fbpx
Wikipedia

Modern synthesis (20th century)

The modern synthesis[a] was the early 20th-century synthesis of Charles Darwin's theory of evolution and Gregor Mendel's ideas on heredity into a joint mathematical framework. Julian Huxley coined the term in his 1942 book, Evolution: The Modern Synthesis.

Several major ideas about evolution came together in the population genetics of the early 20th century to form the modern synthesis, including genetic variation, natural selection, and particulate (Mendelian) inheritance.[1] This ended the eclipse of Darwinism and supplanted a variety of non-Darwinian theories of evolution.

The synthesis combined the ideas of natural selection, Mendelian genetics, and population genetics. It also related the broad-scale macroevolution seen by palaeontologists to the small-scale microevolution of local populations.

The synthesis was defined differently by its founders, with Ernst Mayr in 1959, G. Ledyard Stebbins in 1966, and Theodosius Dobzhansky in 1974 offering differing basic postulates, though they all include natural selection, working on heritable variation supplied by mutation. Other major figures in the synthesis included E. B. Ford, Bernhard Rensch, Ivan Schmalhausen, and George Gaylord Simpson. An early event in the modern synthesis was R. A. Fisher's 1918 paper on mathematical population genetics, though William Bateson, and separately Udny Yule, had already started to show how Mendelian genetics could work in evolution in 1902.

Developments leading up to the synthesis Edit

 
Darwin's pangenesis theory. Every part of the body emits tiny gemmules which migrate to the gonads and contribute to the next generation via the fertilised egg. Changes to the body during an organism's life would be inherited, as in Lamarckism.

Darwin's evolution by natural selection, 1859 Edit

Charles Darwin's 1859 book, On the Origin of Species, convinced most biologists that evolution had occurred, but not that natural selection was its primary mechanism. In the 19th and early 20th centuries, variations of Lamarckism (inheritance of acquired characteristics), orthogenesis (progressive evolution), saltationism (evolution by jumps) and mutationism (evolution driven by mutations) were discussed as alternatives.[3] Darwin himself had sympathy for Lamarckism, but Alfred Russel Wallace advocated natural selection and totally rejected Lamarckism.[4] In 1880, Samuel Butler labelled Wallace's view neo-Darwinism.[5][6]

 
Blending inheritance, implied by pangenesis, causes the averaging out of every characteristic, which as the engineer Fleeming Jenkin pointed out, would make evolution by natural selection impossible.

The eclipse of Darwinism, 1880s onwards Edit

From the 1880s onwards, biologists grew skeptical of Darwinian evolution. This eclipse of Darwinism (in Julian Huxley's words) grew out of the weaknesses in Darwin's account, with respect to his view of inheritance. Darwin believed in blending inheritance, which implied that any new variation, even if beneficial, would be weakened by 50% at each generation, as the engineer Fleeming Jenkin noted in 1868.[7][8] This in turn meant that small variations would not survive long enough to be selected. Blending would therefore directly oppose natural selection. In addition, Darwin and others considered Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics entirely possible, and Darwin's 1868 theory of pangenesis, with contributions to the next generation (gemmules) flowing from all parts of the body, actually implied Lamarckism as well as blending.[9][10][11]

 
August Weismann's germ plasm theory. The hereditary material, the germplasm, is confined to the gonads and the gametes. Somatic cells (of the body) develop afresh in each generation from the germplasm.

Weismann's germ plasm, 1892 Edit

August Weismann's idea, set out in his 1892 book Das Keimplasma: eine Theorie der Vererbung ("The Germ Plasm: a Theory of Inheritance"),[12] was that the hereditary material, which he called the germ plasm, and the rest of the body (the soma) had a one-way relationship: the germ-plasm formed the body, but the body did not influence the germ-plasm, except indirectly in its participation in a population subject to natural selection. If correct, this made Darwin's pangenesis wrong, and Lamarckian inheritance impossible. His experiment on mice, cutting off their tails and showing that their offspring had normal tails, demonstrated that inheritance was 'hard'.[b] He argued strongly and dogmatically[14] for Darwinism and against Lamarckism, polarising opinions among other scientists. This increased anti-Darwinian feeling, contributing to its eclipse.[15][16]

Disputed beginnings Edit

Genetics, mutationism and biometrics, 1900–1918 Edit

 
William Bateson championed Mendelism.

While carrying out breeding experiments to clarify the mechanism of inheritance in 1900, Hugo de Vries and Carl Correns independently rediscovered Gregor Mendel's work. News of this reached William Bateson in England, who reported on the paper during a presentation to the Royal Horticultural Society in May 1900.[17] In Mendelian inheritance, the contributions of each parent retain their integrity, rather than blending with the contribution of the other parent. In the case of a cross between two true-breeding varieties such as Mendel's round and wrinkled peas, the first-generation offspring are all alike, in this case, all round. Allowing these to cross, the original characteristics reappear (segregation): about 3/4 of their offspring are round, 1/4 wrinkled. There is a discontinuity between the appearance of the offspring; de Vries coined the term allele for a variant form of an inherited characteristic.[18] This reinforced a major division of thought, already present in the 1890s, between gradualists who followed Darwin, and saltationists such as Bateson.[19]

The two schools were the Mendelians, such as Bateson and de Vries, who favoured mutationism, evolution driven by mutation, based on genes whose alleles segregated discretely like Mendel's peas;[20][21] and the biometric school, led by Karl Pearson and Walter Weldon. The biometricians argued vigorously against mutationism, saying that empirical evidence indicated that variation was continuous in most organisms, not discrete as Mendelism seemed to predict; they wrongly believed that Mendelism inevitably implied evolution in discontinuous jumps.[22][23]

 
Karl Pearson led the biometric school.

A traditional view is that the biometricians and the Mendelians rejected natural selection and argued for their separate theories for 20 years, the debate only resolved by the development of population genetics.[22][24] A more recent view is that Bateson, de Vries, Thomas Hunt Morgan and Reginald Punnett had by 1918 formed a synthesis of Mendelism and mutationism. The understanding achieved by these geneticists spanned the action of natural selection on alleles (alternative forms of a gene), the Hardy–Weinberg equilibrium, the evolution of continuously-varying traits (like height), and the probability that a new mutation will become fixed. In this view, the early geneticists accepted natural selection but rejected Darwin's non-Mendelian ideas about variation and heredity, and the synthesis began soon after 1900.[25][26] The traditional claim that Mendelians rejected the idea of continuous variation is false; as early as 1902, Bateson and Saunders wrote that "If there were even so few as, say, four or five pairs of possible allelomorphs, the various homo- and heterozygous combinations might, on seriation, give so near an approach to a continuous curve, that the purity of the elements would be unsuspected".[27] Also in 1902, the statistician Udny Yule showed mathematically that given multiple factors, Mendel's theory enabled continuous variation. Yule criticised Bateson's approach as confrontational,[28] but failed to prevent the Mendelians and the biometricians from falling out.[29]

Castle's hooded rats, 1911 Edit

Starting in 1906, William Castle carried out a long study of the effect of selection on coat colour in rats. The piebald or hooded pattern was recessive to the grey wild type. He crossed hooded rats with both wild and "Irish" types, and then back-crossed the offspring with pure hooded rats. The dark stripe on the back was bigger. He then tried selecting different groups for bigger or smaller stripes for 5 generations and found that it was possible to change the characteristics considerably beyond the initial range of variation. This effectively refuted de Vries's claim that continuous variation was caused by the environment and could not be inherited. By 1911, Castle noted that the results could be explained by Darwinian selection on a heritable variation of a sufficient number of Mendelian genes.[30][31][32]

Morgan's fruit flies, 1912 Edit

Thomas Hunt Morgan began his career in genetics as a saltationist and started out trying to demonstrate that mutations could produce new species in fruit flies. However, the experimental work at his lab with the fruit fly, Drosophila melanogaster[c] showed that rather than creating new species in a single step, mutations increased the supply of genetic variation in the population.[33] By 1912, after years of work on the genetics of fruit flies, Morgan showed that these insects had many small Mendelian factors (discovered as mutant flies) on which Darwinian evolution could work as if the variation was fully continuous. The way was open for geneticists to conclude that Mendelism supported Darwinism.[34]

An obstruction: Woodger's positivism, 1929 Edit

The theoretical biologist and philosopher of biology Joseph Henry Woodger led the introduction of positivism into biology with his 1929 book Biological Principles. He saw a mature science as being characterised by a framework of hypotheses that could be verified by facts established by experiments. He criticised the traditional natural history style of biology, including the study of evolution, as immature science, since it relied on narrative.[35] Woodger set out to play the role of Robert Boyle's 1661 Sceptical Chymist, intending to convert the subject of biology into a formal, unified science, and ultimately, following the Vienna Circle of logical positivists like Otto Neurath and Rudolf Carnap, to reduce biology to physics and chemistry. His efforts stimulated the biologist J. B. S. Haldane to push for the axiomatisation of biology, and by influencing thinkers such as Huxley, helped to bring about the modern synthesis.[35] The positivist climate made natural history unfashionable, and in America, research and university-level teaching on evolution declined almost to nothing by the late 1930s. The Harvard physiologist William John Crozier told his students that evolution was not even a science: "You can't experiment with two million years!"[36]

The tide of opinion turned with the adoption of mathematical modelling and controlled experimentation in population genetics, combining genetics, ecology and evolution in a framework acceptable to positivism.[37]

Elements of the synthesis Edit

Fisher and Haldane's mathematical population genetics, 1918–1930 Edit

In 1918, R. A. Fisher wrote "The Correlation between Relatives on the Supposition of Mendelian Inheritance,"[38] which showed how continuous variation could come from a number of discrete genetic loci. In this and other papers, culminating in his 1930 book The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection,[39] Fisher showed how Mendelian genetics was consistent with the idea of evolution by natural selection.[40][d]

In the 1920s, a series of papers by J. B. S. Haldane analyzed real-world examples of natural selection, such as the evolution of industrial melanism in peppered moths.[40] and showed that natural selection could work even faster than Fisher had assumed.[42] Both of these scholars, and others, such as Dobzhansky and Wright, wanted to raise biology to the standards of the physical sciences by basing it on mathematical modeling and empirical testing. Natural selection, once considered unverifiable, was becoming predictable, measurable, and testable.[43]

De Beer's embryology, 1930 Edit

The traditional view is that developmental biology played little part in the modern synthesis,[44] but in his 1930 book Embryos and Ancestors, the evolutionary embryologist Gavin de Beer anticipated evolutionary developmental biology[45] by showing that evolution could occur by heterochrony,[46] such as in the retention of juvenile features in the adult.[47] This, de Beer argued, could cause apparently sudden changes in the fossil record, since embryos fossilise poorly. As the gaps in the fossil record had been used as an argument against Darwin's gradualist evolution, de Beer's explanation supported the Darwinian position.[48] However, despite de Beer, the modern synthesis largely ignored embryonic development when explaining the form of organisms, since population genetics appeared to be an adequate explanation of how such forms evolved.[49][50][e]

Wright's adaptive landscape, 1932 Edit

 
Sewall Wright introduced the idea of a fitness landscape with local optima.

