fbpx
Wikipedia

Reductionism

Reductionism is any of several related philosophical ideas regarding the associations between phenomena which can be described in terms of other simpler or more fundamental phenomena.[1] It is also described as an intellectual and philosophical position that interprets a complex system as the sum of its parts.[2]

René Descartes, in De homine (1662), claimed that non-human animals could be explained reductively as automata; meaning essentially as more mechanically complex versions of this Digesting Duck.

Definitions edit

The Oxford Companion to Philosophy suggests that reductionism is "one of the most used and abused terms in the philosophical lexicon" and suggests a three-part division:[3]

  1. Ontological reductionism: a belief that the whole of reality consists of a minimal number of parts.
  2. Methodological reductionism: the scientific attempt to provide an explanation in terms of ever-smaller entities.
  3. Theory reductionism: the suggestion that a newer theory does not replace or absorb an older one, but reduces it to more basic terms. Theory reduction itself is divisible into three parts: translation, derivation, and explanation.[4]

Reductionism can be applied to any phenomenon, including objects, problems, explanations, theories, and meanings.[4][5][6]

For the sciences, application of methodological reductionism attempts explanation of entire systems in terms of their individual, constituent parts and their interactions. For example, the temperature of a gas is reduced to nothing beyond the average kinetic energy of its molecules in motion. Thomas Nagel and others speak of 'psychophysical reductionism' (the attempted reduction of psychological phenomena to physics and chemistry), and 'physico-chemical reductionism' (the attempted reduction of biology to physics and chemistry).[7] In a very simplified and sometimes contested form, reductionism is said to imply that a system is nothing but the sum of its parts.[5][8]

However, a more nuanced opinion is that a system is composed entirely of its parts, but the system will have features that none of the parts have (which, in essence is the basis of emergentism).[9] "The point of mechanistic explanations is usually showing how the higher level features arise from the parts."[8]

Other definitions are used by other authors. For example, what John Polkinghorne terms 'conceptual' or 'epistemological' reductionism[5] is the definition provided by Simon Blackburn[10] and by Jaegwon Kim:[11] that form of reductionism which concerns a program of replacing the facts or entities involved in one type of discourse with other facts or entities from another type, thereby providing a relationship between them. Richard Jones distinguishes ontological and epistemological reductionism, arguing that many ontological and epistemological reductionists affirm the need for different concepts for different degrees of complexity while affirming a reduction of theories.[9]

The idea of reductionism can be expressed by "levels" of explanation, with higher levels reducible if need be to lower levels. This use of levels of understanding in part expresses our human limitations in remembering detail. However, "most philosophers would insist that our role in conceptualizing reality [our need for a hierarchy of "levels" of understanding] does not change the fact that different levels of organization in reality do have different 'properties'."[9]

Reductionism does not preclude the existence of what might be termed emergent phenomena, but it does imply the ability to understand those phenomena completely in terms of the processes from which they are composed. This reductionist understanding is very different from ontological or strong emergentism, which intends that what emerges in "emergence" is more than the sum of the processes from which it emerges, respectively either in the ontological sense or in the epistemological sense.[12]

Ontological reductionism edit

Richard Jones divides ontological reductionism into two: the reductionism of substances (e.g., the reduction of mind to matter) and the reduction of the number of structures operating in nature (e.g., the reduction of one physical force to another). This permits scientists and philosophers to affirm the former while being anti-reductionists regarding the latter.[13]

Nancey Murphy has claimed that there are two species of ontological reductionism: one that claims that wholes are nothing more than their parts; and atomist reductionism, claiming that wholes are not "really real". She admits that the phrase "really real" is apparently senseless but she has tried to explicate the supposed difference between the two.[14]

Ontological reductionism denies the idea of ontological emergence, and claims that emergence is an epistemological phenomenon that only exists through analysis or description of a system, and does not exist fundamentally.[15]

In some scientific disciplines, ontological reductionism takes two forms: token-identity theory and type-identity theory.[16] In this case, "token" refers to a biological process.[17]

Token ontological reductionism is the idea that every item that exists is a sum item. For perceivable items, it affirms that every perceivable item is a sum of items with a lesser degree of complexity. Token ontological reduction of biological things to chemical things is generally accepted.

Type ontological reductionism is the idea that every type of item is a sum type of item, and that every perceivable type of item is a sum of types of items with a lesser degree of complexity. Type ontological reduction of biological things to chemical things is often rejected.

