fbpx
Wikipedia

Analytic philosophy

Analytic philosophy is a branch of philosophy using analysis, popular in the Western world and particularly the Anglosphere, which began around the turn of the 20th century in the contemporary era in Germany, the United Kingdom, United States, Canada, Australia, New Zealand, and Scandinavia, and continues today.

Analytic philosophy is often contrasted with continental philosophy, coined as a catch-all term for other methods, prominent in Europe, most notably existentialism, phenomenology, and Hegelianism.[1][2] The analytic tradition has been the dominant tradition in Western philosophy since the latter half of the 20th century.[3][4][5] The tradition has been critiqued for ahistoricism and aloofness towards alternative disciplines and outsiders.[6][7][8][9]

Analytic philosophy is characterized by clarity of prose and rigor in arguments, making use of formal logic and mathematics, and, to a lesser degree, the natural sciences.[10][11][12] It is known for a focus on language called the linguistic turn. Analytic philosophy also takes things piecemeal, in "an attempt to focus philosophical reflection on smaller problems that lead to answers to bigger questions".[13][14]

Central figures in the historical development of analytic philosophy are Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, G. E. Moore, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Other important figures in its history include the logical positivists (particularly Rudolf Carnap), W. V. O. Quine, Karl Popper, and ordinary language philosophy (such as Gilbert Ryle or J. L. Austin). After the decline of logical positivism, Saul Kripke, David Lewis, and others led a revival in metaphysics. Alvin Plantinga led a revival in Christian philosophy. Elizabeth Anscombe, Peter Geach, Anthony Kenny, and others developed an analytic approach to Thomism.

History edit

The history of analytic philosophy (taken in the narrower sense of "20th-/21st-century analytic philosophy") is usually thought to begin with the rejection of British idealism, a neo-Hegelian movement.[15]

British idealism as taught by philosophers such as F. H. Bradley (1846–1924) and T. H. Green (1836–1882), dominated English philosophy in the late 19th century. Since its beginning, a basic goal of analytic philosophy has been conceptual clarity,[16] in the name of which Moore and Russell rejected Hegelianism for being obscure—see for example Moore's "A Defence of Common Sense" and Russell's critique of the doctrine of internal relations.[17] Inspired by developments in modern formal logic, the early Russell claimed that the problems of philosophy can be solved by showing the simple constituents of complex notions.[16] An important aspect of British idealism was logical holism—the opinion that there are aspects of the world that can be known only by knowing the whole world. This is closely related to the opinion that relations between items are internal relations, that is, properties of the nature of those items. Russell, along with Wittgenstein, in response promulgated logical atomism and the doctrine of external relations—the belief that the world consists of independent facts.[18]

Russell, during his early career, along with his collaborator Alfred North Whitehead, was much influenced by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925), who developed predicate logic, which allowed a much greater range of sentences to be parsed into logical form than was possible using the ancient Aristotelian logic. Frege was also influential as a philosopher of mathematics in Germany at the beginning of the 20th century. In contrast to Edmund Husserl's 1891 book Philosophie der Arithmetik, which argued that the concept of the cardinal number derived from psychical acts of grouping objects and counting them,[19] Frege argued that mathematics and logic have their own validity, independent of the judgments or mental states of individual mathematicians and logicians (which were the basis of arithmetic according to the "psychologism" of Husserl's Philosophie). Frege further developed his philosophy of logic and mathematics in The Foundations of Arithmetic (1884) and The Basic Laws of Arithmetic (German: Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, 1893–1903), where he provided an alternative to psychologistic accounts of the concept of number.

Like Frege, Russell argued that mathematics is reducible to logical fundamentals in The Principles of Mathematics (1903). Later, his book written with Whitehead, Principia Mathematica (1910–1913), encouraged many philosophers to renew their interest in the development of symbolic logic. Additionally, Russell adopted Frege's predicate logic as his primary philosophical method, a method Russell thought could expose the underlying structure of philosophical problems. For example, the English word "is" has three distinct meanings which predicate logic can express as follows:

  • For the sentence 'the cat is asleep', the is of predication means that "x is P" (denoted as P(x)).
  • For the sentence 'there is a cat', the is of existence means that "there is an x" (∃x).
  • For the sentence 'three is half of six', the is of identity means that "x is the same as y" (x=y).

Russell sought to resolve various philosophical problems by applying such logical distinctions, most famously in his analysis of definite descriptions in "On Denoting" (1905).[20]

Ideal language edit

From about 1910 to 1930, analytic philosophers like Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein emphasized creating an ideal language for philosophical analysis, which would be free from the ambiguities of ordinary language that, in their opinion, often made philosophy invalid. During this phase, Russell and Wittgenstein sought to understand language (and hence philosophical problems) by using logic to formalize how philosophical statements are made.

Logical atomism edit

Russell became an advocate of logical atomism. Wittgenstein developed a comprehensive system of logical atomism in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (German: Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung, 1921). He thereby argued that the universe is the totality of actual states of affairs and that these states of affairs can be expressed by the language of first-order predicate logic. Thus a picture of the universe can be constructed by expressing facts in the form of atomic propositions and linking them using logical operators.

Logical positivism edit

During the late 1920s to 1940s, a group of philosophers of the Vienna Circle and the Berlin Circle developed Russell and Wittgenstein's formalism into a doctrine known as "logical positivism" (or logical empiricism). Logical positivism used formal logical methods to develop an empiricist account of knowledge.[21] Philosophers such as Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, along with other members of the Vienna Circle, claimed that the truths of logic and mathematics were tautologies, and those of science were verifiable empirical claims. These two constituted the entire universe of meaningful judgments; anything else was nonsense. The claims of ethics, aesthetics, and theology were consequently reduced to pseudo-statements, neither empirically true nor false and therefore meaningless. In reaction to what he considered excesses of logical positivism, Karl Popper insisted on the role of falsification in the philosophy of science—although his general method was also part of the analytic tradition.[22] With the coming to power of Adolf Hitler and Nazism in 1933, many members of the Vienna and Berlin Circles fled to Britain and the US, which helped to reinforce the dominance of logical positivism and analytic philosophy in anglophone countries.

Logical positivists typically considered philosophy as having a minimal function. For them, philosophy concerned the clarification of thoughts, rather than having a distinct subject matter of its own. The positivists adopted the verification principle, according to which every meaningful statement is either analytic or is capable of being verified by experience. This caused the logical positivists to reject many traditional problems of philosophy, especially those of metaphysics or ontology, as meaningless.

Ordinary language edit

After World War II, during the late 1940s and 1950s, analytic philosophy became involved with ordinary-language analysis. This resulted in two main trends. One continued Wittgenstein's later philosophy, which differed dramatically from his early work of the Tractatus. The other, known as "Oxford philosophy", involved J. L. Austin.[23] In contrast to earlier analytic philosophers (including the early Wittgenstein) who thought philosophers should avoid the deceptive trappings of natural language by constructing ideal languages, ordinary-language philosophers claimed that ordinary language already represents many subtle distinctions not recognized in the formulation of traditional philosophical theories or problems. While schools such as logical positivism emphasize logical terms, supposed to be universal and separate from contingent factors (such as culture, language, historical conditions), ordinary-language philosophy emphasizes the use of language by ordinary people. The most prominent ordinary-language philosophers during the 1950s were the aforementioned Austin and Gilbert Ryle.

Ordinary-language philosophers often sought to dissolve philosophical problems by showing them to be the result of ordinary misunderstanding language. Examples include Ryle, who tried to dispose of "Descartes' myth", and Wittgenstein.

Contemporary analytic philosophy edit

Although contemporary philosophers who self-identify as "analytic" have widely divergent interests, assumptions, and methods—and have often rejected the fundamental premises that defined analytic philosophy before 1960—analytic philosophy today is usually considered to be determined by a particular style,[10] characterized by precision and thoroughness about a specific topic, and resistance to "imprecise or cavalier discussions of broad topics".[24]

During the 1950s, logical positivism was challenged influentially by Wittgenstein in the Philosophical Investigations, Quine in "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", and Sellars in Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. After 1960, anglophone philosophy began to incorporate a wider range of interests, opinions, and methods.[24] Still, many philosophers in Britain and America still consider themselves "analytic philosophers".[25][10] They have done so largely by expanding the notion of "analytic philosophy" from the specific programs that dominated anglophone philosophy before 1960 to a much more general notion of an "analytic" style.[24]

Many philosophers and historians have attempted to define or describe analytic philosophy. Those definitions often include an emphasis on conceptual analysis: A.P. Martinich draws an analogy between analytic philosophy's interest in conceptual analysis and analytic chemistry, which aims to determine chemical compositions.[26] Steven D. Hales described analytic philosophy as one of three types of philosophical method practiced in the West: "[i]n roughly reverse order by number of proponents, they are phenomenology, ideological philosophy, and analytic philosophy".[27]

Scott Soames agrees that clarity is important: analytic philosophy, he says, has "an implicit commitment—albeit faltering and imperfect—to the ideals of clarity, rigor and argumentation" and it "aims at truth and knowledge, as opposed to moral or spiritual improvement [...] the goal in analytic philosophy is to discover what is true, not to provide a useful recipe for living one's life". Soames also states that analytic philosophy is characterized by "a more piecemeal approach. There is, I think, a widespread presumption within the tradition that it is often possible to make philosophical progress by intensively investigating a small, circumscribed range of philosophical issues while holding broader, systematic questions in abeyance".[28]

