fbpx
Wikipedia

Mathematics

Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics with the major subdisciplines of number theory,[1] algebra,[2] geometry,[1] and analysis,[3][4] respectively. There is no general consensus among mathematicians about a common definition for their academic discipline.

Most mathematical activity involves the discovery of properties of abstract objects and the use of pure reason to prove them. These objects consist of either abstractions from nature or—in modern mathematics—entities that are stipulated to have certain properties, called axioms. A proof consists of a succession of applications of deductive rules to already established results. These results include previously proved theorems, axioms, and—in case of abstraction from nature—some basic properties that are considered true starting points of the theory under consideration.[5]

Mathematics is essential in the natural sciences, engineering, medicine, finance, computer science and the social sciences. Although mathematics is extensively used for modeling phenomena, the fundamental truths of mathematics are independent from any scientific experimentation. Some areas of mathematics, such as statistics and game theory, are developed in close correlation with their applications and are often grouped under applied mathematics. Other areas are developed independently from any application (and are therefore called pure mathematics), but often later find practical applications.[6][7] The problem of integer factorization, for example, which goes back to Euclid in 300 BC, had no practical application before its use in the RSA cryptosystem, now widely used for the security of computer networks.

Historically, the concept of a proof and its associated mathematical rigour first appeared in Greek mathematics, most notably in Euclid's Elements.[8] Since its beginning, mathematics was essentially divided into geometry and arithmetic (the manipulation of natural numbers and fractions), until the 16th and 17th centuries, when algebra[a] and infinitesimal calculus were introduced as new areas. Since then, the interaction between mathematical innovations and scientific discoveries has led to a rapid lockstep increase in the development of both.[9] At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis of mathematics led to the systematization of the axiomatic method,[10] which heralded a dramatic increase in the number of mathematical areas and their fields of application. The contemporary Mathematics Subject Classification lists more than 60 first-level areas of mathematics.

Etymology

The word mathematics comes from Ancient Greek máthēma (μάθημα), meaning "that which is learnt",[11] "what one gets to know", hence also "study" and "science". The word came to have the narrower and more technical meaning of "mathematical study" even in Classical times.[12] Its adjective is mathēmatikós (μαθηματικός), meaning "related to learning" or "studious", which likewise further came to mean "mathematical".[13] In particular, mathēmatikḗ tékhnē (μαθηματικὴ τέχνη; Latin: ars mathematica) meant "the mathematical art".[11]

Similarly, one of the two main schools of thought in Pythagoreanism was known as the mathēmatikoi (μαθηματικοί)—which at the time meant "learners" rather than "mathematicians" in the modern sense. The Pythagoreans were likely the first to constrain the use of the word to just the study of arithmetic and geometry. By the time of Aristotle (384–322 BC) this meaning was fully established.[14]

In Latin, and in English until around 1700, the term mathematics more commonly meant "astrology" (or sometimes "astronomy") rather than "mathematics"; the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800. This change has resulted in several mistranslations: For example, Saint Augustine's warning that Christians should beware of mathematici, meaning "astrologers", is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians.[15]

The apparent plural form in English goes back to the Latin neuter plural mathematica (Cicero), based on the Greek plural ta mathēmatiká (τὰ μαθηματικά) and means roughly "all things mathematical", although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic(al) and formed the noun mathematics anew, after the pattern of physics and metaphysics, inherited from Greek.[16] In English, the noun mathematics takes a singular verb. It is often shortened to maths or, in North America, math.[17]

Areas of mathematics

Before the Renaissance, mathematics was divided into two main areas: arithmetic—regarding the manipulation of numbers, and geometry, regarding the study of shapes.[18] Some types of pseudoscience, such as numerology and astrology, were not then clearly distinguished from mathematics.[19]

During the Renaissance, two more areas appeared. Mathematical notation led to algebra which, roughly speaking, consists of the study and the manipulation of formulas. Calculus, consisting of the two subfields differential calculus and integral calculus, is the study of continuous functions, which model the typically nonlinear relationships between varying quantities, as represented by variables. This division into four main areas–arithmetic, geometry, algebra, calculus[20]–endured until the end of the 19th century. Areas such as celestial mechanics and solid mechanics were then studied by mathematicians, but now are considered as belonging to physics.[21] The subject of combinatorics has been studied for much of recorded history, yet did not become a separate branch of mathematics until the seventeenth century.[22]

At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis in mathematics and the resulting systematization of the axiomatic method led to an explosion of new areas of mathematics.[23][10] The 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification contains no less than sixty-three first-level areas.[24] Some of these areas correspond to the older division, as is true regarding number theory (the modern name for higher arithmetic) and geometry. Several other first-level areas have "geometry" in their names or are otherwise commonly considered part of geometry. Algebra and calculus do not appear as first-level areas but are respectively split into several first-level areas. Other first-level areas emerged during the 20th century or had not previously been considered as mathematics, such as mathematical logic and foundations.[25]

Number theory

 
This is the Ulam spiral, which illustrates the distribution of prime numbers. The dark diagonal lines in the spiral hint at the hypothesized approximate independence between being prime and being a value of a quadratic polynomial, a conjecture now known as Hardy and Littlewood's Conjecture F.

Number theory began with the manipulation of numbers, that is, natural numbers   and later expanded to integers   and rational numbers   Number theory was once called arithmetic, but nowadays this term is mostly used for numerical calculations.[26] Number theory dates back to ancient Babylon and probably China. Two prominent early number theorists were Euclid of ancient Greece and Diophantus of Alexandria.[27] The modern study of number theory in its abstract form is largely attributed to Pierre de Fermat and Leonhard Euler. The field came to full fruition with the contributions of Adrien-Marie Legendre and Carl Friedrich Gauss.[28]

Many easily stated number problems have solutions that require sophisticated methods, often from across mathematics. A prominent example is Fermat's Last Theorem. This conjecture was stated in 1637 by Pierre de Fermat, but it was proved only in 1994 by Andrew Wiles, who used tools including scheme theory from algebraic geometry, category theory, and homological algebra.[29] Another example is Goldbach's conjecture, which asserts that every even integer greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers. Stated in 1742 by Christian Goldbach, it remains unproven despite considerable effort.[30]

Number theory includes several subareas, including analytic number theory, algebraic number theory, geometry of numbers (method oriented), diophantine equations, and transcendence theory (problem oriented).[25]

Geometry

 
On the surface of a sphere, Euclidian geometry only applies as a local approximation. For larger scales the sum of the angles of a triangle is not equal to 180°.

Geometry is one of the oldest branches of mathematics. It started with empirical recipes concerning shapes, such as lines, angles and circles, which were developed mainly for the needs of surveying and architecture, but has since blossomed out into many other subfields.[31]

A fundamental innovation was the ancient Greeks' introduction of the concept of proofs, which require that every assertion must be proved. For example, it is not sufficient to verify by measurement that, say, two lengths are equal; their equality must be proven via reasoning from previously accepted results (theorems) and a few basic statements. The basic statements are not subject to proof because they are self-evident (postulates), or are part of the definition of the subject of study (axioms). This principle, foundational for all mathematics, was first elaborated for geometry, and was systematized by Euclid around 300 BC in his book Elements.[32][33]

The resulting Euclidean geometry is the study of shapes and their arrangements constructed from lines, planes and circles in the Euclidean plane (plane geometry) and the three-dimensional Euclidean space.[b][31]

Euclidean geometry was developed without change of methods or scope until the 17th century, when René Descartes introduced what is now called Cartesian coordinates. This constituted a major change of paradigm: Instead of defining real numbers as lengths of line segments (see number line), it allowed the representation of points using their coordinates, which are numbers. Algebra (and later, calculus) can thus be used to solve geometrical problems. Geometry was split into two new subfields: synthetic geometry, which uses purely geometrical methods, and analytic geometry, which uses coordinates systemically.[34]

Analytic geometry allows the study of curves unrelated to circles and lines. Such curves can be defined as the graph of functions, the study of which led to differential geometry. They can also be defined as implicit equations, often polynomial equations (which spawned algebraic geometry). Analytic geometry also makes it possible to consider Euclidean spaces of higher than three dimensions.[31]

In the 19th century, mathematicians discovered non-Euclidean geometries, which do not follow the parallel postulate. By questioning that postulate's truth, this discovery has been viewed as joining Russel's paradox in revealing the foundational crisis of mathematics. This aspect of the crisis was solved by systematizing the axiomatic method, and adopting that the truth of the chosen axioms is not a mathematical problem.[35][10] In turn, the axiomatic method allows for the study of various geometries obtained either by changing the axioms or by considering properties that do not change under specific transformations of the space.[36]

Today's subareas of geometry include:[25]

Algebra

 
The quadratic formula, which concisely expresses the solutions of all quadratic equations
 
The Rubik's Cube group is a concrete application of group theory[37]

Algebra is the art of manipulating equations and formulas. Diophantus (3rd century) and al-Khwarizmi (9th century) were the two main precursors of algebra.[38][39] Diophantus solved some equations involving unknown natural numbers by deducing new relations until he obtained the solution. Al-Khwarizmi introduced systematic methods for transforming equations, such as moving a term from one side of an equation into the other side. The term algebra is derived from the Arabic word al-jabr meaning 'the reunion of broken parts'[40] that he used for naming one of these methods in the title of his main treatise.

Algebra became an area in its own right only with François Viète (1540–1603), who introduced the use of variables for representing unknown or unspecified numbers.[41] Variables allow mathematicians to describe the operations that have to be done on the numbers represented using mathematical formulas.

Until the 19th century, algebra consisted mainly of the study of linear equations (presently linear algebra), and polynomial equations in a single unknown, which were called algebraic equations (a term still in use, although it may be ambiguous). During the 19th century, mathematicians began to use variables to represent things other than numbers (such as matrices, modular integers, and geometric transformations), on which generalizations of arithmetic operations are often valid.[42] The concept of algebraic structure addresses this, consisting of a set whose elements are unspecified, of operations acting on the elements of the set, and rules that these operations must follow. The scope of algebra thus grew to include the study of algebraic structures. This object of algebra was called modern algebra or abstract algebra, as established by the influence and works of Emmy Noether.[43] (The latter term appears mainly in an educational context, in opposition to elementary algebra, which is concerned with the older way of manipulating formulas.)

Some types of algebraic structures have useful and often fundamental properties, in many areas of mathematics. Their study became autonomous parts of algebra, and include:[25]

The study of types of algebraic structures as mathematical objects is the purpose of universal algebra and category theory.[44] The latter applies to every mathematical structure (not only algebraic ones). At its origin, it was introduced, together with homological algebra for allowing the algebraic study of non-algebraic objects such as topological spaces; this particular area of application is called algebraic topology.[45]

Calculus and analysis

 
A Cauchy sequence consists of elements that become arbitrarily close to each other as the sequence progresses (from left to right).

Calculus, formerly called infinitesimal calculus, was introduced independently and simultaneously by 17th-century mathematicians Newton and Leibniz.[46] It is fundamentally the study of the relationship of variables that depend on each other. Calculus was expanded in the 18th century by Euler with the introduction of the concept of a function and many other results.[47] Presently, "calculus" refers mainly to the elementary part of this theory, and "analysis" is commonly used for advanced parts.

Analysis is further subdivided into real analysis, where variables represent real numbers, and complex analysis, where variables represent complex numbers. Analysis includes many subareas shared by other areas of mathematics which include:[25]

Discrete mathematics

 
A diagram representing a two-state Markov chain. The states are represented by 'A' and 'E'. The numbers are the probability of flipping the state.

Discrete mathematics, broadly speaking, is the study of individual, countable mathematical objects. An example is the set of all integers.[48] Because the objects of study here are discrete, the methods of calculus and mathematical analysis do not directly apply.[c] Algorithms—especially their implementation and computational complexity—play a major role in discrete mathematics.[49]

The four color theorem and optimal sphere packing were two major problems of discrete mathematics solved in the second half of the 20th century.[50] The P versus NP problem, which remains open to this day, is also important for discrete mathematics, since its solution would potentially impact a large number of computationally difficult problems.[51]

Discrete mathematics includes:[25]

Mathematical logic and set theory

 
The Venn diagram is a commonly used method to illustrate the relations between sets.

The two subjects of mathematical logic and set theory have belonged to mathematics since the end of the 19th century.[52][53] Before this period, sets were not considered to be mathematical objects, and logic, although used for mathematical proofs, belonged to philosophy and was not specifically studied by mathematicians.[54]

Before Cantor's study of infinite sets, mathematicians were reluctant to consider actually infinite collections, and considered infinity to be the result of endless enumeration. Cantor's work offended many mathematicians not only by considering actually infinite sets[55] but by showing that this implies different sizes of infinity, per Cantor's diagonal argument. This led to the controversy over Cantor's set theory.[56]

In the same period, various areas of mathematics concluded the former intuitive definitions of the basic mathematical objects were insufficient for ensuring mathematical rigour. Examples of such intuitive definitions are "a set is a collection of objects", "natural number is what is used for counting", "a point is a shape with a zero length in every direction", "a curve is a trace left by a moving point", etc.

This became the foundational crisis of mathematics.[57] It was eventually solved in mainstream mathematics by systematizing the axiomatic method inside a formalized set theory. Roughly speaking, each mathematical object is defined by the set of all similar objects and the properties that these objects must have.[23] For example, in Peano arithmetic, the natural numbers are defined by "zero is a number", "each number has a unique successor", "each number but zero has a unique predecessor", and some rules of reasoning.[58] This mathematical abstraction from reality is embodied in the modern philosophy of formalism, as founded by David Hilbert around 1910.[59]

The "nature" of the objects defined this way is a philosophical problem that mathematicians leave to philosophers, even if many mathematicians have opinions on this nature, and use their opinion—sometimes called "intuition"—to guide their study and proofs. The approach allows considering "logics" (that is, sets of allowed deducing rules), theorems, proofs, etc. as mathematical objects, and to prove theorems about them. For example, Gödel's incompleteness theorems assert, roughly speaking that, in every consistent formal system that contains the natural numbers, there are theorems that are true (that is provable in a stronger system), but not provable inside the system.[60] This approach to the foundations of mathematics was challenged during the first half of the 20th century by mathematicians led by Brouwer, who promoted intuitionistic logic, which explicitly lacks the law of excluded middle.[61][62]

These problems and debates led to a wide expansion of mathematical logic, with subareas such as model theory (modeling some logical theories inside other theories), proof theory, type theory, computability theory and computational complexity theory.[25] Although these aspects of mathematical logic were introduced before the rise of computers, their use in compiler design, program certification, proof assistants and other aspects of computer science, contributed in turn to the expansion of these logical theories.[63]

Statistics and other decision sciences

 
Whatever the form of a random population distribution (μ), the sampling mean (x̄) tends to a Gaussian distribution and its variance (σ) is given by the central limit theorem of probability theory.[64]

The field of statistics is a mathematical application that is employed for the collection and processing of data samples, using procedures based on mathematical methods especially probability theory. Statisticians generate data with random sampling or randomized experiments.[65] The design of a statistical sample or experiment determines the analytical methods that will be used. Analysis of data from observational studies is done using statistical models and the theory of inference, using model selection and estimation. The models and consequential predictions should then be tested against new data.[d]

Statistical theory studies decision problems such as minimizing the risk (expected loss) of a statistical action, such as using a procedure in, for example, parameter estimation, hypothesis testing, and selecting the best. In these traditional areas of mathematical statistics, a statistical-decision problem is formulated by minimizing an objective function, like expected loss or cost, under specific constraints. For example, designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence.[66] Because of its use of optimization, the mathematical theory of statistics overlaps with other decision sciences, such as operations research, control theory, and mathematical economics.[67]

Computational mathematics

Computational mathematics is the study of mathematical problems that are typically too large for human, numerical capacity.[68][69] Numerical analysis studies methods for problems in analysis using functional analysis and approximation theory; numerical analysis broadly includes the study of approximation and discretization with special focus on rounding errors.[70] Numerical analysis and, more broadly, scientific computing also study non-analytic topics of mathematical science, especially algorithmic-matrix-and-graph theory. Other areas of computational mathematics include computer algebra and symbolic computation.

History

Ancient

The history of mathematics is an ever-growing series of abstractions. Evolutionarily speaking, the first abstraction to ever be discovered, one shared by many animals,[71] was probably that of numbers: the realization that, for example, a collection of two apples and a collection of two oranges (say) have something in common, namely that there are two of them. As evidenced by tallies found on bone, in addition to recognizing how to count physical objects, prehistoric peoples may have also known how to count abstract quantities, like time—days, seasons, or years.[72][73]

 
The Babylonian mathematical tablet Plimpton 322, dated to 1800 BC

Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 BC, when the Babylonians and Egyptians began using arithmetic, algebra, and geometry for taxation and other financial calculations, for building and construction, and for astronomy.[74] The oldest mathematical texts from Mesopotamia and Egypt are from 2000 to 1800 BC. Many early texts mention Pythagorean triples and so, by inference, the Pythagorean theorem seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical concept after basic arithmetic and geometry. It is in Babylonian mathematics that elementary arithmetic (addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division) first appear in the archaeological record. The Babylonians also possessed a place-value system and used a sexagesimal numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time.[75]

In the 6th century BC, Greek mathematics began to emerge as a distinct discipline and some Ancient Greeks such as the Pythagoreans appeared to have considered it a subject in its own right.[76] Around 300 BC, Euclid organized mathematical knowledge by way of postulates and first principles, which evolved into the axiomatic method that is used in mathematics today, consisting of definition, axiom, theorem, and proof.[77] His book, Elements, is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time.[78] The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be Archimedes (c. 287–212 BC) of Syracuse.[79] He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of solids of revolution and used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under the arc of a parabola with the summation of an infinite series, in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus.[80] Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are conic sections (Apollonius of Perga, 3rd century BC),[81] trigonometry (Hipparchus of Nicaea, 2nd century BC),[82] and the beginnings of algebra (Diophantus, 3rd century AD).[83]

 
The numerals used in the Bakhshali manuscript, dated between the 2nd century BC and the 2nd century AD

The Hindu–Arabic numeral system and the rules for the use of its operations, in use throughout the world today, evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in India and were transmitted to the Western world via Islamic mathematics.[84] Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of sine and cosine, and an early form of infinite series.[85][86]

Medieval and later

 
A page from al-Khwārizmī's Algebra

During the Golden Age of Islam, especially during the 9th and 10th centuries, mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics. The most notable achievement of Islamic mathematics was the development of algebra. Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in spherical trigonometry and the addition of the decimal point to the Arabic numeral system.[87] Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian, such as Al-Khwarismi, Omar Khayyam and Sharaf al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī.[88] The Greek and Arabic mathematical texts were in turn translated to Latin during the Middle Ages and made available in Europe.[89]

During the early modern period, mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in Western Europe, with innovations that revolutionized mathematics, such as the introduction of variables and symbolic notation by François Viète (1540–1603), the introduction of coordinates by René Descartes (1596–1650) for reducing geometry to algebra, and the development of calculus by Isaac Newton (1642–1726/27) and Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716) in the 17th century. Leonhard Euler (1707–1783), the most notable mathematician of the 18th century, unified these innovations into a single corpus with a standardized terminology, and completed them with the discovery and the proof of numerous theorems. Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician Carl Gauss, who made numerous contributions to fields such as algebra, analysis, differential geometry, matrix theory, number theory, and statistics.[90] In the early 20th century, Kurt Gödel transformed mathematics by publishing his incompleteness theorems, which show in part that any consistent axiomatic system—if powerful enough to describe arithmetic—will contain true propositions that cannot be proved.[60]

Mathematics has since been greatly extended, and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and science, to the benefit of both. Mathematical discoveries continue to be made to this very day. According to Mikhail B. Sevryuk, in the January 2006 issue of the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, "The number of papers and books included in the Mathematical Reviews database since 1940 (the first year of operation of MR) is now more than 1.9 million, and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year. The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical theorems and their proofs."[91]

Symbolic notation and terminology

 
An explanation of the sigma (Σ) summation notation

Mathematical notation is widely used in science and engineering for representing complex concepts and properties in a concise, unambiguous, and accurate way. This notation consists of symbols used for representing operations, unspecified numbers, relations and any other mathematical objects, and then assembling them into expressions and formulas.[92] More precisely, numbers and other mathematical objects are represented by symbols called variables, which are generally Latin or Greek letters, and often include subscripts. Operation and relations are generally represented by specific symbols or glyphs,[93] such as + (plus), × (multiplication),   (integral), = (equal), and < (less than).[94] All these symbols are generally grouped according to specific rules to form expressions and formulas.[95] Normally, expressions and formulas do not appear alone, but are included in sentences of the current language, where expressions play the role of noun phrases and formulas play the role of clauses.

