fbpx
Wikipedia

Calculus

Calculus, originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the calculus of infinitesimals", is the mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations.

It has two major branches, differential calculus and integral calculus; the former concerns instantaneous rates of change, and the slopes of curves, while the latter concerns accumulation of quantities, and areas under or between curves. These two branches are related to each other by the fundamental theorem of calculus, and they make use of the fundamental notions of convergence of infinite sequences and infinite series to a well-defined limit.[1]

Infinitesimal calculus was developed independently in the late 17th century by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.[2][3] Later work, including codifying the idea of limits, put these developments on a more solid conceptual footing. Today, calculus has widespread uses in science, engineering, and social science.[4]

Etymology

In mathematics education, calculus denotes courses of elementary mathematical analysis, which are mainly devoted to the study of functions and limits. The word calculus is Latin for "small pebble" (the diminutive of calx, meaning "stone"), a meaning which still persists in medicine. Because such pebbles were used for counting out distances,[5] tallying votes, and doing abacus arithmetic, the word came to mean a method of computation. In this sense, it was used in English at least as early as 1672, several years prior to the publications of Leibniz and Newton.[6]

In addition to the differential calculus and integral calculus, the term is also used for naming specific methods of calculation and related theories which seek to model a particular concept in terms of mathematics. Examples of this convention include propositional calculus, Ricci calculus, calculus of variations, lambda calculus, and process calculus. Furthermore, the term "calculus" has variously been applied in ethics and philosophy, for such systems as Bentham's felicific calculus, and the ethical calculus.

History

Modern calculus was developed in 17th-century Europe by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (independently of each other, first publishing around the same time) but elements of it appeared in ancient Greece, then in China and the Middle East, and still later again in medieval Europe and in India.

Ancient precursors

Egypt

Calculations of volume and area, one goal of integral calculus, can be found in the Egyptian Moscow papyrus (c. 1820 BC), but the formulae are simple instructions, with no indication as to how they were obtained.[7][8]

Greece

 
Archimedes used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under a parabola in his work Quadrature of the Parabola.

Laying the foundations for integral calculus and foreshadowing the concept of the limit, ancient Greek mathematician Eudoxus of Cnidus (c. 390 – 337 BC) developed the method of exhaustion to prove the formulas for cone and pyramid volumes.

During the Hellenistic period, this method was further developed by Archimedes (c. 287c. 212 BC), who combined it with a concept of the indivisibles—a precursor to infinitesimals—allowing him to solve several problems now treated by integral calculus. In The Method of Mechanical Theorems he describes. for example, calculating the center of gravity of a solid hemisphere, the center of gravity of a frustum of a circular paraboloid, and the area of a region bounded by a parabola and one of its secant lines.[9]

China

The method of exhaustion was later discovered independently in China by Liu Hui in the 3rd century AD in order to find the area of a circle.[10][11] In the 5th century AD, Zu Gengzhi, son of Zu Chongzhi, established a method[12][13] that would later be called Cavalieri's principle to find the volume of a sphere.

Medieval

Middle East

 
Ibn al-Haytham, 11th-century Arab mathematician and physicist

In the Middle East, Hasan Ibn al-Haytham, Latinized as Alhazen (c. 965 – c. 1040 AD) derived a formula for the sum of fourth powers. He used the results to carry out what would now be called an integration of this function, where the formulae for the sums of integral squares and fourth powers allowed him to calculate the volume of a paraboloid.[14]

India

In the 14th century, Indian mathematicians gave a non-rigorous method, resembling differentiation, applicable to some trigonometric functions. Madhava of Sangamagrama and the Kerala School of Astronomy and Mathematics thereby stated components of calculus. A complete theory encompassing these components is now well known in the Western world as the Taylor series or infinite series approximations.[15][16] However, they were not able to "combine many differing ideas under the two unifying themes of the derivative and the integral, show the connection between the two, and turn calculus into the great problem-solving tool we have today".[14]

Modern

Johannes Kepler's work Stereometrica Doliorum formed the basis of integral calculus.[17] Kepler developed a method to calculate the area of an ellipse by adding up the lengths of many radii drawn from a focus of the ellipse.[18]

A significant work was a treatise, the origin being Kepler's methods,[18] written by Bonaventura Cavalieri, who argued that volumes and areas should be computed as the sums of the volumes and areas of infinitesimally thin cross-sections. The ideas were similar to Archimedes' in The Method, but this treatise is believed to have been lost in the 13th century, and was only rediscovered in the early 20th century, and so would have been unknown to Cavalieri. Cavalieri's work was not well respected since his methods could lead to erroneous results, and the infinitesimal quantities he introduced were disreputable at first.

The formal study of calculus brought together Cavalieri's infinitesimals with the calculus of finite differences developed in Europe at around the same time. Pierre de Fermat, claiming that he borrowed from Diophantus, introduced the concept of adequality, which represented equality up to an infinitesimal error term.[19] The combination was achieved by John Wallis, Isaac Barrow, and James Gregory, the latter two proving predecessors to the second fundamental theorem of calculus around 1670.[20][21]

The product rule and chain rule,[22] the notions of higher derivatives and Taylor series,[23] and of analytic functions[24] were used by Isaac Newton in an idiosyncratic notation which he applied to solve problems of mathematical physics. In his works, Newton rephrased his ideas to suit the mathematical idiom of the time, replacing calculations with infinitesimals by equivalent geometrical arguments which were considered beyond reproach. He used the methods of calculus to solve the problem of planetary motion, the shape of the surface of a rotating fluid, the oblateness of the earth, the motion of a weight sliding on a cycloid, and many other problems discussed in his Principia Mathematica (1687). In other work, he developed series expansions for functions, including fractional and irrational powers, and it was clear that he understood the principles of the Taylor series. He did not publish all these discoveries, and at this time infinitesimal methods were still considered disreputable.[25]

 
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was the first to state clearly the rules of calculus.
 
Isaac Newton developed the use of calculus in his laws of motion and gravitation.

These ideas were arranged into a true calculus of infinitesimals by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who was originally accused of plagiarism by Newton.[26] He is now regarded as an independent inventor of and contributor to calculus. His contribution was to provide a clear set of rules for working with infinitesimal quantities, allowing the computation of second and higher derivatives, and providing the product rule and chain rule, in their differential and integral forms. Unlike Newton, Leibniz put painstaking effort into his choices of notation.[27]

Today, Leibniz and Newton are usually both given credit for independently inventing and developing calculus. Newton was the first to apply calculus to general physics and Leibniz developed much of the notation used in calculus today.[28]: 51–52  The basic insights that both Newton and Leibniz provided were the laws of differentiation and integration, emphasizing that differentiation and integration are inverse processes, second and higher derivatives, and the notion of an approximating polynomial series.

When Newton and Leibniz first published their results, there was great controversy over which mathematician (and therefore which country) deserved credit. Newton derived his results first (later to be published in his Method of Fluxions), but Leibniz published his "Nova Methodus pro Maximis et Minimis" first. Newton claimed Leibniz stole ideas from his unpublished notes, which Newton had shared with a few members of the Royal Society. This controversy divided English-speaking mathematicians from continental European mathematicians for many years, to the detriment of English mathematics.[29] A careful examination of the papers of Leibniz and Newton shows that they arrived at their results independently, with Leibniz starting first with integration and Newton with differentiation. It is Leibniz, however, who gave the new discipline its name. Newton called his calculus "the science of fluxions", a term that endured in English schools into the 19th century.[30]: 100  The first complete treatise on calculus to be written in English and use the Leibniz notation was not published until 1815.[31]

Since the time of Leibniz and Newton, many mathematicians have contributed to the continuing development of calculus. One of the first and most complete works on both infinitesimal and integral calculus was written in 1748 by Maria Gaetana Agnesi.[32][33]

Foundations

In calculus, foundations refers to the rigorous development of the subject from axioms and definitions. In early calculus the use of infinitesimal quantities was thought unrigorous, and was fiercely criticized by a number of authors, most notably Michel Rolle and Bishop Berkeley. Berkeley famously described infinitesimals as the ghosts of departed quantities in his book The Analyst in 1734. Working out a rigorous foundation for calculus occupied mathematicians for much of the century following Newton and Leibniz, and is still to some extent an active area of research today.[34]

Several mathematicians, including Maclaurin, tried to prove the soundness of using infinitesimals, but it would not be until 150 years later when, due to the work of Cauchy and Weierstrass, a way was finally found to avoid mere "notions" of infinitely small quantities.[35] The foundations of differential and integral calculus had been laid. In Cauchy's Cours d'Analyse, we find a broad range of foundational approaches, including a definition of continuity in terms of infinitesimals, and a (somewhat imprecise) prototype of an (ε, δ)-definition of limit in the definition of differentiation.[36] In his work Weierstrass formalized the concept of limit and eliminated infinitesimals (although his definition can actually validate nilsquare infinitesimals). Following the work of Weierstrass, it eventually became common to base calculus on limits instead of infinitesimal quantities, though the subject is still occasionally called "infinitesimal calculus". Bernhard Riemann used these ideas to give a precise definition of the integral.[37] It was also during this period that the ideas of calculus were generalized to the complex plane with the development of complex analysis.[38]

In modern mathematics, the foundations of calculus are included in the field of real analysis, which contains full definitions and proofs of the theorems of calculus. The reach of calculus has also been greatly extended. Henri Lebesgue invented measure theory, based on earlier developments by Émile Borel, and used it to define integrals of all but the most pathological functions.[39] Laurent Schwartz introduced distributions, which can be used to take the derivative of any function whatsoever.[40]

Limits are not the only rigorous approach to the foundation of calculus. Another way is to use Abraham Robinson's non-standard analysis. Robinson's approach, developed in the 1960s, uses technical machinery from mathematical logic to augment the real number system with infinitesimal and infinite numbers, as in the original Newton-Leibniz conception. The resulting numbers are called hyperreal numbers, and they can be used to give a Leibniz-like development of the usual rules of calculus.[41] There is also smooth infinitesimal analysis, which differs from non-standard analysis in that it mandates neglecting higher-power infinitesimals during derivations.[34] Based on the ideas of F. W. Lawvere and employing the methods of category theory, smooth infinitesimal analysis views all functions as being continuous and incapable of being expressed in terms of discrete entities. One aspect of this formulation is that the law of excluded middle does not hold.[34] The law of excluded middle is also rejected in constructive mathematics, a branch of mathematics that insists that proofs of the existence of a number, function, or other mathematical object should give a construction of the object. Reformulations of calculus in a constructive framework are generally part of the subject of constructive analysis.[34]

Significance

While many of the ideas of calculus had been developed earlier in Greece, China, India, Iraq, Persia, and Japan, the use of calculus began in Europe, during the 17th century, when Newton and Leibniz built on the work of earlier mathematicians to introduce its basic principles.[11][25][42] The Hungarian polymath John von Neumann wrote of this work,

The calculus was the first achievement of modern mathematics and it is difficult to overestimate its importance. I think it defines more unequivocally than anything else the inception of modern mathematics, and the system of mathematical analysis, which is its logical development, still constitutes the greatest technical advance in exact thinking.[43]

Applications of differential calculus include computations involving velocity and acceleration, the slope of a curve, and optimization.[44]: 341–453  Applications of integral calculus include computations involving area, volume, arc length, center of mass, work, and pressure.[44]: 685–700  More advanced applications include power series and Fourier series.