A few of the most important and active topics and subtopics of analytic philosophy are summarized by the following sections

Metaphysics edit

One striking difference with respect to early analytic philosophy was the revival of metaphysical theorizing during the second half of the 20th century. Philosophers such as David Kellogg Lewis[29] and David Armstrong[30] developed elaborate theories on a range of topics such as universals,[31][32] causation,[33] possibility and necessity,[34] and abstract objects.[35]

Among the developments that resulted in the revival of metaphysical theorizing were Quine's attack on the analytic–synthetic distinction, which was generally considered to weaken Carnap's distinction between existence questions internal to a framework and those external to it.[36] Important also for the revival of metaphysics was the further development of modal logic, including the work of Saul Kripke, who argued in Naming and Necessity and elsewhere for the existence of essences and the possibility of necessary, a posteriori truths.[37]

Metaphysics remains a fertile topic of research, having recovered from the attacks of A.J. Ayer and the logical positivists. Although many discussions are continuations of old ones from previous decades and centuries, the debate remains active. The philosophy of fiction, the problem of empty names, and the debate over existence's status as a property have all become major concerns, while perennial issues such as free will, possible worlds, and the philosophy of time have been revived.[38][39]

Science has also had an increasingly significant role in metaphysics. The theory of special relativity has had a profound effect on the philosophy of time, and quantum physics is routinely discussed in the free will debate.[39] The weight given to scientific evidence is largely due to widespread commitments among philosophers to scientific realism and naturalism.

Philosophy of language edit

Philosophy of language is a topic that has decreased in activity during the last four decades, as evidenced by the fact that few major philosophers today treat it as a primary research topic. Indeed, while the debate remains fierce, it is still strongly influenced by those authors from the first half of the century: Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, J.L. Austin, Alfred Tarski, and W.V.O. Quine.

In Saul Kripke's publication Naming and Necessity, he argued influentially that flaws in common theories of proper names are indicative of larger misunderstandings of the metaphysics of necessity and possibility. By wedding the techniques of modal logic to a causal theory of reference, Kripke was widely regarded as reviving theories of essence and identity as respectable topics of philosophical discussion.

Another influential philosopher, Pavel Tichý initiated Transparent Intensional Logic, an original theory of the logical analysis of natural languages—the theory is devoted to the problem of saying exactly what it is that we learn, know and can communicate when we come to understand what a sentence means.

Logical pluralism edit

Many valued logics have been popular since Polish logician Jan Lukasiewicz. Recent approaches have led to logical pluralism and dialetheism, advocated by the likes of JC Beall and Graham Priest.

Philosophy of mind and cognitive science edit

Motivated by the logical positivists' interest in verificationism, logical behaviorism was the most prominent theory of mind of analytic philosophy for the first half of the 20th century.[40] Behaviorists tended to opine either that statements about the mind were equivalent to statements about behavior and dispositions to behave in particular ways or that mental states were directly equivalent to behavior and dispositions to behave. Behaviorism later became much less popular, in favor of type physicalism or functionalism, theories that identified mental states with brain states. During this period, topics of the philosophy of mind were often related strongly to topics of cognitive science such as modularity or innateness. Finally, analytic philosophy has featured a certain number of philosophers who were dualists, and recently forms of property dualism have had a resurgence; the most prominent representative is David Chalmers.[41]

John Searle suggests that the obsession with the philosophy of language during the 20th century has been superseded by an emphasis on the philosophy of mind,[42] in which functionalism is currently the dominant theory. In recent years, a central focus of research in the philosophy of mind has been consciousness. While there is a general consensus for the global neuronal workspace model of consciousness,[43] there are many opinions as to the specifics. The best known theories are Daniel Dennett's heterophenomenology, Fred Dretske and Michael Tye's representationalism, and the higher-order theories of either David M. Rosenthal—who advocates a higher-order thought (HOT) model—or David Armstrong and William Lycan—who advocate a higher-order perception (HOP) model. An alternative higher-order theory, the higher-order global states (HOGS) model, is offered by Robert van Gulick.[44]

Epistemology edit

Owing largely to Gettier's 1963 paper "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?",[45] epistemology resurged as a topic of analytic philosophy during the last 50 years. A large portion of current epistemological research is intended to resolve the problems that Gettier's examples presented to the traditional justified true belief model of knowledge, including developing theories of justification to deal with Gettier's examples, or giving alternatives to the justified true belief model. Other and related topics of contemporary research include debates between internalism and externalism,[46] basic knowledge, the nature of evidence, the value of knowledge, epistemic luck, virtue epistemology, the role of intuitions in justification, and treating knowledge as a primitive concept.

Ethics edit

Due to the commitments to empiricism and symbolic logic in the early analytic period, early analytic philosophers often thought that inquiry in the ethical domain could not be made rigorous enough to merit any attention.[47] It was only with the emergence of ordinary language philosophers that ethics started to become an acceptable area of inquiry for analytic philosophers.[47] Philosophers working with the analytic tradition have gradually come to distinguish three major types of moral philosophy.

  • Meta-ethics which investigates moral terms and concepts;[48]
  • Normative ethics which examines and produces normative ethical judgments;
  • Applied ethics, which investigates how existing normative principles should be applied to difficult or borderline cases, often cases created by new technology or new scientific knowledge.

Meta-ethics edit

Twentieth-century meta-ethics has two origins. The first is G.E. Moore's investigation into the nature of ethical terms (e.g., good) in his Principia Ethica (1903), which identified the naturalistic fallacy. Along with Hume's famous is/ought distinction, the naturalistic fallacy was a major topic of investigation for analytical philosophers.

The second is in logical positivism and its attitude that unverifiable statements are meaningless. Although that attitude was adopted originally to promote scientific investigation by rejecting grand metaphysical systems, it had the side effect of making (ethical and aesthetic) value judgments (as well as religious statements and beliefs) meaningless. But because value judgments are of significant importance in human life, it became incumbent on logical positivism to develop an explanation of the nature and meaning of value judgments. As a result, analytic philosophers avoided normative ethics and instead began meta-ethical investigations into the nature of moral terms, statements, and judgments.

The logical positivists opined that statements about value—including all ethical and aesthetic judgments—are non-cognitive; that is, they cannot be objectively verified or falsified. Instead, the logical positivists adopted an emotivist theory, which was that value judgments expressed the attitude of the speaker. For example, in this view, saying, "Killing is wrong", is equivalent to saying, "Boo to murder", or saying the word "murder" with a particular tone of disapproval.

While analytic philosophers generally accepted non-cognitivism, emotivism had many deficiencies. It evolved into more sophisticated non-cognitivist theories such as the expressivism of Charles Stevenson, and the universal prescriptivism of R.M. Hare, which was based on J.L. Austin's philosophy of speech acts.

These theories were not without their critics. Philippa Foot contributed several essays attacking all these theories. J.O. Urmson's article "On Grading" called the is/ought distinction into question.

As non-cognitivism, the is/ought distinction, and the naturalistic fallacy began to be called into question, analytic philosophers showed a renewed interest in the traditional questions of moral philosophy. Perhaps the most influential being Elizabeth Anscombe, whose monograph Intention was called by Donald Davidson "the most important treatment of action since Aristotle".[49] A favorite student and friend of Ludwig Wittgenstein, her 1958 article "Modern Moral Philosophy" introduced the term "consequentialism" into the philosophical lexicon, declared the "is-ought" impasse to be unproductive, and resulted in a revival of virtue ethics.

Normative ethics edit

The first half of the 20th century was marked by skepticism toward and neglect of normative ethics. Related subjects, such as social and political philosophy, aesthetics, and philosophy of history, became only marginal topics of English-language philosophy during this period.

During this time, utilitarianism was the only non-skeptical type of ethics to remain popular. However, as the influence of logical positivism began to decrease mid-century, analytic philosophers had renewed interest in ethics. G.E.M. Anscombe's 1958 "Modern Moral Philosophy" sparked a revival of Aristotle's virtue ethical approach and John Rawls's 1971 A Theory of Justice restored interest in Kantian ethical philosophy. Today, contemporary normative ethics is dominated by three schools: consequentialism, virtue ethics, and deontology.

Applied ethics edit

A significant feature of analytic philosophy since approximately 1970 has been the emergence of applied ethics—an interest in the application of moral principles to specific practical issues. The philosophers following this orientation view ethics as involving humanistic values, which involve practical implications and applications in the way people interact and lead their lives socially.[50]

Topics of special interest for applied ethics include environmental issues, animal rights, and the many challenges created by advancing medical science.[51][52][53] In education, applied ethics addressed themes such as punishment in schools, equality of educational opportunity, and education for democracy.[54]

Philosophy of religion edit

In Analytic Philosophy of Religion, James Franklin Harris noted that

analytic philosophy has been a very heterogeneous 'movement'.... some forms of analytic philosophy have proven very sympathetic to the philosophy of religion and have provided a philosophical mechanism for responding to other more radical and hostile forms of analytic philosophy.[55]: 3 

As with the study of ethics, early analytic philosophy tended to avoid the study of philosophy of religion, largely dismissing (as per the logical positivists) the subject as part of metaphysics and therefore meaningless.[56] The demise of logical positivism renewed interest in philosophy of religion, prompting philosophers like William Alston, John Mackie, Alvin Plantinga, Robert Merrihew Adams, Richard Swinburne, and Antony Flew not only to introduce new problems, but to re-study classical topics such as the nature of miracles, theistic arguments, the problem of evil, (see existence of God) the rationality of belief in God, concepts of the nature of God, and many more.[57]

Plantinga, Mackie and Flew debated the logical validity of the free will defense as a way to solve the problem of evil.[58] Alston, grappling with the consequences of analytic philosophy of language, worked on the nature of religious language. Adams worked on the relationship of faith and morality.[59] Analytic epistemology and metaphysics has formed the basis for some philosophically sophisticated theistic arguments, like those of the reformed epistemologists like Plantinga.