Michael Ruse has criticized ontological reductionism as an improper argument against vitalism.[18]

Methodological reductionism edit

In a biological context, methodological reductionism means attempting to explain all biological phenomena in terms of their underlying biochemical and molecular processes.[19]

In religion edit

Anthropologists Edward Burnett Tylor and James George Frazer employed some religious reductionist arguments.[20]

Theory reductionism edit

Theory reduction is the process by which a more general theory absorbs a special theory.[2] It can be further divided into translation, derivation, and explanation.[21] For example, both Kepler's laws of the motion of the planets and Galileo's theories of motion formulated for terrestrial objects are reducible to Newtonian theories of mechanics because all the explanatory power of the former are contained within the latter. Furthermore, the reduction is considered beneficial because Newtonian mechanics is a more general theory—that is, it explains more events than Galileo's or Kepler's. Besides scientific theories, theory reduction more generally can be the process by which one explanation subsumes another.

In mathematics edit

In mathematics, reductionism can be interpreted as the philosophy that all mathematics can (or ought to) be based on a common foundation, which for modern mathematics is usually axiomatic set theory. Ernst Zermelo was one of the major advocates of such an opinion; he also developed much of axiomatic set theory. It has been argued that the generally accepted method of justifying mathematical axioms by their usefulness in common practice can potentially weaken Zermelo's reductionist claim.[22]

Jouko Väänänen has argued for second-order logic as a foundation for mathematics instead of set theory,[23] whereas others have argued for category theory as a foundation for certain aspects of mathematics.[24][25]

The incompleteness theorems of Kurt Gödel, published in 1931, caused doubt about the attainability of an axiomatic foundation for all of mathematics. Any such foundation would have to include axioms powerful enough to describe the arithmetic of the natural numbers (a subset of all mathematics). Yet Gödel proved that, for any consistent recursively enumerable axiomatic system powerful enough to describe the arithmetic of the natural numbers, there are (model-theoretically) true propositions about the natural numbers that cannot be proved from the axioms. Such propositions are known as formally undecidable propositions. For example, the continuum hypothesis is undecidable in the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory as shown by Cohen.

In science edit

Reductionist thinking and methods form the basis for many of the well-developed topics of modern science, including much of physics, chemistry and molecular biology. Classical mechanics in particular is seen as a reductionist framework. For instance, we understand the solar system in terms of its components (the sun and the planets) and their interactions.[26] Statistical mechanics can be considered as a reconciliation of macroscopic thermodynamic laws with the reductionist method of explaining macroscopic properties in terms of microscopic components, although it has been argued that reduction in physics 'never goes all the way in practice'.[27]

In computer science edit

The role of reduction in computer science can be thought as a precise and unambiguous mathematical formalization of the philosophical idea of "theory reductionism". In a general sense, a problem (or set) is said to be reducible to another problem (or set), if there is a computable/feasible method to translate the questions of the former into the latter, so that, if one knows how to computably/feasibly solve the latter problem, then one can computably/feasibly solve the former. Thus, the latter can only be at least as "hard" to solve as the former.

Reduction in theoretical computer science is pervasive in both: the mathematical abstract foundations of computation; and in real-world performance or capability analysis of algorithms. More specifically, reduction is a foundational and central concept, not only in the realm of mathematical logic and abstract computation in computability (or recursive) theory, where it assumes the form of e.g. Turing reduction, but also in the realm of real-world computation in time (or space) complexity analysis of algorithms, where it assumes the form of e.g. polynomial-time reduction.

Criticism edit

Free will edit

Philosophers of the Enlightenment worked to insulate human free will from reductionism. Descartes separated the material world of mechanical necessity from the world of mental free will. German philosophers introduced the concept of the "noumenal" realm that is not governed by the deterministic laws of "phenomenal" nature, where every event is completely determined by chains of causality.[28] The most influential formulation was by Immanuel Kant, who distinguished between the causal deterministic framework the mind imposes on the world—the phenomenal realm—and the world as it exists for itself, the noumenal realm, which, as he believed, included free will. To insulate theology from reductionism, 19th century post-Enlightenment German theologians, especially Friedrich Schleiermacher and Albrecht Ritschl, used the Romantic method of basing religion on the human spirit, so that it is a person's feeling or sensibility about spiritual matters that comprises religion.[29]

Causation edit

Most common philosophical understandings of causation involve reducing it to some collection of non-causal facts. Opponents of these reductionist views have given arguments that the non-causal facts in question are insufficient to determine the causal facts.[30]

Alfred North Whitehead's metaphysics opposed reductionism. He refers to this as the "fallacy of the misplaced concreteness". His scheme was to frame a rational, general understanding of phenomena, derived from our reality.

