fbpx
Wikipedia

Philosophy of science

Philosophy of science is a branch of philosophy concerned with the foundations, methods, and implications of science. The central questions of this study concern what qualifies as science, the reliability of scientific theories, and the ultimate purpose of science. This discipline overlaps with metaphysics, ontology, and epistemology, for example, when it explores the relationship between science and truth. Philosophy of science focuses on metaphysical, epistemic and semantic aspects of science. Ethical issues such as bioethics and scientific misconduct are often considered ethics or science studies rather than the philosophy of science.

There is no consensus among philosophers about many of the central problems concerned with the philosophy of science, including whether science can reveal the truth about unobservable things and whether scientific reasoning can be justified at all. In addition to these general questions about science as a whole, philosophers of science consider problems that apply to particular sciences (such as biology or physics). Some philosophers of science also use contemporary results in science to reach conclusions about philosophy itself.

While philosophical thought pertaining to science dates back at least to the time of Aristotle, general philosophy of science emerged as a distinct discipline only in the 20th century in the wake of the logical positivist movement, which aimed to formulate criteria for ensuring all philosophical statements' meaningfulness and objectively assessing them. Charles Sanders Peirce and Karl Popper moved on from positivism to establish a modern set of standards for scientific methodology. Thomas Kuhn's 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions was also formative, challenging the view of scientific progress as the steady, cumulative acquisition of knowledge based on a fixed method of systematic experimentation and instead of arguing that any progress is relative to a "paradigm", the set of questions, concepts, and practices that define a scientific discipline in a particular historical period.[1]

Subsequently, the coherentist approach to science, in which a theory is validated if it makes sense of observations as part of a coherent whole, became prominent due to W. V. Quine and others. Some thinkers such as Stephen Jay Gould seek to ground science in axiomatic assumptions, such as the uniformity of nature. A vocal minority of philosophers, and Paul Feyerabend in particular, argue that there is no such thing as the "scientific method", so all approaches to science should be allowed, including explicitly supernatural ones. Another approach to thinking about science involves studying how knowledge is created from a sociological perspective, an approach represented by scholars like David Bloor and Barry Barnes. Finally, a tradition in continental philosophy approaches science from the perspective of a rigorous analysis of human experience.

Philosophies of the particular sciences range from questions about the nature of time raised by Einstein's general relativity, to the implications of economics for public policy. A central theme is whether the terms of one scientific theory can be intra- or intertheoretically reduced to the terms of another. That is, can chemistry be reduced to physics, or can sociology be reduced to individual psychology? The general questions of philosophy of science also arise with greater specificity in some particular sciences. For instance, the question of the validity of scientific reasoning is seen in a different guise in the foundations of statistics. The question of what counts as science and what should be excluded arises as a life-or-death matter in the philosophy of medicine. Additionally, the philosophies of biology, psychology, and the social sciences explore whether the scientific studies of human nature can achieve objectivity or are inevitably shaped by values and by social relations.

Introduction

Defining science

 
Karl Popper in the 1980s

Distinguishing between science and non-science is referred to as the demarcation problem. For example, should psychoanalysis, creation science, and historical materialism be considered pseudosciences? Karl Popper called this the central question in the philosophy of science.[2] However, no unified account of the problem has won acceptance among philosophers, and some regard the problem as unsolvable or uninteresting.[3][4] Martin Gardner has argued for the use of a Potter Stewart standard ("I know it when I see it") for recognizing pseudoscience.[5]

Early attempts by the logical positivists grounded science in observation while non-science was non-observational and hence meaningless.[6] Popper argued that the central property of science is falsifiability. That is, every genuinely scientific claim is capable of being proven false, at least in principle.[7]

An area of study or speculation that masquerades as science in an attempt to claim a legitimacy that it would not otherwise be able to achieve is referred to as pseudoscience, fringe science, or junk science.[8] Physicist Richard Feynman coined the term "cargo cult science" for cases in which researchers believe they are doing science because their activities have the outward appearance of it but actually lack the "kind of utter honesty" that allows their results to be rigorously evaluated.[9]

Scientific explanation

A closely related question is what counts as a good scientific explanation. In addition to providing predictions about future events, society often takes scientific theories to provide explanations for events that occur regularly or have already occurred. Philosophers have investigated the criteria by which a scientific theory can be said to have successfully explained a phenomenon, as well as what it means to say a scientific theory has explanatory power.

One early and influential account of scientific explanation is the deductive-nomological model. It says that a successful scientific explanation must deduce the occurrence of the phenomena in question from a scientific law.[10] This view has been subjected to substantial criticism, resulting in several widely acknowledged counterexamples to the theory.[11] It is especially challenging to characterize what is meant by an explanation when the thing to be explained cannot be deduced from any law because it is a matter of chance, or otherwise cannot be perfectly predicted from what is known. Wesley Salmon developed a model in which a good scientific explanation must be statistically relevant to the outcome to be explained.[12][13] Others have argued that the key to a good explanation is unifying disparate phenomena or providing a causal mechanism.[13]

Justifying science

 
The expectations chickens might form about farmer behavior illustrate the "problem of induction".

Although it is often taken for granted, it is not at all clear how one can infer the validity of a general statement from a number of specific instances or infer the truth of a theory from a series of successful tests.[14] For example, a chicken observes that each morning the farmer comes and gives it food, for hundreds of days in a row. The chicken may therefore use inductive reasoning to infer that the farmer will bring food every morning. However, one morning, the farmer comes and kills the chicken. How is scientific reasoning more trustworthy than the chicken's reasoning?

One approach is to acknowledge that induction cannot achieve certainty, but observing more instances of a general statement can at least make the general statement more probable. So the chicken would be right to conclude from all those mornings that it is likely the farmer will come with food again the next morning, even if it cannot be certain. However, there remain difficult questions about the process of interpreting any given evidence into a probability that the general statement is true. One way out of these particular difficulties is to declare that all beliefs about scientific theories are subjective, or personal, and correct reasoning is merely about how evidence should change one's subjective beliefs over time.[14]

Some argue that what scientists do is not inductive reasoning at all but rather abductive reasoning, or inference to the best explanation. In this account, science is not about generalizing specific instances but rather about hypothesizing explanations for what is observed. As discussed in the previous section, it is not always clear what is meant by the "best explanation". Ockham's razor, which counsels choosing the simplest available explanation, thus plays an important role in some versions of this approach. To return to the example of the chicken, would it be simpler to suppose that the farmer cares about it and will continue taking care of it indefinitely or that the farmer is fattening it up for slaughter? Philosophers have tried to make this heuristic principle more precise in terms of theoretical parsimony or other measures. Yet, although various measures of simplicity have been brought forward as potential candidates, it is generally accepted that there is no such thing as a theory-independent measure of simplicity. In other words, there appear to be as many different measures of simplicity as there are theories themselves, and the task of choosing between measures of simplicity appears to be every bit as problematic as the job of choosing between theories.[15] Nicholas Maxwell has argued for some decades that unity rather than simplicity is the key non-empirical factor in influencing choice of theory in science, persistent preference for unified theories in effect committing science to the acceptance of a metaphysical thesis concerning unity in nature. In order to improve this problematic thesis, it needs to be represented in the form of a hierarchy of theses, each thesis becoming more insubstantial as one goes up the hierarchy.[16]

Observation inseparable from theory

 
Seen through a telescope, the Einstein cross seems to provide evidence for five different objects, but this observation is theory-laden. If we assume the theory of general relativity, the image only provides evidence for two objects.

When making observations, scientists look through telescopes, study images on electronic screens, record meter readings, and so on. Generally, on a basic level, they can agree on what they see, e.g., the thermometer shows 37.9 degrees C. But, if these scientists have different ideas about the theories that have been developed to explain these basic observations, they may disagree about what they are observing. For example, before Albert Einstein's general theory of relativity, observers would have likely interpreted an image of the Einstein cross as five different objects in space. In light of that theory, however, astronomers will tell you that there are actually only two objects, one in the center and four different images of a second object around the sides. Alternatively, if other scientists suspect that something is wrong with the telescope and only one object is actually being observed, they are operating under yet another theory. Observations that cannot be separated from theoretical interpretation are said to be theory-laden.[17]

All observation involves both perception and cognition. That is, one does not make an observation passively, but rather is actively engaged in distinguishing the phenomenon being observed from surrounding sensory data. Therefore, observations are affected by one's underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions, and that understanding may influence what is perceived, noticed, or deemed worthy of consideration. In this sense, it can be argued that all observation is theory-laden.[17]

The purpose of science

Should science aim to determine ultimate truth, or are there questions that science cannot answer? Scientific realists claim that science aims at truth and that one ought to regard scientific theories as true, approximately true, or likely true. Conversely, scientific anti-realists argue that science does not aim (or at least does not succeed) at truth, especially truth about unobservables like electrons or other universes.[18] Instrumentalists argue that scientific theories should only be evaluated on whether they are useful. In their view, whether theories are true or not is beside the point, because the purpose of science is to make predictions and enable effective technology.

Realists often point to the success of recent scientific theories as evidence for the truth (or near truth) of current theories.[19][20] Antirealists point to either the many false theories in the history of science,[21][22] epistemic morals,[23] the success of false modeling assumptions,[24] or widely termed postmodern criticisms of objectivity as evidence against scientific realism.[19] Antirealists attempt to explain the success of scientific theories without reference to truth.[25] Some antirealists claim that scientific theories aim at being accurate only about observable objects and argue that their success is primarily judged by that criterion.[23]

Values and science

Values intersect with science in different ways. There are epistemic values that mainly guide the scientific research. The scientific enterprise is embedded in particular culture and values through individual practitioners. Values emerge from science, both as product and process and can be distributed among several cultures in the society. When it comes to the justification of science in the sense of general public participation by single practitioners, science plays the role of a mediator between evaluating the standards and policies of society and its participating individuals, wherefore science indeed falls victim to vandalism and sabotage adapting the means to the end.[26]

If it is unclear what counts as science, how the process of confirming theories works, and what the purpose of science is, there is considerable scope for values and other social influences to shape science. Indeed, values can play a role ranging from determining which research gets funded to influencing which theories achieve scientific consensus.[27] For example, in the 19th century, cultural values held by scientists about race shaped research on evolution, and values concerning social class influenced debates on phrenology (considered scientific at the time).[28] Feminist philosophers of science, sociologists of science, and others explore how social values affect science.

History

Pre-modern

The origins of philosophy of science trace back to Plato and Aristotle,[29] who distinguished the forms of approximate and exact reasoning, set out the threefold scheme of abductive, deductive, and inductive inference, and also analyzed reasoning by analogy. The eleventh century Arab polymath Ibn al-Haytham (known in Latin as Alhazen) conducted his research in optics by way of controlled experimental testing and applied geometry, especially in his investigations into the images resulting from the reflection and refraction of light. Roger Bacon (1214–1294), an English thinker and experimenter heavily influenced by al-Haytham, is recognized by many to be the father of modern scientific method.[30] His view that mathematics was essential to a correct understanding of natural philosophy is considered to have been 400 years ahead of its time.[31]

Modern

 
Francis Bacon's statue at Gray's Inn, South Square, London

Francis Bacon (no direct relation to Roger, who lived 300 years earlier) was a seminal figure in philosophy of science at the time of the Scientific Revolution. In his work Novum Organum (1620)—an allusion to Aristotle's Organon—Bacon outlined a new system of logic to improve upon the old philosophical process of syllogism. Bacon's method relied on experimental histories to eliminate alternative theories.[32] In 1637, René Descartes established a new framework for grounding scientific knowledge in his treatise, Discourse on Method, advocating the central role of reason as opposed to sensory experience. By contrast, in 1713, the 2nd edition of Isaac Newton's Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica argued that "... hypotheses ... have no place in experimental philosophy. In this philosophy[,] propositions are deduced from the phenomena and rendered general by induction."[33] This passage influenced a "later generation of philosophically-inclined readers to pronounce a ban on causal hypotheses in natural philosophy".[33] In particular, later in the 18th century, David Hume would famously articulate skepticism about the ability of science to determine causality and gave a definitive formulation of the problem of induction. The 19th century writings of John Stuart Mill are also considered important in the formation of current conceptions of the scientific method, as well as anticipating later accounts of scientific explanation.[34]

Logical positivism

Instrumentalism became popular among physicists around the turn of the 20th century, after which logical positivism defined the field for several decades. Logical positivism accepts only testable statements as meaningful, rejects metaphysical interpretations, and embraces verificationism (a set of theories of knowledge that combines logicism, empiricism, and linguistics to ground philosophy on a basis consistent with examples from the empirical sciences). Seeking to overhaul all of philosophy and convert it to a new scientific philosophy,[35] the Berlin Circle and the Vienna Circle propounded logical positivism in the late 1920s.

Interpreting Ludwig Wittgenstein's early philosophy of language, logical positivists identified a verifiability principle or criterion of cognitive meaningfulness. From Bertrand Russell's logicism they sought reduction of mathematics to logic. They also embraced Russell's logical atomism, Ernst Mach's phenomenalism—whereby the mind knows only actual or potential sensory experience, which is the content of all sciences, whether physics or psychology—and Percy Bridgman's operationalism. Thereby, only the verifiable was scientific and cognitively meaningful, whereas the unverifiable was unscientific, cognitively meaningless "pseudostatements"—metaphysical, emotive, or such—not worthy of further review by philosophers, who were newly tasked to organize knowledge rather than develop new knowledge.

Logical positivism is commonly portrayed as taking the extreme position that scientific language should never refer to anything unobservable—even the seemingly core notions of causality, mechanism, and principles—but that is an exaggeration. Talk of such unobservables could be allowed as metaphorical—direct observations viewed in the abstract—or at worst metaphysical or emotional. Theoretical laws would be reduced to empirical laws, while theoretical terms would garner meaning from observational terms via correspondence rules. Mathematics in physics would reduce to symbolic logic via logicism, while rational reconstruction would convert ordinary language into standardized equivalents, all networked and united by a logical syntax. A scientific theory would be stated with its method of verification, whereby a logical calculus or empirical operation could verify its falsity or truth.

In the late 1930s, logical positivists fled Germany and Austria for Britain and America. By then, many had replaced Mach's phenomenalism with Otto Neurath's physicalism, and Rudolf Carnap had sought to replace verification with simply confirmation. With World War II's close in 1945, logical positivism became milder, logical empiricism, led largely by Carl Hempel, in America, who expounded the covering law model of scientific explanation as a way of identifying the logical form of explanations without any reference to the suspect notion of "causation". The logical positivist movement became a major underpinning of analytic philosophy,[36] and dominated Anglosphere philosophy, including philosophy of science, while influencing sciences, into the 1960s. Yet the movement failed to resolve its central problems,[37][38][39] and its doctrines were increasingly assaulted. Nevertheless, it brought about the establishment of philosophy of science as a distinct subdiscipline of philosophy, with Carl Hempel playing a key role.[40]

 
For Kuhn, the addition of epicycles in Ptolemaic astronomy was "normal science" within a paradigm, whereas the Copernican revolution was a paradigm shift.

