fbpx
Wikipedia

Conjecture

In mathematics, a conjecture is a conclusion or a proposition that is proffered on a tentative basis without proof.[1][2][3] Some conjectures, such as the Riemann hypothesis (still a conjecture) or Fermat's Last Theorem (a conjecture until proven in 1995 by Andrew Wiles), have shaped much of mathematical history as new areas of mathematics are developed in order to prove them.[4]

The real part (red) and imaginary part (blue) of the Riemann zeta function along the critical line Re(s) = 1/2. The first non-trivial zeros can be seen at Im(s) = ±14.135, ±21.022 and ±25.011. The Riemann hypothesis, a famous conjecture, says that all non-trivial zeros of the zeta function lie along the critical line.

Resolution of conjectures edit

Proof edit

Formal mathematics is based on provable truth. In mathematics, any number of cases supporting a universally quantified conjecture, no matter how large, is insufficient for establishing the conjecture's veracity, since a single counterexample could immediately bring down the conjecture. Mathematical journals sometimes publish the minor results of research teams having extended the search for a counterexample farther than previously done. For instance, the Collatz conjecture, which concerns whether or not certain sequences of integers terminate, has been tested for all integers up to 1.2 × 1012 (over a trillion). However, the failure to find a counterexample after extensive search does not constitute a proof that the conjecture is true—because the conjecture might be false but with a very large minimal counterexample.

Nevertheless, mathematicians often regard a conjecture as strongly supported by evidence even though not yet proved. That evidence may be of various kinds, such as verification of consequences of it or strong interconnections with known results.[5]

A conjecture is considered proven only when it has been shown that it is logically impossible for it to be false. There are various methods of doing so; see methods of mathematical proof for more details.

One method of proof, applicable when there are only a finite number of cases that could lead to counterexamples, is known as "brute force": in this approach, all possible cases are considered and shown not to give counterexamples. In some occasions, the number of cases is quite large, in which case a brute-force proof may require as a practical matter the use of a computer algorithm to check all the cases. For example, the validity of the 1976 and 1997 brute-force proofs of the four color theorem by computer was initially doubted, but was eventually confirmed in 2005 by theorem-proving software.

When a conjecture has been proven, it is no longer a conjecture but a theorem. Many important theorems were once conjectures, such as the Geometrization theorem (which resolved the Poincaré conjecture), Fermat's Last Theorem, and others.

Disproof edit

Conjectures disproven through counterexample are sometimes referred to as false conjectures (cf. the Pólya conjecture and Euler's sum of powers conjecture). In the case of the latter, the first counterexample found for the n=4 case involved numbers in the millions, although it has been subsequently found that the minimal counterexample is actually smaller.

Independent conjectures edit

Not every conjecture ends up being proven true or false. The continuum hypothesis, which tries to ascertain the relative cardinality of certain infinite sets, was eventually shown to be independent from the generally accepted set of Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms of set theory. It is therefore possible to adopt this statement, or its negation, as a new axiom in a consistent manner (much as Euclid's parallel postulate can be taken either as true or false in an axiomatic system for geometry).

In this case, if a proof uses this statement, researchers will often look for a new proof that doesn't require the hypothesis (in the same way that it is desirable that statements in Euclidean geometry be proved using only the axioms of neutral geometry, i.e. without the parallel postulate). The one major exception to this in practice is the axiom of choice, as the majority of researchers usually do not worry whether a result requires it—unless they are studying this axiom in particular.

Conditional proofs edit

Sometimes, a conjecture is called a hypothesis when it is used frequently and repeatedly as an assumption in proofs of other results. For example, the Riemann hypothesis is a conjecture from number theory that — amongst other things — makes predictions about the distribution of prime numbers. Few number theorists doubt that the Riemann hypothesis is true. In fact, in anticipation of its eventual proof, some have even proceeded to develop further proofs which are contingent on the truth of this conjecture. These are called conditional proofs: the conjectures assumed appear in the hypotheses of the theorem, for the time being.

These "proofs", however, would fall apart if it turned out that the hypothesis was false, so there is considerable interest in verifying the truth or falsity of conjectures of this type.