In science edit

An alternative term for ontological reductionism is fragmentalism,[31] often used in a pejorative sense.[32] In cognitive psychology, George Kelly developed "constructive alternativism" as a form of personal construct psychology and an alternative to what he considered "accumulative fragmentalism". For this theory, knowledge is seen as the construction of successful mental models of the exterior world, rather than the accumulation of independent "nuggets of truth".[33] Others argue that inappropriate use of reductionism limits our understanding of complex systems. In particular, ecologist Robert Ulanowicz says that science must develop techniques to study ways in which larger scales of organization influence smaller ones, and also ways in which feedback loops create structure at a given level, independently of details at a lower level of organization. He advocates (and uses) information theory as a framework to study propensities in natural systems.[34] The limits of the application of reductionism are claimed to be especially evident at levels of organization with greater complexity, including living cells,[35] neural networks, ecosystems, society, and other systems formed from assemblies of large numbers of diverse components linked by multiple feedback loops.[35][36]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Wendy Doniger, ed. (1999). "Reductionism". Merriam-Webster's Encyclopedia of World Religions. Merriam-Webster. p. 911. ISBN 978-0877790440.
  2. ^ a b Kricheldorf, Hans R. (2016). Getting It Right in Science and Medicine: Can Science Progress through Errors? Fallacies and Facts. Cham: Springer. p. 63. ISBN 978-3319303864.
  3. ^ Michael Ruse (2005). "Entry for "reductionism"". In Ted Honderich (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 793. ISBN 978-0191037474.
  4. ^ a b Alyssa Ney. "Reductionism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. IEP, University of Tennessee. Retrieved March 13, 2015.
  5. ^ a b c John Polkinghorne (2002). "Reductionism". Interdisciplinary Encyclopedia of Religion and Science. Advanced School for Interdisciplinary Research; Pontifical University of the Holy Cross.
  6. ^ For reductionism referred to explanations, theories, and meanings, see Willard Van Orman Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism. Quine objected to the positivistic, reductionist "belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience" as an intractable problem.
  7. ^ Thomas Nagel (2012). Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False. Oxford University Press. pp. 4–5. ISBN 978-0199919758.
  8. ^ a b Peter Godfrey-Smith (2013). Philosophy of Biology. Princeton University Press. p. 16. ISBN 978-1400850440.
  9. ^ a b c Richard H. Jones (2000). "Clarification of terminology". Reductionism: Analysis and the Fullness of Reality. Bucknell University Press. pp. 19– [27–28, 32]. ISBN 978-0838754399.
  10. ^ Simon Blackburn (2005). "Entry on 'reductionism'". Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press, UK. p. 311. ISBN 978-0198610137.
  11. ^ Jaegwon Kim (2005). "Entry for 'mental reductionism'". In Ted Honderich (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 794. ISBN 978-0191037474.
  12. ^ Axelrod and Cohen "Harnessing Complexity"
  13. ^ Richard H. Jones (2000), Reductionism: Analysis and the Fullness of Reality, pp. 24—26, 29–31. Lewisburg, Pa.: Bucknell University Press.
  14. ^ Nancey Murphy, "Reductionism and Emergence. A Critical Perspective." In Human Identity at the Intersection of Science, Technology and Religion. Edited by Nancey Murphy, and Christopher C. Knight. Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2010. P. 82.
  15. ^ Silberstein, Michael; McGeever, John (April 1999). "The Search for Ontological Emergence". The Philosophical Quarterly. 49 (195): 201–214. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00136. ISSN 0031-8094.
  16. ^ "Scientific Reduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  17. ^ "Reductionism in Biology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2022.
  18. ^ Ruse, Michael (1989). (PDF). Am. Zool. 29 (3): 1061–1066. doi:10.1093/icb/29.3.1061. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2008-10-02.
  19. ^ Brigandt, Ingo; Love, Alan (2017). "Reductionism in Biology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2019-04-28.
  20. ^ Strenski, Ivan. "Classic Twentieth-Century Theorist of the Study of Religion: Defending the Inner Sanctum of Religious Experience or Storming It." pp. 176–209 in Thinking About Religion: An Historical Introduction to Theories of Religion. Malden: Blackwell, 2006.
  21. ^ "Reductionism | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  22. ^ Taylor, R. Gregory (1993). "Zermelo, Reductionism, and the Philosophy of Mathematics". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 34 (4): 539–563. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093633905.
  23. ^ Väänänen, J. (2001). "Second-Order Logic and Foundations of Mathematics". Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 7 (4): 504–520. doi:10.2307/2687796. JSTOR 2687796. S2CID 7465054.
  24. ^ Awodey, S. (1996). "Structure in Mathematics and Logic: A Categorical Perspective". Philos. Math. Series III. 4 (3): 209–237. doi:10.1093/philmat/4.3.209.
  25. ^ Lawvere, F. W. (1966). "The Category of Categories as a Foundation for Mathematics". Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra (La Jolla, Calif., 1965). New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 1–20.
  26. ^ McCauley, Joseph L. (2009). Dynamics of Markets: The New Financial Economics, Second Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 241. ISBN 978-0521429627.
  27. ^ Simpson, William M. R.; Horsley, Simon A.H. (29 March 2022). "Toppling the Pyramids: Physics Without Physical State Monism". In Austin, Christopher J.; Marmodoro, Anna; Roselli, Andrea (eds.). Powers, Time and Free Will. Synthese Library. Vol. 451. Synthese Library. pp. 17–50. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-92486-7_2. ISBN 9781003125860 – via Springer.
  28. ^ Guyer, Paul (2020), "18th Century German Aesthetics", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2023-03-16
  29. ^ Philip Clayton and Zachary Simpson, eds. The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science (2006) p. 161
  30. ^ John W Carroll (2009). "Chapter 13: Anti-reductionism". In Helen Beebee; Christopher Hitchcock; Peter Menzies (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Causation. Oxford Handbooks Online. p. 292. ISBN 978-0199279739.
  31. ^ Kukla A (1996). "Antirealist Explanations of the Success of Science". Philosophy of Science. 63 (1): S298–S305. doi:10.1086/289964. JSTOR 188539. S2CID 171074337.
  32. ^ Pope ML (1982). "Personal construction of formal knowledge". Interchange. 13 (4): 3–14. doi:10.1007/BF01191417. S2CID 198195182.
  33. ^ Pope ML, Watts M (1988). "Constructivist Goggles: Implications for Process in Teaching and Learning Physics". Eur. J. Phys. 9 (2): 101–109. Bibcode:1988EJPh....9..101P. doi:10.1088/0143-0807/9/2/004. S2CID 250876891.
  34. ^ R.E. Ulanowicz, Ecology: The Ascendant Perspective, Columbia University Press (1997) (ISBN 0231108281)
  35. ^ a b Huber, F; Schnauss, J; Roenicke, S; Rauch, P; Mueller, K; Fuetterer, C; Kaes, J (2013). "Emergent complexity of the cytoskeleton: from single filaments to tissue". Advances in Physics. 62 (1): 1–112. Bibcode:2013AdPhy..62....1H. doi:10.1080/00018732.2013.771509. PMC 3985726. PMID 24748680. online
  36. ^ Clayton, P; Davies, P, eds. (2006). "The Re-emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion". New York: Oxford University Press. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)