Thomas Kuhn

In the 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn argued that the process of observation and evaluation takes place within a paradigm, a logically consistent "portrait" of the world that is consistent with observations made from its framing. A paradigm also encompasses the set of questions and practices that define a scientific discipline. He characterized normal science as the process of observation and "puzzle solving" which takes place within a paradigm, whereas revolutionary science occurs when one paradigm overtakes another in a paradigm shift.[41]

Kuhn denied that it is ever possible to isolate the hypothesis being tested from the influence of the theory in which the observations are grounded, and he argued that it is not possible to evaluate competing paradigms independently. More than one logically consistent construct can paint a usable likeness of the world, but there is no common ground from which to pit two against each other, theory against theory. Each paradigm has its own distinct questions, aims, and interpretations. Neither provides a standard by which the other can be judged, so there is no clear way to measure scientific progress across paradigms.

For Kuhn, the choice of paradigm was sustained by rational processes, but not ultimately determined by them. The choice between paradigms involves setting two or more "portraits" against the world and deciding which likeness is most promising. For Kuhn, acceptance or rejection of a paradigm is a social process as much as a logical process. Kuhn's position, however, is not one of relativism.[42] According to Kuhn, a paradigm shift occurs when a significant number of observational anomalies arise in the old paradigm and a new paradigm makes sense of them. That is, the choice of a new paradigm is based on observations, even though those observations are made against the background of the old paradigm.

Current approaches

Naturalism's axiomatic assumptions

All scientific study inescapably builds on at least some essential assumptions that are untested by scientific processes.[43][44] Kuhn concurs that all science is based on an approved agenda of unprovable assumptions about the character of the universe, rather than merely on empirical facts. These assumptions—a paradigm—comprise a collection of beliefs, values and techniques that are held by a given scientific community, which legitimize their systems and set the limitations to their investigation.[45] For naturalists, nature is the only reality, the only paradigm. There is no such thing as 'supernatural'. The scientific method is to be used to investigate all reality,[46] and Naturalism is the implicit philosophy of working scientists.[47]

The following basic assumptions are needed to justify the scientific method.[48]

  1. that there is an objective reality shared by all rational observers.[48][49] "The basis for rationality is acceptance of an external objective reality."[50] "As an individual we cannot know that the sensory information we perceive is generated artificially or originates from a real world. Any belief that it arises from a real world outside us is actually an assumption. It seems more beneficial to assume that an objective reality exists than to live with solipsism, and so people are quite happy to make this assumption. In fact we made this assumption unconsciously when we began to learn about the world as infants. The world outside ourselves appears to respond in ways which are consistent with it being real. ... The assumption of objectivism is essential if we are to attach the contemporary meanings to our sensations and feelings and make more sense of them."[51] "Without this assumption, there would be only the thoughts and images in our own mind (which would be the only existing mind) and there would be no need of science, or anything else."[52]
  2. that this objective reality is governed by natural laws.[48][49] "Science, at least today, assumes that the universe obeys to knoweable principles that don't depend on time or place, nor on subjective parameters such as what we think, know or how we behave."[50] Hugh Gauch argues that science presupposes that "the physical world is orderly and comprehensible".[53]
  3. that reality can be discovered by means of systematic observation and experimentation.[48][49] Stanley Sobottka said: "The assumption of external reality is necessary for science to function and to flourish. For the most part, science is the discovering and explaining of the external world."[52] "Science attempts to produce knowledge that is as universal and objective as possible within the realm of human understanding."[50]
  4. that Nature has uniformity of laws and most if not all things in nature must have at least a natural cause.[49] Biologist Stephen Jay Gould referred to these two closely related propositions as the constancy of nature's laws and the operation of known processes.[54] Simpson agrees that the axiom of uniformity of law, an unprovable postulate, is necessary in order for scientists to extrapolate inductive inference into the unobservable past in order to meaningfully study it.[55]
  5. that experimental procedures will be done satisfactorily without any deliberate or unintentional mistakes that will influence the results.[49]
  6. that experimenters won't be significantly biased by their presumptions.[49]
  7. that random sampling is representative of the entire population.[49] A simple random sample (SRS) is the most basic probabilistic option used for creating a sample from a population. The benefit of SRS is that the investigator is guaranteed to choose a sample that represents the population that ensures statistically valid conclusions.[56]

Coherentism

 
Jeremiah Horrocks makes the first observation of the transit of Venus in 1639, as imagined by the artist W. R. Lavender in 1903.

In contrast to the view that science rests on foundational assumptions, coherentism asserts that statements are justified by being a part of a coherent system. Or, rather, individual statements cannot be validated on their own: only coherent systems can be justified.[57] A prediction of a transit of Venus is justified by its being coherent with broader beliefs about celestial mechanics and earlier observations. As explained above, observation is a cognitive act. That is, it relies on a pre-existing understanding, a systematic set of beliefs. An observation of a transit of Venus requires a huge range of auxiliary beliefs, such as those that describe the optics of telescopes, the mechanics of the telescope mount, and an understanding of celestial mechanics. If the prediction fails and a transit is not observed, that is likely to occasion an adjustment in the system, a change in some auxiliary assumption, rather than a rejection of the theoretical system.[citation needed]

In fact, according to the Duhem–Quine thesis, after Pierre Duhem and W.V. Quine, it is impossible to test a theory in isolation.[58] One must always add auxiliary hypotheses in order to make testable predictions. For example, to test Newton's Law of Gravitation in the solar system, one needs information about the masses and positions of the Sun and all the planets. Famously, the failure to predict the orbit of Uranus in the 19th century led not to the rejection of Newton's Law but rather to the rejection of the hypothesis that the solar system comprises only seven planets. The investigations that followed led to the discovery of an eighth planet, Neptune. If a test fails, something is wrong. But there is a problem in figuring out what that something is: a missing planet, badly calibrated test equipment, an unsuspected curvature of space, or something else.[citation needed]

One consequence of the Duhem–Quine thesis is that one can make any theory compatible with any empirical observation by the addition of a sufficient number of suitable ad hoc hypotheses. Karl Popper accepted this thesis, leading him to reject naïve falsification. Instead, he favored a "survival of the fittest" view in which the most falsifiable scientific theories are to be preferred.[59]

Anything goes methodology

Paul Feyerabend (1924–1994) argued that no description of scientific method could possibly be broad enough to include all the approaches and methods used by scientists, and that there are no useful and exception-free methodological rules governing the progress of science. He argued that "the only principle that does not inhibit progress is: anything goes".[60]

Feyerabend said that science started as a liberating movement, but that over time it had become increasingly dogmatic and rigid and had some oppressive features, and thus had become increasingly an ideology. Because of this, he said it was impossible to come up with an unambiguous way to distinguish science from religion, magic, or mythology. He saw the exclusive dominance of science as a means of directing society as authoritarian and ungrounded.[60] Promulgation of this epistemological anarchism earned Feyerabend the title of "the worst enemy of science" from his detractors.[61]

Sociology of scientific knowledge methodology

According to Kuhn, science is an inherently communal activity which can only be done as part of a community.[62] For him, the fundamental difference between science and other disciplines is the way in which the communities function. Others, especially Feyerabend and some post-modernist thinkers, have argued that there is insufficient difference between social practices in science and other disciplines to maintain this distinction. For them, social factors play an important and direct role in scientific method, but they do not serve to differentiate science from other disciplines. On this account, science is socially constructed, though this does not necessarily imply the more radical notion that reality itself is a social construct.

Michel Foucault sought to analyze and uncover how disciplines within the social sciences developed and adopted the methodologies used by their practitioners. In works like The Archaeology of Knowledge, he used the term human sciences. The human sciences do not comprise mainstream academic disciplines; they are rather an interdisciplinary space for the reflection on man who is the subject of more mainstream scientific knowledge, taken now as an object, sitting between these more conventional areas, and of course associating with disciplines such as anthropology, psychology, sociology, and even history.[63] Rejecting the realist view of scientific inquiry, Foucault argued throughout his work that scientific discourse is not simply an objective study of phenomena, as both natural and social scientists like to believe, but is rather the product of systems of power relations struggling to construct scientific disciplines and knowledge within given societies.[64] With the advances of scientific disciplines, such as psychology and anthropology, the need to separate, categorize, normalize and institutionalize populations into constructed social identities became a staple of the sciences. Constructions of what were considered "normal" and "abnormal" stigmatized and ostracized groups of people, like the mentally ill and sexual and gender minorities.[65]

However, some (such as Quine) do maintain that scientific reality is a social construct:

Physical objects are conceptually imported into the situation as convenient intermediaries not by definition in terms of experience, but simply as irreducible posits comparable, epistemologically, to the gods of Homer ... For my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in physical objects and not in Homer's gods; and I consider it a scientific error to believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing, the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conceptions only as cultural posits.[66]

The public backlash of scientists against such views, particularly in the 1990s, became known as the science wars.[67]

A major development in recent decades has been the study of the formation, structure, and evolution of scientific communities by sociologists and anthropologists – including David Bloor, Harry Collins, Bruno Latour, Ian Hacking and Anselm Strauss. Concepts and methods (such as rational choice, social choice or game theory) from economics have also been applied[by whom?] for understanding the efficiency of scientific communities in the production of knowledge. This interdisciplinary field has come to be known as science and technology studies.[68] Here the approach to the philosophy of science is to study how scientific communities actually operate.

Continental philosophy

Philosophers in the continental philosophical tradition are not traditionally categorized[by whom?] as philosophers of science. However, they have much to say about science, some of which has anticipated themes in the analytical tradition. For example, in The Genealogy of Morals (1887) Friedrich Nietzsche advanced the thesis that the motive for the search for truth in sciences is a kind of ascetic ideal.[69]

 
Hegel with his Berlin students
Sketch by Franz Kugler

In general, continental philosophy views science from a world-historical perspective. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) became one of the first philosophers to support this view. Philosophers such as Pierre Duhem (1861-1916) and Gaston Bachelard (1884-1962) also wrote their works with this world-historical approach to science, predating Kuhn's 1962 work by a generation or more. All of these approaches involve a historical and sociological turn to science, with a priority on lived experience (a kind of Husserlian "life-world"), rather than a progress-based or anti-historical approach as emphasised in the analytic tradition. One can trace this continental strand of thought through the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl (1859-1938), the late works of Merleau-Ponty (Nature: Course Notes from the Collège de France, 1956–1960), and the hermeneutics of Martin Heidegger (1889-1976).[70]

The largest effect on the continental tradition with respect to science came from Martin Heidegger's critique of the theoretical attitude in general, which of course includes the scientific attitude.[71] For this reason, the continental tradition has remained much more skeptical of the importance of science in human life and in philosophical inquiry. Nonetheless, there have been a number of important works: especially those of a Kuhnian precursor, Alexandre Koyré (1892-1964). Another important development was that of Michel Foucault's analysis of historical and scientific thought in The Order of Things (1966) and his study of power and corruption within the "science" of madness.[72] Post-Heideggerian authors contributing to continental philosophy of science in the second half of the 20th century include Jürgen Habermas (e.g., Truth and Justification, 1998), Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker (The Unity of Nature, 1980; German: Die Einheit der Natur (1971)), and Wolfgang Stegmüller (Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, 1973–1986).

Other topics

Reductionism

Analysis involves breaking an observation or theory down into simpler concepts in order to understand it. Reductionism can refer to one of several philosophical positions related to this approach. One type of reductionism suggests that phenomena are amenable to scientific explanation at lower levels of analysis and inquiry. Perhaps a historical event might be explained in sociological and psychological terms, which in turn might be described in terms of human physiology, which in turn might be described in terms of chemistry and physics.[73] Daniel Dennett distinguishes legitimate reductionism from what he calls greedy reductionism, which denies real complexities and leaps too quickly to sweeping generalizations.[74]

Social accountability

A broad issue affecting the neutrality of science concerns the areas which science chooses to explore—that is, what part of the world and of humankind are studied by science. Philip Kitcher in his Science, Truth, and Democracy[75] argues that scientific studies that attempt to show one segment of the population as being less intelligent, successful or emotionally backward compared to others have a political feedback effect which further excludes such groups from access to science. Thus such studies undermine the broad consensus required for good science by excluding certain people, and so proving themselves in the end to be unscientific.

Philosophy of particular sciences

There is no such thing as philosophy-free science; there is only science whose philosophical baggage is taken on board without examination.[76]

— Daniel Dennett, Darwin's Dangerous Idea, 1995

In addition to addressing the general questions regarding science and induction, many philosophers of science are occupied by investigating foundational problems in particular sciences. They also examine the implications of particular sciences for broader philosophical questions. The late 20th and early 21st century has seen a rise in the number of practitioners of philosophy of a particular science.[77]

Philosophy of statistics

The problem of induction discussed above is seen in another form in debates over the foundations of statistics.[78] The standard approach to statistical hypothesis testing avoids claims about whether evidence supports a hypothesis or makes it more probable. Instead, the typical test yields a p-value, which is the probability of the evidence being such as it is, under the assumption that the hypothesis being tested is true. If the p-value is too low, the hypothesis is rejected, in a way analogous to falsification. In contrast, Bayesian inference seeks to assign probabilities to hypotheses. Related topics in philosophy of statistics include probability interpretations, overfitting, and the difference between correlation and causation.

Philosophy of mathematics

Philosophy of mathematics is concerned with the philosophical foundations and implications of mathematics.[79] The central questions are whether numbers, triangles, and other mathematical entities exist independently of the human mind and what is the nature of mathematical propositions. Is asking whether "1+1=2" is true fundamentally different from asking whether a ball is red? Was calculus invented or discovered? A related question is whether learning mathematics requires experience or reason alone. What does it mean to prove a mathematical theorem and how does one know whether a mathematical proof is correct? Philosophers of mathematics also aim to clarify the relationships between mathematics and logic, human capabilities such as intuition, and the material universe.

Philosophy of physics

Unsolved problem in physics:

How does the quantum description of reality, which includes elements such as the "superposition of states" and "wavefunction collapse", give rise to the reality we perceive?

Philosophy of physics is the study of the fundamental, philosophical questions underlying modern physics, the study of matter and energy and how they interact. The main questions concern the nature of space and time, atoms and atomism. Also included are the predictions of cosmology, the interpretation of quantum mechanics, the foundations of statistical mechanics, causality, determinism, and the nature of physical laws.[80] Classically, several of these questions were studied as part of metaphysics (for example, those about causality, determinism, and space and time).

Philosophy of chemistry

Philosophy of chemistry is the philosophical study of the methodology and content of the science of chemistry. It is explored by philosophers, chemists, and philosopher-chemist teams. It includes research on general philosophy of science issues as applied to chemistry. For example, can all chemical phenomena be explained by quantum mechanics or is it not possible to reduce chemistry to physics? For another example, chemists have discussed the philosophy of how theories are confirmed in the context of confirming reaction mechanisms. Determining reaction mechanisms is difficult because they cannot be observed directly. Chemists can use a number of indirect measures as evidence to rule out certain mechanisms, but they are often unsure if the remaining mechanism is correct because there are many other possible mechanisms that they have not tested or even thought of.[81] Philosophers have also sought to clarify the meaning of chemical concepts which do not refer to specific physical entities, such as chemical bonds.

