia have appeared all based on Newton s 3rd edition of 1726 The first from 1729 by Andrew Motte 3 was described by Newton scholar I Bernard Cohen in 1968 as still of enormous value in conveying to us the sense of Newton s words in their own time and it is generally faithful to the original clear and well written 118 The 1729 version was the basis for several republications often incorporating revisions among them a widely used modernised English version of 1934 which appeared under the editorial name of Florian Cajori though completed and published only some years after his death Cohen pointed out ways in which the 18th century terminology and punctuation of the 1729 translation might be confusing to modern readers but he also made severe criticisms of the 1934 modernised English version and showed that the revisions had been made without regard to the original also demonstrating gross errors that provided the final impetus to our decision to produce a wholly new translation 119 The second full English translation into modern English is the work that resulted from this decision by collaborating translators I Bernard Cohen Anne Whitman and Julia Budenz it was published in 1999 with a guide by way of introduction 120 The third such translation is due to Ian Bruce and appears with many other translations of mathematical works of the 17th and 18th centuries on his website 121 The fourth such translation is due to Charles Leedham Green and is published as The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Isaac Newton Translated and Annotated by C R Leedham Green 122 The main aim of this translation by a research mathematician is to be less opaque and truer to the underlying mathematics and physics than the Cohen Whitman Budenz translation Dana Densmore and William H Donahue have published a translation of the work s central argument published in 1996 along with expansion of included proofs and ample commentary 123 The book was developed as a textbook for classes at St John s College and the aim of this translation is to be faithful to the Latin text 124 In 2014 British astronaut Tim Peake named his upcoming mission to the International Space Station Principia after the book in honour of Britain s greatest scientist 125 Tim Peake s Principia launched on December 15 2015 aboard Soyuz TMA 19M 126 See also EditAtomism Elements of the Philosophy of Newton Isaac Newton s occult studiesReferences Edit The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Encyclopaedia Britannica London Among versions of the Principia online 1 a b Volume 1 of the 1729 English translation is available as an online scan limited parts of the 1729 translation misidentified as based on the 1687 edition have also been transcribed online J M Steele University of Toronto review online from Canadian Association of Physicists Archived 1 April 2010 at the Wayback Machine of N Guicciardini s Reading the Principia The Debate on Newton s Mathematical Methods for Natural Philosophy from 1687 to 1736 Cambridge UP 1999 a book which also states summary before title page that the Principia is considered one of the masterpieces in the history of science in French Alexis Clairaut Du systeme du monde dans les principes de la gravitation universelle in Histoires amp Memoires de l Academie Royale des Sciences for 1745 published 1749 at p 329 according to a note on p 329 Clairaut s paper was read at a session of November 1747 G E Smith Newton s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2008 Edition E N Zalta ed a b The content of infinitesimal calculus in the Principia was recognized both in Newton s lifetime and later among others by the Marquis de l Hospital whose 1696 book Analyse des infiniment petits Infinitesimal analysis stated in its preface about the Principia that nearly all of it is of this calculus lequel est presque tout de ce calcul See also D T Whiteside 1970 The mathematical principles underlying Newton s Principia Mathematica Journal for the History of Astronomy vol 1 1970 116 138 especially at p 120 a b Or frame no hypotheses as traditionally translated at vol 2 p 392 in the 1729 English version Newton Isaac Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica Newton s personally annotated 1st edition a b c In Latin Isaac Newton s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica the Third edition 1726 with variant readings assembled and ed by Alexandre Koyre and I Bernard Cohen with the assistance of Anne Whitman Cambridge MA 1972 Harvard UP Hermann Claudine 2008 La traduction et les commentaires des Principia de Newton par Emilie du Chatelet Bibnum Textes Fondateurs de la Science in French doi 10 4000 bibnum 722 S2CID 164354455 translate google co uk amelioree From Motte s translation of 1729 at 3rd page of Author s Preface and see also J W Herivel The background to Newton s Principia Oxford University Press 1965 The De motu corporum in gyrum article indicates the topics that reappear in the Principia Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Definitions