Analytic philosophy of religion has also been preoccupied with Wittgenstein, as well as his interpretation of Søren Kierkegaard's philosophy of religion.[60] Using first-hand remarks (which was later published in Philosophical Investigations, Culture and Value, and other works), philosophers such as Peter Winch and Norman Malcolm developed what has come to be known as contemplative philosophy, a Wittgensteinian school of thought rooted in the "Swansea tradition", and which includes Wittgensteinians such as Rush Rhees, Peter Winch, and D.Z. Phillips, among others. The name "contemplative philosophy" was first coined by D.Z. Phillips in Philosophy's Cool Place, which rests on an interpretation of a passage from Wittgenstein's Culture and Value.[61] This interpretation was first labeled, "Wittgensteinian Fideism", by Kai Nielsen but those who consider themselves Wittgensteinians in the Swansea tradition have relentlessly and repeatedly rejected this construal as a caricature of Wittgenstein's considered position; this is especially true of D.Z. Phillips.[62] Responding to this interpretation, Kai Nielsen and D.Z. Phillips became two of the most prominent philosophers on Wittgenstein's philosophy of religion.[63]

Philosophy of science edit

Reacting against both the verificationism of the logical positivists as well as the critiques of the philosopher of science Karl Popper, who had suggested the falsifiability criterion on which to judge the demarcation between science and non-science, discussions of philosophy of science during the last 40 years were dominated by social constructivist and cognitive relativist theories of science. Thomas Samuel Kuhn with his formulation of paradigm shifts and Paul Feyerabend with his epistemological anarchism are significant for these discussions.[64] The philosophy of biology has also undergone considerable growth, particularly due to the considerable debate in recent years over the nature of evolution, particularly natural selection.[65] Daniel Dennett and his 1995 book Darwin's Dangerous Idea, which defends Neo-Darwinism, stand at the foreground of this debate.[66]

Political philosophy edit

Liberalism edit

Current analytic political philosophy owes much to John Rawls, who in a series of papers from the 1950s onward (most notably "Two Concepts of Rules" and "Justice as Fairness") and his 1971 book A Theory of Justice, produced a sophisticated defense of a generally liberal egalitarian account of distributive justice. This was followed soon by Rawls's colleague Robert Nozick's book Anarchy, State, and Utopia, a defence of free-market libertarianism. Isaiah Berlin also had a lasting influence on both analytic political philosophy and liberalism with his lecture "Two Concepts of Liberty"[citation needed].

During recent decades there have also been several critiques of liberalism, including the feminist critiques of Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin, the communitarian critiques of Michael Sandel and Alasdair MacIntyre (although neither of them endorses the term), and the multiculturalist critiques of Amy Gutmann and Charles Taylor. Although not an analytic philosopher, Jürgen Habermas is another prominent—if controversial—author of contemporary analytic political philosophy, whose social theory is a blend of social science, Marxism, neo-Kantianism, and American pragmatism[citation needed].

Consequentialist libertarianism also derives from the analytic tradition[citation needed].

Analytical Marxism edit

Another development of political philosophy was the emergence of the school of analytical Marxism. Members of this school seek to apply techniques of analytic philosophy and modern social science such as rational choice theory to clarify the theories of Karl Marx and his successors. The best-known member of this school is G. A. Cohen, whose 1978 work, Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defence, is generally considered to represent the genesis of this school. In that book, Cohen used logical and linguistic analysis to clarify and defend Marx's materialist conception of history. Other prominent analytical Marxists include the economist John Roemer, the social scientist Jon Elster, and the sociologist Erik Olin Wright. The work of these later philosophers have furthered Cohen's work by bringing to bear modern social science methods, such as rational choice theory, to supplement Cohen's use of analytic philosophical techniques in the interpretation of Marxian theory.

Cohen himself would later engage directly with Rawlsian political philosophy to advance a socialist theory of justice that contrasts with both traditional Marxism and the theories advanced by Rawls and Nozick. In particular, he indicates Marx's principle of from each according to his ability, to each according to his need.

Communitarianism edit

Communitarians such as Alasdair MacIntyre, Charles Taylor, Michael Walzer, and Michael Sandel advance a critique of liberalism that uses analytic techniques to isolate the main assumptions of liberal individualists, such as Rawls, and then challenges these assumptions. In particular, communitarians challenge the liberal assumption that the individual can be considered as fully autonomous from the community in which he lives and is brought up. Instead, they argue for a conception of the individual that emphasizes the role that the community plays in forming his or her values, thought processes and opinions. Communitarianism has a complex relationship with the analytic tradition, as its major exponents often engage at length with figures generally considered continental, notably G. W. F. Hegel and Friedrich Nietzsche.