The population geneticist Sewall Wright focused on combinations of genes that interacted as complexes, and the effects of inbreeding on small relatively isolated populations, which could be subject to genetic drift. In a 1932 paper, he introduced the concept of an adaptive landscape in which phenomena such as cross breeding and genetic drift in small populations could push them away from adaptive peaks, which would in turn allow natural selection to push them towards new adaptive peaks.[40][52] Wright's model would appeal to field naturalists such as Theodosius Dobzhansky and Ernst Mayr who were becoming aware of the importance of geographical isolation in real world populations.[42] The work of Fisher, Haldane and Wright helped to found the discipline of theoretical population genetics.[53][54][55]

Dobzhansky's evolutionary genetics, 1937 Edit

 
Drosophila pseudoobscura, the fruit fly which served as Theodosius Dobzhansky's model organism

Theodosius Dobzhansky, an immigrant from the Soviet Union to the United States, who had been a postdoctoral worker in Morgan's fruit fly lab, was one of the first to apply genetics to natural populations. He worked mostly with Drosophila pseudoobscura. He says pointedly: "Russia has a variety of climates from the Arctic to sub-tropical... Exclusively laboratory workers who neither possess nor wish to have any knowledge of living beings in nature were and are in a minority."[56] Not surprisingly, there were other Russian geneticists with similar ideas, though for some time their work was known to only a few in the West. His 1937 work Genetics and the Origin of Species[57] was a key step in bridging the gap between population geneticists and field naturalists. It presented the conclusions reached by Fisher, Haldane, and especially Wright in their highly mathematical papers in a form that was easily accessible to others.[40][42] Further, Dobzhansky asserted the physicality, and hence the biological reality, of the mechanisms of inheritance: that evolution was based on material genes, arranged in a string on physical hereditary structures, the chromosomes, and linked more or less strongly to each other according to their actual physical distances on the chromosomes. As with Haldane and Fisher, Dobzhansky's "evolutionary genetics"[58] was a genuine science, now unifying cell biology, genetics, and both micro and macroevolution.[43] His work emphasized that real-world populations had far more genetic variability than the early population geneticists had assumed in their models and that genetically distinct sub-populations were important. Dobzhansky argued that natural selection worked to maintain genetic diversity as well as by driving change. He was influenced by his exposure in the 1920s to the work of Sergei Chetverikov, who had looked at the role of recessive genes in maintaining a reservoir of genetic variability in a population, before his work was shut down by the rise of Lysenkoism in the Soviet Union.[40][42] By 1937, Dobzhansky was able to argue that mutations were the main source of evolutionary changes and variability, along with chromosome rearrangements, effects of genes on their neighbours during development, and polyploidy. Next, genetic drift (he used the term in 1941), selection, migration, and geographical isolation could change gene frequencies. Thirdly, mechanisms like ecological or sexual isolation and hybrid sterility could fix the results of the earlier processes.[59]

Ford's ecological genetics, 1940 Edit

 
E. B. Ford studied polymorphism in the scarlet tiger moth for many years.

E. B. Ford was an experimental naturalist who wanted to test natural selection in nature, virtually inventing the field of ecological genetics.[60] His work on natural selection in wild populations of butterflies and moths was the first to show that predictions made by R. A. Fisher were correct. In 1940, he was the first to describe and define genetic polymorphism, and to predict that human blood group polymorphisms might be maintained in the population by providing some protection against disease.[60][61] His 1949 book Mendelism and Evolution[62] helped to persuade Dobzhansky to change the emphasis in the third edition of his famous textbook Genetics and the Origin of Species from drift to selection.[63]

Schmalhausen's stabilizing selection, 1941 Edit

Ivan Schmalhausen developed the theory of stabilizing selection, the idea that selection can preserve a trait at some value, publishing a paper in Russian titled "Stabilizing selection and its place among factors of evolution" in 1941 and a monograph Factors of Evolution: The Theory of Stabilizing Selection[64] in 1945. He developed it from J. M. Baldwin's 1902 concept that changes induced by the environment will ultimately be replaced by hereditary changes (including the Baldwin effect on behaviour), following that theory's implications to their Darwinian conclusion, and bringing him into conflict with Lysenkoism. Schmalhausen observed that stabilizing selection would remove most variations from the norm, most mutations being harmful.[65][66][67] Dobzhansky called the work "an important missing link in the modern view of evolution".[68]

Huxley's popularising synthesis, 1942 Edit

 
Julian Huxley presented a serious but popularising version of the theory in his 1942 book Evolution: The Modern Synthesis.

In 1942, Julian Huxley's serious but popularising[69][70] Evolution: The Modern Synthesis[2] introduced a name for the synthesis and intentionally set out to promote a "synthetic point of view" on the evolutionary process. He imagined a wide synthesis of many sciences: genetics, developmental physiology, ecology, systematics, palaeontology, cytology, and mathematical analysis of biology, and assumed that evolution would proceed differently in different groups of organisms according to how their genetic material was organised and their strategies for reproduction, leading to progressive but varying evolutionary trends.[70] His vision was of an "evolutionary humanism",[71] with a system of ethics and a meaningful place for "Man" in the world grounded in a unified theory of evolution which would demonstrate progress leading to humanity at its summit. Natural selection was in his view a "fact of nature capable of verification by observation and experiment", while the "period of synthesis" of the 1920s and 1930s had formed a "more unified science",[71] rivalling physics and enabling the "rebirth of Darwinism".[71]

However, the book was not the research text that it appeared to be. In the view of the philosopher of science Michael Ruse, and in Huxley's own opinion, Huxley was "a generalist, a synthesizer of ideas, rather than a specialist".[69] Ruse observes that Huxley wrote as if he were adding empirical evidence to the mathematical framework established by Fisher and the population geneticists, but that this was not so. Huxley avoided mathematics, for instance not even mentioning Fisher's fundamental theorem of natural selection. Instead, Huxley used a mass of examples to demonstrate that natural selection is powerful and that it works on Mendelian genes. The book was successful in its goal of persuading readers of the reality of evolution, effectively illustrating topics such as island biogeography, speciation, and competition. Huxley further showed that the appearance of long-term orthogenetic trends – predictable directions for evolution – in the fossil record were readily explained as allometric growth (since parts are interconnected). All the same, Huxley did not reject orthogenesis out of hand, but maintained a belief in progress all his life, with Homo sapiens as the endpoint, and he had since 1912 been influenced by the vitalist philosopher Henri Bergson, though in public he maintained an atheistic position on evolution.[69] Huxley's belief in progress within evolution and evolutionary humanism was shared in various forms by Dobzhansky, Mayr, Simpson and Stebbins, all of them writing about "the future of Mankind". Both Huxley and Dobzhansky admired the palaeontologist priest Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, Huxley writing the introduction to Teilhard's 1955 book on orthogenesis, The Phenomenon of Man. This vision required evolution to be seen as the central and guiding principle of biology.[71]

Mayr's allopatric speciation, 1942 Edit

 
Ernst Mayr argued that geographic isolation was needed to provide sufficient reproductive isolation for new species to form.

Ernst Mayr's key contribution to the synthesis was Systematics and the Origin of Species, published in 1942.[72] It asserted the importance of and set out to explain population variation in evolutionary processes including speciation. He analysed in particular the effects of polytypic species, geographic variation, and isolation by geographic and other means.[73] Mayr emphasized the importance of allopatric speciation, where geographically isolated sub-populations diverge so far that reproductive isolation occurs. He was skeptical of the reality of sympatric speciation believing that geographical isolation was a prerequisite for building up intrinsic (reproductive) isolating mechanisms. Mayr also introduced the biological species concept that defined a species as a group of interbreeding or potentially interbreeding populations that were reproductively isolated from all other populations.[40][42][74][75] Before he left Germany for the United States in 1930, Mayr had been influenced by the work of the German biologist Bernhard Rensch, who in the 1920s had analyzed the geographic distribution of polytypic species, paying particular attention to how variations between populations correlated with factors such as differences in climate.[76][77][78]

 
George Gaylord Simpson argued against the naive view that evolution such as of the horse took place in a "straight-line". He noted that any chosen line is one path in a complex branching tree, natural selection having no imposed direction.

Simpson's palaeontology, 1944 Edit

George Gaylord Simpson was responsible for showing that the modern synthesis was compatible with palaeontology in his 1944 book Tempo and Mode in Evolution. Simpson's work was crucial because so many palaeontologists had disagreed, in some cases vigorously, with the idea that natural selection was the main mechanism of evolution. It showed that the trends of linear progression (in for example the evolution of the horse) that earlier palaeontologists had used as support for neo-Lamarckism and orthogenesis did not hold up under careful examination. Instead, the fossil record was consistent with the irregular, branching, and non-directional pattern predicted by the modern synthesis.[40][42]

Society for the Study of Evolution, 1946 Edit

During World War II, Mayr edited a series of bulletins of the Committee on Common Problems of Genetics, Paleontology, and Systematics, formed in 1943, reporting on discussions of a "synthetic attack" on the interdisciplinary problems of evolution. In 1946, the committee became the Society for the Study of Evolution, with Mayr, Dobzhansky and Sewall Wright the first of the signatories. Mayr became the editor of its journal, Evolution. From Mayr and Dobzhansky's point of view, suggests the historian of science Betty Smocovitis, Darwinism was reborn, evolutionary biology was legitimised, and genetics and evolution were synthesised into a newly unified science. Everything fitted into the new framework, except "heretics" like Richard Goldschmidt who annoyed Mayr and Dobzhansky by insisting on the possibility of speciation by macromutation, creating "hopeful monsters". The result was "bitter controversy".[51]

 
Speciation via polyploidy: a diploid cell may fail to separate during meiosis, producing diploid gametes, which self-fertilize to produce a fertile tetraploid zygote that cannot interbreed with its parent species.

Stebbins's botany, 1950 Edit

The botanist G. Ledyard Stebbins extended the synthesis to encompass botany. He described the important effects on speciation of hybridization and polyploidy in plants in his 1950 book Variation and Evolution in Plants. These permitted evolution to proceed rapidly at times, polyploidy in particular evidently being able to create new species effectively instantaneously.[40][79]

Definitions by the founders Edit

The modern synthesis was defined differently by its various founders, with differing numbers of basic postulates, as shown in the table.

Definitions of the modern synthesis by its founders, as they numbered them
Component Mayr 1959 Stebbins, 1966 Dobzhansky, 1974
Mutation (1) Randomness in all events that produce new genotypes, e.g. mutation [80] (1) a source of variability, but not of direction[81] (1) yields genetic raw materials[82]
Recombination (1) Randomness in recombination, fertilisation[80] (2) a source of variability, but not of direction[81]
Chromosomal organisation (3) affects genetic linkage, arranges variation in gene pool[81]
Natural selection (2) is only direction-giving factor,[80][83] as seen in adaptations to physical and biotic environment[80] (4) guides changes to gene pool[81] (2) constructs evolutionary changes from genetic raw materials[82]
Reproductive isolation (5) limits direction in which selection can guide the population[81] (3) makes divergence irreversible in sexual organisms[82]

After the synthesis Edit

After the synthesis, evolutionary biology continued to develop with major contributions from workers including W. D. Hamilton,[84] George C. Williams,[85] E. O. Wilson,[86] Edward B. Lewis[87] and others.

Hamilton's inclusive fitness, 1964 Edit

In 1964, W. D. Hamilton published two papers on "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour". These defined inclusive fitness as the number of offspring equivalents an individual rears, rescues or otherwise supports through its behaviour. This was contrasted with personal reproductive fitness, the number of offspring that the individual directly begets. Hamilton, and others such as John Maynard Smith, argued that a gene's success consisted in maximising the number of copies of itself, either by begetting them or by indirectly encouraging begetting by related individuals who shared the gene, the theory of kin selection.[84][88]

Williams's gene-centred evolution, 1966 Edit

In 1966, George C. Williams published Adaptation and Natural Selection, outlined a gene-centred view of evolution following Hamilton's concepts, disputing the idea of evolutionary progress, and attacking the then widespread theory of group selection. Williams argued that natural selection worked by changing the frequency of alleles, and could not work at the level of groups.[89][85] Gene-centred evolution was popularised by Richard Dawkins in his 1976 book The Selfish Gene and developed in his more technical writings.[90][91]

Wilson's sociobiology, 1975 Edit

 
Ant societies have evolved elaborate caste structures, widely different in size and function.

In 1975, E. O. Wilson published his controversial[92] book Sociobiology: The New Synthesis, the subtitle alluding to the modern synthesis[86] as he attempted to bring the study of animal society into the evolutionary fold. This appeared radically new, although Wilson was following Darwin, Fisher, Dawkins and others.[86] Critics such as Gerhard Lenski noted that he was following Huxley, Simpson and Dobzhansky's approach, which Lenski considered needlessly reductive as far as human society was concerned.[93] By 2000, the proposed discipline of sociobiology had morphed into the relatively well-accepted discipline of evolutionary psychology.[86]

Lewis's homeotic genes, 1978 Edit

 
Evolutionary developmental biology has formed a synthesis of evolutionary and developmental biology, discovering deep homology between the embryogenesis of such different animals as insects and vertebrates.