The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 1 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Axioms or Laws of Motion The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 19 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Section I The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 41 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Section II The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 57 This relationship between circular curvature speed and radial force now often known as Huygens formula was independently found by Newton in the 1660s and by Huygens in the 1650s the conclusion was published without proof by Huygens in 1673 This was given by Isaac Newton through his Inverse Square Law Newton Sir Isaac Machin John 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte pp 79 153 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Section IX The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 177 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Section XI The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 218 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Section XI Proposition LXVI The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 234 Newton Sir Isaac Machin John 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte pp 239 256 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Section XII The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume I B Motte p 263 Gillispie Charles Coulston 1960 The Edge of Objectivity An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas Princeton University Press p 254 ISBN 0 691 02350 6 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Proposition 48 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 176 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Scholium to proposition 50 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 181 Eric J Aiton The Cartesian vortex theory chapter 11 in Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise of astrophysics Part A Tycho Brahe to Newton eds R Taton amp C Wilson Cambridge Cambridge University press 1989 at pp 207 221 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Scholium to proposition 53 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 197 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 252 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 262 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Phaenomena The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 206 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 213 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 220 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 323 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 332 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 255 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 305 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 306 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 320 See Curtis Wilson The Newtonian achievement in astronomy pages 233 274 in R Taton amp C Wilson eds 1989 The General History of Astronomy Volume 2A at page 233 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Proposition 12 Corollary The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 233 a b Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Proposition 11 amp preceding Hypothesis The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 232 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Proposition 8 Corollary 2 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 228 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Proposition 12 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte pp 232 233 Newton s position is seen to go beyond literal Copernican heliocentrism practically to the modern position in regard to the Solar System barycenter see Barycenter Inside or outside the Sun Knudsen Jens M Hjorth Poul 2012 Elements of Newtonian Mechanics illustrated ed Springer Science amp Business Media p 30 ISBN 978 3 642 97599 8 Extract of page 30 See online Principia 1729 translation vol 2 Books 2 amp 3 starting at page 387 of volume 2 1729 a b Edelglass et al Matter and Mind ISBN 0 940262 45 2 p 54 See online Principia 1729 translation vol 2 Books 2 amp 3 at page 392 of volume 2 1729 Snobelen Stephen The General Scholium to Isaac Newton s Principia mathematica Archived from the original on 8 June 2008 Retrieved 31 May 2008 Ducheyne Steffen The General Scholium Some notes on Newton s published and unpublished endeavours PDF Lias Sources and Documents Relating to the Early Modern History of Ideas 33 2 223 274 Archived from the original PDF on 17 December 2008 Retrieved 19 November 2008 Paraphrase of 1686 report by Halley in H W Turnbull ed Correspondence of Isaac Newton Vol 2 cited above pp 431 448 Cook 1998 A Cook Edmond Halley Charting the Heavens and the Seas Oxford University Press 1998 at pp 147 and 152 As dated e g by D T Whiteside in The Prehistory of the Principia from 1664 to 1686 Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 45 1991 11 61 Cook 1998 