Aesthetics edit

As a result of what seemed like rejections of the traditional aesthetic notions of beauty and sublimity from post-modern thinkers, analytic philosophers were slow to consider art and aesthetic judgment. Susanne Langer[67] and Nelson Goodman[68] addressed these problems in an analytic style during the 1950s and 1960s. Since Goodman, aesthetics as a discipline for analytic philosophers has flourished.[69] Rigorous efforts to pursue analyses of traditional aesthetic concepts were performed by Guy Sircello in the 1970s and 1980s, resulting in new analytic theories of love,[70] sublimity,[71] and beauty.[72]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ A.C. Grayling (ed.), Philosophy 2: Further through the Subject (Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 2: "Analytic philosophy is mainly associated with the contemporary English-speaking world, but it is by no means the only important philosophical tradition. In this volume two other immensely rich and important such traditions are introduced: Indian philosophy, and philosophical thought in Europe from the time of Hegel." L.J. Cohen, The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 5: "So, despite a few overlaps, analytical philosophy is not difficult to distinguish broadly [...] from other modern movements, like phenomenology, say, or existentialism, or from the large amount of philosophizing that has also gone on in the present century within frameworks deriving from other influential thinkers like Aquinas, Hegel, or Marx." H.-J. Glock, What Is Analytic Philosophy? (Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 86: "Most non-analytic philosophers of the twentieth century do not belong to continental philosophy."
  2. ^ Critchley, Simon (2001). Continental philosophy a very short introduction. Oxford University Press. OCLC 1200924441. [...]the distinction rests upon a confusion of geographical and methodological terms, as if one were to classify cars into front-wheel drive and Japanese. [...] the distinction between analytic and Continental philosophy rests upon a confused comparison of methodological and geographical categories.
  3. ^ Vienne, J.M. (1997). Philosophie analytique et histoire de la philosophie: actes du colloque (Université de Nantes, 1991). Problèmes et controverses (in French). J. Vrin. p. 140. ISBN 978-2-7116-1312-0. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  4. ^ Luft, S. (2019). Philosophie lehren: Ein Buch zur philosophischen Hochschuldidaktik (in German). Felix Meiner Verlag. p. 258. ISBN 978-3-7873-3766-8. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  5. ^ Glock, H.J. (2008). What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge University Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-521-87267-6. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  6. ^ Glock, H.J. (2008). What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge University Press. p. 231. ISBN 978-0-521-87267-6. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  7. ^ Akehurst, Thomas L. (1 March 2009). "Writing history for the ahistorical: Analytic philosophy and its past". History of European Ideas. 35 (1): 116–121. doi:10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2008.09.002. ISSN 0191-6599. S2CID 143566283.
  8. ^ Beaney, Michael (20 June 2013). Beaney, Michael (ed.). "The Historiography of Analytic Philosophy". The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199238842.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-923884-2. Retrieved 18 February 2022.
  9. ^ Koopman, Colin. "Bernard Williams on Philosophy's Need for History" (PDF). pages.uoregon.edu. Retrieved 1 March 2022.
  10. ^ a b c Brian Leiter (2006) webpage . Quote on the definition: "'Analytic' philosophy today names a style of doing philosophy, not a philosophical program or a set of substantive views. Analytic philosophers, crudely speaking, aim for argumentative clarity and precision; draw freely on the tools of logic; and often identify, professionally and intellectually, more closely with the sciences and mathematics, than with the humanities."
  11. ^ Glock, H.J. (2004). "Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher?". Metaphilosophy. 35 (4): 419–444. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.2004.00329.x.
  12. ^ Colin McGinn, The Making of a Philosopher: My Journey through Twentieth-Century Philosophy (HarperCollins, 2002), p. xi.: "analytical philosophy [is] too narrow a label, since [it] is not generally a matter of taking a word or concept and analyzing it (whatever exactly that might be). [...] This tradition emphasizes clarity, rigor, argument, theory, truth. It is not a tradition that aims primarily for inspiration or consolation or ideology. Nor is it particularly concerned with 'philosophy of life', though parts of it are. This kind of philosophy is more like science than religion, more like mathematics than poetry—though it is neither science nor mathematics."
  13. ^ See, e.g., Avrum Stroll, Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy (Columbia University Press, 2000), p. 5: "[I]t is difficult to give a precise definition of 'analytic philosophy' since it is not so much a specific doctrine as a loose concatenation of approaches to problems." Also, see Stroll (2000), p. 7: "I think Sluga is right in saying 'it may be hopeless to try to determine the essence of analytic philosophy.' Nearly every proposed definition has been challenged by some scholar. [...] [W]e are dealing with a family resemblance concept."
  14. ^ See Hans-Johann Glock, What Is Analytic Philosophy? (Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 205: "The answer to the title question, then, is that analytic philosophy is a tradition held together both by ties of mutual influence and by family resemblances."
  15. ^ Michael Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2013, p. 383.
  16. ^ a b Mautner, Thomas (editor) (2005) The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, entry for "Analytic philosophy", pp. 22–23
  17. ^ "Analytic philosophy opposed right from its beginning English neo-Hegelianism of Bradley's sort and similar ones. It did not only criticize the latter's denial of the existence of an external world (anyway an unjust criticism), but also the bombastic, obscure style of Hegel's writings." Jonkers, Peter (2003). "Perspectives on Twentieth Century Philosophy: A Reply to Tom Rockmore". Ars Disputandi. 3. doi:10.1080/15665399.2003.10819802. ISSN 1566-5399. S2CID 70060684.
  18. ^ Baillie, James, "Introduction to Bertrand Russell" in Contemporary Analytic Philosophy, Second Edition (Prentice Hall, 1997), p. 25.
  19. ^ Willard, Dallas (1980). "Husserl on a Logic that Failed". Philosophical Review. 89 (1): 52–53. doi:10.2307/2184863. JSTOR 2184863.
  20. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1905). "On Denoting". Mind. 14: 473–493. from the original on 31 March 2006.
  21. ^ Carnap, R. (1928). The Logical Structure of the World. Felix Meiner Verlag. ISBN 978-0-8126-9523-6. LCCN 66013604.
  22. ^ Popper, Karl R. (2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7.
  23. ^ Longworth, Guy (2017), "John Langshaw Austin", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 21 July 2020
  24. ^ a b c "Analytic Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Iep.utm.edu. from the original on 3 July 2009. Retrieved 13 April 2018.
  25. ^ "Without exception, the best philosophy departments in the United States are dominated by analytic philosophy, and among the leading philosophers in the United States, all but a tiny handful would be classified as analytic philosophers. Practitioners of types of philosophizing that are not in the analytic tradition—such as phenomenology, classical pragmatism, existentialism, or Marxism—feel it necessary to define their position in relation to analytic philosophy." John Searle (2003), Contemporary Philosophy in the United States in N. Bunnin and E. P. Tsui-James (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, 2nd ed., (Blackwell, 2003), p. 1.
  26. ^ A.P. Martinich, ed. (2001). A companion to analytic philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 1–5. doi:10.1002/9780470998656.ch1. ISBN 978-0-631-21415-1.
  27. ^ Hales, Steven D. (2002). Analytic philosophy : classic readings. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thomson Learning. pp. 1–10. ISBN 978-0-534-51277-4.
  28. ^ Soames, Scott (2003). The dawn of analysis (2nd print., 1st papers. print ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press. pp. xiii–xvii. ISBN 978-0-691-11573-3.
  29. ^ Weatherson, Brian (2016), "David Lewis", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 21 July 2020
  30. ^ Jackson, Frank (2016), "Armstrong, David Malet (1926–2014)", Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1 ed.), London: Routledge, doi:10.4324/9780415249126-v035-1, ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6, retrieved 21 July 2020
  31. ^ Armstrong, David Malet (1995). Universals and scientific realism. Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 0-521-28033-8. OCLC 174240749.
  32. ^ Lewis, David (March 1986). "Against structural universals". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 64 (1): 25–46. doi:10.1080/00048408612342211. ISSN 0004-8402.
  33. ^ Hitchcock, Christopher (6 March 2015), "Lewis on Causation", A Companion to David Lewis, Oxford, UK: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, pp. 295–311, doi:10.1002/9781118398593.ch19, ISBN 978-1-118-39859-3
  34. ^ Lewis, David K. (2008). On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell Publ. ISBN 978-0-631-22426-6. OCLC 552327787.
  35. ^ Rosen, Gideon (2020), "Abstract Objects", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 21 July 2020
  36. ^ S. Yablo and A. Gallois, Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 72, (1998), pp. 229–261, 263–283 first part 12 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine
  37. ^ Zimmerman, Dean W., "Prologue" in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1 (Oxford University Press, 2004), p. xix.
  38. ^ Everett, Anthony and Thomas Hofweber (eds.) (2000), Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-Existence.
  39. ^ a b Van Inwagen, Peter, and Dean Zimmerman (eds.) (1998), Metaphysics: The Big Questions.
  40. ^ Graham, George, "Behaviorism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). [1]
  41. ^ Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Dualism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  42. ^ Postrel and Feser, February 2000, Reality Principles: An Interview with John R. Searle at . February 2000. Archived from the original on 29 September 2008. Retrieved 23 September 2008.
  43. ^ Dennett, D. (2001). "Are we explaining consciousness yet?". Cognition. 79 (1–2): 221–237. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00130-X. PMID 11164029. S2CID 2235514.
  44. ^ For summaries and some criticism of the different higher-order theories, see Van Gulick, Robert (2006) "Mirror Mirror – Is That All?" In Kriegel & Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. The final draft is also available here (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2 October 2008. Retrieved 23 September 2008.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link). For Van Gulick's own view, see Van Gulick, Robert. "Higher-Order Global States HOGS: An Alternative Higher-Order Model of Consciousness." In Gennaro, R.J., (ed.) Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
  45. ^ Gettier, Edmund (15 July 2020), "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?" (PDF), Arguing About Knowledge, Routledge, pp. 14–15, doi:10.4324/9781003061038-5, ISBN 978-1-003-06103-8, S2CID 243290967
  46. ^ Bonjour, Laurence, "Recent Work on the Internalism–Externalism Controversy" in Dancy, Sosa, and Steup (eds.), A Companion to Epistemology, Second Edition (Wiley-Blackwell, 2010), p. 33.
  47. ^ a b Schwartz, Stephen P. (2012). A Brief History of Analytic Philosophy: From Russell to Rawls. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-27172-8.
  48. ^ Kuusela, Oskari (2011). Key Terms in Ethics. London: Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 61. ISBN 978-1-4411-6610-4.
  49. ^ From the cover of the 2000 Harvard University Press edition of Intention.
  50. ^ Ikuenobe, Polycarp (2006). Philosophical Perspectives on Communalism and Morality in African Traditions. Oxford: Lexington Books. p. 104. ISBN 978-0-7391-1131-4.
  51. ^ Brennan, Andrew and Yeuk-Sze Lo (2002). "Environmental Ethics" §2 1 August 2013 at the Wayback Machine, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  52. ^ Gruen, Lori (2003). "The Moral Status of Animals," in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  53. ^ See Hursthouse, Rosalind (2003). "Virtue Ethics" §3, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and Donchin, Anne (2004). "Feminist Bioethics" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  54. ^ Heyting, Frieda; Lenzen, Dieter; White, John (2002). Methods in Philosophy of Education. New York: Routledge. pp. 18. ISBN 978-0-415-24260-8.
  55. ^ Harris, James Franklin (2002). Analytic philosophy of religion. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ISBN 978-1-4020-0530-5. (432 pages) (volume 3 of Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, ISSN 1568-1556)
  56. ^ (a notable exception is the series of Michael B. Forest's 1934–36 Mind articles involving the Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern science).
  57. ^ Peterson, Michael et al. (2003). Reason and Religious Belief
  58. ^ Mackie, John L. (1982). The Miracle of Theism: Arguments For and Against the Existence of God
  59. ^ Adams, Robert M. (1987). The Virtue of Faith And Other Essays in Philosophical Theology
  60. ^ Creegan, Charles. (1989). Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard: Religion, Individuality and Philosophical Method
  61. ^ Phillips, D.Z. (1999). Philosophy's Cool Place. Cornell University Press. The quote is from Wittgenstein's Culture and Value (2e): "My ideal is a certain coolness. A temple providing a setting for the passions without meddling with them.
  62. ^ Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Fideism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  63. ^ Nielsen, Kai and D.Z. Phillips. (2005). Wittgensteinian Fideism?
  64. ^ Glock 2008, p. 47.
  65. ^ Hull, David L. and Ruse, Michael, "Preface" in The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology (Cambridge University Press, 2007), pp. xix, xx.
  66. ^ Lennox, James G., "Darwinism and Neo-Darwinism" in Sakar and Plutynski (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology (Blackwell Publishing, 2008), p. 89.
  67. ^ Susanne Langer, Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art (1953)
  68. ^ Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1968. 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1976. Based on his 1960–61 John Locke lectures.
  69. ^ Kivy, Peter, "Introduction: Aesthetics Today" in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics (Blackwell Publishing, 2004), p. 4.
  70. ^ Guy Sircello, Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
  71. ^ Guy Sircello "How Is a Theory of the Sublime Possible?" The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn, 1993), pp. 541–550
  72. ^ Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.