Further reading edit

  • Churchland, Patricia (1986), Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. MIT Press.
  • Dawkins, Richard (1976), The Selfish Gene. Oxford University Press; 2nd edition, December 1989.
  • Dennett, Daniel C. (1995) Darwin's Dangerous Idea. Simon & Schuster.
  • Descartes (1637), Discourses, Part V.
  • Dupre, John (1993), The Disorder of Things. Harvard University Press.
  • Galison, Peter and David J. Stump, eds. (1996), The Disunity of the Sciences: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power. Stanford University Press.
  • Jones, Richard H. (2013), Analysis & the Fullness of Reality: An Introduction to Reductionism & Emergence. Jackson Square Books.
  • Laughlin, Robert (2005), A Different Universe: Reinventing Physics from the Bottom Down. Basic Books.
  • Nagel, Ernest (1961), The Structure of Science. New York.
  • Pinker, Steven (2002), The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. Viking Penguin.
  • Ruse, Michael (1988), Philosophy of Biology. Albany, NY.
  • Rosenberg, Alexander (2006), Darwinian Reductionism or How to Stop Worrying and Love Molecular Biology. University of Chicago Press.
  • Eric Scerri The reduction of chemistry to physics has become a central aspect of the philosophy of chemistry. See several articles by this author.
  • Weinberg, Steven (1992), Dreams of a Final Theory: The Scientist's Search for the Ultimate Laws of Nature, Pantheon Books.
  • Weinberg, Steven (2002) describes what he terms the culture war among physicists in his review of A New Kind of Science.
  • Capra, Fritjof (1982), The Turning Point.
  • Lopez, F., Il pensiero olistico di Ippocrate. Riduzionismo, antiriduzionismo, scienza della complessità nel trattato sull'Antica Medicina, vol. IIA, Ed. Pubblisfera, Cosenza Italy 2008.
  • Maureen L Pope, Personal construction of formal knowledge, Humanities Social Science and Law, 13.4, December, 1982, pp. 3–14
  • Tara W. Lumpkin, Perceptual Diversity: Is Polyphasic Consciousness Necessary for Global Survival? December 28, 2006, bioregionalanimism.com 2016-04-10 at the Wayback Machine
  • Vandana Shiva, 1995, Monocultures, Monopolies and the Masculinisation of Knowledge. International Development Research Centre (IDRC) Reports: Gender Equity. 23: 15–17.
  • The Anti-Realist Side of the Debate: A Theory's Predictive Success does not Warrant Belief in the Unobservable Entities it Postulates Andre Kukla and Joel Walmsley.

