fbpx
Wikipedia

Occam's razor

Occam's razor (also spelled Ockham's razor or Ocham's razor; Latin: novacula Occami) in philosophy is the problem-solving principle that recommends searching for explanations constructed with the smallest possible set of elements. It is also known as the principle of parsimony or the law of parsimony (Latin: lex parsimoniae). Attributed to William of Ockham, a 14th-century English philosopher and theologian, it is frequently cited as Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem, which translates as "Entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity",[1][2] although Occam never used these exact words. Popularly, the principle is sometimes inaccurately[3] paraphrased as "The simplest explanation is usually the best one."[4]

This philosophical razor advocates that when presented with competing hypotheses about the same prediction, one should prefer the one that requires the fewest assumptions[3] and that this is not meant to be a way of choosing between hypotheses that make different predictions. Similarly, in science, Occam's razor is used as an abductive heuristic in the development of theoretical models rather than as a rigorous arbiter between candidate models.[5][6]

History

The phrase Occam's razor did not appear until a few centuries after William of Ockham's death in 1347. Libert Froidmont, in his On Christian Philosophy of the Soul, gives him credit for the phrase, speaking of "novacula occami".[7] Ockham did not invent this principle, but its fame—and its association with him—may be due to the frequency and effectiveness with which he used it.[8] Ockham stated the principle in various ways, but the most popular version, "Entities are not to be multiplied without necessity" (Non sunt multiplicanda entia sine necessitate) was formulated by the Irish Franciscan philosopher John Punch in his 1639 commentary on the works of Duns Scotus.[9]

Formulations before William of Ockham

 
Part of a page from John Duns Scotus's book Commentaria oxoniensia ad IV libros magistri Sententiarus, showing the words: "Pluralitas non est ponenda sine necessitate", i.e., "Plurality is not to be posited without necessity"

The origins of what has come to be known as Occam's razor are traceable to the works of earlier philosophers such as John Duns Scotus (1265–1308), Robert Grosseteste (1175–1253), Maimonides (Moses ben-Maimon, 1138–1204), and even Aristotle (384–322 BC).[10][11] Aristotle writes in his Posterior Analytics, "We may assume the superiority ceteris paribus [other things being equal] of the demonstration which derives from fewer postulates or hypotheses." Ptolemy (c. AD 90 – c. 168) stated, "We consider it a good principle to explain the phenomena by the simplest hypothesis possible."[12]

Phrases such as "It is vain to do with more what can be done with fewer" and "A plurality is not to be posited without necessity" were commonplace in 13th-century scholastic writing.[12] Robert Grosseteste, in Commentary on [Aristotle's] the Posterior Analytics Books (Commentarius in Posteriorum Analyticorum Libros) (c. 1217–1220), declares: "That is better and more valuable which requires fewer, other circumstances being equal... For if one thing were demonstrated from many and another thing from fewer equally known premises, clearly that is better which is from fewer because it makes us know quickly, just as a universal demonstration is better than particular because it produces knowledge from fewer premises. Similarly in natural science, in moral science, and in metaphysics the best is that which needs no premises and the better that which needs the fewer, other circumstances being equal."[13]

The Summa Theologica of Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274) states that "it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many." Aquinas uses this principle to construct an objection to God's existence, an objection that he in turn answers and refutes generally (cf. quinque viae), and specifically, through an argument based on causality.[14] Hence, Aquinas acknowledges the principle that today is known as Occam's razor, but prefers causal explanations to other simple explanations (cf. also Correlation does not imply causation).

William of Ockham

 
Manuscript illustration of William of Ockham

William of Ockham (circa 1287–1347) was an English Franciscan friar and theologian, an influential medieval philosopher and a nominalist. His popular fame as a great logician rests chiefly on the maxim attributed to him and known as Occam's razor. The term razor refers to distinguishing between two hypotheses either by "shaving away" unnecessary assumptions or cutting apart two similar conclusions.

While it has been claimed that Occam's razor is not found in any of William's writings,[15] one can cite statements such as Numquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necessitate ("Plurality must never be posited without necessity"), which occurs in his theological work on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (Quaestiones et decisiones in quattuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi; ed. Lugd., 1495, i, dist. 27, qu. 2, K).

Nevertheless, the precise words sometimes attributed to William of Ockham, Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem (Entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity),[16] are absent in his extant works;[17] this particular phrasing comes from John Punch,[18] who described the principle as a "common axiom" (axioma vulgare) of the Scholastics.[9] William of Ockham himself seems to restrict the operation of this principle in matters pertaining to miracles and God's power, considering a plurality of miracles possible in the Eucharist[further explanation needed] simply because it pleases God.[12]

This principle is sometimes phrased as Pluralitas non est ponenda sine necessitate ("Plurality should not be posited without necessity").[19] In his Summa Totius Logicae, i. 12, William of Ockham cites the principle of economy, Frustra fit per plura quod potest fieri per pauciora ("It is futile to do with more things that which can be done with fewer"; Thorburn, 1918, pp. 352–53; Kneale and Kneale, 1962, p. 243.)

Later formulations

To quote Isaac Newton, "We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances. Therefore, to the same natural effects we must, as far as possible, assign the same causes."[20][21] In the sentence hypotheses non fingo, Newton affirms the success of this approach.

Bertrand Russell offers a particular version of Occam's razor: "Whenever possible, substitute constructions out of known entities for inferences to unknown entities."[22]

Around 1960, Ray Solomonoff founded the theory of universal inductive inference, the theory of prediction based on observations – for example, predicting the next symbol based upon a given series of symbols. The only assumption is that the environment follows some unknown but computable probability distribution. This theory is a mathematical formalization of Occam's razor.[23][24][25]

Another technical approach to Occam's razor is ontological parsimony.[26] Parsimony means spareness and is also referred to as the Rule of Simplicity. This is considered a strong version of Occam's razor.[27][28] A variation used in medicine is called the "Zebra": a physician should reject an exotic medical diagnosis when a more commonplace explanation is more likely, derived from Theodore Woodward's dictum "When you hear hoofbeats, think of horses not zebras".[29]

Ernst Mach formulated the stronger version of Occam's razor into physics, which he called the Principle of Economy stating: "Scientists must use the simplest means of arriving at their results and exclude everything not perceived by the senses."[30]

This principle goes back at least as far as Aristotle, who wrote "Nature operates in the shortest way possible."[27] The idea of parsimony or simplicity in deciding between theories, though not the intent of the original expression of Occam's razor, has been assimilated into common culture as the widespread layman's formulation that "the simplest explanation is usually the correct one."[27]

Justifications

Aesthetic

Prior to the 20th century, it was a commonly held belief that nature itself was simple and that simpler hypotheses about nature were thus more likely to be true. This notion was deeply rooted in the aesthetic value that simplicity holds for human thought and the justifications presented for it often drew from theology.[clarification needed] Thomas Aquinas made this argument in the 13th century, writing, "If a thing can be done adequately by means of one, it is superfluous to do it by means of several; for we observe that nature does not employ two instruments [if] one suffices."[31]

Beginning in the 20th century, epistemological justifications based on induction, logic, pragmatism, and especially probability theory have become more popular among philosophers.[7]

Empirical

Occam's razor has gained strong empirical support in helping to converge on better theories (see Uses section below for some examples).

In the related concept of overfitting, excessively complex models are affected by statistical noise (a problem also known as the bias-variance trade-off), whereas simpler models may capture the underlying structure better and may thus have better predictive performance. It is, however, often difficult to deduce which part of the data is noise (cf. model selection, test set, minimum description length, Bayesian inference, etc.).

Testing the razor

The razor's statement that "other things being equal, simpler explanations are generally better than more complex ones" is amenable to empirical testing. Another interpretation of the razor's statement would be that "simpler hypotheses are generally better than the complex ones". The procedure to test the former interpretation would compare the track records of simple and comparatively complex explanations. If one accepts the first interpretation, the validity of Occam's razor as a tool would then have to be rejected if the more complex explanations were more often correct than the less complex ones (while the converse would lend support to its use). If the latter interpretation is accepted, the validity of Occam's razor as a tool could possibly be accepted if the simpler hypotheses led to correct conclusions more often than not.

 
Possible explanations can become needlessly complex. It might be coherent, for instance, to add the involvement of leprechauns to any explanation, but Occam's razor would prevent such additions unless they were necessary.

Even if some increases in complexity are sometimes necessary, there still remains a justified general bias toward the simpler of two competing explanations. To understand why, consider that for each accepted explanation of a phenomenon, there is always an infinite number of possible, more complex, and ultimately incorrect, alternatives. This is so because one can always burden a failing explanation with an ad hoc hypothesis. Ad hoc hypotheses are justifications that prevent theories from being falsified.

For example, if a man, accused of breaking a vase, makes supernatural claims that leprechauns were responsible for the breakage, a simple explanation might be that the man did it, but ongoing ad hoc justifications (e.g. "... and that's not me breaking it on the film; they tampered with that, too") could successfully prevent complete disproof. This endless supply of elaborate competing explanations, called saving hypotheses, cannot be technically ruled out – except by using Occam's razor.[32][33][34]

Any more complex theory might still possibly be true. A study of the predictive validity of Occam's razor found 32 published papers that included 97 comparisons of economic forecasts from simple and complex forecasting methods. None of the papers provided a balance of evidence that complexity of method improved forecast accuracy. In the 25 papers with quantitative comparisons, complexity increased forecast errors by an average of 27 percent.[35]

Practical considerations and pragmatism

Mathematical

One justification of Occam's razor is a direct result of basic probability theory. By definition, all assumptions introduce possibilities for error; if an assumption does not improve the accuracy of a theory, its only effect is to increase the probability that the overall theory is wrong.

There have also been other attempts to derive Occam's razor from probability theory, including notable attempts made by Harold Jeffreys and E. T. Jaynes. The probabilistic (Bayesian) basis for Occam's razor is elaborated by David J. C. MacKay in chapter 28 of his book Information Theory, Inference, and Learning Algorithms,[36] where he emphasizes that a prior bias in favor of simpler models is not required.

William H. Jefferys and James O. Berger (1991) generalize and quantify the original formulation's "assumptions" concept as the degree to which a proposition is unnecessarily accommodating to possible observable data.[37] They state, "A hypothesis with fewer adjustable parameters will automatically have an enhanced posterior probability, due to the fact that the predictions it makes are sharp."[37] The use of "sharp" here is not only a tongue-in-cheek reference to the idea of a razor, but also indicates that such predictions are more accurate than competing predictions. The model they propose balances the precision of a theory's predictions against their sharpness, preferring theories that sharply make correct predictions over theories that accommodate a wide range of other possible results. This, again, reflects the mathematical relationship between key concepts in Bayesian inference (namely marginal probability, conditional probability, and posterior probability).

The bias–variance tradeoff is a framework that incorporates the Occam's razor principle in its balance between overfitting (associated with lower bias but higher variance) and underfitting (associated with lower variance but higher bias).[38]

Other philosophers

Karl Popper

Karl Popper argues that a preference for simple theories need not appeal to practical or aesthetic considerations. Our preference for simplicity may be justified by its falsifiability criterion: we prefer simpler theories to more complex ones "because their empirical content is greater; and because they are better testable".[39] The idea here is that a simple theory applies to more cases than a more complex one, and is thus more easily falsifiable. This is again comparing a simple theory to a more complex theory where both explain the data equally well.

Elliott Sober

The philosopher of science Elliott Sober once argued along the same lines as Popper, tying simplicity with "informativeness": The simplest theory is the more informative, in the sense that it requires less information to a question.[40] He has since rejected this account of simplicity, purportedly because it fails to provide an epistemic justification for simplicity. He now believes that simplicity considerations (and considerations of parsimony in particular) do not count unless they reflect something more fundamental. Philosophers, he suggests, may have made the error of hypostatizing simplicity (i.e., endowed it with a sui generis existence), when it has meaning only when embedded in a specific context (Sober 1992). If we fail to justify simplicity considerations on the basis of the context in which we use them, we may have no non-circular justification: "Just as the question 'why be rational?' may have no non-circular answer, the same may be true of the question 'why should simplicity be considered in evaluating the plausibility of hypotheses?'"[41]

Richard Swinburne

Richard Swinburne argues for simplicity on logical grounds:

... the simplest hypothesis proposed as an explanation of phenomena is more likely to be the true one than is any other available hypothesis, that its predictions are more likely to be true than those of any other available hypothesis, and that it is an ultimate a priori epistemic principle that simplicity is evidence for truth.

— Swinburne 1997

According to Swinburne, since our choice of theory cannot be determined by data (see Underdetermination and Duhem–Quine thesis), we must rely on some criterion to determine which theory to use. Since it is absurd to have no logical method for settling on one hypothesis amongst an infinite number of equally data-compliant hypotheses, we should choose the simplest theory: "Either science is irrational [in the way it judges theories and predictions probable] or the principle of simplicity is a fundamental synthetic a priori truth.".[42]

Ludwig Wittgenstein

From the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus:

  • 3.328 "If a sign is not necessary then it is meaningless. That is the meaning of Occam's Razor."
(If everything in the symbolism works as though a sign had meaning, then it has meaning.)
  • 4.04 "In the proposition, there must be exactly as many things distinguishable as there are in the state of affairs, which it represents. They must both possess the same logical (mathematical) multiplicity (cf. Hertz's Mechanics, on Dynamic Models)."
  • 5.47321 "Occam's Razor is, of course, not an arbitrary rule nor one justified by its practical success. It simply says that unnecessary elements in a symbolism mean nothing. Signs which serve one purpose are logically equivalent; signs which serve no purpose are logically meaningless."

and on the related concept of "simplicity":

  • 6.363 "The procedure of induction consists in accepting as true the simplest law that can be reconciled with our experiences."