Mathematics has developed a rich terminology covering a broad range of fields that study the properties of various abstract, idealized objects and how they interact. It is based on rigorous definitions that provide a standard foundation for communication. An axiom or postulate is a mathematical statement that is taken to be true without need of proof. If a mathematical statement has yet to be proven (or disproven), it is termed a conjecture. Through a series of rigorous arguments employing deductive reasoning, a statement that is proven to be true becomes a theorem. A specialized theorem that is mainly used to prove another theorem is called a lemma. A proven instance that forms part of a more general finding is termed a corallary.[96]

Numerous technical terms used in mathematics are neologisms, such as polynomial and homeomorphism.[97] Other technical terms are words of the common language that are used in an accurate meaning that may differs slightly from their common meaning. For example, in mathematics, "or" means "one, the other or both", while, in common language, it is either amiguous or means "one or the other but not both" (in mathematics, the latter is called "exclusive or"). Finally, many mathematical terms are common words that are used with a completely different meaning.[98] This may lead to sentences that are correct and true mathematical assertions, but appear to be nonsense to people who do not have the required background. For example, "every free module is flat" and "a field is always a ring".

Relationship with sciences

Mathematics is used in most sciences for modeling phenomena, which then allows predictions to be made from experimental laws.[99] The independence of mathematical truth from any experimentation implies that the accuracy of such predictions depends only on the adequacy of the model.[100] Inaccurate predictions, rather than being caused by invalid mathematical concepts, imply the need to change the mathematical model used.[101] For example, the perihelion precession of Mercury could only be explained after the emergence of Einstein's general relativity, which replaced Newton's law of gravitation as a better mathematical model.[102]

There is still a philosophical debate whether mathematics is a science. However, in practice, mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists, and mathematics shares much in common with the physical sciences. Like them, it is falsifiable, which means in mathematics that, if a result or a theory is wrong, this can be proved by providing a counterexample. Similarly as in science, theories and results (theorems) are often obtained from experimentation.[103] In mathematics, the experimentation may consist of computation on selected examples or of the study of figures or other representations of mathematical objects (often mind representations without physical support). For example, when asked how he came about his theorems, Gauss once replied "durch planmässiges Tattonieren" (through systematic experimentation).[104] However, some authors emphasize that mathematics differs from the modern notion of science by not relying on empirical evidence.[105][106][107][108]


Pure and applied mathematics

 
 
Isaac Newton (left) and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz developed infinitesimal calculus.

Until the 19th century, the development of mathematics in the West was mainly motivated by the needs of technology and science, and there was no clear distinction between pure and applied mathematics.[109] For example, the natural numbers and arithmetic were introduced for the need of counting, and geometry was motivated by surveying, architecture and astronomy. Later, Isaac Newton introduced infinitesimal calculus for explaining the movement of the planets with his law of gravitation. Moreover, most mathematicians were also scientists, and many scientists were also mathematicians.[110] However, a notable exception occurred with the tradition of pure mathematics in Ancient Greece.[111]

In the 19th century, mathematicians such as Karl Weierstrass and Richard Dedekind increasingly focused their research on internal problems, that is, pure mathematics.[109][112] This led to split mathematics into pure mathematics and applied mathematics, the latter being often considered as having a lower value among mathematical purists. However, the lines between the two are frequently blurred.[113]

The aftermath of World War II led to a surge in the development of applied mathematics in the US and elsewhere.[114][115] Many of the theories developed for applications were found interesting from the point of view of pure mathematics, and many results of pure mathematics were shown to have applications outside mathematics; in turn, the study of these applications may give new insights on the "pure theory".[116][117]

An example of the first case is the theory of distributions, introduced by Laurent Schwartz for validating computations done in quantum mechanics, which became immediately an important tool of (pure) mathematical analysis.[118] An example of the second case is the decidability of the first-order theory of the real numbers, a problem of pure mathematics that was proved true by Alfred Tarski, with an algorithm that is impossible to implement because of a computational complexity that is much too high.[119] For getting an algorithm that can be implemented and can solve systems of polynomial equations and inequalities, George Collins introduced the cylindrical algebraic decomposition that became a fundamental tool in real algebraic geometry.[120]

In the present day, the distinction between pure and applied mathematics is more a question of personal research aim of mathematicians than a division of mathematics into broad areas.[121][122] The Mathematics Subject Classification has a section for "general applied mathematics" but does not mention "pure mathematics".[25] However, these terms are still used in names of some university departments, such as at the Faculty of Mathematics at the University of Cambridge.

Unreasonable effectiveness

The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics is a phenomenon that was named and first made explicit by physicist Eugene Wigner.[7] It is the fact that many mathematical theories, even the "purest" have applications outside their initial object. These applications may be completely outside their initial area of mathematics, and may concern physical phenomena that were completely unknown when the mathematical theory was introduced.[123] Examples of unexpected applications of mathematical theories can be found in many areas of mathematics.

A notable example is the prime factorization of natural numbers that was discovered more than 2,000 years before its common use for secure internet communications through the RSA cryptosystem.[124] A second historical example is the theory of ellipses. They were studied by the ancient Greek mathematicians as conic sections (that is, intersections of cones with planes). It is almost 2,000 years later that Johannes Kepler discovered that the trajectories of the planets are ellipses.[125]

In the 19th century, the internal development of geometry (pure mathematics) lead to define and study non-Euclidean geometries, spaces of dimension higher than three and manifolds. At this time, these concepts seemed totally disconnected from the physical reality, but at the beginning of the 20th century, Albert Einstein developed the theory of relativity that uses fundamentally these concepts. In particular, spacetime of the special relativity is a non-Euclidean space of dimension four, and spacetime of the general relativity is a (curved) manifold of dimension four.[126][127]

A striking aspect of the interaction between mathematics and physics is when mathematics drives research in physics. This is illustrated by the discoveries of the positron and the baryon   In both cases, the equations of the theories had unexplained solutions, which led to conjecture the existence of an unknown particle, and to search these particles. In both cases, these particles were discovered a few years later by specific experiments.[128][129][130]

Specific sciences

Physics

 
Diagram of a pendulum

Mathematics and physics have influenced each other over their modern history. Modern physics uses mathematics abundantly,[131] and is also the motivation of major mathematical developments.[132] See above for examples of this strong interaction.

Computing

The rise of technology in the 20th century opened the way to a new science: computing.[e] This field is closely related to mathematics in several ways. Theoretical computer science is essentially mathematical in nature. Communication technologies apply branches of mathematics that may be very old (e.g., arithmetic), especially with respect to transmission security, in cryptography and coding theory. Discrete mathematics is useful in many areas of computer science, such as complexity theory, information theory, graph theory, and so on.[citation needed]

In return, computing has also become essential for obtaining new results.[citation needed] This is a group of techniques known as experimental mathematics, which is the use of experimentation to discover mathematical insights.[133] The most well-known example is the four-color theorem, which was proven in 1976 with the help of a computer. This revolutionized traditional mathematics, where the rule was that the mathematician should verify each part of the proof. In 1998, the Kepler conjecture seemed to also be partially proven by computer. An international team had since worked on writing a formal proof; it was finished (and verified) in 2015.[citation needed]

Once written formally, a proof can be verified using a program called a proof assistant.[134] These programs are useful in situations where one is uncertain about a proof's correctness.[134]

A major open problem in theoretical computer science is P versus NP. It is one of the seven Millennium Prize Problems.[135]

Biology and chemistry

 
The skin of this giant pufferfish exhibits a Turing pattern, which can be modeled by reaction–diffusion systems.

Biology uses probability extensively - for example, in ecology or neurobiology.[136] Most of the discussion of probability in biology, however, centers on the concept of evolutionary fitness.[136]

Ecology heavily uses modeling to simulate population dynamics,[136][137] study ecosystems such as the predator-prey model, measure pollution diffusion,[138] or to assess climate change.[139] The dynamics of a population can be modeled by coupled differential equations, such as the Lotka–Volterra equations.[140] However, there is the problem of model validation. This is particularly acute when the results of modeling influence political decisions; the existence of contradictory models could allow nations to choose the most favorable model.[141]

Genotype evolution can be modeled with the Hardy-Weinberg principle.[citation needed]

Phylogeography uses probabilistic models.[citation needed]

Medicine uses statistical hypothesis testing, run on data from clinical trials, to determine whether a new treatment works.[citation needed]

Since the start of the 20th century, chemistry has used computing to model molecules in three dimensions. It turns out that the form of macromolecules in biology is variable and determines the action. Such modeling uses Euclidean geometry; neighboring atoms form a polyhedron whose distances and angles are fixed by the laws of interaction.[citation needed]

Earth sciences

Structural geology and climatology use probabilistic models to predict the risk of natural catastrophes.[citation needed] Similarly, meteorology, oceanography, and planetology also use mathematics due to their heavy use of models.[citation needed]

Social sciences

Areas of mathematics used in the social sciences include probability/statistics and differential equations (stochastic or deterministic).[citation needed] These areas used in fields such as sociology, psychology, economics, finance, and linguistics.[citation needed]

 
Supply and demand curves, like this one, are a staple of mathematical economics.

The fundamental postulate of mathematical economics is that of the rational individual actor – Homo economicus (lit.'economic man').[142] In this model, each individual aims solely to accumulate as much profit as possible,[142] and always makes optimal choices using perfect information.[143][better source needed] This atomistic view of economics allows it to relatively easily mathematize its thinking, because individual calculations are transposed into mathematical calculations. Such mathematical modeling allows one to probe economic mechanisms which would be very difficult to discover by a "literary" analysis.[citation needed] For example, explanations of economic cycles are not trivial. Without mathematical modeling, it is hard to go beyond simple statistical observations or unproven speculation.[citation needed]

However, many people have rejected or criticized the concept of Homo economicus.[143][better source needed] Economists note that real people usually have limited information and often make poor choices.[143][better source needed] Also, as shown in laboratory experiments, people care about fairness and sometimes altruism, not just personal gain.[143][better source needed] According to critics, mathematization is a veneer that allows for the material's scientific valorization.[citation needed]

At the start of the 20th century, there was a movement to express historical movements in formulas.[citation needed] In 1922, Nikolai Kondratiev discerned the ~50-year-long Kondratiev cycle, which explains phases of economic growth or crisis.[144] Towards the end of the 19th century, Nicolas-Remi Brück [fr] and Charles Henri Lagrange [fr] had extended their analysis into geopolitics. They wanted to establish the historical existence of vast movements that took peoples to their apogee, then to their decline.[145][verification needed] More recently, Peter Turchin has been working on developing cliodynamics since the 1990s.[146] (In particular, he discovered the Turchin cycle, which predicts that violence spikes in a short cycle of ~50-year intervals, superimposed over a longer cycle of ~200–300 years.[147])

Even so, mathematization of the social sciences is not without danger. In the controversial book Fashionable Nonsense (1997), Sokal and Bricmont denounced the unfounded or abusive use of scientific terminology, particularly from mathematics or physics, in the social sciences. The study of complex systems (evolution of unemployment, business capital, demographic evolution of a population, etc.) uses elementary mathematical knowledge. However, the choice of counting criteria, particularly for unemployment, or of models can be subject to controversy.[citation needed]

Relationship with astrology and esotericism

Mathematics has had a close relationship with astrology for a long time. Biased by astral themes, it had motivated the study of astronomy. Renowned mathematicians have also been considered to be renowned astrologists; for example, Ptolemy, Arab astronomers, Regiomantus, Cardano, Kepler, or John Dee. In the Middle Ages, astrology was considered a science that included mathematics. In his encyclopedia, Theodor Zwinger wrote that astrology was a mathematical science that studied the "active movement of bodies as they act on other bodies". He reserved to mathematics the need to "calculate with probability the influences [of stars]" to foresee their "conjunctions and oppositions".[148] Contemporary Eastern astrological theories pride themselves on following scientific methods. In particular, statistical astrology uses statistical tests to provide evidence of eventual correlations between the positions of stars and the futures of people. Despite this, as of 2009, studies by Paul Choisnard [fr] and Michel Gauquelin, conducted at the margins of scientific research, have not found any admissible evidence of a cause-and-effect relationship.

Mathematics is also a component of esotericism. Very frequently, mathematicians themselves have been tempted to find, in figures or numbers, a hidden meaning that serves as the key to discover the world. In the Pythagorean school, each number had a symbolic meaning and the initiates’ oath was recited by a tetractys.[149] Similarly, Plato was not content to enumerate the solids that bear his name; he also attributed to each a nature (water, air, fire, earth, universe).[150] Arithmosophy[clarification needed], numerology, and gematria tended, using calculations with numbers, to find hidden meanings in texts or to extract predictive powers from them. This fascination for numbers and figures continues to this day, as some attribute hidden virtues to the pentagram or the golden ratio.

As of the 21st century, these disciplines are no longer considered sciences.[151]

Philosophy

Reality

The connection between mathematics and material reality has led to philosophical debates since at least the time of Pythagoras. The ancient philosopher Plato argued that abstractions that reflect material reality have themselves a reality that exists outside space and time. As a result, the philosophical view that mathematical objects somehow exist on their own in abstraction is often referred to as Platonism. Independently of their possible philosophical opinions, modern mathematicians may be generally considered as Platonists, since they think of and talk of their objects of study as real objects.[152]

Armand Borel summarized this view of mathematics reality as follows, and provided quotations of G. H. Hardy, Charles Hermite, Henri Poincaré and Albert Einstein that support his views.[128]

Something becomes objective (as opposed to "subjective") as soon as we are convinced that it exists in the minds of others in the same form as it does in ours and that we can think about it and discuss it together.[153] Because the language of mathematics is so precise, it is ideally suited to defining concepts for which such a consensus exists. In my opinion, that is sufficient to provide us with a feeling of an objective existence, of a reality of mathematics ...

Nevertheless, Platonism and the concurrent views on abstraction do not explain the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics.[154]

Proposed definitions

There is no general consensus about a definition of mathematics or its epistemological status—that is, its place among other human activities.[155][156] A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics, or consider it undefinable.[155] There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science.[156] Some just say, "mathematics is what mathematicians do".[155] This makes sense, as there is a strong consensus among them about what is mathematics and what is not. Most proposed definitions try to define mathematics by its object of study.[157]

Aristotle defined mathematics as "the science of quantity" and this definition prevailed until the 18th century. However, Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics; in his view, abstraction and studying quantity as a property "separable in thought" from real instances set mathematics apart.[158] In the 19th century, when mathematicians began to address topics—such as infinite sets—which have no clear-cut relation to physical reality, a variety of new definitions were given.[159] With the large number of new areas of mathematics that appeared since the beginning of the 20th century and continue to appear, defining mathematics by this object of study becomes an impossible task.

Another approach for defining mathematics is to use its methods. So, an area of study can be qualified as mathematics as soon as one can prove theorem—assertions whose validity relies on a proof, that is, a purely-logical deduction.[160] Others take the perspective that mathematics is an investigation of axiomatic set theory, as this study is now a foundational discipline for much of modern mathematics.[161]

Rigor

Mathematical reasoning requires rigor. This means that the definitions must be absolutely unambiguous and the proofs must be reducible to a succession of applications of inference rules,[f] without any use of empirical evidence and intuition.[g][162] Rigorous reasoning is not specific to mathematics, but, in mathematics, the standard of rigor is much higher than elsewhere. Despite mathematics' concision, rigorous proofs can require hundreds of pages to express. The emergence of computer-assisted proofs has allowed proof lengths to further expand,[h][163] such as the 255-page Feit–Thompson theorem.[i] The result of this trend is a philosophy of the quasi-empiricist proof that can not be considered infallible, but has a probability attached to it.[10]

The concept of rigor in mathematics dates back to ancient Greece, where their society encouraged logical, deductive reasoning. However, this rigorous approach would tend to discourage exploration of new approaches, such as irrational numbers and concepts of infinity. The method of demonstrating rigorous proof was enhanced in the sixteenth century through the use of symbolic notation. In the 18th century, social transition led to mathematicians earning their keep through teaching, which led to more careful thinking about the underlying concepts of mathematics. This produced more rigorous approaches, while transitioning from geometric methods to algebraic and then arithmetic proofs.[10]

At the end of the 19th century, it appeared that the definitions of the basic concepts of mathematics were not accurate enough for avoiding paradoxes (non-Euclidean geometries and Weierstrass function) and contradictions (Russel's paradox). This was solved by the inclusion of axioms with the apodictic inference rules of mathematical theories; the re-introduction of axiomatic method pioneered by the ancient Greeks.[10] It results that "rigor" is no more a relevant concept in mathematics, as a proof is either correct or erroneous, and a "rigorous proof" is simply a pleonasm. Where a special concept of rigor comes into play is in the socialized aspects of a proof, wherein it may be demonstrably refuted by other mathematicians. After a proof has been accepted for many years or even decades, it can then be considered as reliable.[164]

Nevertheless, the concept of "rigor" may remain useful for teaching to beginners what is a mathematical proof.[165]

Training and practice

Education

Mathematics has a remarkable ability to cross cultural boundaries and time periods. As a human activity, the practice of mathematics has a social side, which includes education, careers, recognition, popularization, and so on. In education, mathematics is a core part of the curriculum and forms an important element of the STEM academic disciplines. Prominent careers for professional mathematicians include math teacher or professor, statistician, actuary, financial analyst, economist, accountant, commodity trader, or computer consultant.[166]

Archaeological evidence shows that instruction in mathematics occurred as early as the second millennium BCE in ancient Babylonia.[167] Comparable evidence has been unearthed for scribal mathematics training in the ancient Near East and then for the Greco-Roman world starting around 300 BCE.[168] The oldest known mathematics textbook is the Rhind papyrus, dated from circa 1650 BCE in Eygpt.[169] Due to a scarcity of books, mathematical teachings in ancient India were communicated using memorized oral tradition since the Vedic period (c. 1500 – c. 500 BCE).[170] In Imperial China during the Tang dynasty (618–907 CE), a mathematics curriculum was adopted for the civil service exam to join the state bureaucracy.[171]

Following the Dark Ages, mathematics education in Europe was provided by religious schools as part of the Quadrivium. Formal instruction in pedagogy began with Jesuit schools in the 16th and 17th century. Most mathematical curriculum remained at a basic and practical level until the nineteenth century, when it began to flourish in France and Germany. The oldest journal addressing instruction in mathematics was L'Enseignement Mathématique, which began publication in 1899.[172] The Western advancements in science and technology led to the establishment of centralized education systems in many nation-states, with mathematics as a core component—initially for its military applications.[173] While the content of courses varies, in the present day nearly all countries teach mathematics to students for significant amounts of time.[174]

During school, mathematical capabilities and positive expectations have a strong association with career interest in the field. Extrinsic factors such as feedback motivation by teachers, parents, and peer groups can influence the level of interest in mathematics.[175] Some students studying math may develop an apprehension or fear about their performance in the subject. This is known as math anxiety or math phobia, and is considered the most prominent of the disorders impacting academic performance. Math anxiety can develop due to various factors such as parental and teacher attitudes, social stereotypes, and personal traits. Help to counteract the anxiety can come from changes in instructional approaches, by interactions with parents and teachers, and by tailored treatments for the individual.[176]

Psychology (aesthetic, creativity and intuition)

The validity of a mathematical theorem relies only on the rigor of its proof, which could theoretically be done automatically by a computer program. This does not mean that there is no place for creativity in a mathematical work. On the contrary, many important mathematical results (theorems) are solutions of problems that other mathematicians failed to solve, and the invention of a way for solving them may be a fundamental way of the solving process.[177][178] An extreme example is Apery's theorem: Roger Apery provided only the ideas for a proof, and the formal proof was given only several months later by three other mathematicians.[179]

Creativity and rigor are not the only psychological aspects of the activity of mathematicians. Some mathematicians can see their activity as a game, more specifically as solving puzzles.[180] This aspect of mathematical activity is emphasized in recreational mathematics.