Important examples edit

Fermat's Last Theorem edit

In number theory, Fermat's Last Theorem (sometimes called Fermat's conjecture, especially in older texts) states that no three positive integers  ,  , and   can satisfy the equation   for any integer value of   greater than two.

This theorem was first conjectured by Pierre de Fermat in 1637 in the margin of a copy of Arithmetica, where he claimed that he had a proof that was too large to fit in the margin.[6] The first successful proof was released in 1994 by Andrew Wiles, and formally published in 1995, after 358 years of effort by mathematicians. The unsolved problem stimulated the development of algebraic number theory in the 19th century, and the proof of the modularity theorem in the 20th century. It is among the most notable theorems in the history of mathematics, and prior to its proof it was in the Guinness Book of World Records for "most difficult mathematical problems".[7]

Four color theorem edit

 
A four-coloring of a map of the states of the United States (ignoring lakes).

In mathematics, the four color theorem, or the four color map theorem, states that given any separation of a plane into contiguous regions, producing a figure called a map, no more than four colors are required to color the regions of the map—so that no two adjacent regions have the same color. Two regions are called adjacent if they share a common boundary that is not a corner, where corners are the points shared by three or more regions.[8] For example, in the map of the United States of America, Utah and Arizona are adjacent, but Utah and New Mexico, which only share a point that also belongs to Arizona and Colorado, are not.

Möbius mentioned the problem in his lectures as early as 1840.[9] The conjecture was first proposed on October 23, 1852[10] when Francis Guthrie, while trying to color the map of counties of England, noticed that only four different colors were needed. The five color theorem, which has a short elementary proof, states that five colors suffice to color a map and was proven in the late 19th century;[11] however, proving that four colors suffice turned out to be significantly harder. A number of false proofs and false counterexamples have appeared since the first statement of the four color theorem in 1852.

The four color theorem was ultimately proven in 1976 by Kenneth Appel and Wolfgang Haken. It was the first major theorem to be proved using a computer. Appel and Haken's approach started by showing that there is a particular set of 1,936 maps, each of which cannot be part of a smallest-sized counterexample to the four color theorem (i.e., if they did appear, one could make a smaller counter-example). Appel and Haken used a special-purpose computer program to confirm that each of these maps had this property. Additionally, any map that could potentially be a counterexample must have a portion that looks like one of these 1,936 maps. Showing this with hundreds of pages of hand analysis, Appel and Haken concluded that no smallest counterexample exists because any must contain, yet do not contain, one of these 1,936 maps. This contradiction means there are no counterexamples at all and that the theorem is therefore true. Initially, their proof was not accepted by mathematicians at all because the computer-assisted proof was infeasible for a human to check by hand.[12] However, the proof has since then gained wider acceptance, although doubts still remain.[13]

Hauptvermutung edit

The Hauptvermutung (German for main conjecture) of geometric topology is the conjecture that any two triangulations of a triangulable space have a common refinement, a single triangulation that is a subdivision of both of them. It was originally formulated in 1908, by Steinitz and Tietze.[14]

This conjecture is now known to be false. The non-manifold version was disproved by John Milnor[15] in 1961 using Reidemeister torsion.

The manifold version is true in dimensions m ≤ 3. The cases m = 2 and 3 were proved by Tibor Radó and Edwin E. Moise[16] in the 1920s and 1950s, respectively.

Weil conjectures edit

In mathematics, the Weil conjectures were some highly influential proposals by André Weil (1949) on the generating functions (known as local zeta-functions) derived from counting the number of points on algebraic varieties over finite fields.

A variety V over a finite field with q elements has a finite number of rational points, as well as points over every finite field with qk elements containing that field. The generating function has coefficients derived from the numbers Nk of points over the (essentially unique) field with qk elements.

Weil conjectured that such zeta-functions should be rational functions, should satisfy a form of functional equation, and should have their zeroes in restricted places. The last two parts were quite consciously modeled on the Riemann zeta function and Riemann hypothesis. The rationality was proved by Dwork (1960), the functional equation by Grothendieck (1965), and the analogue of the Riemann hypothesis was proved by Deligne (1974).