Philosophy of astronomy

The philosophy of astronomy seeks to understand and analyze the methodologies and technologies used by experts in the discipline, focusing on how observations made about space and astrophysical phenomena can be studied. Given that astronomers rely and use theories and formulas from other scientific disciplines, such as chemistry and physics, the pursuit of understanding how knowledge can be obtained about the cosmos, as well as the relation in which our planet and Solar System have within our personal views of our place in the universe, philosophical insights into how facts about space can be scientifically analyzed and configure with other established knowledge is a main point of inquiry.

Philosophy of Earth sciences

The philosophy of Earth science is concerned with how humans obtain and verify knowledge of the workings of the Earth system, including the atmosphere, hydrosphere, and geosphere (solid earth). Earth scientists’ ways of knowing and habits of mind share important commonalities with other sciences, but also have distinctive attributes that emerge from the complex, heterogeneous, unique, long-lived, and non-manipulatable nature of the Earth system.

Philosophy of biology

 
Peter Godfrey-Smith was awarded the Lakatos Award[82] for his 2009 book Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection, which discusses the philosophical foundations of the theory of evolution.[83][84]

Philosophy of biology deals with epistemological, metaphysical, and ethical issues in the biological and biomedical sciences. Although philosophers of science and philosophers generally have long been interested in biology (e.g., Aristotle, Descartes, Leibniz and even Kant), philosophy of biology only emerged as an independent field of philosophy in the 1960s and 1970s.[85] Philosophers of science began to pay increasing attention to developments in biology, from the rise of the modern synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s to the discovery of the structure of deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) in 1953 to more recent advances in genetic engineering. Other key ideas such as the reduction of all life processes to biochemical reactions as well as the incorporation of psychology into a broader neuroscience are also addressed. Research in current philosophy of biology includes investigation of the foundations of evolutionary theory (such as Peter Godfrey-Smith's work),[86] and the role of viruses as persistent symbionts in host genomes. As a consequence, the evolution of genetic content order is seen as the result of competent genome editors[further explanation needed] in contrast to former narratives in which error replication events (mutations) dominated.

Philosophy of medicine

 
A fragment of the Hippocratic Oath from the third century

Beyond medical ethics and bioethics, the philosophy of medicine is a branch of philosophy that includes the epistemology and ontology/metaphysics of medicine. Within the epistemology of medicine, evidence-based medicine (EBM) (or evidence-based practice (EBP)) has attracted attention, most notably the roles of randomisation,[87][88][89] blinding and placebo controls. Related to these areas of investigation, ontologies of specific interest to the philosophy of medicine include Cartesian dualism, the monogenetic conception of disease[90] and the conceptualization of 'placebos' and 'placebo effects'.[91][92][93][94] There is also a growing interest in the metaphysics of medicine,[95] particularly the idea of causation. Philosophers of medicine might not only be interested in how medical knowledge is generated, but also in the nature of such phenomena. Causation is of interest because the purpose of much medical research is to establish causal relationships, e.g. what causes disease, or what causes people to get better.[96]

Philosophy of psychiatry

Philosophy of psychiatry explores philosophical questions relating to psychiatry and mental illness. The philosopher of science and medicine Dominic Murphy identifies three areas of exploration in the philosophy of psychiatry. The first concerns the examination of psychiatry as a science, using the tools of the philosophy of science more broadly. The second entails the examination of the concepts employed in discussion of mental illness, including the experience of mental illness, and the normative questions it raises. The third area concerns the links and discontinuities between the philosophy of mind and psychopathology.[97]

Philosophy of psychology

 
Wilhelm Wundt (seated) with colleagues in his psychological laboratory, the first of its kind

Philosophy of psychology refers to issues at the theoretical foundations of modern psychology. Some of these issues are epistemological concerns about the methodology of psychological investigation. For example, is the best method for studying psychology to focus only on the response of behavior to external stimuli or should psychologists focus on mental perception and thought processes?[98] If the latter, an important question is how the internal experiences of others can be measured. Self-reports of feelings and beliefs may not be reliable because, even in cases in which there is no apparent incentive for subjects to intentionally deceive in their answers, self-deception or selective memory may affect their responses. Then even in the case of accurate self-reports, how can responses be compared across individuals? Even if two individuals respond with the same answer on a Likert scale, they may be experiencing very different things.

Other issues in philosophy of psychology are philosophical questions about the nature of mind, brain, and cognition, and are perhaps more commonly thought of as part of cognitive science, or philosophy of mind. For example, are humans rational creatures?[98] Is there any sense in which they have free will, and how does that relate to the experience of making choices? Philosophy of psychology also closely monitors contemporary work conducted in cognitive neuroscience, psycholinguistics, and artificial intelligence, questioning what they can and cannot explain in psychology.

Philosophy of psychology is a relatively young field, because psychology only became a discipline of its own in the late 1800s. In particular, neurophilosophy has just recently become its own field with the works of Paul Churchland and Patricia Churchland.[77] Philosophy of mind, by contrast, has been a well-established discipline since before psychology was a field of study at all. It is concerned with questions about the very nature of mind, the qualities of experience, and particular issues like the debate between dualism and monism.

Philosophy of social science

The philosophy of social science is the study of the logic and method of the social sciences, such as sociology and cultural anthropology.[99] Philosophers of social science are concerned with the differences and similarities between the social and the natural sciences, causal relationships between social phenomena, the possible existence of social laws, and the ontological significance of structure and agency.

The French philosopher, Auguste Comte (1798–1857), established the epistemological perspective of positivism in The Course in Positivist Philosophy, a series of texts published between 1830 and 1842. The first three volumes of the Course dealt chiefly with the natural sciences already in existence (geoscience, astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology), whereas the latter two emphasised the inevitable coming of social science: "sociologie".[100] For Comte, the natural sciences had to necessarily arrive first, before humanity could adequately channel its efforts into the most challenging and complex "Queen science" of human society itself. Comte offers an evolutionary system proposing that society undergoes three phases in its quest for the truth according to a general 'law of three stages'. These are (1) the theological, (2) the metaphysical, and (3) the positive.[101]

Comte's positivism established the initial philosophical foundations for formal sociology and social research. Durkheim, Marx, and Weber are more typically cited as the fathers of contemporary social science. In psychology, a positivistic approach has historically been favoured in behaviourism. Positivism has also been espoused by 'technocrats' who believe in the inevitability of social progress through science and technology.[102]

The positivist perspective has been associated with 'scientism'; the view that the methods of the natural sciences may be applied to all areas of investigation, be it philosophical, social scientific, or otherwise. Among most social scientists and historians, orthodox positivism has long since lost popular support. Today, practitioners of both social and physical sciences instead take into account the distorting effect of observer bias and structural limitations. This scepticism has been facilitated by a general weakening of deductivist accounts of science by philosophers such as Thomas Kuhn, and new philosophical movements such as critical realism and neopragmatism. The philosopher-sociologist Jürgen Habermas has critiqued pure instrumental rationality as meaning that scientific-thinking becomes something akin to ideology itself.[103]

Philosophy of technology

The philosophy of technology is a sub-field of philosophy that studies the nature of technology. Specific research topics include study of the role of tacit and explicit knowledge in creating and using technology, the nature of functions in technological artifacts, the role of values in design, and ethics related to technology. Technology and engineering can both involve the application of scientific knowledge. The philosophy of engineering is an emerging sub-field of the broader philosophy of technology.