Uses

Science and the scientific method

 
Andreas Cellarius's illustration of the Copernican system, from the Harmonia Macrocosmica (1660). Future positions of the sun, moon and other solar system bodies can be calculated using a geocentric model (the earth is at the centre) or using a heliocentric model (the sun is at the centre). Both work, but the geocentric model arrives at the same conclusions through a much more complex system of calculations than the heliocentric model. This was pointed out in a preface to Copernicus' first edition of De revolutionibus orbium coelestium.

In science, Occam's razor is used as a heuristic to guide scientists in developing theoretical models rather than as an arbiter between published models.[5][6] In physics, parsimony was an important heuristic in Albert Einstein's formulation of special relativity,[43][44] in the development and application of the principle of least action by Pierre Louis Maupertuis and Leonhard Euler,[45] and in the development of quantum mechanics by Max Planck, Werner Heisenberg and Louis de Broglie.[6][46]

In chemistry, Occam's razor is often an important heuristic when developing a model of a reaction mechanism.[47][48] Although it is useful as a heuristic in developing models of reaction mechanisms, it has been shown to fail as a criterion for selecting among some selected published models.[6] In this context, Einstein himself expressed caution when he formulated Einstein's Constraint: "It can scarcely be denied that the supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience."[49][50][51] An often-quoted version of this constraint (which cannot be verified as posited by Einstein himself)[52] reduces this to "Everything should be kept as simple as possible, but not simpler."

In the scientific method, Occam's razor is not considered an irrefutable principle of logic or a scientific result; the preference for simplicity in the scientific method is based on the falsifiability criterion. For each accepted explanation of a phenomenon, there may be an extremely large, perhaps even incomprehensible, number of possible and more complex alternatives. Since failing explanations can always be burdened with ad hoc hypotheses to prevent them from being falsified, simpler theories are preferable to more complex ones because they tend to be more testable.[53][54][55] As a logical principle, Occam's razor would demand that scientists accept the simplest possible theoretical explanation for existing data. However, science has shown repeatedly that future data often support more complex theories than do existing data. Science prefers the simplest explanation that is consistent with the data available at a given time, but the simplest explanation may be ruled out as new data become available.[5][54] That is, science is open to the possibility that future experiments might support more complex theories than demanded by current data and is more interested in designing experiments to discriminate between competing theories than favoring one theory over another based merely on philosophical principles.[53][54][55]

When scientists use the idea of parsimony, it has meaning only in a very specific context of inquiry. Several background assumptions are required for parsimony to connect with plausibility in a particular research problem.[clarification needed] The reasonableness of parsimony in one research context may have nothing to do with its reasonableness in another. It is a mistake to think that there is a single global principle that spans diverse subject matter.[55]

It has been suggested that Occam's razor is a widely accepted example of extraevidential consideration, even though it is entirely a metaphysical assumption. Most of the time, however, Occam's razor is a conservative tool, cutting out "crazy, complicated constructions" and assuring "that hypotheses are grounded in the science of the day", thus yielding "normal" science: models of explanation and prediction.[6] There are, however, notable exceptions where Occam's razor turns a conservative scientist into a reluctant revolutionary. For example, Max Planck interpolated between the Wien and Jeans radiation laws and used Occam's razor logic to formulate the quantum hypothesis, even resisting that hypothesis as it became more obvious that it was correct.[6]

Appeals to simplicity were used to argue against the phenomena of meteorites, ball lightning, continental drift, and reverse transcriptase.[56] One can argue for atomic building blocks for matter, because it provides a simpler explanation for the observed reversibility of both mixing[clarification needed] and chemical reactions as simple separation and rearrangements of atomic building blocks. At the time, however, the atomic theory was considered more complex because it implied the existence of invisible particles that had not been directly detected. Ernst Mach and the logical positivists rejected John Dalton's atomic theory until the reality of atoms was more evident in Brownian motion, as shown by Albert Einstein.[57]

In the same way, postulating the aether is more complex than transmission of light through a vacuum. At the time, however, all known waves propagated through a physical medium, and it seemed simpler to postulate the existence of a medium than to theorize about wave propagation without a medium. Likewise, Isaac Newton's idea of light particles seemed simpler than Christiaan Huygens's idea of waves, so many favored it. In this case, as it turned out, neither the wave—nor the particle—explanation alone suffices, as light behaves like waves and like particles.

Three axioms presupposed by the scientific method are realism (the existence of objective reality), the existence of natural laws, and the constancy of natural law. Rather than depend on provability of these axioms, science depends on the fact that they have not been objectively falsified. Occam's razor and parsimony support, but do not prove, these axioms of science. The general principle of science is that theories (or models) of natural law must be consistent with repeatable experimental observations. This ultimate arbiter (selection criterion) rests upon the axioms mentioned above.[54]

If multiple models of natural law make exactly the same testable predictions, they are equivalent and there is no need for parsimony to choose a preferred one. For example, Newtonian, Hamiltonian and Lagrangian classical mechanics are equivalent. Physicists have no interest in using Occam's razor to say the other two are wrong. Likewise, there is no demand for simplicity principles to arbitrate between wave and matrix formulations of quantum mechanics. Science often does not demand arbitration or selection criteria between models that make the same testable predictions.[54]

Biology

Biologists or philosophers of biology use Occam's razor in either of two contexts both in evolutionary biology: the units of selection controversy and systematics. George C. Williams in his book Adaptation and Natural Selection (1966) argues that the best way to explain altruism among animals is based on low-level (i.e., individual) selection as opposed to high-level group selection. Altruism is defined by some evolutionary biologists (e.g., R. Alexander, 1987; W. D. Hamilton, 1964) as behavior that is beneficial to others (or to the group) at a cost to the individual, and many posit individual selection as the mechanism that explains altruism solely in terms of the behaviors of individual organisms acting in their own self-interest (or in the interest of their genes, via kin selection). Williams was arguing against the perspective of others who propose selection at the level of the group as an evolutionary mechanism that selects for altruistic traits (e.g., D. S. Wilson & E. O. Wilson, 2007). The basis for Williams' contention is that of the two, individual selection is the more parsimonious theory. In doing so he is invoking a variant of Occam's razor known as Morgan's Canon: "In no case is an animal activity to be interpreted in terms of higher psychological processes, if it can be fairly interpreted in terms of processes which stand lower in the scale of psychological evolution and development." (Morgan 1903).

However, more recent biological analyses, such as Richard Dawkins' The Selfish Gene, have contended that Morgan's Canon is not the simplest and most basic explanation. Dawkins argues the way evolution works is that the genes propagated in most copies end up determining the development of that particular species, i.e., natural selection turns out to select specific genes, and this is really the fundamental underlying principle that automatically gives individual and group selection as emergent features of evolution.

Zoology provides an example. Muskoxen, when threatened by wolves, form a circle with the males on the outside and the females and young on the inside. This is an example of a behavior by the males that seems to be altruistic. The behavior is disadvantageous to them individually but beneficial to the group as a whole and was thus seen by some to support the group selection theory. Another interpretation is kin selection: if the males are protecting their offspring, they are protecting copies of their own alleles. Engaging in this behavior would be favored by individual selection if the cost to the male musk ox is less than half of the benefit received by his calf – which could easily be the case if wolves have an easier time killing calves than adult males. It could also be the case that male musk oxen would be individually less likely to be killed by wolves if they stood in a circle with their horns pointing out, regardless of whether they were protecting the females and offspring. That would be an example of regular natural selection – a phenomenon called "the selfish herd".

Systematics is the branch of biology that attempts to establish patterns of relationship among biological taxa, today generally thought to reflect evolutionary history. It is also concerned with their classification. There are three primary camps in systematics: cladists, pheneticists, and evolutionary taxonomists. Cladists hold that classification should be based on synapomorphies (shared, derived character states), pheneticists contend that overall similarity (synapomorphies and complementary symplesiomorphies) is the determining criterion, while evolutionary taxonomists say that both genealogy and similarity count in classification (in a manner determined by the evolutionary taxonomist).[58][59]

It is among the cladists that Occam's razor is applied, through the method of cladistic parsimony. Cladistic parsimony (or maximum parsimony) is a method of phylogenetic inference that yields phylogenetic trees (more specifically, cladograms). Cladograms are branching, diagrams used to represent hypotheses of relative degree of relationship, based on synapomorphies. Cladistic parsimony is used to select as the preferred hypothesis of relationships the cladogram that requires the fewest implied character state transformations (or smallest weight, if characters are differentially weighted). Critics of the cladistic approach often observe that for some types of data, parsimony could produce the wrong results, regardless of how much data is collected (this is called statistical inconsistency, or long branch attraction). However, this criticism is also potentially true for any type of phylogenetic inference, unless the model used to estimate the tree reflects the way that evolution actually happened. Because this information is not empirically accessible, the criticism of statistical inconsistency against parsimony holds no force.[60] For a book-length treatment of cladistic parsimony, see Elliott Sober's Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference (1988). For a discussion of both uses of Occam's razor in biology, see Sober's article "Let's Razor Ockham's Razor" (1990).

Other methods for inferring evolutionary relationships use parsimony in a more general way. Likelihood methods for phylogeny use parsimony as they do for all likelihood tests, with hypotheses requiring fewer differing parameters (i.e., numbers or different rates of character change or different frequencies of character state transitions) being treated as null hypotheses relative to hypotheses requiring more differing parameters. Thus, complex hypotheses must predict data much better than do simple hypotheses before researchers reject the simple hypotheses. Recent advances employ information theory, a close cousin of likelihood, which uses Occam's razor in the same way. Of course, the choice of the "shortest tree" relative to a not-so-short tree under any optimality criterion (smallest distance, fewest steps, or maximum likelihood) is always based on parsimony [61]

Francis Crick has commented on potential limitations of Occam's razor in biology. He advances the argument that because biological systems are the products of (an ongoing) natural selection, the mechanisms are not necessarily optimal in an obvious sense. He cautions: "While Ockham's razor is a useful tool in the physical sciences, it can be a very dangerous implement in biology. It is thus very rash to use simplicity and elegance as a guide in biological research."[62] This is an ontological critique of parsimony.

In biogeography, parsimony is used to infer ancient vicariant events or migrations of species or populations by observing the geographic distribution and relationships of existing organisms. Given the phylogenetic tree, ancestral population subdivisions are inferred to be those that require the minimum amount of change.

Religion

In the philosophy of religion, Occam's razor is sometimes applied to the existence of God. William of Ockham himself was a Christian. He believed in God, and in the authority of Scripture; he writes that "nothing ought to be posited without a reason given, unless it is self-evident (literally, known through itself) or known by experience or proved by the authority of Sacred Scripture."[63] Ockham believed that an explanation has no sufficient basis in reality when it does not harmonize with reason, experience, or the Bible. However, unlike many theologians of his time, Ockham did not believe God could be logically proven with arguments. To Ockham, science was a matter of discovery, but theology was a matter of revelation and faith. He states: "only faith gives us access to theological truths. The ways of God are not open to reason, for God has freely chosen to create a world and establish a way of salvation within it apart from any necessary laws that human logic or rationality can uncover."[64]

Thomas Aquinas, in the Summa Theologica, uses a formulation of Occam's razor to construct an objection to the idea that God exists, which he refutes directly with a counterargument:[65]

Further, it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many. But it seems that everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other principles, supposing God did not exist. For all natural things can be reduced to one principle which is nature; and all voluntary things can be reduced to one principle which is human reason, or will. Therefore there is no need to suppose God's existence.

In turn, Aquinas answers this with the quinque viae, and addresses the particular objection above with the following answer:

Since nature works for a determinate end under the direction of a higher agent, whatever is done by nature must needs be traced back to God, as to its first cause. So also whatever is done voluntarily must also be traced back to some higher cause other than human reason or will, since these can change or fail; for all things that are changeable and capable of defect must be traced back to an immovable and self-necessary first principle, as was shown in the body of the Article.

Rather than argue for the necessity of a god, some theists base their belief upon grounds independent of, or prior to, reason, making Occam's razor irrelevant. This was the stance of Søren Kierkegaard, who viewed belief in God as a leap of faith that sometimes directly opposed reason.[66] This is also the doctrine of Gordon Clark's presuppositional apologetics, with the exception that Clark never thought the leap of faith was contrary to reason (see also Fideism).

Various arguments in favor of God establish God as a useful or even necessary assumption. Contrastingly some anti-theists hold firmly to the belief that assuming the existence of God introduces unnecessary complexity (Schmitt 2005, e.g., the Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit).

Another application of the principle is to be found in the work of George Berkeley (1685–1753). Berkeley was an idealist who believed that all of reality could be explained in terms of the mind alone. He invoked Occam's razor against materialism, stating that matter was not required by his metaphysics and was thus eliminable. One potential problem with this belief[for whom?] is that it's possible, given Berkeley's position, to find solipsism itself more in line with the razor than a God-mediated world beyond a single thinker.

Occam's razor may also be recognized in the apocryphal story about an exchange between Pierre-Simon Laplace and Napoleon. It is said that in praising Laplace for one of his recent publications, the emperor asked how it was that the name of God, which featured so frequently in the writings of Lagrange, appeared nowhere in Laplace's. At that, he is said to have replied, "It's because I had no need of that hypothesis."[67] Though some points of this story illustrate Laplace's atheism, more careful consideration suggests that he may instead have intended merely to illustrate the power of methodological naturalism, or even simply that the fewer logical premises one assumes, the stronger is one's conclusion.