Mathematicians can find an aesthetic value to mathematics. Like beauty, it is hard to define, it is commonly related to elegance, which involves qualities like simplicity, symmetry, completeness, and generality. G. H. Hardy in A Mathematician's Apology expressed the belief that the aesthetic considerations are, in themselves, sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics. He also identified other criteria such as significance, unexpectedness, and inevitability, which contribute to mathematical aesthetic.[181] Paul Erdős expressed this sentiment more ironically by speaking of "The Book", a supposed divine collection of the most beautiful proofs. The 1998 book Proofs from THE BOOK, inspired by Erdős, is a collection of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments. Some examples of particularly elegant results included are Euclid's proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers and the fast Fourier transform for harmonic analysis.[182]

Some feel that to consider mathematics a science is to downplay its artistry and history in the seven traditional liberal arts.[183] One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematical results are created (as in art) or discovered (as in science).[128] The popularity of recreational mathematics is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions.

In the 20th century, the mathematician L. E. J. Brouwer even initiated a philosophical perspective known as intuitionism, which primarily identifies mathematics with certain creative processes in the mind.[59] Intuitionism is in turn one flavor of a stance known as constructivism, which only considers a mathematical object valid if it can be directly constructed, not merely guaranteed by logic indirectly. This leads committed constructivists to reject certain results, particularly arguments like existential proofs based on the law of excluded middle.[184]

In the end, neither constructivism nor intuitionism displaced classical mathematics or achieved mainstream acceptance. However, these programs have motivated specific developments, such as intuitionistic logic and other foundational insights, which are appreciated in their own right.[184]

Cultural impact

Artistic expression

 
Cover page of Traité de l'harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels by Jean-Philippe Rameau

Notes that sound well together to a Western ear are sounds whose fundamental frequencies of vibration are in simple ratios. For example, an octave doubles the frequency and a perfect fifth multiplies it by  .[185][186][better source needed]

This link between frequencies and harmony was discussed in Traité de l'harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels by Jean-Philippe Rameau,[187] a French baroque composer and music theoretician. It rests on the analysis of harmonics (noted 2 to 15 in the following figure) of a fundamental Do (noted 1); the first harmonics and their octaves sound well together.

 
Harmonics on a staff

The curve in red has a logarithmic shape, which reflects the following two phenomena:

  • The pitch of the sound, which in our auditory system is proportional to the logarithm of the sound's frequency.
  • The harmonic frequencies, which are integer multiples of the fundamental frequency.
 
Fractal with a scaling symmetry and a central symmetry

Humans, as well as some other animals, find symmetric patterns to be more beautiful.[188] Mathematically, the symmetries of an object form a group known as the symmetry group.[189]

For example, the group underlying mirror symmetry is the cyclic group of two elements,  . A Rorschach test is a figure invariant by this symmetry, as well as a butterfly, and animal bodies more generally (at least on the surface).[citation needed] Waves on the sea surface possess translation symmetry: moving one's viewpoint by the distance between wave crests does not change one's view of the sea.[citation needed] Furthermore, fractals possess (usually approximate[citation needed]) self-similarity.[190][191][better source needed]

Popularization

Popular mathematics is the act of presenting mathematics without technical terms.[192] Presenting mathematics may be hard since the general public suffers from mathematical anxiety and mathematical objects are highly abstract.[193] However, popular mathematics writing can overcome this by using applications or cultural links.[194] Despite this, mathematics is rarely the topic of popularization in printed or televised media.

Literature and film

There are many biographies about mathematicians, but mathematics is a poorly explored theme in literature and film, though it is present.

Novels

 
Cover detail from Flatland

Films

Plays

  • Proof (2000), by David Auburn
  • One zéro show : spectacle arithmétique en 0 acte et 1 tableau… blanc ; (suivi de) Du point… à la ligne : spectacle géométrique en ligne… et en surface (2001), by Denis Guedj
  • L'affaire 3.14, by Cédric Aubouy
  • Galois Poincaré, mythes et maths, by Cédric Aubouy and David Latini

TV series

Awards and prize problems

 
The front side of the Fields Medal with an illustration of the Greek polymath Archimedes

The most prestigious award in mathematics is the Fields Medal,[200][201] established in 1936 and awarded every four years (except around World War II) to up to four individuals.[202][203] It is considered the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize.[203]

Other prestigious mathematics awards include:[204]

A famous list of 23 open problems, called "Hilbert's problems", was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician David Hilbert.[212] This list has achieved great celebrity among mathematicians,[213] and, as of 2022, at least thirteen of the problems (depending how some are interpreted) have been solved.[214]

A new list of seven important problems, titled the "Millennium Prize Problems", was published in 2000. Only one of them, the Riemann hypothesis, duplicates one of Hilbert's problems. A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward.[215] To date, only one of these problems, the Poincaré conjecture, has been solved.[216]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Here, algebra is taken in its modern sense, which is, roughly speaking, the art of manipulating formulas.
  2. ^ This includes conic sections, which are intersections of circular cylinders and planes.
  3. ^ However, some advanced methods of analysis are sometimes used; for example, methods of complex analysis applied to generating series.
  4. ^ Like other mathematical sciences such as physics and computer science, statistics is an autonomous discipline rather than a branch of applied mathematics. Like research physicists and computer scientists, research statisticians are mathematical scientists. Many statisticians have a degree in mathematics, and some statisticians are also mathematicians.
  5. ^ Ada Lovelace, in the 1840s, is known for having written the first computer program ever in collaboration with Charles Babbage
  6. ^ This does not mean to make explicit all inference rules that are used. On the contrary, this is generally impossible, without computers and proof assistants. Even with this modern technology, it may take years of human work for writing down a completely detailed proof.
  7. ^ This does not mean that empirical evidence and intuition are not needed for choosing the theorems to be proved and to prove them.
  8. ^ For considering as reliable a large computation occurring in a proof, one generally requires two computations using independent software
  9. ^ The book containing the complete proof has more than 1,000 pages.