See also

Footnotes

  1. ^ . Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 2015-04-17. Instead, he argued that the paradigm determines the kinds of experiments scientists perform, the types of questions they ask, and the problems they consider important.
  2. ^ Thornton, Stephen (2006). "Karl Popper". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2007-06-27. Retrieved 2007-12-01.
  3. ^ . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008. Archived from the original on 2015-09-05.
  4. ^ Laudan, Larry (1983). "The Demise of the Demarcation Problem". In Grünbaum, Adolf; Cohen, Robert Sonné; Laudan, Larry (eds.). Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honor of Adolf Grünbaum. Springer. ISBN 978-90-277-1533-3.
  5. ^ Gordin, Michael D. (2012). The Pseudoscience Wars: Immanuel Velikovsky and the Birth of the Modern Fringe. University of Chicago Press. pp. 12–13. ISBN 978-0-226-30442-7.
  6. ^ Uebel, Thomas (2006). "Vienna Circle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2007-06-26. Retrieved 2007-12-01.
  7. ^ Popper, Karl (2004). The logic of scientific discovery (reprint ed.). London & New York: Routledge Classics. ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7First published 1959 by Hutchinson & Co.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
  8. ^ "Pseudoscientific – pretending to be scientific, falsely represented as being scientific". Oxford American Dictionary. Oxford English Dictionary.; Hansson, Sven Ove (1996). "Defining Pseudoscience". Philosophia Naturalis. 33: 169–176., as cited in . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008. Archived from the original on 2015-09-05.. The Stanford article states: "Many writers on pseudoscience have emphasized that pseudoscience is non-science posing as science. The foremost modern classic on the subject (Gardner 1957) bears the title Fads and Fallacies in the Name of Science. According to Brian Baigrie (1988, 438), "[w]hat is objectionable about these beliefs is that they masquerade as genuinely scientific ones." These and many other authors assume that to be pseudoscientific, an activity or a teaching has to satisfy the following two criteria (Hansson 1996): (1) it is not scientific, and (2) its major proponents try to create the impression that it is scientific".
    • For example, Hewitt, Paul G.; Suchocki, John; Hewitt, Leslie A. (2003). Conceptual Physical Science (3rd ed.). Addison Wesley. ISBN 0-321-05173-4., Bennett, Jeffrey O. (2003). The Cosmic Perspective (3rd ed.). Addison Wesley. ISBN 0-8053-8738-2.; See also, e.g., Gauch HG Jr. Scientific Method in Practice (2003).
    • A 2006 National Science Foundation report on Science and engineering indicators quoted Michael Shermer's (1997) definition of pseudoscience: '"claims presented so that they appear [to be] scientific even though they lack supporting evidence and plausibility"(p. 33). In contrast, science is "a set of methods designed to describe and interpret observed and inferred phenomena, past or present, and aimed at building a testable body of knowledge open to rejection or confirmation" (p. 17)'. Shermer, Michael (1997). Why People Believe Weird Things: Pseudoscience, Superstition, and Other Confusions of Our Time. New York: W.H. Freeman and Company. ISBN 978-0-7167-3090-3. as cited by National Science Foundation; Division of Science Resources Statistics (2006). "Science and Technology: Public Attitudes and Understanding". Science and engineering indicators 2006.
    • "A pretended or spurious science; a collection of related beliefs about the world mistakenly regarded as being based on scientific method or as having the status that scientific truths now have," from the Oxford English Dictionary, second edition 1989.
  9. ^ Feynman, Richard. (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2013-12-01. Retrieved 2015-10-25.
  10. ^ Hempel, Carl G.; Oppenheim, Paul (1948). "Studies in the Logic of Explanation". Philosophy of Science. 15 (2): 135–175. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.294.3693. doi:10.1086/286983. S2CID 16924146.
  11. ^ Salmon, Merrilee; Earman, John; Glymour, Clark; Lenno, James G.; Machamer, Peter; McGuire, J.E.; Norton, John D.; Salmon, Wesley C.; Schaffner, Kenneth F. (1992). Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Prentice-Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-663345-7.
  12. ^ Salmon, Wesley (1971). Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. ISBN 9780822974116.
  13. ^ a b Woodward, James (2003). "Scientific Explanation". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2007-07-06. Retrieved 2007-12-07.
  14. ^ a b Vickers, John (2013). "The Problem of Induction". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2014-04-07. Retrieved 2014-02-25.
  15. ^ Baker, Alan (2013). "Simplicity". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2014-03-26. Retrieved 2014-02-25.
  16. ^ Nicholas Maxwell (1998) The Comprehensibility of the Universe 2018-02-27 at the Wayback Machine Clarendon Press; (2017) Understanding Scientific Progress: Aim-Oriented Empiricism 2018-02-20 at the Wayback Machine, Paragon House, St. Paul
  17. ^ a b Bogen, Jim (2013). "Theory and Observation in Science". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2014-02-27. Retrieved 2014-02-25.
  18. ^ Levin, Michael (1984). "What Kind of Explanation is Truth?". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.). Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 124–1139. ISBN 978-0-520-05155-3.
  19. ^ a b Boyd, Richard (2002). "Scientific Realism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2007-07-06. Retrieved 2007-12-01.
  20. ^ Specific examples include:
    • Popper, Karl (2002). Conjectures and Refutations. London & New York: Routledge Classics. ISBN 978-0-415-28594-0First published 1963 by Routledge and Kegan Paul{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
    • Smart, J.J.C. (1968). Between Science and Philosophy. New York: Random House.
    • Putnam, Hilary (1975). Mathematics, Matter and Method (Philosophical Papers, Vol. I). London: Cambridge University Press.
    • Putnam, Hilary (1978). Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    • Boyd, Richard (1984). "The Current Status of Scientific Realism". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.). Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 41–82. ISBN 978-0-520-05155-3.
  21. ^ Stanford, P. Kyle (2006). Exceeding Our Grasp: Science, History, and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-517408-3.
  22. ^ Laudan, Larry (1981). "A Confutation of Convergent Realism". Philosophy of Science. 48: 218–249. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.594.2523. doi:10.1086/288975. S2CID 108290084.
  23. ^ a b van Fraassen, Bas (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824424-0.
  24. ^ Winsberg, Eric (September 2006). "Models of Success Versus the Success of Models: Reliability without Truth". Synthese. 152: 1–19. doi:10.1007/s11229-004-5404-6. S2CID 18275928.
  25. ^ Stanford, P. Kyle (June 2000). "An Antirealist Explanation of the Success of Science". Philosophy of Science. 67 (2): 266–284. doi:10.1086/392775. S2CID 35878807.
  26. ^ Rosenstock, Linda; Lee, Lore Jackson (January 2002). "Attacks on Science: The Risks to Evidence-Based Policy". American Journal of Public Health. 92 (1): 14–18. doi:10.2105/ajph.92.1.14. ISSN 0090-0036. PMC 1447376. PMID 11772749.
  27. ^ Longino, Helen (2013). "The Social Dimensions of Scientific Knowledge". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2014-03-26. Retrieved 2014-03-06.
  28. ^ Douglas Allchin, "Values in Science and in Science Education," in International Handbook of Science Education, B.J. Fraser and K.G. Tobin (eds.), 2:1083–1092, Kluwer Academic Publishers (1988).
  29. ^ Aristotle, "Prior Analytics", Hugh Tredennick (trans.), pp. 181–531 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, 1938.
  30. ^ Lindberg, David C. (1980). Science in the Middle Ages. University of Chicago Press. pp. 350–351. ISBN 978-0-226-48233-0.
  31. ^ Clegg, Brian. "The First Scientist: A Life of Roger Bacon" 2018-07-08 at the Wayback Machine. Carroll and Graf Publishers, NY, 2003, p. 2.
  32. ^ Bacon, Francis Novum Organum (The New Organon), 1620. Bacon's work described many of the accepted principles, underscoring the importance of empirical results, data gathering and experiment. Encyclopædia Britannica (1911), "Bacon, Francis" states: [In Novum Organum, we ] "proceed to apply what is perhaps the most valuable part of the Baconian method, the process of exclusion or rejection. This elimination of the non-essential, ..., is the most important of Bacon's contributions to the logic of induction, and that in which, as he repeatedly says, his method differs from all previous philosophies."
  33. ^ a b McMullin, Ernan. . www.paricenter.com. Pari Center for New Learning. Archived from the original on 24 October 2015. Retrieved 29 October 2015.
  34. ^ "John Stuart Mill (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu. from the original on 2010-01-06. Retrieved 2009-07-31.
  35. ^ Michael Friedman, Reconsidering Logical Positivism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p. xiv 2016-06-28 at the Wayback Machine.
  36. ^ See "Vienna Circle" 2015-08-10 at the Wayback Machine in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  37. ^ Smith, L.D. (1986). Behaviorism and Logical Positivism: A Reassessment of the Alliance. Stanford University Press. p. 314. ISBN 978-0-8047-1301-6. LCCN 85030366. Retrieved 2016-01-27. The secondary and historical literature on logical positivism affords substantial grounds for concluding that logical positivism failed to solve many of the central problems it generated for itself. Prominent among the unsolved problems was the failure to find an acceptable statement of the verifiability (later confirmability) criterion of meaningfulness. Until a competing tradition emerged (about the late 1950s), the problems of logical positivism continued to be attacked from within that tradition. But as the new tradition in the philosophy of science began to demonstrate its effectiveness—by dissolving and rephrasing old problems as well as by generating new ones—philosophers began to shift allegiances to the new tradition, even though that tradition has yet to receive a canonical formulation.
  38. ^ Bunge, M.A. (1996). Finding Philosophy in Social Science. Yale University Press. p. 317. ISBN 978-0-300-06606-7. LCCN lc96004399. Retrieved 2016-01-27. To conclude, logical positivism was progressive compared with the classical positivism of Ptolemy, Hume, d'Alembert, Comte, John Stuart Mill, and Ernst Mach. It was even more so by comparison with its contemporary rivals—neo-Thomism, neo-Kantianism, intuitionism, dialectical materialism, phenomenology, and existentialism. However, neo-positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science, whether natural or social. It failed because it remained anchored to sense-data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics, overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis, and denounced realism and materialism as metaphysical nonsense. Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers, notably Popper (1959 [1935], 1963), logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists. Regrettably, the anti-positivism fashionable in the metatheory of social science is often nothing but an excuse for sloppiness and wild speculation.
  39. ^ . 7 August 2000. Archived from the original on January 7, 2014. Retrieved 7 January 2014. The upshot is that the positivists seem caught between insisting on the V.C. [Verifiability Criterion]—but for no defensible reason—or admitting that the V.C. requires a background language, etc., which opens the door to relativism, etc. In light of this dilemma, many folk—especially following Popper's "last-ditch" effort to "save" empiricism/positivism/realism with the falsifiability criterion—have agreed that positivism is a dead-end.
  40. ^ Friedman, Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge U P, 1999), p. xii 2016-06-28 at the Wayback Machine.
  41. ^ Bird, Alexander (2013). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Thomas Kuhn". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2017-07-13. Retrieved 2015-10-26.
  42. ^ T.S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed., Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Pr., 1970, p. 206. ISBN 0-226-45804-0
  43. ^ Priddy 1998
  44. ^ Whitehead 1997, p. 135, “All science must start with some assumptions as to the ultimate analysis of the facts with which it deals.”
  45. ^ Boldman 2007
  46. ^ Papineau, David "Naturalism" 26 April 2018 at the Wayback Machine, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  47. ^ Strahler 1992, p. 3 The naturalistic view is espoused by science as its fundamental assumption."
  48. ^ a b c d Heilbron 2003, p. vii.
  49. ^ a b c d e f g Chen 2009, pp. 1–2.
  50. ^ a b c Durak 2008.
  51. ^ Vaccaro, Joan. "Theism and Atheism". from the original on 17 February 2018. Retrieved 22 December 2017.
  52. ^ a b Sobottka 2005, p. 11.
  53. ^ Gauch 2002, p. 154, "Expressed as a single grand statement, science presupposes that the physical world is orderly and comprehensible. The most obvious components of this comprehensive presupposition are that the physical world exists and that our sense perceptions are generally reliable."
  54. ^ Gould 1987, p. 120, "You cannot go to a rocky outcrop and observe either the constancy of nature's laws or the working of known processes. It works the other way around." You first assume these propositions and "then you go to the outcrop of rock."
  55. ^ Simpson 1963, pp. 24–48, "Uniformity is an unprovable postulate justified, or indeed required, on two grounds. First, nothing in our incomplete but extensive knowledge of history disagrees with it. Second, only with this postulate is a rational interpretation of history possible and we are justified in seeking—as scientists we must seek—such a rational interpretation."
  56. ^ "Simple Random Sampling". 14 December 2010. from the original on 2 January 2018. Retrieved 2 January 2018. A simple random sample (SRS) is the most basic probabilistic option used for creating a sample from a population. Each SRS is made of individuals drawn from a larger population, completely at random. As a result, said individuals have an equal chance of being selected throughout the sampling process. The benefit of SRS is that as a result, the investigator is guaranteed to choose a sample which is representative of the population, which ensures statistically valid conclusions.
  57. ^ Olsson, Erik (2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2018-09-14. Retrieved 2015-10-26.
  58. ^ Sandra Harding (1976). Can theories be refuted?: essays on the Dunhem–Quine thesis. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 9–. ISBN 978-90-277-0630-0. from the original on 2016-06-28. Retrieved 2016-01-27.
  59. ^ Popper, Karl (2005). The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Taylor & Francis e-Library ed.). London and New York: Routledge / Taylor & Francis e-Library. chapters 3–4. ISBN 978-0-203-99462-7.
  60. ^ a b Paul Feyerabend, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge (1975), ISBN 0-391-00381-X, 0-86091-222-1, 0-86091-481-X, 0-86091-646-4, 0-86091-934-X, 0-902308-91-2
  61. ^ Preston, John (2007-02-15). "Paul Feyerabend". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  62. ^ Kuhn, T.S. (1996). "[Postscript]". The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd. ed. [Univ. of Chicago Pr]. p. 176. ISBN 978-0-226-45808-3. A paradigm is what the members of a community of scientists share, and, conversely, a scientific community consists of men who share a paradigm.
  63. ^ "Foucault, Michel". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  64. ^ Morrison, Thomas (2018). "Foucault's Elephant". Philosophy Now. No. 127. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  65. ^ Power, Jason L. (2015). "'Disciplining' Truth and Science: Michel Foucault and the Power of Social Science" (PDF). World Scientific News. 7: 15–29. ISSN 2392-2192. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  66. ^ Quine, Willard Van Orman (1980). "Two Dogmas of Empiricism". From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-32351-3.
  67. ^ Ashman, Keith M.; Barringer, Philip S., eds. (2001). After the Science Wars. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-21209-0. Retrieved 29 October 2015. The 'war' is between scientists who believe that science and its methods are objective, and an increasing number of social scientists, historians, philosophers, and others gathered under the umbrella of Science Studies.
  68. ^ Woodhouse, Edward. Science Technology and Society. Spring 2015 ed. n.p.: U Readers, 2014. Print.
  69. ^ Hatab, Lawrence J. (2008). "How Does the Ascetic Ideal Function in Nietzsche's Genealogy?". The Journal of Nietzsche Studies. 35 (35/36): 106–123. doi:10.2307/jnietstud.35.2008.0106. S2CID 170630145. from the original on 2016-03-04. Retrieved 2019-10-22.
  70. ^ Gutting, Gary (2004), Continental Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
  71. ^ Wheeler, Michael (2015). "Martin Heidegger". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2015-10-16. Retrieved 2015-10-29.
  72. ^ Foucault, Michel (1961). Khalfa, Jean (ed.). History of Madness [Folie et Déraison: Histoire de la folie à l'âge classique]. Translated by Murphy, Jonathan; Khalfa, Jean. London: Routledge (published 2013). ISBN 9781134473809. from the original on 15 July 2019. Retrieved 3 Mar 2019.
  73. ^ Cat, Jordi (2013). "The Unity of Science". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2014-04-07. Retrieved 2014-03-01.
  74. ^ Levine, George (2008). Darwin Loves You: Natural Selection and the Re-enchantment of the World. Princeton University Press. p. 104. ISBN 978-0-691-13639-4. Retrieved 28 October 2015.
  75. ^ Kitcher, Philip (2001). Science, Truth, and Democracy. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198033356. Retrieved 26 September 2020.
  76. ^ Dennett, Daniel (1995). Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. Simon and Schuster. p. 21. ISBN 978-1-4391-2629-5.
  77. ^ a b Bickle, John; Mandik, Peter; Landreth, Anthony (2010). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "The Philosophy of Neuroscience". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2013-12-02. Retrieved 2015-12-28(Summer 2010 Edition){{cite web}}: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
  78. ^ Romeijn, Jan-Willem (2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Philosophy of Statistics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2018-09-14. Retrieved 2015-10-29.
  79. ^ Horsten, Leon (2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Philosophy of Mathematics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2015-10-29.
  80. ^ Ismael, Jenann (2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Quantum Mechanics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2015-11-06. Retrieved 2015-10-29.
  81. ^ Weisberg, Michael; Needham, Paul; Hendry, Robin (2011). "Philosophy of Chemistry". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2014-04-07. Retrieved 2014-02-14.
  82. ^ "Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method". from the original on 2012-08-02. Retrieved 2018-07-03.
  83. ^ Gewertz, Ken (February 8, 2007). . Harvard University Gazette. Archived from the original on October 11, 2008. Retrieved July 3, 2018..
  84. ^ Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford University Press. 2010.
  85. ^ Hull D. (1969), What philosophy of biology is not, Journal of the History of Biology, 2, pp. 241–268.
  86. ^ Recent examples include Okasha S. (2006), Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press, and Godfrey-Smith P. (2009), Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  87. ^ Papineau, D (1994). "The Virtues of Randomization". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 45 (2): 437–450. doi:10.1093/bjps/45.2.437. S2CID 123314067.
  88. ^ Worrall, J (2002). "What Evidence in Evidence-Based Medicine?". Philosophy of Science. 69 (3): S316–330. doi:10.1086/341855. JSTOR 3081103. S2CID 55078796.
  89. ^ Worrall, J. (2007). "Why there's no cause to randomize". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 58 (3): 451–488. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.120.7314. doi:10.1093/bjps/axm024. S2CID 16964968.
  90. ^ Lee, K., 2012. The Philosophical Foundations of Modern Medicine, London/New York, Palgrave/Macmillan.
  91. ^ Grünbaum, A (1981). "The Placebo Concept". Behaviour Research and Therapy. 19 (2): 157–167. doi:10.1016/0005-7967(81)90040-1. PMID 7271692.
  92. ^ Gøtzsche, P.C. (1994). "Is there logic in the placebo?". Lancet. 344 (8927): 925–926. doi:10.1016/s0140-6736(94)92273-x. PMID 7934350. S2CID 33650340.
  93. ^ Nunn, R., 2009. It's time to put the placebo out of our misery" British Medical Journal 338, b1568.
  94. ^ Turner, A (2012). "Placebos" and the logic of placebo comparison". Biology & Philosophy. 27 (3): 419–432. doi:10.1007/s10539-011-9289-8. hdl:1983/6426ce5a-ab57-419c-bc3c-e57d20608807. S2CID 4488616. from the original on 2018-12-29. Retrieved 2018-12-29.
  95. ^ Worrall, J (2011). "Causality in medicine: getting back to the Hill top". Preventive Medicine. 53 (4–5): 235–238. doi:10.1016/j.ypmed.2011.08.009. PMID 21888926.
  96. ^ Cartwright, N (2009). "What are randomised controlled trials good for?" (PDF). Philosophical Studies. 147 (1): 59–70. doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9450-2. S2CID 56203659. (PDF) from the original on 2018-07-24. Retrieved 2019-09-01.
  97. ^ Murphy, Dominic (Spring 2015). "Philosophy of Psychiatry 2019-03-18 at the Wayback Machine". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta. Accessed 18 August 2016.
  98. ^ a b Mason, Kelby; Sripada, Chandra Sekhar; Stich, Stephen (2010). (PDF). In Moral, Dermot (ed.). Routledge Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophy. London: Routledge. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-05-17. Retrieved 2014-02-20.
  99. ^ Hollis, Martin (1994). The Philosophy of Social Science: An Introduction. Cambridge. ISBN 978-0-521-44780-5.
  100. ^ "Stanford Encyclopaedia: Auguste Comte". from the original on 2017-10-11. Retrieved 2010-01-10.
  101. ^ Giddens, Positivism and Sociology, 1
  102. ^ Schunk, Learning Theories: An Educational Perspective, 5th, 315
  103. ^ Outhwaite, William, 1988 Habermas: Key Contemporary Thinkers, Polity Press (Second Edition 2009), ISBN 978-0-7456-4328-1 p. 68

Sources

  • Boldman, Lee (2007). "Chapter 6, The Privileged Status of Science" (PDF).
  • Chen, Christina S. (2009). Larson, Thomas (ed.). "Atheism and the Assumptions of Science and Religion". Lyceum. X (2): 1–10.
  • Durak, Antoine Berke (6 June 2008). "The nature of reality and knowledge".
  • Gauch, Hugh G. (2002). Scientific Method in Practice. Cambridge University Press.
  • Gould, Stephen J (1987). Time's Arrow, Time's Cycle: Myth and Metaphor in the Discovery of Geological Time. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. p. 120. ISBN 978-0-674-89199-9. You first assume.
  • Heilbron, J.L., ed. (2003). The Oxford Companion to the History of Modern Science. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511229-0.
  • Kneale, William; Kneale, Martha (1962). The Development of Logic. London: Oxford University Press. p. 243. ISBN 978-0-19-824183-6.
  • Priddy, Robert (1998). "Chapter Five, Scientific Objectivity in Question". Science Limited.
  • Simpson, G.G. (1963). "Historical science". In Albritton, Jr., C.C. (ed.). Fabric of geology. Stanford, California: Freeman, Cooper, and Company. pp. 24–48.
  • Sobottka, Stanley (2005). "Consciousness" (PDF). p. 11.
  • Whitehead, A.N. (1997) [1920]. Science and the Modern World. Lowell Lectures. Free Press. p. 135. ISBN 978-0-684-83639-3. LCCN 67002244.