References edit

Further reading edit

  • The London Philosophy Study Guide 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject: Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein
  • Dummett, Michael. The Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.
  • Hirschberger, Johannes. A Short History of Western Philosophy, ed. Clare Hay. . ISBN 978-0-7188-3092-2
  • Hylton, Peter. Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.
  • Soames, Scott. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume 1, The Dawn of Analysis. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003.
  • Passmore, John. A Hundred Years of Philosophy, revised ed. New York: Basic Books, 1966.
  • Weitz, Morris, ed. Twentieth Century Philosophy: The Analytic Tradition. New York: Free Press, 1966.

External links edit

analytic, philosophy, branch, philosophy, using, analysis, popular, western, world, particularly, anglosphere, which, began, around, turn, 20th, century, contemporary, germany, united, kingdom, united, states, canada, australia, zealand, scandinavia, continues. Analytic philosophy is a branch of philosophy using analysis popular in the Western world and particularly the Anglosphere which began around the turn of the 20th century in the contemporary era in Germany the United Kingdom United States Canada Australia New Zealand and Scandinavia and continues today Analytic philosophy is often contrasted with continental philosophy coined as a catch all term for other methods prominent in Europe most notably existentialism phenomenology and Hegelianism 1 2 The analytic tradition has been the dominant tradition in Western philosophy since the latter half of the 20th century 3 4 5 The tradition has been critiqued for ahistoricism and aloofness towards alternative disciplines and outsiders 6 7 8 9 Analytic philosophy is characterized by clarity of prose and rigor in arguments making use of formal logic and mathematics and to a lesser degree the natural sciences 10 11 12 It is known for a focus on language called the linguistic turn Analytic philosophy also takes things piecemeal in an attempt to focus philosophical reflection on smaller problems that lead to answers to bigger questions 13 14 Central figures in the historical development of analytic philosophy are Gottlob Frege Bertrand Russell G E Moore and Ludwig Wittgenstein Other important figures in its history include the logical positivists particularly Rudolf Carnap W V O Quine Karl Popper and ordinary language philosophy such as Gilbert Ryle or J L Austin After the decline of logical positivism Saul Kripke David Lewis and others led a revival in metaphysics Alvin Plantinga led a revival in Christian philosophy Elizabeth Anscombe Peter Geach Anthony Kenny and others developed an analytic approach to Thomism Contents 1 History 1 1 Ideal language 1 2 Logical atomism 1 3 Logical positivism 1 4 Ordinary language 2 Contemporary analytic philosophy 2 1 Metaphysics 2 1 1 Philosophy of language 2 1 2 Logical pluralism 2 1 3 Philosophy of mind and cognitive science 2 2 Epistemology 2 3 Ethics 2 3 1 Meta ethics 2 3 2 Normative ethics 2 3 3 Applied ethics 2 4 Philosophy of religion 2 5 Philosophy of science 2 6 Political philosophy 2 6 1 Liberalism 2 6 2 Analytical Marxism 2 6 3 Communitarianism 2 7 Aesthetics 3 See also 4 Notes 5 References 6 Further reading 7 External linksHistory editThe history of analytic philosophy taken in the narrower sense of 20th 21st century analytic philosophy is usually thought to begin with the rejection of British idealism a neo Hegelian movement 15 British idealism as taught by philosophers such as F H Bradley 1846 1924 and T H Green 1836 1882 dominated English philosophy in the late 19th century Since its beginning a basic goal of analytic philosophy has been conceptual clarity 16 in the name of which Moore and Russell rejected Hegelianism for being obscure see for example Moore s A Defence of Common Sense and Russell s critique of the doctrine of internal relations 17 Inspired by developments in modern formal logic the early Russell claimed that the problems of philosophy can be solved by showing the simple constituents of complex notions 16 An important aspect of British idealism was logical holism the opinion that there are aspects of the world that can be known only by knowing the whole world This is closely related to the opinion that relations between items are internal relations that is properties of the nature of those items Russell along with Wittgenstein in response promulgated logical atomism and the doctrine of external relations the belief that the world consists of independent facts 18 Russell during his early career along with his collaborator Alfred North Whitehead was much influenced by Gottlob Frege 1848 1925 who developed predicate logic which allowed a much greater range of sentences to be parsed into logical form than was possible using the ancient Aristotelian logic Frege was also influential as a philosopher of mathematics in Germany at the beginning of the 20th century In contrast to Edmund Husserl s 1891 book Philosophie der Arithmetik which argued that the concept of the cardinal number derived from psychical acts of grouping objects and counting them 19 Frege argued that mathematics and logic have their own validity independent of the judgments or mental states of individual mathematicians and logicians which were the basis of arithmetic according to the psychologism of Husserl s Philosophie Frege further developed his philosophy of logic and mathematics in The Foundations of Arithmetic 1884 and The Basic Laws of Arithmetic German Grundgesetze der Arithmetik 1893 1903 where he provided an alternative to psychologistic accounts of the concept of number Like Frege Russell argued that mathematics is reducible to logical fundamentals in The Principles of Mathematics 1903 Later his book written with Whitehead Principia Mathematica 1910 1913 encouraged many philosophers to renew their interest in the development of symbolic logic Additionally Russell adopted Frege s predicate logic as his primary philosophical method a method Russell thought could expose the underlying structure of philosophical problems For example the English word is has three distinct meanings which predicate logic can express as follows For the sentence the cat is asleep the is of predication means that x is P denoted as P x For the sentence there is a cat the is of existence means that there is an x x For the sentence three is half of six the is of identity means that x is the same as y x y Russell sought to resolve various philosophical problems by applying such logical distinctions most famously in his analysis of definite descriptions in On Denoting 1905 20 Ideal language edit Main article Ideal language philosophy From about 1910 to 1930 analytic philosophers like Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein emphasized creating an ideal language for philosophical analysis which would be free from the ambiguities of ordinary language that in their opinion often made philosophy invalid During this phase Russell and Wittgenstein sought to understand language and hence philosophical problems by using logic to formalize how philosophical statements are made Logical atomism edit Russell became an advocate of logical atomism Wittgenstein developed a comprehensive system of logical atomism in his Tractatus Logico Philosophicus German Logisch Philosophische Abhandlung 1921 He thereby argued that the universe is the totality of actual states of affairs and that these states of affairs can be expressed by the language of first order predicate logic Thus a picture of the universe can be constructed by expressing facts in the form of atomic propositions and linking them using logical operators Logical positivism edit Main article Logical positivism During the late 1920s to 1940s a group of philosophers of the Vienna Circle and the Berlin Circle developed Russell and Wittgenstein s formalism into a doctrine known as logical positivism or logical empiricism Logical positivism used formal logical methods to develop an empiricist account of knowledge 21 Philosophers such as Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach along with other members of the Vienna Circle claimed that the truths of logic and mathematics were tautologies and those of science were verifiable empirical claims These two constituted the entire universe of meaningful judgments anything else was nonsense The claims of ethics aesthetics and theology were consequently reduced to pseudo statements neither empirically true nor false and therefore meaningless In reaction to what he considered excesses of logical positivism Karl Popper insisted on the role of falsification in the philosophy of science although his general method was also part of the analytic tradition 22 With the coming to power of Adolf Hitler and Nazism in 1933 many members of the Vienna and Berlin Circles fled to Britain and the US which helped to reinforce the dominance of logical positivism and analytic philosophy in anglophone countries Logical positivists typically considered philosophy as having a minimal function For them philosophy concerned the clarification of thoughts rather than having a distinct subject matter of its own The positivists adopted the verification principle according to which every meaningful statement is either analytic or is capable of being verified by experience This caused the logical positivists to reject many traditional problems of philosophy especially those of metaphysics or ontology as meaningless Ordinary language edit Main article Ordinary language philosophy After World War II during the late 1940s and 1950s analytic philosophy became involved with ordinary language analysis This resulted in two main trends One continued Wittgenstein s later philosophy which differed dramatically from his early work of the Tractatus The other known as Oxford philosophy involved J L Austin 23 In contrast to earlier analytic philosophers including the early Wittgenstein who thought philosophers should avoid the deceptive trappings of natural language by constructing ideal languages ordinary language philosophers claimed that ordinary language already represents many subtle distinctions not recognized in the formulation of traditional philosophical theories or problems While schools such as logical positivism emphasize logical terms supposed to be universal and separate from contingent factors such as culture language historical conditions ordinary language philosophy emphasizes the use of language by ordinary people The most prominent ordinary language philosophers during the 1950s were the aforementioned Austin and Gilbert Ryle Ordinary language philosophers often sought to dissolve philosophical problems by showing them to be the result of ordinary misunderstanding language Examples include Ryle who tried to dispose of Descartes myth and Wittgenstein Contemporary analytic philosophy editAlthough contemporary philosophers who self identify as analytic have widely divergent interests assumptions and methods and have often rejected the fundamental premises that defined analytic philosophy before 1960 analytic philosophy today is usually considered to be determined by a particular style 10 characterized by precision and thoroughness about a specific topic and resistance to imprecise or cavalier discussions of broad topics 24 During the 1950s logical positivism was challenged influentially by Wittgenstein in the Philosophical Investigations Quine in Two Dogmas of Empiricism and Sellars in Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind After 1960 anglophone philosophy began to incorporate a wider range of interests