External links edit

  • Alyssa Ney, "Reductionism" in: Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Ingo Brigandt and Alan Love, "Reductionism in Biology" in: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • John Dupré: The Disunity of Science—an interview at the Galilean Library covering criticisms of reductionism.
  • Monica Anderson: Reductionism Considered Harmful 2019-04-16 at the Wayback Machine
  • Reduction and Emergence in Chemistry, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

reductionism, confused, with, reductionist, experimental, music, genre, term, used, phenomenological, tradition, western, philosophy, phenomenological, reduction, several, related, philosophical, ideas, regarding, associations, between, phenomena, which, descr. Not to be confused with the reductionist experimental music genre For term used phenomenological tradition in Western philosophy see phenomenological reduction Reductionism is any of several related philosophical ideas regarding the associations between phenomena which can be described in terms of other simpler or more fundamental phenomena 1 It is also described as an intellectual and philosophical position that interprets a complex system as the sum of its parts 2 Rene Descartes in De homine 1662 claimed that non human animals could be explained reductively as automata meaning essentially as more mechanically complex versions of this Digesting Duck Contents 1 Definitions 1 1 Ontological reductionism 1 2 Methodological reductionism 1 3 In religion 1 4 Theory reductionism 1 5 In mathematics 1 6 In science 1 7 In computer science 2 Criticism 2 1 Free will 2 2 Causation 2 3 In science 3 See also 4 References 5 Further reading 6 External linksDefinitions editThe Oxford Companion to Philosophy suggests that reductionism is one of the most used and abused terms in the philosophical lexicon and suggests a three part division 3 Ontological reductionism a belief that the whole of reality consists of a minimal number of parts Methodological reductionism the scientific attempt to provide an explanation in terms of ever smaller entities Theory reductionism the suggestion that a newer theory does not replace or absorb an older one but reduces it to more basic terms Theory reduction itself is divisible into three parts translation derivation and explanation 4 Reductionism can be applied to any phenomenon including objects problems explanations theories and meanings 4 5 6 For the sciences application of methodological reductionism attempts explanation of entire systems in terms of their individual constituent parts and their interactions For example the temperature of a gas is reduced to nothing beyond the average kinetic energy of its molecules in motion Thomas Nagel and others speak of psychophysical reductionism the attempted reduction of psychological phenomena to physics and chemistry and physico chemical reductionism the attempted reduction of biology to physics and chemistry 7 In a very simplified and sometimes contested form reductionism is said to imply that a system is nothing but the sum of its parts 5 8 However a more nuanced opinion is that a system is composed entirely of its parts but the system will have features that none of the parts have which in essence is the basis of emergentism 9 The point of mechanistic explanations is usually showing how the higher level features arise from the parts 8 Other definitions are used by other authors For example what John Polkinghorne terms conceptual or epistemological reductionism 5 is the definition provided by Simon Blackburn 10 and by Jaegwon Kim 11 that form of reductionism which concerns a program of replacing the facts or entities involved in one type of discourse with other facts or entities from another type thereby providing a relationship between them Richard Jones distinguishes ontological and epistemological reductionism arguing that many ontological and epistemological reductionists affirm the need for different concepts for different degrees of complexity while affirming a reduction of theories 9 The idea of reductionism can be expressed by levels of explanation with higher levels reducible if need be to lower levels This use of levels of understanding in part expresses our human limitations in remembering detail However most philosophers would insist that our role in conceptualizing reality our need for a hierarchy of levels of understanding does not change the fact that different levels of organization in reality do have different properties 9 Reductionism does not preclude the existence of what might be termed emergent phenomena but it does imply the ability to understand those phenomena completely in terms of the processes from which they are composed This reductionist understanding is very different from ontological or strong emergentism which intends that what emerges in emergence is more than the sum of the processes from which it emerges respectively either in the ontological sense or in the epistemological sense 12 Ontological reductionism edit Richard Jones divides ontological reductionism into two the reductionism of substances e g the reduction of mind to matter and the reduction of the number of structures operating in nature e g the reduction of one physical force to another This permits scientists and philosophers to affirm the former while being anti reductionists regarding the latter 13 Nancey Murphy has claimed that there are two species of ontological reductionism one that claims that wholes are nothing more than their parts and atomist reductionism claiming that wholes are not really real She admits that the phrase really real is