Calculus is also used to gain a more precise understanding of the nature of space, time, and motion. For centuries, mathematicians and philosophers wrestled with paradoxes involving division by zero or sums of infinitely many numbers. These questions arise in the study of motion and area. The ancient Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea gave several famous examples of such paradoxes. Calculus provides tools, especially the limit and the infinite series, that resolve the paradoxes.[45]

Principles

Limits and infinitesimals

Calculus is usually developed by working with very small quantities. Historically, the first method of doing so was by infinitesimals. These are objects which can be treated like real numbers but which are, in some sense, "infinitely small". For example, an infinitesimal number could be greater than 0, but less than any number in the sequence 1, 1/2, 1/3, ... and thus less than any positive real number. From this point of view, calculus is a collection of techniques for manipulating infinitesimals. The symbols   and   were taken to be infinitesimal, and the derivative   was their ratio.[34]

The infinitesimal approach fell out of favor in the 19th century because it was difficult to make the notion of an infinitesimal precise. In the late 19th century, infinitesimals were replaced within academia by the epsilon, delta approach to limits. Limits describe the behavior of a function at a certain input in terms of its values at nearby inputs. They capture small-scale behavior using the intrinsic structure of the real number system (as a metric space with the least-upper-bound property). In this treatment, calculus is a collection of techniques for manipulating certain limits. Infinitesimals get replaced by sequences of smaller and smaller numbers, and the infinitely small behavior of a function is found by taking the limiting behavior for these sequences. Limits were thought to provide a more rigorous foundation for calculus, and for this reason they became the standard approach during the 20th century. However, the infinitesimal concept was revived in the 20th century with the introduction of non-standard analysis and smooth infinitesimal analysis, which provided solid foundations for the manipulation of infinitesimals.[34]

Differential calculus

 
Tangent line at (x0, f(x0)). The derivative f′(x) of a curve at a point is the slope (rise over run) of the line tangent to that curve at that point.

Differential calculus is the study of the definition, properties, and applications of the derivative of a function. The process of finding the derivative is called differentiation. Given a function and a point in the domain, the derivative at that point is a way of encoding the small-scale behavior of the function near that point. By finding the derivative of a function at every point in its domain, it is possible to produce a new function, called the derivative function or just the derivative of the original function. In formal terms, the derivative is a linear operator which takes a function as its input and produces a second function as its output. This is more abstract than many of the processes studied in elementary algebra, where functions usually input a number and output another number. For example, if the doubling function is given the input three, then it outputs six, and if the squaring function is given the input three, then it outputs nine. The derivative, however, can take the squaring function as an input. This means that the derivative takes all the information of the squaring function—such as that two is sent to four, three is sent to nine, four is sent to sixteen, and so on—and uses this information to produce another function. The function produced by differentiating the squaring function turns out to be the doubling function.[28]: 32 

In more explicit terms the "doubling function" may be denoted by g(x) = 2x and the "squaring function" by f(x) = x2. The "derivative" now takes the function f(x), defined by the expression "x2", as an input, that is all the information—such as that two is sent to four, three is sent to nine, four is sent to sixteen, and so on—and uses this information to output another function, the function g(x) = 2x, as will turn out.

In Lagrange's notation, the symbol for a derivative is an apostrophe-like mark called a prime. Thus, the derivative of a function called f is denoted by f′, pronounced "f prime" or "f dash". For instance, if f(x) = x2 is the squaring function, then f′(x) = 2x is its derivative (the doubling function g from above).

If the input of the function represents time, then the derivative represents change with respect to time. For example, if f is a function that takes a time as input and gives the position of a ball at that time as output, then the derivative of f is how the position is changing in time, that is, it is the velocity of the ball.[28]: 18–20 

If a function is linear (that is, if the graph of the function is a straight line), then the function can be written as y = mx + b, where x is the independent variable, y is the dependent variable, b is the y-intercept, and:

 

This gives an exact value for the slope of a straight line.[46]: 6  If the graph of the function is not a straight line, however, then the change in y divided by the change in x varies. Derivatives give an exact meaning to the notion of change in output with respect to change in input. To be concrete, let f be a function, and fix a point a in the domain of f. (a, f(a)) is a point on the graph of the function. If h is a number close to zero, then a + h is a number close to a. Therefore, (a + h, f(a + h)) is close to (a, f(a)). The slope between these two points is

 

This expression is called a difference quotient. A line through two points on a curve is called a secant line, so m is the slope of the secant line between (a, f(a)) and (a + h, f(a + h)). The secant line is only an approximation to the behavior of the function at the point a because it does not account for what happens between a and a + h. It is not possible to discover the behavior at a by setting h to zero because this would require dividing by zero, which is undefined. The derivative is defined by taking the limit as h tends to zero, meaning that it considers the behavior of f for all small values of h and extracts a consistent value for the case when h equals zero:

 

Geometrically, the derivative is the slope of the tangent line to the graph of f at a. The tangent line is a limit of secant lines just as the derivative is a limit of difference quotients. For this reason, the derivative is sometimes called the slope of the function f.[46]: 61–63 

Here is a particular example, the derivative of the squaring function at the input 3. Let f(x) = x2 be the squaring function.

 
The derivative f′(x) of a curve at a point is the slope of the line tangent to that curve at that point. This slope is determined by considering the limiting value of the slopes of secant lines. Here the function involved (drawn in red) is f(x) = x3x. The tangent line (in green) which passes through the point (−3/2, −15/8) has a slope of 23/4. Note that the vertical and horizontal scales in this image are different.
 

The slope of the tangent line to the squaring function at the point (3, 9) is 6, that is to say, it is going up six times as fast as it is going to the right. The limit process just described can be performed for any point in the domain of the squaring function. This defines the derivative function of the squaring function or just the derivative of the squaring function for short. A computation similar to the one above shows that the derivative of the squaring function is the doubling function.[46]: 63 

Leibniz notation

A common notation, introduced by Leibniz, for the derivative in the example above is

 

In an approach based on limits, the symbol dy/dx is to be interpreted not as the quotient of two numbers but as a shorthand for the limit computed above.[46]: 74  Leibniz, however, did intend it to represent the quotient of two infinitesimally small numbers, dy being the infinitesimally small change in y caused by an infinitesimally small change dx applied to x. We can also think of d/dx as a differentiation operator, which takes a function as an input and gives another function, the derivative, as the output. For example:

 

In this usage, the dx in the denominator is read as "with respect to x".[46]: 79  Another example of correct notation could be:

 

Even when calculus is developed using limits rather than infinitesimals, it is common to manipulate symbols like dx and dy as if they were real numbers; although it is possible to avoid such manipulations, they are sometimes notationally convenient in expressing operations such as the total derivative.

Integral calculus

 
Integration can be thought of as measuring the area under a curve, defined by f(x), between two points (here a and b).
 
A sequence of midpoint Riemann sums over a regular partition of an interval: the total area of the rectangles converges to the integral of the function.

Integral calculus is the study of the definitions, properties, and applications of two related concepts, the indefinite integral and the definite integral. The process of finding the value of an integral is called integration.[44]: 508  The indefinite integral, also known as the antiderivative, is the inverse operation to the derivative.[46]: 163–165  F is an indefinite integral of f when f is a derivative of F. (This use of lower- and upper-case letters for a function and its indefinite integral is common in calculus.) The definite integral inputs a function and outputs a number, which gives the algebraic sum of areas between the graph of the input and the x-axis. The technical definition of the definite integral involves the limit of a sum of areas of rectangles, called a Riemann sum.[47]: 282 

A motivating example is the distance traveled in a given time.[46]: 153  If the speed is constant, only multiplication is needed:

 

But if the speed changes, a more powerful method of finding the distance is necessary. One such method is to approximate the distance traveled by breaking up the time into many short intervals of time, then multiplying the time elapsed in each interval by one of the speeds in that interval, and then taking the sum (a Riemann sum) of the approximate distance traveled in each interval. The basic idea is that if only a short time elapses, then the speed will stay more or less the same. However, a Riemann sum only gives an approximation of the distance traveled. We must take the limit of all such Riemann sums to find the exact distance traveled.

When velocity is constant, the total distance traveled over the given time interval can be computed by multiplying velocity and time. For example, travelling a steady 50 mph for 3 hours results in a total distance of 150 miles. Plotting the velocity as a function of time yields a rectangle with height equal to the velocity and width equal to the time elapsed. Therefore, the product of velocity and time also calculates the rectangular area under the (constant) velocity curve.[44]: 535  This connection between the area under a curve and distance traveled can be extended to any irregularly shaped region exhibiting a fluctuating velocity over a given time period. If f(x) represents speed as it varies over time, the distance traveled between the times represented by a and b is the area of the region between f(x) and the x-axis, between x = a and x = b.

To approximate that area, an intuitive method would be to divide up the distance between a and b into a number of equal segments, the length of each segment represented by the symbol Δx. For each small segment, we can choose one value of the function f(x). Call that value h. Then the area of the rectangle with base Δx and height h gives the distance (time Δx multiplied by speed h) traveled in that segment. Associated with each segment is the average value of the function above it, f(x) = h. The sum of all such rectangles gives an approximation of the area between the axis and the curve, which is an approximation of the total distance traveled. A smaller value for Δx will give more rectangles and in most cases a better approximation, but for an exact answer we need to take a limit as Δx approaches zero.[44]: 512–522 

The symbol of integration is  , an elongated S chosen to suggest summation.[44]: 529  The definite integral is written as:

 

and is read "the integral from a to b of f-of-x with respect to x." The Leibniz notation dx is intended to suggest dividing the area under the curve into an infinite number of rectangles, so that their width Δx becomes the infinitesimally small dx.[28]: 44 

The indefinite integral, or antiderivative, is written:

 

Functions differing by only a constant have the same derivative, and it can be shown that the antiderivative of a given function is actually a family of functions differing only by a constant.[47]: 326  Since the derivative of the function y = x2 + C, where C is any constant, is y′ = 2x, the antiderivative of the latter is given by:

 

The unspecified constant C present in the indefinite integral or antiderivative is known as the constant of integration.[48]: 135 

Fundamental theorem

The fundamental theorem of calculus states that differentiation and integration are inverse operations.[47]: 290  More precisely, it relates the values of antiderivatives to definite integrals. Because it is usually easier to compute an antiderivative than to apply the definition of a definite integral, the fundamental theorem of calculus provides a practical way of computing definite integrals. It can also be interpreted as a precise statement of the fact that differentiation is the inverse of integration.