opinions and methods 24 Still many philosophers in Britain and America still consider themselves analytic philosophers 25 10 They have done so largely by expanding the notion of analytic philosophy from the specific programs that dominated anglophone philosophy before 1960 to a much more general notion of an analytic style 24 Many philosophers and historians have attempted to define or describe analytic philosophy Those definitions often include an emphasis on conceptual analysis A P Martinich draws an analogy between analytic philosophy s interest in conceptual analysis and analytic chemistry which aims to determine chemical compositions 26 Steven D Hales described analytic philosophy as one of three types of philosophical method practiced in the West i n roughly reverse order by number of proponents they are phenomenology ideological philosophy and analytic philosophy 27 Scott Soames agrees that clarity is important analytic philosophy he says has an implicit commitment albeit faltering and imperfect to the ideals of clarity rigor and argumentation and it aims at truth and knowledge as opposed to moral or spiritual improvement the goal in analytic philosophy is to discover what is true not to provide a useful recipe for living one s life Soames also states that analytic philosophy is characterized by a more piecemeal approach There is I think a widespread presumption within the tradition that it is often possible to make philosophical progress by intensively investigating a small circumscribed range of philosophical issues while holding broader systematic questions in abeyance 28 A few of the most important and active topics and subtopics of analytic philosophy are summarized by the following sections Metaphysics edit Main article Metaphysics One striking difference with respect to early analytic philosophy was the revival of metaphysical theorizing during the second half of the 20th century Philosophers such as David Kellogg Lewis 29 and David Armstrong 30 developed elaborate theories on a range of topics such as universals 31 32 causation 33 possibility and necessity 34 and abstract objects 35 Among the developments that resulted in the revival of metaphysical theorizing were Quine s attack on the analytic synthetic distinction which was generally considered to weaken Carnap s distinction between existence questions internal to a framework and those external to it 36 Important also for the revival of metaphysics was the further development of modal logic including the work of Saul Kripke who argued in Naming and Necessity and elsewhere for the existence of essences and the possibility of necessary a posteriori truths 37 Metaphysics remains a fertile topic of research having recovered from the attacks of A J Ayer and the logical positivists Although many discussions are continuations of old ones from previous decades and centuries the debate remains active The philosophy of fiction the problem of empty names and the debate over existence s status as a property have all become major concerns while perennial issues such as free will possible worlds and the philosophy of time have been revived 38 39 Science has also had an increasingly significant role in metaphysics The theory of special relativity has had a profound effect on the philosophy of time and quantum physics is routinely discussed in the free will debate 39 The weight given to scientific evidence is largely due to widespread commitments among philosophers to scientific realism and naturalism Philosophy of language edit Main article Philosophy of language Philosophy of language is a topic that has decreased in activity during the last four decades as evidenced by the fact that few major philosophers today treat it as a primary research topic Indeed while the debate remains fierce it is still strongly influenced by those authors from the first half of the century Gottlob Frege Bertrand Russell Ludwig Wittgenstein J L Austin Alfred Tarski and W V O Quine In Saul Kripke s publication Naming and Necessity he argued influentially that flaws in common theories of proper names are indicative of larger misunderstandings of the metaphysics of necessity and possibility By wedding the techniques of modal logic to a causal theory of reference Kripke was widely regarded as reviving theories of essence and identity as respectable topics of philosophical discussion Another influential philosopher Pavel Tichy initiated Transparent Intensional Logic an original theory of the logical analysis of natural languages the theory is devoted to the problem of saying exactly what it is that we learn know and can communicate when we come to understand what a sentence means Logical pluralism edit Many valued logics have been popular since Polish logician Jan Lukasiewicz Recent approaches have led to logical pluralism and dialetheism advocated by the likes of JC Beall and Graham Priest Philosophy of mind and cognitive science edit Motivated by the logical positivists interest in verificationism logical behaviorism was the most prominent theory of mind of analytic philosophy for the first half of the 20th century 40 Behaviorists tended to opine either that statements about the mind were equivalent to statements about behavior and dispositions to behave in particular ways or that mental states were directly equivalent to behavior and dispositions to behave Behaviorism later became much less popular in favor of type physicalism or functionalism theories that identified mental states with brain states During this period topics of the philosophy of mind were often related strongly to topics of cognitive science such as modularity or innateness Finally analytic philosophy has featured a certain number of philosophers who were dualists and recently forms of property dualism have had a resurgence the most prominent representative is David Chalmers 41 John Searle suggests that the obsession with the philosophy of language during the 20th century has been superseded by an emphasis on the philosophy of mind 42 in which functionalism is currently the dominant theory In recent years a central focus of research in the philosophy of mind has been consciousness While there is a general consensus for the global neuronal workspace model of consciousness 43 there are many opinions as to the specifics The best known theories are Daniel Dennett s heterophenomenology Fred Dretske and Michael Tye s representationalism and the higher order theories of either David M Rosenthal who advocates a higher order thought HOT model or David Armstrong and William Lycan who advocate a higher order perception HOP model An alternative higher order theory the higher order global states HOGS model is offered by Robert van Gulick 44 Epistemology edit Main article Epistemology Owing largely to Gettier s 1963 paper Is Justified True Belief Knowledge 45 epistemology resurged as a topic of analytic philosophy during the last 50 years A large portion of current epistemological research is intended to resolve the problems that Gettier s examples presented to the traditional justified true belief model of knowledge including developing theories of justification to deal with Gettier s examples or giving alternatives to the justified true belief model Other and related topics of contemporary research include debates between internalism and externalism 46 basic knowledge the nature of evidence the value of knowledge epistemic luck virtue epistemology the role of intuitions in justification and treating knowledge as a primitive concept Ethics edit Due to the commitments to empiricism and symbolic logic in the early analytic period early analytic philosophers often thought that inquiry in the ethical domain could not be made rigorous enough to merit any attention 47 It was only with the emergence of ordinary language philosophers that ethics started to become an acceptable area of inquiry for analytic philosophers 47 Philosophers working with the analytic tradition have gradually come to distinguish three major types of moral philosophy Meta ethics which investigates moral terms and concepts 48 Normative ethics which examines and produces normative ethical judgments Applied ethics which investigates how existing normative principles should be applied to difficult or borderline cases often cases created by new technology or new scientific knowledge Meta ethics edit Twentieth century meta ethics has two origins The first is G E Moore s investigation into the nature of ethical terms e g good in his Principia Ethica 1903 which identified the naturalistic fallacy Along with Hume s famous is ought distinction the naturalistic fallacy was a major topic of investigation for analytical philosophers The second is in logical positivism and its attitude that unverifiable statements are meaningless Although that attitude was adopted originally to promote scientific investigation by rejecting grand metaphysical systems it had the side effect of making ethical and aesthetic value judgments as well as religious statements and beliefs meaningless But because value judgments are of significant importance in human life it became incumbent on logical positivism to develop an explanation of the nature and meaning of value judgments As a result analytic philosophers avoided normative ethics and instead began meta ethical investigations into the nature of moral terms statements and judgments The logical positivists opined that statements about value including all ethical and aesthetic judgments are non cognitive that is they cannot be objectively verified or falsified Instead the logical positivists adopted an emotivist theory which was that value judgments expressed the attitude of the speaker For example in this view saying Killing is wrong is equivalent to saying Boo to murder or saying the word murder with a particular tone of disapproval While analytic philosophers generally accepted non cognitivism emotivism had many deficiencies It evolved into more sophisticated non cognitivist theories such as the expressivism of Charles Stevenson and the universal prescriptivism of R M Hare which was based on J L Austin s philosophy of speech acts These theories were not without their critics Philippa Foot contributed several essays attacking all these theories J O Urmson s article On Grading called the is ought distinction into question As non cognitivism the is ought distinction and the naturalistic fallacy began to be called into question analytic philosophers showed a renewed interest in the traditional questions of moral philosophy Perhaps the most influential being Elizabeth Anscombe whose monograph Intention was called by Donald Davidson the most important treatment of action since Aristotle 49 A favorite student and friend of Ludwig Wittgenstein her 1958 article Modern Moral Philosophy introduced the term consequentialism into the philosophical lexicon declared the is ought impasse to be unproductive and resulted in a revival of virtue ethics Normative ethics edit The first half of the 20th century was marked by skepticism toward and neglect of normative ethics Related subjects such as social and political philosophy aesthetics and philosophy of history became only marginal topics of English language philosophy during this period During this time utilitarianism was the only non skeptical type of ethics to remain popular However as the influence of logical positivism began to decrease mid century analytic philosophers had renewed interest in ethics G E M Anscombe s 1958 Modern Moral Philosophy sparked a revival of Aristotle s virtue ethical approach and John Rawls s 1971 A Theory of Justice restored interest in Kantian ethical philosophy Today contemporary normative ethics is dominated by three