References

  1. ^ a b "mathematics, n.". Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. 2012. from the original on November 16, 2019. Retrieved June 16, 2012. The science of space, number, quantity, and arrangement, whose methods involve logical reasoning and usually the use of symbolic notation, and which includes geometry, arithmetic, algebra, and analysis.
  2. ^ Kneebone, G. T. (1963). Mathematical Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics: An Introductory Survey. Dover. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-486-41712-7. from the original on January 7, 2017. Retrieved June 20, 2015. Mathematics ... is simply the study of abstract structures, or formal patterns of connectedness.
  3. ^ LaTorre, Donald R.; Kenelly, John W.; Biggers, Sherry S.; Carpenter, Laurel R.; Reed, Iris B.; Harris, Cynthia R. (2011). Calculus Concepts: An Informal Approach to the Mathematics of Change. Cengage Learning. p. 2. ISBN 978-1-4390-4957-0. from the original on January 7, 2017. Retrieved June 20, 2015. Calculus is the study of change—how things change, and how quickly they change.
  4. ^ Ramana, B. V. (2007). Applied Mathematics. Tata McGraw–Hill Education. p. 2.10. ISBN 978-0-07-066753-2. from the original on July 12, 2022. Retrieved July 30, 2022. The mathematical study of change, motion, growth or decay is calculus.
  5. ^ Hipólito, Inês Viegas (2015). "Abstract Cognition and the Nature of Mathematical Proof" (PDF). In Kanzian, Christian; Mitterer, Josef; Neges, Katharina (eds.). Realism – Relativism – Constructivism. 38th International Wittgenstein Symposium, August 9–15, 2015. Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria. Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society. pp. 132–134. Retrieved November 5, 2022. (at ResearchGate November 5, 2022, at the Wayback Machine)
  6. ^ Peterson 2001, p. 12.
  7. ^ a b Wigner, Eugene (1960). "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences". Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics. 13 (1): 1–14. Bibcode:1960CPAM...13....1W. doi:10.1002/cpa.3160130102. from the original on February 28, 2011.
  8. ^ Wise, David. "Eudoxus' Influence on Euclid's Elements with a close look at The Method of Exhaustion". jwilson.coe.uga.edu. from the original on June 1, 2019. Retrieved October 26, 2019.
  9. ^ Alexander, Amir (2011). "The Skeleton in the Closet: Should Historians of Science Care about the History of Mathematics?". Isis. 102 (3): 475–480. doi:10.1086/661620. PMID 22073771. S2CID 21629993.
  10. ^ a b c d e f Kleiner, Israel (December 1991). "Rigor and Proof in Mathematics: A Historical Perspective". Mathematics Magazine. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. 64 (5): 291–314. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1991.11977625. JSTOR 2690647.
  11. ^ a b Harper, Douglas. "mathematic (n.)". Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  12. ^ Both meanings can be found in Plato, the narrower in Republic. 510c. . Archived from the original on February 24, 2021. Retrieved June 19, 2019.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link) CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link), but Plato did not use a math- word; Aristotle did, commenting on it. μαθηματική. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project. OED Online. Mathematics.
  13. ^ Harper, Douglas. "mathematical (adj.)". Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  14. ^ Perisho, Margaret W. (Spring 1965). "The Etymology of Mathematical Terms". Pi Mu Epsilon Journal. 4 (2): 62–66. JSTOR 24338341.
  15. ^ Boas, Ralph (1995) [1991]. "What Augustine Didn't Say About Mathematicians". Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits: A Collection of Mathematics, Verse, and Stories by the Late Ralph P. Boas, Jr. Cambridge University Press. p. 257. ISBN 978-0-88385-323-8. from the original on May 20, 2020. Retrieved January 17, 2018.
  16. ^ The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology, Oxford English Dictionary, sub "mathematics", "mathematic", "mathematics".
  17. ^ "maths, n." and "math, n.3" April 4, 2020, at the Wayback Machine. Oxford English Dictionary, on-line version (2012).
  18. ^ Bell, E. T. (2012). The Development of Mathematics. Dover Books on Mathematics (reprint, revised ed.). Courier Corporation. p. 3. ISBN 9780486152288.
  19. ^ Tiwari, Sarju (1992). Mathematics in History, Culture, Philosophy, and Science. Mittal Publications. p. 27. ISBN 9788170994046.
  20. ^ Restivo, S. (December 2013). Mathematics in Society and History. Springer Netherlands. pp. 14–15. ISBN 9789401129442.
  21. ^ Musielak, Dora (2022). Leonhard Euler and the Foundations of Celestial Mechanics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–183. ISBN 9783031123221.
  22. ^ Biggs, N. L. (May 1979). "The roots of combinatorics". Historia Mathematica. 6 (2): 109–136. doi:10.1016/0315-0860(79)90074-0.
  23. ^ a b Warner, Evan (2013). "Splash Talk: The Foundational Crisis of Mathematics" (PDF). Columbia University. pp. 1–17. Retrieved November 4, 2022.
  24. ^ Dunne, Edward; Hulek, Klaus (March 2020). "Mathematics Subject Classification 2020" (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 67 (3). Retrieved November 4, 2022.
  25. ^ a b c d e f g h "MSC2020-Mathematics Subject Classification System" (PDF). zbMath. Associate Editors of Mathematical Reviews and zbMATH. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  26. ^ LeVeque, William J. (January 5, 2014). Fundamentals of Number Theory. Dover Publications. pp. 1–30. ISBN 9780486141503.
  27. ^ Goldman, Jay (1997). The Queen of Mathematics: A Historically Motivated Guide to Number Theory. CRC Press. pp. 1–3. ISBN 9781439864623.
  28. ^ Weil, André (2007). Number Theory, An Approach Through History From Hammurapi to Legendre. Birkhäuser Boston. pp. 1–3. ISBN 9780817645717.
  29. ^ Kleiner, Israel (February 2000). "From Fermat to Wiles: Fermat's Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem". Elemente der Mathematik. 55: 19–37. doi:10.1007/PL00000079. S2CID 53319514.
  30. ^ Wang, Yuan (2002). The Goldbach Conjecture. Series in pure mathematics. Vol. 4 (revised ed.). World Scientific. pp. 1–18. ISBN 9789812776600.
  31. ^ a b c Straume, Eldar (September 2014). "A Survey of the Development of Geometry up to 1870". ePrint. arXiv:1409.1140. Bibcode:2014arXiv1409.1140S.
  32. ^ Hilbert, David (1962). The Foundations of Geometry. Open Court Publishing Company. p. 1.
  33. ^ Hartshorne, Robin (November 11, 2013). Geometry: Euclid and Beyond. Springer New York. pp. 9–13. ISBN 9780387226767.
  34. ^ Boyer, Carl B. (June 28, 2012). History of Analytic Geometry. Dover Publications. pp. 74–102. ISBN 9780486154510.
  35. ^ Stump, David J. (1997). "Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900". Perspectives on Science. 5 (3): 383. doi:10.1162/posc_a_00532. S2CID 117709681.
  36. ^ O'Connor, J. J.; Robertson, E. F. (February 1996). "Non-Euclidean geometry". MacTuror. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved November 6, 2022.
  37. ^ Joyner, D. (2008). Adventures in group theory: Rubik's Cube, Merlin's machine, and other mathematical toys (2nd ed.). Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 219–232. ISBN 9780801890130.
  38. ^ Christianidis, Jean; Oaks, Jeffrey (May 2013). "Practicing algebra in late antiquity: The problem-solving of Diophantus of Alexandria". Historia Mathematica. 40 (2): 127–163. doi:10.1016/j.hm.2012.09.001.
  39. ^ Kleiner 2007, "History of Classical Algebra" pp. 3–5.
  40. ^ Lim, Lisa (December 21, 2018). "Where algebra got its x from, and Xmas its X". South China Morning Post. Retrieved August 9, 2022.
  41. ^ Oaks, J. A. (2018). "François Viète's revolution in algebra" (PDF). Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 72 (3): 245–302. doi:10.1007/s00407-018-0208-0. S2CID 125704699. Retrieved November 8, 2022.
  42. ^ Kleiner 2007, "History of Linear Algebra" pp. 79–101.
  43. ^ Corry, Leo (December 6, 2012). Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures. Birkhäuser Basel. pp. 247–252. ISBN 9783034879170.
  44. ^ Riche, Jacques (2007). Beziau, J. Y.; Costa-Leite, Alexandre (eds.). From Universal Algebra to Universal Logic. Perspective on Universal Logic. Italy: Polimetrica International Scientific. pp. 3–39. ISBN 9788876990779.
  45. ^ Krömer, Ralph (2007). Tool and Object: A History and Philosophy of Category Theory. Science Networks. Historical Studies. Vol. 32. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. xxi–xxv, 1–91. ISBN 9783764375249.
  46. ^ Guicciardini, Niccolo (2017). "The Newton–Leibniz Calculus Controversy, 1708–1730" (PDF). In Schliesser, Eric; Smeenk, Chris (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Newton. Oxford handbooks. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199930418.013.9. ISBN 9780199930418. Retrieved November 9, 2022.
  47. ^ O'Connor, J. J.; Robertson, E. F. (September 1998). "Leonhard Euler". MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved November 9, 2022.
  48. ^ Franklin, James (2017). "Discrete and continuous: a fundamental dichotomy in mathematics". Journal of Humanistic Mathematics. 7 (2): 355–378. doi:10.5642/jhummath.201702.18. S2CID 6945363. Retrieved November 10, 2022.
  49. ^ Maurer, Stephen B. (1997). Rosenstein, Joseph G.; Franzblau, Deborah S.; Roberts, Fred S. (eds.). What is Discrete Mathematics? The Many Answers. Discrete Mathematics in the Schools. DIMACS: Series in Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science. Vol. 36. American Mathematical Society. pp. 121–124. ISBN 9780821885789.
  50. ^ Downey, Rod (2014). Turing's Legacy: Developments from Turing's Ideas in Logic. Issue 42 of Lecture Notes in Logic. Cambridge University Press. pp. 260–261. ISBN 9781107043480.
  51. ^ Sipser, Michael (July 1992). The history and status of the P versus NP question. STOC '92: Proceedings of the twenty-fourth annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing. pp. 603–618. doi:10.1145/129712.129771.
  52. ^ Ewald, William (November 17, 2018). "The Emergence of First-Order Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 2, 2022.
  53. ^ Ferreirós, José (June 18, 2020). "The Early Development of Set Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 2, 2022.
  54. ^ Ferreirós, José (2001). "The Road to Modern Logic—An Interpretation" (PDF). Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 7 (4): 441–484. doi:10.2307/2687794. hdl:11441/38373. JSTOR 2687794. S2CID 43258676. Retrieved November 11, 2022.
  55. ^ Wolchover, Natalie (December 3, 2013). "Dispute over Infinity Divides Mathematicians". Scientific American. Retrieved November 1, 2022.
  56. ^ Zhuang, C. "Wittgenstein's analysis on Cantor's diagonal argument". PhilArchive. Retrieved November 18, 2022.
  57. ^ Avigad, Jeremy; Reck, Erich H. (December 11, 2001). ""Clarifying the nature of the infinite": the development of metamathematics and proof theory" (PDF). Carnegie Mellon Technical Report CMU-PHIL-120. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  58. ^ Hamilton, Alan G. (1982). Numbers, Sets and Axioms: The Apparatus of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 3–4. ISBN 9780521287616.
  59. ^ a b Snapper, Ernst (September 1979). "The Three Crises in Mathematics: Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism". Mathematics Magazine. 52 (4): 207–16. doi:10.2307/2689412. JSTOR 2689412.
  60. ^ a b Raatikainen, Panu (October 2005). "On the Philosophical Relevance of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 59 (4): 513–534. doi:10.3917/rip.234.0513. JSTOR 23955909. S2CID 52083793. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  61. ^ Moschovakis, Joan (September 4, 2018). "Intuitionistic Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  62. ^ McCarty, Charles (2006). "At the Heart of Analysis: Intuitionism and Philosophy". Philosophia Scientiæ, Cahier spécial 6: 81–94. doi:10.4000/philosophiascientiae.411.
  63. ^ Halpern, Joseph; Harper, Robert; Immerman, Neil; Kolaitis, Phokion; Vardi, Moshe; Vianu, Victor (2001). "On the Unusual Effectiveness of Logic in Computer Science" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on March 3, 2021. Retrieved January 15, 2021.
  64. ^ Rouaud, Mathieu (2013). Probability, Statistics and Estimation (PDF). p. 10. Archived (PDF) from the original on October 9, 2022.
  65. ^ Rao, C.R. (1997). Statistics and Truth: Putting Chance to Work. World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-02-3111-8.
  66. ^ Rao, C.R. (1981). "Foreword". In Arthanari, T.S.; Dodge, Yadolah (eds.). Mathematical programming in statistics. Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics. New York: Wiley. pp. vii–viii. ISBN 978-0-471-08073-2. MR 0607328.
  67. ^ Whittle 1994, pp. 10–11, 14–18.
  68. ^ Marchuk, Gurii Ivanovich (April 2020). "G I Marchuk's plenary: ICM 1970". MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  69. ^ Johnson, Gary M.; Cavallini, John S. (September 1991). Phua, Kang Hoh; Loe, Kia Fock (eds.). Grand Challenges, High Performance Computing, and Computational Science. Singapore Supercomputing Conference'90: Supercomputing For Strategic Advantage. World Scientific. p. 28.
  70. ^ Trefethen, Lloyd N. (2008). Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). Numerical Analysis (PDF). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. pp. 604–615. ISBN 9780691118802. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  71. ^ Dehaene, Stanislas; Dehaene-Lambertz, Ghislaine; Cohen, Laurent (August 1998). "Abstract representations of numbers in the animal and human brain". Trends in Neurosciences. 21 (8): 355–61. doi:10.1016/S0166-2236(98)01263-6. PMID 9720604. S2CID 17414557.
  72. ^ See, for example, Wilder, Raymond L. Evolution of Mathematical Concepts; an Elementary Study. passim.
  73. ^ Zaslavsky, Claudia (1999). Africa Counts: Number and Pattern in African Culture. Chicago Review Press. ISBN 978-1-61374-115-3. OCLC 843204342.
  74. ^ Kline 1990, Chapter 1.
  75. ^ Boyer 1991, "Mesopotamia" pp. 24–27.
  76. ^ Heath, Thomas Little (1981) [1921]. A History of Greek Mathematics: From Thales to Euclid. New York: Dover Publications. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-486-24073-2.
  77. ^ Mueller, I. (1969). "Euclid's Elements and the Axiomatic Method". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 20 (4): 289–309. doi:10.1093/bjps/20.4.289. ISSN 0007-0882. JSTOR 686258.
  78. ^ Boyer 1991, "Euclid of Alexandria" p. 119.
  79. ^ Boyer 1991, "Archimedes of Syracuse" p. 120.
  80. ^ Boyer 1991, "Archimedes of Syracuse" p. 130.
  81. ^ Boyer 1991, "Apollonius of Perga" p. 145.
  82. ^ Boyer 1991, "Greek Trigonometry and Mensuration" p. 162.
  83. ^ Boyer 1991, "Revival and Decline of Greek Mathematics" p. 180.
  84. ^ Ore, Øystein (1988). Number Theory and Its History. Courier Corporation. pp. 19–24. ISBN 9780486656205.
  85. ^ Singh, A. N. (January 1936). "On the Use of Series in Hindu Mathematics". Osiris. 1: 606–628. doi:10.1086/368443. JSTOR 301627. S2CID 144760421.
  86. ^ Kolachana, A.; Mahesh, K.; Ramasubramanian, K. (2019). Use of series in India. Studies in Indian Mathematics and Astronomy. Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. Singapore: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-981-13-7326-8_20. ISBN 978-981-13-7325-1. S2CID 190176726.
  87. ^ Saliba, George (1994). A history of Arabic astronomy: planetary theories during the golden age of Islam. New York University Press. ISBN 978-0-8147-7962-0. OCLC 28723059.
  88. ^ Faruqi, Yasmeen M. (2006). "Contributions of Islamic scholars to the scientific enterprise". International Education Journal. Shannon Research Press. 7 (4): 391–399. Retrieved November 14, 2022.
  89. ^ Lorch, Richard (June 2001). "Greek-Arabic-Latin: The Transmission of Mathematical Texts in the Middle Ages" (PDF). Science in Context. Cambridge University Press. 14 (1–2): 313–331. doi:10.1017/S0269889701000114. S2CID 146539132.
  90. ^ Archibald, Raymond Clare (January 1949). "History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century". The American Mathematical Monthly. Part 2: Outline of the History of Mathematics. 56 (1): 35–56. doi:10.2307/2304570. JSTOR 2304570.
  91. ^ Sevryuk 2006, pp. 101–09.
  92. ^ Wolfram, Stephan (October 2000). Mathematical notation: Past and future. MathML and Math on the Web: MathML International Conference 2000, Urbana Champaign, USA. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  93. ^ Douglas, Heather; Headley, Marcia Gail; Hadden, Stephanie; LeFevre, Jo-Anne (December 3, 2020). "Knowledge of Mathematical Symbols Goes Beyond Numbers". Journal of Numerical Cognition. 6 (3): 322–354. doi:10.5964/jnc.v6i3.293. S2CID 228085700.
  94. ^ Letourneau, Mary; Wright Sharp, Jennifer (2017). "AMS style guide" (PDF). American Mathematical Society. p. 75. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  95. ^ Jansen, A. R.; Marriott, K.; Yelland, G. W. (2000). Constituent structure in mathematical expressions (PDF). Proceedings of the 22th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. Vol. 22. p. 238. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  96. ^ Rossi, Richard J. (2011). Theorems, Corollaries, Lemmas, and Methods of Proof. Pure and Applied Mathematics: A Wiley Series of Texts, Monographs and Tracts. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 1–14, 47–48. ISBN 9781118030578.
  97. ^ "Earliest Uses of Some Words of Mathematics". MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  98. ^ Silver, Daniel S. (2017). "The New Language of Mathematics". The American Scientist. 105 (6): 364–371. doi:10.1511/2017.105.6.364. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  99. ^ Bellomo, Nicola; Preziosi, Luigi (December 22, 1994). Modelling Mathematical Methods and Scientific Computation. Mathematical Modeling. Vol. 1. CRC Press. p. 1. ISBN 9780849383311.
  100. ^ Hennig, Christian (2010). "Mathematical Models and Reality: A Constructivist Perspective". Foundations of Science. 15: 29–48. doi:10.1007/s10699-009-9167-x. S2CID 6229200. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  101. ^ Frigg, Roman; Hartmann, Stephan (February 4, 2020). "Models in Science". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  102. ^ Stewart, Ian (2018). "Mathematics, Maps, and Models". In Wuppuluri, Shyam; Doria, Francisco Antonio (eds.). The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality. The Frontiers Collection. Springer. pp. 345–356. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-72478-2_18. ISBN 9783319724782.
  103. ^ "The science checklist applied: Mathematics". undsci.berkeley.edu. from the original on October 27, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  104. ^ Mackay, A. L. (1991). Dictionary of Scientific Quotations. London: Taylor & Francis. p. 100. ISBN 9780750301060.
  105. ^ Bishop, Alan (1991). "Environmental activities and mathematical culture". Mathematical Enculturation: A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education. Norwell, Massachusetts: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 20–59. ISBN 978-0-7923-1270-3. from the original on December 25, 2020. Retrieved April 5, 2020.
  106. ^ Shasha, Dennis Elliot; Lazere, Cathy A. (1998). Out of Their Minds: The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists. Springer. p. 228. ISBN 9780387982694.
  107. ^ Nickles, Thomas (2013). "The Problem of Demarcation". Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. p. 104. ISBN 9780226051826.
  108. ^ Pigliucci, Massimo (2014). "Are There 'Other' Ways of Knowing?". Philosophy Now. from the original on May 13, 2020. Retrieved April 6, 2020.
  109. ^ a b Ferreirós, J. (2007). "Ό Θεὸς Άριθμητίζει: The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss". In Goldstein, Catherine; Schappacher, Norbert; Schwermer, Joachim (eds.). The Shaping of Arithmetic after C.F. Gauss's Disquisitiones Arithmeticae. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 235–268. ISBN 9783540347200.
  110. ^ Kuhn, Thomas S. (1976). "Mathematical vs. Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science". The Journal of Interdisciplinary History. The MIT Press. 7 (1): 1–31. doi:10.2307/202372. JSTOR 202372.
  111. ^ Asper, Markus (2009). "The two cultures of mathematics in ancient Greece". In Robson, Eleanor; Stedall, Jacqueline (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics. Oxford Handbooks in Mathematics. OUP Oxford. pp. 107–132. ISBN 9780199213122.
  112. ^ Maddy, P. (2008). (PDF). The Review of Symbolic Logic. 1 (1): 16–41. doi:10.1017/S1755020308080027. S2CID 18122406. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  113. ^ Silver, Daniel S. (2017). "In Defense of Pure Mathematics". In Pitici, Mircea (ed.). The Best Writing on Mathematics, 2016. Princeton University Press. pp. 17–26. ISBN 9780691175294.
  114. ^ Parshall, Karen Hunger (2022). "The American Mathematical Society and Applied Mathematics from the 1920s to the 1950s: A Revisionist Account". Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 59 (3): 405–427. doi:10.1090/bull/1754. S2CID 249561106. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  115. ^ Stolz, Michael (2002). "The History Of Applied Mathematics And The History Of Society". Synthese. 133: 43–57. doi:10.1023/A:1020823608217. S2CID 34271623. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  116. ^ Lin, C. C . (March 1976). "On the role of applied mathematics". Advances in Mathematics. 19 (3): 267–288. doi:10.1016/0001-8708(76)90024-4.
  117. ^ Peressini, Anthony (September 1999). Applying Pure Mathematics (PDF). Philosophy of Science. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers. Vol. 66. pp. S1–S13. JSTOR 188757. Retrieved November 30, 2022.
  118. ^ Lützen, J. (2011). "Examples and reflections on the interplay between mathematics and physics in the 19th and 20th century". In Schlote, K. H.; Schneider, M. (eds.). Mathematics meets physics: A contribution to their interaction in the 19th and the first half of the 20th century. Frankfurt am Main: Verlag Harri Deutsch. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  119. ^ Marker, Dave (July 1996). "Model theory and exponentiation". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 43 (7): 753–759. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  120. ^ Chen, Changbo; Maza, Marc Moreno (August 2014). Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition in the RegularChains Library. International Congress on Mathematical Software 2014. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 8592. Berlin: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-44199-2_65. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  121. ^ Pérez-Escobar, José Antonio; Sarikaya, Deniz (2021). "Purifying applied mathematics and applying pure mathematics: how a late Wittgensteinian perspective sheds light onto the dichotomy". European Journal for Philosophy of Science. 12 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1007/s13194-021-00435-9. S2CID 245465895.
  122. ^ Takase, M. (2014). "Pure Mathematics and Applied Mathematics are Inseparably Intertwined: Observation of the Early Analysis of the Infinity". A Mathematical Approach to Research Problems of Science and Technology. Mathematics for Industry. Vol. 5. Tokyo: Springer. pp. 393–399. doi:10.1007/978-4-431-55060-0_29. ISBN 978-4-431-55059-4.
  123. ^ Sarukkai, Sundar (February 10, 2005). "Revisiting the 'unreasonable effectiveness' of mathematics". Current Science. 88 (3): 415–423. JSTOR 24110208.
  124. ^ Wagstaff, Jr., Samuel S. (2021). "History of Integer Factoring" (PDF). In Bos, Joppe W.; Stam, Martijn (eds.). Computational Cryptography, Algorithmic Aspects of Cryptography, A Tribute to AKL. London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series 469. Cambridge University Press. pp. 41–77. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  125. ^ "Curves: Ellipse". MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  126. ^ Mukunth, Vasudevan (September 10, 2015). "Beyond the Surface of Einstein's Relativity Lay a Chimerical Geometry". The Wire. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  127. ^ Wilson, Edwin B.; Lewis, Gilbert N. (November 1912). "The Space-Time Manifold of Relativity. The Non-Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics". Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 48 (11): 389–507. doi:10.2307/20022840. JSTOR 20022840.
  128. ^ a b c Borel, Armand (1983). "Mathematics: Art and Science". The Mathematical Intelligencer. Springer. 5 (4): 9–17. doi:10.4171/news/103/8. ISSN 1027-488X.
  129. ^ Hanson, Norwood Russell (November 1961). "Discovering the Positron (I)". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. The University of Chicago Press. 12 (47): 194–214. doi:10.1093/bjps/xiii.49.54. JSTOR 685207.
  130. ^ Ginammi, Michele (February 2016). "Avoiding reification: Heuristic effectiveness of mathematics and the prediction of the Ω particle". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 53: 20–27. Bibcode:2016SHPMP..53...20G. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.12.001.
  131. ^ Wagh, Sanjay Moreshwar; Deshpande, Dilip Abasaheb (September 27, 2012). ESSENTIALS OF PHYSICS. PHI Learning Pvt. Ltd. p. 3. ISBN 978-81-203-4642-0.
  132. ^ Atiyah, Michael (1990). (PDF). Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians. p. 31. Archived from the original (PDF) on September 28, 2013. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  133. ^ Borwein, J.; Borwein, P.; Girgensohn, R.; Parnes, S. (1996). . oldweb.cecm.sfu.ca. Archived from the original on January 21, 2008.
  134. ^ a b Geuvers, H. (February 2009). "Proof assistants: History, ideas and future". Sādhanā. 34: 3–4.
  135. ^ "P versus NP problem | mathematics | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  136. ^ a b c Millstein, Roberta (September 8, 2016). "Probability in Biology: The Case of Fitness" (PDF). In Hájek, Alan; Hitchcock, Christopher (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. pp. 601–622. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199607617.013.27.
  137. ^ See for example Anne Laurent, Roland Gamet, Jérôme Pantel, Tendances nouvelles en modélisation pour l'environnement, actes du congrès «Programme environnement, vie et sociétés» 15-17 janvier 1996, CNRS
  138. ^ Bouleau 1999, pp. 282–283.
  139. ^ Bouleau 1999, p. 285.
  140. ^ "1.4: The Lotka-Volterra Predator-Prey Model". Mathematics LibreTexts. January 5, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  141. ^ Bouleau 1999, p. 287.
  142. ^ a b Zak, Paul J. (December 16, 2010). Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy. Princeton University Press. p. 158. ISBN 978-1-4008-3736-6.
  143. ^ a b c d Kim, Oliver W. (May 29, 2014). "Meet Homo Economicus". The Harvard Crimson. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  144. ^ "Kondratiev, Nikolai Dmitrievich | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  145. ^ Dictionnaire en économie et science sociale, Ed.Nathan Paris, dictionnaire Larousse en 3. vol, Paris. Les définitions des cycles sont nombreuses, entre autres, en sciences: évolution de systèmes qui les ramènent à leur état initial ou, en sociologie, mouvement(s) récurrent(s) d'activité(s) politique(s) et économique(s).[full citation needed]
  146. ^ "Cliodynamics: a science for predicting the future". ZDNET. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  147. ^ Wolchover, Natalie (August 3, 2012). "Will the US Really Experience a Violent Upheaval in 2020?". Live Science. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  148. ^ Beaujouan, Guy (1994). Comprendre et maîtriser la nature au Moyen Age: mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan (in French). Librairie Droz. p. 130. ISBN 978-2-600-00040-6.
  149. ^ Dahan-Dalmedico, A.; Peiffer, J. (1986). Une histoire des mathématiques : Routes et dédales. p. 47.
  150. ^ Platon, Le Timée, 53 c - 56c[full citation needed]
  151. ^ "L'astrologie à l'épreuve : ça ne marche pas, ça n'a jamais marché ! / Afis Science - Association française pour l'information scientifique". Afis Science - Association française pour l’information scientifique (in French). Retrieved December 28, 2022.
  152. ^ Balaguer, Mark (2016). "Platonism in Metaphysics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on January 30, 2022. Retrieved April 2, 2022.
  153. ^ See White, L. (1947). "The locus of mathematical reality: An anthropological footnote". Philosophy of Science. 14 (4): 289–303. doi:10.1086/286957. S2CID 119887253. 189303; also in Newman, J. R. (1956). The World of Mathematics. Vol. 4. New York: Simon and Schuster. pp. 2348–2364.
  154. ^ Dorato, Mauro (2005). "Why are laws mathematical?" (PDF). The Software of the Universe, An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Laws of Nature. Ashgate. pp. 31–66. ISBN 9780754639947. Retrieved December 5, 2022.
  155. ^ a b c Mura, Roberta (December 1993). "Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences". Educational Studies in Mathematics. 25 (4): 375–85. doi:10.1007/BF01273907. JSTOR 3482762. S2CID 122351146.
  156. ^ a b Tobies, Renate; Neunzert, Helmut (2012). Iris Runge: A Life at the Crossroads of Mathematics, Science, and Industry. Springer. p. 9. ISBN 978-3-0348-0229-1. [I]t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general. Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face, and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science, a branch of the humanities, or an art form.
  157. ^ Ziegler, Günter M.; Loos, Andreas (November 2, 2017). Kaiser, G. (ed.). "What is Mathematics?" and why we should ask, where one should experience and learn that, and how to teach it. Proceedings of the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education. ICME-13 Monographs. Springer. pp. 63–77. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-62597-3_5. ISBN 978-3-319-62596-6.
  158. ^ Franklin, James (July 8, 2009). Philosophy of Mathematics. pp. 104–106. ISBN 978-0-08-093058-9.
  159. ^ Cajori, Florian (1893). A History of Mathematics. American Mathematical Society (1991 reprint). pp. 285–286. ISBN 978-0-8218-2102-2.
  160. ^ Brown, Ronald; Porter, Timothy (January 2000). "The Methodology of Mathematics". The Mathematical Gazette. 79 (485): 321–334. doi:10.2307/3618304. JSTOR 3618304. S2CID 178923299.
  161. ^ Strauss, Danie (2011). "Defining mathematics". Acta Academica. 43 (4): 1–28. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  162. ^ Hamami, Yacin (June 2022). "Mathematical Rigor and Proof" (PDF). The Review of Symbolic Logic. 15 (2): 409–449. doi:10.1017/S1755020319000443. S2CID 209980693. Retrieved November 21, 2022.
  163. ^ Peterson, Ivars (1988). The Mathematical Tourist. Freeman. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-7167-1953-3. A few complain that the computer program can't be verified properly, (in reference to the Haken–Apple proof of the Four Color Theorem).
  164. ^ Perminov, V. Ya. (1988). "On the Reliability of Mathematical Proofs". Philosophy of Mathematics. Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 42 (167 (4)): 500–508.
  165. ^ Davis, Jon D.; McDuffie, Amy Roth; Drake, Corey; Seiwelld, Amanda L. (2019). "Teachers' perceptions of the official curriculum: Problem solving and rigor". International Journal of Educational Research. 93: 91–100. doi:10.1016/j.ijer.2018.10.002. S2CID 149753721.
  166. ^ Endsley, Kezia (2021). Mathematicians and Statisticians: A Practical Career Guide. Practical Career Guides. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–3. ISBN 9781538145173.
  167. ^ Robson, Eleanor (2009). "Mathematics education in an Old Babylonian scribal school". In Robson, Eleanor; Stedall, Jacqueline (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780199213122.
  168. ^ Bernard, Alain; Proust, Christine; Ross, Micah (2014). "Mathematics Education in Antiquity". In Karp, A.; Schubring, G. (eds.). Handbook on the History of Mathematics Education. New York: Springer. pp. 27–53. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-9155-2_3. ISBN 978-1-4614-9154-5.
  169. ^ Dudley, Underwood (April 2002). "The World's First Mathematics Textbook". Math Horizons. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. 9 (4): 8–11. doi:10.1080/10724117.2002.11975154. JSTOR 25678363. S2CID 126067145.
  170. ^ Subramarian, F. Indian pedagogy and problem solving in ancient Thamizhakam (PDF). History and Pedagogy of Mathematics conference, 16–20 July 2012. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  171. ^ Siu, Man Keung (2004). "Official Curriculum in Mathematics in Ancient China: How did Candidates Study for the Examination?". How Chinese Learn Mathematics (PDF). Series on Mathematics Education. Vol. 1. pp. 157–185. doi:10.1142/9789812562241_0006. ISBN 978-981-256-014-8. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  172. ^ Jones, Phillip S. (1967). "The History of Mathematical Education". The American Mathematical Monthly. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. 74 (1): 38–55. doi:10.2307/2314867. JSTOR 2314867.
  173. ^ Schubring, Gert; Furinghetti, Fulvia; Siu, Man Keung (August 2012). "Introduction: the history of mathematics teaching. Indicators for modernization processes in societies". ZDM Mathematics Education. 44 (4): 457–459. doi:10.1007/s11858-012-0445-7. S2CID 145507519.
  174. ^ von Davier, Matthias; Foy, Pierre; Martin, Michael O.; Mullis, Ina V.S. (2020). "Examining eTIMSS Country Differences Between eTIMSS Data and Bridge Data: A Look at Country-Level Mode of Administration Effects". TIMSS 2019 International Results in Mathematics and Science (PDF). TIMSS & PIRLS International Study Center, Lynch School of Education and Human Development, Boston College and International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement. p. 13.1. ISBN 978-1-889938-54-7. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  175. ^ Rowan-Kenyon, Heather T.; Swan, Amy K.; Creager, Marie F. (March 2012). "Social Cognitive Factors, Support, and Engagement: Early Adolescents' Math Interests as Precursors to Choice of Career" (PDF). The Career Development Quarterly. 60 (1): 2–15. doi:10.1002/j.2161-0045.2012.00001.x. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  176. ^ Luttenberger, Silke; Wimmer, Sigrid; Paechter, Manuela (2018). "Spotlight on math anxiety". Psychology Research and Behavior Management. 11: 311–322. doi:10.2147/PRBM.S141421. PMC 6087017. PMID 30123014.
  177. ^ Yaftian, Narges (June 2, 2015). "The Outlook of the Mathematicians' Creative Processes". Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences. 191: 2519–2525. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.04.617.
  178. ^ Nadjafikhah, Mehdi; Yaftian, Narges (October 10, 2013). "The Frontage of Creativity and Mathematical Creativity". Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences. 90: 344–350. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2013.07.101.
  179. ^ van der Poorten, A. (1979). "A proof that Euler missed... Apéry's Proof of the irrationality of ζ(3)" (PDF). The Mathematical Intelligencer. 1 (4): 195–203. doi:10.1007/BF03028234. S2CID 121589323. Retrieved November 22, 2022.
  180. ^ Petkovi, Miodrag (September 2, 2009). Famous Puzzles of Great Mathematicians. American Mathematical Society. pp. xiii–xiv. ISBN 9780821848142.
  181. ^ Hardy, G. H. (1940). A Mathematician's Apology. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42706-7. Retrieved November 22, 2022. See also A Mathematician's Apology.
  182. ^ Alon, Noga; Goldston, Dan; Sárközy, András; Szabados, József; Tenenbaum, Gérald; Garcia, Stephan Ramon; Shoemaker, Amy L. (March 2015). Alladi, Krishnaswami; Krantz, Steven G. (eds.). "Reflections on Paul Erdős on His Birth Centenary, Part II". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 62 (3): 226–247. doi:10.1090/noti1223.
  183. ^ See, for example Bertrand Russell's statement "Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty ..." in his History of Western Philosophy. 1919. p. 60.
  184. ^ a b Iemhoff, Rosalie (2020). "Intuitionism in the Philosophy of Mathematics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on April 21, 2022. Retrieved April 2, 2022.
  185. ^ "Musical Mathematics: Just Intonation – The Chrysalis Foundation". www.chrysalis-foundation.org. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  186. ^ "Just Intonation Explained". www.kylegann.com. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  187. ^ Rameau, Jean-Philippe (1986) [1722]. "Traité de l'harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels". Collection de musicologie. Paris: Méridiens Klincksieck [fr]. p. 432. ISBN 978-2-86563-157-5.
  188. ^ Enquist, Magnus; Arak, Anthony (November 1994). "Symmetry, beauty and evolution". Nature. 372 (6502): 169–172. doi:10.1038/372169a0. ISSN 1476-4687.
  189. ^ Hestenes, David (1999). "Symmetry Groups" (PDF). geocalc.clas.asu.edu. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  190. ^ Bradley, Larry (2010). "Fractals - Chaos & Fractals". www.stsci.edu. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  191. ^ "Self-similarity". math.bu.edu. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  192. ^ Kissane, Barry (July 2009). Popular mathematics. 22nd Biennial Conference of The Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers. Fremantle, Western Australia: Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers. pp. 125–126.
  193. ^ Steen, L. A. (December 6, 2012). Mathematics Today Twelve Informal Essays. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 2. ISBN 978-1-4613-9435-8.
  194. ^ Pitici, Mircea (February 14, 2017). The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-8560-2.
  195. ^ a b Dan (January 23, 2022). "12 Best Mathematical Science Fiction Books". The Best Sci Fi Books. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  196. ^ Chung, Catherine (November 6, 2019). "From Alice in Wonderland to the Hitchhiker's Guide: top 10 books about mathematics". the Guardian. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  197. ^ a b "Mathematics in Movies". people.math.harvard.edu. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  198. ^ a b c "Top 8 movies about mathematicians". Mathematics | University of Waterloo. August 13, 2021. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  199. ^ a b "The Mathematical TV Database". www.qedcat.com. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  200. ^ Monastyrsky 2001, p. 1: "The Fields Medal is now indisputably the best known and most influential award in mathematics."
  201. ^ Riehm 2002, pp. 778–82.
  202. ^ "Fields Medal | International Mathematical Union (IMU)". www.mathunion.org. from the original on December 26, 2018. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  203. ^ a b "Fields Medal". Maths History. from the original on March 22, 2019. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  204. ^ "Mathematics Prizes". Wolfram MathWorld. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  205. ^ "About the Abel Prize". The Abel Prize. from the original on April 14, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  206. ^ "Abel Prize | mathematics award". Encyclopedia Britannica. from the original on January 26, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  207. ^ "CHERN MEDAL AWARD" (PDF). www.mathunion.org. June 1, 2009. (PDF) from the original on June 17, 2009. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  208. ^ "Chern Medal Award". International Mathematical Union (IMU). from the original on August 25, 2010. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  209. ^ "The Leroy P Steele Prize of the AMS". School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  210. ^ Chern, S. S.; Hirzebruch, F. (September 2000). Wolf Prize in Mathematics. doi:10.1142/4149. ISBN 978-981-02-3945-9. from the original on February 21, 2022. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  211. ^ "The Wolf Prize". Wolf Foundation. from the original on January 12, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  212. ^ "Hilbert's Problems: 23 and Math". Simons Foundation. May 6, 2020. from the original on January 23, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  213. ^ Feferman, Solomon (1998). "Deciding the undecidable: Wrestling with Hilbert's problems" (PDF). In the Light of Logic. Logic and Computation in Philosophy series. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–27. ISBN 0-19-508030-0. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  214. ^ "Hilbert's Problems: 23 and Math". Simons Foundation. May 6, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  215. ^ "The Millennium Prize Problems". Clay Mathematics Institute. from the original on July 3, 2015. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  216. ^ "Millennium Problems". Clay Mathematics Institute. from the original on December 20, 2018. Retrieved January 23, 2022.