Philosophy of mind

In his article "Sensations and Brain Processes" (1959), J. J. C. Smart invoked Occam's razor with the aim to justify his preference of the mind-brain identity theory over spirit-body dualism. Dualists state that there are two kinds of substances in the universe: physical (including the body) and spiritual, which is non-physical. In contrast, identity theorists state that everything is physical, including consciousness, and that there is nothing nonphysical. Though it is impossible to appreciate the spiritual when limiting oneself to the physical[citation needed], Smart maintained that identity theory explains all phenomena by assuming only a physical reality. Subsequently, Smart has been severely criticized for his use (or misuse) of Occam's razor and ultimately retracted his advocacy of it in this context. Paul Churchland (1984) states that by itself Occam's razor is inconclusive regarding duality. In a similar way, Dale Jacquette (1994) stated that Occam's razor has been used in attempts to justify eliminativism and reductionism in the philosophy of mind. Eliminativism is the thesis that the ontology of folk psychology including such entities as "pain", "joy", "desire", "fear", etc., are eliminable in favor of an ontology of a completed neuroscience.

Penal ethics

In penal theory and the philosophy of punishment, parsimony refers specifically to taking care in the distribution of punishment in order to avoid excessive punishment. In the utilitarian approach to the philosophy of punishment, Jeremy Bentham's "parsimony principle" states that any punishment greater than is required to achieve its end is unjust. The concept is related but not identical to the legal concept of proportionality. Parsimony is a key consideration of the modern restorative justice, and is a component of utilitarian approaches to punishment, as well as the prison abolition movement. Bentham believed that true parsimony would require punishment to be individualised to take account of the sensibility of the individual—an individual more sensitive to punishment should be given a proportionately lesser one, since otherwise needless pain would be inflicted. Later utilitarian writers have tended to abandon this idea, in large part due to the impracticality of determining each alleged criminal's relative sensitivity to specific punishments.[68]

Probability theory and statistics

Marcus Hutter's universal artificial intelligence builds upon Solomonoff's mathematical formalization of the razor to calculate the expected value of an action.

There are various papers in scholarly journals deriving formal versions of Occam's razor from probability theory, applying it in statistical inference, and using it to come up with criteria for penalizing complexity in statistical inference. Papers[69][70] have suggested a connection between Occam's razor and Kolmogorov complexity.[71]

One of the problems with the original formulation of the razor is that it only applies to models with the same explanatory power (i.e., it only tells us to prefer the simplest of equally good models). A more general form of the razor can be derived from Bayesian model comparison, which is based on Bayes factors and can be used to compare models that don't fit the observations equally well. These methods can sometimes optimally balance the complexity and power of a model. Generally, the exact Occam factor is intractable, but approximations such as Akaike information criterion, Bayesian information criterion, Variational Bayesian methods, false discovery rate, and Laplace's method are used. Many artificial intelligence researchers are now employing such techniques, for instance through work on Occam Learning or more generally on the Free energy principle.

Statistical versions of Occam's razor have a more rigorous formulation than what philosophical discussions produce. In particular, they must have a specific definition of the term simplicity, and that definition can vary. For example, in the KolmogorovChaitin minimum description length approach, the subject must pick a Turing machine whose operations describe the basic operations believed to represent "simplicity" by the subject. However, one could always choose a Turing machine with a simple operation that happened to construct one's entire theory and would hence score highly under the razor. This has led to two opposing camps: one that believes Occam's razor is objective, and one that believes it is subjective.

Objective razor

The minimum instruction set of a universal Turing machine requires approximately the same length description across different formulations, and is small compared to the Kolmogorov complexity of most practical theories. Marcus Hutter has used this consistency to define a "natural" Turing machine of small size as the proper basis for excluding arbitrarily complex instruction sets in the formulation of razors.[72] Describing the program for the universal program as the "hypothesis", and the representation of the evidence as program data, it has been formally proven under Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that "the sum of the log universal probability of the model plus the log of the probability of the data given the model should be minimized."[73] Interpreting this as minimising the total length of a two-part message encoding model followed by data given model gives us the minimum message length (MML) principle.[69][70]

One possible conclusion from mixing the concepts of Kolmogorov complexity and Occam's razor is that an ideal data compressor would also be a scientific explanation/formulation generator. Some attempts have been made to re-derive known laws from considerations of simplicity or compressibility.[24][74]

According to Jürgen Schmidhuber, the appropriate mathematical theory of Occam's razor already exists, namely, Solomonoff's theory of optimal inductive inference[75] and its extensions.[76] See discussions in David L. Dowe's "Foreword re C. S. Wallace"[77] for the subtle distinctions between the algorithmic probability work of Solomonoff and the MML work of Chris Wallace, and see Dowe's "MML, hybrid Bayesian network graphical models, statistical consistency, invariance and uniqueness"[78] both for such discussions and for (in section 4) discussions of MML and Occam's razor. For a specific example of MML as Occam's razor in the problem of decision tree induction, see Dowe and Needham's "Message Length as an Effective Ockham's Razor in Decision Tree Induction".[79]

Software development

In software development, the rule of least power argues the correct programming language to use is the one that is simplest while also solving the targeted software problem. In that form the rule is often credited to Tim Berners-Lee since it appeared in his design guidelines for the original Hypertext Transfer Protocol.[80] Complexity in this context is measured either by placing a language into the Chomsky hierarchy or by listing idiomatic features of the language and comparing according to some agreed to scale of difficulties between idioms. Many languages once thought to be of lower complexity have evolved or later been discovered to be more complex than originally intended; so, in practice this rule is applied to the relative ease of a programmer to obtain the power of the language, rather than the precise theoretical limits of the language.

Controversial aspects

Occam's razor is not an embargo against the positing of any kind of entity, or a recommendation of the simplest theory come what may.[a] Occam's razor is used to adjudicate between theories that have already passed "theoretical scrutiny" tests and are equally well-supported by evidence.[b] Furthermore, it may be used to prioritize empirical testing between two equally plausible but unequally testable hypotheses; thereby minimizing costs and wastes while increasing chances of falsification of the simpler-to-test hypothesis.[citation needed]

Another contentious aspect of the razor is that a theory can become more complex in terms of its structure (or syntax), while its ontology (or semantics) becomes simpler, or vice versa.[c] Quine, in a discussion on definition, referred to these two perspectives as "economy of practical expression" and "economy in grammar and vocabulary", respectively.[82]

Galileo Galilei lampooned the misuse of Occam's razor in his Dialogue. The principle is represented in the dialogue by Simplicio. The telling point that Galileo presented ironically was that if one really wanted to start from a small number of entities, one could always consider the letters of the alphabet as the fundamental entities, since one could construct the whole of human knowledge out of them.

Anti-razors

Occam's razor has met some opposition from people who consider it too extreme or rash. Walter Chatton (c.  1290–1343) was a contemporary of William of Ockham who took exception to Occam's razor and Ockham's use of it. In response he devised his own anti-razor: "If three things are not enough to verify an affirmative proposition about things, a fourth must be added and so on." Although there have been several philosophers who have formulated similar anti-razors since Chatton's time, no one anti-razor has perpetuated in as much notability as Chatton's anti-razor, although this could be the case of the Late Renaissance Italian motto of unknown attribution Se non è vero, è ben trovato ("Even if it is not true, it is well conceived") when referred to a particularly artful explanation.

Anti-razors have also been created by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716), Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), and Karl Menger (1902–1985). Leibniz's version took the form of a principle of plenitude, as Arthur Lovejoy has called it: the idea being that God created the most varied and populous of possible worlds. Kant felt a need to moderate the effects of Occam's razor and thus created his own counter-razor: "The variety of beings should not rashly be diminished."[83]

Karl Menger found mathematicians to be too parsimonious with regard to variables so he formulated his Law Against Miserliness, which took one of two forms: "Entities must not be reduced to the point of inadequacy" and "It is vain to do with fewer what requires more." A less serious but even more extremist anti-razor is 'Pataphysics, the "science of imaginary solutions" developed by Alfred Jarry (1873–1907). Perhaps the ultimate in anti-reductionism, "'Pataphysics seeks no less than to view each event in the universe as completely unique, subject to no laws but its own." Variations on this theme were subsequently explored by the Argentine writer Jorge Luis Borges in his story/mock-essay "Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius". Physicist R. V. Jones contrived Crabtree's Bludgeon, which states that "[n]o set of mutually inconsistent observations can exist for which some human intellect cannot conceive a coherent explanation, however complicated."[84]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ "Ockham's razor does not say that the more simple a hypothesis, the better."[81]
  2. ^ "Today, we think of the principle of parsimony as a heuristic device. We don't assume that the simpler theory is correct and the more complex one false. We know from experience that more often than not the theory that requires more complicated machinations is wrong. Until proved otherwise, the more complex theory competing with a simpler explanation should be put on the back burner, but not thrown onto the trash heap of history until proven false."[81]
  3. ^ "While these two facets of simplicity are frequently conflated, it is important to treat them as distinct. One reason for doing so is that considerations of parsimony and of elegance typically pull in different directions. Postulating extra entities may allow a theory to be formulated more simply, while reducing the ontology of a theory may only be possible at the price of making it syntactically more complex."[53]