Poincaré conjecture edit

In mathematics, the Poincaré conjecture is a theorem about the characterization of the 3-sphere, which is the hypersphere that bounds the unit ball in four-dimensional space. The conjecture states that:

Every simply connected, closed 3-manifold is homeomorphic to the 3-sphere.

An equivalent form of the conjecture involves a coarser form of equivalence than homeomorphism called homotopy equivalence: if a 3-manifold is homotopy equivalent to the 3-sphere, then it is necessarily homeomorphic to it.

Originally conjectured by Henri Poincaré in 1904, the theorem concerns a space that locally looks like ordinary three-dimensional space but is connected, finite in size, and lacks any boundary (a closed 3-manifold). The Poincaré conjecture claims that if such a space has the additional property that each loop in the space can be continuously tightened to a point, then it is necessarily a three-dimensional sphere. An analogous result has been known in higher dimensions for some time.

After nearly a century of effort by mathematicians, Grigori Perelman presented a proof of the conjecture in three papers made available in 2002 and 2003 on arXiv. The proof followed on from the program of Richard S. Hamilton to use the Ricci flow to attempt to solve the problem. Hamilton later introduced a modification of the standard Ricci flow, called Ricci flow with surgery to systematically excise singular regions as they develop, in a controlled way, but was unable to prove this method "converged" in three dimensions.[17] Perelman completed this portion of the proof. Several teams of mathematicians have verified that Perelman's proof is correct.

The Poincaré conjecture, before being proven, was one of the most important open questions in topology.

Riemann hypothesis edit

In mathematics, the Riemann hypothesis, proposed by Bernhard Riemann (1859), is a conjecture that the non-trivial zeros of the Riemann zeta function all have real part 1/2. The name is also used for some closely related analogues, such as the Riemann hypothesis for curves over finite fields.

The Riemann hypothesis implies results about the distribution of prime numbers. Along with suitable generalizations, some mathematicians consider it the most important unresolved problem in pure mathematics.[18] The Riemann hypothesis, along with the Goldbach conjecture, is part of Hilbert's eighth problem in David Hilbert's list of 23 unsolved problems; it is also one of the Clay Mathematics Institute Millennium Prize Problems.

P versus NP problem edit

The P versus NP problem is a major unsolved problem in computer science. Informally, it asks whether every problem whose solution can be quickly verified by a computer can also be quickly solved by a computer; it is widely conjectured that the answer is no. It was essentially first mentioned in a 1956 letter written by Kurt Gödel to John von Neumann. Gödel asked whether a certain NP-complete problem could be solved in quadratic or linear time.[19] The precise statement of the P=NP problem was introduced in 1971 by Stephen Cook in his seminal paper "The complexity of theorem proving procedures"[20] and is considered by many to be the most important open problem in the field.[21] It is one of the seven Millennium Prize Problems selected by the Clay Mathematics Institute to carry a US$1,000,000 prize for the first correct solution.