In 1977, recombinant DNA technology enabled biologists to start to explore the genetic control of development. The growth of evolutionary developmental biology from 1978, when Edward B. Lewis discovered homeotic genes, showed that many so-called toolkit genes act to regulate development, influencing the expression of other genes. It also revealed that some of the regulatory genes are extremely ancient, so that animals as different as insects and mammals share control mechanisms; for example, the Pax6 gene is involved in forming the eyes of mice and of fruit flies. Such deep homology provided strong evidence for evolution and indicated the paths that evolution had taken.[87]

Later syntheses Edit

In 1982, a historical note on a series of evolutionary biology books[f] could state without qualification that evolution is the central organizing principle of biology. Smocovitis commented on this that "What the architects of the synthesis had worked to construct had by 1982 become a matter of fact", adding in a footnote that "the centrality of evolution had thus been rendered tacit knowledge, part of the received wisdom of the profession".[94]

By the late 20th century, however, the modern synthesis was showing its age, and fresh syntheses to remedy its defects and fill in its gaps were proposed from different directions. These have included such diverse fields as the study of society,[86] developmental biology,[49] epigenetics,[95] molecular biology, microbiology, genomics,[96] symbiogenesis, and horizontal gene transfer.[97] The physiologist Denis Noble argues that these additions render neo-Darwinism in the sense of the early 20th century's modern synthesis "at the least, incomplete as a theory of evolution",[97] and one that has been falsified by later biological research.[97]

Michael Rose and Todd Oakley note that evolutionary biology, formerly divided and "Balkanized", has been brought together by genomics. It has in their view discarded at least five common assumptions from the modern synthesis, namely that the genome is always a well-organised set of genes; that each gene has a single function; that species are well adapted biochemically to their ecological niches; that species are the durable units of evolution, and all levels from organism to organ, cell and molecule within the species are characteristic of it; and that the design of every organism and cell is efficient. They argue that the "new biology" integrates genomics, bioinformatics, and evolutionary genetics into a general-purpose toolkit for a "Postmodern Synthesis".[53]

Pigliucci's extended evolutionary synthesis, 2007 Edit

In 2007, more than half a century after the modern synthesis, Massimo Pigliucci called for an extended evolutionary synthesis to incorporate aspects of biology that had not been included or had not existed in the mid-20th century.[98][99] It revisits the relative importance of different factors, challenges assumptions made in the modern synthesis, and adds new factors[99][100] such as multilevel selection, transgenerational epigenetic inheritance, niche construction, and evolvability.[101][95][102]

Koonin's 'post-modern' evolutionary synthesis, 2009 Edit

 
A 21st century tree of life showing horizontal gene transfers among prokaryotes and the saltational endosymbiosis events that created the eukaryotes, neither fitting into the 20th century's modern synthesis

In 2009, Darwin's 200th anniversary, the Origin of Species' 150th, and the 200th of Lamarck's "early evolutionary synthesis",[96] Philosophie Zoologique, the evolutionary biologist Eugene Koonin stated that while "the edifice of the [early 20th century] Modern Synthesis has crumbled, apparently, beyond repair",[96] a new 21st-century synthesis could be glimpsed. Three interlocking revolutions had, he argued, taken place in evolutionary biology: molecular, microbiological, and genomic. The molecular revolution included the neutral theory, that most mutations are neutral and that negative selection happens more often than the positive form, and that all current life evolved from a single common ancestor. In microbiology, the synthesis has expanded to cover the prokaryotes, using ribosomal RNA to form a tree of life. Finally, genomics brought together the molecular and microbiological syntheses - in particular, horizontal gene transfer between bacteria shows that prokaryotes can freely share genes. Many of these points had already been made by other researchers such as Ulrich Kutschera and Karl J. Niklas.[103]

Towards a replacement synthesis Edit

 
Inputs to the modern synthesis, with other topics (inverted colours) such as developmental biology that were not joined with evolutionary biology until the turn of the 21st century[103]

Biologists, alongside scholars of the history and philosophy of biology, have continued to debate the need for, and possible nature of, a replacement synthesis. For example, in 2017 Philippe Huneman and Denis M. Walsh stated in their book Challenging the Modern Synthesis that numerous theorists had pointed out that the disciplines of embryological developmental theory, morphology, and ecology had been omitted. They noted that all such arguments amounted to a continuing desire to replace the modern synthesis with one that united "all biological fields of research related to evolution, adaptation, and diversity in a single theoretical framework."[104] They observed further that there are two groups of challenges to the way the modern synthesis viewed inheritance. The first is that other modes such as epigenetic inheritance, phenotypic plasticity, the Baldwin effect, and the maternal effect allow new characteristics to arise and be passed on and for the genes to catch up with the new adaptations later. The second is that all such mechanisms are part, not of an inheritance system, but a developmental system: the fundamental unit is not a discrete selfishly competing gene, but a collaborating system that works at all levels from genes and cells to organisms and cultures to guide evolution.[105] The molecular biologist Sean B. Carroll has commented that had Huxley had access to evolutionary developmental biology, "embryology would have been a cornerstone of his Modern Synthesis, and so evo-devo is today a key element of a more complete, expanded evolutionary synthesis."[106]

Historiography Edit

Looking back at the conflicting accounts of the modern synthesis, the historian Betty Smocovitis notes in her 1996 book Unifying Biology: The Evolutionary Synthesis and Evolutionary Biology that both historians and philosophers of biology have attempted to grasp its scientific meaning, but have found it "a moving target";[107] the only thing they agreed on was that it was a historical event.[107] In her words

"by the late 1980s the notoriety of the evolutionary synthesis was recognized ... So notorious did 'the synthesis' become, that few serious historically minded analysts would touch the subject, let alone know where to begin to sort through the interpretive mess left behind by the numerous critics and commentators".[108]

See also Edit

Notes Edit

  1. ^ Also known variously as the New Synthesis, the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis, the Evolutionary Synthesis, and the neo-Darwinian Synthesis. These alternative terms are ambiguous as they could possibly include later syntheses, so this article uses Julian Huxley's 1942 "modern synthesis"[2] throughout.
  2. ^ Peter Gauthier has however argued that Weismann's experiment showed only that injury did not affect the germplasm. It did not test the effect of Lamarckian use and disuse.[13]
  3. ^ Morgan's work with fruit flies helped establish the link between Mendelian genetics and the chromosomal theory of inheritance, that the hereditary material was embodied in these bodies within the cell nucleus.[33]
  4. ^ Fisher also analysed sexual selection in his book, but his work was largely ignored, and Darwin's case for such selection misunderstood, so it formed no substantial part of the modern synthesis.[41]
  5. ^ Though C. H. Waddington had called for embryology to be added to the synthesis in his 1953 paper "Epigenetics and Evolution".[51]
  6. ^ In a reissue of Dobzhansky's Genetics and the Origin of Species.