apparently senseless but she has tried to explicate the supposed difference between the two 14 Ontological reductionism denies the idea of ontological emergence and claims that emergence is an epistemological phenomenon that only exists through analysis or description of a system and does not exist fundamentally 15 In some scientific disciplines ontological reductionism takes two forms token identity theory and type identity theory 16 In this case token refers to a biological process 17 Token ontological reductionism is the idea that every item that exists is a sum item For perceivable items it affirms that every perceivable item is a sum of items with a lesser degree of complexity Token ontological reduction of biological things to chemical things is generally accepted Type ontological reductionism is the idea that every type of item is a sum type of item and that every perceivable type of item is a sum of types of items with a lesser degree of complexity Type ontological reduction of biological things to chemical things is often rejected Michael Ruse has criticized ontological reductionism as an improper argument against vitalism 18 Methodological reductionism edit In a biological context methodological reductionism means attempting to explain all biological phenomena in terms of their underlying biochemical and molecular processes 19 In religion edit Anthropologists Edward Burnett Tylor and James George Frazer employed some religious reductionist arguments 20 Theory reductionism edit Theory reduction is the process by which a more general theory absorbs a special theory 2 It can be further divided into translation derivation and explanation 21 For example both Kepler s laws of the motion of the planets and Galileo s theories of motion formulated for terrestrial objects are reducible to Newtonian theories of mechanics because all the explanatory power of the former are contained within the latter Furthermore the reduction is considered beneficial because Newtonian mechanics is a more general theory that is it explains more events than Galileo s or Kepler s Besides scientific theories theory reduction more generally can be the process by which one explanation subsumes another In mathematics edit In mathematics reductionism can be interpreted as the philosophy that all mathematics can or ought to be based on a common foundation which for modern mathematics is usually axiomatic set theory Ernst Zermelo was one of the major advocates of such an opinion he also developed much of axiomatic set theory It has been argued that the generally accepted method of justifying mathematical axioms by their usefulness in common practice can potentially weaken Zermelo s reductionist claim 22 Jouko Vaananen has argued for second order logic as a foundation for mathematics instead of set theory 23 whereas others have argued for category theory as a foundation for certain aspects of mathematics 24 25 The incompleteness theorems of Kurt Godel published in 1931 caused doubt about the attainability of an axiomatic foundation for all of mathematics Any such foundation would have to include axioms powerful enough to describe the arithmetic of the natural numbers a subset of all mathematics Yet Godel proved that for any consistent recursively enumerable axiomatic system powerful enough to describe the arithmetic of the natural numbers there are model theoretically true propositions about the natural numbers that cannot be proved from the axioms Such propositions are known as formally undecidable propositions For example the continuum hypothesis is undecidable in the Zermelo Fraenkel set theory as shown by Cohen In science edit Reductionist thinking and methods form the basis for many of the well developed topics of modern science including much of physics chemistry and molecular biology Classical mechanics in particular is seen as a reductionist framework For instance we understand the solar system in terms of its components the sun and the planets and their interactions 26 Statistical mechanics can be considered as a reconciliation of macroscopic thermodynamic laws with the reductionist method of explaining macroscopic properties in terms of microscopic components although it has been argued that reduction in physics never goes all the way in practice 27 In computer science edit The role of reduction in computer science can be thought as a precise and unambiguous mathematical formalization of the philosophical idea of theory reductionism In a general sense a problem or set is said to be reducible to another problem or set if there is a computable feasible method to translate the questions of the former into the latter so that if one knows how to computably feasibly solve the latter problem then one can computably feasibly solve the former Thus the latter can only be at least as hard to solve as the former Reduction in theoretical computer science is pervasive in both the mathematical abstract foundations of computation and in real world performance or capability analysis of algorithms More specifically reduction is a foundational and central concept not only in the realm of mathematical logic and abstract computation in computability or recursive theory where it assumes the form of e g Turing reduction but also in the realm of real world computation in time or space complexity analysis of algorithms where it assumes the form of e g polynomial time reduction Criticism editFree will edit Main article Free will Philosophers of the Enlightenment worked to insulate human free will from reductionism Descartes separated the material world of mechanical necessity from the world of mental free will