Further reading

  • Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S. (2003), Bayesian Epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
  • Gutting, Gary (2004), Continental Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
  • Peter, Godfrey-Smith (2003), Theory and Reality: An Introduction the Philosophy of Science, University of Chicago Press.
  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed. Univ. of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-45804-5.
  • Losee, J. (1998), A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
  • Papineau, David (2005) Science, Problems of the Philosophy of. Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford.
  • Salmon, Merrilee; John Earman, Clark Glymour, James G. Lenno, Peter Machamer, J.E. McGuire, John D. Norton, Wesley C. Salmon, Kenneth F. Schaffner (1992). Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Prentice-Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-663345-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  • Popper, Karl, (1963) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, ISBN 0-415-04318-2.
  • van Fraassen, Bas (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824424-0.
  • Ziman, John (2000). Real Science: what it is, and what it means. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

External links

philosophy, science, this, article, about, branch, philosophy, journal, philosophy, science, journal, branch, philosophy, concerned, with, foundations, methods, implications, science, central, questions, this, study, concern, what, qualifies, science, reliabil. This article is about the branch of philosophy For the journal see Philosophy of Science journal Philosophy of science is a branch of philosophy concerned with the foundations methods and implications of science The central questions of this study concern what qualifies as science the reliability of scientific theories and the ultimate purpose of science This discipline overlaps with metaphysics ontology and epistemology for example when it explores the relationship between science and truth Philosophy of science focuses on metaphysical epistemic and semantic aspects of science Ethical issues such as bioethics and scientific misconduct are often considered ethics or science studies rather than the philosophy of science There is no consensus among philosophers about many of the central problems concerned with the philosophy of science including whether science can reveal the truth about unobservable things and whether scientific reasoning can be justified at all In addition to these general questions about science as a whole philosophers of science consider problems that apply to particular sciences such as biology or physics Some philosophers of science also use contemporary results in science to reach conclusions about philosophy itself While philosophical thought pertaining to science dates back at least to the time of Aristotle general philosophy of science emerged as a distinct discipline only in the 20th century in the wake of the logical positivist movement which aimed to formulate criteria for ensuring all philosophical statements meaningfulness and objectively assessing them Charles Sanders Peirce and Karl Popper moved on from positivism to establish a modern set of standards for scientific methodology Thomas Kuhn s 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions was also formative challenging the view of scientific progress as the steady cumulative acquisition of knowledge based on a fixed method of systematic experimentation and instead of arguing that any progress is relative to a paradigm the set of questions concepts and practices that define a scientific discipline in a particular historical period 1 Subsequently the coherentist approach to science in which a theory is validated if it makes sense of observations as part of a coherent whole became prominent due to W V Quine and others Some thinkers such as Stephen Jay Gould seek to ground science in axiomatic assumptions such as the uniformity of nature A vocal minority of philosophers and Paul Feyerabend in particular argue that there is no such thing as the scientific method so all approaches to science should be allowed including explicitly supernatural ones Another approach to thinking about science involves studying how knowledge is created from a sociological perspective an approach represented by scholars like David Bloor and Barry Barnes Finally a tradition in continental philosophy approaches science from the perspective of a rigorous analysis of human experience Philosophies of the particular sciences range from questions about the nature of time raised by Einstein s general relativity to the implications of economics for public policy A central theme is whether the terms of one scientific theory can be intra or intertheoretically reduced to the terms of another That is can chemistry be reduced to physics or can sociology be reduced to individual psychology The general questions of philosophy of science also arise with greater specificity in some particular sciences For instance the question of the validity of scientific reasoning is seen in a different guise in the foundations of statistics The question of what counts as science and what should be excluded arises as a life or death matter in the philosophy of medicine Additionally the philosophies of biology psychology and the social sciences explore whether the scientific studies of human nature can achieve objectivity or are inevitably shaped by values and by social relations Contents 1 Introduction 1 1 Defining science 1 2 Scientific explanation 1 3 Justifying science 1 4 Observation inseparable from theory 1 5 The purpose of science 1 6 Values and science 2 History 2 1 Pre modern 2 2 Modern 2 3 Logical positivism 2 4 Thomas Kuhn 3 Current approaches 3 1 Naturalism s axiomatic assumptions 3 2 Coherentism 3 3 Anything goes methodology 3 4 Sociology of scientific knowledge methodology 3 5 Continental philosophy 4 Other topics 4 1 Reductionism 4 2 Social accountability 5 Philosophy of particular sciences 5 1 Philosophy of statistics 5 2 Philosophy of mathematics 5 3 Philosophy of physics 5 4 Philosophy of chemistry 5 5 Philosophy of astronomy 5 6 Philosophy of Earth sciences 5 7 Philosophy of biology 5 8 Philosophy of medicine 5 9 Philosophy of psychiatry 5 10 Philosophy of psychology 5 11 Philosophy of social science 5 12 Philosophy of technology 6 See also 7 Footnotes 8 Sources 9 Further reading 10 External linksIntroduction EditDefining science Edit Main article Demarcation problem Karl Popper in the 1980s Distinguishing between science and non science is referred to as the demarcation problem For example should psychoanalysis creation science and historical materialism be considered pseudosciences Karl Popper called this the central question in the philosophy of science 2 However no unified account of the problem has won acceptance among philosophers and some regard the problem as unsolvable or uninteresting 3 4 Martin Gardner has argued for the use of a Potter Stewart standard I know it when I see it for recognizing pseudoscience 5 Early attempts by the logical positivists grounded science in observation while non science was non observational and hence meaningless 6 Popper argued that the central property of science is falsifiability That is every genuinely scientific claim is capable of being proven false at least in principle 7 An area of study or speculation that masquerades as science in an attempt to claim a legitimacy that it would not otherwise be able to achieve is referred to as pseudoscience fringe science or junk science 8 Physicist Richard Feynman coined the term cargo cult science for cases in which researchers believe they are doing science because their activities have the outward appearance of it but actually lack the kind of utter honesty that allows their results to be rigorously evaluated 9 Scientific explanation Edit Main article Scientific explanation A closely related question is what counts as a good scientific explanation In addition to providing predictions about future events society often takes scientific theories to provide explanations for events that occur regularly or have already occurred Philosophers have investigated the criteria by which a scientific theory can be said to have successfully explained a phenomenon as well as what it means to say a scientific theory has explanatory power One early and influential account of scientific explanation is the deductive nomological model It says that a successful scientific explanation must deduce the occurrence of the phenomena in question from a scientific law 10 This view has been subjected to substantial criticism resulting in several widely acknowledged counterexamples to the theory 11 It is especially challenging to characterize what is meant by an explanation when the thing to be explained cannot be deduced from any law because it is a matter of chance or otherwise cannot be perfectly predicted from what is known Wesley Salmon developed a model in which a good scientific explanation must be statistically relevant to the outcome to be explained 12 13 Others have argued that the key to a good explanation is unifying disparate phenomena or providing a causal mechanism 13 Justifying science Edit Main article Problem of induction The expectations chickens might form about farmer behavior illustrate the problem of induction Although it is often taken for granted it is not at all clear how one can infer the validity of a general statement from a number of specific instances or infer the truth of a theory from a series of successful tests 14 For example a chicken observes that each morning the farmer comes and gives it food for hundreds of days in a row The chicken may therefore use inductive reasoning to infer that the farmer will bring food every morning However one morning the farmer comes and kills the chicken How is scientific reasoning more trustworthy than the chicken s reasoning One approach is to acknowledge that induction cannot achieve certainty but observing more instances of a general statement can at least make the general statement more probable So the chicken would be right to conclude from all those mornings that it is likely the farmer will come with food again the next morning even if it cannot be certain However there remain difficult questions about the process of interpreting any given evidence into a probability that the general statement is true One way out of these particular difficulties is to declare that all beliefs about scientific theories are subjective or personal and correct reasoning is merely about how evidence should change one s subjective beliefs over time 14 Some argue that what scientists do is not inductive reasoning at all but rather abductive reasoning or inference to the best explanation In this account science is not about generalizing specific instances but rather about hypothesizing explanations for what is observed As discussed in the previous section it is not always clear what is meant by the best explanation Ockham s razor which counsels choosing the simplest available explanation thus plays an important role in some versions of this approach To return to the example of the chicken would it be simpler to suppose that the farmer cares about it and will continue taking care of it indefinitely or that the farmer is fattening it up for slaughter Philosophers have tried to make this heuristic principle more precise in terms of theoretical parsimony or other measures Yet although various measures of simplicity have been brought forward as potential candidates it is generally accepted that there is no such thing as a theory independent measure of simplicity In other words there appear to be as many different measures of simplicity as there are theories themselves and the task of choosing between measures of simplicity appears to be every bit as problematic as the job of choosing between theories 15 Nicholas Maxwell has argued for some decades that unity rather than simplicity is the key non empirical factor in influencing choice of theory in science persistent preference for unified theories in effect committing science to the acceptance of a metaphysical thesis concerning unity in nature In order to improve this problematic thesis it needs to be represented in the form of a hierarchy of theses each thesis becoming more insubstantial as one goes up the hierarchy 16 Observation inseparable from theory Edit Seen through a telescope the Einstein cross seems to provide evidence for five different objects but this observation is theory laden If we assume the theory of general relativity the image only provides evidence for two objects When making observations scientists look through telescopes study images on electronic screens record meter readings and so on Generally on a basic level they can agree on what they see e g the thermometer shows 37 9 degrees C But if these scientists have different ideas about the theories that have been developed to explain these basic observations they may disagree about what they are observing For example before Albert Einstein s general theory of relativity observers would have likely interpreted an image of the Einstein cross as five different objects in space In light of that theory however astronomers will tell you that there are actually only two objects one in the center and four different images of a second object around the sides Alternatively if other scientists suspect that something is wrong with the telescope and only one object is actually being observed they are operating under yet another theory Observations that cannot be separated from theoretical interpretation are said to be theory laden 17 All observation involves both perception and cognition That is one does not make an observation passively but rather is actively engaged in distinguishing the phenomenon being observed from surrounding sensory data Therefore observations are affected by one s underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions and that understanding may influence what is perceived noticed or deemed worthy of consideration In this sense it can be argued that all observation is theory laden 17 The purpose of science Edit See also Scientific realism and Instrumentalism Should science aim to determine ultimate truth or are there questions that science cannot answer Scientific realists claim that science aims at truth and that one ought to regard scientific theories as true approximately true or likely true Conversely scientific anti realists argue that science does not aim or at least does not succeed at truth especially truth about unobservables like electrons or other universes 18 Instrumentalists argue that scientific theories should only be evaluated on whether they are useful In their view whether theories are true or not is beside the point because the purpose of science is to make predictions and enable effective technology Realists often point to the success of recent scientific theories as evidence for the truth or near truth of current theories 19 20 Antirealists point to either the many false theories in the history of science 21 22 epistemic morals 23 the success of false modeling assumptions 24 or widely termed postmodern criticisms of objectivity as evidence against scientific realism 19 Antirealists attempt to explain the success of scientific theories without reference to truth 25 Some antirealists claim that scientific theories aim at being accurate only about observable objects and argue that their success is primarily judged by that criterion 23 Values and science Edit Values intersect with science in different ways There are epistemic values that mainly guide the scientific research The scientific enterprise is embedded in particular culture and values through individual practitioners Values emerge from science both as product and process and can be distributed among several cultures in the society When it comes to the justification of science in the sense of general public participation by single practitioners science plays the role of a mediator between evaluating the standards and policies of society and its participating individuals wherefore science indeed falls victim to vandalism and sabotage adapting the means to the end 26 If it is unclear what counts as science how the process of confirming theories works and what the purpose of science is there is considerable scope for values and other social influences to shape science Indeed values can play a role ranging from determining which research gets funded to influencing which theories achieve scientific consensus 27 For example in the 19th century cultural values held by scientists about race shaped research on evolution and values concerning social class influenced debates on phrenology considered scientific at the time 28 Feminist philosophers of science sociologists of science and others explore how social values affect science History EditSee also History of scientific method History of science and History of philosophy Pre modern Edit The origins of philosophy of science trace back to Plato and Aristotle 29 who distinguished the forms of approximate and exact reasoning set out the threefold scheme of abductive deductive and inductive inference and also analyzed reasoning by analogy The eleventh century Arab polymath Ibn al Haytham known in Latin as Alhazen conducted his research in optics by way of controlled experimental testing and applied geometry especially in his investigations into the images resulting from the reflection and refraction of light Roger Bacon 1214 1294 an English thinker and experimenter heavily influenced by al Haytham is recognized by many to be the father of modern scientific method 30 His view that mathematics was essential to a correct understanding of natural philosophy is considered to have been 400 years ahead of its time 31 Modern Edit Francis Bacon s statue at Gray s Inn South Square London Francis Bacon no direct relation to Roger who lived 300 years earlier was a seminal figure in philosophy of science at the time of the Scientific Revolution In his work Novum Organum 1620 an allusion to Aristotle s Organon Bacon outlined a new system of logic to improve upon the old philosophical process of syllogism Bacon s method relied on experimental histories to eliminate alternative theories 32 In 1637 Rene Descartes established a new framework for grounding scientific knowledge in his treatise Discourse on Method advocating the central role of reason as opposed to sensory experience By contrast in 1713 the 2nd edition of Isaac Newton s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica argued that hypotheses have no place in experimental philosophy In this philosophy propositions are deduced from the phenomena and rendered general by induction 33 This passage influenced a later generation of philosophically inclined readers to pronounce a ban on causal hypotheses in natural philosophy 33 In particular later in the 18th century David Hume would famously articulate skepticism about the ability of science to determine causality and gave a definitive formulation of the problem of induction The 19th century writings of John Stuart Mill are also considered important in the formation of current