Bibliography

  • Bouleau, Nicolas (1999). Philosophie des mathématiques et de la modélisation: Du chercheur à l'ingénieur. L'Harmattan. ISBN 9782738481252.
  • Boyer, Carl Benjamin (1991). A History of Mathematics (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley. ISBN 978-0-471-54397-8.
  • Eves, Howard (1990). An Introduction to the History of Mathematics (6th ed.). Saunders. ISBN 978-0-03-029558-4.
  • Kleiner, Izraïl' (2007). A History of Abstract Algebra. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 9780817646844.
  • Kline, Morris (1990). Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (Paperback ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-506135-2.
  • Monastyrsky, Michael (2001). "Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal" (PDF). CMS – NOTES – de la SMC. Canadian Mathematical Society. 33 (2–3). (PDF) from the original on August 13, 2006. Retrieved July 28, 2006.
  • Oakley, Barbara (2014). A Mind For Numbers: How to Excel at Math and Science (Even If You Flunked Algebra). New York: Penguin Random House. ISBN 978-0-399-16524-5. A Mind for Numbers.
  • Peirce, Benjamin (1881). Peirce, Charles Sanders (ed.). "Linear associative algebra". American Journal of Mathematics (Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C.S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed.). 4 (1–4): 97–229. doi:10.2307/2369153. hdl:2027/hvd.32044030622997. JSTOR 2369153. Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C. S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed. Google Eprint and as an extract, D. Van Nostrand, 1882, Google Eprint. from the original on March 31, 2021. Retrieved November 17, 2020..
  • Peterson, Ivars (2001). Mathematical Tourist, New and Updated Snapshots of Modern Mathematics. Owl Books. ISBN 978-0-8050-7159-7.
  • Popper, Karl R. (1995). "On knowledge". In Search of a Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years. New York: Routledge. Bibcode:1992sbwl.book.....P. ISBN 978-0-415-13548-1.
  • Riehm, Carl (August 2002). "The Early History of the Fields Medal" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 49 (7): 778–82. (PDF) from the original on October 26, 2006. Retrieved October 2, 2006.
  • Sevryuk, Mikhail B. (January 2006). "Book Reviews" (PDF). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 43 (1): 101–09. doi:10.1090/S0273-0979-05-01069-4. (PDF) from the original on July 23, 2006. Retrieved June 24, 2006.
  • Waltershausen, Wolfgang Sartorius von (1965) [first published 1856]. Gauss zum Gedächtniss. Sändig Reprint Verlag H. R. Wohlwend. ISBN 978-3-253-01702-5.
  • Whittle, Peter (1994). "Almost home". In Kelly, F.P. (ed.). Probability, statistics and optimisation: A Tribute to Peter Whittle (previously "A realised path: The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 (revised 2002)" ed.). Chichester: John Wiley. pp. 1–28. ISBN 978-0-471-94829-2. from the original on December 19, 2013.