Other conjectures edit

In other sciences edit

Karl Popper pioneered the use of the term "conjecture" in scientific philosophy.[24] Conjecture is related to hypothesis, which in science refers to a testable conjecture.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ "Definition of CONJECTURE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2019-11-12.
  2. ^ Oxford Dictionary of English (2010 ed.).
  3. ^ Schwartz, JL (1995). Shuttling between the particular and the general: reflections on the role of conjecture and hypothesis in the generation of knowledge in science and mathematics. Oxford University Press. p. 93. ISBN 9780195115772.
  4. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Fermat's Last Theorem". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2019-11-12.
  5. ^ Franklin, James (2016). "Logical probability and the strength of mathematical conjectures" (PDF). Mathematical Intelligencer. 38 (3): 14–19. doi:10.1007/s00283-015-9612-3. S2CID 30291085. (PDF) from the original on 2017-03-09. Retrieved 30 June 2021.
  6. ^ Ore, Oystein (1988) [1948], Number Theory and Its History, Dover, pp. 203–204, ISBN 978-0-486-65620-5
  7. ^ "Science and Technology". The Guinness Book of World Records. Guinness Publishing Ltd. 1995.
  8. ^ Georges Gonthier (December 2008). "Formal Proof—The Four-Color Theorem". Notices of the AMS. 55 (11): 1382–1393. From this paper: Definitions: A planar map is a set of pairwise disjoint subsets of the plane, called regions. A simple map is one whose regions are connected open sets. Two regions of a map are adjacent if their respective closures have a common point that is not a corner of the map. A point is a corner of a map if and only if it belongs to the closures of at least three regions. Theorem: The regions of any simple planar map can be colored with only four colors, in such a way that any two adjacent regions have different colors.
  9. ^ W. W. Rouse Ball (1960) The Four Color Theorem, in Mathematical Recreations and Essays, Macmillan, New York, pp 222-232.
  10. ^ Donald MacKenzie, Mechanizing Proof: Computing, Risk, and Trust (MIT Press, 2004) p103
  11. ^ Heawood, P. J. (1890). "Map-Colour Theorems". Quarterly Journal of Mathematics. 24. Oxford: 332–338.
  12. ^ Swart, E. R. (1980). "The Philosophical Implications of the Four-Color Problem". The American Mathematical Monthly. 87 (9): 697–702. doi:10.2307/2321855. ISSN 0002-9890. JSTOR 2321855.
  13. ^ Wilson, Robin (2014). Four colors suffice : how the map problem was solved (Revised color ed.). Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. pp. 216–222. ISBN 9780691158228. OCLC 847985591.
  14. ^ "Triangulation and the Hauptvermutung". www.maths.ed.ac.uk. Retrieved 2019-11-12.
  15. ^ Milnor, John W. (1961). "Two complexes which are homeomorphic but combinatorially distinct". Annals of Mathematics. 74 (2): 575–590. doi:10.2307/1970299. JSTOR 1970299. MR 0133127.
  16. ^ Moise, Edwin E. (1977). Geometric Topology in Dimensions 2 and 3. New York: New York : Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-0-387-90220-3.
  17. ^ Hamilton, Richard S. (1997). "Four-manifolds with positive isotropic curvature". Communications in Analysis and Geometry. 5 (1): 1–92. doi:10.4310/CAG.1997.v5.n1.a1. MR 1456308. Zbl 0892.53018.
  18. ^ Bombieri, Enrico (2000). (PDF). Clay Mathematics Institute. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2015-12-22. Retrieved 2019-11-12.
  19. ^ Juris Hartmanis 1989, Gödel, von Neumann, and the P = NP problem, Bulletin of the European Association for Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 38, pp. 101–107
  20. ^ Cook, Stephen (1971). "The complexity of theorem proving procedures". Proceedings of the Third Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing. pp. 151–158. doi:10.1145/800157.805047. ISBN 9781450374644. S2CID 7573663.
  21. ^ Lance Fortnow, The status of the P versus NP problem, Communications of the ACM 52 (2009), no. 9, pp. 78–86. doi:10.1145/1562164.1562186
  22. ^ Richards, Ian (1974). "On the Incompatibility of Two Conjectures Concerning Primes". Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 80: 419–438. doi:10.1090/S0002-9904-1974-13434-8.
  23. ^ Langlands, Robert (1967), Letter to Prof. Weil
  24. ^ Popper, Karl (2004). Conjectures and refutations : the growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-28594-1.