schools consequentialism virtue ethics and deontology Applied ethics edit A significant feature of analytic philosophy since approximately 1970 has been the emergence of applied ethics an interest in the application of moral principles to specific practical issues The philosophers following this orientation view ethics as involving humanistic values which involve practical implications and applications in the way people interact and lead their lives socially 50 Topics of special interest for applied ethics include environmental issues animal rights and the many challenges created by advancing medical science 51 52 53 In education applied ethics addressed themes such as punishment in schools equality of educational opportunity and education for democracy 54 Philosophy of religion edit In Analytic Philosophy of Religion James Franklin Harris noted that analytic philosophy has been a very heterogeneous movement some forms of analytic philosophy have proven very sympathetic to the philosophy of religion and have provided a philosophical mechanism for responding to other more radical and hostile forms of analytic philosophy 55 3 As with the study of ethics early analytic philosophy tended to avoid the study of philosophy of religion largely dismissing as per the logical positivists the subject as part of metaphysics and therefore meaningless 56 The demise of logical positivism renewed interest in philosophy of religion prompting philosophers like William Alston John Mackie Alvin Plantinga Robert Merrihew Adams Richard Swinburne and Antony Flew not only to introduce new problems but to re study classical topics such as the nature of miracles theistic arguments the problem of evil see existence of God the rationality of belief in God concepts of the nature of God and many more 57 Plantinga Mackie and Flew debated the logical validity of the free will defense as a way to solve the problem of evil 58 Alston grappling with the consequences of analytic philosophy of language worked on the nature of religious language Adams worked on the relationship of faith and morality 59 Analytic epistemology and metaphysics has formed the basis for some philosophically sophisticated theistic arguments like those of the reformed epistemologists like Plantinga Analytic philosophy of religion has also been preoccupied with Wittgenstein as well as his interpretation of Soren Kierkegaard s philosophy of religion 60 Using first hand remarks which was later published in Philosophical Investigations Culture and Value and other works philosophers such as Peter Winch and Norman Malcolm developed what has come to be known as contemplative philosophy a Wittgensteinian school of thought rooted in the Swansea tradition and which includes Wittgensteinians such as Rush Rhees Peter Winch and D Z Phillips among others The name contemplative philosophy was first coined by D Z Phillips in Philosophy s Cool Place which rests on an interpretation of a passage from Wittgenstein s Culture and Value 61 This interpretation was first labeled Wittgensteinian Fideism by Kai Nielsen but those who consider themselves Wittgensteinians in the Swansea tradition have relentlessly and repeatedly rejected this construal as a caricature of Wittgenstein s considered position this is especially true of D Z Phillips 62 Responding to this interpretation Kai Nielsen and D Z Phillips became two of the most prominent philosophers on Wittgenstein s philosophy of religion 63 Philosophy of science edit Main article Philosophy of science Reacting against both the verificationism of the logical positivists as well as the critiques of the philosopher of science Karl Popper who had suggested the falsifiability criterion on which to judge the demarcation between science and non science discussions of philosophy of science during the last 40 years were dominated by social constructivist and cognitive relativist theories of science Thomas Samuel Kuhn with his formulation of paradigm shifts and Paul Feyerabend with his epistemological anarchism are significant for these discussions 64 The philosophy of biology has also undergone considerable growth particularly due to the considerable debate in recent years over the nature of evolution particularly natural selection 65 Daniel Dennett and his 1995 book Darwin s Dangerous Idea which defends Neo Darwinism stand at the foreground of this debate 66 Political philosophy edit Liberalism edit Current analytic political philosophy owes much to John Rawls who in a series of papers from the 1950s onward most notably Two Concepts of Rules and Justice as Fairness and his 1971 book A Theory of Justice produced a sophisticated defense of a generally liberal egalitarian account of distributive justice This was followed soon by Rawls s colleague Robert Nozick s book Anarchy State and Utopia a defence of free market libertarianism Isaiah Berlin also had a lasting influence on both analytic political philosophy and liberalism with his lecture Two Concepts of Liberty citation needed During recent decades there have also been several critiques of liberalism including the feminist critiques of Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin the communitarian critiques of Michael Sandel and Alasdair MacIntyre although neither of them endorses the term and the multiculturalist critiques of Amy Gutmann and Charles Taylor Although not an analytic philosopher Jurgen Habermas is another prominent if controversial author of contemporary analytic political philosophy whose social theory is a blend of social science Marxism neo Kantianism and American pragmatism citation needed Consequentialist libertarianism also derives from the analytic tradition citation needed Analytical Marxism edit Another development of political philosophy was the emergence of the school of analytical Marxism Members of this school seek to apply techniques of analytic philosophy and modern social science such as rational choice theory to clarify the theories of Karl Marx and his successors The best known member of this school is G A Cohen whose 1978 work Karl Marx s Theory of History A Defence is generally considered to represent the genesis of this school In that book Cohen used logical and linguistic analysis to clarify and defend Marx s materialist conception of history Other prominent analytical Marxists include the economist John Roemer the social scientist Jon Elster and the sociologist Erik Olin Wright The work of these later philosophers have furthered Cohen s work by bringing to bear modern social science methods such as rational choice theory to supplement Cohen s use of analytic philosophical techniques in the interpretation of Marxian theory Cohen himself would later engage directly with Rawlsian political philosophy to advance a socialist theory of justice that contrasts with both traditional Marxism and the theories advanced by Rawls and Nozick In particular he indicates Marx s principle of from each according to his ability to each according to his need Communitarianism edit Communitarians such as Alasdair MacIntyre Charles Taylor Michael Walzer and Michael Sandel advance a critique of liberalism that uses analytic techniques to isolate the main assumptions of liberal individualists such as Rawls and then challenges these assumptions In particular communitarians challenge the liberal assumption that the individual can be considered as fully autonomous from the community in which he lives and is brought up Instead they argue for a conception of the individual that emphasizes the role that the community plays in forming his or her values thought processes and opinions Communitarianism has a complex relationship with the analytic tradition as its major exponents often engage at length with figures generally considered continental notably G W F Hegel and Friedrich Nietzsche Aesthetics edit Main article Aesthetics As a result of what seemed like rejections of the traditional aesthetic notions of beauty and sublimity from post modern thinkers analytic philosophers were slow to consider art and aesthetic judgment Susanne Langer 67 and Nelson Goodman 68 addressed these problems in an analytic style during the 1950s and 1960s Since Goodman aesthetics as a discipline for analytic philosophers has flourished 69 Rigorous efforts to pursue analyses of traditional aesthetic concepts were performed by Guy Sircello in the 1970s and 1980s resulting in new analytic theories of love 70 sublimity 71 and beauty 72 See also editAnalytic phenomenology Analytical Thomism Logicism Philosophical analysis Postanalytic philosophy ScientismNotes edit A C Grayling ed Philosophy 2 Further through the Subject Oxford University Press 1998 p 2 Analytic philosophy is mainly associated with the contemporary English speaking world but it is by no means the only important philosophical tradition In this volume two other immensely rich and important such traditions are introduced Indian philosophy and philosophical thought in Europe from the time of Hegel L J Cohen The Dialogue of Reason An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy Oxford University Press 1986 p 5 So despite a few overlaps analytical philosophy is not difficult to distinguish broadly from other modern movements like phenomenology say or existentialism or from the large amount of philosophizing that has also gone on in the present century within frameworks deriving from other influential thinkers like Aquinas Hegel or Marx H J Glock What Is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2008 p 86 Most non analytic philosophers of the twentieth century do not belong to continental philosophy Critchley Simon 2001 Continental philosophy a very short introduction Oxford University Press OCLC 1200924441 the distinction rests upon a confusion of geographical and methodological terms as if one were to classify cars into front wheel drive and Japanese the distinction between analytic and Continental philosophy rests upon a confused comparison of methodological and geographical categories Vienne J M 1997 Philosophie analytique et histoire de la philosophie actes du colloque Universite de Nantes 1991 Problemes et controverses in French J Vrin p 140 ISBN 978 2 7116 1312 0 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Luft S 2019 Philosophie lehren Ein Buch zur philosophischen Hochschuldidaktik in German Felix Meiner Verlag p 258 ISBN 978 3 7873 3766 8 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Glock H J 2008 What is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 1 ISBN 978 0 521 87267 6 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Glock H J 2008 What is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 231 ISBN 978 0 521 87267 6 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Akehurst Thomas L 1 March 2009 Writing history for the ahistorical Analytic philosophy and its past History of European Ideas 35 1 116 121 doi 10 1016 j histeuroideas 2008 09 002 ISSN 0191 6599 S2CID 143566283 Beaney Michael 20 June 2013 Beaney Michael ed The Historiography of Analytic Philosophy The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199238842 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 923884 2 Retrieved 18 February 2022 Koopman Colin Bernard Williams on Philosophy s Need for History PDF pages uoregon edu Retrieved 1 March 2022 a b c Brian Leiter 2006 webpage Analytic and Continental Philosophy Quote on the definition Analytic philosophy today names a style of doing philosophy not a philosophical program or a set of substantive views Analytic philosophers crudely speaking aim for argumentative clarity and precision draw freely on the tools of logic and often identify professionally and intellectually more closely with the sciences and mathematics