Further reading

mathematics, other, uses, disambiguation, math, maths, redirect, here, other, uses, math, disambiguation, area, knowledge, that, includes, topics, numbers, formulas, related, structures, shapes, spaces, which, they, contained, quantities, their, changes, these. For other uses see Mathematics disambiguation Math and Maths redirect here For other uses see Math disambiguation Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers formulas and related structures shapes and the spaces in which they are contained and quantities and their changes These topics are represented in modern mathematics with the major subdisciplines of number theory 1 algebra 2 geometry 1 and analysis 3 4 respectively There is no general consensus among mathematicians about a common definition for their academic discipline Most mathematical activity involves the discovery of properties of abstract objects and the use of pure reason to prove them These objects consist of either abstractions from nature or in modern mathematics entities that are stipulated to have certain properties called axioms A proof consists of a succession of applications of deductive rules to already established results These results include previously proved theorems axioms and in case of abstraction from nature some basic properties that are considered true starting points of the theory under consideration 5 Mathematics is essential in the natural sciences engineering medicine finance computer science and the social sciences Although mathematics is extensively used for modeling phenomena the fundamental truths of mathematics are independent from any scientific experimentation Some areas of mathematics such as statistics and game theory are developed in close correlation with their applications and are often grouped under applied mathematics Other areas are developed independently from any application and are therefore called pure mathematics but often later find practical applications 6 7 The problem of integer factorization for example which goes back to Euclid in 300 BC had no practical application before its use in the RSA cryptosystem now widely used for the security of computer networks Historically the concept of a proof and its associated mathematical rigour first appeared in Greek mathematics most notably in Euclid s Elements 8 Since its beginning mathematics was essentially divided into geometry and arithmetic the manipulation of natural numbers and fractions until the 16th and 17th centuries when algebra a and infinitesimal calculus were introduced as new areas Since then the interaction between mathematical innovations and scientific discoveries has led to a rapid lockstep increase in the development of both 9 At the end of the 19th century the foundational crisis of mathematics led to the systematization of the axiomatic method 10 which heralded a dramatic increase in the number of mathematical areas and their fields of application The contemporary Mathematics Subject Classification lists more than 60 first level areas of mathematics Contents 1 Etymology 2 Areas of mathematics 2 1 Number theory 2 2 Geometry 2 3 Algebra 2 4 Calculus and analysis 2 5 Discrete mathematics 2 6 Mathematical logic and set theory 2 7 Statistics and other decision sciences 2 8 Computational mathematics 3 History 3 1 Ancient 3 2 Medieval and later 4 Symbolic notation and terminology 5 Relationship with sciences 5 1 Pure and applied mathematics 5 2 Unreasonable effectiveness 5 3 Specific sciences 5 3 1 Physics 5 3 2 Computing 5 3 3 Biology and chemistry 5 3 4 Earth sciences 5 3 5 Social sciences 6 Relationship with astrology and esotericism 7 Philosophy 7 1 Reality 7 2 Proposed definitions 7 3 Rigor 8 Training and practice 8 1 Education 8 2 Psychology aesthetic creativity and intuition 9 Cultural impact 9 1 Artistic expression 9 2 Popularization 9 3 Literature and film 9 3 1 Novels 9 3 2 Films 9 3 3 Plays 9 3 4 TV series 10 Awards and prize problems 11 See also 12 Notes 13 References 14 Bibliography 14 1 Further readingEtymologyThe word mathematics comes from Ancient Greek mathema ma8hma meaning that which is learnt 11 what one gets to know hence also study and science The word came to have the narrower and more technical meaning of mathematical study even in Classical times 12 Its adjective is mathematikos ma8hmatikos meaning related to learning or studious which likewise further came to mean mathematical 13 In particular mathematikḗ tekhne ma8hmatikὴ texnh Latin ars mathematica meant the mathematical art 11 Similarly one of the two main schools of thought in Pythagoreanism was known as the mathematikoi ma8hmatikoi which at the time meant learners rather than mathematicians in the modern sense The Pythagoreans were likely the first to constrain the use of the word to just the study of arithmetic and geometry By the time of Aristotle 384 322 BC this meaning was fully established 14 In Latin and in English until around 1700 the term mathematics more commonly meant astrology or sometimes astronomy rather than mathematics the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800 This change has resulted in several mistranslations For example Saint Augustine s warning that Christians should beware of mathematici meaning astrologers is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians 15 The apparent plural form in English goes back to the Latin neuter plural mathematica Cicero based on the Greek plural ta mathematika tὰ ma8hmatika and means roughly all things mathematical although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic al and formed the noun mathematics anew after the pattern of physics and metaphysics inherited from Greek 16 In English the noun mathematics takes a singular verb It is often shortened to maths or in North America math 17 Areas of mathematicsBefore the Renaissance mathematics was divided into two main areas arithmetic regarding the manipulation of numbers and geometry regarding the study of shapes 18 Some types of pseudoscience such as numerology and astrology were not then clearly distinguished from mathematics 19 During the Renaissance two more areas appeared Mathematical notation led to algebra which roughly speaking consists of the study and the manipulation of formulas Calculus consisting of the two subfields differential calculus and integral calculus is the study of continuous functions which model the typically nonlinear relationships between varying quantities as represented by variables This division into four main areas arithmetic geometry algebra calculus 20 endured until the end of the 19th century Areas such as celestial mechanics and solid mechanics were then studied by mathematicians but now are considered as belonging to physics 21 The subject of combinatorics has been studied for much of recorded history yet did not become a separate branch of mathematics until the seventeenth century 22 At the end of the 19th century the foundational crisis in mathematics and the resulting systematization of the axiomatic method led to an explosion of new areas of mathematics 23 10 The 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification contains no less than sixty three first level areas 24 Some of these areas correspond to the older division as is true regarding number theory the modern name for higher arithmetic and geometry Several other first level areas have geometry in their names or are otherwise commonly considered part of geometry Algebra and calculus do not appear as first level areas but are respectively split into several first level areas Other first level areas emerged during the 20th century or had not previously been considered as mathematics such as mathematical logic and foundations 25 Number theory Main article Number theory This is the Ulam spiral which illustrates the distribution of prime numbers The dark diagonal lines in the spiral hint at the hypothesized approximate independence between being prime and being a value of a quadratic polynomial a conjecture now known as Hardy and Littlewood s Conjecture F Number theory began with the manipulation of numbers that is natural numbers N displaystyle mathbb N and later expanded to integers Z displaystyle mathbb Z and rational numbers Q displaystyle mathbb Q Number theory was once called arithmetic but nowadays this term is mostly used for numerical calculations 26 Number theory dates back to ancient Babylon and probably China Two prominent early number theorists were Euclid of ancient Greece and Diophantus of Alexandria 27 The modern study of number theory in its abstract form is largely attributed to Pierre de Fermat and Leonhard Euler The field came to full fruition with the contributions of Adrien Marie Legendre and Carl Friedrich Gauss 28 Many easily stated number problems have solutions that require sophisticated methods often from across mathematics A prominent example is Fermat s Last Theorem This conjecture was stated in 1637 by Pierre de Fermat but it was proved only in 1994 by Andrew Wiles who used tools including scheme theory from algebraic geometry category theory and homological algebra 29 Another example is Goldbach s conjecture which asserts that every even integer greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers Stated in 1742 by Christian Goldbach it remains unproven despite considerable effort 30 Number theory includes several subareas including analytic number theory algebraic number theory geometry of numbers method oriented diophantine equations and transcendence theory problem oriented 25 Geometry Main article Geometry On the surface of a sphere Euclidian geometry only applies as a local approximation For larger scales the sum of the angles of a triangle is not equal to 180 Geometry is one of the oldest branches of mathematics It started with empirical recipes concerning shapes such as lines angles and circles which were developed mainly for the needs of surveying and architecture but has since blossomed out into many other subfields 31 A fundamental innovation was the ancient Greeks introduction of the concept of proofs which require that every assertion must be proved For example it is not sufficient to verify by measurement that say two lengths are equal their equality must be proven via reasoning from previously accepted results theorems and a few basic statements The basic statements are not subject to proof because they are self evident postulates or are part of the definition of the subject of study axioms This principle foundational for all mathematics was first elaborated for geometry and was systematized by Euclid around 300 BC in his book Elements 32 33 The resulting Euclidean geometry is the study of shapes and their arrangements constructed from lines planes and circles in the Euclidean plane plane geometry and the three dimensional Euclidean space b 31 Euclidean geometry was developed without change of methods or scope until the 17th century when Rene Descartes introduced what is now called Cartesian coordinates This constituted a major change of paradigm Instead of defining real numbers as lengths of line segments see number line it allowed the representation of points using their coordinates which are numbers Algebra and later calculus can thus be used to solve geometrical problems Geometry was split into two new subfields synthetic geometry which uses purely geometrical methods and analytic geometry which uses coordinates systemically 34 Analytic geometry allows the study of curves unrelated to circles and lines Such curves can be defined as the graph of functions the study of which led to differential geometry They can also be defined as implicit equations often polynomial equations which spawned algebraic geometry Analytic geometry also makes it possible to consider Euclidean spaces of higher than three dimensions 31 In the 19th century mathematicians discovered non Euclidean geometries which do not follow the parallel postulate By questioning that postulate s truth this discovery has been viewed as joining Russel s paradox in revealing the foundational crisis of mathematics This aspect of the crisis was solved by systematizing the axiomatic method and adopting that the truth of the chosen axioms is not a mathematical problem 35 10 In turn the axiomatic method allows for the study of various geometries obtained either by changing the axioms or by considering properties that do not change under specific transformations of the space 36 Today s subareas of geometry include 25 Projective geometry introduced in the 16th century by Girard Desargues extends Euclidean geometry by adding points at infinity at which parallel lines intersect This simplifies many aspects of classical geometry by unifying the treatments for intersecting and parallel lines Affine geometry the study of properties relative to parallelism and independent from the concept of length Differential geometry the study of curves surfaces and their generalizations which are defined using differentiable functions Manifold theory the study of shapes that are not necessarily embedded in a larger space Riemannian geometry the study of distance properties in curved spaces Algebraic geometry the study of curves surfaces and their generalizations which are defined using polynomials Topology the study of properties that are kept under continuous deformations Algebraic topology the use in topology of algebraic methods mainly homological algebra Discrete geometry the study of finite configurations in geometry Convex geometry the study of convex sets which takes its importance from its applications in optimization Complex geometry the geometry obtained by replacing real numbers with complex numbers Algebra Main article Algebra The quadratic formula which concisely expresses the solutions of all quadratic equations The Rubik s Cube group is a concrete application of group theory 37 Algebra is the art of manipulating equations and formulas Diophantus 3rd century and al Khwarizmi 9th century were the two main precursors of algebra 38 39 Diophantus solved some equations involving unknown natural numbers by deducing new relations until he obtained the solution Al Khwarizmi introduced systematic methods for transforming equations such as moving a term from one side of an equation into the other side The term algebra is derived from the Arabic word al jabr meaning the reunion of broken parts 40 that he used for naming one of these methods in the title of his main treatise Algebra became an area in its own right only with Francois Viete 1540 1603 who introduced the use of variables for representing unknown or unspecified numbers 41 Variables allow mathematicians to describe the operations that have to be done on the numbers represented using mathematical formulas Until the 19th century algebra consisted mainly of the study of linear equations presently linear algebra and polynomial equations in a single unknown which were called algebraic equations a term still in use although it may be ambiguous During the 19th century mathematicians began to use variables to represent things other than numbers such as matrices modular integers and geometric transformations on which generalizations of arithmetic operations are often valid 42 The concept of algebraic structure addresses this consisting of a set whose elements are unspecified of operations acting on the elements of the set and rules that these operations must follow The scope of algebra thus grew to include the study of algebraic structures This object of algebra was called modern algebra or abstract algebra as established by the influence and works of Emmy Noether 43 The latter term appears mainly in an educational context in opposition to elementary algebra which is concerned with the older way of manipulating formulas Some types of algebraic structures have useful and often fundamental properties in many areas of mathematics Their study became autonomous parts of algebra and include 25 group theory field theory vector spaces whose study is essentially the same as linear algebra ring theory commutative algebra which is the study of commutative rings includes the study of polynomials and is a foundational part of algebraic geometry homological algebra Lie algebra and Lie group theory Boolean algebra which is widely used for the study of the logical structure of computers The study of types of algebraic structures as mathematical objects is the purpose of universal algebra and category theory 44 The latter applies to every mathematical structure not only algebraic ones At its origin it was introduced together with homological algebra for allowing the algebraic study of non algebraic objects such as topological spaces this particular area of application is called algebraic topology 45 Calculus and analysis Main articles Calculus and Mathematical analysis A Cauchy sequence consists of elements that become arbitrarily close to each other as the sequence progresses from left to right Calculus formerly called infinitesimal calculus was introduced independently and simultaneously by 17th century mathematicians Newton and Leibniz 46 It is fundamentally the study of the relationship of variables that depend on each other Calculus was expanded in the 18th century by Euler with the introduction of the concept of a function and many other results 47 Presently calculus refers mainly to the elementary part of this theory and analysis is commonly used for advanced parts Analysis is further subdivided into real analysis where variables represent real numbers and complex analysis where variables represent complex numbers Analysis includes many subareas shared by other areas of mathematics which include 25 Multivariable calculus Functional analysis where variables represent varying functions Integration measure theory and potential theory all strongly related with probability theory on a continuum Ordinary differential equations Partial differential equations Numerical analysis mainly devoted to the computation on computers of solutions of ordinary and partial differential equations that arise in many applications Discrete mathematics Main article Discrete mathematics A diagram representing a two state Markov chain The states are represented by A and E The numbers are the probability of flipping the state Discrete mathematics broadly speaking is the study of individual countable mathematical objects An example is the set of all integers 48 Because the objects of study here are discrete the methods of calculus and mathematical analysis do not directly apply c Algorithms especially their implementation and computational complexity play a major role in discrete mathematics 49 The four color theorem and optimal sphere packing were two major problems of discrete mathematics solved in the second half of the 20th century 50 The P versus NP problem which remains open to this day is also important for discrete mathematics since its solution would potentially impact a large number of computationally difficult problems 51 Discrete mathematics includes 25 Combinatorics the art of enumerating mathematical objects that satisfy some given constraints Originally these objects were elements or subsets of a given set this has been extended to various objects which establishes a strong link between combinatorics and other parts of discrete mathematics For example discrete geometry includes counting configurations of geometric shapes Graph theory and hypergraphs Coding theory including error correcting codes and a part of cryptography Matroid theory Discrete geometry Discrete probability distributions Game theory although continuous games are also studied most common games such as chess and poker are discrete Discrete optimization including combinatorial optimization integer programming constraint programmingMathematical logic and set theory The Venn diagram is a commonly used method to illustrate the relations between sets Main articles Mathematical logic and set theory The two subjects of mathematical logic and set theory have belonged to mathematics since the end of the 19th century 52 53 Before this period sets were not considered to be mathematical objects and logic although used for mathematical proofs belonged to philosophy and was not specifically studied by mathematicians 54 Before Cantor s study of infinite sets mathematicians were reluctant to consider actually infinite collections and considered infinity to be the result of endless enumeration Cantor s work offended many mathematicians not only by considering actually infinite sets 55 but by showing that this implies different sizes of infinity per Cantor s diagonal argument This led to the controversy over Cantor s set theory 56 In the same period various areas of mathematics concluded the former intuitive definitions of the basic mathematical objects were insufficient for ensuring mathematical rigour Examples of such intuitive definitions are a set is a collection of objects natural number is what is used for counting a point is a shape with a zero length in every direction a curve is a trace left by a moving point etc This became the foundational crisis of mathematics 57 It was eventually solved in mainstream mathematics by systematizing the axiomatic method inside a formalized set theory Roughly speaking each mathematical object is defined by the set of all similar objects and the properties that these objects must have 23 For example in Peano arithmetic the natural numbers are defined by zero is a number each number has a unique successor each number but zero has a unique predecessor and some rules of reasoning 58 This mathematical abstraction from reality is embodied in the modern philosophy of formalism as founded by David Hilbert around 1910 59 The nature of the objects defined this way is a philosophical problem that mathematicians leave to philosophers even if many mathematicians have opinions on this nature and use their opinion sometimes called intuition to guide their study and proofs The approach allows considering logics that is sets of allowed deducing rules theorems proofs etc as mathematical objects and to prove theorems about them For example Godel s incompleteness theorems assert roughly speaking that in every consistent formal system that contains the natural numbers there are theorems that are true that is provable in a stronger system but not provable inside the system 60 This approach to the foundations of mathematics was challenged during the first half of the 20th century by mathematicians led by Brouwer who promoted intuitionistic logic which explicitly lacks the law of excluded middle 61 62 These problems and debates led to a wide expansion of mathematical logic with subareas such as model theory modeling some logical theories inside other theories proof theory type theory computability theory and computational complexity theory 25 Although these aspects of mathematical logic were introduced before the rise of computers their use in compiler design program certification proof assistants and other aspects of computer science contributed in turn to the expansion of these logical theories 63 Statistics and other decision sciences Main articles Statistics and Probability theory Whatever the form of a random population distribution m the sampling mean x tends to a Gaussian distribution and its variance s is given by the central limit theorem of probability theory 64 The field of statistics is a mathematical application that is employed for the collection and processing of data samples using procedures based on mathematical methods especially probability theory Statisticians generate data with random sampling or randomized experiments 65 The design of a statistical sample or experiment determines the analytical methods that will be used Analysis of data from observational studies is done using statistical models and the theory of inference using model selection and estimation The models and consequential predictions should then be tested against new data d Statistical theory studies decision problems such as minimizing the risk expected loss of a statistical action such as using a procedure in for example parameter estimation hypothesis testing and selecting the best In these traditional areas of mathematical statistics a statistical decision problem is formulated by minimizing an objective function like expected loss or cost under specific constraints For example designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence 66 Because of its use of optimization the mathematical theory of statistics overlaps with other decision sciences such as operations research control theory and mathematical economics 67 Computational mathematics Main article Computational mathematics Computational mathematics is the study of mathematical problems that are typically too large for human numerical capacity 68 69 Numerical analysis studies methods for problems in analysis using functional analysis and approximation theory numerical analysis broadly includes the study of approximation and discretization with special focus on rounding errors 70 Numerical analysis and more broadly scientific computing also study non analytic topics of mathematical science especially algorithmic matrix and graph theory Other areas of computational mathematics include computer algebra and symbolic computation HistoryMain article History of mathematics Ancient The history of mathematics is an ever growing series of abstractions Evolutionarily speaking the first abstraction to ever be discovered one shared by many animals 71 was probably that of numbers the realization that for example a collection of two apples and a collection of two oranges say have something in common namely that there are two of them As evidenced by tallies found on bone in addition to recognizing how to count physical objects prehistoric peoples may have also known how to count abstract quantities like time days seasons or years 72 73 The Babylonian mathematical tablet Plimpton 322 dated to 1800 BC Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 BC when the Babylonians and Egyptians began using arithmetic algebra and geometry for taxation and other financial calculations for building and construction and for astronomy 74 The oldest mathematical texts from Mesopotamia and Egypt are from 2000 to 1800 BC Many early texts mention Pythagorean triples and so by inference the Pythagorean theorem seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical concept after basic arithmetic and geometry It is in Babylonian mathematics that elementary arithmetic addition subtraction multiplication and division first appear in the archaeological record The Babylonians also possessed a place value system and used a sexagesimal numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time 75 In the 6th century BC Greek mathematics began to emerge as a distinct discipline and some Ancient Greeks such as the Pythagoreans appeared to have considered it a subject in its own right 76 Around 300 BC Euclid organized mathematical knowledge by way of postulates and first principles which evolved into the axiomatic method that is used in mathematics today consisting of definition axiom theorem and proof 77 His book Elements is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time 78 The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be Archimedes c 287 212 BC of Syracuse 79 He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of solids of revolution and used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under the arc of a parabola with the summation of an infinite series in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus 80 Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are conic sections Apollonius of Perga 3rd century BC 81 trigonometry Hipparchus of Nicaea 2nd century BC 82 and the beginnings of algebra Diophantus 3rd century AD 83 The numerals used in the Bakhshali manuscript dated between the 2nd century BC and the 2nd century AD The Hindu Arabic numeral system and the rules for the use of its operations in use throughout the world today evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in India and were transmitted to the Western world via Islamic mathematics 84 Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of sine and cosine and an early form of infinite series 85 86 Medieval and later A page from al Khwarizmi s Algebra During the Golden Age of Islam especially during the 9th and 10th centuries mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics The most notable achievement of Islamic mathematics was the development of algebra Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in spherical trigonometry and the addition of the decimal point to the Arabic numeral system 87 Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian such as Al Khwarismi Omar Khayyam and Sharaf al Din al Ṭusi 88 The Greek and Arabic mathematical texts were in turn translated to Latin during the Middle Ages and made available in Europe 89 During the early modern period mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in Western Europe with innovations that revolutionized mathematics such as the introduction of variables and symbolic notation by Francois Viete 1540 1603 the introduction of coordinates by Rene Descartes 1596 1650 for reducing geometry to algebra and the development of calculus by Isaac Newton 1642 1726 27 and Gottfried Leibniz 1646 1716 in the 17th century Leonhard Euler 1707 1783 the most notable mathematician of the 18th century unified these innovations into a single corpus with a standardized terminology and completed them with the discovery and the proof of numerous theorems Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician Carl Gauss who made numerous contributions to fields such as algebra analysis differential geometry matrix theory number theory and statistics 90 In the early 20th century Kurt Godel transformed mathematics by publishing his incompleteness theorems which show in part that any consistent axiomatic system if powerful enough to describe arithmetic will contain true propositions that cannot be proved 60 Mathematics has since been greatly extended and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and science to the benefit of both Mathematical discoveries continue to be made to this very day According to Mikhail B Sevryuk in the January 2006 issue of the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society The number of papers and books included in the Mathematical Reviews