References

  1. ^ Barry, C. M. (27 May 2014). "Who sharpened Occam's Razor?". Irish Philosophy.
  2. ^ Schaffer, Jonathan (2015). "What Not to Multiply Without Necessity" (PDF). Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 93 (4): 644–664. doi:10.1080/00048402.2014.992447. S2CID 16923735.
  3. ^ a b Ball, Philip (11 August 2016). "The Tyranny of Simple Explanations". The Atlantic. Retrieved 2 February 2023.
  4. ^ Duignan, Brian. "Occam's Razor". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 11 May 2021.
  5. ^ a b c Hugh G. Gauch, Scientific Method in Practice, Cambridge University Press, 2003, ISBN 0-521-01708-4, ISBN 978-0-521-01708-4.
  6. ^ a b c d e f Hoffman, Roald; Minkin, Vladimir I.; Carpenter, Barry K. (1997). "Ockham's Razor and Chemistry". International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry. 3: 3–28.
  7. ^ a b Sober, Elliott (2015). Ockam's Razor: A User's Manual. Cambridge University Press. p. 4. ISBN 978-1107692534.
  8. ^ Roger Ariew, Ockham's Razor: A Historical and Philosophical Analysis of Ockham's Principle of Parsimony, 1976
  9. ^ a b Johannes Poncius's commentary on John Duns Scotus's Opus Oxoniense, book III, dist. 34, q. 1. in John Duns Scotus Opera Omnia, vol.15, Ed. Luke Wadding, Louvain (1639), reprinted Paris: Vives, (1894) p.483a
  10. ^ Aristotle, Physics 189a15, On the Heavens 271a33. See also Franklin, op cit. note 44 to chap. 9.
  11. ^ Charlesworth, M. J. (1956). "Aristotle's Razor". Philosophical Studies. 6: 105–112. doi:10.5840/philstudies1956606.
  12. ^ a b c Franklin, James (2001). The Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability before Pascal. The Johns Hopkins University Press. Chap 9. p. 241.
  13. ^ Alistair Cameron Crombie, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100–1700 (1953) pp. 85–86
  14. ^ "SUMMA THEOLOGICA: The existence of God (Prima Pars, Q. 2)". Newadvent.org. from the original on 28 April 2013. Retrieved 26 March 2013.
  15. ^ Vallee, Jacques (11 February 2013). "What Ockham really said". Boing Boing. from the original on 31 March 2013. Retrieved 26 March 2013.
  16. ^ Bauer, Laurie (2007). The linguistics Student's Handbook. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. p. 155.
  17. ^ Flew, Antony (1979). A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Pan Books. p. 253.
  18. ^ Crombie, Alistair Cameron (1959), Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard, Vol. 2, p. 30.
  19. ^ "Ockham's razor". Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. 2010. from the original on 23 August 2010. Retrieved 12 June 2010.
  20. ^ Hawking, Stephen (2003). On the Shoulders of Giants. Running Press. p. 731. ISBN 978-0-7624-1698-1. Retrieved 24 February 2016.
  21. ^ Primary source: Newton (2011, p. 387) wrote the following two "philosophizing rules" at the beginning of part 3 of the Principia 1726 edition.
    Regula I. Causas rerum naturalium non-plures admitti debere, quam quæ & veræ sint & earum phænomenis explicandis sufficient.
    Regula II. Ideoque effectuum naturalium ejusdem generis eædem assignandæ sunt causæ, quatenus fieri potest.
  22. ^ Logical Constructions. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2016.
  23. ^ Induction: From Kolmogorov and Solomonoff to De Finetti and Back to Kolmogorov JJ McCall – Metroeconomica, 2004 – Wiley Online Library.
  24. ^ a b Soklakov, A. N. (2002). "Occam's Razor as a formal basis for a physical theory". Foundations of Physics Letters. 15 (2): 107–135. arXiv:math-ph/0009007. Bibcode:2000math.ph...9007S. doi:10.1023/A:1020994407185. S2CID 14940740.
  25. ^ Rathmanner, Samuel; Hutter, Marcus (2011). "A philosophical treatise of universal induction". Entropy. 13 (6): 1076–1136. arXiv:1105.5721. Bibcode:2011Entrp..13.1076R. doi:10.3390/e13061076. S2CID 2499910.
  26. ^ Baker, Alan (25 February 2010). "Simplicity". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition).
  27. ^ a b c "What is Occam's Razor?". math.ucr.edu. from the original on 6 July 2017.
  28. ^ Stormy Dawn (17 July 2017). Everywhere The Soles of Your Feet Shall Tread. ISBN 9781480838024.
  29. ^ Sotos, John G. (2006) [1991]. Zebra Cards: An Aid to Obscure Diagnoses. Mt. Vernon, VA: Mt. Vernon Book Systems. ISBN 978-0-9818193-0-3.
  30. ^ Becher, Erich (1905). "The Philosophical Views of Ernst Mach". The Philosophical Review. 14 (5): 535–562. doi:10.2307/2177489. JSTOR 2177489.
  31. ^ Pegis 1945.
  32. ^ Stanovich, Keith E. (2007). How to Think Straight About Psychology. Boston: Pearson Education, pp. 19–33.
  33. ^ . skepdic.com. Archived from the original on 27 April 2009.
  34. ^ Swinburne 1997 and Williams, Gareth T, 2008.
  35. ^ Green, K. C.; Armstrong, J. S. (2015). "Simple versus complex forecasting: The evidence". Journal of Business Research. 68 (8): 1678–1685. doi:10.1016/j.jbusres.2015.03.026. (subscription required)
  36. ^ MacKay, David J. C. (2003). Information Theory, Inference, and Learning Algorithms (PDF). Bibcode:2003itil.book.....M. (PDF) from the original on 15 September 2012.
  37. ^ a b Jefferys, William H.; Berger, James O. (1991). "Ockham's Razor and Bayesian Statistics" (PDF). American Scientist. 80 (1): 64–72. JSTOR 29774559. (PDF) from the original on 4 March 2005. (preprint available as "Sharpening Occam's Razor on a Bayesian Strop").
  38. ^ James, Gareth; et al. (2013). An Introduction to Statistical Learning. springer. pp. 105, 203–204. ISBN 9781461471370.
  39. ^ Popper, Karl (1992) [1934]. Logik der Forschung [The Logic of Scientific Discovery] (2nd ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 121–132. ISBN 978-84-309-0711-3.
  40. ^ Sober, Elliott (1975). Simplicity. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824407-3.
  41. ^ Sober, Elliott (2004). "What is the Problem of Simplicity?". In Zellner, Arnold; Keuzenkamp, Hugo A.; McAleer, Michael (eds.). Simplicity, Inference and Modeling: Keeping it Sophisticatedly Simple. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. pp. 13–31. ISBN 978-0-521-80361-8. Retrieved 4 August 2012.
  42. ^ Swinburne, Richard (1997). Simplicity as Evidence for Truth. Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0-87462-164-8.
  43. ^ Einstein, Albert (1905). "Does the Inertia of a Body Depend Upon Its Energy Content?". Annalen der Physik (in German). 323 (18): 639–41. Bibcode:1905AnP...323..639E. doi:10.1002/andp.19053231314.
  44. ^ L. Nash, The Nature of the Natural Sciences, Boston: Little, Brown (1963).
  45. ^ de Maupertuis, P. L. M. (1744). Mémoires de l'Académie Royale (in French). p. 423.
  46. ^ de Broglie, L. (1925). Annales de Physique (in French). pp. 22–128.
  47. ^ RA Jackson, Mechanism: An Introduction to the Study of Organic Reactions, Clarendon, Oxford, 1972.
  48. ^ Carpenter, B. K. (1984). Determination of Organic Reaction Mechanism, New York: Wiley-Interscience.
  49. ^ Einstein, Albert (1934). "On the Method of Theoretical Physics". Philosophy of Science. 1 (2): 165 [163–169]. doi:10.1086/286316. ISSN 0031-8248. JSTOR 184387. S2CID 44787169.
  50. ^ Mettenheim, Christoph von (1998). Popper Versus Einstein: On the Philosophical Foundations of Physics. p. 34. ISBN 978-3-16-146910-7.
  51. ^ Geis, Gilbert; Geis, Professor Emeritus of Criminology Law and & Society Gilbert; Bienen, Leigh B. (1998). Crimes of the Century: From Leopold and Loeb to O.J. Simpson. UPNE. p. 39. ISBN 978-1-55553-360-1.
  52. ^ "Everything Should Be Made as Simple as Possible, But Not Simpler". from the original on 29 May 2012.
  53. ^ a b c Alan Baker (2010) [2004]. "Simplicity". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. California: Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054.
  54. ^ a b c d e Courtney, A.; Courtney, M. (2008). "Comments Regarding 'On the Nature of Science'". Physics in Canada. 64 (3): 7–8. arXiv:0812.4932. Bibcode:2008arXiv0812.4932C.
  55. ^ a b c Sober, Elliott (1994). "Let's Razor Occam's Razor". In Knowles, Dudley (ed.). Explanation and Its Limits. Cambridge University Press. pp. 73–93.
  56. ^ Rabinowitz, Matthew; Myers, Lance; Banjevic, Milena; Chan, Albert; Sweetkind-Singer, Joshua; Haberer, Jessica; McCann, Kelly; Wolkowicz, Roland (1 March 2006). "Accurate prediction of HIV-1 drug response from the reverse transcriptase and protease amino acid sequences using sparse models created by convex optimization". Bioinformatics. 22 (5): 541–549. doi:10.1093/bioinformatics/btk011. ISSN 1367-4803. PMID 16368772.
  57. ^ Paul Pojman (2009). "Ernst Mach". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. California: Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054.
  58. ^ Sober, Elliot (1998). Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference (2nd ed.). Massachusetts Institute of Technology: The MIT Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-262-69144-4.
  59. ^ Wiley, Edward O. (1981). Phylogenetics: the theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics. Wiley and Sons Interscience.
  60. ^ Brower, AVZ (2017). "Statistical consistency and phylogenetic inference: a brief review". Cladistics. 34 (5): 562–567. doi:10.1111/cla.12216. PMID 34649374.
  61. ^ Brower &, Schuh (2021). Biological Systematics: Principles and Applications (3rd edn.). Cornell University Press.
  62. ^ Crick 1988, p. 146.
  63. ^ "William Ockham". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford. Retrieved 24 February 2016.
  64. ^ Dale T Irvin & Scott W Sunquist. History of World Christian Movement Volume, I: Earliest Christianity to 1453, p. 434. ISBN 9781570753961.
  65. ^ "SUMMA THEOLOGICA: The existence of God (Prima Pars, Q. 2)". Newadvent.org. from the original on 28 April 2013. Retrieved 26 March 2013.
  66. ^ McDonald 2005.
  67. ^ p. 282, Mémoires du docteur F. Antommarchi, ou les derniers momens de Napoléon 14 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine, vol. 1, 1825, Paris: Barrois L'Ainé
  68. ^ Tonry, Michael (2005). (PDF). Columbia Law Review. 105: 1233–1275. Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 June 2006.
  69. ^ a b Chris S. Wallace and David M. Boulton; Computer Journal, Volume 11, Issue 2, 1968 Page(s):185–194, "An information measure for classification."
  70. ^ a b Chris S. Wallace and David L. Dowe; Computer Journal, Volume 42, Issue 4, Sep 1999 Page(s):270–283, "Minimum Message Length and Kolmogorov Complexity."
  71. ^ Nannen, Volker. "A short introduction to Model Selection, Kolmogorov Complexity and Minimum Description Length" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2 June 2010. Retrieved 3 July 2010.
  72. ^ "Algorithmic Information Theory". from the original on 24 December 2007.
  73. ^ Paul M. B. Vitányi and Ming Li; IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, Volume 46, Issue 2, Mar 2000 Page(s):446–464, "Minimum Description Length Induction, Bayesianism and Kolmogorov Complexity."
  74. ^ Standish, Russell K (2000). "Why Occam's Razor". Foundations of Physics Letters. 17 (3): 255–266. arXiv:physics/0001020. Bibcode:2004FoPhL..17..255S. doi:10.1023/B:FOPL.0000032475.18334.0e. S2CID 17143230.
  75. ^ Solomonoff, Ray (1964). "A formal theory of inductive inference. Part I." Information and Control. 7 (1–22): 1964. doi:10.1016/s0019-9958(64)90223-2.
  76. ^ Schmidhuber, J. (2006). "The New AI: General & Sound & Relevant for Physics". In Goertzel, B.; Pennachin, C. (eds.). Artificial General Intelligence. pp. 177–200. arXiv:cs.AI/0302012.
  77. ^ Dowe, David L. (2008). "Foreword re C. S. Wallace". Computer Journal. 51 (5): 523–560. doi:10.1093/comjnl/bxm117. S2CID 5387092.
  78. ^ David L. Dowe (2010): "MML, hybrid Bayesian network graphical models, statistical consistency, invariance and uniqueness. A formal theory of inductive inference." Handbook of the Philosophy of Science – (HPS Volume 7) Philosophy of Statistics, Elsevier 2010 Page(s):901–982.
  79. ^ Scott Needham and David L. Dowe (2001):" Message Length as an Effective Ockham's Razor in Decision Tree Induction." Proc. 8th International Workshop on Artificial Intelligence and Statistics (AI+STATS 2001), Key West, Florida, U.S.A., Jan. 2001 Page(s): 253–260 "2001 Ockham.pdf" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 23 September 2015. Retrieved 2 September 2015.
  80. ^ Berners-Lee, Tim (4 March 2013). "Principles of Design". World Wide Web Consortium.
  81. ^ a b Robert T. Carroll (12 September 2014). "Occam's Razor". The Skeptic's Dictionary. from the original on 1 March 2016. Retrieved 24 February 2016.
  82. ^ Quine, W V O (1961). "Two dogmas of empiricism". From a logical point of view. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 20–46. ISBN 978-0-674-32351-3.
  83. ^ Immanuel Kant (1929). Norman Kemp-Smith transl (ed.). The Critique of Pure Reason. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 92. from the original on 16 May 2012. Retrieved 27 October 2012. Entium varietates non-temere esse minuendas
  84. ^ Gordon Woo (20 June 2011). Calculating Catastrophe. World Scientific. pp. 303–. ISBN 978-1-84816-893-0.

Further reading

  • Ariew, Roger (1976). Ockham's Razor: A Historical and Philosophical Analysis of Ockham's Principle of Parsimony. Champaign-Urbana, University of Illinois.
  • Churchland, Paul M. (1984). Matter and Consciousness. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-53050-7.
  • Crick, Francis H. C. (1988). What Mad Pursuit: A Personal View of Scientific Discovery. New York, New York: Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-09137-9.
  • Dowe, David L.; Steve Gardner; Graham Oppy (December 2007). "Bayes not Bust! Why Simplicity is no Problem for Bayesians" (PDF). British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 58 (4): 709–754. doi:10.1093/bjps/axm033. S2CID 8863978. Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022.
  • Duda, Richard O.; Peter E. Hart; David G. Stork (2000). Pattern Classification (2nd ed.). Wiley-Interscience. pp. 487–489. ISBN 978-0-471-05669-0.
  • Epstein, Robert (1984). "The Principle of Parsimony and Some Applications in Psychology". Journal of Mind Behavior. 5: 119–130.
  • Hoffmann, Roald; Vladimir I. Minkin; Barry K. Carpenter (1997). "Ockham's Razor and Chemistry". Hyle. 3: 3–28. Retrieved 14 April 2006.
  • Jacquette, Dale (1994). Philosophy of Mind. Engleswoods Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. pp. 34–36. ISBN 978-0-13-030933-4.
  • Jaynes, Edwin Thompson (1994). "Model Comparison and Robustness". Probability Theory: The Logic of Science. ISBN 978-0-521-59271-0.
  • Jefferys, William H.; Berger, James O. (1991). "Ockham's Razor and Bayesian Statistics". American Scientist. 80: 64–72. (Preprint available as "Sharpening Occam's Razor on a Bayesian Strop").
  • Katz, Jerrold (1998). Realistic Rationalism. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-11229-1.
  • Kneale, William; Martha Kneale (1962). The Development of Logic. London: Oxford University Press. p. 243. ISBN 978-0-19-824183-6.
  • MacKay, David J. C. (2003). Information Theory, Inference and Learning Algorithms. Cambridge University Press. Bibcode:2003itil.book.....M. ISBN 978-0-521-64298-9. Retrieved 24 February 2016.
  • Maurer, A. (1984). "Ockham's Razor and Chatton's Anti-Razor". Mediaeval Studies. 46: 463–475. doi:10.1484/J.MS.2.306670.
  • McDonald, William (2005). "Søren Kierkegaard". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 April 2006.
  • Menger, Karl (1960). "A Counterpart of Ockham's Razor in Pure and Applied Mathematics: Ontological Uses". Synthese. 12 (4): 415–428. doi:10.1007/BF00485426. S2CID 46962297.
  • Morgan, C. Lloyd (1903). . An Introduction to Comparative Psychology (2nd ed.). London: W. Scott. p. 59. ISBN 978-0-89093-171-4. Archived from the original on 12 April 2005. Retrieved 15 April 2006.
  • Newton, Isaac (2011) [1726]. Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica (3rd ed.). London: Henry Pemberton. ISBN 978-1-60386-435-0.
  • Nolan, D. (1997). "Quantitative Parsimony". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 48 (3): 329–343. doi:10.1093/bjps/48.3.329. S2CID 229320568.
  • Basic Writings of St. Thomas Aquinas. Translated by Pegis, A. C. New York: Random House. 1945. p. 129. ISBN 978-0-87220-380-8.
  • Popper, Karl (1992) [First composed 1934 (Logik der Forschung)]. "7. Simplicity". The Logic of Scientific Discovery (2nd ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 121–132. ISBN 978-84-309-0711-3.
  • Rodríguez-Fernández, J. L. (1999). "Ockham's Razor". Endeavour. 23 (3): 121–125. doi:10.1016/S0160-9327(99)01199-0.
  • Schmitt, Gavin C. (2005). . Archived from the original on 11 February 2007. Retrieved 15 April 2006.
  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). "Sensations and Brain Processes". The Philosophical Review. 68 (2): 141–156. doi:10.2307/2182164. JSTOR 2182164.
  • Sober, Elliott (1975). Simplicity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Sober, Elliott (1981). (PDF). British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 32 (2): 145–156. doi:10.1093/bjps/32.2.145. S2CID 120916709. Archived from the original (PDF) on 15 December 2011. Retrieved 4 August 2012.
  • Sober, Elliott (1990). "Let's Razor Ockham's Razor". In Dudley Knowles (ed.). Explanation and its Limits. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 73–94.
  • Sober, Elliott (2002). Zellner; et al. (eds.). (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 November 2006. Retrieved 4 August 2012.
  • Sober, Elliott (2015). Ockham's Razors - A User's Manual. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-06849--0.
  • Swinburne, Richard (1997). Simplicity as Evidence for Truth. Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0-87462-164-8.
  • Thorburn, W. M. (1918). "The Myth of Occam's Razor". Mind. 27 (107): 345–353. doi:10.1093/mind/XXVII.3.345.
  • Williams, George C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A Critique of some Current Evolutionary Thought. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02615-2.