References Edit

  1. ^ Gould 2002, p. 216
  2. ^ a b Huxley 2010.
  3. ^ Bowler 2003, pp. 236–256
  4. ^ Kutschera, Ulrich (December 2003). "A comparative analysis of the Darwin–Wallace papers and the development of the concept of natural selection". Theory in Biosciences. 122 (4): 343–359. doi:10.1007/s12064-003-0063-6. S2CID 24297627.
  5. ^ Butler, Samuel (1880). Unconscious Memory. David Bogue. p. 280. I may predict with some certainty that before long we shall find the original Darwinism of Dr. Erasmus Darwin … generally accepted instead of the neo-Darwinism of to-day, and that the variations whose accumulation results in species will be recognised as due to the wants and endeavours of the living forms in which they appear, instead of being ascribed to chance, or, in other words, to unknown causes, as by Mr. Charles Darwin's system
  6. ^ Beccaloni, George (2013). "On the Terms "Darwinism" and "Neo-Darwinism"". A. R. Wallace Website.
  7. ^ Bowler 2003, pp. 196–253
  8. ^ Larson 2004, pp. 105–129
  9. ^ Gayon, Jean (1998). Darwinism's Struggle for Survival: Heredity and the Hypothesis of Natural Selection. Cambridge University Press. pp. 2–3. ISBN 978-0-521-56250-8.
  10. ^ Darwin, Charles (1868). The variation of animals and plants under domestication. John Murray. ISBN 978-1-4191-8660-8.
  11. ^ Holterhoff, Kate (2014). "The History and Reception of Charles Darwin's Hypothesis of Pangenesis". Journal of the History of Biology. 47 (4): 661–695. doi:10.1007/s10739-014-9377-0. PMID 24570302. S2CID 207150548.
  12. ^ Weismann, August (1892). Das Keimplasma: eine Theorie der Vererbung [The Germ Plasm: A theory of inheritance]. Jena: Fischer.
  13. ^ Gauthier, Peter (March–May 1990). "Does Weismann's Experiment Constitute a Refutation of the Lamarckian Hypothesis?". BIOS. 61 (1/2): 6–8. JSTOR 4608123.
  14. ^ Bowler 1989, p. 248.
  15. ^ Bowler 2003, pp. 253–256
  16. ^ Bowler 1989, pp. 247–253, 257.
  17. ^ Ambrose, Mike. . Norwich, UK: Germplasm Resources Unit, John Innes Centre. Archived from the original on 14 June 2016. Retrieved 14 December 2017.
  18. ^ "Reviewing Mendel's Laws". Pearson. Retrieved 14 October 2017.
  19. ^ Bateson 1894: Mutations (as 'sports') and polymorphisms were well known long before the Mendelian recovery.
  20. ^ Larson 2004, pp. 157–166
  21. ^ Bowler 1989, pp. 275–276
  22. ^ a b Grafen & Ridley 2006, p. 69
  23. ^ Provine 2001, p. 69
  24. ^ Olby, Robert (September 1989). "The Dimensions of Scientific Controversy: The Biometric-Mendelian Debate". The British Journal for the History of Science. 22 (3): 299–320. doi:10.1017/s0007087400026170. JSTOR 4026898. PMID 11621982. S2CID 36719974.
  25. ^ Gayon, J. (1988). Darwinism's Struggle for Survival: Heredity and the Hypothesis of Natural Selection. Cambridge University Press.
  26. ^ Stoltzfus, Arlin; Cable, Kele (2014). "Mendelian-Mutationism: The Forgotten Evolutionary Synthesis" (PDF). Journal of the History of Biology. 47 (4): 501–546. doi:10.1007/s10739-014-9383-2. PMID 24811736. S2CID 23263558. (PDF) from the original on 2014-11-30.
  27. ^ Bateson, William; Saunders, E. R. (1902). "Experimental Studies in the Physiology of Heredity". Royal Society. Reports to the Evolution Committee.
  28. ^ Yule, G. Udny (1902). "Mendel's Laws and their probable relations to inter-racial heredity". New Phytologist. 1 (10): 226–227. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8137.1902.tb07336.x.
  29. ^ Provine 2001, pp. 81–82.
  30. ^ Provine 2001, pp. 109–114.
  31. ^ Castle, W. E. (7 April 1905). "The Mutation Theory of Organic Evolution, from the Standpoint of Animal Breeding". Science. 21 (536): 521–525. Bibcode:1905Sci....21..521C. doi:10.1126/science.21.536.521. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 17770959.
  32. ^ Vicedo, Marga (2000). Castle, William Ernest (1867-1962), biologist. American National Biography Online. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/anb/9780198606697.article.1302308.
  33. ^ a b Bowler 2003, pp. 271–272
  34. ^ Provine 2001, pp. 120–121.
  35. ^ a b Smocovitis 1996, pp. 100–114
  36. ^ Smocovitis 1996, pp. 114–119
  37. ^ Smocovitis 1996, pp. 119–122
  38. ^ Fisher, Ronald A. (January 1919). "XV.—The Correlation between Relatives on the Supposition of Mendelian Inheritance". Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh. 52 (2): 399–433. doi:10.1017/S0080456800012163. OCLC 4981124. S2CID 181213898. "Paper read by J. Arthur Thomson on July 8, 1918 to the Royal Society of Edinburgh."
  39. ^ Fisher 1999
  40. ^ a b c d e f g h Larson 2004, pp. 221–243
  41. ^ Hosken, David J.; House, Clarissa M. (25 January 2011). "Sexual Selection". Current Biology. 21 (2): R62–R65. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2010.11.053. PMID 21256434. S2CID 18470445.
  42. ^ a b c d e f Bowler 2003, pp. 325–339
  43. ^ a b Smocovitis 1996, pp. 122–132
  44. ^ Smocovitis 1996, p. 192
  45. ^ Held, Lewis I. (2014). How the Snake Lost its Legs. Curious Tales from the Frontier of Evo-Devo. Cambridge University Press. p. 67. ISBN 978-1-107-62139-8.
  46. ^ Gould 1977, pp. 221–222
  47. ^ Hall, B. K. (2003). "Evo-Devo: evolutionary developmental mechanisms". International Journal of Developmental Biology. 47 (7–8): 491–495. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.113.5158. PMID 14756324.
  48. ^ Ingo Brigandt (2006). "Homology and heterochrony: the evolutionary embryologist Gavin Rylands de Beer (1899-1972)" (PDF). Journal of Experimental Zoology. 306B (4): 317–328. doi:10.1002/jez.b.21100. PMID 16506229. (PDF) from the original on 2006-11-04.
  49. ^ a b Gilbert, S. F.; Opitz, J. M.; Raff, R. A. (1996). "Resynthesizing evolutionary and developmental biology". Developmental Biology. 173 (2): 357–372. doi:10.1006/dbio.1996.0032. PMID 8605997.
  50. ^ Adams, M. (1991). Warren, L.; Koprowski, H. (eds.). Through the looking glass: The evolution of Soviet Darwinism. pp. 37–63. ISBN 978-0-471-56068-5. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  51. ^ a b Smocovitis 1996, pp. 153–171
  52. ^ Wright 1932, pp. 356–366
  53. ^ a b Rose, Michael R.; Oakley, Todd H. (November 24, 2007). "The new biology: beyond the Modern Synthesis" (PDF). Biology Direct. 2 (30): 30. doi:10.1186/1745-6150-2-30. PMC 2222615. PMID 18036242. (PDF) from the original on 2014-03-21.
  54. ^ Huxley, Julian (1942). Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. Allen & Unwin.
  55. ^ Ridley, Matt (1996). Evolution (2nd ed.). Blackwell Science. ISBN 978-0632042920.
  56. ^ Mayr & Provine 1998, p. 231
  57. ^ Dobzhansky 1937
  58. ^ Smocovitis 1996, p. 127
  59. ^ Eldredge, Niles (1985). Unfinished Synthesis: Biological Hierarchies and Modern Evolutionary Thought. Oxford University Press. p. 17. ISBN 978-0-19-536513-9.
  60. ^ a b Ford 1964
  61. ^ Ford 1975
  62. ^ Ford, E. B. (1949). Mendelism and Evolution. Methuen.
  63. ^ Dobzhansky 1951
  64. ^ Schmalhausen, Ivan I.; Dordick, Isadore (trans.) (1949). Dobzhansky, Theodosius (ed.). Factors of Evolution. The Theory of Stabilizing Selection. Philadelphia and Toronto: Blakiston Company.
  65. ^ Levit, Georgy S.; Hossfeld, Uwe; Olsson, Lennart (2006). "From the 'Modern Synthesis' to Cybernetics: Ivan Ivanovich Schmalhausen (1884–1963) and his Research Program for a Synthesis of Evolutionary and Developmental Biology". Journal of Experimental Zoology. 306B (2006): 89–106. doi:10.1002/jez.b.21087. PMID 16419076. S2CID 23594114.
  66. ^ Adams, M. B. (June 1988). "A Missing Link in the Evolutionary Synthesis. I. I. Schmalhausen. Factors of Evolution: The Theory of Stabilizing Selection". Isis. 79 (297): 281–284. doi:10.1086/354706. PMID 3049441. S2CID 146660877.
  67. ^ Glass, Bentley (December 1951). "Reviews and Brief Notices Factors of Evolution. The Theory of Stabilizing Selection. I. I. Schmalhausen, Isadore Dordick, Theodosius Dobzhansky". Quarterly Review of Biology. 26 (4): 384–385. doi:10.1086/398434.
  68. ^ Mayr & Provine 1998, p. ix.
  69. ^ a b c Ruse 1996, pp. 328–338
  70. ^ a b Lamm, Ehud. "Review of Julian Huxley, Evolution: The Modern Synthesis – The Definitive Edition, with a new foreword by Massimo Pigliucci and Gerd B. Müller" (PDF). MIT Press. (PDF) from the original on 2011-12-24. Retrieved 21 August 2017.
  71. ^ a b c d Smocovitis 1996, pp. 138–153
  72. ^ Mayr 1999
  73. ^ Hey, Jody; Fitch, Walter M.; Ayala, Francisco J. (2005). "Systematics and the origin of species: An introduction". PNAS. 102 (supplement 1): 6515–6519. Bibcode:2005PNAS..102.6515H. doi:10.1073/pnas.0501939102. PMC 1131868. PMID 15851660.
  74. ^ Mayr & Provine 1998, pp. 33–34
  75. ^ Mayr 1982.
  76. ^ Rensch 1947; Rensch 1959
  77. ^ Smith, Charles H. "Rensch, Bernhard (Carl Emmanuel) (Germany 1900-1990)". Some Biogeographers, Evolutionists and Ecologists: Chrono-Biographical Sketches. Western Kentucky University. Retrieved 14 December 2017.
  78. ^ Mayr & Provine 1998, pp. 298–299, 416
  79. ^ Smocovitis, V. B. (2001). "G. Ledyard Stebbins and the evolutionary synthesis". Annual Review of Genetics. 35: 803–814. doi:10.1146/annurev.genet.35.102401.091525. PMID 11700300.
  80. ^ a b c d Mayr, E.: Where Are We? Cold Spring Harbor Symposium of Quantitative Biology 24, 1–14, 1959
  81. ^ a b c d e Stebbins, G. L.: Processes of Organic Evolution, p. 12. Prentice Hall, 1966
  82. ^ a b c Dobzhansky, T.: In: Ayala, F., Dobzhansky, T. (eds.) Chance and Creativity in Evolution, pp. 307–338. University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles (1974)
  83. ^ Mayr, E.: In: Mayr, E., Provine, W. (eds.) Some Thoughts on the History of the Evolutionary Synthesis, pp. 1–48. Harvard University Press, 1980
  84. ^ a b Hamilton, W. D. (1964). "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour I" (PDF). Journal of Theoretical Biology. 7 (1): 1–52. Bibcode:1964JThBi...7....1H. doi:10.1016/0022-5193(64)90038-4. PMID 5875341. (PDF) from the original on 2016-12-18.
  85. ^ a b Williams, George C. (1966). Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton University Press. p. 307. ISBN 978-0-691-02615-2.
  86. ^ a b c d e Yudell, Michael; Desalle, Rob (2000). "Sociobiology. The New Synthesis. by Edward O. Wilson". Journal of the History of Biology. 33 (3): 577–584. doi:10.1023/a:1004845822189. JSTOR 4331614. S2CID 88047081.
  87. ^ a b Gilbert, S. F. (2000). A New Evolutionary Synthesis. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  88. ^ Maynard Smith, John (1964). "Group Selection and Kin Selection". Nature. 201 (4924): 1145–1147. Bibcode:1964Natur.201.1145S. doi:10.1038/2011145a0. S2CID 4177102.
  89. ^ Pinker, Steven (1994). The Language Instinct. Harper Perennial Modern Classics. p. 294.
  90. ^ Okasha, Samir (September 22, 2006). "Population Genetics" – via plato.stanford.edu. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  91. ^ Dawkins, Richard (1982). The Extended Phenotype. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-288051-2.
  92. ^ Fisher, Helen (16 October 1994). "'Wilson,' They Said, 'Your All Wet!'". New York Times. Retrieved 21 July 2015.
  93. ^ Lenski, Gerhard (1976). "Sociobiology. The New Synthesis. by Edward O. Wilson". Social Forces. 55 (2): 530–531. doi:10.2307/2576242. JSTOR 2576242.
  94. ^ Smocovitis 1996, pp. 186–187.
  95. ^ a b Pigliucci, Massimo; Finkelman, Leonard (2014). "The Extended (Evolutionary) Synthesis Debate: Where Science Meets Philosophy". BioScience. 64 (6): 511–516. doi:10.1093/biosci/biu062.
  96. ^ a b c Koonin, Eugene V. (November 2009). "The Origin at 150: is a new evolutionary synthesis in sight?". Trends in Genetics. 25 (11): 473–475. doi:10.1016/j.tig.2009.09.007. PMC 2784144. PMID 19836100.
  97. ^ a b c Noble, Denis (2011). "Neo-Darwinism, the Modern Synthesis and selfish genes: are they of use in physiology?". The Journal of Physiology. 589 (5): 1007–1015. doi:10.1113/jphysiol.2010.201384. PMC 3060581. PMID 21135048.
  98. ^ Wade, Michael J. (2011). "The Neo-Modern Synthesis: The Confluence of New Data and Explanatory Concepts". BioScience. 61 (5): 407–408. doi:10.1525/bio.2011.61.5.10.
  99. ^ a b John Odling-Smee et al. "The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions". Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, August 2015.
  100. ^ Wade, Michael J. (2011). "The Neo-Modern Synthesis: The Confluence of New Data and Explanatory Concepts". BioScience. 61 (5): 407–408. doi:10.1525/bio.2011.61.5.10.
  101. ^ Danchin, É.; Charmantier, A.; Champagne, F. A.; Mesoudi, A.; Pujol, B.; Blanchet, S. (2011). "Beyond DNA: integrating inclusive inheritance into an extended theory of evolution". Nature Reviews Genetics. 12 (7): 475–486. doi:10.1038/nrg3028. PMID 21681209. S2CID 8837202.
  102. ^ Laubichler, Manfred D.; Renn, Jürgen (2015). "Extended evolution: A Conceptual Framework for Integrating Regulatory Networks and Niche Construction". Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution. 324 (7): 565–577. doi:10.1002/jez.b.22631. PMC 4744698. PMID 26097188.
  103. ^ a b Kutschera, Ulrich; Niklas, Karl J. (June 2004). "The modern theory of biological evolution: an expanded synthesis". Naturwissenschaften. 91 (6): 255–276. Bibcode:2004NW.....91..255K. doi:10.1007/s00114-004-0515-y. PMID 15241603. S2CID 10731711.
  104. ^ Huneman, Philippe; Walsh, Denis M. (2017). Challenging the Modern Synthesis: Adaptation, Development, and Inheritance. Oxford University Press. pp. 76 (Chapter 2). ISBN 978-0-19-068145-6.
  105. ^ Huneman, Philippe; Walsh, Denis M. (2017). Challenging the Modern Synthesis: Adaptation, Development, and Inheritance. Oxford University Press. pp. Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-068145-6.
  106. ^ Carroll, Sean B. (2008). "Evo-Devo and an Expanding Evolutionary Synthesis: A Genetic Theory of Morphological Evolution". Cell. 134 (1): 25–36. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2008.06.030. PMID 18614008. S2CID 2513041.
  107. ^ a b Smocovitis 1996, p. 187
  108. ^ Smocovitis 1996, p. 43