The fundamental theorem of calculus states: If a function f is continuous on the interval [a, b] and if F is a function whose derivative is f on the interval (a, b), then

 

Furthermore, for every x in the interval (a, b),

 

This realization, made by both Newton and Leibniz, was key to the proliferation of analytic results after their work became known. (The extent to which Newton and Leibniz were influenced by immediate predecessors, and particularly what Leibniz may have learned from the work of Isaac Barrow, is difficult to determine because of the priority dispute between them.[49]) The fundamental theorem provides an algebraic method of computing many definite integrals—without performing limit processes—by finding formulae for antiderivatives. It is also a prototype solution of a differential equation. Differential equations relate an unknown function to its derivatives, and are ubiquitous in the sciences.[50]: 351–352 

Applications

 
The logarithmic spiral of the Nautilus shell is a classical image used to depict the growth and change related to calculus.

Calculus is used in every branch of the physical sciences,[51]: 1  actuarial science, computer science, statistics, engineering, economics, business, medicine, demography, and in other fields wherever a problem can be mathematically modeled and an optimal solution is desired.[52] It allows one to go from (non-constant) rates of change to the total change or vice versa, and many times in studying a problem we know one and are trying to find the other.[53] Calculus can be used in conjunction with other mathematical disciplines. For example, it can be used with linear algebra to find the "best fit" linear approximation for a set of points in a domain. Or, it can be used in probability theory to determine the expectation value of a continuous random variable given a probability density function.[54]: 37  In analytic geometry, the study of graphs of functions, calculus is used to find high points and low points (maxima and minima), slope, concavity and inflection points. Calculus is also used to find approximate solutions to equations; in practice it is the standard way to solve differential equations and do root finding in most applications. Examples are methods such as Newton's method, fixed point iteration, and linear approximation. For instance, spacecraft use a variation of the Euler method to approximate curved courses within zero gravity environments.

Physics makes particular use of calculus; all concepts in classical mechanics and electromagnetism are related through calculus. The mass of an object of known density, the moment of inertia of objects, and the potential energies due to gravitational and electromagnetic forces can all be found by the use of calculus. An example of the use of calculus in mechanics is Newton's second law of motion, which states that the derivative of an object's momentum with respect to time equals the net force upon it. Alternatively, Newton's second law can be expressed by saying that the net force is equal to the object's mass times its acceleration, which is the time derivative of velocity and thus the second time derivative of spatial position. Starting from knowing how an object is accelerating, we use calculus to derive its path.[55]

Maxwell's theory of electromagnetism and Einstein's theory of general relativity are also expressed in the language of differential calculus.[56][57]: 52–55  Chemistry also uses calculus in determining reaction rates[58]: 599  and in studying radioactive decay.[58]: 814  In biology, population dynamics starts with reproduction and death rates to model population changes.[59][60]: 631 

Green's theorem, which gives the relationship between a line integral around a simple closed curve C and a double integral over the plane region D bounded by C, is applied in an instrument known as a planimeter, which is used to calculate the area of a flat surface on a drawing.[61] For example, it can be used to calculate the amount of area taken up by an irregularly shaped flower bed or swimming pool when designing the layout of a piece of property.

In the realm of medicine, calculus can be used to find the optimal branching angle of a blood vessel so as to maximize flow.[62] Calculus can be applied to understand how quickly a drug is eliminated from a body or how quickly a cancerous tumour grows.[63]

In economics, calculus allows for the determination of maximal profit by providing a way to easily calculate both marginal cost and marginal revenue.[64]: 387 