at p 147 Westfall 1980 R S Westfall Never at Rest A Biography of Isaac Newton Cambridge University Press 1980 at p 404 Cook 1998 at p 151 Westfall 1980 at p 406 also pp 191 192 Westfall 1980 at p 406 n 15 Westfall 1980 at pp 153 156 The fundamental study of Newton s progress in writing the Principia is in I Bernard Cohen s Introduction to Newton s Principia Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1971 at part 2 The writing and the first publication of the Principia pp 47 142 Newton Sir Isaac 1729 Introduction to Book 3 The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Volume II Benjamin Motte p 200 Smith G 2008 Newton s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Zalta E N Ed Metaphysics Research Lab Dept of Philosophy Stanford University Winter 2008 ISSN 1095 5054 Retrieved 21 October 2022 Newton Isaac 1728 A Treatise of the System of the World I Bernard Cohen Introduction to Newton s A Treatise of the System of the World facsimile of second English edition of 1731 London Dawsons of Pall Mall 1969 reprinted in A Treatise of the System of the World Dover Phoenix Editions 2004 ISBN 0 486 43880 5 Newton Sir Isaac 1740 The System of the World Demonstrated in an Easy and Popular Manner Being a Proper Introduction to the Most Sublime Philosophy By the Illustrious Sir Isaac Newton Translated into English A corrected reprint of the second edition Richard Westfall 1980 Never at Rest p 453 ISBN 0 521 27435 4 Clerk Halley s 29 October 2013 Halley and the Principia Halley s Log Retrieved 7 December 2019 Museum of London exhibit including facsimile of title page from John Flamsteed s copy of 1687 edition of Newton s Principia Museumoflondon org uk Archived from the original on 31 March 2012 Retrieved 16 March 2012 Bill Bryson 2004 A Short History of Nearly Everything Random House Inc p 74 ISBN 978 0 385 66004 4 The Henryk Niewodniczanski Institute of Nuclear Physics Particle Physics and Astrophysics Research a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a Missing or empty url help Rovelli Carlo 2000 Notes for a brief history of quantum gravity arXiv gr qc 0006061 a b D T Whiteside The pre history of the Principia from 1664 to 1686 Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 45 1991 pages 11 61 especially at 13 20 2 See J Bruce Brackenridge The key to Newton s dynamics the Kepler problem and the Principia University of California Press 1995 especially at pages 20 21 See page 10 in D T Whiteside Before the Principia the maturing of Newton s thoughts on dynamical astronomy 1664 1684 Journal for the History of Astronomy i 1970 pages 5 19 a b Hooke s 1674 statement in An Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth from Observations is available in online facsimile here See page 239 in Curtis Wilson 1989 The Newtonian achievement in astronomy ch 13 pages 233 274 in Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise of astrophysics 2A Tycho Brahe to Newton CUP 1989 a b c d e H W Turnbull ed Correspondence of Isaac Newton Vol 2 1676 1687 Cambridge University Press 1960 giving the Hooke Newton correspondence of November 1679 to January 1679 80 at pp 297 314 and the 1686 correspondence over Hooke s priority claim at pp 431 448 Correspondence vol 2 already cited at p 297 Several commentators have followed Hooke in calling Newton s spiral path mistaken or even a blunder but there are also the following facts a that Hooke left out of account Newton s specific statement that the motion resulted from dropping a heavy body suspended in the Air i e a resisting medium see Newton to Hooke 28 November 1679 document 236 at page 301 Correspondence vol 2 cited above and compare Hooke s report to the Royal Society on 11 December 1679 where Hooke reported the matter supposing no resistance see D Gjertsen Newton Handbook 1986 at page 259 and b that Hooke s reply of 9 December 1679 to Newton considered the cases of motion both with and without air resistance The resistance free path was what Hooke called an elliptueid but a line in Hooke s diagram showing the path for his case of air resistance was though elongated also another inward spiralling path ending at the Earth s centre Hooke wrote where the Medium has a power of impeding and destroying its motion the curve in wch it would move would be some what like the Line AIKLMNOP amp c and would terminate in the center C Hooke s path including air resistance was therefore to this extent like Newton s see Correspondence vol 2 cited above at pages 304 306 document 237 with accompanying figure The diagrams are also available online see Curtis Wilson chapter 13 in Planetary Astronomy from the Renaissance to the Rise of Astrophysics Part A Tycho Brahe to Newton Cambridge UP 1989 at page 241 showing Newton s 1679 diagram with spiral and extract of his letter also at page 242 showing Hooke s 1679 diagram including two paths closed curve and spiral Newton pointed out in his later correspondence over the priority claim that the descent in a spiral is true in a resisting medium such as our air is see Correspondence vol 