German philosophers introduced the concept of the noumenal realm that is not governed by the deterministic laws of phenomenal nature where every event is completely determined by chains of causality 28 The most influential formulation was by Immanuel Kant who distinguished between the causal deterministic framework the mind imposes on the world the phenomenal realm and the world as it exists for itself the noumenal realm which as he believed included free will To insulate theology from reductionism 19th century post Enlightenment German theologians especially Friedrich Schleiermacher and Albrecht Ritschl used the Romantic method of basing religion on the human spirit so that it is a person s feeling or sensibility about spiritual matters that comprises religion 29 Causation edit Most common philosophical understandings of causation involve reducing it to some collection of non causal facts Opponents of these reductionist views have given arguments that the non causal facts in question are insufficient to determine the causal facts 30 Alfred North Whitehead s metaphysics opposed reductionism He refers to this as the fallacy of the misplaced concreteness His scheme was to frame a rational general understanding of phenomena derived from our reality In science edit An alternative term for ontological reductionism is fragmentalism 31 often used in a pejorative sense 32 In cognitive psychology George Kelly developed constructive alternativism as a form of personal construct psychology and an alternative to what he considered accumulative fragmentalism For this theory knowledge is seen as the construction of successful mental models of the exterior world rather than the accumulation of independent nuggets of truth 33 Others argue that inappropriate use of reductionism limits our understanding of complex systems In particular ecologist Robert Ulanowicz says that science must develop techniques to study ways in which larger scales of organization influence smaller ones and also ways in which feedback loops create structure at a given level independently of details at a lower level of organization He advocates and uses information theory as a framework to study propensities in natural systems 34 The limits of the application of reductionism are claimed to be especially evident at levels of organization with greater complexity including living cells 35 neural networks ecosystems society and other systems formed from assemblies of large numbers of diverse components linked by multiple feedback loops 35 36 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Psychology portalAntireductionism Eliminative materialism Emergentism Further facts Materialism Multiple realizability Physicalism Technological determinismReferences edit Wendy Doniger ed 1999 Reductionism Merriam Webster s Encyclopedia of World Religions Merriam Webster p 911 ISBN 978 0877790440 a b Kricheldorf Hans R 2016 Getting It Right in Science and Medicine Can Science Progress through Errors Fallacies and Facts Cham Springer p 63 ISBN 978 3319303864 Michael Ruse 2005 Entry for reductionism In Ted Honderich ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy 2nd ed Oxford University Press p 793 ISBN 978 0191037474 a b Alyssa Ney Reductionism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy IEP University of Tennessee Retrieved March 13 2015 a b c John Polkinghorne 2002 Reductionism Interdisciplinary Encyclopedia of Religion and Science Advanced School for Interdisciplinary Research Pontifical University of the Holy Cross For reductionism referred to explanations theories and meanings see Willard Van Orman Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism Quine objected to the positivistic reductionist belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience as an intractable problem Thomas Nagel 2012 Mind and Cosmos Why the Materialist Neo Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False Oxford University Press pp 4 5 ISBN 978 0199919758 a b Peter Godfrey Smith 2013 Philosophy of Biology Princeton University Press p 16 ISBN 978 1400850440 a b c Richard H Jones 2000 Clarification of terminology Reductionism Analysis and the Fullness of Reality Bucknell University Press pp 19 27 28 32 ISBN 978 0838754399 Simon Blackburn 2005 Entry on reductionism Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press UK p 311 ISBN 978 0198610137 Jaegwon Kim 2005 Entry for mental reductionism In Ted Honderich ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy 2nd ed Oxford University Press p 794 ISBN 978 0191037474 Axelrod and Cohen Harnessing Complexity Richard H Jones 2000 Reductionism Analysis and the Fullness of Reality pp 24 26 29 31 Lewisburg Pa Bucknell University Press Nancey Murphy Reductionism and Emergence A Critical Perspective In Human Identity at the Intersection of Science Technology and Religion Edited by Nancey Murphy and Christopher C Knight Burlington VT Ashgate 2010 P 82 Silberstein Michael McGeever John April 1999 The Search for Ontological Emergence The Philosophical Quarterly 49 195 201 214 doi 10 1111 1467 9213 00136 ISSN 0031 8094 Scientific Reduction The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 Reductionism in Biology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2022 Ruse Michael 1989 Do Organisms Exist PDF Am Zool 29 3 1061 1066 doi 10 1093 icb 29 3 1061 Archived from the original PDF on 2008 10 02 Brigandt Ingo Love Alan 2017 Reductionism in Biology In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2019 04 28 Strenski Ivan Classic Twentieth Century Theorist of the Study of Religion Defending the Inner Sanctum of Religious Experience or Storming It