database since 1940 the first year of operation of MR is now more than 1 9 million and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical theorems and their proofs 91 Symbolic notation and terminologyMain articles Mathematical notation Language of mathematics and Glossary of mathematics An explanation of the sigma S summation notation Mathematical notation is widely used in science and engineering for representing complex concepts and properties in a concise unambiguous and accurate way This notation consists of symbols used for representing operations unspecified numbers relations and any other mathematical objects and then assembling them into expressions and formulas 92 More precisely numbers and other mathematical objects are represented by symbols called variables which are generally Latin or Greek letters and often include subscripts Operation and relations are generally represented by specific symbols or glyphs 93 such as plus multiplication textstyle int integral equal and lt less than 94 All these symbols are generally grouped according to specific rules to form expressions and formulas 95 Normally expressions and formulas do not appear alone but are included in sentences of the current language where expressions play the role of noun phrases and formulas play the role of clauses Mathematics has developed a rich terminology covering a broad range of fields that study the properties of various abstract idealized objects and how they interact It is based on rigorous definitions that provide a standard foundation for communication An axiom or postulate is a mathematical statement that is taken to be true without need of proof If a mathematical statement has yet to be proven or disproven it is termed a conjecture Through a series of rigorous arguments employing deductive reasoning a statement that is proven to be true becomes a theorem A specialized theorem that is mainly used to prove another theorem is called a lemma A proven instance that forms part of a more general finding is termed a corallary 96 Numerous technical terms used in mathematics are neologisms such as polynomial and homeomorphism 97 Other technical terms are words of the common language that are used in an accurate meaning that may differs slightly from their common meaning For example in mathematics or means one the other or both while in common language it is either amiguous or means one or the other but not both in mathematics the latter is called exclusive or Finally many mathematical terms are common words that are used with a completely different meaning 98 This may lead to sentences that are correct and true mathematical assertions but appear to be nonsense to people who do not have the required background For example every free module is flat and a field is always a ring Relationship with sciencesMathematics is used in most sciences for modeling phenomena which then allows predictions to be made from experimental laws 99 The independence of mathematical truth from any experimentation implies that the accuracy of such predictions depends only on the adequacy of the model 100 Inaccurate predictions rather than being caused by invalid mathematical concepts imply the need to change the mathematical model used 101 For example the perihelion precession of Mercury could only be explained after the emergence of Einstein s general relativity which replaced Newton s law of gravitation as a better mathematical model 102 There is still a philosophical debate whether mathematics is a science However in practice mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists and mathematics shares much in common with the physical sciences Like them it is falsifiable which means in mathematics that if a result or a theory is wrong this can be proved by providing a counterexample Similarly as in science theories and results theorems are often obtained from experimentation 103 In mathematics the experimentation may consist of computation on selected examples or of the study of figures or other representations of mathematical objects often mind representations without physical support For example when asked how he came about his theorems Gauss once replied durch planmassiges Tattonieren through systematic experimentation 104 However some authors emphasize that mathematics differs from the modern notion of science by not relying on empirical evidence 105 106 107 108 Pure and applied mathematics Main articles Applied mathematics and Pure mathematics Isaac Newton left and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz developed infinitesimal calculus Until the 19th century the development of mathematics in the West was mainly motivated by the needs of technology and science and there was no clear distinction between pure and applied mathematics 109 For example the natural numbers and arithmetic were introduced for the need of counting and geometry was motivated by surveying architecture and astronomy Later Isaac Newton introduced infinitesimal calculus for explaining the movement of the planets with his law of gravitation Moreover most mathematicians were also scientists and many scientists were also mathematicians 110 However a notable exception occurred with the tradition of pure mathematics in Ancient Greece 111 In the 19th century mathematicians such as Karl Weierstrass and Richard Dedekind increasingly focused their research on internal problems that is pure mathematics 109 112 This led to split mathematics into pure mathematics and applied mathematics the latter being often considered as having a lower value among mathematical purists However the lines between the two are frequently blurred 113 The aftermath of World War II led to a surge in the development of applied mathematics in the US and elsewhere 114 115 Many of the theories developed for applications were found interesting from the point of view of pure mathematics and many results of pure mathematics were shown to have applications outside mathematics in turn the study of these applications may give new insights on the pure theory 116 117 An example of the first case is the theory of distributions introduced by Laurent Schwartz for validating computations done in quantum mechanics which became immediately an important tool of pure mathematical analysis 118 An example of the second case is the decidability of the first order theory of the real numbers a problem of pure mathematics that was proved true by Alfred Tarski with an algorithm that is impossible to implement because of a computational complexity that is much too high 119 For getting an algorithm that can be implemented and can solve systems of polynomial equations and inequalities George Collins introduced the cylindrical algebraic decomposition that became a fundamental tool in real algebraic geometry 120 In the present day the distinction between pure and applied mathematics is more a question of personal research aim of mathematicians than a division of mathematics into broad areas 121 122 The Mathematics Subject Classification has a section for general applied mathematics but does not mention pure mathematics 25 However these terms are still used in names of some university departments such as at the Faculty of Mathematics at the University of Cambridge Unreasonable effectiveness The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics is a phenomenon that was named and first made explicit by physicist Eugene Wigner 7 It is the fact that many mathematical theories even the purest have applications outside their initial object These applications may be completely outside their initial area of mathematics and may concern physical phenomena that were completely unknown when the mathematical theory was introduced 123 Examples of unexpected applications of mathematical theories can be found in many areas of mathematics A notable example is the prime factorization of natural numbers that was discovered more than 2 000 years before its common use for secure internet communications through the RSA cryptosystem 124 A second historical example is the theory of ellipses They were studied by the ancient Greek mathematicians as conic sections that is intersections of cones with planes It is almost 2 000 years later that Johannes Kepler discovered that the trajectories of the planets are ellipses 125 In the 19th century the internal development of geometry pure mathematics lead to define and study non Euclidean geometries spaces of dimension higher than three and manifolds At this time these concepts seemed totally disconnected from the physical reality but at the beginning of the 20th century Albert Einstein developed the theory of relativity that uses fundamentally these concepts In particular spacetime of the special relativity is a non Euclidean space of dimension four and spacetime of the general relativity is a curved manifold of dimension four 126 127 A striking aspect of the interaction between mathematics and physics is when mathematics drives research in physics This is illustrated by the discoveries of the positron and the baryon W displaystyle Omega In both cases the equations of the theories had unexplained solutions which led to conjecture the existence of an unknown particle and to search these particles In both cases these particles were discovered a few years later by specific experiments 128 129 130 Specific sciences This subsection needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Mathematics relationship to science news newspapers books scholar JSTOR December 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message This subsection is written like a personal reflection personal essay or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor s personal feelings or presents an original argument about a topic Please help improve it by rewriting it in an encyclopedic style December 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Physics Main article Relationship between mathematics and physics Diagram of a pendulum Mathematics and physics have influenced each other over their modern history Modern physics uses mathematics abundantly 131 and is also the motivation of major mathematical developments 132 See above for examples of this strong interaction Computing Further information Theoretical computer science and Computational mathematics The rise of technology in the 20th century opened the way to a new science computing e This field is closely related to mathematics in several ways Theoretical computer science is essentially mathematical in nature Communication technologies apply branches of mathematics that may be very old e g arithmetic especially with respect to transmission security in cryptography and coding theory Discrete mathematics is useful in many areas of computer science such as complexity theory information theory graph theory and so on citation needed In return computing has also become essential for obtaining new results citation needed This is a group of techniques known as experimental mathematics which is the use of experimentation to discover mathematical insights 133 The most well known example is the four color theorem which was proven in 1976 with the help of a computer This revolutionized traditional mathematics where the rule was that the mathematician should verify each part of the proof In 1998 the Kepler conjecture seemed to also be partially proven by computer An international team had since worked on writing a formal proof it was finished and verified in 2015 citation needed Once written formally a proof can be verified using a program called a proof assistant 134 These programs are useful in situations where one is uncertain about a proof s correctness 134 A major open problem in theoretical computer science is P versus NP It is one of the seven Millennium Prize Problems 135 Biology and chemistry Main articles Mathematical and theoretical biology and Mathematical chemistry The skin of this giant pufferfish exhibits a Turing pattern which can be modeled by reaction diffusion systems Biology uses probability extensively for example in ecology or neurobiology 136 Most of the discussion of probability in biology however centers on the concept of evolutionary fitness 136 Ecology heavily uses modeling to simulate population dynamics 136 137 study ecosystems such as the predator prey model measure pollution diffusion 138 or to assess climate change 139 The dynamics of a population can be modeled by coupled differential equations such as the Lotka Volterra equations 140 However there is the problem of model validation This is particularly acute when the results of modeling influence political decisions the existence of contradictory models could allow nations to choose the most favorable model 141 Genotype evolution can be modeled with the Hardy Weinberg principle citation needed Phylogeography uses probabilistic models citation needed Medicine uses statistical hypothesis testing run on data from clinical trials to determine whether a new treatment works citation needed Since the start of the 20th century chemistry has used computing to model molecules in three dimensions It turns out that the form of macromolecules in biology is variable and determines the action Such modeling uses Euclidean geometry neighboring atoms form a polyhedron whose distances and angles are fixed by the laws of interaction citation needed Earth sciences Main article Geomathematics Structural geology and climatology use probabilistic models to predict the risk of natural catastrophes citation needed Similarly meteorology oceanography and planetology also use mathematics due to their heavy use of models citation needed Social sciences Further information Mathematical economics and Historical dynamics Areas of mathematics used in the social sciences include probability statistics and differential equations stochastic or deterministic citation needed These areas used in fields such as sociology psychology economics finance and linguistics citation needed Supply and demand curves like this one are a staple of mathematical economics The fundamental postulate of mathematical economics is that of the rational individual actor Homo economicus lit economic man 142 In this model each individual aims solely to accumulate as much profit as possible 142 and always makes optimal choices using perfect information 143 better source needed This atomistic view of economics allows it to relatively easily mathematize its thinking because individual calculations are transposed into mathematical calculations Such mathematical modeling allows one to probe economic mechanisms which would be very difficult to discover by a literary analysis citation needed For example explanations of economic cycles are not trivial Without mathematical modeling it is hard to go beyond simple statistical observations or unproven speculation citation needed However many people have rejected or criticized the concept of Homo economicus 143 better source needed Economists note that real people usually have limited information and often make poor choices 143 better source needed Also as shown in laboratory experiments people care about fairness and sometimes altruism not just personal gain 143 better source needed According to critics mathematization is a veneer that allows for the material s scientific valorization citation needed At the start of the 20th century there was a movement to express historical movements in formulas citation needed In 1922 Nikolai Kondratiev discerned the 50 year long Kondratiev cycle which explains phases of economic growth or crisis 144 Towards the end of the 19th century Nicolas Remi Bruck fr and Charles Henri Lagrange fr had extended their analysis into geopolitics They wanted to establish the historical existence of vast movements that took peoples to their apogee then to their decline 145 verification needed More recently Peter Turchin has been working on developing cliodynamics since the 1990s 146 In particular he discovered the Turchin cycle which predicts that violence spikes in a short cycle of 50 year intervals superimposed over a longer cycle of 200 300 years 147 Even so mathematization of the social sciences is not without danger In the controversial book Fashionable Nonsense 1997 Sokal and Bricmont denounced the unfounded or abusive use of scientific terminology particularly from mathematics or physics in the social sciences The study of complex systems evolution of unemployment business capital demographic evolution of a population etc uses elementary mathematical knowledge However the choice of counting criteria particularly for unemployment or of models can be subject to controversy citation needed Relationship with astrology and esotericismMathematics has had a close relationship with astrology for a long time Biased by astral themes it had motivated the study of astronomy Renowned mathematicians have also been considered to be renowned astrologists for example Ptolemy Arab astronomers Regiomantus Cardano Kepler or John Dee In the Middle Ages astrology was considered a science that included mathematics In his encyclopedia Theodor Zwinger wrote that astrology was a mathematical science that studied the active movement of bodies as they act on other bodies He reserved to mathematics the need to calculate with probability the influences of stars to foresee their conjunctions and oppositions 148 Contemporary Eastern astrological theories pride themselves on following scientific methods In particular statistical astrology uses statistical tests to provide evidence of eventual correlations between the positions of stars and the futures of people Despite this as of 2009 studies by Paul Choisnard fr and Michel Gauquelin conducted at the margins of scientific research have not found any admissible evidence of a cause and effect relationship Mathematics is also a component of esotericism Very frequently mathematicians themselves have been tempted to find in figures or numbers a hidden meaning that serves as the key to discover the world In the Pythagorean school each number had a symbolic meaning and the initiates oath was recited by a tetractys 149 Similarly Plato was not content to enumerate the solids that bear his name he also attributed to each a nature water air fire earth universe 150 Arithmosophy clarification needed numerology and gematria tended using calculations with numbers to find hidden meanings in texts or to extract predictive powers from them This fascination for numbers and figures continues to this day as some attribute hidden virtues to the pentagram or the golden ratio As of the 21st century these disciplines are no longer considered sciences 151 PhilosophyMain article Philosophy of mathematics Reality The connection between mathematics and material reality has led to philosophical debates since at least the time of Pythagoras The ancient philosopher Plato argued that abstractions that reflect material reality have themselves a reality that exists outside space and time As a result the philosophical view that mathematical objects somehow exist on their own in abstraction is often referred to as Platonism Independently of their possible philosophical opinions modern mathematicians may be generally considered as Platonists since they think of and talk of their objects of study as real objects 152 Armand Borel summarized this view of mathematics reality as follows and provided quotations of G H Hardy Charles Hermite Henri Poincare and Albert Einstein that support his views 128 Something becomes objective as opposed to subjective as soon as we are convinced that it exists in the minds of others in the same form as it does in ours and that we can think about it and discuss it together 153 Because the language of mathematics is so precise it is ideally suited to defining concepts for which such a consensus exists In my opinion that is sufficient to provide us with a feeling of an objective existence of a reality of mathematics Nevertheless Platonism and the concurrent views on abstraction do not explain the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics 154 Proposed definitions Main article Definitions of mathematics There is no general consensus about a definition of mathematics or its epistemological status that is its place among other human activities 155 156 A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics or consider it undefinable 155 There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science 156 Some just say mathematics is what mathematicians do 155 This makes sense as there is a strong consensus among them about what is mathematics and what is not Most proposed definitions try to define mathematics by its object of study 157 Aristotle defined mathematics as the science of quantity and this definition prevailed until the 18th century However Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics in his view abstraction and studying quantity as a property separable in thought from real instances set mathematics apart 158 In the 19th century when mathematicians began to address topics such as infinite sets which have no clear cut relation to physical reality a variety of new definitions were given 159 With the large number of new areas of mathematics that appeared since the beginning of the 20th century and continue to appear defining mathematics by this object of study becomes an impossible task Another approach for defining mathematics is to use its methods So an area of study can be qualified as mathematics as soon as one can prove theorem assertions whose validity relies on a proof that is a purely logical deduction 160 Others take the perspective that mathematics is an investigation of axiomatic set theory as this study is now a foundational discipline for much of modern mathematics 161 Rigor See also Logic Mathematical reasoning requires rigor This means that the definitions must be absolutely unambiguous and the proofs must be reducible to a succession of applications of inference rules f without any use of empirical evidence and intuition g 162 Rigorous reasoning is not specific to mathematics but in mathematics the standard of rigor is much higher than elsewhere Despite mathematics concision rigorous proofs can require hundreds of pages to express The emergence of computer assisted proofs has allowed proof lengths to further expand h 163 such as the 255 page Feit Thompson theorem i The result of this trend is a philosophy of the quasi empiricist proof that can not be considered infallible but has a probability attached to it 10 The concept of rigor in mathematics dates back to ancient Greece where their society encouraged logical deductive reasoning However this rigorous approach would tend to discourage exploration of new approaches such as irrational numbers and concepts of infinity The method of demonstrating rigorous proof was enhanced in the sixteenth century through the use of symbolic notation In the 18th century social transition led to mathematicians earning their keep through teaching which led to more careful thinking about the underlying concepts of mathematics This produced more rigorous approaches while transitioning from geometric methods to algebraic and then arithmetic proofs 10 At the end of the 19th century it appeared that the definitions of the basic concepts of mathematics were not accurate enough for avoiding paradoxes non Euclidean geometries and Weierstrass function and contradictions Russel s paradox This was solved by the inclusion of axioms with the apodictic inference rules of mathematical theories the re introduction of axiomatic method pioneered by the ancient Greeks 10 It results that rigor is no more a relevant concept in mathematics as a proof is either correct or erroneous and a rigorous proof is simply a pleonasm Where a special concept of rigor comes into play is in the socialized aspects of a proof wherein it may be demonstrably refuted by other mathematicians After a proof has been accepted for many years or even decades it can then be considered as reliable 164 Nevertheless the concept of rigor may remain useful for teaching to beginners what is a mathematical proof 165 Training and practiceEducation Main article Mathematics education Mathematics has a remarkable ability to cross cultural boundaries and time periods As a human activity the practice of mathematics has a social side which includes education careers recognition popularization and so on In education mathematics is a core part of the curriculum and forms an important element of the STEM academic disciplines Prominent careers for professional mathematicians include math teacher or professor statistician actuary financial analyst economist accountant commodity trader or computer consultant 166 Archaeological evidence shows that instruction in mathematics occurred as early as the second millennium BCE in ancient Babylonia 167 Comparable evidence has been unearthed for scribal mathematics training in the ancient Near East and then for the Greco Roman world starting around 300 BCE 168 The oldest known mathematics textbook is the Rhind papyrus dated from circa 1650 BCE in Eygpt 169 Due to a scarcity of books mathematical teachings in ancient India were communicated using memorized oral tradition since the Vedic period c 1500 c 500 BCE 170 In Imperial China during the Tang dynasty 618 907 CE a mathematics curriculum was adopted for the civil service exam to join the state bureaucracy 171 Following the Dark Ages mathematics education in Europe was provided by religious schools as part of the Quadrivium Formal instruction in pedagogy began with Jesuit schools in the 16th and 17th century Most mathematical curriculum remained at a basic and practical level until the nineteenth century when it began to flourish in France and Germany The oldest journal addressing instruction in mathematics was L Enseignement Mathematique which began publication in 1899 172 The Western advancements in science and technology led to the establishment of centralized education systems in many nation states with mathematics as a core component initially for its military applications 173 While the content of courses varies in the present day nearly all countries teach mathematics to students for significant amounts of time 174 During school mathematical capabilities and positive expectations have a strong association with career interest in the field Extrinsic factors such as feedback motivation by teachers parents and peer groups can influence the level of interest in mathematics 175 Some students studying math may develop an apprehension or fear about their performance in the subject This is known as math anxiety or math phobia and is considered the most prominent of the disorders impacting academic performance Math anxiety can develop due to various factors such as parental and teacher attitudes social stereotypes and personal traits Help to counteract the anxiety can come from changes in instructional approaches by interactions with parents and teachers and by tailored treatments for the individual 176 Psychology aesthetic creativity and intuition The validity of a mathematical theorem relies only on the rigor of its proof which could theoretically be done automatically by a computer program This does not mean that there is no place for creativity in a mathematical work On the contrary many important mathematical results theorems are solutions of problems that other mathematicians failed to solve and the invention of a way for solving them may be a fundamental way of the solving process 177 178 An extreme example is Apery s theorem Roger Apery provided only the ideas for a proof and the formal proof was given only several months later by three other mathematicians 179 Creativity and rigor are not the only psychological aspects of the activity of mathematicians Some mathematicians can see their activity as a game more specifically as solving puzzles 180 This aspect of mathematical activity is emphasized in recreational mathematics Mathematicians can find an aesthetic value to mathematics Like beauty it is hard to define it is commonly related to elegance which involves qualities like simplicity symmetry completeness and generality G H Hardy in A Mathematician s Apology expressed the belief that the aesthetic considerations are in themselves sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics He also identified other criteria such as significance unexpectedness and inevitability which contribute to mathematical aesthetic 181 Paul Erdos expressed this sentiment more ironically by speaking of The Book a supposed divine collection of the most beautiful proofs The 1998 book Proofs from THE BOOK inspired by Erdos is a collection of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments Some examples of particularly elegant results included are Euclid s proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers and the fast Fourier transform for harmonic analysis 182 Some feel that to consider mathematics a science is to downplay its artistry and history in the seven traditional liberal arts 183 One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematical results are created as in art or discovered as in science 128 The popularity of recreational mathematics is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions In the 20th century the mathematician L E J Brouwer even initiated a philosophical perspective known as intuitionism which primarily identifies mathematics with certain creative processes in the mind 59 Intuitionism is in turn one flavor of a stance known as constructivism which only considers a mathematical object valid if it can be directly constructed not merely guaranteed by logic indirectly This leads committed constructivists to reject certain results particularly arguments like existential proofs based on the law of excluded middle 184 In the end neither constructivism nor intuitionism displaced classical mathematics or achieved mainstream acceptance However these programs have motivated specific developments such as intuitionistic logic and other foundational insights which are appreciated in their own right 184 Cultural impactThe examples and perspective in this section deal primarily with Western culture and do not represent a worldwide view of the subject You may improve this section discuss the issue on the talk page or create a new section as appropriate December 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Artistic expression Main article Mathematics and art