conceptions of the scientific method as well as anticipating later accounts of scientific explanation 34 Logical positivism Edit Main article Logical positivism Instrumentalism became popular among physicists around the turn of the 20th century after which logical positivism defined the field for several decades Logical positivism accepts only testable statements as meaningful rejects metaphysical interpretations and embraces verificationism a set of theories of knowledge that combines logicism empiricism and linguistics to ground philosophy on a basis consistent with examples from the empirical sciences Seeking to overhaul all of philosophy and convert it to a new scientific philosophy 35 the Berlin Circle and the Vienna Circle propounded logical positivism in the late 1920s Interpreting Ludwig Wittgenstein s early philosophy of language logical positivists identified a verifiability principle or criterion of cognitive meaningfulness From Bertrand Russell s logicism they sought reduction of mathematics to logic They also embraced Russell s logical atomism Ernst Mach s phenomenalism whereby the mind knows only actual or potential sensory experience which is the content of all sciences whether physics or psychology and Percy Bridgman s operationalism Thereby only the verifiable was scientific and cognitively meaningful whereas the unverifiable was unscientific cognitively meaningless pseudostatements metaphysical emotive or such not worthy of further review by philosophers who were newly tasked to organize knowledge rather than develop new knowledge Logical positivism is commonly portrayed as taking the extreme position that scientific language should never refer to anything unobservable even the seemingly core notions of causality mechanism and principles but that is an exaggeration Talk of such unobservables could be allowed as metaphorical direct observations viewed in the abstract or at worst metaphysical or emotional Theoretical laws would be reduced to empirical laws while theoretical terms would garner meaning from observational terms via correspondence rules Mathematics in physics would reduce to symbolic logic via logicism while rational reconstruction would convert ordinary language into standardized equivalents all networked and united by a logical syntax A scientific theory would be stated with its method of verification whereby a logical calculus or empirical operation could verify its falsity or truth In the late 1930s logical positivists fled Germany and Austria for Britain and America By then many had replaced Mach s phenomenalism with Otto Neurath s physicalism and Rudolf Carnap had sought to replace verification with simply confirmation With World War II s close in 1945 logical positivism became milder logical empiricism led largely by Carl Hempel in America who expounded the covering law model of scientific explanation as a way of identifying the logical form of explanations without any reference to the suspect notion of causation The logical positivist movement became a major underpinning of analytic philosophy 36 and dominated Anglosphere philosophy including philosophy of science while influencing sciences into the 1960s Yet the movement failed to resolve its central problems 37 38 39 and its doctrines were increasingly assaulted Nevertheless it brought about the establishment of philosophy of science as a distinct subdiscipline of philosophy with Carl Hempel playing a key role 40 For Kuhn the addition of epicycles in Ptolemaic astronomy was normal science within a paradigm whereas the Copernican revolution was a paradigm shift Thomas Kuhn Edit Main article The Structure of Scientific Revolutions In the 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Thomas Kuhn argued that the process of observation and evaluation takes place within a paradigm a logically consistent portrait of the world that is consistent with observations made from its framing A paradigm also encompasses the set of questions and practices that define a scientific discipline He characterized normal science as the process of observation and puzzle solving which takes place within a paradigm whereas revolutionary science occurs when one paradigm overtakes another in a paradigm shift 41 Kuhn denied that it is ever possible to isolate the hypothesis being tested from the influence of the theory in which the observations are grounded and he argued that it is not possible to evaluate competing paradigms independently More than one logically consistent construct can paint a usable likeness of the world but there is no common ground from which to pit two against each other theory against theory Each paradigm has its own distinct questions aims and interpretations Neither provides a standard by which the other can be judged so there is no clear way to measure scientific progress across paradigms For Kuhn the choice of paradigm was sustained by rational processes but not ultimately determined by them The choice between paradigms involves setting two or more portraits against the world and deciding which likeness is most promising For Kuhn acceptance or rejection of a paradigm is a social process as much as a logical process Kuhn s position however is not one of relativism 42 According to Kuhn a paradigm shift occurs when a significant number of observational anomalies arise in the old paradigm and a new paradigm makes sense of them That is the choice of a new paradigm is based on observations even though those observations are made against the background of the old paradigm Current approaches EditNaturalism s axiomatic assumptions Edit All scientific study inescapably builds on at least some essential assumptions that are untested by scientific processes 43 44 Kuhn concurs that all science is based on an approved agenda of unprovable assumptions about the character of the universe rather than merely on empirical facts These assumptions a paradigm comprise a collection of beliefs values and techniques that are held by a given scientific community which legitimize their systems and set the limitations to their investigation 45 For naturalists nature is the only reality the only paradigm There is no such thing as supernatural The scientific method is to be used to investigate all reality 46 and Naturalism is the implicit philosophy of working scientists 47 The following basic assumptions are needed to justify the scientific method 48 that there is an objective reality shared by all rational observers 48 49 The basis for rationality is acceptance of an external objective reality 50 As an individual we cannot know that the sensory information we perceive is generated artificially or originates from a real world Any belief that it arises from a real world outside us is actually an assumption It seems more beneficial to assume that an objective reality exists than to live with solipsism and so people are quite happy to make this assumption In fact we made this assumption unconsciously when we began to learn about the world as infants The world outside ourselves appears to respond in ways which are consistent with it being real The assumption of objectivism is essential if we are to attach the contemporary meanings to our sensations and feelings and make more sense of them 51 Without this assumption there would be only the thoughts and images in our own mind which would be the only existing mind and there would be no need of science or anything else 52 that this objective reality is governed by natural laws 48 49 Science at least today assumes that the universe obeys to knoweable principles that don t depend on time or place nor on subjective parameters such as what we think know or how we behave 50 Hugh Gauch argues that science presupposes that the physical world is orderly and comprehensible 53 that reality can be discovered by means of systematic observation and experimentation 48 49 Stanley Sobottka said The assumption of external reality is necessary for science to function and to flourish For the most part science is the discovering and explaining of the external world 52 Science attempts to produce knowledge that is as universal and objective as possible within the realm of human understanding 50 that Nature has uniformity of laws and most if not all things in nature must have at least a natural cause 49 Biologist Stephen Jay Gould referred to these two closely related propositions as the constancy of nature s laws and the operation of known processes 54 Simpson agrees that the axiom of uniformity of law an unprovable postulate is necessary in order for scientists to extrapolate inductive inference into the unobservable past in order to meaningfully study it 55 that experimental procedures will be done satisfactorily without any deliberate or unintentional mistakes that will influence the results 49 that experimenters won t be significantly biased by their presumptions 49 that random sampling is representative of the entire population 49 A simple random sample SRS is the most basic probabilistic option used for creating a sample from a population The benefit of SRS is that the investigator is guaranteed to choose a sample that represents the population that ensures statistically valid conclusions 56 Coherentism Edit Main article Coherentism Jeremiah Horrocks makes the first observation of the transit of Venus in 1639 as imagined by the artist W R Lavender in 1903 In contrast to the view that science rests on foundational assumptions coherentism asserts that statements are justified by being a part of a coherent system Or rather individual statements cannot be validated on their own only coherent systems can be justified 57 A prediction of a transit of Venus is justified by its being coherent with broader beliefs about celestial mechanics and earlier observations As explained above observation is a cognitive act That is it relies on a pre existing understanding a systematic set of beliefs An observation of a transit of Venus requires a huge range of auxiliary beliefs such as those that describe the optics of telescopes the mechanics of the telescope mount and an understanding of celestial mechanics If the prediction fails and a transit is not observed that is likely to occasion an adjustment in the system a change in some auxiliary assumption rather than a rejection of the theoretical system citation needed In fact according to the Duhem Quine thesis after Pierre Duhem and W V Quine it is impossible to test a theory in isolation 58 One must always add auxiliary hypotheses in order to make testable predictions For example to test Newton s Law of Gravitation in the solar system one needs information about the masses and positions of the Sun and all the planets Famously the failure to predict the orbit of Uranus in the 19th century led not to the rejection of Newton s Law but rather to the rejection of the hypothesis that the solar system comprises only seven planets The investigations that followed led to the discovery of an eighth planet Neptune If a test fails something is wrong But there is a problem in figuring out what that something is a missing planet badly calibrated test equipment an unsuspected curvature of space or something else citation needed One consequence of the Duhem Quine thesis is that one can make any theory compatible with any empirical observation by the addition of a sufficient number of suitable ad hoc hypotheses Karl Popper accepted this thesis leading him to reject naive falsification Instead he favored a survival of the fittest view in which the most falsifiable scientific theories are to be preferred 59 Anything goes methodology Edit Main article Epistemological anarchism Paul Karl Feyerabend Paul Feyerabend 1924 1994 argued that no description of scientific method could possibly be broad enough to include all the approaches and methods used by scientists and that there are no useful and exception free methodological rules governing the progress of science He argued that the only principle that does not inhibit progress is anything goes 60 Feyerabend said that science started as a liberating movement but that over time it had become increasingly dogmatic and rigid and had some oppressive features and thus had become increasingly an ideology Because of this he said it was impossible to come up with an unambiguous way to distinguish science from religion magic or mythology He saw the exclusive dominance of science as a means of directing society as authoritarian and ungrounded 60 Promulgation of this epistemological anarchism earned Feyerabend the title of the worst enemy of science from his detractors 61 Sociology of scientific knowledge methodology Edit Main article Sociology of scientific knowledge According to Kuhn science is an inherently communal activity which can only be done as part of a community 62 For him the fundamental difference between science and other disciplines is the way in which the communities function Others especially Feyerabend and some post modernist thinkers have argued that there is insufficient difference between social practices in science and other disciplines to maintain this distinction For them social factors play an important and direct role in scientific method but they do not serve to differentiate science from other disciplines On this account science is socially constructed though this does not necessarily imply the more radical notion that reality itself is a social construct Michel Foucault sought to analyze and uncover how disciplines within the social sciences developed and adopted the methodologies used by their practitioners In works like The Archaeology of Knowledge he used the term human sciences The human sciences do not comprise mainstream academic disciplines they are rather an interdisciplinary space for the reflection on man who is the subject of more mainstream scientific knowledge taken now as an object sitting between these more conventional areas and of course associating with disciplines such as anthropology psychology sociology and even history 63 Rejecting the realist view of scientific inquiry Foucault argued throughout his work that scientific discourse is not simply an objective study of phenomena as both natural and social scientists like to believe but is rather the product of systems of power relations struggling to construct scientific disciplines and knowledge within given societies 64 With the advances of scientific disciplines such as psychology and anthropology the need to separate categorize normalize and institutionalize populations into constructed social identities became a staple of the sciences Constructions of what were considered normal and abnormal stigmatized and ostracized groups of people like the mentally ill and sexual and gender minorities 65 However some such as Quine do maintain that scientific reality is a social construct Physical objects are conceptually imported into the situation as convenient intermediaries not by definition in terms of experience but simply as irreducible posits comparable epistemologically to the gods of Homer For my part I do qua lay physicist believe in physical objects and not in Homer s gods and I consider it a scientific error to believe otherwise But in point of epistemological footing the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind Both sorts of entities enter our conceptions only as cultural posits 66 The public backlash of scientists against such views particularly in the 1990s became known as the science wars 67 A major development in recent decades has been the study of the formation structure and evolution of scientific communities by sociologists and anthropologists including David Bloor Harry Collins Bruno Latour Ian Hacking and Anselm Strauss Concepts and methods such as rational choice social choice or game theory from economics have also been applied by whom for understanding the efficiency of scientific communities in the production of knowledge This interdisciplinary field has come to be known as science and technology studies 68 Here the approach to the philosophy of science is to study how scientific communities actually operate Continental philosophy Edit Philosophers in the continental philosophical tradition are not traditionally categorized by whom as philosophers of science However they have much to say about science some of which has anticipated themes in the analytical tradition For example in The Genealogy of Morals 1887 Friedrich Nietzsche advanced the thesis that the motive for the search for truth in sciences is a kind of ascetic ideal 69 Hegel with his Berlin studentsSketch by Franz Kugler In general continental philosophy views science from a world historical perspective Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 1770 1831 became one of the first philosophers to support this view Philosophers such as Pierre Duhem 1861 1916 and Gaston Bachelard 1884 1962 also wrote their works with this world historical approach to science predating Kuhn s 1962 work by a generation or more All of these approaches involve a historical and sociological turn to science with a priority on lived experience a kind of Husserlian life world rather than a progress based or anti historical approach as emphasised in the analytic tradition One can trace this continental strand of thought through the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl 1859 1938 the late works of Merleau Ponty Nature Course Notes from the College de France 1956 1960 and the hermeneutics of Martin Heidegger 1889 1976 70 The largest effect on the continental tradition with respect to science came from Martin Heidegger s critique of the theoretical attitude in general which of course includes the scientific attitude 71 For this reason the continental tradition has remained much more skeptical of the importance of science in human life and in philosophical inquiry Nonetheless there have been a number of important works especially those of a Kuhnian precursor Alexandre Koyre 1892 1964 Another important development was that of Michel Foucault s analysis of historical and scientific thought in The Order of Things 1966 and his study of power and corruption within the science of madness 72 Post Heideggerian authors contributing to continental philosophy of science in the second half of the 20th century include Jurgen Habermas e g Truth and Justification 1998 Carl Friedrich von Weizsacker The Unity of Nature 1980 German Die Einheit der Natur 1971 and Wolfgang Stegmuller Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie 1973 1986 Other topics EditReductionism Edit Analysis involves breaking an observation or theory down into simpler concepts in order to understand it Reductionism can refer to one of several philosophical positions related to this approach One type of reductionism suggests that phenomena are amenable to scientific explanation at lower levels of analysis and inquiry Perhaps a historical event might be explained in sociological and psychological terms which in turn might be described in terms of human physiology which in turn might be described in terms of chemistry and physics 73 Daniel Dennett distinguishes legitimate reductionism from what he calls greedy reductionism which denies real complexities and leaps too quickly to sweeping generalizations 74 Social accountability Edit See also The Mismeasure of Man A broad issue