See also

References

  1. ^ DeBaggis, Henry F.; Miller, Kenneth S. (1966). Foundations of the Calculus. Philadelphia: Saunders. OCLC 527896.
  2. ^ Boyer, Carl B. (1959). The History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development. New York: Dover. OCLC 643872.
  3. ^ Bardi, Jason Socrates (2006). The Calculus Wars : Newton, Leibniz, and the Greatest Mathematical Clash of All Time. New York: Thunder's Mouth Press. ISBN 1-56025-706-7.
  4. ^ Hoffmann, Laurence D.; Bradley, Gerald L. (2004). Calculus for Business, Economics, and the Social and Life Sciences (8th ed.). Boston: McGraw Hill. ISBN 0-07-242432-X.
  5. ^ See, for example:
    • "history - Were metered taxis busy roaming Imperial Rome?". Skeptics Stack Exchange. 17 June 2020. Retrieved 13 February 2022.
    • Cousineau, Phil (15 March 2010). Wordcatcher: An Odyssey into the World of Weird and Wonderful Words. Simon and Schuster. p. 58. ISBN 978-1-57344-550-4. OCLC 811492876.
  6. ^ "calculus". Oxford English Dictionary (Online ed.). Oxford University Press. (Subscription or participating institution membership required.)
  7. ^ Kline, Morris (16 August 1990). Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times: Volume 1. Oxford University Press. pp. 15–21. ISBN 978-0-19-506135-2.
  8. ^ Imhausen, Annette (2016). Mathematics in Ancient Egypt: A Contextual History. Princeton University Press. p. 112. ISBN 978-1-4008-7430-9. OCLC 934433864.
  9. ^ See, for example:
    • Powers, J. (2020). ""Did Archimedes do calculus?"" (PDF). Mathematical Association of America. Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022.
    • Jullien, Vincent (2015). "Archimedes and Indivisibles". Seventeenth-Century Indivisibles Revisited. Science Networks. Historical Studies. Vol. 49. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 451–457. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-00131-9_18. ISBN 978-3-319-00130-2.
    • Plummer, Brad (9 August 2006). "Modern X-ray technology reveals Archimedes' math theory under forged painting". Stanford University. Retrieved 28 February 2022.
    • Archimedes (2004). The Works of Archimedes, Volume 1: The Two Books On the Sphere and the Cylinder. Translated by Netz, Reviel. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-66160-7.
    • Gray, Shirley; Waldman, Cye H. (20 October 2018). "Archimedes Redux: Center of Mass Applications from The Method". The College Mathematics Journal. 49 (5): 346–352. doi:10.1080/07468342.2018.1524647. ISSN 0746-8342. S2CID 125411353.
  10. ^ Dun, Liu; Fan, Dainian; Cohen, Robert Sonné (1966). A comparison of Archimdes' and Liu Hui's studies of circles. Chinese studies in the history and philosophy of science and technology. Vol. 130. Springer. p. 279. ISBN 978-0-7923-3463-7.,pp. 279ff
  11. ^ a b Dainian Fan; R. S. Cohen (1996). Chinese studies in the history and philosophy of science and technology. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. ISBN 0-7923-3463-9. OCLC 32272485.
  12. ^ Katz, Victor J. (2008). A history of mathematics (3rd ed.). Boston, MA: Addison-Wesley. p. 203. ISBN 978-0-321-38700-4.
  13. ^ Zill, Dennis G.; Wright, Scott; Wright, Warren S. (2009). Calculus: Early Transcendentals (3 ed.). Jones & Bartlett Learning. p. xxvii. ISBN 978-0-7637-5995-7. Extract of page 27
  14. ^ a b Katz, Victor J. (June 1995). "Ideas of Calculus in Islam and India". Mathematics Magazine. 68 (3): 163–174. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1995.11996307. ISSN 0025-570X. JSTOR 2691411.
  15. ^ O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "An overview of Indian mathematics", MacTutor History of Mathematics archive, University of St Andrews
  16. ^ Plofker, Kim (2009). Mathematics in India. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-3407-5. OCLC 650305544.
  17. ^ "Johannes Kepler: His Life, His Laws and Times". NASA. 24 September 2016. Retrieved 10 June 2021.
  18. ^ a b Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Infinitesimal Calculus § History" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 14 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 537.
  19. ^ Weil, André (1984). Number theory: An approach through History from Hammurapi to Legendre. Boston: Birkhauser Boston. p. 28. ISBN 0-8176-4565-9.
  20. ^ Hollingdale, Stuart (1991). "Review of Before Newton: The Life and Times of Isaac Barrow". Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London. 45 (2): 277–279. doi:10.1098/rsnr.1991.0027. ISSN 0035-9149. JSTOR 531707. S2CID 165043307. The most interesting to us are Lectures X-XII, in which Barrow comes close to providing a geometrical demonstration of the fundamental theorem of the calculus... He did not realize, however, the full significance of his results, and his rejection of algebra means that his work must remain a piece of mid-17th century geometrical analysis of mainly historic interest.
  21. ^ Bressoud, David M. (2011). "Historical Reflections on Teaching the Fundamental Theorem of Integral Calculus". The American Mathematical Monthly. 118 (2): 99. doi:10.4169/amer.math.monthly.118.02.099. S2CID 21473035.
  22. ^ Blank, Brian E.; Krantz, Steven George (2006). Calculus: Single Variable, Volume 1 (Illustrated ed.). Springer Science & Business Media. p. 248. ISBN 978-1-931914-59-8.
  23. ^ Ferraro, Giovanni (2007). The Rise and Development of the Theory of Series up to the Early 1820s (Illustrated ed.). Springer Science & Business Media. p. 87. ISBN 978-0-387-73468-2.
  24. ^ Guicciardini, Niccolò (2005). "Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica, first edition (1687)". Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640-1940. Elsevier. pp. 59–87. doi:10.1016/b978-044450871-3/50086-3. ISBN 978-0-444-50871-3. [Newton] immediately realised that quadrature problems (the inverse problems) could be tackled via infinite series: as we would say nowadays, by expanding the integrand in power series and integrating term-wise.
  25. ^ a b Grattan-Guinness, I., ed. (2005). Landmark writings in Western mathematics 1640-1940. Amsterdam: Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-50871-6. OCLC 60416766.
  26. ^ Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (2008). The Early Mathematical Manuscripts of Leibniz. Cosimo, Inc. p. 228. ISBN 978-1-605-20533-5.
  27. ^ Mazur, Joseph (2014). Enlightening Symbols / A Short History of Mathematical Notation and Its Hidden Powers. Princeton University Press. p. 166. ISBN 978-0-691-17337-5. Leibniz understood symbols, their conceptual powers as well as their limitations. He would spend years experimenting with some—adjusting, rejecting, and corresponding with everyone he knew, consulting with as many of the leading mathematicians of the time who were sympathetic to his fastidiousness.
  28. ^ a b c d Frautschi, Steven C.; Olenick, Richard P.; Apostol, Tom M.; Goodstein, David L. (2007). The Mechanical Universe: Mechanics and Heat (Advanced ed.). Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-71590-4. OCLC 227002144.
  29. ^ Schrader, Dorothy V. (1962). "The Newton-Leibniz controversy concerning the discovery of the calculus". The Mathematics Teacher. 55 (5): 385–396. doi:10.5951/MT.55.5.0385. ISSN 0025-5769. JSTOR 27956626.
  30. ^ Stedall, Jacqueline (2012). The History of Mathematics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-191-63396-6.
  31. ^ Stenhouse, Brigitte (May 2020). "Mary Somerville's early contributions to the circulation of differential calculus". Historia Mathematica. 51: 1–25. doi:10.1016/j.hm.2019.12.001. S2CID 214472568.
  32. ^ Allaire, Patricia R. (2007). Foreword. A Biography of Maria Gaetana Agnesi, an Eighteenth-century Woman Mathematician. By Cupillari, Antonella. Lewiston, New York: Edwin Mellen Press. p. iii. ISBN 978-0-7734-5226-8.
  33. ^ Unlu, Elif (April 1995). "Maria Gaetana Agnesi". Agnes Scott College.
  34. ^ a b c d e f Bell, John L. (6 September 2013). "Continuity and Infinitesimals". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 February 2022.
  35. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1946). History of Western Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. p. 857. The great mathematicians of the seventeenth century were optimistic and anxious for quick results; consequently they left the foundations of analytical geometry and the infinitesimal calculus insecure. Leibniz believed in actual infinitesimals, but although this belief suited his metaphysics it had no sound basis in mathematics. Weierstrass, soon after the middle of the nineteenth century, showed how to establish the calculus without infinitesimals, and thus at last made it logically secure. Next came Georg Cantor, who developed the theory of continuity and infinite number. "Continuity" had been, until he defined it, a vague word, convenient for philosophers like Hegel, who wished to introduce metaphysical muddles into mathematics. Cantor gave a precise significance to the word, and showed that continuity, as he defined it, was the concept needed by mathematicians and physicists. By this means a great deal of mysticism, such as that of Bergson, was rendered antiquated.
  36. ^ Grabiner, Judith V. (1981). The Origins of Cauchy's Rigorous Calculus. Cambridge: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-387-90527-3.
  37. ^ Archibald, Tom (2008). "The Development of Rigor in Mathematical Analysis". In Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 117–129. ISBN 978-0-691-11880-2. OCLC 682200048.
  38. ^ Rice, Adrian (2008). "A Chronology of Mathematical Events". In Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 1010–1014. ISBN 978-0-691-11880-2. OCLC 682200048.
  39. ^ Siegmund-Schultze, Reinhard (2008). "Henri Lebesgue". In Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 796–797. ISBN 978-0-691-11880-2. OCLC 682200048.
  40. ^ Barany, Michael J.; Paumier, Anne-Sandrine; Lützen, Jesper (November 2017). "From Nancy to Copenhagen to the World: The internationalization of Laurent Schwartz and his theory of distributions". Historia Mathematica. 44 (4): 367–394. doi:10.1016/j.hm.2017.04.002.
  41. ^ Daubin, Joseph W. (2008). "Abraham Robinson". In Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 822–823. ISBN 978-0-691-11880-2. OCLC 682200048.
  42. ^ Kline, Morris (1990). Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times. v. 3. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-977048-9. OCLC 726764443.
  43. ^ von Neumann, J. (1947). "The Mathematician". In Heywood, R. B. (ed.). The Works of the Mind. University of Chicago Press. pp. 180–196. Reprinted in Bródy, F.; Vámos, T., eds. (1995). The Neumann Compendium. World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd. pp. 618–626. ISBN 981-02-2201-7.
  44. ^ a b c d e f Herman, Edwin; Strang, Gilbert; et al. (2017). Calculus. Volume 1. Houston, Texas: OpenStax. ISBN 978-1-938168-02-4. OCLC 1022848630.
  45. ^ Cheng, Eugenia (2017). Beyond Infinity: An Expedition to the Outer Limits of Mathematics. Basic Books. pp. 206–210. ISBN 978-1-541-64413-7. OCLC 1003309980.
  46. ^ a b c d e f g Salas, Saturnino L.; Hille, Einar (1971). Calculus; one and several variables. Waltham, Mass.: Xerox College Pub. OCLC 135567.
  47. ^ a b c Hughes-Hallett, Deborah; McCallum, William G.; Gleason, Andrew M.; et al. (2013). Calculus: Single and Multivariable (6th ed.). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. ISBN 978-0-470-88861-2. OCLC 794034942.
  48. ^ Moebs, William; Ling, Samuel J.; Sanny, Jeff; et al. (2022). University Physics, Volume 1. OpenStax. ISBN 978-1-947172-20-3. OCLC 961352944.
  49. ^ See, for example:
    • Mahoney, Michael S. (1990). "Barrow's mathematics: Between ancients and moderns". In Feingold, M. (ed.). Before Newton. Cambridge University Press. pp. 179–249. ISBN 978-0-521-06385-2.
    • Feingold, M. (June 1993). "Newton, Leibniz, and Barrow Too: An Attempt at a Reinterpretation". Isis. 84 (2): 310–338. Bibcode:1993Isis...84..310F. doi:10.1086/356464. ISSN 0021-1753. S2CID 144019197.
    • Probst, Siegmund (2015). "Leibniz as Reader and Second Inventor: The Cases of Barrow and Mengoli". In Goethe, Norma B.; Beeley, Philip; Rabouin, David (eds.). G.W. Leibniz, Interrelations Between Mathematics and Philosophy. Archimedes: New Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology. Vol. 41. Springer. pp. 111–134. ISBN 978-9-401-79663-7.
  50. ^ Herman, Edwin; Strang, Gilbert; et al. (2017). Calculus. Volume 2. Houston, Texas: OpenStax. ISBN 978-1-5066-9807-6. OCLC 1127050110.
  51. ^ Baron, Margaret E. (1969). The origins of the infinitesimal calculus (1st ed.). Oxford. ISBN 978-1-483-28092-9. OCLC 892067655.
  52. ^ Kayaspor, Ali (28 August 2022). "The Beautiful Applications of Calculus in Real Life". Medium. Retrieved 26 September 2022.
  53. ^ Hu, Zhiying (14 April 2021). "The Application and Value of Calculus in Daily Life". 2021 2nd Asia-Pacific Conference on Image Processing, Electronics and Computers. Ipec2021. Dalian China: ACM: 562–564. doi:10.1145/3452446.3452583. ISBN 978-1-4503-8981-5. S2CID 233384462.
  54. ^ Kardar, Mehran (2007). Statistical Physics of Particles. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-87342-0. OCLC 860391091.
  55. ^ Garber, Elizabeth (2001). The language of physics : the calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1750-1914. Springer Science+Business Media. ISBN 978-1-4612-7272-4. OCLC 921230825.
  56. ^ Hall, Graham (2008). "Maxwell's Electromagnetic Theory and Special Relativity". Philosophical Transactions: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 366 (1871): 1849–1860. Bibcode:2008RSPTA.366.1849H. doi:10.1098/rsta.2007.2192. ISSN 1364-503X. JSTOR 25190792. PMID 18218598. S2CID 502776.
  57. ^ Gbur, Greg (2011). Mathematical Methods for Optical Physics and Engineering. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-511-91510-9. OCLC 704518582.
  58. ^ a b Atkins, Peter W.; Jones, Loretta (2010). Chemical principles : the quest for insight (5th ed.). New York: W.H. Freeman. ISBN 978-1-4292-1955-6. OCLC 501943698.
  59. ^ Murray, J. D. (2002). Mathematical biology. I, Introduction (3rd ed.). New York: Springer. ISBN 0-387-22437-8. OCLC 53165394.
  60. ^ Neuhauser, Claudia (2011). Calculus for biology and medicine (3rd ed.). Boston: Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-321-64468-8. OCLC 426065941.
  61. ^ Gatterdam, R. W. (1981). "The planimeter as an example of Green's theorem". The American Mathematical Monthly. 88 (9): 701–704. doi:10.2307/2320679. JSTOR 2320679.
  62. ^ Adam, John A. (June 2011). "Blood Vessel Branching: Beyond the Standard Calculus Problem". Mathematics Magazine. 84 (3): 196–207. doi:10.4169/math.mag.84.3.196. ISSN 0025-570X. S2CID 8259705.
  63. ^ Mackenzie, Dana (2004). "Mathematical Modeling and Cancer" (PDF). SIAM News. 37 (1). Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022.
  64. ^ Perloff, Jeffrey M. (2018). Microeconomics : Theory and Applications with Calculus (4th global ed.). Harlow, United Kingdom. ISBN 978-1-292-15446-6. OCLC 1064041906.

Further reading

External links

  • "Calculus", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
  • Weisstein, Eric W. "Calculus". MathWorld.
  • Topics on Calculus at PlanetMath.
  • Calculus Made Easy (1914) by Silvanus P. Thompson Full text in PDF
  • Calculus on In Our Time at the BBC
  • Calculus.org: The Calculus page at University of California, Davis – contains resources and links to other sites
  • Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics: Calculus & Analysis
  • The Role of Calculus in College Mathematics from ERICDigests.org
  • OpenCourseWare Calculus from the Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  • Infinitesimal Calculus – an article on its historical development, in Encyclopedia of Mathematics, ed. Michiel Hazewinkel.
  • Daniel Kleitman, MIT. "Calculus for Beginners and Artists".
  • Calculus training materials at imomath.com
  • (in English and Arabic) The Excursion of Calculus, 1772