than with the humanities Glock H J 2004 Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher Metaphilosophy 35 4 419 444 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9973 2004 00329 x Colin McGinn The Making of a Philosopher My Journey through Twentieth Century Philosophy HarperCollins 2002 p xi analytical philosophy is too narrow a label since it is not generally a matter of taking a word or concept and analyzing it whatever exactly that might be This tradition emphasizes clarity rigor argument theory truth It is not a tradition that aims primarily for inspiration or consolation or ideology Nor is it particularly concerned with philosophy of life though parts of it are This kind of philosophy is more like science than religion more like mathematics than poetry though it is neither science nor mathematics See e g Avrum Stroll Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy Columbia University Press 2000 p 5 I t is difficult to give a precise definition of analytic philosophy since it is not so much a specific doctrine as a loose concatenation of approaches to problems Also see Stroll 2000 p 7 I think Sluga is right in saying it may be hopeless to try to determine the essence of analytic philosophy Nearly every proposed definition has been challenged by some scholar W e are dealing with a family resemblance concept See Hans Johann Glock What Is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2008 p 205 The answer to the title question then is that analytic philosophy is a tradition held together both by ties of mutual influence and by family resemblances Michael Beaney ed The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy Oxford University Press 2013 p 383 a b Mautner Thomas editor 2005 The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy entry for Analytic philosophy pp 22 23 Analytic philosophy opposed right from its beginning English neo Hegelianism of Bradley s sort and similar ones It did not only criticize the latter s denial of the existence of an external world anyway an unjust criticism but also the bombastic obscure style of Hegel s writings Jonkers Peter 2003 Perspectives on Twentieth Century Philosophy A Reply to Tom Rockmore Ars Disputandi 3 doi 10 1080 15665399 2003 10819802 ISSN 1566 5399 S2CID 70060684 Baillie James Introduction to Bertrand Russell in Contemporary Analytic Philosophy Second Edition Prentice Hall 1997 p 25 Willard Dallas 1980 Husserl on a Logic that Failed Philosophical Review 89 1 52 53 doi 10 2307 2184863 JSTOR 2184863 Russell Bertrand 1905 On Denoting Mind 14 473 493 Archived from the original on 31 March 2006 Carnap R 1928 The Logical Structure of the World Felix Meiner Verlag ISBN 978 0 8126 9523 6 LCCN 66013604 Popper Karl R 2002 The Logic of Scientific Discovery Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 27844 7 Longworth Guy 2017 John Langshaw Austin in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 21 July 2020 a b c Analytic Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Iep utm edu Archived from the original on 3 July 2009 Retrieved 13 April 2018 Without exception the best philosophy departments in the United States are dominated by analytic philosophy and among the leading philosophers in the United States all but a tiny handful would be classified as analytic philosophers Practitioners of types of philosophizing that are not in the analytic tradition such as phenomenology classical pragmatism existentialism or Marxism feel it necessary to define their position in relation to analytic philosophy John Searle 2003 Contemporary Philosophy in the United States in N Bunnin and E P Tsui James eds The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy 2nd ed Blackwell 2003 p 1 A P Martinich ed 2001 A companion to analytic philosophy Malden MA Blackwell pp 1 5 doi 10 1002 9780470998656 ch1 ISBN 978 0 631 21415 1 Hales Steven D 2002 Analytic philosophy classic readings Belmont CA Wadsworth Thomson Learning pp 1 10 ISBN 978 0 534 51277 4 Soames Scott 2003 The dawn of analysis 2nd print 1st papers print ed Princeton NJ Princeton Univ Press pp xiii xvii ISBN 978 0 691 11573 3 Weatherson Brian 2016 David Lewis in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 21 July 2020 Jackson Frank 2016 Armstrong David Malet 1926 2014 Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 ed London Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 v035 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 retrieved 21 July 2020 Armstrong David Malet 1995 Universals and scientific realism Cambridge Univ Press ISBN 0 521 28033 8 OCLC 174240749 Lewis David March 1986 Against structural universals Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 1 25 46 doi 10 1080 00048408612342211 ISSN 0004 8402 Hitchcock Christopher 6 March 2015 Lewis on Causation A Companion to David Lewis Oxford UK John Wiley amp Sons Ltd pp 295 311 doi 10 1002 9781118398593 ch19 ISBN 978 1 118 39859 3 Lewis David K 2008 On the plurality of worlds Blackwell Publ ISBN 978 0 631 22426 6 OCLC 552327787 Rosen Gideon 2020 Abstract Objects in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 21 July 2020 S Yablo and A Gallois Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes Vol 72 1998 pp 229 261 263 283 first part Archived 12 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine Zimmerman Dean W Prologue in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics Volume 1 Oxford University Press 2004 p xix Everett Anthony and Thomas Hofweber eds 2000 Empty Names Fiction and the Puzzles of Non Existence a b Van Inwagen Peter and Dean Zimmerman eds 1998 Metaphysics The Big Questions Graham George Behaviorism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2010 Edition Edward N Zalta ed 1 Zalta Edward N ed Dualism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Postrel and Feser February 2000 Reality Principles An Interview with John R Searle at Reality Principles An Interview with John R Searle February 2000 Archived from the original on 29 September 2008 Retrieved 23 September 2008 Dennett D 2001 Are we explaining consciousness yet Cognition 79 1 2 221 237 doi 10 1016 S0010 0277 00 00130 X PMID 11164029 S2CID 2235514 For summaries and some criticism of the different higher order theories see Van Gulick Robert 2006 Mirror Mirror Is That All In Kriegel amp Williford eds Self Representational Approaches to Consciousness Cambridge MA MIT Press The final draft is also available here Archived copy PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2 October 2008 Retrieved 23 September 2008 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link For Van Gulick s own view see Van Gulick Robert Higher Order Global States HOGS An Alternative Higher Order Model of Consciousness In Gennaro R J ed Higher Order Theories of Consciousness An Anthology Amsterdam and Philadelphia John Benjamins Gettier Edmund 15 July 2020 Is Justified True Belief Knowledge PDF Arguing About Knowledge Routledge pp 14 15 doi 10 4324 9781003061038 5 ISBN 978 1 003 06103 8 S2CID 243290967 Bonjour Laurence Recent Work on the Internalism Externalism Controversy in Dancy Sosa and Steup eds A Companion to Epistemology Second Edition Wiley Blackwell 2010 p 33 a b Schwartz Stephen P 2012 A Brief History of Analytic Philosophy From Russell to Rawls John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 27172 8 Kuusela Oskari 2011 Key Terms in Ethics London Continuum International Publishing Group p 61 ISBN 978 1 4411 6610 4 From the cover of the 2000 Harvard University Press edition of Intention Ikuenobe Polycarp 2006 Philosophical Perspectives on Communalism and Morality in African Traditions Oxford Lexington Books p 104 ISBN 978 0 7391 1131 4 Brennan Andrew and Yeuk Sze Lo 2002 Environmental Ethics 2 Archived 1 August 2013 at the Wayback Machine in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Gruen Lori 2003 The Moral Status of Animals in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy See Hursthouse Rosalind 2003 Virtue Ethics 3 in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and Donchin Anne 2004 Feminist Bioethics in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Heyting Frieda Lenzen Dieter White John 2002 Methods in Philosophy of Education New York Routledge pp 18 ISBN 978 0 415 24260 8 Harris James Franklin 2002 Analytic philosophy of religion Dordrecht Kluwer ISBN 978 1 4020 0530 5 432 pages volume 3 of Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion ISSN 1568 1556 a notable exception is the series of Michael B Forest s 1934 36 Mind articles involving the Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern science Peterson Michael et al 2003 Reason and Religious Belief Mackie John L 1982 The Miracle of Theism Arguments For and Against the Existence of God Adams Robert M 1987 The Virtue of Faith And Other Essays in Philosophical Theology Creegan Charles 1989 Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard Religion Individuality and Philosophical Method Phillips D Z 1999 Philosophy s Cool Place Cornell University Press The quote is from Wittgenstein s Culture and Value 2e My ideal is a certain coolness A temple providing a setting for the passions without meddling with them Zalta Edward N ed Fideism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Nielsen Kai and D Z Phillips 2005 Wittgensteinian Fideism Glock 2008 p 47 Hull David L and Ruse Michael Preface in The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Cambridge University Press 2007 pp xix xx Lennox James G Darwinism and Neo Darwinism in Sakar and Plutynski eds A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Blackwell Publishing 2008 p 89 Susanne Langer Feeling and Form A Theory of Art 1953 Nelson Goodman Languages of Art An Approach to a Theory of Symbols Indianapolis Bobbs Merrill 1968 2nd ed Indianapolis Hackett 1976 Based on his 1960 61 John Locke lectures Kivy Peter Introduction Aesthetics Today in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics Blackwell Publishing 2004 p 4 Guy Sircello Love and Beauty Princeton NJ Princeton University Press 1989 Guy Sircello How Is a Theory of the Sublime Possible The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Vol 51 No 4 Autumn 1993 pp 541 550 Guy Sircello A New Theory of Beauty Princeton Essays on the Arts 1 Princeton NJ Princeton University Press 1975 References editAristotle Metaphysics Geach P Mental Acts London 1957 Kenny A J P Wittgenstein London 1973 Aaron Preston Analytic philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico PhilosophicusFurther reading editThe London Philosophy Study Guide Archived 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read depending on the student s familiarity with the subject Frege Russell and Wittgenstein Dummett Michael The Origins of Analytical Philosophy Cambridge MA Harvard University Press 1993 Hirschberger Johannes A Short History of Western Philosophy ed Clare Hay Short History of Western Philosophy A ISBN 978 0 7188 3092 2 Hylton Peter Russell Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press 1990 Soames Scott Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century Volume 1 The Dawn of Analysis Princeton Princeton University Press 2003 Passmore John A Hundred Years of Philosophy revised ed New York Basic Books 1966 Weitz Morris ed Twentieth Century Philosophy The Analytic Tradition New York Free Press 1966 External links edit Analytic philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Zalta Edward N ed Conceptions of Analysis in Analytic Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Analytic philosophy at Curlie Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Analytic philosophy amp oldid 1205014024, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.