2 cited above at page 433 document 286 See page 309 in Correspondence of Isaac Newton Vol 2 cited above at document 239 See Curtis Wilson 1989 at page 244 See Meanest foundations and nobler superstructures Hooke Newton and the Compounding of the Celestiall Motions of the Planetts Ofer Gal 2003 at page 9 See for example the 1729 English translation of the Principia at page 66 R S Westfall Never at Rest 1980 at pages 391 292 The second extract is quoted and translated in W W Rouse Ball An Essay on Newton s Principia London and New York Macmillan 1893 at page 69 The original statements by Clairaut in French are found with orthography here as in the original in Explication abregee du systeme du monde et explication des principaux phenomenes astronomiques tiree des Principes de M Newton 1759 at Introduction section IX page 6 Il ne faut pas croire que cette idee de Hook diminue la gloire de M Newton and L exemple de Hook serves a faire voir quelle distance il y a entre une verite entrevue amp une verite demontree California Institute of Technology 10 November 2020 News Release 10 NOV 2020 Hundreds of copies of Newton s Principia found in new census Findings suggest that Isaac Newton s 17th century masterpiece was more widely read EurekAlert Retrieved 11 November 2020 Henry P Macomber Census of Owners of 1687 First and 1726 Presentation Edition of Newton s Principia The Papers of the Bibliographical Society of America volume 47 1953 pages 269 300 at page 269 Macomber op cit page 270 Feingold Mordechai and Svorencik Andrej 2020 A preliminary census of copies of the first edition of Newton s Principia 1687 Annals of Science 77 3 pages 253 348 Dean Jason W and Cumby Jamie 2021 Principles of Principia Some Notes on the Print Run for the First Edition The Book Collector 70 3 pages 418 435 Newton Isaac Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica Cambridge Digital Library Retrieved 3 July 2013 Newton Isaac 1687 Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica in Latin Swem Library Jussu Societatis Regiae ac Typis Josephi Streater Archived from the original on 15 December 2012 Principia mystery annotations We re pretty sure whodunit but what was he thinking 4 March 2020 Special Collections amp University Archives stanford edu The Crawford collection at the Royal Observatory Edinburgh The Royal Observatory Edinburgh Retrieved 3 July 2013 Newton s book back in Uppsala University Library Uppsala University Retrieved 10 May 2014 Beautiful Science Ideas that Changed the World Astronomy Retrieved 2 January 2016 A scientific gem Isaac Newton 1643 1727 Retrieved 5 July 2016 Lork Tim December 2021 Chapter 22 Principia Echoes from the Vault Echoes from the Vault Retrieved 6 November 2017 Annotated first edition copy of Newton s Principia University of Sydney Library University of Sydney Retrieved 17 April 2019 Westrin Stefan 2 September 2012 Boktjuven pa Vasa Arbetarbladet in Swedish Retrieved 20 June 2020 Rawlinson Kevin 15 December 2016 Isaac Newton masterwork becomes most expensive science book sold The Guardian Retrieved 19 December 2016 The Correspondence of Isaac Newton vol 4 Cambridge University Press 1967 at pp 519 n 2 The Correspondence of Isaac Newton vol 4 Cambridge University press 1967 at p 42 I Bernard Cohen Introduction to the Principia Cambridge 1971 Richard S Westfall Never at Rest A Biography of Isaac Newton Cambridge U Press 1980 ISBN 0 521 23143 4 at p 699 The Correspondence of Isaac Newton vol 4 Cambridge University press 1967 at pp 518 520 The Correspondence of Isaac Newton vol 5 Cambridge University press 1975 Bentley s letter to Newton of October 1709 at pp 7 8 describes Cotes perhaps unenviable position in relation to his master Bentley You need not be so shy of giving Mr Cotes too much trouble he has more esteem for you and obligations to you than to think that trouble too grievous but however he does it at my Orders to whom he owes more than that Westfall pp 712 716 Westfall pp 751 760 Westfall p 750 Westfall p 802 In Latin Isaac Newton Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica volume 1 of a facsimile of a reprint 1833 of the 3rd 1726 edition as annotated in 1740 42 by Thomas LeSeur amp Francois Jacquier with the assistance of J L Calandrini See Translating Newton s Principia The Marquise du Chatelet s Revisions and Additions for a French Audience Author Judith P Zinsser Source Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London Vol 55 No 2 May 2001 pp 227 245 I Bernard Cohen 1968 Introduction at page i to facsimile reprint of 1729 English translation of Newton s Principia London 1968 Dawsons of Pall Mall See pages 29 37 in I Bernard Cohen 1999 A Guide to Newton s Principia published as an introduction to Isaac Newton The Principia Mathematical principles of natural philosophy a new translation by I Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman University of California Press 1999 Isaac Newton The Principia Mathematical principles of natural philosophy a new translation by I Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman preceded by A Guide to Newton s Principia by I Bernard Cohen University of California Press 1999 ISBN 978 0 520 08816 0 ISBN 978 0 520 08817 7 Ian Bruce http www 17centurymaths com C R Leedham Green editor The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy CUP 2021 ISBN 978 1107020658 Dana Densmore and William H Donahue Newton s Principia The Central Argument Translation Notes and Expanded Proofs Green Lion Press 3rd edition 2003 ISBN 978 1 888009 23 1 978 1 888009 23 1 Densmore and Donahue pp xv xvi Ghosh Pallab 17 July 2014 Tim Peake mission name pays tribute to Isaac Newton BBC News Roscosmos Announces New Soyuz Progress Launch Dates NASA 9 June 2015 Further reading EditMiller Laura Reading Popular Newtonianism Print the Principia and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science University of Virginia Press 2018 online review Alexandre Koyre Newtonian studies London Chapman and Hall 1965 I Bernard Cohen Introduction to Newton sPrincipia Harvard University Press 1971 Richard S Westfall Force in Newton s physics the science of dynamics in the seventeenth century New York American Elsevier 1971 S Chandrasekhar Newton s Principia for the common reader New York Oxford University Press 1995 Guicciardini N 2005 Philosophia Naturalis in Grattan Guinness I ed Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics Elsevier 59 87 Andrew Janiak Newton as Philosopher Cambridge University Press 2008 Francois De Gandt Force and geometry in Newton s Principia trans Curtis Wilson Princeton NJ Princeton University Press c1995 Steffen Ducheyne The main Business of Natural Philosophy Isaac Newton s Natural Philosophical Methodology Dordrecht e a Springer 2012 John Herivel The background to Newton s Principia a study of Newton s dynamical researches in the years 1664 84 Oxford Clarendon Press 1965 Brian Ellis The Origin and Nature of Newton s Laws of Motion in Beyond the Edge of Certainty ed R G Colodny Pittsburgh University Pittsburgh Press 1965 29 68 E A Burtt Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science Garden City NY Doubleday and Company 1954 Colin Pask Magnificent Principia Exploring Isaac Newton s Masterpiece New York Prometheus Books 2013 External links Edit Wikimedia Commons has media related to Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica Latin versions Edit Wikisource has original text related to this article Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica First edition 1687 Trinity College Library Cambridge High resolution digitised version of Newton s own copy of the first edition with annotations Cambridge University Cambridge Digital Library High resolution digitised version of Newton s own copy of the first edition interleaved with blank pages for his annotations and corrections 1687 Newton s Principia first edition 1687 in Latin High resolution presentation of the Gunnerus Library copy 1687 Newton s Principia first edition 1687 in Latin Project Gutenberg ETH Bibliothek Zurich From the library of Gabriel Cramer Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica From the Rare Book and Special Collection Division at the Library of CongressSecond edition 1713 ETH Bibliothek Zurich ETH Bibliothek Zurich pirated Amsterdam reprint of 1723 Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica Adv b 39 2 a 1713 edition with annotations by Newton in the collections of Cambridge University Library and fully digitised in Cambridge Digital LibraryThird edition 1726 ETH Bibliothek Zurich Later Latin editions Principia in Latin annotated 1833 Glasgow reprint volume 1 with Books 1 and 2 of the Latin edition annotated by Leseur Jacquier and Calandrini 1739 42 described above Archive org 1871 reprint of the 1726 edition English translations Edit Wikisource has original text related to this article The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy American edition 1846 Andrew Motte 1729 first English translation of third edition 1726 WikiSource Partial Google books vol 1 with Book 1 Internet Archive vol 2 with Books 2 and 3 Book 3 starts at p 200 Google s metadata wrongly labels this vol 1 Partial HTML Robert Thorpe 1802 translation N W Chittenden ed 1846 American Edition a partly modernised English version largely the Motte translation of 1729 Wikisource Archive org 1 Archive org 2 eBooks Adelaide eBooks Adelaide Percival Frost 1863 translation with interpolations Archive org Florian Cajori 1934 modernisation of 1729 Motte and 1802 Thorpe translations Ian Bruce has made a complete translation of the third edition with notes on his website Charles Leedham Green 2021 has published a complete and heavily annotated translation Cambridge Cambridge University Press Other links Edit David R Wilkins of the School of Mathematics at Trinity College Dublin has transcribed a few sections into TeX and METAPOST and made the source as well as a formatted PDF available at Extracts from the Works of Isaac Newton Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica amp oldid 1144871451, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.