calculus, this, article, about, branch, mathematics, other, uses, disambiguation, originally, called, infinitesimal, calculus, calculus, infinitesimals, mathematical, study, continuous, change, same, that, geometry, study, shape, algebra, study, generalization. This article is about the branch of mathematics For other uses see Calculus disambiguation Calculus originally called infinitesimal calculus or the calculus of infinitesimals is the mathematical study of continuous change in the same way that geometry is the study of shape and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations It has two major branches differential calculus and integral calculus the former concerns instantaneous rates of change and the slopes of curves while the latter concerns accumulation of quantities and areas under or between curves These two branches are related to each other by the fundamental theorem of calculus and they make use of the fundamental notions of convergence of infinite sequences and infinite series to a well defined limit 1 Infinitesimal calculus was developed independently in the late 17th century by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 2 3 Later work including codifying the idea of limits put these developments on a more solid conceptual footing Today calculus has widespread uses in science engineering and social science 4 Contents 1 Etymology 2 History 2 1 Ancient precursors 2 1 1 Egypt 2 1 2 Greece 2 1 3 China 2 2 Medieval 2 2 1 Middle East 2 2 2 India 2 3 Modern 2 4 Foundations 2 5 Significance 3 Principles 3 1 Limits and infinitesimals 3 2 Differential calculus 3 3 Leibniz notation 3 4 Integral calculus 3 5 Fundamental theorem 4 Applications 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksEtymologyIn mathematics education calculus denotes courses of elementary mathematical analysis which are mainly devoted to the study of functions and limits The word calculus is Latin for small pebble the diminutive of calx meaning stone a meaning which still persists in medicine Because such pebbles were used for counting out distances 5 tallying votes and doing abacus arithmetic the word came to mean a method of computation In this sense it was used in English at least as early as 1672 several years prior to the publications of Leibniz and Newton 6 In addition to the differential calculus and integral calculus the term is also used for naming specific methods of calculation and related theories which seek to model a particular concept in terms of mathematics Examples of this convention include propositional calculus Ricci calculus calculus of variations lambda calculus and process calculus Furthermore the term calculus has variously been applied in ethics and philosophy for such systems as Bentham s felicific calculus and the ethical calculus HistoryMain article History of calculus Modern calculus was developed in 17th century Europe by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz independently of each other first publishing around the same time but elements of it appeared in ancient Greece then in China and the Middle East and still later again in medieval Europe and in India Ancient precursors Egypt Calculations of volume and area one goal of integral calculus can be found in the Egyptian Moscow papyrus c 1820 BC but the formulae are simple instructions with no indication as to how they were obtained 7 8 Greece See also Greek mathematics Archimedes used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under a parabola in his work Quadrature of the Parabola Laying the foundations for integral calculus and foreshadowing the concept of the limit ancient Greek mathematician Eudoxus of Cnidus c 390 337 BC developed the method of exhaustion to prove the formulas for cone and pyramid volumes During the Hellenistic period this method was further developed by Archimedes c 287 c 212 BC who combined it with a concept of the indivisibles a precursor to infinitesimals allowing him to solve several problems now treated by integral calculus In The Method of Mechanical Theorems he describes for example calculating the center of gravity of a solid hemisphere the center of gravity of a frustum of a circular paraboloid and the area of a region bounded by a parabola and one of its secant lines 9 China The method of exhaustion was later discovered independently in China by Liu Hui in the 3rd century AD in order to find the area of a circle 10 11 In the 5th century AD Zu Gengzhi son of Zu Chongzhi established a method 12 13 that would later be called Cavalieri s principle to find the volume of a sphere Medieval Middle East Ibn al Haytham 11th century Arab mathematician and physicist In the Middle East Hasan Ibn al Haytham Latinized as Alhazen c 965 c 1040 AD derived a formula for the sum of fourth powers He used the results to carry out what would now be called an integration of this function where the formulae for the sums of integral squares and fourth powers allowed him to calculate the volume of a paraboloid 14 India In the 14th century Indian mathematicians gave a non rigorous method resembling differentiation applicable to some trigonometric functions Madhava of Sangamagrama and the Kerala School of Astronomy and Mathematics thereby stated components of calculus A complete theory encompassing these components is now well known in the Western world as the Taylor series or infinite series approximations 15 16 However they were not able to combine many differing ideas under the two unifying themes of the derivative and the integral show the connection between the two and turn calculus into the great problem solving tool we have today 14 Modern Johannes Kepler s work Stereometrica Doliorum formed the basis of integral calculus 17 Kepler developed a method to calculate the area of an ellipse by adding up the lengths of many radii drawn from a focus of the ellipse 18 A significant work was a treatise the origin being Kepler s methods 18 written by Bonaventura Cavalieri who argued that volumes and areas should be computed as the sums of the volumes and areas of infinitesimally thin cross sections The ideas were similar to Archimedes in The Method but this treatise is believed to have been lost in the 13th century and was only rediscovered in the early 20th century and so would have been unknown to Cavalieri Cavalieri s work was not well respected since his methods could lead to erroneous results and the infinitesimal quantities he introduced were disreputable at first The formal study of calculus brought together Cavalieri s infinitesimals with the calculus of finite differences developed in Europe at around the same time Pierre de Fermat claiming that he borrowed from Diophantus introduced the concept of adequality which represented equality up to an infinitesimal error term 19 The combination was achieved by John Wallis Isaac Barrow and James Gregory the latter two proving predecessors to the second fundamental theorem of calculus around 1670 20 21 The product rule and chain rule 22 the notions of higher derivatives and Taylor series 23 and of analytic functions 24 were used by Isaac Newton in an idiosyncratic notation which he applied to solve problems of mathematical physics In his works Newton rephrased his ideas to suit the mathematical idiom of the time replacing calculations with infinitesimals by equivalent geometrical arguments which were considered beyond reproach He used the methods of calculus to solve the problem of planetary motion the shape of the surface of a rotating fluid the oblateness of the earth the motion of a weight sliding on a cycloid and many other problems discussed in his Principia Mathematica 1687 In other work he developed series expansions for functions including fractional and irrational powers and it was clear that he understood the principles of the Taylor series He did not publish all these discoveries and at this time infinitesimal methods were still considered disreputable 25 Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was the first to state clearly the rules of calculus Isaac Newton developed the use of calculus in his laws of motion and gravitation These ideas were arranged into a true calculus of infinitesimals by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz who was originally accused of plagiarism by Newton 26 He is now regarded as an independent inventor of and contributor to calculus His contribution was to provide a clear set of rules for working with infinitesimal quantities allowing the computation of second and higher derivatives and providing the product rule and chain rule in their differential and integral forms Unlike Newton Leibniz put painstaking effort into his choices of notation 27 Today Leibniz and Newton are usually both given credit for independently inventing and developing calculus Newton was the first to apply calculus to general physics and Leibniz developed much of the notation used in calculus today 28 51 52 The basic insights that both Newton and Leibniz provided were the laws of differentiation and integration emphasizing that differentiation and integration are inverse processes second and higher derivatives and the notion of an approximating polynomial series When Newton and Leibniz first published their results there was great controversy over which mathematician and therefore which country deserved credit Newton derived his results first later to be published in his Method of Fluxions but Leibniz published his Nova Methodus pro Maximis et Minimis first Newton claimed Leibniz stole ideas from his unpublished notes which Newton had shared with a few members of the Royal Society This controversy divided English speaking mathematicians from continental European mathematicians for many years to the detriment of English mathematics 29 A careful examination of the papers of Leibniz and Newton shows that they arrived at their results independently with Leibniz starting first with integration and Newton with differentiation It is Leibniz however who gave the new discipline its name Newton called his calculus the science of fluxions a term that endured in English schools into the 19th century 30 100 The first complete treatise on calculus to be written in English and use the Leibniz notation was not published until 1815 31 Since the time of Leibniz and Newton many mathematicians have contributed to the continuing development of calculus One of the first and most complete works on both infinitesimal and integral calculus was written in 1748 by Maria Gaetana Agnesi 32 33 Maria Gaetana Agnesi Foundations In calculus foundations refers to the rigorous development of the subject from axioms and definitions In early calculus the use of infinitesimal quantities was thought unrigorous and was fiercely criticized by a number of authors most notably Michel Rolle and Bishop Berkeley Berkeley famously described infinitesimals as the ghosts of departed quantities in his book The Analyst in 1734 Working out a rigorous foundation for calculus occupied mathematicians for much of the century following Newton and Leibniz and is still to some extent an active area of research today 34 Several mathematicians including Maclaurin tried to prove the soundness of using infinitesimals but it would not be until 150 years later when due to the work of Cauchy and Weierstrass a way was finally found to avoid mere notions of infinitely small quantities 35 The foundations of differential and integral calculus had been laid In Cauchy s Cours d Analyse we find a broad range of foundational approaches including a definition of continuity in terms of infinitesimals and a somewhat imprecise prototype of an e d definition of limit in the definition of differentiation 36 In his work Weierstrass formalized the concept of limit and eliminated infinitesimals although his definition can actually validate nilsquare infinitesimals Following the work of Weierstrass it eventually became common to base calculus on limits instead of infinitesimal quantities though the subject is still occasionally called infinitesimal calculus Bernhard Riemann used these ideas to give a precise definition of the integral 37 It was also during this period that the ideas of calculus were generalized to the complex plane with the development of complex analysis 38 In modern mathematics the foundations of calculus are included in the field of real analysis which contains full definitions and proofs of the theorems of calculus The reach of calculus has also been greatly extended Henri Lebesgue invented measure theory based on earlier developments by Emile Borel and used it to define integrals of all but the most pathological functions 39 Laurent Schwartz introduced distributions which can be used to take the derivative of any function whatsoever 40 Limits are not the only rigorous approach to the foundation of calculus Another way is to use Abraham Robinson s non standard analysis Robinson s approach developed in the 1960s uses technical machinery from mathematical logic to augment the real number system with