Sources Edit

Further reading Edit

modern, synthesis, 20th, century, other, uses, modern, synthesis, disambiguation, modern, synthesis, early, 20th, century, synthesis, charles, darwin, theory, evolution, gregor, mendel, ideas, heredity, into, joint, mathematical, framework, julian, huxley, coi. For other uses see Modern synthesis disambiguation The modern synthesis a was the early 20th century synthesis of Charles Darwin s theory of evolution and Gregor Mendel s ideas on heredity into a joint mathematical framework Julian Huxley coined the term in his 1942 book Evolution The Modern Synthesis Several major ideas about evolution came together in the population genetics of the early 20th century to form the modern synthesis including genetic variation natural selection and particulate Mendelian inheritance 1 This ended the eclipse of Darwinism and supplanted a variety of non Darwinian theories of evolution The synthesis combined the ideas of natural selection Mendelian genetics and population genetics It also related the broad scale macroevolution seen by palaeontologists to the small scale microevolution of local populations The synthesis was defined differently by its founders with Ernst Mayr in 1959 G Ledyard Stebbins in 1966 and Theodosius Dobzhansky in 1974 offering differing basic postulates though they all include natural selection working on heritable variation supplied by mutation Other major figures in the synthesis included E B Ford Bernhard Rensch Ivan Schmalhausen and George Gaylord Simpson An early event in the modern synthesis was R A Fisher s 1918 paper on mathematical population genetics though William Bateson and separately Udny Yule had already started to show how Mendelian genetics could work in evolution in 1902 Contents 1 Developments leading up to the synthesis 1 1 Darwin s evolution by natural selection 1859 1 2 The eclipse of Darwinism 1880s onwards 1 3 Weismann s germ plasm 1892 2 Disputed beginnings 2 1 Genetics mutationism and biometrics 1900 1918 2 2 Castle s hooded rats 1911 2 3 Morgan s fruit flies 1912 3 An obstruction Woodger s positivism 1929 4 Elements of the synthesis 4 1 Fisher and Haldane s mathematical population genetics 1918 1930 4 2 De Beer s embryology 1930 4 3 Wright s adaptive landscape 1932 4 4 Dobzhansky s evolutionary genetics 1937 4 5 Ford s ecological genetics 1940 4 6 Schmalhausen s stabilizing selection 1941 4 7 Huxley s popularising synthesis 1942 4 8 Mayr s allopatric speciation 1942 4 9 Simpson s palaeontology 1944 4 10 Society for the Study of Evolution 1946 4 11 Stebbins s botany 1950 5 Definitions by the founders 6 After the synthesis 6 1 Hamilton s inclusive fitness 1964 6 2 Williams s gene centred evolution 1966 6 3 Wilson s sociobiology 1975 6 4 Lewis s homeotic genes 1978 7 Later syntheses 7 1 Pigliucci s extended evolutionary synthesis 2007 7 2 Koonin s post modern evolutionary synthesis 2009 7 3 Towards a replacement synthesis 8 Historiography 9 See also 10 Notes 11 References 12 Sources 13 Further readingDevelopments leading up to the synthesis Edit nbsp Darwin s pangenesis theory Every part of the body emits tiny gemmules which migrate to the gonads and contribute to the next generation via the fertilised egg Changes to the body during an organism s life would be inherited as in Lamarckism Further information History of evolutionary thought Darwin s evolution by natural selection 1859 Edit Main articles Evolution and Natural selection Charles Darwin s 1859 book On the Origin of Species convinced most biologists that evolution had occurred but not that natural selection was its primary mechanism In the 19th and early 20th centuries variations of Lamarckism inheritance of acquired characteristics orthogenesis progressive evolution saltationism evolution by jumps and mutationism evolution driven by mutations were discussed as alternatives 3 Darwin himself had sympathy for Lamarckism but Alfred Russel Wallace advocated natural selection and totally rejected Lamarckism 4 In 1880 Samuel Butler labelled Wallace s view neo Darwinism 5 6 nbsp Blending inheritance implied by pangenesis causes the averaging out of every characteristic which as the engineer Fleeming Jenkin pointed out would make evolution by natural selection impossible The eclipse of Darwinism 1880s onwards Edit Main article The eclipse of Darwinism From the 1880s onwards biologists grew skeptical of Darwinian evolution This eclipse of Darwinism in Julian Huxley s words grew out of the weaknesses in Darwin s account with respect to his view of inheritance Darwin believed in blending inheritance which implied that any new variation even if beneficial would be weakened by 50 at each generation as the engineer Fleeming Jenkin noted in 1868 7 8 This in turn meant that small variations would not survive long enough to be selected Blending would therefore directly oppose natural selection In addition Darwin and others considered Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics entirely possible and Darwin s 1868 theory of pangenesis with contributions to the next generation gemmules flowing from all parts of the body actually implied Lamarckism as well as blending 9 10 11 nbsp August Weismann s germ plasm theory The hereditary material the germplasm is confined to the gonads and the gametes Somatic cells of the body develop afresh in each generation from the germplasm Weismann s germ plasm 1892 Edit Main article Germ plasm August Weismann s idea set out in his 1892 book Das Keimplasma eine Theorie der Vererbung The Germ Plasm a Theory of Inheritance 12 was that the hereditary material which he called the germ plasm and the rest of the body the soma had a one way relationship the germ plasm formed the body but the body did not influence the germ plasm except indirectly in its participation in a population subject to natural selection If correct this made Darwin s pangenesis wrong and Lamarckian inheritance impossible His experiment on mice cutting off their tails and showing that their offspring had normal tails demonstrated that inheritance was hard b He argued strongly and dogmatically 14 for Darwinism and against Lamarckism polarising opinions among other scientists This increased anti Darwinian feeling contributing to its eclipse 15 16 Disputed beginnings EditGenetics mutationism and biometrics 1900 1918 Edit Main articles Mutationism and Biostatistics nbsp William Bateson championed Mendelism While carrying out breeding experiments to clarify the mechanism of inheritance in 1900 Hugo de Vries and Carl Correns independently rediscovered Gregor Mendel s work News of this reached William Bateson in England who reported on the paper during a presentation to the Royal Horticultural Society in May 1900 17 In Mendelian inheritance the contributions of each parent retain their integrity rather than blending with the contribution of the other parent In the case of a cross between two true breeding varieties such as Mendel s round and wrinkled peas the first generation offspring are all alike in this case all round Allowing these to cross the original characteristics reappear segregation about 3 4 of their offspring are round 1 4 wrinkled There is a discontinuity between the appearance of the offspring de Vries coined the term allele for a variant form of an inherited characteristic 18 This reinforced a major division of thought already present in the 1890s between gradualists who followed Darwin and saltationists such as Bateson 19 The two schools were the Mendelians such as Bateson and de Vries who favoured mutationism evolution driven by mutation based on genes whose alleles segregated discretely like Mendel s peas 20 21 and the biometric school led by Karl Pearson and Walter Weldon The biometricians argued vigorously against mutationism saying that empirical evidence indicated that variation was continuous in most organisms not discrete as Mendelism seemed to predict they wrongly believed that Mendelism inevitably implied evolution in discontinuous jumps 22 23 nbsp Karl Pearson led the biometric school A traditional view is that the biometricians and the Mendelians rejected natural selection and argued for their separate theories for 20 years the debate only resolved by the development of population genetics 22 24 A more recent view is that Bateson de Vries Thomas Hunt Morgan and Reginald Punnett had by 1918 formed a synthesis of Mendelism and mutationism The understanding achieved by these geneticists spanned the action of natural selection on alleles alternative forms of a gene the Hardy Weinberg equilibrium the evolution of continuously varying traits like height and the probability that a new mutation will become fixed In this view the early geneticists accepted natural selection but rejected Darwin s non Mendelian ideas about variation and heredity and the synthesis began soon after 1900 25 26 The traditional claim that Mendelians rejected the idea of continuous variation is false as early as 1902 Bateson and Saunders wrote that If there were even so few as say four or five pairs of possible allelomorphs the various homo and heterozygous combinations might on seriation give so near an approach to a continuous curve that the purity of the elements would be unsuspected 27 Also in 1902 the statistician Udny Yule showed mathematically that given multiple factors Mendel s theory enabled continuous variation Yule criticised Bateson s approach as confrontational 28 but failed to prevent the Mendelians and the biometricians from falling out 29 Castle s hooded rats 1911 Edit Starting in 1906 William Castle carried out a long study of the effect of selection on coat colour in rats The piebald or hooded pattern was recessive to the grey wild type He crossed hooded rats with both wild and Irish types and then back crossed the offspring with pure hooded rats The dark stripe on the back was bigger He then tried selecting different groups for bigger or smaller stripes for 5 generations and found that it was possible to change the characteristics considerably beyond the initial range of variation This effectively refuted de Vries s claim that continuous variation was caused by the environment and could not be inherited By 1911 Castle noted that the results could be explained by Darwinian selection on a heritable variation of a sufficient number of Mendelian genes 30 31 32 Morgan s fruit flies 1912 Edit Main article Thomas Hunt Morgan Thomas Hunt Morgan began his career in genetics as a saltationist and started out trying to demonstrate that mutations could produce new species in fruit flies However the experimental work at his lab with the fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster c showed that rather than creating new species in a single step mutations increased the supply of genetic variation in the population 33 By 1912 after years of work on the genetics of fruit flies Morgan showed that these insects had many small Mendelian factors discovered as mutant flies on which Darwinian evolution could work as if the variation was fully continuous The way was open for geneticists to conclude that Mendelism supported Darwinism 34 An obstruction Woodger s positivism 1929 EditFurther information Joseph Henry Woodger The theoretical biologist and philosopher of biology Joseph Henry Woodger led the introduction of positivism into biology with his 1929 book Biological Principles He saw a mature science as being characterised by a framework of hypotheses that could be verified by facts established by experiments He criticised the traditional natural history style of biology including the study of evolution as immature science since it relied on narrative 35 Woodger set out to play the role of Robert Boyle s 1661 Sceptical Chymist intending to convert the subject of biology into a formal unified science and ultimately following the Vienna Circle of logical positivists like Otto Neurath and Rudolf Carnap to reduce biology to physics and chemistry His efforts stimulated the biologist J B S Haldane to push for the axiomatisation of biology and by influencing thinkers such as Huxley helped to bring about the modern synthesis 35 The positivist climate made natural history unfashionable and in America research and university level teaching on evolution declined almost to nothing by the late 1930s The Harvard physiologist William John Crozier told his students that evolution was not even a science You can t experiment with two million years 36 The tide of opinion turned with the adoption of mathematical modelling and controlled experimentation in population genetics combining genetics ecology and evolution in a framework acceptable to positivism 37 Elements of the synthesis EditFisher and Haldane s mathematical population genetics 1918 1930 Edit Main article A Mathematical Theory of Natural and Artificial Selection In 1918 R A Fisher wrote The Correlation between Relatives on the Supposition of Mendelian Inheritance 38 which showed how continuous variation could come from a number of discrete genetic loci In this and other papers culminating in his 1930 book The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection 39 Fisher showed how Mendelian genetics was consistent with the idea of evolution by natural selection 40 d In the 1920s a series of papers by J B S Haldane analyzed real world examples of natural selection such as the evolution of industrial melanism in peppered moths 40 and showed that natural selection could work even faster than Fisher had assumed 42 Both of these scholars and others such as Dobzhansky and Wright wanted to raise biology to the standards of the physical sciences by basing it on mathematical modeling and empirical testing Natural selection once considered unverifiable was becoming predictable measurable and testable 43 De Beer s embryology 1930 Edit The traditional view is that developmental biology played little part in the modern synthesis 44 but in his 1930 book Embryos and Ancestors the evolutionary embryologist Gavin de Beer anticipated evolutionary