External links

  • Ockham's Razor, BBC Radio 4 discussion with Sir Anthony Kenny, Marilyn Adams & Richard Cross (In Our Time, 31 May 2007)

occam, razor, ockham, razor, redirects, here, aerial, theatre, company, ockham, razor, theatre, company, australian, radio, program, radio, national, also, spelled, ockham, razor, ocham, razor, latin, novacula, occami, philosophy, problem, solving, principle, . Ockham s razor redirects here For the aerial theatre company see Ockham s Razor Theatre Company For the Australian radio program see Radio National Occam s razor also spelled Ockham s razor or Ocham s razor Latin novacula Occami in philosophy is the problem solving principle that recommends searching for explanations constructed with the smallest possible set of elements It is also known as the principle of parsimony or the law of parsimony Latin lex parsimoniae Attributed to William of Ockham a 14th century English philosopher and theologian it is frequently cited as Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem which translates as Entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity 1 2 although Occam never used these exact words Popularly the principle is sometimes inaccurately 3 paraphrased as The simplest explanation is usually the best one 4 This philosophical razor advocates that when presented with competing hypotheses about the same prediction one should prefer the one that requires the fewest assumptions 3 and that this is not meant to be a way of choosing between hypotheses that make different predictions Similarly in science Occam s razor is used as an abductive heuristic in the development of theoretical models rather than as a rigorous arbiter between candidate models 5 6 Contents 1 History 1 1 Formulations before William of Ockham 1 2 William of Ockham 1 3 Later formulations 2 Justifications 2 1 Aesthetic 2 2 Empirical 2 2 1 Testing the razor 2 3 Practical considerations and pragmatism 2 4 Mathematical 2 5 Other philosophers 2 5 1 Karl Popper 2 5 2 Elliott Sober 2 5 3 Richard Swinburne 2 5 4 Ludwig Wittgenstein 3 Uses 3 1 Science and the scientific method 3 2 Biology 3 3 Religion 3 4 Philosophy of mind 3 5 Penal ethics 3 6 Probability theory and statistics 3 6 1 Objective razor 3 7 Software development 4 Controversial aspects 5 Anti razors 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External linksHistory EditThe phrase Occam s razor did not appear until a few centuries after William of Ockham s death in 1347 Libert Froidmont in his On Christian Philosophy of the Soul gives him credit for the phrase speaking of novacula occami 7 Ockham did not invent this principle but its fame and its association with him may be due to the frequency and effectiveness with which he used it 8 Ockham stated the principle in various ways but the most popular version Entities are not to be multiplied without necessity Non sunt multiplicanda entia sine necessitate was formulated by the Irish Franciscan philosopher John Punch in his 1639 commentary on the works of Duns Scotus 9 Formulations before William of Ockham Edit Part of a page from John Duns Scotus s book Commentaria oxoniensia ad IV libros magistri Sententiarus showing the words Pluralitas non est ponenda sine necessitate i e Plurality is not to be posited without necessity The origins of what has come to be known as Occam s razor are traceable to the works of earlier philosophers such as John Duns Scotus 1265 1308 Robert Grosseteste 1175 1253 Maimonides Moses ben Maimon 1138 1204 and even Aristotle 384 322 BC 10 11 Aristotle writes in his Posterior Analytics We may assume the superiority ceteris paribus other things being equal of the demonstration which derives from fewer postulates or hypotheses Ptolemy c AD 90 c 168 stated We consider it a good principle to explain the phenomena by the simplest hypothesis possible 12 Phrases such as It is vain to do with more what can be done with fewer and A plurality is not to be posited without necessity were commonplace in 13th century scholastic writing 12 Robert Grosseteste in Commentary on Aristotle s the Posterior Analytics Books Commentarius in Posteriorum Analyticorum Libros c 1217 1220 declares That is better and more valuable which requires fewer other circumstances being equal For if one thing were demonstrated from many and another thing from fewer equally known premises clearly that is better which is from fewer because it makes us know quickly just as a universal demonstration is better than particular because it produces knowledge from fewer premises Similarly in natural science in moral science and in metaphysics the best is that which needs no premises and the better that which needs the fewer other circumstances being equal 13 The Summa Theologica of Thomas Aquinas 1225 1274 states that it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many Aquinas uses this principle to construct an objection to God s existence an objection that he in turn answers and refutes generally cf quinque viae and specifically through an argument based on causality 14 Hence Aquinas acknowledges the principle that today is known as Occam s razor but prefers causal explanations to other simple explanations cf also Correlation does not imply causation William of Ockham Edit Manuscript illustration of William of Ockham William of Ockham circa 1287 1347 was an English Franciscan friar and theologian an influential medieval philosopher and a nominalist His popular fame as a great logician rests chiefly on the maxim attributed to him and known as Occam s razor The term razor refers to distinguishing between two hypotheses either by shaving away unnecessary assumptions or cutting apart two similar conclusions While it has been claimed that Occam s razor is not found in any of William s writings 15 one can cite statements such as Numquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necessitate Plurality must never be posited without necessity which occurs in his theological work on the Sentences of Peter Lombard Quaestiones et decisiones in quattuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi ed Lugd 1495 i dist 27 qu 2 K Nevertheless the precise words sometimes attributed to William of Ockham Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem Entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity 16 are absent in his extant works 17 this particular phrasing comes from John Punch 18 who described the principle as a common axiom axioma vulgare of the Scholastics 9 William of Ockham himself seems to restrict the operation of this principle in matters pertaining to miracles and God s power considering a plurality of miracles possible in the Eucharist further explanation needed simply because it pleases God 12 This principle is sometimes phrased as Pluralitas non est ponenda sine necessitate Plurality should not be posited without necessity 19 In his Summa Totius Logicae i 12 William of Ockham cites the principle of economy Frustra fit per plura quod potest fieri per pauciora It is futile to do with more things that which can be done with fewer Thorburn 1918 pp 352 53 Kneale and Kneale 1962 p 243 Later formulations Edit To quote Isaac Newton We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances Therefore to the same natural effects we must as far as possible assign the same causes 20 21 In the sentence hypotheses non fingo Newton affirms the success of this approach Bertrand Russell offers a particular version of Occam s razor Whenever possible substitute constructions out of known entities for inferences to unknown entities 22 Around 1960 Ray Solomonoff founded the theory of universal inductive inference the theory of prediction based on observations for example predicting the next symbol based upon a given series of symbols The only assumption is that the environment follows some unknown but computable probability distribution This theory is a mathematical formalization of Occam s razor 23 24 25 Another technical approach to Occam s razor is ontological parsimony 26 Parsimony means spareness and is also referred to as the Rule of Simplicity This is considered a strong version of Occam s razor 27 28 A variation used in medicine is called the Zebra a physician should reject an exotic medical diagnosis when a more commonplace explanation is more likely derived from Theodore Woodward s dictum When you hear hoofbeats think of horses not zebras 29 Ernst Mach formulated the stronger version of Occam s razor into physics which he called the Principle of Economy stating Scientists must use the simplest means of arriving at their results and exclude everything not perceived by the senses 30 This principle goes back at least as far as Aristotle who wrote Nature operates in the shortest way possible 27 The idea of parsimony or simplicity in deciding between theories though not the intent of the original expression of Occam s razor has been assimilated into common culture as the widespread layman s formulation that the simplest explanation is usually the correct one 27 Justifications EditAesthetic Edit Prior to the 20th century it was a commonly held belief that nature itself was simple and that simpler hypotheses about nature were thus more likely to be true This notion was deeply rooted in the aesthetic value that simplicity holds for human thought and the justifications presented for it often drew from theology clarification needed Thomas Aquinas made this argument in the 13th century writing If a thing can be done adequately by means of one it is superfluous to do it by means of several for we observe that nature does not employ two instruments if one suffices 31 Beginning in the 20th century epistemological justifications based on induction logic pragmatism and especially probability theory have become more popular among philosophers 7 Empirical Edit Occam s razor has gained strong empirical support in helping to converge on better theories see Uses section below for some examples In the related concept of overfitting excessively complex models are affected by statistical noise a problem also known as the bias variance trade off whereas simpler models may capture the underlying structure better and may thus have better predictive performance It is however often difficult to deduce which part of the data is noise cf model selection test set minimum description length Bayesian inference etc Testing the razor Edit This section possibly contains original research Author of this section cites very few reliable sources and also consistently conflates simplicity with logical truth Occam s razor is not built to differentiate true hypotheses from false ones Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed January 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message The razor s statement that other things being equal simpler explanations are generally better than more complex ones is amenable to empirical testing Another interpretation of the razor s statement would be that simpler hypotheses are generally better than the complex ones The procedure to test the former interpretation would compare the track records of simple and comparatively complex explanations If one accepts the first interpretation the validity of Occam s razor as a tool would then have to be rejected if the more complex explanations were more often correct than the less complex ones while the converse would lend support to its use If the latter interpretation is accepted the validity of Occam s razor as a tool could possibly be accepted if the simpler hypotheses led to correct conclusions more often than not Possible explanations can become needlessly complex It might be coherent for instance to add the involvement of leprechauns to any explanation but Occam s razor would prevent such additions unless they were necessary Even if some increases in complexity are sometimes necessary there still remains a justified general bias toward the simpler of two competing explanations To understand why consider that for each accepted explanation of a phenomenon there is always an infinite number of possible more complex and ultimately incorrect alternatives This is so because one can always burden a failing explanation with an ad hoc hypothesis Ad hoc hypotheses are justifications that prevent theories from being falsified For example if a man accused of breaking a vase makes supernatural claims that leprechauns were responsible for the breakage a simple explanation might be that the man did it but ongoing ad hoc justifications e g and that s not me breaking it on the film they tampered with that too could successfully prevent complete disproof This endless supply of elaborate competing explanations called saving hypotheses cannot be technically ruled out except by using Occam s razor 32 33 34 Any more complex theory might still possibly be true A study of the predictive validity of Occam s razor found 32 published papers that included 97 comparisons of economic forecasts from simple and complex forecasting methods None of the papers provided a balance of evidence that complexity of method improved forecast accuracy In the 25 papers with quantitative comparisons complexity increased forecast errors by an average of 27 percent 35 Practical considerations and pragmatism Edit See also Pragmatism and Problem of induction Mathematical Edit Main article Akaike information criterion One justification of Occam s razor is a direct result of basic probability theory By definition all assumptions introduce possibilities for error if an assumption does not improve the accuracy of a theory its only effect is to increase the probability that the overall theory is wrong There have also been other attempts to derive Occam s razor from probability theory including notable attempts made by Harold Jeffreys and E T Jaynes The probabilistic Bayesian basis for Occam s razor is elaborated by David J C MacKay in chapter 28 of his book Information Theory Inference and Learning Algorithms 36 where he emphasizes that a prior bias in favor of simpler models is not required William H Jefferys and James O Berger 1991 generalize and quantify the original formulation s assumptions concept as the degree to which a proposition is unnecessarily accommodating to possible observable data 37 They state A hypothesis with fewer adjustable parameters will automatically have an enhanced posterior probability due to the fact that the predictions it makes are sharp 37 The use of sharp here is not only a tongue in cheek reference to the idea of a razor but also indicates that such predictions are more accurate than competing predictions The model they propose balances the precision of a theory s predictions against their sharpness preferring theories that sharply make correct predictions over theories that accommodate a wide range of other possible results This again reflects the mathematical relationship between key concepts in Bayesian inference namely marginal probability conditional probability and posterior probability The bias variance tradeoff is a framework that incorporates the Occam s razor principle in its balance between overfitting associated with lower bias but higher variance and underfitting associated with lower variance but higher bias 38 Other philosophers Edit Karl Popper Edit Karl Popper argues that a preference for simple theories need not appeal to practical or aesthetic considerations Our preference for simplicity may be justified by its falsifiability criterion we prefer simpler theories to more complex ones because their empirical content is greater and because they are better testable 39 The idea here is that a simple theory applies to more cases than a more complex one and is thus more easily falsifiable This is again comparing a simple theory to a more complex theory where both explain the data equally well Elliott Sober Edit The philosopher of science Elliott Sober once argued along the same lines as Popper tying simplicity with informativeness The simplest theory is the more informative in the sense that it requires less information to a question 40 He has since rejected this account of simplicity purportedly because it fails to provide an epistemic justification for simplicity He now believes that simplicity considerations and considerations of parsimony in particular do not count unless they reflect something more fundamental Philosophers he suggests may have made the error of hypostatizing