affecting the neutrality of science concerns the areas which science chooses to explore that is what part of the world and of humankind are studied by science Philip Kitcher in his Science Truth and Democracy 75 argues that scientific studies that attempt to show one segment of the population as being less intelligent successful or emotionally backward compared to others have a political feedback effect which further excludes such groups from access to science Thus such studies undermine the broad consensus required for good science by excluding certain people and so proving themselves in the end to be unscientific Philosophy of particular sciences EditThere is no such thing as philosophy free science there is only science whose philosophical baggage is taken on board without examination 76 Daniel Dennett Darwin s Dangerous Idea 1995 In addition to addressing the general questions regarding science and induction many philosophers of science are occupied by investigating foundational problems in particular sciences They also examine the implications of particular sciences for broader philosophical questions The late 20th and early 21st century has seen a rise in the number of practitioners of philosophy of a particular science 77 Philosophy of statistics Edit Main article Philosophy of statistics The problem of induction discussed above is seen in another form in debates over the foundations of statistics 78 The standard approach to statistical hypothesis testing avoids claims about whether evidence supports a hypothesis or makes it more probable Instead the typical test yields a p value which is the probability of the evidence being such as it is under the assumption that the hypothesis being tested is true If the p value is too low the hypothesis is rejected in a way analogous to falsification In contrast Bayesian inference seeks to assign probabilities to hypotheses Related topics in philosophy of statistics include probability interpretations overfitting and the difference between correlation and causation Philosophy of mathematics Edit Main article Philosophy of mathematics Philosophy of mathematics is concerned with the philosophical foundations and implications of mathematics 79 The central questions are whether numbers triangles and other mathematical entities exist independently of the human mind and what is the nature of mathematical propositions Is asking whether 1 1 2 is true fundamentally different from asking whether a ball is red Was calculus invented or discovered A related question is whether learning mathematics requires experience or reason alone What does it mean to prove a mathematical theorem and how does one know whether a mathematical proof is correct Philosophers of mathematics also aim to clarify the relationships between mathematics and logic human capabilities such as intuition and the material universe Philosophy of physics Edit Main article Philosophy of physics Unsolved problem in physics How does the quantum description of reality which includes elements such as the superposition of states and wavefunction collapse give rise to the reality we perceive more unsolved problems in physics Philosophy of physics is the study of the fundamental philosophical questions underlying modern physics the study of matter and energy and how they interact The main questions concern the nature of space and time atoms and atomism Also included are the predictions of cosmology the interpretation of quantum mechanics the foundations of statistical mechanics causality determinism and the nature of physical laws 80 Classically several of these questions were studied as part of metaphysics for example those about causality determinism and space and time Philosophy of chemistry Edit Main article Philosophy of chemistry Philosophy of chemistry is the philosophical study of the methodology and content of the science of chemistry It is explored by philosophers chemists and philosopher chemist teams It includes research on general philosophy of science issues as applied to chemistry For example can all chemical phenomena be explained by quantum mechanics or is it not possible to reduce chemistry to physics For another example chemists have discussed the philosophy of how theories are confirmed in the context of confirming reaction mechanisms Determining reaction mechanisms is difficult because they cannot be observed directly Chemists can use a number of indirect measures as evidence to rule out certain mechanisms but they are often unsure if the remaining mechanism is correct because there are many other possible mechanisms that they have not tested or even thought of 81 Philosophers have also sought to clarify the meaning of chemical concepts which do not refer to specific physical entities such as chemical bonds Philosophy of astronomy Edit The philosophy of astronomy seeks to understand and analyze the methodologies and technologies used by experts in the discipline focusing on how observations made about space and astrophysical phenomena can be studied Given that astronomers rely and use theories and formulas from other scientific disciplines such as chemistry and physics the pursuit of understanding how knowledge can be obtained about the cosmos as well as the relation in which our planet and Solar System have within our personal views of our place in the universe philosophical insights into how facts about space can be scientifically analyzed and configure with other established knowledge is a main point of inquiry Philosophy of Earth sciences Edit The philosophy of Earth science is concerned with how humans obtain and verify knowledge of the workings of the Earth system including the atmosphere hydrosphere and geosphere solid earth Earth scientists ways of knowing and habits of mind share important commonalities with other sciences but also have distinctive attributes that emerge from the complex heterogeneous unique long lived and non manipulatable nature of the Earth system Philosophy of biology Edit Main article Philosophy of biology Peter Godfrey Smith was awarded the Lakatos Award 82 for his 2009 book Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection which discusses the philosophical foundations of the theory of evolution 83 84 Philosophy of biology deals with epistemological metaphysical and ethical issues in the biological and biomedical sciences Although philosophers of science and philosophers generally have long been interested in biology e g Aristotle Descartes Leibniz and even Kant philosophy of biology only emerged as an independent field of philosophy in the 1960s and 1970s 85 Philosophers of science began to pay increasing attention to developments in biology from the rise of the modern synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s to the discovery of the structure of deoxyribonucleic acid DNA in 1953 to more recent advances in genetic engineering Other key ideas such as the reduction of all life processes to biochemical reactions as well as the incorporation of psychology into a broader neuroscience are also addressed Research in current philosophy of biology includes investigation of the foundations of evolutionary theory such as Peter Godfrey Smith s work 86 and the role of viruses as persistent symbionts in host genomes As a consequence the evolution of genetic content order is seen as the result of competent genome editors further explanation needed in contrast to former narratives in which error replication events mutations dominated Philosophy of medicine Edit Main article Philosophy of medicine A fragment of the Hippocratic Oath from the third century Beyond medical ethics and bioethics the philosophy of medicine is a branch of philosophy that includes the epistemology and ontology metaphysics of medicine Within the epistemology of medicine evidence based medicine EBM or evidence based practice EBP has attracted attention most notably the roles of randomisation 87 88 89 blinding and placebo controls Related to these areas of investigation ontologies of specific interest to the philosophy of medicine include Cartesian dualism the monogenetic conception of disease 90 and the conceptualization of placebos and placebo effects 91 92 93 94 There is also a growing interest in the metaphysics of medicine 95 particularly the idea of causation Philosophers of medicine might not only be interested in how medical knowledge is generated but also in the nature of such phenomena Causation is of interest because the purpose of much medical research is to establish causal relationships e g what causes disease or what causes people to get better 96 Philosophy of psychiatry Edit Main article Philosophy of psychiatry Philosophy of psychiatry explores philosophical questions relating to psychiatry and mental illness The philosopher of science and medicine Dominic Murphy identifies three areas of exploration in the philosophy of psychiatry The first concerns the examination of psychiatry as a science using the tools of the philosophy of science more broadly The second entails the examination of the concepts employed in discussion of mental illness including the experience of mental illness and the normative questions it raises The third area concerns the links and discontinuities between the philosophy of mind and psychopathology 97 Philosophy of psychology Edit Main article Philosophy of psychology Wilhelm Wundt seated with colleagues in his psychological laboratory the first of its kind Philosophy of psychology refers to issues at the theoretical foundations of modern psychology Some of these issues are epistemological concerns about the methodology of psychological investigation For example is the best method for studying psychology to focus only on the response of behavior to external stimuli or should psychologists focus on mental perception and thought processes 98 If the latter an important question is how the internal experiences of others can be measured Self reports of feelings and beliefs may not be reliable because even in cases in which there is no apparent incentive for subjects to intentionally deceive in their answers self deception or selective memory may affect their responses Then even in the case of accurate self reports how can responses be compared across individuals Even if two individuals respond with the same answer on a Likert scale they may be experiencing very different things Other issues in philosophy of psychology are philosophical questions about the nature of mind brain and cognition and are perhaps more commonly thought of as part of cognitive science or philosophy of mind For example are humans rational creatures 98 Is there any sense in which they have free will and how does that relate to the experience of making choices Philosophy of psychology also closely monitors contemporary work conducted in cognitive neuroscience psycholinguistics and artificial intelligence questioning what they can and cannot explain in psychology Philosophy of psychology is a relatively young field because psychology only became a discipline of its own in the late 1800s In particular neurophilosophy has just recently become its own field with the works of Paul Churchland and Patricia Churchland 77 Philosophy of mind by contrast has been a well established discipline since before psychology was a field of study at all It is concerned with questions about the very nature of mind the qualities of experience and particular issues like the debate between dualism and monism Philosophy of social science Edit Main article Philosophy of social science The philosophy of social science is the study of the logic and method of the social sciences such as sociology and cultural anthropology 99 Philosophers of social science are concerned with the differences and similarities between the social and the natural sciences causal relationships between social phenomena the possible existence of social laws and the ontological significance of structure and agency The French philosopher Auguste Comte 1798 1857 established the epistemological perspective of positivism in The Course in Positivist Philosophy a series of texts published between 1830 and 1842 The first three volumes of the Course dealt chiefly with the natural sciences already in existence geoscience astronomy physics chemistry biology whereas the latter two emphasised the inevitable coming of social science sociologie 100 For Comte the natural sciences had to necessarily arrive first before humanity could adequately channel its efforts into the most challenging and complex Queen science of human society itself Comte offers an evolutionary system proposing that society undergoes three phases in its quest for the truth according to a general law of three stages These are 1 the theological 2 the metaphysical and 3 the positive 101 Comte s positivism established the initial philosophical foundations for formal sociology and social research Durkheim Marx and Weber are more typically cited as the fathers of contemporary social science In psychology a positivistic approach has historically been favoured in behaviourism Positivism has also been espoused by technocrats who believe in the inevitability of social progress through science and technology 102 The positivist perspective has been associated with scientism the view that the methods of the natural sciences may be applied to all areas of investigation be it philosophical social scientific or otherwise Among most social scientists and historians orthodox positivism has long since lost popular support Today practitioners of both social and physical sciences instead take into account the distorting effect of observer bias and structural limitations This scepticism has been facilitated by a general weakening of deductivist accounts of science by philosophers such as Thomas Kuhn and new philosophical movements such as critical realism and neopragmatism The philosopher sociologist Jurgen Habermas has critiqued pure instrumental rationality as meaning that scientific thinking becomes something akin to ideology itself 103 Philosophy of technology Edit Main article Philosophy of technology The philosophy of technology is a sub field of philosophy that studies the nature of technology Specific research topics include study of the role of tacit and explicit knowledge in creating and using technology the nature of functions in technological artifacts the role of values in design and ethics related to technology Technology and engineering can both involve the application of scientific knowledge The philosophy of engineering is an emerging sub field of the broader philosophy of technology See also Edit Philosophy portal Science portalBayesian epistemology Criticism of science History and philosophy of science List of philosophers of science Metaphysical naturalism Metascience Objectivity philosophy Philosophy of engineering Science policyFootnotes Edit Thomas S Kuhn Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 2015 04 17 Instead he argued that the paradigm determines the kinds of experiments scientists perform the types of questions they ask and the problems they consider important Thornton Stephen 2006 Karl Popper Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2007 06 27 Retrieved 2007 12 01 Science and Pseudo science Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2008 Archived from the original on 2015 09 05 Laudan Larry 1983 The Demise of the Demarcation Problem In Grunbaum Adolf Cohen Robert Sonne Laudan Larry eds Physics Philosophy and Psychoanalysis Essays in Honor of Adolf Grunbaum Springer ISBN 978 90 277 1533 3 Gordin Michael D 2012 The Pseudoscience Wars Immanuel Velikovsky and the Birth of the Modern Fringe University of Chicago Press pp 12 13 ISBN 978 0 226 30442 7 Uebel Thomas 2006 Vienna Circle Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2007 06 26 Retrieved 2007 12 01 Popper Karl 2004 The logic of scientific discovery reprint ed London amp New York Routledge Classics ISBN 978 0 415 27844 7First published 1959 by Hutchinson amp Co a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint postscript link Pseudoscientific pretending to be scientific falsely represented as being scientific Oxford American Dictionary Oxford English Dictionary Hansson Sven Ove 1996 Defining Pseudoscience Philosophia Naturalis 33 169 176 as cited in Science and Pseudo science Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2008 Archived from the original on 2015 09 05 The Stanford article states Many writers on pseudoscience have emphasized that pseudoscience is non science posing as science The foremost modern classic on the subject Gardner 1957 bears the title Fads and Fallacies in the Name of Science According to Brian Baigrie 1988 438 w hat is objectionable about these beliefs is that they masquerade as genuinely scientific ones These and many other authors assume that to be pseudoscientific an activity or a teaching has to satisfy the following two criteria Hansson 1996 1 it is not scientific and 2 its major proponents try to create the impression that it is scientific For example Hewitt Paul G Suchocki John Hewitt Leslie A 2003 Conceptual Physical Science 3rd ed Addison Wesley ISBN 0 321 05173 4 Bennett Jeffrey O 2003 The Cosmic Perspective 3rd ed Addison Wesley ISBN 0 8053 8738 2 See also e g Gauch HG Jr Scientific Method in Practice 2003 A 2006 National Science Foundation report on Science and engineering indicators quoted Michael Shermer s 1997 definition of pseudoscience claims presented so that they appear to be scientific even though they lack supporting evidence and plausibility p 33 In contrast science is a set of methods designed to describe and interpret observed and inferred phenomena past or present and aimed at building a testable body of knowledge open to rejection or confirmation p 17 Shermer Michael 1997 Why People Believe Weird Things Pseudoscience Superstition and Other Confusions of Our Time New York W H Freeman and Company ISBN 978 0 7167 3090 3 as cited by National Science Foundation Division of Science Resources Statistics 2006 Science and Technology Public Attitudes and Understanding Science and engineering indicators 2006 A pretended or spurious science a collection of related beliefs about the world mistakenly regarded as being based on scientific method or as having the status that scientific truths now have from the Oxford English Dictionary second edition 1989 Feynman Richard Cargo Cult Science PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2013 12 01 Retrieved 2015 10 25 Hempel Carl G Oppenheim Paul 1948 Studies in the Logic of Explanation Philosophy of Science 15 2 135 175 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 294 3693 doi 10 1086 286983 S2CID 16924146 Salmon Merrilee Earman John Glymour Clark Lenno James G Machamer Peter McGuire J E Norton John D Salmon Wesley C Schaffner Kenneth F 1992 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 663345 7 Salmon Wesley 1971 Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance Pittsburgh University of Pittsburgh Press ISBN 9780822974116 a b Woodward James 2003 Scientific Explanation Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2007 07 06 Retrieved 2007 12 07 a b Vickers John 2013 The Problem of Induction Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2014 04 07 Retrieved 2014 02 25 Baker Alan 2013 