pp 176 209 in Thinking About Religion An Historical Introduction to Theories of Religion Malden Blackwell 2006 Reductionism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Taylor R Gregory 1993 Zermelo Reductionism and the Philosophy of Mathematics Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 34 4 539 563 doi 10 1305 ndjfl 1093633905 Vaananen J 2001 Second Order Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 4 504 520 doi 10 2307 2687796 JSTOR 2687796 S2CID 7465054 Awodey S 1996 Structure in Mathematics and Logic A Categorical Perspective Philos Math Series III 4 3 209 237 doi 10 1093 philmat 4 3 209 Lawvere F W 1966 The Category of Categories as a Foundation for Mathematics Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra La Jolla Calif 1965 New York Springer Verlag pp 1 20 McCauley Joseph L 2009 Dynamics of Markets The New Financial Economics Second Edition Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 241 ISBN 978 0521429627 Simpson William M R Horsley Simon A H 29 March 2022 Toppling the Pyramids Physics Without Physical State Monism In Austin Christopher J Marmodoro Anna Roselli Andrea eds Powers Time and Free Will Synthese Library Vol 451 Synthese Library pp 17 50 doi 10 1007 978 3 030 92486 7 2 ISBN 9781003125860 via Springer Guyer Paul 2020 18th Century German Aesthetics in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2023 03 16 Philip Clayton and Zachary Simpson eds The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science 2006 p 161 John W Carroll 2009 Chapter 13 Anti reductionism In Helen Beebee Christopher Hitchcock Peter Menzies eds The Oxford Handbook of Causation Oxford Handbooks Online p 292 ISBN 978 0199279739 Kukla A 1996 Antirealist Explanations of the Success of Science Philosophy of Science 63 1 S298 S305 doi 10 1086 289964 JSTOR 188539 S2CID 171074337 Pope ML 1982 Personal construction of formal knowledge Interchange 13 4 3 14 doi 10 1007 BF01191417 S2CID 198195182 Pope ML Watts M 1988 Constructivist Goggles Implications for Process in Teaching and Learning Physics Eur J Phys 9 2 101 109 Bibcode 1988EJPh 9 101P doi 10 1088 0143 0807 9 2 004 S2CID 250876891 R E Ulanowicz Ecology The Ascendant Perspective Columbia University Press 1997 ISBN 0231108281 a b Huber F Schnauss J Roenicke S Rauch P Mueller K Fuetterer C Kaes J 2013 Emergent complexity of the cytoskeleton from single filaments to tissue Advances in Physics 62 1 1 112 Bibcode 2013AdPhy 62 1H doi 10 1080 00018732 2013 771509 PMC 3985726 PMID 24748680 online Clayton P Davies P eds 2006 The Re emergence of Emergence The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion New York Oxford University Press a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Further reading editChurchland Patricia 1986 Neurophilosophy Toward a Unified Science of the Mind Brain MIT Press Dawkins Richard 1976 The Selfish Gene Oxford University Press 2nd edition December 1989 Dennett Daniel C 1995 Darwin s Dangerous Idea Simon amp Schuster Descartes 1637 Discourses Part V Dupre John 1993 The Disorder of Things Harvard University Press Galison Peter and David J Stump eds 1996 The Disunity of the Sciences Boundaries Contexts and Power Stanford University Press Jones Richard H 2013 Analysis amp the Fullness of Reality An Introduction to Reductionism amp Emergence Jackson Square Books Laughlin Robert 2005 A Different Universe Reinventing Physics from the Bottom Down Basic Books Nagel Ernest 1961 The Structure of Science New York Pinker Steven 2002 The Blank Slate The Modern Denial of Human Nature Viking Penguin Ruse Michael 1988 Philosophy of Biology Albany NY Rosenberg Alexander 2006 Darwinian Reductionism or How to Stop Worrying and Love Molecular Biology University of Chicago Press Eric Scerri The reduction of chemistry to physics has become a central aspect of the philosophy of chemistry See several articles by this author Weinberg Steven 1992 Dreams of a Final Theory The Scientist s Search for the Ultimate Laws of Nature Pantheon Books Weinberg Steven 2002 describes what he terms the culture war among physicists in his review of A New Kind of Science Capra Fritjof 1982 The Turning Point Lopez F Il pensiero olistico di Ippocrate Riduzionismo antiriduzionismo scienza della complessita nel trattato sull Antica Medicina vol IIA Ed Pubblisfera Cosenza Italy 2008 Maureen L Pope Personal construction of formal knowledge Humanities Social Science and Law 13 4 December 1982 pp 3 14 Tara W Lumpkin Perceptual Diversity Is Polyphasic Consciousness Necessary for Global Survival December 28 2006 bioregionalanimism com Archived 2016 04 10 at the Wayback Machine Vandana Shiva 1995 Monocultures Monopolies and the Masculinisation of Knowledge International Development Research Centre IDRC Reports Gender Equity 23 15 17 Gender and Equity v 23 no 2 July 1995 The Anti Realist Side of the Debate A Theory s Predictive Success does not Warrant Belief in the Unobservable Entities it Postulates Andre Kukla and Joel Walmsley External links edit nbsp Look up reductionism in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Reductionism Alyssa Ney Reductionism in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ingo Brigandt and Alan Love Reductionism in Biology in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy John Dupre The Disunity of Science an interview at the Galilean Library covering criticisms of reductionism Monica Anderson Reductionism Considered Harmful Archived 2019 04 16 at the Wayback Machine Reduction and Emergence in Chemistry Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Reductionism amp oldid 1199669811, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.