simplicity i e endowed it with a sui generis existence when it has meaning only when embedded in a specific context Sober 1992 If we fail to justify simplicity considerations on the basis of the context in which we use them we may have no non circular justification Just as the question why be rational may have no non circular answer the same may be true of the question why should simplicity be considered in evaluating the plausibility of hypotheses 41 Richard Swinburne Edit Richard Swinburne argues for simplicity on logical grounds the simplest hypothesis proposed as an explanation of phenomena is more likely to be the true one than is any other available hypothesis that its predictions are more likely to be true than those of any other available hypothesis and that it is an ultimate a priori epistemic principle that simplicity is evidence for truth Swinburne 1997 According to Swinburne since our choice of theory cannot be determined by data see Underdetermination and Duhem Quine thesis we must rely on some criterion to determine which theory to use Since it is absurd to have no logical method for settling on one hypothesis amongst an infinite number of equally data compliant hypotheses we should choose the simplest theory Either science is irrational in the way it judges theories and predictions probable or the principle of simplicity is a fundamental synthetic a priori truth 42 Ludwig Wittgenstein Edit From the Tractatus Logico Philosophicus 3 328 If a sign is not necessary then it is meaningless That is the meaning of Occam s Razor If everything in the symbolism works as though a sign had meaning then it has meaning 4 04 In the proposition there must be exactly as many things distinguishable as there are in the state of affairs which it represents They must both possess the same logical mathematical multiplicity cf Hertz s Mechanics on Dynamic Models 5 47321 Occam s Razor is of course not an arbitrary rule nor one justified by its practical success It simply says that unnecessary elements in a symbolism mean nothing Signs which serve one purpose are logically equivalent signs which serve no purpose are logically meaningless and on the related concept of simplicity 6 363 The procedure of induction consists in accepting as true the simplest law that can be reconciled with our experiences Uses EditThis section possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed May 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Science and the scientific method Edit Andreas Cellarius s illustration of the Copernican system from the Harmonia Macrocosmica 1660 Future positions of the sun moon and other solar system bodies can be calculated using a geocentric model the earth is at the centre or using a heliocentric model the sun is at the centre Both work but the geocentric model arrives at the same conclusions through a much more complex system of calculations than the heliocentric model This was pointed out in a preface to Copernicus first edition of De revolutionibus orbium coelestium In science Occam s razor is used as a heuristic to guide scientists in developing theoretical models rather than as an arbiter between published models 5 6 In physics parsimony was an important heuristic in Albert Einstein s formulation of special relativity 43 44 in the development and application of the principle of least action by Pierre Louis Maupertuis and Leonhard Euler 45 and in the development of quantum mechanics by Max Planck Werner Heisenberg and Louis de Broglie 6 46 In chemistry Occam s razor is often an important heuristic when developing a model of a reaction mechanism 47 48 Although it is useful as a heuristic in developing models of reaction mechanisms it has been shown to fail as a criterion for selecting among some selected published models 6 In this context Einstein himself expressed caution when he formulated Einstein s Constraint It can scarcely be denied that the supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience 49 50 51 An often quoted version of this constraint which cannot be verified as posited by Einstein himself 52 reduces this to Everything should be kept as simple as possible but not simpler In the scientific method Occam s razor is not considered an irrefutable principle of logic or a scientific result the preference for simplicity in the scientific method is based on the falsifiability criterion For each accepted explanation of a phenomenon there may be an extremely large perhaps even incomprehensible number of possible and more complex alternatives Since failing explanations can always be burdened with ad hoc hypotheses to prevent them from being falsified simpler theories are preferable to more complex ones because they tend to be more testable 53 54 55 As a logical principle Occam s razor would demand that scientists accept the simplest possible theoretical explanation for existing data However science has shown repeatedly that future data often support more complex theories than do existing data Science prefers the simplest explanation that is consistent with the data available at a given time but the simplest explanation may be ruled out as new data become available 5 54 That is science is open to the possibility that future experiments might support more complex theories than demanded by current data and is more interested in designing experiments to discriminate between competing theories than favoring one theory over another based merely on philosophical principles 53 54 55 When scientists use the idea of parsimony it has meaning only in a very specific context of inquiry Several background assumptions are required for parsimony to connect with plausibility in a particular research problem clarification needed The reasonableness of parsimony in one research context may have nothing to do with its reasonableness in another It is a mistake to think that there is a single global principle that spans diverse subject matter 55 It has been suggested that Occam s razor is a widely accepted example of extraevidential consideration even though it is entirely a metaphysical assumption Most of the time however Occam s razor is a conservative tool cutting out crazy complicated constructions and assuring that hypotheses are grounded in the science of the day thus yielding normal science models of explanation and prediction 6 There are however notable exceptions where Occam s razor turns a conservative scientist into a reluctant revolutionary For example Max Planck interpolated between the Wien and Jeans radiation laws and used Occam s razor logic to formulate the quantum hypothesis even resisting that hypothesis as it became more obvious that it was correct 6 Appeals to simplicity were used to argue against the phenomena of meteorites ball lightning continental drift and reverse transcriptase 56 One can argue for atomic building blocks for matter because it provides a simpler explanation for the observed reversibility of both mixing clarification needed and chemical reactions as simple separation and rearrangements of atomic building blocks At the time however the atomic theory was considered more complex because it implied the existence of invisible particles that had not been directly detected Ernst Mach and the logical positivists rejected John Dalton s atomic theory until the reality of atoms was more evident in Brownian motion as shown by Albert Einstein 57 In the same way postulating the aether is more complex than transmission of light through a vacuum At the time however all known waves propagated through a physical medium and it seemed simpler to postulate the existence of a medium than to theorize about wave propagation without a medium Likewise Isaac Newton s idea of light particles seemed simpler than Christiaan Huygens s idea of waves so many favored it In this case as it turned out neither the wave nor the particle explanation alone suffices as light behaves like waves and like particles Three axioms presupposed by the scientific method are realism the existence of objective reality the existence of natural laws and the constancy of natural law Rather than depend on provability of these axioms science depends on the fact that they have not been objectively falsified Occam s razor and parsimony support but do not prove these axioms of science The general principle of science is that theories or models of natural law must be consistent with repeatable experimental observations This ultimate arbiter selection criterion rests upon the axioms mentioned above 54 If multiple models of natural law make exactly the same testable predictions they are equivalent and there is no need for parsimony to choose a preferred one For example Newtonian Hamiltonian and Lagrangian classical mechanics are equivalent Physicists have no interest in using Occam s razor to say the other two are wrong Likewise there is no demand for simplicity principles to arbitrate between wave and matrix formulations of quantum mechanics Science often does not demand arbitration or selection criteria between models that make the same testable predictions 54 Biology Edit This section has an unclear citation style The references used may be made clearer with a different or consistent style of citation and footnoting January 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Biologists or philosophers of biology use Occam s razor in either of two contexts both in evolutionary biology the units of selection controversy and systematics George C Williams in his book Adaptation and Natural Selection 1966 argues that the best way to explain altruism among animals is based on low level i e individual selection as opposed to high level group selection Altruism is defined by some evolutionary biologists e g R Alexander 1987 W D Hamilton 1964 as behavior that is beneficial to others or to the group at a cost to the individual and many posit individual selection as the mechanism that explains altruism solely in terms of the behaviors of individual organisms acting in their own self interest or in the interest of their genes via kin selection Williams was arguing against the perspective of others who propose selection at the level of the group as an evolutionary mechanism that selects for altruistic traits e g D S Wilson amp E O Wilson 2007 The basis for Williams contention is that of the two individual selection is the more parsimonious theory In doing so he is invoking a variant of Occam s razor known as Morgan s Canon In no case is an animal activity to be interpreted in terms of higher psychological processes if it can be fairly interpreted in terms of processes which stand lower in the scale of psychological evolution and development Morgan 1903 However more recent biological analyses such as Richard Dawkins The Selfish Gene have contended that Morgan s Canon is not the simplest and most basic explanation Dawkins argues the way evolution works is that the genes propagated in most copies end up determining the development of that particular species i e natural selection turns out to select specific genes and this is really the fundamental underlying principle that automatically gives individual and group selection as emergent features of evolution Zoology provides an example Muskoxen when threatened by wolves form a circle with the males on the outside and the females and young on the inside This is an example of a behavior by the males that seems to be altruistic The behavior is disadvantageous to them individually but beneficial to the group as a whole and was thus seen by some to support the group selection theory Another interpretation is kin selection if the males are protecting their offspring they are protecting copies of their own alleles Engaging in this behavior would be favored by individual selection if the cost to the male musk ox is less than half of the benefit received by his calf which could easily be the case if wolves have an easier time killing calves than adult males It could also be the case that male musk oxen would be individually less likely to be killed by wolves if they stood in a circle with their horns pointing out regardless of whether they were protecting the females and offspring That would be an example of regular natural selection a phenomenon called the selfish herd Systematics is the branch of biology that attempts to establish patterns of relationship among biological taxa today generally thought to reflect evolutionary history It is also concerned with their classification There are three primary camps in systematics cladists pheneticists and evolutionary taxonomists Cladists hold that classification should be based on synapomorphies shared derived character states pheneticists contend that overall similarity synapomorphies and complementary symplesiomorphies is the determining criterion while evolutionary taxonomists say that both genealogy and similarity count in classification in a manner determined by the evolutionary taxonomist 58 59 It is among the cladists that Occam s razor is applied through the method of cladistic parsimony Cladistic parsimony or maximum parsimony is a method of phylogenetic inference that yields phylogenetic trees more specifically cladograms Cladograms are branching diagrams used to represent hypotheses of relative degree of relationship based on synapomorphies Cladistic parsimony is used to select as the preferred hypothesis of relationships the cladogram that requires the fewest implied character state transformations or smallest weight if characters are differentially weighted Critics of the cladistic approach often observe that for some types of data parsimony could produce the wrong results regardless of how much data is collected this is called statistical inconsistency or long branch attraction However this criticism is also potentially true for any type of phylogenetic inference unless the model used to estimate the tree reflects the way that evolution actually happened Because this information is not empirically accessible the criticism of statistical inconsistency against parsimony holds no force 60 For a book length treatment of cladistic parsimony see Elliott Sober s Reconstructing the Past Parsimony Evolution and Inference 1988 For a discussion of both uses of Occam s razor in biology see Sober s article Let s Razor Ockham s Razor 1990 Other methods for inferring evolutionary relationships use parsimony in a more general way Likelihood methods for phylogeny use parsimony as they do for all likelihood tests with hypotheses requiring fewer differing parameters i e numbers or different rates of character change or different frequencies of character state transitions being treated as null hypotheses relative to hypotheses requiring more differing parameters Thus complex hypotheses must predict data much better than do simple hypotheses before researchers reject the simple hypotheses Recent advances employ information theory a close cousin of likelihood which uses Occam s razor in the same way Of course the choice of the shortest tree relative to a not so short tree under any optimality criterion smallest distance fewest steps or maximum likelihood is always based on parsimony 61 Francis Crick has commented on potential limitations of Occam s razor in biology He advances the argument that because biological systems are the products of an ongoing natural selection the mechanisms are not necessarily optimal in an obvious sense He cautions While Ockham s razor is a useful tool in the physical sciences it can be a very dangerous implement in biology It is thus very rash to use simplicity and elegance as a guide in biological research 62 This is an ontological critique of parsimony In biogeography parsimony is used to infer ancient vicariant events or migrations of species or populations by observing the geographic distribution and relationships of existing organisms Given the phylogenetic tree ancestral population subdivisions are inferred to be those that require the minimum amount of change Religion Edit Main article Existence of God In the philosophy of religion Occam s razor is sometimes applied to the existence of God William of Ockham himself was a Christian He believed in God and in the authority of Scripture he writes that nothing ought to be posited without a reason given unless it is self evident literally known through itself or known by experience or proved by the authority of Sacred