developmental biology 45 by showing that evolution could occur by heterochrony 46 such as in the retention of juvenile features in the adult 47 This de Beer argued could cause apparently sudden changes in the fossil record since embryos fossilise poorly As the gaps in the fossil record had been used as an argument against Darwin s gradualist evolution de Beer s explanation supported the Darwinian position 48 However despite de Beer the modern synthesis largely ignored embryonic development when explaining the form of organisms since population genetics appeared to be an adequate explanation of how such forms evolved 49 50 e Wright s adaptive landscape 1932 Edit nbsp Sewall Wright introduced the idea of a fitness landscape with local optima Further information Population genetics History The population geneticist Sewall Wright focused on combinations of genes that interacted as complexes and the effects of inbreeding on small relatively isolated populations which could be subject to genetic drift In a 1932 paper he introduced the concept of an adaptive landscape in which phenomena such as cross breeding and genetic drift in small populations could push them away from adaptive peaks which would in turn allow natural selection to push them towards new adaptive peaks 40 52 Wright s model would appeal to field naturalists such as Theodosius Dobzhansky and Ernst Mayr who were becoming aware of the importance of geographical isolation in real world populations 42 The work of Fisher Haldane and Wright helped to found the discipline of theoretical population genetics 53 54 55 Dobzhansky s evolutionary genetics 1937 Edit Further information Genetics and the Origin of Species nbsp Drosophila pseudoobscura the fruit fly which served as Theodosius Dobzhansky s model organismTheodosius Dobzhansky an immigrant from the Soviet Union to the United States who had been a postdoctoral worker in Morgan s fruit fly lab was one of the first to apply genetics to natural populations He worked mostly with Drosophila pseudoobscura He says pointedly Russia has a variety of climates from the Arctic to sub tropical Exclusively laboratory workers who neither possess nor wish to have any knowledge of living beings in nature were and are in a minority 56 Not surprisingly there were other Russian geneticists with similar ideas though for some time their work was known to only a few in the West His 1937 work Genetics and the Origin of Species 57 was a key step in bridging the gap between population geneticists and field naturalists It presented the conclusions reached by Fisher Haldane and especially Wright in their highly mathematical papers in a form that was easily accessible to others 40 42 Further Dobzhansky asserted the physicality and hence the biological reality of the mechanisms of inheritance that evolution was based on material genes arranged in a string on physical hereditary structures the chromosomes and linked more or less strongly to each other according to their actual physical distances on the chromosomes As with Haldane and Fisher Dobzhansky s evolutionary genetics 58 was a genuine science now unifying cell biology genetics and both micro and macroevolution 43 His work emphasized that real world populations had far more genetic variability than the early population geneticists had assumed in their models and that genetically distinct sub populations were important Dobzhansky argued that natural selection worked to maintain genetic diversity as well as by driving change He was influenced by his exposure in the 1920s to the work of Sergei Chetverikov who had looked at the role of recessive genes in maintaining a reservoir of genetic variability in a population before his work was shut down by the rise of Lysenkoism in the Soviet Union 40 42 By 1937 Dobzhansky was able to argue that mutations were the main source of evolutionary changes and variability along with chromosome rearrangements effects of genes on their neighbours during development and polyploidy Next genetic drift he used the term in 1941 selection migration and geographical isolation could change gene frequencies Thirdly mechanisms like ecological or sexual isolation and hybrid sterility could fix the results of the earlier processes 59 Ford s ecological genetics 1940 Edit nbsp E B Ford studied polymorphism in the scarlet tiger moth for many years Further information Ecological genetics E B Ford was an experimental naturalist who wanted to test natural selection in nature virtually inventing the field of ecological genetics 60 His work on natural selection in wild populations of butterflies and moths was the first to show that predictions made by R A Fisher were correct In 1940 he was the first to describe and define genetic polymorphism and to predict that human blood group polymorphisms might be maintained in the population by providing some protection against disease 60 61 His 1949 book Mendelism and Evolution 62 helped to persuade Dobzhansky to change the emphasis in the third edition of his famous textbook Genetics and the Origin of Species from drift to selection 63 Schmalhausen s stabilizing selection 1941 Edit Further information Stabilizing selection Ivan Schmalhausen developed the theory of stabilizing selection the idea that selection can preserve a trait at some value publishing a paper in Russian titled Stabilizing selection and its place among factors of evolution in 1941 and a monograph Factors of Evolution The Theory of Stabilizing Selection 64 in 1945 He developed it from J M Baldwin s 1902 concept that changes induced by the environment will ultimately be replaced by hereditary changes including the Baldwin effect on behaviour following that theory s implications to their Darwinian conclusion and bringing him into conflict with Lysenkoism Schmalhausen observed that stabilizing selection would remove most variations from the norm most mutations being harmful 65 66 67 Dobzhansky called the work an important missing link in the modern view of evolution 68 Huxley s popularising synthesis 1942 Edit Main article Evolution The Modern Synthesis nbsp Julian Huxley presented a serious but popularising version of the theory in his 1942 book Evolution The Modern Synthesis In 1942 Julian Huxley s serious but popularising 69 70 Evolution The Modern Synthesis 2 introduced a name for the synthesis and intentionally set out to promote a synthetic point of view on the evolutionary process He imagined a wide synthesis of many sciences genetics developmental physiology ecology systematics palaeontology cytology and mathematical analysis of biology and assumed that evolution would proceed differently in different groups of organisms according to how their genetic material was organised and their strategies for reproduction leading to progressive but varying evolutionary trends 70 His vision was of an evolutionary humanism 71 with a system of ethics and a meaningful place for Man in the world grounded in a unified theory of evolution which would demonstrate progress leading to humanity at its summit Natural selection was in his view a fact of nature capable of verification by observation and experiment while the period of synthesis of the 1920s and 1930s had formed a more unified science 71 rivalling physics and enabling the rebirth of Darwinism 71 However the book was not the research text that it appeared to be In the view of the philosopher of science Michael Ruse and in Huxley s own opinion Huxley was a generalist a synthesizer of ideas rather than a specialist 69 Ruse observes that Huxley wrote as if he were adding empirical evidence to the mathematical framework established by Fisher and the population geneticists but that this was not so Huxley avoided mathematics for instance not even mentioning Fisher s fundamental theorem of natural selection Instead Huxley used a mass of examples to demonstrate that natural selection is powerful and that it works on Mendelian genes The book was successful in its goal of persuading readers of the reality of evolution effectively illustrating topics such as island biogeography speciation and competition Huxley further showed that the appearance of long term orthogenetic trends predictable directions for evolution in the fossil record were readily explained as allometric growth since parts are interconnected All the same Huxley did not reject orthogenesis out of hand but maintained a belief in progress all his life with Homo sapiens as the endpoint and he had since 1912 been influenced by the vitalist philosopher Henri Bergson though in public he maintained an atheistic position on evolution 69 Huxley s belief in progress within evolution and evolutionary humanism was shared in various forms by Dobzhansky Mayr Simpson and Stebbins all of them writing about the future of Mankind Both Huxley and Dobzhansky admired the palaeontologist priest Pierre Teilhard de Chardin Huxley writing the introduction to Teilhard s 1955 book on orthogenesis The Phenomenon of Man This vision required evolution to be seen as the central and guiding principle of biology 71 Mayr s allopatric speciation 1942 Edit Main articles Systematics and the Origin of Species and Allopatric speciation nbsp Ernst Mayr argued that geographic isolation was needed to provide sufficient reproductive isolation for new species to form Ernst Mayr s key contribution to the synthesis was Systematics and the Origin of Species published in 1942 72 It asserted the importance of and set out to explain population variation in evolutionary processes including speciation He analysed in particular the effects of polytypic species geographic variation and isolation by geographic and other means 73 Mayr emphasized the importance of allopatric speciation where geographically isolated sub populations diverge so far that reproductive isolation occurs He was skeptical of the reality of sympatric speciation believing that geographical isolation was a prerequisite for building up intrinsic reproductive isolating mechanisms Mayr also introduced the biological species concept that defined a species as a group of interbreeding or potentially interbreeding populations that were reproductively isolated from all other populations 40 42 74 75 Before he left Germany for the United States in 1930 Mayr had been influenced by the work of the German biologist Bernhard Rensch who in the 1920s had analyzed the geographic distribution of polytypic species paying particular attention to how variations between populations correlated with factors such as differences in climate 76 77 78 nbsp George Gaylord Simpson argued against the naive view that evolution such as of the horse took place in a straight line He noted that any chosen line is one path in a complex branching tree natural selection having no imposed direction Simpson s palaeontology 1944 Edit George Gaylord Simpson was responsible for showing that the modern synthesis was compatible with palaeontology in his 1944 book Tempo and Mode in Evolution Simpson s work was crucial because so many palaeontologists had disagreed in some cases vigorously with the idea that natural selection was the main mechanism of evolution It showed that the trends of linear progression in for example the evolution of the horse that earlier palaeontologists had used as support for neo Lamarckism and orthogenesis did not hold up under careful examination Instead the fossil record was consistent with the irregular branching and non directional pattern predicted by the modern synthesis 40 42 Society for the Study of Evolution 1946 Edit During World War II Mayr edited a series of bulletins of the Committee on Common Problems of Genetics Paleontology and Systematics formed in 1943 reporting on discussions of a synthetic attack on the interdisciplinary problems of evolution In 1946 the committee became the Society for the Study of Evolution with Mayr Dobzhansky and Sewall Wright the first of the signatories Mayr became the editor of its journal Evolution From Mayr and Dobzhansky s point of view suggests the historian of science Betty Smocovitis Darwinism was reborn evolutionary biology was legitimised and genetics and evolution were synthesised into a newly unified science Everything fitted into the new framework except heretics like Richard Goldschmidt who annoyed Mayr and Dobzhansky by insisting on the possibility of speciation by macromutation creating hopeful monsters The result was bitter controversy 51 nbsp Speciation via polyploidy a diploid cell may fail to separate during meiosis producing diploid gametes which self fertilize to produce a fertile tetraploid zygote that cannot interbreed with its parent species Stebbins s botany 1950 Edit The botanist G Ledyard Stebbins extended the synthesis to encompass botany He described the important effects on speciation of hybridization and polyploidy in plants in his 1950 book Variation and Evolution in Plants These permitted evolution to proceed rapidly at times polyploidy in particular evidently being able to create new species effectively instantaneously 40 79 Definitions by the founders EditThe modern synthesis was defined differently by its various founders with differing numbers of basic postulates as shown in the table Definitions of the modern synthesis by its founders as they numbered them Component Mayr 1959 Stebbins 1966 Dobzhansky 1974Mutation 1 Randomness in all events that produce new genotypes e g mutation 80 1 a source of variability but not of direction 81 1 yields genetic raw materials 82 Recombination 1 Randomness in recombination fertilisation 80 2 a source of variability but not of direction 81 Chromosomal organisation 3 affects genetic linkage arranges variation in gene pool 81 Natural selection 2 is only direction giving factor 80 83 as seen in adaptations to physical and biotic environment 80 4 guides changes to gene pool 81 2 constructs evolutionary changes from genetic raw materials 82 Reproductive isolation 5 limits direction in which selection can guide the population 81 3 makes divergence irreversible