infinitesimal and infinite numbers as in the original Newton Leibniz conception The resulting numbers are called hyperreal numbers and they can be used to give a Leibniz like development of the usual rules of calculus 41 There is also smooth infinitesimal analysis which differs from non standard analysis in that it mandates neglecting higher power infinitesimals during derivations 34 Based on the ideas of F W Lawvere and employing the methods of category theory smooth infinitesimal analysis views all functions as being continuous and incapable of being expressed in terms of discrete entities One aspect of this formulation is that the law of excluded middle does not hold 34 The law of excluded middle is also rejected in constructive mathematics a branch of mathematics that insists that proofs of the existence of a number function or other mathematical object should give a construction of the object Reformulations of calculus in a constructive framework are generally part of the subject of constructive analysis 34 Significance While many of the ideas of calculus had been developed earlier in Greece China India Iraq Persia and Japan the use of calculus began in Europe during the 17th century when Newton and Leibniz built on the work of earlier mathematicians to introduce its basic principles 11 25 42 The Hungarian polymath John von Neumann wrote of this work The calculus was the first achievement of modern mathematics and it is difficult to overestimate its importance I think it defines more unequivocally than anything else the inception of modern mathematics and the system of mathematical analysis which is its logical development still constitutes the greatest technical advance in exact thinking 43 Applications of differential calculus include computations involving velocity and acceleration the slope of a curve and optimization 44 341 453 Applications of integral calculus include computations involving area volume arc length center of mass work and pressure 44 685 700 More advanced applications include power series and Fourier series Calculus is also used to gain a more precise understanding of the nature of space time and motion For centuries mathematicians and philosophers wrestled with paradoxes involving division by zero or sums of infinitely many numbers These questions arise in the study of motion and area The ancient Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea gave several famous examples of such paradoxes Calculus provides tools especially the limit and the infinite series that resolve the paradoxes 45 PrinciplesLimits and infinitesimals Main articles Limit of a function and Infinitesimal Calculus is usually developed by working with very small quantities Historically the first method of doing so was by infinitesimals These are objects which can be treated like real numbers but which are in some sense infinitely small For example an infinitesimal number could be greater than 0 but less than any number in the sequence 1 1 2 1 3 and thus less than any positive real number From this point of view calculus is a collection of techniques for manipulating infinitesimals The symbols d x displaystyle dx and d y displaystyle dy were taken to be infinitesimal and the derivative d y d x displaystyle dy dx was their ratio 34 The infinitesimal approach fell out of favor in the 19th century because it was difficult to make the notion of an infinitesimal precise In the late 19th century infinitesimals were replaced within academia by the epsilon delta approach to limits Limits describe the behavior of a function at a certain input in terms of its values at nearby inputs They capture small scale behavior using the intrinsic structure of the real number system as a metric space with the least upper bound property In this treatment calculus is a collection of techniques for manipulating certain limits Infinitesimals get replaced by sequences of smaller and smaller numbers and the infinitely small behavior of a function is found by taking the limiting behavior for these sequences Limits were thought to provide a more rigorous foundation for calculus and for this reason they became the standard approach during the 20th century However the infinitesimal concept was revived in the 20th century with the introduction of non standard analysis and smooth infinitesimal analysis which provided solid foundations for the manipulation of infinitesimals 34 Differential calculus Main article Differential calculus Tangent line at x0 f x0 The derivative f x of a curve at a point is the slope rise over run of the line tangent to that curve at that point Differential calculus is the study of the definition properties and applications of the derivative of a function The process of finding the derivative is called differentiation Given a function and a point in the domain the derivative at that point is a way of encoding the small scale behavior of the function near that point By finding the derivative of a function at every point in its domain it is possible to produce a new function called the derivative function or just the derivative of the original function In formal terms the derivative is a linear operator which takes a function as its input and produces a second function as its output This is more abstract than many of the processes studied in elementary algebra where functions usually input a number and output another number For example if the doubling function is given the input three then it outputs six and if the squaring function is given the input three then it outputs nine The derivative however can take the squaring function as an input This means that the derivative takes all the information of the squaring function such as that two is sent to four three is sent to nine four is sent to sixteen and so on and uses this information to produce another function The function produced by differentiating the squaring function turns out to be the doubling function 28 32 In more explicit terms the doubling function may be denoted by g x 2x and the squaring function by f x x2 The derivative now takes the function f x defined by the expression x2 as an input that is all the information such as that two is sent to four three is sent to nine four is sent to sixteen and so on and uses this information to output another function the function g x 2x as will turn out In Lagrange s notation the symbol for a derivative is an apostrophe like mark called a prime Thus the derivative of a function called f is denoted by f pronounced f prime or f dash For instance if f x x2 is the squaring function then f x 2x is its derivative the doubling function g from above If the input of the function represents time then the derivative represents change with respect to time For example if f is a function that takes a time as input and gives the position of a ball at that time as output then the derivative of f is how the position is changing in time that is it is the velocity of the ball 28 18 20 If a function is linear that is if the graph of the function is a straight line then the function can be written as y mx b where x is the independent variable y is the dependent variable b is the y intercept and m rise run change in y change in x D y D x displaystyle m frac text rise text run frac text change in y text change in x frac Delta y Delta x This gives an exact value for the slope of a straight line 46 6 If the graph of the function is not a straight line however then the change in y divided by the change in x varies Derivatives give an exact meaning to the notion of change in output with respect to change in input To be concrete let f be a function and fix a point a in the domain of f a f a is a point on the graph of the function If h is a number close to zero then a h is a number close to a Therefore a h f a h is close to a f a The slope between these two points is m f a h f a a h a f a h f a h displaystyle m frac f a h f a a h a frac f a h f a h This expression is called a difference quotient A line through two points on a curve is called a secant line so m is the slope of the secant line between a f a and a h f a h The secant line is only an approximation to the behavior of the function at the point a because it does not account for what happens between a and a h It is not possible to discover the behavior at a by setting h to zero because this would require dividing by zero which is undefined The derivative is defined by taking the limit as h tends to zero meaning that it considers the behavior of f for all small values of h and extracts a consistent value for the case when h equals zero lim h 0 f a h f a h displaystyle lim h to 0 f a h f a over h Geometrically the derivative is the slope of the tangent line to the graph of f at a The tangent line is a limit of secant lines just as the derivative is a limit of difference quotients For this reason the derivative is sometimes called the slope of the function f 46 61 63 Here is a particular example the derivative of the squaring function at the input 3 Let f x x2 be the squaring function The derivative f x of a curve at a point is the slope of the line tangent to that curve at that point This slope is determined by considering the limiting value of the slopes of secant lines Here the function involved drawn in red is f x x3 x The tangent line in green which passes through the point 3 2 15 8 has a slope of 23 4 Note that the vertical and horizontal scales in this image are different f 3 lim h 0 3 h 2 3 2 h lim h 0 9 6 h h 2 9 h lim h 0 6 h h 2 h lim h 0 6 h 6 displaystyle begin aligned f 3 amp lim h to 0 3 h 2 3 2 over h amp lim h to 0 9 6h h 2 9 over h amp lim h to 0 6h h 2 over h amp lim h to 0 6 h amp 6 end aligned The slope of the tangent line to the squaring function at the point 3 9 is 6 that is to say it is going up six times as fast as it is going to the right The limit process just described can be performed for any point in the domain of the squaring function This defines the derivative function of the squaring function or just the derivative of the squaring function for short A computation similar to the one above shows that the derivative of the squaring function is the doubling function 46 63 Leibniz notation Main article Leibniz s notation A common notation introduced by Leibniz for the derivative in the example above is y x 2 d y d x 2 x displaystyle begin aligned y amp x 2 frac dy dx amp 2x end aligned In an approach based on limits the symbol dy dx is to be interpreted not as the quotient of two numbers but as a shorthand for the limit computed above 46 74 Leibniz however did intend it to represent the quotient of two infinitesimally small numbers dy being the infinitesimally small change in y caused by an infinitesimally small change dx applied to x We can also think of d dx as a differentiation operator which takes a function as an input and gives another function the derivative as the output For example d d x x 2 2 x displaystyle frac d dx x 2 2x In this usage the dx in the denominator is read as with respect to x 46 79 Another example of correct notation could be g t t 2 2 t 4 d d t g t 2 t 2 displaystyle begin aligned g t amp t 2 2t 4 d over dt g t amp 2t 2 end aligned Even when calculus is developed using limits rather than infinitesimals it is common to manipulate symbols like dx and dy as if they were real numbers although it is possible to avoid such manipulations they are sometimes notationally convenient in expressing operations such as the total derivative Integral calculus Main article Integral Integration can be thought of as measuring the area under a curve defined by f x between two points here a and b A sequence of midpoint Riemann sums over a regular partition of an interval the total area of the rectangles converges to the integral of the function Integral calculus is the study of the definitions properties and applications of two related concepts the indefinite integral and the definite integral The process of finding the value of an integral is called integration 44 508 The indefinite integral also known as the antiderivative is the inverse operation to the derivative 46 163 165 F is an indefinite integral of f when f is a derivative of F This use of lower and upper case letters for a function and its indefinite integral is common in calculus The definite integral inputs a function and outputs a number which gives the algebraic sum of areas between the graph of the input and the x axis The technical definition of the definite integral involves the limit of a sum of areas of rectangles called a Riemann sum 47 282 A motivating example is the distance traveled in a given time 46 153 If the speed is constant only multiplication is needed D i s t a n c e S p e e d T i m e displaystyle mathrm Distance mathrm Speed cdot mathrm Time But if the speed changes a more powerful method of finding the distance is necessary One such method is to approximate the distance traveled by breaking up the time into many short intervals of time then multiplying the time elapsed in each interval by one of the