Scripture 63 Ockham believed that an explanation has no sufficient basis in reality when it does not harmonize with reason experience or the Bible However unlike many theologians of his time Ockham did not believe God could be logically proven with arguments To Ockham science was a matter of discovery but theology was a matter of revelation and faith He states only faith gives us access to theological truths The ways of God are not open to reason for God has freely chosen to create a world and establish a way of salvation within it apart from any necessary laws that human logic or rationality can uncover 64 Thomas Aquinas in the Summa Theologica uses a formulation of Occam s razor to construct an objection to the idea that God exists which he refutes directly with a counterargument 65 Further it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many But it seems that everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other principles supposing God did not exist For all natural things can be reduced to one principle which is nature and all voluntary things can be reduced to one principle which is human reason or will Therefore there is no need to suppose God s existence In turn Aquinas answers this with the quinque viae and addresses the particular objection above with the following answer Since nature works for a determinate end under the direction of a higher agent whatever is done by nature must needs be traced back to God as to its first cause So also whatever is done voluntarily must also be traced back to some higher cause other than human reason or will since these can change or fail for all things that are changeable and capable of defect must be traced back to an immovable and self necessary first principle as was shown in the body of the Article Rather than argue for the necessity of a god some theists base their belief upon grounds independent of or prior to reason making Occam s razor irrelevant This was the stance of Soren Kierkegaard who viewed belief in God as a leap of faith that sometimes directly opposed reason 66 This is also the doctrine of Gordon Clark s presuppositional apologetics with the exception that Clark never thought the leap of faith was contrary to reason see also Fideism Various arguments in favor of God establish God as a useful or even necessary assumption Contrastingly some anti theists hold firmly to the belief that assuming the existence of God introduces unnecessary complexity Schmitt 2005 e g the Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit Another application of the principle is to be found in the work of George Berkeley 1685 1753 Berkeley was an idealist who believed that all of reality could be explained in terms of the mind alone He invoked Occam s razor against materialism stating that matter was not required by his metaphysics and was thus eliminable One potential problem with this belief for whom is that it s possible given Berkeley s position to find solipsism itself more in line with the razor than a God mediated world beyond a single thinker Occam s razor may also be recognized in the apocryphal story about an exchange between Pierre Simon Laplace and Napoleon It is said that in praising Laplace for one of his recent publications the emperor asked how it was that the name of God which featured so frequently in the writings of Lagrange appeared nowhere in Laplace s At that he is said to have replied It s because I had no need of that hypothesis 67 Though some points of this story illustrate Laplace s atheism more careful consideration suggests that he may instead have intended merely to illustrate the power of methodological naturalism or even simply that the fewer logical premises one assumes the stronger is one s conclusion Philosophy of mind Edit In his article Sensations and Brain Processes 1959 J J C Smart invoked Occam s razor with the aim to justify his preference of the mind brain identity theory over spirit body dualism Dualists state that there are two kinds of substances in the universe physical including the body and spiritual which is non physical In contrast identity theorists state that everything is physical including consciousness and that there is nothing nonphysical Though it is impossible to appreciate the spiritual when limiting oneself to the physical citation needed Smart maintained that identity theory explains all phenomena by assuming only a physical reality Subsequently Smart has been severely criticized for his use or misuse of Occam s razor and ultimately retracted his advocacy of it in this context Paul Churchland 1984 states that by itself Occam s razor is inconclusive regarding duality In a similar way Dale Jacquette 1994 stated that Occam s razor has been used in attempts to justify eliminativism and reductionism in the philosophy of mind Eliminativism is the thesis that the ontology of folk psychology including such entities as pain joy desire fear etc are eliminable in favor of an ontology of a completed neuroscience Penal ethics Edit In penal theory and the philosophy of punishment parsimony refers specifically to taking care in the distribution of punishment in order to avoid excessive punishment In the utilitarian approach to the philosophy of punishment Jeremy Bentham s parsimony principle states that any punishment greater than is required to achieve its end is unjust The concept is related but not identical to the legal concept of proportionality Parsimony is a key consideration of the modern restorative justice and is a component of utilitarian approaches to punishment as well as the prison abolition movement Bentham believed that true parsimony would require punishment to be individualised to take account of the sensibility of the individual an individual more sensitive to punishment should be given a proportionately lesser one since otherwise needless pain would be inflicted Later utilitarian writers have tended to abandon this idea in large part due to the impracticality of determining each alleged criminal s relative sensitivity to specific punishments 68 Probability theory and statistics Edit Marcus Hutter s universal artificial intelligence builds upon Solomonoff s mathematical formalization of the razor to calculate the expected value of an action There are various papers in scholarly journals deriving formal versions of Occam s razor from probability theory applying it in statistical inference and using it to come up with criteria for penalizing complexity in statistical inference Papers 69 70 have suggested a connection between Occam s razor and Kolmogorov complexity 71 One of the problems with the original formulation of the razor is that it only applies to models with the same explanatory power i e it only tells us to prefer the simplest of equally good models A more general form of the razor can be derived from Bayesian model comparison which is based on Bayes factors and can be used to compare models that don t fit the observations equally well These methods can sometimes optimally balance the complexity and power of a model Generally the exact Occam factor is intractable but approximations such as Akaike information criterion Bayesian information criterion Variational Bayesian methods false discovery rate and Laplace s method are used Many artificial intelligence researchers are now employing such techniques for instance through work on Occam Learning or more generally on the Free energy principle Statistical versions of Occam s razor have a more rigorous formulation than what philosophical discussions produce In particular they must have a specific definition of the term simplicity and that definition can vary For example in the Kolmogorov Chaitin minimum description length approach the subject must pick a Turing machine whose operations describe the basic operations believed to represent simplicity by the subject However one could always choose a Turing machine with a simple operation that happened to construct one s entire theory and would hence score highly under the razor This has led to two opposing camps one that believes Occam s razor is objective and one that believes it is subjective Objective razor Edit The minimum instruction set of a universal Turing machine requires approximately the same length description across different formulations and is small compared to the Kolmogorov complexity of most practical theories Marcus Hutter has used this consistency to define a natural Turing machine of small size as the proper basis for excluding arbitrarily complex instruction sets in the formulation of razors 72 Describing the program for the universal program as the hypothesis and the representation of the evidence as program data it has been formally proven under Zermelo Fraenkel set theory that the sum of the log universal probability of the model plus the log of the probability of the data given the model should be minimized 73 Interpreting this as minimising the total length of a two part message encoding model followed by data given model gives us the minimum message length MML principle 69 70 One possible conclusion from mixing the concepts of Kolmogorov complexity and Occam s razor is that an ideal data compressor would also be a scientific explanation formulation generator Some attempts have been made to re derive known laws from considerations of simplicity or compressibility 24 74 According to Jurgen Schmidhuber the appropriate mathematical theory of Occam s razor already exists namely Solomonoff s theory of optimal inductive inference 75 and its extensions 76 See discussions in David L Dowe s Foreword re C S Wallace 77 for the subtle distinctions between the algorithmic probability work of Solomonoff and the MML work of Chris Wallace and see Dowe s MML hybrid Bayesian network graphical models statistical consistency invariance and uniqueness 78 both for such discussions and for in section 4 discussions of MML and Occam s razor For a specific example of MML as Occam s razor in the problem of decision tree induction see Dowe and Needham s Message Length as an Effective Ockham s Razor in Decision Tree Induction 79 Software development Edit In software development the rule of least power argues the correct programming language to use is the one that is simplest while also solving the targeted software problem In that form the rule is often credited to Tim Berners Lee since it appeared in his design guidelines for the original Hypertext Transfer Protocol 80 Complexity in this context is measured either by placing a language into the Chomsky hierarchy or by listing idiomatic features of the language and comparing according to some agreed to scale of difficulties between idioms Many languages once thought to be of lower complexity have evolved or later been discovered to be more complex than originally intended so in practice this rule is applied to the relative ease of a programmer to obtain the power of the language rather than the precise theoretical limits of the language Controversial aspects EditOccam s razor is not an embargo against the positing of any kind of entity or a recommendation of the simplest theory come what may a Occam s razor is used to adjudicate between theories that have already passed theoretical scrutiny tests and are equally well supported by evidence b Furthermore it may be used to prioritize empirical testing between two equally plausible but unequally testable hypotheses thereby minimizing costs and wastes while increasing chances of falsification of the simpler to test hypothesis citation needed Another contentious aspect of the razor is that a theory can become more complex in terms of its structure or syntax while its ontology or semantics becomes simpler or vice versa c Quine in a discussion on definition referred to these two perspectives as economy of practical expression and economy in grammar and vocabulary respectively 82 Galileo Galilei lampooned the misuse of Occam s razor in his Dialogue The principle is represented in the dialogue by Simplicio The telling point that Galileo presented ironically was that if one really wanted to start from a small number of entities one could always consider the letters of the alphabet as the fundamental entities since one could construct the whole of human knowledge out of them Anti razors EditOccam s razor has met some opposition from people who consider it too extreme or rash Walter Chatton c 1290 1343 was a contemporary of William of Ockham who took exception to Occam s razor and Ockham s use of it In response he devised his own anti razor If three things are not enough to verify an affirmative proposition about things a fourth must be added and so on Although there have been several philosophers who have formulated similar anti razors since Chatton s time no one anti razor has perpetuated in as much notability as Chatton s anti razor although this could be the case of the Late Renaissance Italian motto of unknown attribution Se non e vero e ben trovato Even if it is not true it is well conceived when referred to a particularly artful explanation Anti razors have also been created by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 1646 1716 Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 and Karl Menger 1902 1985 Leibniz s version took the form of a principle of plenitude as Arthur Lovejoy has called it the idea being that God created the most varied and populous of possible worlds Kant felt a need to moderate the effects of Occam s razor and thus created his own counter razor The variety of beings should not rashly be diminished 83 Karl Menger found mathematicians to be too parsimonious with regard to variables so he formulated his Law Against Miserliness which took one of two forms Entities must not be reduced to the point of inadequacy and It is vain to do with fewer what requires more A less serious but even more extremist anti razor is Pataphysics the science of imaginary solutions developed by Alfred Jarry 1873 1907 Perhaps the ultimate in anti reductionism Pataphysics seeks no less than to view each event in the universe as completely unique subject to no laws but its own Variations on this theme were subsequently explored by the Argentine writer Jorge Luis Borges in his story mock essay Tlon Uqbar Orbis Tertius Physicist R V Jones contrived Crabtree s Bludgeon which states that n o set of mutually inconsistent observations can exist for which some human intellect cannot conceive a coherent explanation however complicated 84 See also Edit Philosophy portal Psychology portal Science portalChekhov s gun Dramatic principle that every element in a story must be necessary Duck test Classification based on observable evidence Explanatory power Ability of a theory to explain a subject Hanlon s razor Adage to assume stupidity over malice Hickam s dictum Medical principle that a patient s symptoms could be caused by several diseases Hitchens s razor Epistemological razor KISS principle Design principle preferring simplicity Minimum description length Model selection principle Minimum message length Formal information theory restatement of Occam s Razor Newton s flaming laser sword Australian mathematician and philosopherPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets Philosophical razor Principle that allows one to eliminate unlikely explanations Philosophy of science Study of foundations methods and implications of science Simplicity State of being simpleNotes Edit Ockham s razor does not say that the more simple a hypothesis the better 81 Today we think of the principle of parsimony as a heuristic device We don t assume that the simpler theory is correct and the more complex one false We know from experience that more often than not the theory that requires more complicated machinations is wrong Until proved otherwise the more complex theory competing with a simpler explanation should be put on the back burner but not thrown onto the trash heap of history until proven false 81 While these two facets of simplicity are frequently conflated it is important to treat them as distinct One reason for doing so is that considerations of parsimony and of elegance typically pull in different directions Postulating extra entities may allow a theory to be formulated more simply while reducing the ontology of a theory may only be possible at the price of making it syntactically more complex 53 References Edit Barry C M 27 May 2014 Who sharpened