in sexual organisms 82 After the synthesis EditAfter the synthesis evolutionary biology continued to develop with major contributions from workers including W D Hamilton 84 George C Williams 85 E O Wilson 86 Edward B Lewis 87 and others Hamilton s inclusive fitness 1964 Edit Further information Inclusive fitness and Kin selection In 1964 W D Hamilton published two papers on The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour These defined inclusive fitness as the number of offspring equivalents an individual rears rescues or otherwise supports through its behaviour This was contrasted with personal reproductive fitness the number of offspring that the individual directly begets Hamilton and others such as John Maynard Smith argued that a gene s success consisted in maximising the number of copies of itself either by begetting them or by indirectly encouraging begetting by related individuals who shared the gene the theory of kin selection 84 88 Williams s gene centred evolution 1966 Edit Further information Gene centered view of evolution and Adaptation and Natural Selection In 1966 George C Williams published Adaptation and Natural Selection outlined a gene centred view of evolution following Hamilton s concepts disputing the idea of evolutionary progress and attacking the then widespread theory of group selection Williams argued that natural selection worked by changing the frequency of alleles and could not work at the level of groups 89 85 Gene centred evolution was popularised by Richard Dawkins in his 1976 book The Selfish Gene and developed in his more technical writings 90 91 Wilson s sociobiology 1975 Edit nbsp Ant societies have evolved elaborate caste structures widely different in size and function Main article Sociobiology In 1975 E O Wilson published his controversial 92 book Sociobiology The New Synthesis the subtitle alluding to the modern synthesis 86 as he attempted to bring the study of animal society into the evolutionary fold This appeared radically new although Wilson was following Darwin Fisher Dawkins and others 86 Critics such as Gerhard Lenski noted that he was following Huxley Simpson and Dobzhansky s approach which Lenski considered needlessly reductive as far as human society was concerned 93 By 2000 the proposed discipline of sociobiology had morphed into the relatively well accepted discipline of evolutionary psychology 86 Lewis s homeotic genes 1978 Edit nbsp Evolutionary developmental biology has formed a synthesis of evolutionary and developmental biology discovering deep homology between the embryogenesis of such different animals as insects and vertebrates Main article Evolutionary developmental biology In 1977 recombinant DNA technology enabled biologists to start to explore the genetic control of development The growth of evolutionary developmental biology from 1978 when Edward B Lewis discovered homeotic genes showed that many so called toolkit genes act to regulate development influencing the expression of other genes It also revealed that some of the regulatory genes are extremely ancient so that animals as different as insects and mammals share control mechanisms for example the Pax6 gene is involved in forming the eyes of mice and of fruit flies Such deep homology provided strong evidence for evolution and indicated the paths that evolution had taken 87 Later syntheses EditIn 1982 a historical note on a series of evolutionary biology books f could state without qualification that evolution is the central organizing principle of biology Smocovitis commented on this that What the architects of the synthesis had worked to construct had by 1982 become a matter of fact adding in a footnote that the centrality of evolution had thus been rendered tacit knowledge part of the received wisdom of the profession 94 By the late 20th century however the modern synthesis was showing its age and fresh syntheses to remedy its defects and fill in its gaps were proposed from different directions These have included such diverse fields as the study of society 86 developmental biology 49 epigenetics 95 molecular biology microbiology genomics 96 symbiogenesis and horizontal gene transfer 97 The physiologist Denis Noble argues that these additions render neo Darwinism in the sense of the early 20th century s modern synthesis at the least incomplete as a theory of evolution 97 and one that has been falsified by later biological research 97 Michael Rose and Todd Oakley note that evolutionary biology formerly divided and Balkanized has been brought together by genomics It has in their view discarded at least five common assumptions from the modern synthesis namely that the genome is always a well organised set of genes that each gene has a single function that species are well adapted biochemically to their ecological niches that species are the durable units of evolution and all levels from organism to organ cell and molecule within the species are characteristic of it and that the design of every organism and cell is efficient They argue that the new biology integrates genomics bioinformatics and evolutionary genetics into a general purpose toolkit for a Postmodern Synthesis 53 Pigliucci s extended evolutionary synthesis 2007 Edit Main article Extended evolutionary synthesis In 2007 more than half a century after the modern synthesis Massimo Pigliucci called for an extended evolutionary synthesis to incorporate aspects of biology that had not been included or had not existed in the mid 20th century 98 99 It revisits the relative importance of different factors challenges assumptions made in the modern synthesis and adds new factors 99 100 such as multilevel selection transgenerational epigenetic inheritance niche construction and evolvability 101 95 102 Koonin s post modern evolutionary synthesis 2009 Edit nbsp A 21st century tree of life showing horizontal gene transfers among prokaryotes and the saltational endosymbiosis events that created the eukaryotes neither fitting into the 20th century s modern synthesisIn 2009 Darwin s 200th anniversary the Origin of Species 150th and the 200th of Lamarck s early evolutionary synthesis 96 Philosophie Zoologique the evolutionary biologist Eugene Koonin stated that while the edifice of the early 20th century Modern Synthesis has crumbled apparently beyond repair 96 a new 21st century synthesis could be glimpsed Three interlocking revolutions had he argued taken place in evolutionary biology molecular microbiological and genomic The molecular revolution included the neutral theory that most mutations are neutral and that negative selection happens more often than the positive form and that all current life evolved from a single common ancestor In microbiology the synthesis has expanded to cover the prokaryotes using ribosomal RNA to form a tree of life Finally genomics brought together the molecular and microbiological syntheses in particular horizontal gene transfer between bacteria shows that prokaryotes can freely share genes Many of these points had already been made by other researchers such as Ulrich Kutschera and Karl J Niklas 103 Towards a replacement synthesis Edit nbsp Inputs to the modern synthesis with other topics inverted colours such as developmental biology that were not joined with evolutionary biology until the turn of the 21st century 103 Biologists alongside scholars of the history and philosophy of biology have continued to debate the need for and possible nature of a replacement synthesis For example in 2017 Philippe Huneman and Denis M Walsh stated in their book Challenging the Modern Synthesis that numerous theorists had pointed out that the disciplines of embryological developmental theory morphology and ecology had been omitted They noted that all such arguments amounted to a continuing desire to replace the modern synthesis with one that united all biological fields of research related to evolution adaptation and diversity in a single theoretical framework 104 They observed further that there are two groups of challenges to the way the modern synthesis viewed inheritance The first is that other modes such as epigenetic inheritance phenotypic plasticity the Baldwin effect and the maternal effect allow new characteristics to arise and be passed on and for the genes to catch up with the new adaptations later The second is that all such mechanisms are part not of an inheritance system but a developmental system the fundamental unit is not a discrete selfishly competing gene but a collaborating system that works at all levels from genes and cells to organisms and cultures to guide evolution 105 The molecular biologist Sean B Carroll has commented that had Huxley had access to evolutionary developmental biology embryology would have been a cornerstone of his Modern Synthesis and so evo devo is today a key element of a more complete expanded evolutionary synthesis 106 Historiography EditLooking back at the conflicting accounts of the modern synthesis the historian Betty Smocovitis notes in her 1996 book Unifying Biology The Evolutionary Synthesis and Evolutionary Biology that both historians and philosophers of biology have attempted to grasp its scientific meaning but have found it a moving target 107 the only thing they agreed on was that it was a historical event 107 In her words by the late 1980s the notoriety of the evolutionary synthesis was recognized So notorious did the synthesis become that few serious historically minded analysts would touch the subject let alone know where to begin to sort through the interpretive mess left behind by the numerous critics and commentators 108 See also EditDevelopmental systems theory Gene centered view of evolution History of evolutionary thought Neo Darwinism Objections to evolutionNotes Edit Also known variously as the New Synthesis the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis the Evolutionary Synthesis and the neo Darwinian Synthesis These alternative terms are ambiguous as they could possibly include later syntheses so this article uses Julian Huxley s 1942 modern synthesis 2 throughout Peter Gauthier has however argued that Weismann s experiment showed only that injury did not affect the germplasm It did not test the effect of Lamarckian use and disuse 13 Morgan s work with fruit flies helped establish the link between Mendelian genetics and the chromosomal theory of inheritance that the hereditary material was embodied in these bodies within the cell nucleus 33 Fisher also analysed sexual selection in his book but his work was largely ignored and Darwin s case for such selection misunderstood so it formed no substantial part of the modern synthesis 41 Though C H Waddington had called for embryology to be added to the synthesis in his 1953 paper Epigenetics and Evolution 51 In a reissue of Dobzhansky s Genetics and the Origin of Species References Edit Gould 2002 p 216 a b Huxley 2010 Bowler 2003 pp 236 256 Kutschera Ulrich December 2003 A comparative analysis of the Darwin Wallace papers and the development of the concept of natural selection Theory in Biosciences 122 4 343 359 doi 10 1007 s12064 003 0063 6 S2CID 24297627 Butler Samuel 1880 Unconscious Memory David Bogue p 280 I may predict with some certainty that before long we shall find the original Darwinism of Dr Erasmus Darwin generally accepted instead of the neo Darwinism of to day and that the variations whose accumulation results in species will be recognised as due to the wants and endeavours of the living forms in which they appear instead of being ascribed to chance or in other words to unknown causes as by Mr Charles Darwin s system Beccaloni George 2013 On the Terms Darwinism and Neo Darwinism A R Wallace Website Bowler 2003 pp 196 253 Larson 2004 pp 105 129 Gayon Jean 1998 Darwinism s Struggle for Survival Heredity and the Hypothesis of Natural Selection Cambridge University Press pp 2 3 ISBN 978 0 521 56250 8 Darwin Charles 1868 The variation of animals and plants under domestication John Murray ISBN 978 1 4191 8660 8 Holterhoff Kate 2014 The History and Reception of Charles Darwin s Hypothesis of Pangenesis Journal of the History of Biology 47 4 661 695 doi 10 1007 s10739 014 9377 0 PMID 24570302 S2CID 207150548 Weismann August 1892 Das Keimplasma eine Theorie der Vererbung The Germ Plasm A theory of inheritance Jena Fischer Gauthier Peter March May 1990 Does Weismann s Experiment Constitute a Refutation of the Lamarckian Hypothesis BIOS 61 1 2 6 8 JSTOR 4608123 Bowler 1989 p 248 Bowler 2003 pp 253 256 Bowler 1989 pp 247 253 257 Ambrose Mike Mendel s Peas Norwich UK Germplasm Resources Unit John Innes Centre Archived from the original on 14 June 2016 Retrieved 14 December 2017 Reviewing Mendel s Laws Pearson Retrieved 14 October 2017 Bateson 1894 Mutations as sports and polymorphisms were well known long before the Mendelian recovery Larson 2004 pp 157 166 Bowler 1989 pp 275 276 a b Grafen amp Ridley 2006 p 69 Provine 2001 p 69 Olby Robert September 1989 The Dimensions of Scientific Controversy The Biometric Mendelian Debate The British Journal for the History of Science 22 3 299 320 doi 10 1017 s0007087400026170 JSTOR 4026898 PMID 11621982 S2CID 36719974 Gayon J 1988 Darwinism s Struggle for Survival Heredity and the Hypothesis of Natural Selection Cambridge University Press Stoltzfus Arlin Cable Kele 2014 Mendelian Mutationism The Forgotten Evolutionary Synthesis PDF Journal of the History of Biology 47 4 501 546 doi 10 1007 s10739 014 9383 2 PMID 24811736 S2CID 23263558 Archived PDF from the original on 2014 11 30 Bateson William Saunders E R 1902 Experimental Studies in the Physiology of Heredity Royal Society Reports to the Evolution Committee Yule G Udny 1902 Mendel s Laws and their probable relations to inter racial heredity New Phytologist 1 10 226 227 doi 10 1111 j 1469 8137 1902 tb07336 x Provine 2001 pp 81 82 Provine 2001 pp 109 114 Castle W E 7 April 1905 The Mutation Theory of Organic Evolution from the Standpoint of Animal Breeding Science 21 536 521 525 Bibcode 