Works cited edit

External links edit

  •   Media related to Conjectures at Wikimedia Commons
  • Open Problem Garden

conjecture, text, reconstruction, textual, criticism, mathematics, conjecture, conclusion, proposition, that, proffered, tentative, basis, without, proof, some, conjectures, such, riemann, hypothesis, still, conjecture, fermat, last, theorem, conjecture, until. For text reconstruction see Conjecture textual criticism In mathematics a conjecture is a conclusion or a proposition that is proffered on a tentative basis without proof 1 2 3 Some conjectures such as the Riemann hypothesis still a conjecture or Fermat s Last Theorem a conjecture until proven in 1995 by Andrew Wiles have shaped much of mathematical history as new areas of mathematics are developed in order to prove them 4 The real part red and imaginary part blue of the Riemann zeta function along the critical line Re s 1 2 The first non trivial zeros can be seen at Im s 14 135 21 022 and 25 011 The Riemann hypothesis a famous conjecture says that all non trivial zeros of the zeta function lie along the critical line Contents 1 Resolution of conjectures 1 1 Proof 1 2 Disproof 1 3 Independent conjectures 2 Conditional proofs 3 Important examples 3 1 Fermat s Last Theorem 3 2 Four color theorem 3 3 Hauptvermutung 3 4 Weil conjectures 3 5 Poincare conjecture 3 6 Riemann hypothesis 3 7 P versus NP problem 3 8 Other conjectures 4 In other sciences 5 See also 6 References 6 1 Works cited 7 External linksResolution of conjectures editProof edit Formal mathematics is based on provable truth In mathematics any number of cases supporting a universally quantified conjecture no matter how large is insufficient for establishing the conjecture s veracity since a single counterexample could immediately bring down the conjecture Mathematical journals sometimes publish the minor results of research teams having extended the search for a counterexample farther than previously done For instance the Collatz conjecture which concerns whether or not certain sequences of integers terminate has been tested for all integers up to 1 2 1012 over a trillion However the failure to find a counterexample after extensive search does not constitute a proof that the conjecture is true because the conjecture might be false but with a very large minimal counterexample Nevertheless mathematicians often regard a conjecture as strongly supported by evidence even though not yet proved That evidence may be of various kinds such as verification of consequences of it or strong interconnections with known results 5 A conjecture is considered proven only when it has been shown that it is logically impossible for it to be false There are various methods of doing so see methods of mathematical proof for more details One method of proof applicable when there are only a finite number of cases that could lead to counterexamples is known as brute force in this approach all possible cases are considered and shown not to give counterexamples In some occasions the number of cases is quite large in which case a brute force proof may require as a practical matter the use of a computer algorithm to check all the cases For example the validity of the 1976 and 1997 brute force proofs of the four color theorem by computer was initially doubted but was eventually confirmed in 2005 by theorem proving software When a conjecture has been proven it is no longer a conjecture but a theorem Many important theorems were once conjectures such as the Geometrization theorem which resolved the Poincare conjecture Fermat s Last Theorem and others Disproof edit Conjectures disproven through counterexample are sometimes referred to as false conjectures cf the Polya conjecture and Euler s sum of powers conjecture In the case of the latter the first counterexample found for the n 4 case involved numbers in the millions although it has been subsequently found that the minimal counterexample is actually smaller Independent conjectures edit Not every conjecture ends up being proven true or false The continuum hypothesis which tries to ascertain the relative cardinality of certain infinite sets was eventually shown to be independent from the generally accepted set of Zermelo Fraenkel axioms of set theory It is therefore possible to adopt this statement or its negation as a new axiom in a consistent manner much as Euclid s parallel postulate can be taken either as true or false in an axiomatic system for geometry In this case if a proof uses this statement researchers will often look for a new proof that doesn t require the hypothesis in the same way that it is desirable that statements in Euclidean geometry be proved using only the axioms of neutral geometry i e without the parallel postulate The one major exception to this in practice is the axiom of choice as the majority of researchers usually do not worry whether a result requires it unless they are studying this axiom in particular Conditional proofs editSometimes a conjecture is called a hypothesis when it is used frequently and