speeds in that interval and then taking the sum a Riemann sum of the approximate distance traveled in each interval The basic idea is that if only a short time elapses then the speed will stay more or less the same However a Riemann sum only gives an approximation of the distance traveled We must take the limit of all such Riemann sums to find the exact distance traveled When velocity is constant the total distance traveled over the given time interval can be computed by multiplying velocity and time For example travelling a steady 50 mph for 3 hours results in a total distance of 150 miles Plotting the velocity as a function of time yields a rectangle with height equal to the velocity and width equal to the time elapsed Therefore the product of velocity and time also calculates the rectangular area under the constant velocity curve 44 535 This connection between the area under a curve and distance traveled can be extended to any irregularly shaped region exhibiting a fluctuating velocity over a given time period If f x represents speed as it varies over time the distance traveled between the times represented by a and b is the area of the region between f x and the x axis between x a and x b To approximate that area an intuitive method would be to divide up the distance between a and b into a number of equal segments the length of each segment represented by the symbol Dx For each small segment we can choose one value of the function f x Call that value h Then the area of the rectangle with base Dx and height h gives the distance time Dx multiplied by speed h traveled in that segment Associated with each segment is the average value of the function above it f x h The sum of all such rectangles gives an approximation of the area between the axis and the curve which is an approximation of the total distance traveled A smaller value for Dx will give more rectangles and in most cases a better approximation but for an exact answer we need to take a limit as Dx approaches zero 44 512 522 The symbol of integration is displaystyle int an elongated S chosen to suggest summation 44 529 The definite integral is written as a b f x d x displaystyle int a b f x dx and is read the integral from a to b of f of x with respect to x The Leibniz notation dx is intended to suggest dividing the area under the curve into an infinite number of rectangles so that their width Dx becomes the infinitesimally small dx 28 44 The indefinite integral or antiderivative is written f x d x displaystyle int f x dx Functions differing by only a constant have the same derivative and it can be shown that the antiderivative of a given function is actually a family of functions differing only by a constant 47 326 Since the derivative of the function y x2 C where C is any constant is y 2x the antiderivative of the latter is given by 2 x d x x 2 C displaystyle int 2x dx x 2 C The unspecified constant C present in the indefinite integral or antiderivative is known as the constant of integration 48 135 Fundamental theorem Main article Fundamental theorem of calculus The fundamental theorem of calculus states that differentiation and integration are inverse operations 47 290 More precisely it relates the values of antiderivatives to definite integrals Because it is usually easier to compute an antiderivative than to apply the definition of a definite integral the fundamental theorem of calculus provides a practical way of computing definite integrals It can also be interpreted as a precise statement of the fact that differentiation is the inverse of integration The fundamental theorem of calculus states If a function f is continuous on the interval a b and if F is a function whose derivative is f on the interval a b then a b f x d x F b F a displaystyle int a b f x dx F b F a Furthermore for every x in the interval a b d d x a x f t d t f x displaystyle frac d dx int a x f t dt f x This realization made by both Newton and Leibniz was key to the proliferation of analytic results after their work became known The extent to which Newton and Leibniz were influenced by immediate predecessors and particularly what Leibniz may have learned from the work of Isaac Barrow is difficult to determine because of the priority dispute between them 49 The fundamental theorem provides an algebraic method of computing many definite integrals without performing limit processes by finding formulae for antiderivatives It is also a prototype solution of a differential equation Differential equations relate an unknown function to its derivatives and are ubiquitous in the sciences 50 351 352 Applications The logarithmic spiral of the Nautilus shell is a classical image used to depict the growth and change related to calculus Calculus is used in every branch of the physical sciences 51 1 actuarial science computer science statistics engineering economics business medicine demography and in other fields wherever a problem can be mathematically modeled and an optimal solution is desired 52 It allows one to go from non constant rates of change to the total change or vice versa and many times in studying a problem we know one and are trying to find the other 53 Calculus can be used in conjunction with other mathematical disciplines For example it can be used with linear algebra to find the best fit linear approximation for a set of points in a domain Or it can be used in probability theory to determine the expectation value of a continuous random variable given a probability density function 54 37 In analytic geometry the study of graphs of functions calculus is used to find high points and low points maxima and minima slope concavity and inflection points Calculus is also used to find approximate solutions to equations in practice it is the standard way to solve differential equations and do root finding in most applications Examples are methods such as Newton s method fixed point iteration and linear approximation For instance spacecraft use a variation of the Euler method to approximate curved courses within zero gravity environments Physics makes particular use of calculus all concepts in classical mechanics and electromagnetism are related through calculus The mass of an object of known density the moment of inertia of objects and the potential energies due to gravitational and electromagnetic forces can all be found by the use of calculus An example of the use of calculus in mechanics is Newton s second law of motion which states that the derivative of an object s momentum with respect to time equals the net force upon it Alternatively Newton s second law can be expressed by saying that the net force is equal to the object s mass times its acceleration which is the time derivative of velocity and thus the second time derivative of spatial position Starting from knowing how an object is accelerating we use calculus to derive its path 55 Maxwell s theory of electromagnetism and Einstein s theory of general relativity are also expressed in the language of differential calculus 56 57 52 55 Chemistry also uses calculus in determining reaction rates 58 599 and in studying radioactive decay 58 814 In biology population dynamics starts with reproduction and death rates to model population changes 59 60 631 Green s theorem which gives the relationship between a line integral around a simple closed curve C and a double integral over the plane region D bounded by C is applied in an instrument known as a planimeter which is used to calculate the area of a flat surface on a drawing 61 For example it can be used to calculate the amount of area taken up by an irregularly shaped flower bed or swimming pool when designing the layout of a piece of property In the realm of medicine calculus can be used to find the optimal branching angle of a blood vessel so as to maximize flow 62 Calculus can be applied to understand how quickly a drug is eliminated from a body or how quickly a cancerous tumour grows 63 In economics calculus allows for the determination of maximal profit by providing a way to easily calculate both marginal cost and marginal revenue 64 387 See alsoMain article Outline of calculus Glossary of calculus List of calculus topics List of derivatives and integrals in alternative calculi List of differentiation identities Publications in calculus Table of integralsReferences DeBaggis Henry F Miller Kenneth S 1966 Foundations of the Calculus Philadelphia Saunders OCLC 527896 Boyer Carl B 1959 The History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development New York Dover OCLC 643872 Bardi Jason Socrates 2006 The Calculus Wars Newton Leibniz and the Greatest Mathematical Clash of All Time New York Thunder s Mouth Press ISBN 1 56025 706 7 Hoffmann Laurence D Bradley Gerald L 2004 Calculus for Business Economics and the Social and Life Sciences 8th ed Boston McGraw Hill ISBN 0 07 242432 X See for example history Were metered taxis busy roaming Imperial Rome Skeptics Stack Exchange 17 June 2020 Retrieved 13 February 2022 Cousineau Phil 15 March 2010 Wordcatcher An Odyssey into the World of Weird and Wonderful Words Simon and Schuster p 58 ISBN 978 1 57344 550 4 OCLC 811492876 calculus Oxford English Dictionary Online ed Oxford University Press Subscription or participating institution membership required Kline Morris 16 August 1990 Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times Volume 1 Oxford University Press pp 15 21 ISBN 978 0 19 506135 2 Imhausen Annette 2016 Mathematics in Ancient Egypt A Contextual History Princeton University Press p 112 ISBN 978 1 4008 7430 9 OCLC 934433864 See for example Powers J 2020 Did Archimedes do calculus PDF Mathematical Association of America Archived PDF from the original on 9 October 2022 Jullien Vincent 2015 Archimedes and Indivisibles Seventeenth Century Indivisibles Revisited Science Networks Historical Studies Vol 49 Cham Springer International Publishing pp 451 457 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 00131 9 18 ISBN 978 3 319 00130 2 Plummer Brad 9 August 2006 Modern X ray technology reveals Archimedes math theory under forged painting Stanford University Retrieved 28 February 2022 Archimedes 2004 The Works of Archimedes Volume 1 The Two Books On the Sphere and the Cylinder Translated by Netz Reviel Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 66160 7 Gray Shirley Waldman Cye H 20 October 2018 Archimedes Redux Center of Mass Applications from The Method The College Mathematics Journal 49 5 346 352 doi 10 1080 07468342 2018 1524647 ISSN 0746 8342 S2CID 125411353 Dun Liu Fan Dainian Cohen Robert Sonne 1966 A comparison of Archimdes and Liu Hui s studies of circles Chinese studies in the history and philosophy of science and technology Vol 130 Springer p 279 ISBN 978 0 7923 3463 7 pp 279ff a b Dainian Fan R S Cohen 1996 Chinese studies in the history and philosophy of science and technology Dordrecht Kluwer Academic Publishers ISBN 0 7923 3463 9 OCLC 32272485 Katz Victor J 2008 A history of mathematics 3rd ed Boston MA Addison Wesley p 203 ISBN 978 0 321 38700 4 Zill Dennis G Wright Scott Wright Warren S 2009 Calculus Early Transcendentals 3 ed Jones amp Bartlett Learning p xxvii ISBN 978 0 7637 5995 7 Extract of page 27 a b Katz Victor J June 1995 Ideas of Calculus in Islam and India Mathematics Magazine 68 3 163 174 doi 10 1080 0025570X 1995 11996307 ISSN 0025 570X JSTOR 2691411 O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F An overview of Indian mathematics MacTutor History of Mathematics archive University of St Andrews Plofker Kim 2009 Mathematics in India Princeton Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 3407 5 OCLC 650305544 Johannes Kepler His Life His Laws and Times NASA 24 September 2016 Retrieved 10 June 2021 a b Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Infinitesimal Calculus History Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 14 11th ed Cambridge University Press p 537 Weil Andre 1984 Number theory An approach through History from Hammurapi to Legendre Boston Birkhauser Boston p 28 ISBN 0 8176 4565 9 Hollingdale Stuart 1991 Review of Before Newton The Life and Times of Isaac Barrow Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 45 2 277 279 doi 10 1098 rsnr 1991 0027 ISSN 0035 9149 JSTOR 531707 S2CID 165043307 The most interesting to us are Lectures X XII in which Barrow comes close to providing a geometrical demonstration of the fundamental theorem of the calculus He did not realize however the full significance of his results and his rejection of algebra means that his work must remain a piece of mid 17th century geometrical analysis of mainly historic interest Bressoud David M 2011 Historical Reflections on Teaching the Fundamental Theorem of Integral Calculus The American Mathematical Monthly 118 2 99 doi 10 4169 amer math monthly 118 02 099 S2CID 21473035 Blank Brian E Krantz Steven George 2006 Calculus Single Variable Volume 1 Illustrated ed Springer Science amp Business Media p 248 ISBN 978 1 931914 59 8 Ferraro Giovanni 2007 The Rise and Development of the Theory of