Occam s Razor Irish Philosophy Schaffer Jonathan 2015 What Not to Multiply Without Necessity PDF Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 4 644 664 doi 10 1080 00048402 2014 992447 S2CID 16923735 a b Ball Philip 11 August 2016 The Tyranny of Simple Explanations The Atlantic Retrieved 2 February 2023 Duignan Brian Occam s Razor Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 11 May 2021 a b c Hugh G Gauch Scientific Method in Practice Cambridge University Press 2003 ISBN 0 521 01708 4 ISBN 978 0 521 01708 4 a b c d e f Hoffman Roald Minkin Vladimir I Carpenter Barry K 1997 Ockham s Razor and Chemistry International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry 3 3 28 a b Sober Elliott 2015 Ockam s Razor A User s Manual Cambridge University Press p 4 ISBN 978 1107692534 Roger Ariew Ockham s Razor A Historical and Philosophical Analysis of Ockham s Principle of Parsimony 1976 a b Johannes Poncius s commentary on John Duns Scotus s Opus Oxoniense book III dist 34 q 1 in John Duns Scotus Opera Omnia vol 15 Ed Luke Wadding Louvain 1639 reprinted Paris Vives 1894 p 483a Aristotle Physics 189a15 On the Heavens 271a33 See also Franklin op cit note 44 to chap 9 Charlesworth M J 1956 Aristotle s Razor Philosophical Studies 6 105 112 doi 10 5840 philstudies1956606 a b c Franklin James 2001 The Science of Conjecture Evidence and Probability before Pascal The Johns Hopkins University Press Chap 9 p 241 Alistair Cameron Crombie Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100 1700 1953 pp 85 86 SUMMA THEOLOGICA The existence of God Prima Pars Q 2 Newadvent org Archived from the original on 28 April 2013 Retrieved 26 March 2013 Vallee Jacques 11 February 2013 What Ockham really said Boing Boing Archived from the original on 31 March 2013 Retrieved 26 March 2013 Bauer Laurie 2007 The linguistics Student s Handbook Edinburgh Edinburgh University Press p 155 Flew Antony 1979 A Dictionary of Philosophy London Pan Books p 253 Crombie Alistair Cameron 1959 Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy Cambridge MA Harvard Vol 2 p 30 Ockham s razor Encyclopaedia Britannica Encyclopaedia Britannica Online 2010 Archived from the original on 23 August 2010 Retrieved 12 June 2010 Hawking Stephen 2003 On the Shoulders of Giants Running Press p 731 ISBN 978 0 7624 1698 1 Retrieved 24 February 2016 Primary source Newton 2011 p 387 wrote the following two philosophizing rules at the beginning of part 3 of the Principia 1726 edition Regula I Causas rerum naturalium non plures admitti debere quam quae amp verae sint amp earum phaenomenis explicandis sufficient Regula II Ideoque effectuum naturalium ejusdem generis eaedem assignandae sunt causae quatenus fieri potest Logical Constructions Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2016 Induction From Kolmogorov and Solomonoff to De Finetti and Back to Kolmogorov JJ McCall Metroeconomica 2004 Wiley Online Library a b Soklakov A N 2002 Occam s Razor as a formal basis for a physical theory Foundations of Physics Letters 15 2 107 135 arXiv math ph 0009007 Bibcode 2000math ph 9007S doi 10 1023 A 1020994407185 S2CID 14940740 Rathmanner Samuel Hutter Marcus 2011 A philosophical treatise of universal induction Entropy 13 6 1076 1136 arXiv 1105 5721 Bibcode 2011Entrp 13 1076R doi 10 3390 e13061076 S2CID 2499910 Baker Alan 25 February 2010 Simplicity In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition a b c What is Occam s Razor math ucr edu Archived from the original on 6 July 2017 Stormy Dawn 17 July 2017 Everywhere The Soles of Your Feet Shall Tread ISBN 9781480838024 Sotos John G 2006 1991 Zebra Cards An Aid to Obscure Diagnoses Mt Vernon VA Mt Vernon Book Systems ISBN 978 0 9818193 0 3 Becher Erich 1905 The Philosophical Views of Ernst Mach The Philosophical Review 14 5 535 562 doi 10 2307 2177489 JSTOR 2177489 Pegis 1945 Stanovich Keith E 2007 How to Think Straight About Psychology Boston Pearson Education pp 19 33 ad hoc hypothesis The Skeptic s Dictionary Skepdic com skepdic com Archived from the original on 27 April 2009 Swinburne 1997 and Williams Gareth T 2008 Green K C Armstrong J S 2015 Simple versus complex forecasting The evidence Journal of Business Research 68 8 1678 1685 doi 10 1016 j jbusres 2015 03 026 subscription required MacKay David J C 2003 Information Theory Inference and Learning Algorithms PDF Bibcode 2003itil book M Archived PDF from the original on 15 September 2012 a b Jefferys William H Berger James O 1991 Ockham s Razor and Bayesian Statistics PDF American Scientist 80 1 64 72 JSTOR 29774559 Archived PDF from the original on 4 March 2005 preprint available as Sharpening Occam s Razor on a Bayesian Strop James Gareth et al 2013 An Introduction to Statistical Learning springer pp 105 203 204 ISBN 9781461471370 Popper Karl 1992 1934 Logik der Forschung The Logic of Scientific Discovery 2nd ed London Routledge pp 121 132 ISBN 978 84 309 0711 3 Sober Elliott 1975 Simplicity Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824407 3 Sober Elliott 2004 What is the Problem of Simplicity In Zellner Arnold Keuzenkamp Hugo A McAleer Michael eds Simplicity Inference and Modeling Keeping it Sophisticatedly Simple Cambridge U K Cambridge University Press pp 13 31 ISBN 978 0 521 80361 8 Retrieved 4 August 2012 Paper as PDF Swinburne Richard 1997 Simplicity as Evidence for Truth Milwaukee Wisconsin Marquette University Press ISBN 978 0 87462 164 8 Einstein Albert 1905 Does the Inertia of a Body Depend Upon Its Energy Content Annalen der Physik in German 323 18 639 41 Bibcode 1905AnP 323 639E doi 10 1002 andp 19053231314 L Nash The Nature of the Natural Sciences Boston Little Brown 1963 de Maupertuis P L M 1744 Memoires de l Academie Royale in French p 423 de Broglie L 1925 Annales de Physique in French pp 22 128 RA Jackson Mechanism An Introduction to the Study of Organic Reactions Clarendon Oxford 1972 Carpenter B K 1984 Determination of Organic Reaction Mechanism New York Wiley Interscience Einstein Albert 1934 On the Method of Theoretical Physics Philosophy of Science 1 2 165 163 169 doi 10 1086 286316 ISSN 0031 8248 JSTOR 184387 S2CID 44787169 Mettenheim Christoph von 1998 Popper Versus Einstein On the Philosophical Foundations of Physics p 34 ISBN 978 3 16 146910 7 Geis Gilbert Geis Professor Emeritus of Criminology Law and amp Society Gilbert Bienen Leigh B 1998 Crimes of the Century From Leopold and Loeb to O J Simpson UPNE p 39 ISBN 978 1 55553 360 1 Everything Should Be Made as Simple as Possible But Not Simpler Archived from the original on 29 May 2012 a b c Alan Baker 2010 2004 Simplicity Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy California Stanford University ISSN 1095 5054 a b c d e Courtney A Courtney M 2008 Comments Regarding On the Nature of Science Physics in Canada 64 3 7 8 arXiv 0812 4932 Bibcode 2008arXiv0812 4932C a b c Sober Elliott 1994 Let s Razor Occam s Razor In Knowles Dudley ed Explanation and Its Limits Cambridge University Press pp 73 93 Rabinowitz Matthew Myers Lance Banjevic Milena Chan Albert Sweetkind Singer Joshua Haberer Jessica McCann Kelly Wolkowicz Roland 1 March 2006 Accurate prediction of HIV 1 drug response from the reverse transcriptase and protease amino acid sequences using sparse models created by convex optimization Bioinformatics 22 5 541 549 doi 10 1093 bioinformatics btk011 ISSN 1367 4803 PMID 16368772 Paul Pojman 2009 Ernst Mach The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy California Stanford University ISSN 1095 5054 Sober Elliot 1998 Reconstructing the Past Parsimony Evolution and Inference 2nd ed Massachusetts Institute of Technology The MIT Press p 7 ISBN 978 0 262 69144 4 Wiley Edward O 1981 Phylogenetics the theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics Wiley and Sons Interscience Brower AVZ 2017 Statistical consistency and phylogenetic inference a brief review Cladistics 34 5 562 567 doi 10 1111 cla 12216 PMID 34649374 Brower amp Schuh 2021 Biological Systematics Principles and Applications 3rd edn Cornell University Press Crick 1988 p 146 William Ockham Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford Retrieved 24 February 2016 Dale T Irvin amp Scott W Sunquist History of World Christian Movement Volume I Earliest Christianity to 1453 p 434 ISBN 9781570753961 SUMMA THEOLOGICA The existence of God Prima Pars Q 2 Newadvent org Archived from the original on 28 April 2013 Retrieved 26 March 2013 McDonald 2005 p 282 Memoires du docteur F Antommarchi ou les derniers momens de Napoleon Archived 14 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine vol 1 1825 Paris Barrois L Aine Tonry Michael 2005 Obsolescence and Immanence in Penal Theory and Policy PDF Columbia Law Review 105 1233 1275 Archived from the original PDF on 23 June 2006 a b Chris S Wallace and David M Boulton Computer Journal Volume 11 Issue 2 1968 Page s 185 194 An information measure for classification a b Chris S Wallace and David L Dowe Computer Journal Volume 42 Issue 4 Sep 1999 Page s 270 283 Minimum Message Length and Kolmogorov Complexity Nannen Volker A short introduction to Model Selection Kolmogorov Complexity and Minimum Description Length PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2 June 2010 Retrieved 3 July 2010 Algorithmic Information Theory Archived from the original on 24 December 2007 Paul M B Vitanyi and Ming Li IEEE Transactions on Information Theory Volume 46 Issue 2 Mar 2000 Page s 446 464 Minimum Description Length Induction Bayesianism and Kolmogorov Complexity Standish Russell K 2000 Why Occam s Razor Foundations of Physics Letters 17 3 255 266 arXiv physics 0001020 Bibcode 2004FoPhL 17 255S doi 10 1023 B FOPL 0000032475 18334 0e S2CID 17143230 Solomonoff Ray 1964 A formal theory of inductive inference Part I Information and Control 7 1 22 1964 doi 10 1016 s0019 9958 64 90223 2 Schmidhuber J 2006 The New AI General amp Sound amp Relevant for Physics In Goertzel B Pennachin C eds Artificial General Intelligence pp 177 200 arXiv cs AI 0302012 Dowe David L 2008 Foreword re C S Wallace Computer Journal 51 5 523 560 doi 10 1093 comjnl bxm117 S2CID 5387092 David L Dowe 2010 MML hybrid Bayesian network graphical models statistical consistency invariance and uniqueness A formal theory of inductive inference Handbook of the Philosophy of Science HPS Volume 7 Philosophy of Statistics Elsevier 2010 Page s 901 982 https web archive org web 20140204001435 http citeseerx ist psu edu viewdoc download doi 10 1 1 185 709 amp rep rep1 amp type pdf Scott Needham and David L Dowe 2001 Message Length as an Effective Ockham s Razor in Decision Tree Induction Proc 8th International Workshop on Artificial Intelligence and Statistics AI STATS 2001 Key West Florida U S A Jan 2001 Page s 253 260 2001 Ockham pdf PDF Archived PDF from the original on 23 September 2015 Retrieved 2 September 2015 Berners Lee Tim 4 March 2013 Principles of Design World Wide Web Consortium a b Robert T Carroll 12 September 2014 Occam s Razor The Skeptic s Dictionary Archived from the original on 1 March 2016 Retrieved 24 February 2016 Quine W V O 1961 Two dogmas of empiricism From a logical point of view Cambridge Harvard University Press pp 20 46 ISBN 978 0 674 32351 3 Immanuel Kant 1929 Norman Kemp Smith transl ed The Critique of Pure Reason Palgrave Macmillan p 92 Archived from the original on 16 May 2012 Retrieved 27 October 2012 Entium varietates non temere esse minuendas Gordon Woo 20 June 2011 Calculating Catastrophe World Scientific pp 303 ISBN 978 1 84816 893 0 Further reading EditAriew Roger 1976 Ockham s Razor A Historical and Philosophical Analysis of Ockham s Principle of Parsimony Champaign Urbana University of Illinois Churchland Paul M 1984 Matter and Consciousness Cambridge Massachusetts MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 53050 7 Crick Francis H C 1988 What Mad Pursuit A Personal View of Scientific Discovery New York New York Basic Books ISBN 978 0 465 09137 9 Dowe David L Steve Gardner Graham Oppy December 2007 Bayes not Bust Why Simplicity is no Problem for Bayesians PDF British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 4 709 754 doi 10 1093 bjps axm033 S2CID 8863978 Archived PDF from the original on 9 October 2022 Duda Richard O Peter E Hart David G Stork 2000 Pattern Classification 2nd ed Wiley Interscience pp 487 489 ISBN 978 0 471 05669 0 Epstein Robert 1984 The Principle of Parsimony and Some Applications in Psychology Journal of Mind Behavior 5 119 130 Hoffmann Roald Vladimir I Minkin Barry K Carpenter 1997 Ockham s Razor and Chemistry Hyle 3 3 28 Retrieved 14 April 2006 Jacquette Dale 1994 Philosophy of Mind Engleswoods Cliffs New Jersey Prentice Hall pp 34 36 ISBN 978 0 13 030933 4 Jaynes Edwin Thompson 1994 Model Comparison and Robustness Probability Theory The Logic of Science ISBN 978 0 521 59271 0 Jefferys William H Berger James O 1991 Ockham s Razor and Bayesian Statistics American Scientist 80 64 72 Preprint available as Sharpening Occam s Razor on a Bayesian Strop Katz Jerrold 1998 Realistic Rationalism MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 11229 1 Kneale William Martha Kneale 1962 The Development of Logic London Oxford University Press p 243 ISBN 978 0 19 824183 6 MacKay David J C 2003 Information Theory Inference and Learning Algorithms Cambridge University Press Bibcode 2003itil book M ISBN 978 0 521 64298 9 Retrieved 24 February 2016 Maurer A 1984 Ockham s Razor and Chatton s Anti Razor Mediaeval Studies 46 463 475 doi 10 1484 J MS 2 306670 McDonald William 2005 Soren Kierkegaard Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 14 April 2006 Menger Karl 1960 A Counterpart of Ockham s Razor in Pure and Applied Mathematics Ontological Uses Synthese 12 4 415 428 doi 10 1007 BF00485426 S2CID 46962297 Morgan C Lloyd 1903 Other Minds than Ours An Introduction to Comparative Psychology 2nd ed London W Scott p 59 ISBN 978 0 89093 171 4 Archived from the original on 12 April 2005 Retrieved 15 April 2006 Newton Isaac 2011 1726 Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica 3rd ed London Henry Pemberton ISBN 978 1 60386 435 0 Nolan D 1997 Quantitative Parsimony British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 3 329 343 doi 10 1093 bjps 48 3 329 S2CID 229320568 Basic Writings of St Thomas Aquinas Translated by Pegis A C New York Random House 1945 p 129 ISBN 978 0 87220 380 8 Popper Karl 1992 First composed 1934 Logik der Forschung 7 Simplicity The Logic of Scientific Discovery 2nd ed London Routledge pp 121 132 ISBN 978 84 309 0711 3 Rodriguez Fernandez J L 1999 Ockham s Razor Endeavour 23 3 121 125 doi 10 1016 S0160 9327 99 01199 0 Schmitt Gavin C 2005 Ockham s Razor Suggests Atheism Archived from the original on 11 February 2007 Retrieved 15 April 2006 Smart J J C 1959 Sensations and Brain Processes The Philosophical Review 68 2 141 156 doi 10 2307 2182164 JSTOR 2182164 Sober Elliott 1975 Simplicity Oxford Oxford University Press Sober Elliott 1981 The Principle of Parsimony PDF British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 2 145 156 doi 10 1093 bjps 32 2 145 S2CID 120916709 Archived from the original PDF on 15 December 2011 Retrieved 4 August 2012 Sober Elliott 1990 Let s Razor Ockham s Razor In Dudley Knowles ed Explanation and its Limits Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 73 94 Sober Elliott 2002 Zellner et al eds What is the Problem of Simplicity PDF Archived from the original PDF on 8 November 2006 Retrieved 4 August 2012 Sober Elliott 2015 Ockham s Razors A User s Manual Cambridge England Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 06849 0 Swinburne Richard 1997 Simplicity as Evidence for Truth Milwaukee Wisconsin Marquette University Press ISBN 978 0 87462 164 8 Thorburn W M 1918 The Myth of Occam s Razor Mind 27 107 345 353 doi 10 1093 mind XXVII 3 345 Williams George C 1966 Adaptation and natural selection A Critique of some Current Evolutionary Thought Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 02615 2 External links Edit Wikimedia Commons has media related to Occam s razor Wikiquote has quotations related to William of Occam Look up Occam s razor or parsimony in Wiktionary the free dictionary Ockham s Razor BBC Radio 4 discussion with Sir Anthony Kenny Marilyn Adams amp Richard Cross In Our Time 31 May 2007 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Occam 27s razor amp oldid 1153049758, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.