repeatedly as an assumption in proofs of other results For example the Riemann hypothesis is a conjecture from number theory that amongst other things makes predictions about the distribution of prime numbers Few number theorists doubt that the Riemann hypothesis is true In fact in anticipation of its eventual proof some have even proceeded to develop further proofs which are contingent on the truth of this conjecture These are called conditional proofs the conjectures assumed appear in the hypotheses of the theorem for the time being These proofs however would fall apart if it turned out that the hypothesis was false so there is considerable interest in verifying the truth or falsity of conjectures of this type Important examples editFermat s Last Theorem edit Main article Fermat s Last Theorem In number theory Fermat s Last Theorem sometimes called Fermat s conjecture especially in older texts states that no three positive integers a displaystyle a nbsp b displaystyle b nbsp and c displaystyle c nbsp can satisfy the equation a n b n c n displaystyle a n b n c n nbsp for any integer value of n displaystyle n nbsp greater than two This theorem was first conjectured by Pierre de Fermat in 1637 in the margin of a copy of Arithmetica where he claimed that he had a proof that was too large to fit in the margin 6 The first successful proof was released in 1994 by Andrew Wiles and formally published in 1995 after 358 years of effort by mathematicians The unsolved problem stimulated the development of algebraic number theory in the 19th century and the proof of the modularity theorem in the 20th century It is among the most notable theorems in the history of mathematics and prior to its proof it was in the Guinness Book of World Records for most difficult mathematical problems 7 Four color theorem edit Main article Four color theorem nbsp A four coloring of a map of the states of the United States ignoring lakes In mathematics the four color theorem or the four color map theorem states that given any separation of a plane into contiguous regions producing a figure called a map no more than four colors are required to color the regions of the map so that no two adjacent regions have the same color Two regions are called adjacent if they share a common boundary that is not a corner where corners are the points shared by three or more regions 8 For example in the map of the United States of America Utah and Arizona are adjacent but Utah and New Mexico which only share a point that also belongs to Arizona and Colorado are not Mobius mentioned the problem in his lectures as early as 1840 9 The conjecture was first proposed on October 23 1852 10 when Francis Guthrie while trying to color the map of counties of England noticed that only four different colors were needed The five color theorem which has a short elementary proof states that five colors suffice to color a map and was proven in the late 19th century 11 however proving that four colors suffice turned out to be significantly harder A number of false proofs and false counterexamples have appeared since the first statement of the four color theorem in 1852 The four color theorem was ultimately proven in 1976 by Kenneth Appel and Wolfgang Haken It was the first major theorem to be proved using a computer Appel and Haken s approach started by showing that there is a particular set of 1 936 maps each of which cannot be part of a smallest sized counterexample to the four color theorem i e if they did appear one could make a smaller counter example Appel and Haken used a special purpose computer program to confirm that each of these maps had this property Additionally any map that could potentially be a counterexample must have a portion that looks like one of these 1 936 maps Showing this with hundreds of pages of hand analysis Appel and Haken concluded that no smallest counterexample exists because any must contain yet do not contain one of these 1 936 maps This contradiction means there are no counterexamples at all and that the theorem is therefore true Initially their proof was not accepted by mathematicians at all because the computer assisted proof was infeasible for a human to check by hand 12 However the proof has since then gained wider acceptance although doubts still remain 13 Hauptvermutung edit Main article Hauptvermutung The Hauptvermutung German for main conjecture of geometric topology is the conjecture that any two triangulations of a triangulable space have a common refinement a single triangulation that is a subdivision of both of them It was originally formulated in 1908 by Steinitz and Tietze 14 This conjecture is now known to be false The non manifold version was disproved by John Milnor 15 in 1961 using Reidemeister torsion The manifold version is true in dimensions m 3 The cases m 2 and 3 were proved by Tibor Rado and Edwin E Moise 16 in the 1920s and 1950s respectively Weil conjectures edit Main article Weil conjectures In mathematics the Weil conjectures were some highly influential proposals by Andre Weil 1949 on the