Series up to the Early 1820s Illustrated ed Springer Science amp Business Media p 87 ISBN 978 0 387 73468 2 Guicciardini Niccolo 2005 Isaac Newton Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica first edition 1687 Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640 1940 Elsevier pp 59 87 doi 10 1016 b978 044450871 3 50086 3 ISBN 978 0 444 50871 3 Newton immediately realised that quadrature problems the inverse problems could be tackled via infinite series as we would say nowadays by expanding the integrand in power series and integrating term wise a b Grattan Guinness I ed 2005 Landmark writings in Western mathematics 1640 1940 Amsterdam Elsevier ISBN 0 444 50871 6 OCLC 60416766 Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm 2008 The Early Mathematical Manuscripts of Leibniz Cosimo Inc p 228 ISBN 978 1 605 20533 5 Mazur Joseph 2014 Enlightening Symbols A Short History of Mathematical Notation and Its Hidden Powers Princeton University Press p 166 ISBN 978 0 691 17337 5 Leibniz understood symbols their conceptual powers as well as their limitations He would spend years experimenting with some adjusting rejecting and corresponding with everyone he knew consulting with as many of the leading mathematicians of the time who were sympathetic to his fastidiousness a b c d Frautschi Steven C Olenick Richard P Apostol Tom M Goodstein David L 2007 The Mechanical Universe Mechanics and Heat Advanced ed Cambridge Cambridgeshire Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 71590 4 OCLC 227002144 Schrader Dorothy V 1962 The Newton Leibniz controversy concerning the discovery of the calculus The Mathematics Teacher 55 5 385 396 doi 10 5951 MT 55 5 0385 ISSN 0025 5769 JSTOR 27956626 Stedall Jacqueline 2012 The History of Mathematics A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 191 63396 6 Stenhouse Brigitte May 2020 Mary Somerville s early contributions to the circulation of differential calculus Historia Mathematica 51 1 25 doi 10 1016 j hm 2019 12 001 S2CID 214472568 Allaire Patricia R 2007 Foreword A Biography of Maria Gaetana Agnesi an Eighteenth century Woman Mathematician By Cupillari Antonella Lewiston New York Edwin Mellen Press p iii ISBN 978 0 7734 5226 8 Unlu Elif April 1995 Maria Gaetana Agnesi Agnes Scott College a b c d e f Bell John L 6 September 2013 Continuity and Infinitesimals Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 20 February 2022 Russell Bertrand 1946 History of Western Philosophy London George Allen amp Unwin Ltd p 857 The great mathematicians of the seventeenth century were optimistic and anxious for quick results consequently they left the foundations of analytical geometry and the infinitesimal calculus insecure Leibniz believed in actual infinitesimals but although this belief suited his metaphysics it had no sound basis in mathematics Weierstrass soon after the middle of the nineteenth century showed how to establish the calculus without infinitesimals and thus at last made it logically secure Next came Georg Cantor who developed the theory of continuity and infinite number Continuity had been until he defined it a vague word convenient for philosophers like Hegel who wished to introduce metaphysical muddles into mathematics Cantor gave a precise significance to the word and showed that continuity as he defined it was the concept needed by mathematicians and physicists By this means a great deal of mysticism such as that of Bergson was rendered antiquated Grabiner Judith V 1981 The Origins of Cauchy s Rigorous Calculus Cambridge MIT Press ISBN 978 0 387 90527 3 Archibald Tom 2008 The Development of Rigor in Mathematical Analysis In Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June Leader Imre eds The Princeton Companion to Mathematics Princeton University Press pp 117 129 ISBN 978 0 691 11880 2 OCLC 682200048 Rice Adrian 2008 A Chronology of Mathematical Events In Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June Leader Imre eds The Princeton Companion to Mathematics Princeton University Press pp 1010 1014 ISBN 978 0 691 11880 2 OCLC 682200048 Siegmund Schultze Reinhard 2008 Henri Lebesgue In Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June Leader Imre eds The Princeton Companion to Mathematics Princeton University Press pp 796 797 ISBN 978 0 691 11880 2 OCLC 682200048 Barany Michael J Paumier Anne Sandrine Lutzen Jesper November 2017 From Nancy to Copenhagen to the World The internationalization of Laurent Schwartz and his theory of distributions Historia Mathematica 44 4 367 394 doi 10 1016 j hm 2017 04 002 Daubin Joseph W 2008 Abraham Robinson In Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June Leader Imre eds The Princeton Companion to Mathematics Princeton University Press pp 822 823 ISBN 978 0 691 11880 2 OCLC 682200048 Kline Morris 1990 Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times v 3 New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 977048 9 OCLC 726764443 von Neumann J 1947 The Mathematician In Heywood R B ed The Works of the Mind University of Chicago Press pp 180 196 Reprinted in Brody F Vamos T eds 1995 The Neumann Compendium World Scientific Publishing Co Pte Ltd pp 618 626 ISBN 981 02 2201 7 a b c d e f Herman Edwin Strang Gilbert et al 2017 Calculus Volume 1 Houston Texas OpenStax ISBN 978 1 938168 02 4 OCLC 1022848630 Cheng Eugenia 2017 Beyond Infinity An Expedition to the Outer Limits of Mathematics Basic Books pp 206 210 ISBN 978 1 541 64413 7 OCLC 1003309980 a b c d e f g Salas Saturnino L Hille Einar 1971 Calculus one and several variables Waltham Mass Xerox College Pub OCLC 135567 a b c Hughes Hallett Deborah McCallum William G Gleason Andrew M et al 2013 Calculus Single and Multivariable 6th ed Hoboken NJ Wiley ISBN 978 0 470 88861 2 OCLC 794034942 Moebs William Ling Samuel J Sanny Jeff et al 2022 University Physics Volume 1 OpenStax ISBN 978 1 947172 20 3 OCLC 961352944 See for example Mahoney Michael S 1990 Barrow s mathematics Between ancients and moderns In Feingold M ed Before Newton Cambridge University Press pp 179 249 ISBN 978 0 521 06385 2 Feingold M June 1993 Newton Leibniz and Barrow Too An Attempt at a Reinterpretation Isis 84 2 310 338 Bibcode 1993Isis 84 310F doi 10 1086 356464 ISSN 0021 1753 S2CID 144019197 Probst Siegmund 2015 Leibniz as Reader and Second Inventor The Cases of Barrow and Mengoli In Goethe Norma B Beeley Philip Rabouin David eds G W Leibniz Interrelations Between Mathematics and Philosophy Archimedes New Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology Vol 41 Springer pp 111 134 ISBN 978 9 401 79663 7 Herman Edwin Strang Gilbert et al 2017 Calculus Volume 2 Houston Texas OpenStax ISBN 978 1 5066 9807 6 OCLC 1127050110 Baron Margaret E 1969 The origins of the infinitesimal calculus 1st ed Oxford ISBN 978 1 483 28092 9 OCLC 892067655 Kayaspor Ali 28 August 2022 The Beautiful Applications of Calculus in Real Life Medium Retrieved 26 September 2022 Hu Zhiying 14 April 2021 The Application and Value of Calculus in Daily Life 2021 2nd Asia Pacific Conference on Image Processing Electronics and Computers Ipec2021 Dalian China ACM 562 564 doi 10 1145 3452446 3452583 ISBN 978 1 4503 8981 5 S2CID 233384462 Kardar Mehran 2007 Statistical Physics of Particles Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 87342 0 OCLC 860391091 Garber Elizabeth 2001 The language of physics the calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe 1750 1914 Springer Science Business Media ISBN 978 1 4612 7272 4 OCLC 921230825 Hall Graham 2008 Maxwell s Electromagnetic Theory and Special Relativity Philosophical Transactions Mathematical Physical and Engineering Sciences 366 1871 1849 1860 Bibcode 2008RSPTA 366 1849H doi 10 1098 rsta 2007 2192 ISSN 1364 503X JSTOR 25190792 PMID 18218598 S2CID 502776 Gbur Greg 2011 Mathematical Methods for Optical Physics and Engineering Cambridge U K Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 511 91510 9 OCLC 704518582 a b Atkins Peter W Jones Loretta 2010 Chemical principles the quest for insight 5th ed New York W H Freeman ISBN 978 1 4292 1955 6 OCLC 501943698 Murray J D 2002 Mathematical biology I Introduction 3rd ed New York Springer ISBN 0 387 22437 8 OCLC 53165394 Neuhauser Claudia 2011 Calculus for biology and medicine 3rd ed Boston Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 321 64468 8 OCLC 426065941 Gatterdam R W 1981 The planimeter as an example of Green s theorem The American Mathematical Monthly 88 9 701 704 doi 10 2307 2320679 JSTOR 2320679 Adam John A June 2011 Blood Vessel Branching Beyond the Standard Calculus Problem Mathematics Magazine 84 3 196 207 doi 10 4169 math mag 84 3 196 ISSN 0025 570X S2CID 8259705 Mackenzie Dana 2004 Mathematical Modeling and Cancer PDF SIAM News 37 1 Archived PDF from the original on 9 October 2022 Perloff Jeffrey M 2018 Microeconomics Theory and Applications with Calculus 4th global ed Harlow United Kingdom ISBN 978 1 292 15446 6 OCLC 1064041906 Further readingAdams Robert A 1999 Calculus A complete course ISBN 978 0 201 39607 2 Albers Donald J Anderson Richard D Loftsgaarden Don O eds 1986 Undergraduate Programs in the Mathematics and Computer Sciences The 1985 1986 Survey Mathematical Association of America Anton Howard Bivens Irl Davis Stephen 2002 Calculus John Willey and Sons Pte Ltd ISBN 978 81 265 1259 1 Apostol Tom M 1967 Calculus Volume 1 One Variable Calculus with an Introduction to Linear Algebra Wiley ISBN 978 0 471 00005 1 Apostol Tom M 1969 Calculus Volume 2 Multi Variable Calculus and Linear Algebra with Applications Wiley ISBN 978 0 471 00007 5 Bell John Lane 1998 A Primer of Infinitesimal Analysis Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 62401 5 Uses synthetic differential geometry and nilpotent infinitesimals Boelkins M 2012 Active Calculus a free open text PDF Archived from the original on 30 May 2013 Retrieved 1 February 2013 Boyer Carl Benjamin 1959 1949 The History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development Dover ed Hafner ISBN 0 486 60509 4 Cajori Florian September 1923 The History of Notations of the Calculus Annals of Mathematics 2nd Series 25 1 1 46 doi 10 2307 1967725 hdl 2027 mdp 39015017345896 JSTOR 1967725 Courant Richard Introduction to calculus and analysis 1 ISBN 978 3 540 65058 4 Gonick Larry 2012 The Cartoon Guide to Calculus William Morrow ISBN 978 0 061 68909 3 OCLC 932781617 Keisler H J 2000 Elementary Calculus An Approach Using Infinitesimals Retrieved 29 August 2010 from http www math wisc edu keisler calc html Landau Edmund 2001 Differential and Integral Calculus American Mathematical Society ISBN 0 8218 2830 4 Lebedev Leonid P Cloud Michael J 2004 The Tools of Calculus Approximating Perfection a Mathematician s Journey into the World of Mechanics Princeton University Press Larson Ron Edwards Bruce H 2010 Calculus 9th ed Brooks Cole Cengage Learning ISBN 978 0 547 16702 2 McQuarrie Donald A 2003 Mathematical Methods for Scientists and Engineers University Science Books ISBN 978 1 891389 24 5 Pickover Cliff 2003 Calculus and Pizza A Math Cookbook for the Hungry Mind ISBN 978 0 471 26987 8 Salas Saturnino L Hille Einar Etgen Garret J 2007 Calculus One and Several Variables 10th ed Wiley ISBN 978 0 471 69804 3 Spivak Michael September 1994 Calculus Publish or Perish publishing ISBN 978 0 914098 89 8 Steen Lynn Arthur ed 1988 Calculus for a New Century A Pump Not a Filter Mathematical Association of America ISBN 0 88385 058 3 Stewart James 2012 Calculus Early Transcendentals 7th ed Brooks Cole Cengage Learning ISBN 978 0 538 49790 9 Thomas George Brinton Finney Ross L Weir Maurice D 1996 Calculus and Analytic Geometry Part 1 Addison Wesley ISBN 978 0 201 53174 9 Thomas George B Weir Maurice D Hass Joel Giordano Frank R 2008 Calculus 11th ed Addison Wesley ISBN 978 0 321 48987 6 Thompson Silvanus P Gardner Martin 1998 Calculus Made Easy ISBN 978 0 312 18548 0 External linksCalculus at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Media from Commons News from Wikinews Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Textbooks from Wikibooks Resources from Wikiversity Calculus Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Weisstein Eric W Calculus MathWorld Topics on Calculus at PlanetMath Calculus Made Easy 1914 by Silvanus P Thompson Full text in PDF Calculus on In Our Time at the BBC Calculus org The Calculus page at University of California Davis contains resources and links to other sites Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics Calculus amp Analysis The Role of Calculus in College Mathematics from ERICDigests org OpenCourseWare Calculus from the Massachusetts Institute of Technology Infinitesimal Calculus an article on its historical development in Encyclopedia of Mathematics ed Michiel Hazewinkel Daniel Kleitman MIT Calculus for Beginners and Artists Calculus training materials at imomath com in English and Arabic The Excursion of Calculus 1772 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Calculus amp oldid 1131527551, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.