Simplicity Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2014 03 26 Retrieved 2014 02 25 Nicholas Maxwell 1998 The Comprehensibility of the Universe Archived 2018 02 27 at the Wayback Machine Clarendon Press 2017 Understanding Scientific Progress Aim Oriented Empiricism Archived 2018 02 20 at the Wayback Machine Paragon House St Paul a b Bogen Jim 2013 Theory and Observation in Science Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2014 02 27 Retrieved 2014 02 25 Levin Michael 1984 What Kind of Explanation is Truth In Jarrett Leplin ed Scientific Realism Berkeley University of California Press pp 124 1139 ISBN 978 0 520 05155 3 a b Boyd Richard 2002 Scientific Realism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2007 07 06 Retrieved 2007 12 01 Specific examples include Popper Karl 2002 Conjectures and Refutations London amp New York Routledge Classics ISBN 978 0 415 28594 0First published 1963 by Routledge and Kegan Paul a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint postscript link Smart J J C 1968 Between Science and Philosophy New York Random House Putnam Hilary 1975 Mathematics Matter and Method Philosophical Papers Vol I London Cambridge University Press Putnam Hilary 1978 Meaning and the Moral Sciences London Routledge and Kegan Paul Boyd Richard 1984 The Current Status of Scientific Realism In Jarrett Leplin ed Scientific Realism Berkeley University of California Press pp 41 82 ISBN 978 0 520 05155 3 Stanford P Kyle 2006 Exceeding Our Grasp Science History and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 517408 3 Laudan Larry 1981 A Confutation of Convergent Realism Philosophy of Science 48 218 249 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 594 2523 doi 10 1086 288975 S2CID 108290084 a b van Fraassen Bas 1980 The Scientific Image Oxford The Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824424 0 Winsberg Eric September 2006 Models of Success Versus the Success of Models Reliability without Truth Synthese 152 1 19 doi 10 1007 s11229 004 5404 6 S2CID 18275928 Stanford P Kyle June 2000 An Antirealist Explanation of the Success of Science Philosophy of Science 67 2 266 284 doi 10 1086 392775 S2CID 35878807 Rosenstock Linda Lee Lore Jackson January 2002 Attacks on Science The Risks to Evidence Based Policy American Journal of Public Health 92 1 14 18 doi 10 2105 ajph 92 1 14 ISSN 0090 0036 PMC 1447376 PMID 11772749 Longino Helen 2013 The Social Dimensions of Scientific Knowledge Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2014 03 26 Retrieved 2014 03 06 Douglas Allchin Values in Science and in Science Education in International Handbook of Science Education B J Fraser and K G Tobin eds 2 1083 1092 Kluwer Academic Publishers 1988 Aristotle Prior Analytics Hugh Tredennick trans pp 181 531 in Aristotle Volume 1 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London 1938 Lindberg David C 1980 Science in the Middle Ages University of Chicago Press pp 350 351 ISBN 978 0 226 48233 0 Clegg Brian The First Scientist A Life of Roger Bacon Archived 2018 07 08 at the Wayback Machine Carroll and Graf Publishers NY 2003 p 2 Bacon Francis Novum Organum The New Organon 1620 Bacon s work described many of the accepted principles underscoring the importance of empirical results data gathering and experiment Encyclopaedia Britannica 1911 Bacon Francis states In Novum Organum we proceed to apply what is perhaps the most valuable part of the Baconian method the process of exclusion or rejection This elimination of the non essential is the most important of Bacon s contributions to the logic of induction and that in which as he repeatedly says his method differs from all previous philosophies a b McMullin Ernan The Impact of Newton s Principia on the Philosophy of Science www paricenter com Pari Center for New Learning Archived from the original on 24 October 2015 Retrieved 29 October 2015 John Stuart Mill Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy plato stanford edu Archived from the original on 2010 01 06 Retrieved 2009 07 31 Michael Friedman Reconsidering Logical Positivism New York Cambridge University Press 1999 p xiv Archived 2016 06 28 at the Wayback Machine See Vienna Circle Archived 2015 08 10 at the Wayback Machine in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Smith L D 1986 Behaviorism and Logical Positivism A Reassessment of the Alliance Stanford University Press p 314 ISBN 978 0 8047 1301 6 LCCN 85030366 Retrieved 2016 01 27 The secondary and historical literature on logical positivism affords substantial grounds for concluding that logical positivism failed to solve many of the central problems it generated for itself Prominent among the unsolved problems was the failure to find an acceptable statement of the verifiability later confirmability criterion of meaningfulness Until a competing tradition emerged about the late 1950s the problems of logical positivism continued to be attacked from within that tradition But as the new tradition in the philosophy of science began to demonstrate its effectiveness by dissolving and rephrasing old problems as well as by generating new ones philosophers began to shift allegiances to the new tradition even though that tradition has yet to receive a canonical formulation Bunge M A 1996 Finding Philosophy in Social Science Yale University Press p 317 ISBN 978 0 300 06606 7 LCCN lc96004399 Retrieved 2016 01 27 To conclude logical positivism was progressive compared with the classical positivism of Ptolemy Hume d Alembert Comte John Stuart Mill and Ernst Mach It was even more so by comparison with its contemporary rivals neo Thomism neo Kantianism intuitionism dialectical materialism phenomenology and existentialism However neo positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science whether natural or social It failed because it remained anchored to sense data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis and denounced realism and materialism as metaphysical nonsense Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers notably Popper 1959 1935 1963 logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists Regrettably the anti positivism fashionable in the metatheory of social science is often nothing but an excuse for sloppiness and wild speculation Popper Falsifiability and the Failure of Positivism 7 August 2000 Archived from the original on January 7 2014 Retrieved 7 January 2014 The upshot is that the positivists seem caught between insisting on the V C Verifiability Criterion but for no defensible reason or admitting that the V C requires a background language etc which opens the door to relativism etc In light of this dilemma many folk especially following Popper s last ditch effort to save empiricism positivism realism with the falsifiability criterion have agreed that positivism is a dead end Friedman Reconsidering Logical Positivism Cambridge U P 1999 p xii Archived 2016 06 28 at the Wayback Machine Bird Alexander 2013 Zalta Edward N ed Thomas Kuhn Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2017 07 13 Retrieved 2015 10 26 T S Kuhn The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 2nd ed Chicago Univ of Chicago Pr 1970 p 206 ISBN 0 226 45804 0 Priddy 1998 Whitehead 1997 p 135 All science must start with some assumptions as to the ultimate analysis of the facts with which it deals Boldman 2007 Papineau David Naturalism Archived 26 April 2018 at the Wayback Machine in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Strahler 1992 p 3harvnb error no target CITEREFStrahler1992 help The naturalistic view is espoused by science as its fundamental assumption a b c d Heilbron 2003 p vii a b c d e f g Chen 2009 pp 1 2 a b c Durak 2008 Vaccaro Joan Theism and Atheism Archived from the original on 17 February 2018 Retrieved 22 December 2017 a b Sobottka 2005 p 11 Gauch 2002 p 154 Expressed as a single grand statement science presupposes that the physical world is orderly and comprehensible The most obvious components of this comprehensive presupposition are that the physical world exists and that our sense perceptions are generally reliable Gould 1987 p 120 You cannot go to a rocky outcrop and observe either the constancy of nature s laws or the working of known processes It works the other way around You first assume these propositions and then you go to the outcrop of rock Simpson 1963 pp 24 48 Uniformity is an unprovable postulate justified or indeed required on two grounds First nothing in our incomplete but extensive knowledge of history disagrees with it Second only with this postulate is a rational interpretation of history possible and we are justified in seeking as scientists we must seek such a rational interpretation Simple Random Sampling 14 December 2010 Archived from the original on 2 January 2018 Retrieved 2 January 2018 A simple random sample SRS is the most basic probabilistic option used for creating a sample from a population Each SRS is made of individuals drawn from a larger population completely at random As a result said individuals have an equal chance of being selected throughout the sampling process The benefit of SRS is that as a result the investigator is guaranteed to choose a sample which is representative of the population which ensures statistically valid conclusions Olsson Erik 2014 Zalta Edward N ed Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2018 09 14 Retrieved 2015 10 26 Sandra Harding 1976 Can theories be refuted essays on the Dunhem Quine thesis Springer Science amp Business Media pp 9 ISBN 978 90 277 0630 0 Archived from the original on 2016 06 28 Retrieved 2016 01 27 Popper Karl 2005 The Logic of Scientific Discovery Taylor amp Francis e Library ed London and New York Routledge Taylor amp Francis e Library chapters 3 4 ISBN 978 0 203 99462 7 a b Paul Feyerabend Against Method Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge 1975 ISBN 0 391 00381 X 0 86091 222 1 0 86091 481 X 0 86091 646 4 0 86091 934 X 0 902308 91 2 Preston John 2007 02 15 Paul Feyerabend In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Kuhn T S 1996 Postscript The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 3rd ed Univ of Chicago Pr p 176 ISBN 978 0 226 45808 3 A paradigm is what the members of a community of scientists share and conversely a scientific community consists of men who share a paradigm Foucault Michel Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 29 August 2022 Morrison Thomas 2018 Foucault s Elephant Philosophy Now No 127 Retrieved 29 August 2022 Power Jason L 2015 Disciplining Truth and Science Michel Foucault and the Power of Social Science PDF World Scientific News 7 15 29 ISSN 2392 2192 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Quine Willard Van Orman 1980 Two Dogmas of Empiricism From a Logical Point of View Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 32351 3 Ashman Keith M Barringer Philip S eds 2001 After the Science Wars London Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 21209 0 Retrieved 29 October 2015 The war is between scientists who believe that science and its methods are objective and an increasing number of social scientists historians philosophers and others gathered under the umbrella of Science Studies Woodhouse Edward Science Technology and Society Spring 2015 ed n p U Readers 2014 Print Hatab Lawrence J 2008 How Does the Ascetic Ideal Function in Nietzsche s Genealogy The Journal of Nietzsche Studies 35 35 36 106 123 doi 10 2307 jnietstud 35 2008 0106 S2CID 170630145 Archived from the original on 2016 03 04 Retrieved 2019 10 22 Gutting Gary 2004 Continental Philosophy of Science Blackwell Publishers Cambridge MA Wheeler Michael 2015 Martin Heidegger Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2015 10 16 Retrieved 2015 10 29 Foucault Michel 1961 Khalfa Jean ed History of Madness Folie et Deraison Histoire de la folie a l age classique Translated by Murphy Jonathan Khalfa Jean London Routledge published 2013 ISBN 9781134473809 Archived from the original on 15 July 2019 Retrieved 3 Mar 2019 Cat Jordi 2013 The Unity of Science Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2014 04 07 Retrieved 2014 03 01 Levine George 2008 Darwin Loves You Natural Selection and the Re enchantment of the World Princeton University Press p 104 ISBN 978 0 691 13639 4 Retrieved 28 October 2015 Kitcher Philip 2001 Science Truth and Democracy Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198033356 Retrieved 26 September 2020 Dennett Daniel 1995 Darwin s Dangerous Idea Evolution and the Meanings of Life Simon and Schuster p 21 ISBN 978 1 4391 2629 5 a b Bickle John Mandik Peter Landreth Anthony 2010 Zalta Edward N ed The Philosophy of Neuroscience Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2013 12 02 Retrieved 2015 12 28 Summer 2010 Edition a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint postscript link Romeijn Jan Willem 2014 Zalta Edward N ed Philosophy of Statistics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2018 09 14 Retrieved 2015 10 29 Horsten Leon 2015 Zalta Edward N ed Philosophy of Mathematics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2015 10 29 Ismael Jenann 2015 Zalta Edward N ed Quantum Mechanics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2015 11 06 Retrieved 2015 10 29 Weisberg Michael Needham Paul Hendry Robin 2011 Philosophy of Chemistry Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2014 04 07 Retrieved 2014 02 14 Philosophy Logic and Scientific Method Archived from the original on 2012 08 02 Retrieved 2018 07 03 Gewertz Ken February 8 2007 The philosophy of evolution Godfrey Smith takes an ingenious evolutionary approach to how the mind works Harvard University Gazette Archived from the original on October 11 2008 Retrieved July 3 2018 Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection Oxford University Press 2010 Hull D 1969 What philosophy of biology is not Journal of the History of Biology 2 pp 241 268 Recent examples include Okasha S 2006 Evolution and the Levels of Selection Oxford Oxford University Press and Godfrey Smith P 2009 Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection Oxford Oxford University Press Papineau D 1994 The Virtues of Randomization British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 2 437 450 doi 10 1093 bjps 45 2 437 S2CID 123314067 Worrall J 2002 What Evidence in Evidence Based Medicine Philosophy of Science 69 3 S316 330 doi 10 1086 341855 JSTOR 3081103 S2CID 55078796 Worrall J 2007 Why there s no cause to randomize British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 3 451 488 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 120 7314 doi 10 1093 bjps axm024 S2CID 16964968 Lee K 2012 The Philosophical Foundations of Modern Medicine London New York Palgrave Macmillan Grunbaum A 1981 The Placebo Concept Behaviour Research and Therapy 19 2 157 167 doi 10 1016 0005 7967 81 90040 1 PMID 7271692 Gotzsche P C 1994 Is there logic in the placebo Lancet 344 8927 925 926 doi 10 1016 s0140 6736 94 92273 x PMID 7934350 S2CID 33650340 Nunn R 2009 It s time to put the placebo out of our misery British Medical Journal 338 b1568 Turner A 2012 Placebos and the logic of placebo comparison Biology amp Philosophy 27 3 419 432 doi 10 1007 s10539 011 9289 8 hdl 1983 6426ce5a ab57 419c bc3c e57d20608807 S2CID 4488616 Archived from the original on 2018 12 29 Retrieved 2018 12 29 Worrall J 2011 Causality in medicine getting back to the Hill top Preventive Medicine 53 4 5 235 238 doi 10 1016 j ypmed 2011 08 009 PMID 21888926 Cartwright N 2009 What are randomised controlled trials good for PDF Philosophical Studies 147 1 59 70 doi 10 1007 s11098 009 9450 2 S2CID 56203659 Archived PDF from the original on 2018 07 24 Retrieved 2019 09 01 Murphy Dominic Spring 2015 Philosophy of Psychiatry Archived 2019 03 18 at the Wayback Machine The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy edited by Edward N Zalta Accessed 18 August 2016 a b Mason Kelby Sripada Chandra Sekhar Stich Stephen 2010 Philosophy of Psychology PDF In Moral Dermot ed Routledge Companion to Twentieth Century Philosophy London Routledge Archived from the original PDF on 2017 05 17 Retrieved 2014 02 20 Hollis Martin 1994 The Philosophy of Social Science An Introduction Cambridge ISBN 978 0 521 44780 5 Stanford Encyclopaedia Auguste Comte Archived from the original on 2017 10 11 Retrieved 2010 01 10 Giddens Positivism and Sociology 1 Schunk Learning Theories An Educational Perspective 5th 315 Outhwaite William 1988 Habermas Key Contemporary Thinkers Polity Press Second Edition 2009 ISBN 978 0 7456 4328 1 p 68Sources EditBoldman Lee 2007 Chapter 6 The Privileged Status of Science PDF Chen Christina S 2009 Larson Thomas ed Atheism and the Assumptions of Science and Religion Lyceum X 2 1 10 Durak Antoine Berke 6 June 2008 The nature of reality and knowledge Gauch Hugh G 2002 Scientific Method in Practice Cambridge University Press Gould Stephen J 1987 Time s Arrow Time s Cycle Myth and Metaphor in the Discovery of Geological Time Cambridge Harvard University Press p 120 ISBN 978 0 674 89199 9 You first assume Heilbron J L ed 2003 The Oxford Companion to the History of Modern Science New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511229 0 Kneale William Kneale Martha 1962 The Development of Logic London Oxford University Press p 243 ISBN 978 0 19 824183 6 Priddy Robert 1998 Chapter Five Scientific Objectivity in Question Science Limited Simpson G G 1963 Historical science In Albritton Jr C C ed Fabric of geology Stanford California Freeman Cooper and Company pp 24 48 Sobottka Stanley 2005 Consciousness PDF p 11 Whitehead A N 1997 1920 Science and the Modern World Lowell Lectures Free Press p 135 ISBN 978 0 684 83639 3 LCCN 67002244 Further reading EditBovens L and Hartmann S 2003 Bayesian Epistemology Oxford University Press Oxford Gutting Gary 2004 Continental Philosophy of Science Blackwell Publishers Cambridge MA Peter Godfrey Smith 2003 Theory and Reality An Introduction the Philosophy of Science University of Chicago Press Kuhn T S 1970 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 2nd ed Univ of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 45804 5 Losee J 1998 A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Oxford University Press Oxford Papineau David 2005 Science Problems of the Philosophy of Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford Salmon Merrilee John Earman Clark Glymour James G Lenno Peter Machamer J E McGuire John D Norton Wesley C Salmon Kenneth F Schaffner 1992 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 663345 7 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Popper Karl 1963 Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge ISBN 0 415 04318 2 van Fraassen Bas 1980 The Scientific Image Oxford The Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824424 0 Ziman John 2000 Real Science what it is and what it means Cambridge Cambridge University Press External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Philosophy of science Wikimedia Commons has media related to Philosophy of science Philosophy of science at PhilPapers Philosophy of science at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Philosophy of science Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Philosophy of science amp oldid 1139771693, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.