generating functions known as local zeta functions derived from counting the number of points on algebraic varieties over finite fields A variety V over a finite field with q elements has a finite number of rational points as well as points over every finite field with qk elements containing that field The generating function has coefficients derived from the numbers Nk of points over the essentially unique field with qk elements Weil conjectured that such zeta functions should be rational functions should satisfy a form of functional equation and should have their zeroes in restricted places The last two parts were quite consciously modeled on the Riemann zeta function and Riemann hypothesis The rationality was proved by Dwork 1960 the functional equation by Grothendieck 1965 and the analogue of the Riemann hypothesis was proved by Deligne 1974 Poincare conjecture edit Main article Poincare conjectureIn mathematics the Poincare conjecture is a theorem about the characterization of the 3 sphere which is the hypersphere that bounds the unit ball in four dimensional space The conjecture states that Every simply connected closed 3 manifold is homeomorphic to the 3 sphere An equivalent form of the conjecture involves a coarser form of equivalence than homeomorphism called homotopy equivalence if a 3 manifold is homotopy equivalent to the 3 sphere then it is necessarily homeomorphic to it Originally conjectured by Henri Poincare in 1904 the theorem concerns a space that locally looks like ordinary three dimensional space but is connected finite in size and lacks any boundary a closed 3 manifold The Poincare conjecture claims that if such a space has the additional property that each loop in the space can be continuously tightened to a point then it is necessarily a three dimensional sphere An analogous result has been known in higher dimensions for some time After nearly a century of effort by mathematicians Grigori Perelman presented a proof of the conjecture in three papers made available in 2002 and 2003 on arXiv The proof followed on from the program of Richard S Hamilton to use the Ricci flow to attempt to solve the problem Hamilton later introduced a modification of the standard Ricci flow called Ricci flow with surgery to systematically excise singular regions as they develop in a controlled way but was unable to prove this method converged in three dimensions 17 Perelman completed this portion of the proof Several teams of mathematicians have verified that Perelman s proof is correct The Poincare conjecture before being proven was one of the most important open questions in topology Riemann hypothesis edit Main article Riemann hypothesis In mathematics the Riemann hypothesis proposed by Bernhard Riemann 1859 is a conjecture that the non trivial zeros of the Riemann zeta function all have real part 1 2 The name is also used for some closely related analogues such as the Riemann hypothesis for curves over finite fields The Riemann hypothesis implies results about the distribution of prime numbers Along with suitable generalizations some mathematicians consider it the most important unresolved problem in pure mathematics 18 The Riemann hypothesis along with the Goldbach conjecture is part of Hilbert s eighth problem in David Hilbert s list of 23 unsolved problems it is also one of the Clay Mathematics Institute Millennium Prize Problems P versus NP problem edit Main article P versus NP problem The P versus NP problem is a major unsolved problem in computer science Informally it asks whether every problem whose solution can be quickly verified by a computer can also be quickly solved by a computer it is widely conjectured that the answer is no It was essentially first mentioned in a 1956 letter written by Kurt Godel to John von Neumann Godel asked whether a certain NP complete problem could be solved in quadratic or linear time 19 The precise statement of the P NP problem was introduced in 1971 by Stephen Cook in his seminal paper The complexity of theorem proving procedures 20 and is considered by many to be the most important open problem in the field 21 It is one of the seven Millennium Prize Problems selected by the Clay Mathematics Institute to carry a US 1 000 000 prize for the first correct solution Other conjectures edit Goldbach s conjecture The twin prime conjecture The Collatz conjecture The Manin conjecture The Maldacena conjecture The Euler conjecture proposed by Euler in the 18th century but for which counterexamples for a number of exponents starting with n 4 were found beginning in the mid 20th century The Hardy Littlewood conjectures are a pair of conjectures concerning the distribution of prime numbers the first of which expands upon the aforementioned twin prime conjecture Neither one has either been proven or disproven but it has been proven that both cannot simultaneously be true i e at least one must be false It has not been proven which one is false but it is widely believed that the first conjecture is true and the second one is false 22 The Langlands program 23 is a