1905Sci 21 521C doi 10 1126 science 21 536 521 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 17770959 Vicedo Marga 2000 Castle William Ernest 1867 1962 biologist American National Biography Online Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 anb 9780198606697 article 1302308 a b Bowler 2003 pp 271 272 Provine 2001 pp 120 121 a b Smocovitis 1996 pp 100 114 Smocovitis 1996 pp 114 119 Smocovitis 1996 pp 119 122 Fisher Ronald A January 1919 XV The Correlation between Relatives on the Supposition of Mendelian Inheritance Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 52 2 399 433 doi 10 1017 S0080456800012163 OCLC 4981124 S2CID 181213898 Paper read by J Arthur Thomson on July 8 1918 to the Royal Society of Edinburgh Fisher 1999 a b c d e f g h Larson 2004 pp 221 243 Hosken David J House Clarissa M 25 January 2011 Sexual Selection Current Biology 21 2 R62 R65 doi 10 1016 j cub 2010 11 053 PMID 21256434 S2CID 18470445 a b c d e f Bowler 2003 pp 325 339 a b Smocovitis 1996 pp 122 132 Smocovitis 1996 p 192 Held Lewis I 2014 How the Snake Lost its Legs Curious Tales from the Frontier of Evo Devo Cambridge University Press p 67 ISBN 978 1 107 62139 8 Gould 1977 pp 221 222 Hall B K 2003 Evo Devo evolutionary developmental mechanisms International Journal of Developmental Biology 47 7 8 491 495 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 113 5158 PMID 14756324 Ingo Brigandt 2006 Homology and heterochrony the evolutionary embryologist Gavin Rylands de Beer 1899 1972 PDF Journal of Experimental Zoology 306B 4 317 328 doi 10 1002 jez b 21100 PMID 16506229 Archived PDF from the original on 2006 11 04 a b Gilbert S F Opitz J M Raff R A 1996 Resynthesizing evolutionary and developmental biology Developmental Biology 173 2 357 372 doi 10 1006 dbio 1996 0032 PMID 8605997 Adams M 1991 Warren L Koprowski H eds Through the looking glass The evolution of Soviet Darwinism pp 37 63 ISBN 978 0 471 56068 5 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help a b Smocovitis 1996 pp 153 171 Wright 1932 pp 356 366 a b Rose Michael R Oakley Todd H November 24 2007 The new biology beyond the Modern Synthesis PDF Biology Direct 2 30 30 doi 10 1186 1745 6150 2 30 PMC 2222615 PMID 18036242 Archived PDF from the original on 2014 03 21 Huxley Julian 1942 Evolution The Modern Synthesis Allen amp Unwin Ridley Matt 1996 Evolution 2nd ed Blackwell Science ISBN 978 0632042920 Mayr amp Provine 1998 p 231 Dobzhansky 1937 Smocovitis 1996 p 127 Eldredge Niles 1985 Unfinished Synthesis Biological Hierarchies and Modern Evolutionary Thought Oxford University Press p 17 ISBN 978 0 19 536513 9 a b Ford 1964 Ford 1975 Ford E B 1949 Mendelism and Evolution Methuen Dobzhansky 1951 Schmalhausen Ivan I Dordick Isadore trans 1949 Dobzhansky Theodosius ed Factors of Evolution The Theory of Stabilizing Selection Philadelphia and Toronto Blakiston Company Levit Georgy S Hossfeld Uwe Olsson Lennart 2006 From the Modern Synthesis to Cybernetics Ivan Ivanovich Schmalhausen 1884 1963 and his Research Program for a Synthesis of Evolutionary and Developmental Biology Journal of Experimental Zoology 306B 2006 89 106 doi 10 1002 jez b 21087 PMID 16419076 S2CID 23594114 Adams M B June 1988 A Missing Link in the Evolutionary Synthesis I I Schmalhausen Factors of Evolution The Theory of Stabilizing Selection Isis 79 297 281 284 doi 10 1086 354706 PMID 3049441 S2CID 146660877 Glass Bentley December 1951 Reviews and Brief Notices Factors of Evolution The Theory of Stabilizing Selection I I Schmalhausen Isadore Dordick Theodosius Dobzhansky Quarterly Review of Biology 26 4 384 385 doi 10 1086 398434 Mayr amp Provine 1998 p ix a b c Ruse 1996 pp 328 338 a b Lamm Ehud Review of Julian Huxley Evolution The Modern Synthesis The Definitive Edition with a new foreword by Massimo Pigliucci and Gerd B Muller PDF MIT Press Archived PDF from the original on 2011 12 24 Retrieved 21 August 2017 a b c d Smocovitis 1996 pp 138 153 Mayr 1999 Hey Jody Fitch Walter M Ayala Francisco J 2005 Systematics and the origin of species An introduction PNAS 102 supplement 1 6515 6519 Bibcode 2005PNAS 102 6515H doi 10 1073 pnas 0501939102 PMC 1131868 PMID 15851660 Mayr amp Provine 1998 pp 33 34 Mayr 1982 Rensch 1947 Rensch 1959 Smith Charles H Rensch Bernhard Carl Emmanuel Germany 1900 1990 Some Biogeographers Evolutionists and Ecologists Chrono Biographical Sketches Western Kentucky University Retrieved 14 December 2017 Mayr amp Provine 1998 pp 298 299 416 Smocovitis V B 2001 G Ledyard Stebbins and the evolutionary synthesis Annual Review of Genetics 35 803 814 doi 10 1146 annurev genet 35 102401 091525 PMID 11700300 a b c d Mayr E Where Are We Cold Spring Harbor Symposium of Quantitative Biology 24 1 14 1959 a b c d e Stebbins G L Processes of Organic Evolution p 12 Prentice Hall 1966 a b c Dobzhansky T In Ayala F Dobzhansky T eds Chance and Creativity in Evolution pp 307 338 University of California Press Berkeley and Los Angeles 1974 Mayr E In Mayr E Provine W eds Some Thoughts on the History of the Evolutionary Synthesis pp 1 48 Harvard University Press 1980 a b Hamilton W D 1964 The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour I PDF Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 1 1 52 Bibcode 1964JThBi 7 1H doi 10 1016 0022 5193 64 90038 4 PMID 5875341 Archived PDF from the original on 2016 12 18 a b Williams George C 1966 Adaptation and Natural Selection Princeton University Press p 307 ISBN 978 0 691 02615 2 a b c d e Yudell Michael Desalle Rob 2000 Sociobiology The New Synthesis by Edward O Wilson Journal of the History of Biology 33 3 577 584 doi 10 1023 a 1004845822189 JSTOR 4331614 S2CID 88047081 a b Gilbert S F 2000 A New Evolutionary Synthesis a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Maynard Smith John 1964 Group Selection and Kin Selection Nature 201 4924 1145 1147 Bibcode 1964Natur 201 1145S doi 10 1038 2011145a0 S2CID 4177102 Pinker Steven 1994 The Language Instinct Harper Perennial Modern Classics p 294 Okasha Samir September 22 2006 Population Genetics via plato stanford edu a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Dawkins Richard 1982 The Extended Phenotype Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 288051 2 Fisher Helen 16 October 1994 Wilson They Said Your All Wet New York Times Retrieved 21 July 2015 Lenski Gerhard 1976 Sociobiology The New Synthesis by Edward O Wilson Social Forces 55 2 530 531 doi 10 2307 2576242 JSTOR 2576242 Smocovitis 1996 pp 186 187 a b Pigliucci Massimo Finkelman Leonard 2014 The Extended Evolutionary Synthesis Debate Where Science Meets Philosophy BioScience 64 6 511 516 doi 10 1093 biosci biu062 a b c Koonin Eugene V November 2009 The Origin at 150 is a new evolutionary synthesis in sight Trends in Genetics 25 11 473 475 doi 10 1016 j tig 2009 09 007 PMC 2784144 PMID 19836100 a b c Noble Denis 2011 Neo Darwinism the Modern Synthesis and selfish genes are they of use in physiology The Journal of Physiology 589 5 1007 1015 doi 10 1113 jphysiol 2010 201384 PMC 3060581 PMID 21135048 Wade Michael J 2011 The Neo Modern Synthesis The Confluence of New Data and Explanatory Concepts BioScience 61 5 407 408 doi 10 1525 bio 2011 61 5 10 a b John Odling Smee et al The extended evolutionary synthesis its structure assumptions and predictions Proceedings of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences August 2015 Wade Michael J 2011 The Neo Modern Synthesis The Confluence of New Data and Explanatory Concepts BioScience 61 5 407 408 doi 10 1525 bio 2011 61 5 10 Danchin E Charmantier A Champagne F A Mesoudi A Pujol B Blanchet S 2011 Beyond DNA integrating inclusive inheritance into an extended theory of evolution Nature Reviews Genetics 12 7 475 486 doi 10 1038 nrg3028 PMID 21681209 S2CID 8837202 Laubichler Manfred D Renn Jurgen 2015 Extended evolution A Conceptual Framework for Integrating Regulatory Networks and Niche Construction Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B Molecular and Developmental Evolution 324 7 565 577 doi 10 1002 jez b 22631 PMC 4744698 PMID 26097188 a b Kutschera Ulrich Niklas Karl J June 2004 The modern theory of biological evolution an expanded synthesis Naturwissenschaften 91 6 255 276 Bibcode 2004NW 91 255K doi 10 1007 s00114 004 0515 y PMID 15241603 S2CID 10731711 Huneman Philippe Walsh Denis M 2017 Challenging the Modern Synthesis Adaptation Development and Inheritance Oxford University Press pp 76 Chapter 2 ISBN 978 0 19 068145 6 Huneman Philippe Walsh Denis M 2017 Challenging the Modern Synthesis Adaptation Development and Inheritance Oxford University Press pp Introduction ISBN 978 0 19 068145 6 Carroll Sean B 2008 Evo Devo and an Expanding Evolutionary Synthesis A Genetic Theory of Morphological Evolution Cell 134 1 25 36 doi 10 1016 j cell 2008 06 030 PMID 18614008 S2CID 2513041 a b Smocovitis 1996 p 187 Smocovitis 1996 p 43Sources EditBateson William 1894 Materials for the Study of Variation Treated with Especial Regard to Discontinuity in the Origin of Species London New York Macmillan LCCN 07001821 OCLC 1944285 Bowler Peter J 2003 Evolution The History of an Idea 3rd completely rev and expanded ed Berkeley CA University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 23693 6 Bowler Peter J 1989 Evolution The History of an Idea 2nd revised ed Berkeley CA University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 06386 0 Dobzhansky Theodosius 1937 Genetics and the Origin of Species Columbia University Biological Series New York Columbia University Press LCCN 37033383 OCLC 766405 1951 Genetics and the Origin of Species Columbia University Biological Series 3rd revised ed New York Columbia University Press LCCN 51014816 OCLC 295774 Fisher R A 1999 1930 The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection Edited with a foreword and notes by J H Bennett A complete variorum ed Oxford UK Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 850440 5 Ford E B 1964 Ecological Genetics Advancement of Science London New York Methuen Publishing John Wiley amp Sons 25 124 227 35 LCCN 64009038 OCLC 875507052 PMID 5701915 1975 Ecological Genetics Advancement of Science 4th ed London New York Chapman and Hall John Wiley amp Sons 25 124 227 35 LCCN 75002165 OCLC 1890603 PMID 5701915 Gould Stephen Jay 1977 Ontogeny and Phylogeny Belknap Press of Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 63940 9 Gould Stephen Jay 2002 The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Belknap Press of Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 00613 3 Grafen Alan Ridley Mark eds 2006 Richard Dawkins How a Scientist Changed the Way We Think Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 929116 8 Huxley Julian 2010 1942 Evolution The Modern Synthesis With a new foreword by Massimo Pigliucci and Gerd B Muller Definitive ed Cambridge MA MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 51366 1 Larson Edward J 2004 Evolution The Remarkable History of a Scientific Theory Modern Library Chronicles Vol 17 New York Modern Library ISBN 978 0 679 64288 6 Mayr Ernst 1982 The Growth of Biological Thought Diversity Evolution and Inheritance Cambridge MA Belknap Press of Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 36445 5 Mayr Ernst 1999 1942 Systematics and the Origin of Species from the Viewpoint of a Zoologist 1st Harvard University Press pbk ed Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 86250 0 Mayr Ernst Provine William B eds 1998 1980 The Evolutionary Synthesis Perspectives on the Unification of Biology With a new preface by Ernst Mayr 1st paperback ed Cambridge MA Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 27226 2 Provine W B 2001 The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics with a new afterword University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 68464 2 Rensch Bernhard 1947 Neuere Probleme der Abstammungslehre Die transspezifische Evolution Newer Problems of Evolutionary Theory The trans specific Evolution in German Stuttgart Ferdinand Enke Verlag OCLC 2271422 1959 Evolution Above the Species Level American Journal of Physical Anthropology English translation of 2nd edition of Neuere Probleme der Abstammungslehre 1954 Columbia Biological Series 19 3 408 410 doi 10 1002 ajpa 1330200329 LCCN 60002460 OCLC 3677530 Ruse Michael 1996 Monad to man the Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 03248 4 Smocovitis Vassiliki Betty 1996 Unifying Biology The Evolutionary Synthesis and Evolutionary Biology pp 1 65 doi 10 1007 bf01947504 ISBN 978 0 691 03343 3 PMID 11623198 S2CID 189833728 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help Wright Sewall 1932 The Roles of Mutation Inbreeding Crossbreeding and Selection in Evolution In Jones Donald F ed Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Genetics Vol 1 Ithaca NY Genetics Society of America OCLC 439596433 Further reading EditAllen Garland E 1978 Thomas Hunt Morgan The Man and His Science Princeton NJ Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 08200 4 Dawkins Richard 1990 The Blind Watchmaker Penguin Science London Penguin Books ISBN 978 0 14 014481 9 Futuyma Douglas J 1998 Evolutionary Biology 3rd ed Sunderland MA Sinauer Associates ISBN 978 0 87893 189 7 Haldane J B S 1932 The Causes of Evolution London New York Longmans Green amp Co LCCN 32033284 OCLC 5006266 This book is based on a series of lectures delivered in January 1931 at the Prifysgol Cymru Aberystwyth and entitled A re examination of Darwinism Huxley Julian ed 1976 Originally published 1940 Oxford UK The Clarendon Press The New Systematics Reprint ed St Clair Shores MI Scholarly Press ISBN 978 0 403 01786 7 Levinson Gene 2020 Rethinking evolution the revolution that s hiding in plain sight World Scientific ISBN 9781786347268 Wright Sewall March 1 1931 Evolution in Mendelian Populations Genetics 16 2 97 159 doi 10 1093 genetics 16 2 97 PMC 1201091 PMID 17246615 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Modern synthesis 20th century amp oldid 1172067131, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.