far reaching web of these ideas of unifying conjectures that link different subfields of mathematics e g between number theory and representation theory of Lie groups Some of these conjectures have since been proved In other sciences editKarl Popper pioneered the use of the term conjecture in scientific philosophy 24 Conjecture is related to hypothesis which in science refers to a testable conjecture See also editBold hypothesis Futures studies Hypotheticals List of conjectures Ramanujan machineReferences edit Definition of CONJECTURE www merriam webster com Retrieved 2019 11 12 Oxford Dictionary of English 2010 ed Schwartz JL 1995 Shuttling between the particular and the general reflections on the role of conjecture and hypothesis in the generation of knowledge in science and mathematics Oxford University Press p 93 ISBN 9780195115772 Weisstein Eric W Fermat s Last Theorem mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2019 11 12 Franklin James 2016 Logical probability and the strength of mathematical conjectures PDF Mathematical Intelligencer 38 3 14 19 doi 10 1007 s00283 015 9612 3 S2CID 30291085 Archived PDF from the original on 2017 03 09 Retrieved 30 June 2021 Ore Oystein 1988 1948 Number Theory and Its History Dover pp 203 204 ISBN 978 0 486 65620 5 Science and Technology The Guinness Book of World Records Guinness Publishing Ltd 1995 Georges Gonthier December 2008 Formal Proof The Four Color Theorem Notices of the AMS 55 11 1382 1393 From this paper Definitions A planar map is a set of pairwise disjoint subsets of the plane called regions A simple map is one whose regions are connected open sets Two regions of a map are adjacent if their respective closures have a common point that is not a corner of the map A point is a corner of a map if and only if it belongs to the closures of at least three regions Theorem The regions of any simple planar map can be colored with only four colors in such a way that any two adjacent regions have different colors W W Rouse Ball 1960 The Four Color Theorem in Mathematical Recreations and Essays Macmillan New York pp 222 232 Donald MacKenzie Mechanizing Proof Computing Risk and Trust MIT Press 2004 p103 Heawood P J 1890 Map Colour Theorems Quarterly Journal of Mathematics 24 Oxford 332 338 Swart E R 1980 The Philosophical Implications of the Four Color Problem The American Mathematical Monthly 87 9 697 702 doi 10 2307 2321855 ISSN 0002 9890 JSTOR 2321855 Wilson Robin 2014 Four colors suffice how the map problem was solved Revised color ed Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press pp 216 222 ISBN 9780691158228 OCLC 847985591 Triangulation and the Hauptvermutung www maths ed ac uk Retrieved 2019 11 12 Milnor John W 1961 Two complexes which are homeomorphic but combinatorially distinct Annals of Mathematics 74 2 575 590 doi 10 2307 1970299 JSTOR 1970299 MR 0133127 Moise Edwin E 1977 Geometric Topology in Dimensions 2 and 3 New York New York Springer Verlag ISBN 978 0 387 90220 3 Hamilton Richard S 1997 Four manifolds with positive isotropic curvature Communications in Analysis and Geometry 5 1 1 92 doi 10 4310 CAG 1997 v5 n1 a1 MR 1456308 Zbl 0892 53018 Bombieri Enrico 2000 The Riemann Hypothesis official problem description PDF Clay Mathematics Institute Archived from the original PDF on 2015 12 22 Retrieved 2019 11 12 Juris Hartmanis 1989 Godel von Neumann and the P NP problem Bulletin of the European Association for Theoretical Computer Science vol 38 pp 101 107 Cook Stephen 1971 The complexity of theorem proving procedures Proceedings of the Third Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing pp 151 158 doi 10 1145 800157 805047 ISBN 9781450374644 S2CID 7573663 Lance Fortnow The status of the P versus NP problem Communications of the ACM 52 2009 no 9 pp 78 86 doi 10 1145 1562164 1562186 Richards Ian 1974 On the Incompatibility of Two Conjectures Concerning Primes Bull Amer Math Soc 80 419 438 doi 10 1090 S0002 9904 1974 13434 8 Langlands Robert 1967 Letter to Prof Weil Popper Karl 2004 Conjectures and refutations the growth of scientific knowledge London Routledge ISBN 0 415 28594 1 Works cited edit Deligne Pierre 1974 La conjecture de Weil I Publications Mathematiques de l IHES 43 43 273 307 doi 10 1007 BF02684373 ISSN 1618 1913 MR 0340258 S2CID 123139343 Dwork Bernard 1960 On the rationality of the zeta function of an algebraic variety American Journal of Mathematics 82 3 American Journal of Mathematics Vol 82 No 3 631 648 doi 10 2307 2372974 ISSN 0002 9327 JSTOR 2372974 MR 0140494 Grothendieck Alexander 1995 1965 Formule de Lefschetz et rationalite des fonctions L Seminaire Bourbaki vol 9 Paris Societe Mathematique de France pp 41 55 MR 1608788External links edit nbsp Look up conjecture in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Media related to Conjectures at Wikimedia Commons Open Problem Garden Unsolved Problems web site Portals nbsp Mathematics nbsp Science Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Conjecture amp oldid 1198163859, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.