Cover page of Traite de l harmonie reduite a ses principes naturels by Jean Philippe Rameau Notes that sound well together to a Western ear are sounds whose fundamental frequencies of vibration are in simple ratios For example an octave doubles the frequency and a perfect fifth multiplies it by 3 2 displaystyle frac 3 2 185 186 better source needed This link between frequencies and harmony was discussed in Traite de l harmonie reduite a ses principes naturels by Jean Philippe Rameau 187 a French baroque composer and music theoretician It rests on the analysis of harmonics noted 2 to 15 in the following figure of a fundamental Do noted 1 the first harmonics and their octaves sound well together Harmonics on a staff The curve in red has a logarithmic shape which reflects the following two phenomena The pitch of the sound which in our auditory system is proportional to the logarithm of the sound s frequency The harmonic frequencies which are integer multiples of the fundamental frequency Fractal with a scaling symmetry and a central symmetry Humans as well as some other animals find symmetric patterns to be more beautiful 188 Mathematically the symmetries of an object form a group known as the symmetry group 189 For example the group underlying mirror symmetry is the cyclic group of two elements Z 2 Z displaystyle mathbb Z 2 mathbb Z A Rorschach test is a figure invariant by this symmetry as well as a butterfly and animal bodies more generally at least on the surface citation needed Waves on the sea surface possess translation symmetry moving one s viewpoint by the distance between wave crests does not change one s view of the sea citation needed Furthermore fractals possess usually approximate citation needed self similarity 190 191 better source needed Popularization Main article Popular mathematicsPopular mathematics is the act of presenting mathematics without technical terms 192 Presenting mathematics may be hard since the general public suffers from mathematical anxiety and mathematical objects are highly abstract 193 However popular mathematics writing can overcome this by using applications or cultural links 194 Despite this mathematics is rarely the topic of popularization in printed or televised media Literature and film Main category Works about mathematicsThis section has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed December 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message This section may contain indiscriminate excessive or irrelevant examples Please improve the article by adding more descriptive text and removing less pertinent examples See Wikipedia s guide to writing better articles for further suggestions December 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message There are many biographies about mathematicians but mathematics is a poorly explored theme in literature and film though it is present Novels Cover detail from Flatland Books by Denis Guedj such as The Parrot s Theorem 195 Zero ou les cinq vies d Aemer fr Der Zahlenteufel Ein Kopfkissenbuch fur alle die Angst vor der Mathematik haben by Hans Magnus Enzensberger The Oxford Murders by Guillermo Martinez Malheur aux gagnants by Julien Heylbroeck Uncle Petros and Goldbach s Conjecture by Apostolos Doxiadis Flatland by Edwin Abbott Abbott 195 The Housekeeper and the Professor by Yōko Ogawa 196 The Planiverse by A K Dewdney Le Grand Roman des maths by Mickael Launay fr Films I Q 1994 by Fred Schepisi Good Will Hunting 1997 by Gus Van Sant 197 198 Love Math and Sex 1997 by Charlotte Silvera Pi 1998 by Darren Aronofsky 198 A Beautiful Mind 2001 by Ron Howard 197 Proof 2005 by John Madden 198 The Oxford Murders 2008 by Alex de la Iglesia 21 2008 by Robert Luketic The Imitation Game 2014 by Morten Tyldum The Man Who Knew Infinity 2015 by Matthew BrownPlays Proof 2000 by David Auburn One zero show spectacle arithmetique en 0 acte et 1 tableau blanc suivi de Du point a la ligne spectacle geometrique en ligne et en surface 2001 by Denis Guedj L affaire 3 14 by Cedric Aubouy Galois Poincare mythes et maths by Cedric Aubouy and David LatiniTV series NUMB3RS by Nicolas Falacci and Cheryl Heuton 199 Eureka by Andrew Cosby and Jaime Paglia 199 Stargate Universe by Brad Wright and Robert C CooperAwards and prize problemsMain category Mathematics awards The front side of the Fields Medal with an illustration of the Greek polymath Archimedes The most prestigious award in mathematics is the Fields Medal 200 201 established in 1936 and awarded every four years except around World War II to up to four individuals 202 203 It is considered the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize 203 Other prestigious mathematics awards include 204 The Abel Prize instituted in 2002 205 and first awarded in 2003 206 The Chern Medal for lifetime achievement introduced in 2009 207 and first awarded in 2010 208 The AMS Leroy P Steele Prize awarded since 1970 209 The Wolf Prize in Mathematics also for lifetime achievement 210 instituted in 1978 211 A famous list of 23 open problems called Hilbert s problems was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician David Hilbert 212 This list has achieved great celebrity among mathematicians 213 and as of 2022 update at least thirteen of the problems depending how some are interpreted have been solved 214 A new list of seven important problems titled the Millennium Prize Problems was published in 2000 Only one of them the Riemann hypothesis duplicates one of Hilbert s problems A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward 215 To date only one of these problems the Poincare conjecture has been solved 216 See also Mathematics portalList of mathematical jargon Lists of mathematicians Lists of mathematics topics Mathematical constant Mathematical sciences Mathematics and art Mathematics education Outline of mathematics Philosophy of mathematics Relationship between mathematics and physics Science technology engineering and mathematicsNotes Here algebra is taken in its modern sense which is roughly speaking the art of manipulating formulas This includes conic sections which are intersections of circular cylinders and planes However some advanced methods of analysis are sometimes used for example methods of complex analysis applied to generating series Like other mathematical sciences such as physics and computer science statistics is an autonomous discipline rather than a branch of applied mathematics Like research physicists and computer scientists research statisticians are mathematical scientists Many statisticians have a degree in mathematics and some statisticians are also mathematicians Ada Lovelace in the 1840s is known for having written the first computer program ever in collaboration with Charles Babbage This does not mean to make explicit all inference rules that are used On the contrary this is generally impossible without computers and proof assistants Even with this modern technology it may take years of human work for writing down a completely detailed proof This does not mean that empirical evidence and intuition are not needed for choosing the theorems to be proved and to prove them For considering as reliable a large computation occurring in a proof one generally requires two computations using independent software The book containing the complete proof has more than 1 000 pages References a b mathematics n Oxford English Dictionary Oxford University Press 2012 Archived from the original on November 16 2019 Retrieved June 16 2012 The science of space number quantity and arrangement whose methods involve logical reasoning and usually the use of symbolic notation and which includes geometry arithmetic algebra and analysis Kneebone G T 1963 Mathematical Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics An Introductory Survey Dover p 4 ISBN 978 0 486 41712 7 Archived from the original on January 7 2017 Retrieved June 20 2015 Mathematics is simply the study of abstract structures or formal patterns of connectedness LaTorre Donald R Kenelly John W Biggers Sherry S Carpenter Laurel R Reed Iris B Harris Cynthia R 2011 Calculus Concepts An Informal Approach to the Mathematics of Change Cengage Learning p 2 ISBN 978 1 4390 4957 0 Archived from the original on January 7 2017 Retrieved June 20 2015 Calculus is the study of change how things change and how quickly they change Ramana B V 2007 Applied Mathematics Tata McGraw Hill Education p 2 10 ISBN 978 0 07 066753 2 Archived from the original on July 12 2022 Retrieved July 30 2022 The mathematical study of change motion growth or decay is calculus Hipolito Ines Viegas 2015 Abstract Cognition and the Nature of Mathematical Proof PDF In Kanzian Christian Mitterer Josef Neges Katharina eds Realism Relativism Constructivism 38th International Wittgenstein Symposium August 9 15 2015 Kirchberg am Wechsel Austria Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society pp 132 134 Retrieved November 5 2022 at ResearchGate Archived November 5 2022 at the Wayback Machine Peterson 2001 p 12 a b Wigner Eugene 1960 The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13 1 1 14 Bibcode 1960CPAM 13 1W doi 10 1002 cpa 3160130102 Archived from the original on February 28 2011 Wise David Eudoxus Influence on Euclid s Elements with a close look at The Method of Exhaustion jwilson coe uga edu Archived from the original on June 1 2019 Retrieved October 26 2019 Alexander Amir 2011 The Skeleton in the Closet Should Historians of Science Care about the History of Mathematics Isis 102 3 475 480 doi 10 1086 661620 PMID 22073771 S2CID 21629993 a b c d e f Kleiner Israel December 1991 Rigor and Proof in Mathematics A Historical Perspective Mathematics Magazine Taylor amp Francis Ltd 64 5 291 314 doi 10 1080 0025570X 1991 11977625 JSTOR 2690647 a b Harper Douglas mathematic n Online Etymology Dictionary Retrieved November 26 2022 Both meanings can be found in Plato the narrower in Republic 510c Archived copy Archived from the original on February 24 2021 Retrieved June 19 2019 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link CS1 maint bot original URL status unknown link but Plato did not use a math word Aristotle did commenting on it ma8hmatikh Liddell Henry George Scott Robert A Greek English Lexicon at the Perseus Project OED Online Mathematics Harper Douglas mathematical adj Online Etymology Dictionary Retrieved November 26 2022 Perisho Margaret W Spring 1965 The Etymology of Mathematical Terms Pi Mu Epsilon Journal 4 2 62 66 JSTOR 24338341 Boas Ralph 1995 1991 What Augustine Didn t Say About Mathematicians Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits A Collection of Mathematics Verse and Stories by the Late Ralph P Boas Jr Cambridge University Press p 257 ISBN 978 0 88385 323 8 Archived from the original on May 20 2020 Retrieved January 17 2018 The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology Oxford English Dictionary sub mathematics mathematic mathematics maths n and math n 3 Archived April 4 2020 at the Wayback Machine Oxford English Dictionary on line version 2012 Bell E T 2012 The Development of Mathematics Dover Books on Mathematics reprint revised ed Courier Corporation p 3 ISBN 9780486152288 Tiwari Sarju 1992 Mathematics in History Culture Philosophy and Science Mittal Publications p 27 ISBN 9788170994046 Restivo S December 2013 Mathematics in Society and History Springer Netherlands pp 14 15 ISBN 9789401129442 Musielak Dora 2022 Leonhard Euler and the Foundations of Celestial Mechanics Springer International Publishing pp 1 183 ISBN 9783031123221 Biggs N L May 1979 The roots of combinatorics Historia Mathematica 6 2 109 136 doi 10 1016 0315 0860 79 90074 0 a b Warner Evan 2013 Splash Talk The Foundational Crisis of Mathematics PDF Columbia University pp 1 17 Retrieved November 4 2022 Dunne Edward Hulek Klaus March 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification 2020 PDF Notices of the American Mathematical Society 67 3 Retrieved November 4 2022 a b c d e f g h MSC2020 Mathematics Subject Classification System PDF zbMath Associate Editors of Mathematical Reviews and zbMATH Retrieved November 26 2022 LeVeque William J January 5 2014 Fundamentals of Number Theory Dover Publications pp 1 30 ISBN 9780486141503 Goldman Jay 1997 The Queen of Mathematics A Historically Motivated Guide to Number Theory CRC Press pp 1 3 ISBN 9781439864623 Weil Andre 2007 Number Theory An Approach Through History From Hammurapi to Legendre Birkhauser Boston pp 1 3 ISBN 9780817645717 Kleiner Israel February 2000 From Fermat to Wiles Fermat s Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem Elemente der Mathematik 55 19 37 doi 10 1007 PL00000079 S2CID 53319514 Wang Yuan 2002 The Goldbach Conjecture Series in pure mathematics Vol 4 revised ed World Scientific pp 1 18 ISBN 9789812776600 a b c Straume Eldar September 2014 A Survey of the Development of Geometry up to 1870 ePrint arXiv 1409 1140 Bibcode 2014arXiv1409 1140S Hilbert David 1962 The Foundations of Geometry Open Court Publishing Company p 1 Hartshorne Robin November 11 2013 Geometry Euclid and Beyond Springer New York pp 9 13 ISBN 9780387226767 Boyer Carl B June 28 2012 History of Analytic Geometry Dover Publications pp 74 102 ISBN 9780486154510 Stump David J 1997 Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900 Perspectives on Science 5 3 383 doi 10 1162 posc a 00532 S2CID 117709681 O Connor J J Robertson E F February 1996 Non Euclidean geometry MacTuror School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Retrieved November 6 2022 Joyner D 2008 Adventures in group theory Rubik s Cube Merlin s machine and other mathematical toys 2nd ed Johns Hopkins University Press pp 219 232 ISBN 9780801890130 Christianidis Jean Oaks Jeffrey May 2013 Practicing algebra in late antiquity The problem solving of Diophantus of Alexandria Historia Mathematica 40 2 127 163 doi 10 1016 j hm 2012 09 001 Kleiner 2007 History of Classical Algebra pp 3 5 Lim Lisa December 21 2018 Where algebra got its x from and Xmas its X South China Morning Post Retrieved August 9 2022 Oaks J A 2018 Francois Viete s revolution in algebra PDF Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 3 245 302 doi 10 1007 s00407 018 0208 0 S2CID 125704699 Retrieved November 8 2022 Kleiner 2007 History of Linear Algebra pp 79 101 Corry Leo December 6 2012 Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures Birkhauser Basel pp 247 252 ISBN 9783034879170 Riche Jacques 2007 Beziau J Y Costa Leite Alexandre eds From Universal Algebra to Universal Logic Perspective on Universal Logic Italy Polimetrica International Scientific pp 3 39 ISBN 9788876990779 Kromer Ralph 2007 Tool and Object A History and Philosophy of Category Theory Science Networks Historical Studies Vol 32 Springer Science amp Business Media pp xxi xxv 1 91 ISBN 9783764375249 Guicciardini Niccolo 2017 The Newton Leibniz Calculus Controversy 1708 1730 PDF In Schliesser Eric Smeenk Chris eds The Oxford Handbook of Newton Oxford handbooks Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199930418 013 9 ISBN 9780199930418 Retrieved November 9 2022 O Connor J J Robertson E F September 1998 Leonhard Euler MacTutor School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Retrieved November 9 2022 Franklin James 2017 Discrete and continuous a fundamental dichotomy in mathematics Journal of Humanistic Mathematics 7 2 355 378 doi 10 5642 jhummath 201702 18 S2CID 6945363 Retrieved November 10 2022 Maurer Stephen B 1997 Rosenstein Joseph G Franzblau Deborah S Roberts Fred S eds What is Discrete Mathematics The Many Answers Discrete Mathematics in the Schools DIMACS Series in Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science Vol 36 American Mathematical Society pp 121 124 ISBN 9780821885789 Downey Rod 2014 Turing s Legacy Developments from Turing s Ideas in Logic Issue 42 of Lecture Notes in Logic Cambridge University Press pp 260 261 ISBN 9781107043480 Sipser Michael July 1992 The history and status of the P versus NP question STOC 92 Proceedings of the twenty fourth annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing pp 603 618 doi 10 1145 129712 129771 Ewald William November 17 2018 The Emergence of First Order Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved November 2 2022 Ferreiros Jose June 18 2020 The Early Development of Set Theory Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved November 2 2022 Ferreiros Jose 2001 The Road to Modern Logic An Interpretation PDF Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 4 441 484 doi 10 2307 2687794 hdl 11441 38373 JSTOR 2687794 S2CID 43258676 Retrieved November 11 2022 Wolchover Natalie December 3 2013 Dispute over Infinity Divides Mathematicians Scientific American Retrieved November 1 2022 Zhuang C Wittgenstein s analysis on Cantor s diagonal argument PhilArchive Retrieved November 18 2022 Avigad Jeremy Reck Erich H December 11 2001 Clarifying the nature of the infinite the development of metamathematics and proof theory PDF Carnegie Mellon Technical Report CMU PHIL 120 Retrieved November 12 2022 Hamilton Alan G 1982 Numbers Sets and Axioms The Apparatus of Mathematics Cambridge University Press pp 3 4 ISBN 9780521287616 a b Snapper Ernst September 1979 The Three Crises in Mathematics Logicism Intuitionism and Formalism Mathematics Magazine 52 4 207 16 doi 10 2307 2689412 JSTOR 2689412 a b Raatikainen Panu October 2005 On the Philosophical Relevance of Godel s Incompleteness Theorems Revue Internationale de Philosophie 59 4 513 534 doi 10 3917 rip 234 0513 JSTOR 23955909 S2CID 52083793 Retrieved November 12 2022 Moschovakis Joan September 4 2018 Intuitionistic Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved November 12 2022 McCarty Charles 2006 At the Heart of Analysis Intuitionism and Philosophy Philosophia Scientiae Cahier special 6 81 94 doi 10 4000 philosophiascientiae 411 Halpern Joseph Harper Robert Immerman Neil Kolaitis Phokion Vardi Moshe Vianu Victor 2001 On the Unusual Effectiveness of Logic in Computer Science PDF Archived PDF from the original on March 3 2021 Retrieved January 15 2021 Rouaud Mathieu 2013 Probability Statistics and Estimation PDF p 10 Archived PDF from the original on October 9 2022 Rao C R 1997 Statistics and Truth Putting Chance to Work World Scientific ISBN 978 981 02 3111 8 Rao C R 1981 Foreword In Arthanari T S Dodge Yadolah eds Mathematical programming in statistics Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics New York Wiley pp vii viii ISBN 978 0 471 08073 2 MR 0607328 Whittle 1994 pp 10 11 14 18 Marchuk Gurii Ivanovich April 2020 G I Marchuk s plenary ICM 1970 MacTutor School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Retrieved November 13 2022 Johnson Gary M Cavallini John S September 1991 Phua Kang Hoh Loe Kia Fock eds Grand Challenges High Performance Computing and Computational Science Singapore Supercomputing Conference 90 Supercomputing For Strategic Advantage World Scientific p 28 Trefethen Lloyd N 2008 Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June Leader Imre eds Numerical Analysis PDF The Princeton Companion to Mathematics Princeton University Press pp 604 615 ISBN 9780691118802 Retrieved November 13 2022 Dehaene Stanislas Dehaene Lambertz Ghislaine Cohen Laurent August 1998 Abstract representations of numbers in the animal and human brain Trends in Neurosciences 21 8 355 61 doi 10 1016 S0166 2236 98 01263 6 PMID 9720604 S2CID 17414557 See for example Wilder Raymond L Evolution of Mathematical Concepts an Elementary Study passim Zaslavsky Claudia 1999 Africa Counts Number and Pattern in African Culture Chicago Review Press ISBN 978 1 61374 115 3 OCLC 843204342 Kline 1990 Chapter 1 Boyer 1991 Mesopotamia pp 24 27 Heath Thomas Little 1981 1921 A History of Greek Mathematics From Thales to Euclid New York Dover Publications p 1 ISBN 978 0 486 24073 2 Mueller I 1969 Euclid s Elements and the Axiomatic Method The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 4 289 309 doi 10 1093 bjps 20 4 289 ISSN 0007 0882 JSTOR 686258 Boyer 1991 Euclid of Alexandria p 119 Boyer 1991 Archimedes of Syracuse p 120 Boyer 1991 Archimedes of Syracuse p 130 Boyer 1991 Apollonius of Perga p 145 Boyer 1991 Greek Trigonometry and Mensuration p 162 Boyer 1991 Revival and Decline of Greek Mathematics p 180 Ore Oystein 1988 Number Theory and Its History Courier Corporation pp 19 24 ISBN 9780486656205 Singh A N January 1936 On the Use of Series in Hindu Mathematics Osiris 1 606 628 doi 10 1086 368443 JSTOR 301627 S2CID 144760421 Kolachana A Mahesh K Ramasubramanian K 2019 Use of series in India Studies in Indian Mathematics and Astronomy Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Singapore Springer doi 10 1007 978 981 13 7326 8 20 ISBN 978 981 13 7325 1 S2CID 190176726 Saliba George 1994 A history of Arabic astronomy planetary theories during the golden age of Islam New York University Press ISBN 978 0 8147 7962 0 OCLC 28723059 Faruqi Yasmeen M 2006 Contributions of Islamic scholars to the scientific enterprise International Education Journal Shannon Research Press 7 4 391 399 Retrieved November 14 2022 Lorch Richard June 2001 Greek Arabic Latin The Transmission of Mathematical Texts in the Middle Ages PDF Science in Context Cambridge University Press 14 1 2 313 331 doi 10 1017 S0269889701000114 S2CID 146539132 Archibald Raymond Clare January 1949 History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century The American Mathematical Monthly Part 2 Outline of the History of Mathematics 56 1 35 56 doi 10 2307 2304570 JSTOR 2304570 Sevryuk 2006 pp 101 09 Wolfram Stephan October 2000 Mathematical notation Past and future MathML and Math on the Web MathML International Conference 2000 Urbana Champaign USA Retrieved November 16 2022 Douglas Heather Headley Marcia Gail Hadden Stephanie LeFevre Jo Anne December 3 2020 Knowledge of Mathematical Symbols Goes Beyond Numbers Journal of Numerical Cognition 6 3 322 354 doi 10 5964 jnc v6i3 293 S2CID 228085700 Letourneau Mary Wright Sharp Jennifer 2017 AMS style guide PDF American Mathematical Society p 75 Retrieved November 16 2022 Jansen A R Marriott K Yelland G W 2000 Constituent structure in mathematical expressions PDF Proceedings of the 22th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society Vol 22 p 238 Retrieved November 16 2022 Rossi Richard J 2011 Theorems Corollaries Lemmas and Methods of Proof Pure and Applied Mathematics A Wiley Series of Texts Monographs and Tracts John Wiley amp Sons pp 1 14 47 48 ISBN 9781118030578 Earliest Uses of Some Words of Mathematics MacTutor School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Retrieved November 19 2022 Silver Daniel S 2017 The New Language of Mathematics The American Scientist 105 6 364 371 doi 10 1511 2017 105 6 364 Retrieved November 19 2022 Bellomo Nicola Preziosi Luigi December 22 1994 Modelling Mathematical Methods and Scientific Computation Mathematical Modeling Vol 1 CRC Press p 1 ISBN 9780849383311 Hennig Christian 2010 Mathematical Models and Reality A Constructivist Perspective Foundations of Science 15 29 48 doi 10 1007 s10699 009 9167 x S2CID 6229200 Retrieved November 17 2022 Frigg Roman Hartmann Stephan February 4 2020 Models in Science Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved November 17 2022 Stewart Ian 2018 Mathematics Maps and Models In Wuppuluri Shyam Doria Francisco Antonio eds The Map and the Territory Exploring the Foundations of Science Thought and Reality The Frontiers Collection Springer pp 345 356 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 72478 2 18 ISBN 9783319724782 The science checklist applied Mathematics undsci berkeley edu Archived from the original on October 27 2019 Retrieved October 27 2019 Mackay A L 1991 Dictionary of Scientific Quotations London Taylor amp Francis p 100 ISBN 9780750301060 Bishop Alan 1991 Environmental activities and mathematical culture Mathematical Enculturation A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education Norwell Massachusetts Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 20 59 ISBN 978 0 7923 1270 3 Archived from the original on December 25 2020 Retrieved April 5 2020 Shasha Dennis Elliot Lazere Cathy A 1998 Out of Their Minds The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists Springer p 228 ISBN 9780387982694 Nickles Thomas 2013 The Problem of Demarcation Philosophy of Pseudoscience Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem Chicago The University of Chicago Press p 104 ISBN 9780226051826 Pigliucci Massimo 2014 Are There Other Ways of Knowing Philosophy Now Archived from the original on May 13 2020 Retrieved April 6 2020 a b Ferreiros J 2007 O 8eὸs Ari8mhtizei The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss In Goldstein Catherine Schappacher Norbert Schwermer Joachim eds The Shaping of Arithmetic after C F Gauss s Disquisitiones Arithmeticae Springer Science amp Business Media pp 235 268 ISBN 9783540347200 Kuhn Thomas S 1976 Mathematical vs Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science The Journal of Interdisciplinary History The MIT Press 7 1 1 31 doi 10 2307 202372 JSTOR 202372 Asper Markus 2009 The two cultures of mathematics in ancient Greece In Robson Eleanor Stedall Jacqueline eds The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics Oxford Handbooks in Mathematics OUP Oxford pp 107 132 ISBN 9780199213122 Maddy P 2008 How applied mathematics became pure PDF The Review of Symbolic Logic 1 1 16 41 doi 10 1017 S1755020308080027 S2CID 18122406 Retrieved November 19 2022 Silver Daniel S 2017 In Defense of Pure Mathematics In Pitici Mircea ed The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016 Princeton University Press pp 17 26 ISBN 9780691175294 Parshall Karen Hunger 2022 The American Mathematical Society and Applied Mathematics from the 1920s to the 1950s A Revisionist Account Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 59 3 405 427 doi 10 1090 bull 1754 S2CID 249561106 Retrieved November 20 2022 Stolz Michael 2002 The History Of Applied Mathematics And The History Of Society Synthese 133 43 57 doi 10 1023 A 1020823608217 S2CID 34271623 Retrieved November 20 2022 Lin C C March 1976 On the role of applied mathematics Advances in Mathematics 19 3 267 288 doi 10 1016 0001 8708 76 90024 4 Peressini Anthony September 1999 Applying Pure Mathematics PDF Philosophy of Science Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association Part I Contributed Papers Vol 66 pp S1 S13 JSTOR 188757 Retrieved November 30 2022 Lutzen J 2011 Examples and reflections on the interplay between mathematics and physics in the 19th and 20th century In Schlote K H Schneider M eds Mathematics meets physics A contribution to their interaction in the 19th and the first half of the 20th century Frankfurt am Main Verlag Harri Deutsch Retrieved November 19 2022 Marker Dave July 1996 Model theory and exponentiation Notices of the American Mathematical Society 43 7 753 759 Retrieved November 19 2022 Chen Changbo Maza Marc Moreno August 2014 Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition in the RegularChains Library International Congress on Mathematical Software 2014 Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 8592 Berlin Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 662 44199 2 65 Retrieved November 19 2022 Perez Escobar Jose Antonio Sarikaya Deniz 2021 Purifying applied mathematics and applying pure mathematics how a late Wittgensteinian perspective sheds light onto the dichotomy European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 1 1 22 doi 10 1007 s13194 021 00435 9 S2CID 245465895 Takase M 2014 Pure Mathematics and Applied Mathematics are Inseparably Intertwined Observation of the Early Analysis of the Infinity A Mathematical Approach to Research Problems of Science and Technology Mathematics for Industry Vol 5 Tokyo Springer pp 393 399 doi 10 1007 978 4 431 55060 0 29 ISBN 978 4 431 55059 4 Sarukkai Sundar February 10 2005 Revisiting the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics Current Science 88 3 415 423 JSTOR 24110208 Wagstaff Jr Samuel S 2021 History of Integer Factoring PDF In Bos Joppe W Stam Martijn eds Computational Cryptography Algorithmic Aspects of Cryptography A Tribute to AKL London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series 469 Cambridge University Press pp 41 77 Retrieved November 20 2022 Curves Ellipse MacTutor School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Retrieved November 20 2022 Mukunth Vasudevan September 10 2015 Beyond the Surface of Einstein s Relativity Lay a Chimerical Geometry The Wire Retrieved November 20 2022 Wilson Edwin B Lewis Gilbert N November 1912 The Space Time Manifold of Relativity The Non Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 48 11 389 507 doi 10 2307 20022840 JSTOR 20022840 a b c Borel Armand 1983 Mathematics Art and Science The Mathematical Intelligencer Springer 5 4 9 17 doi 10 4171 news 103 8 ISSN 1027 488X Hanson Norwood Russell November 1961 Discovering the Positron I The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science The University of Chicago Press 12 47 194 214 doi 10 1093 bjps xiii 49 54 JSTOR 685207 Ginammi Michele February 2016 Avoiding reification Heuristic effectiveness of mathematics and the prediction of the W particle Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 53 20 27 Bibcode 2016SHPMP 53 20G doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2015 12 001 Wagh Sanjay Moreshwar Deshpande Dilip Abasaheb September 27 2012 ESSENTIALS OF PHYSICS PHI Learning Pvt Ltd p 3 ISBN 978 81 203 4642 0 Atiyah Michael 1990 On the Work of Edward Witten PDF Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians p 31 Archived from the original PDF on September 28 2013 Retrieved December 29 2022 Borwein J Borwein P Girgensohn R Parnes S 1996 Conclusion oldweb cecm sfu ca Archived from the original on January 21 2008 a b Geuvers H February 2009 Proof assistants History ideas and future Sadhana 34 3 4 P versus NP problem mathematics Britannica www britannica com Retrieved December 29 2022 a b c Millstein Roberta September 8 2016 Probability in Biology The Case of Fitness PDF In Hajek Alan Hitchcock Christopher eds The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy pp 601 622 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199607617 013 27 See for example Anne Laurent Roland Gamet Jerome Pantel Tendances nouvelles en modelisation pour l environnement actes du congres Programme environnement vie et societes 15 17 janvier 1996 CNRS Bouleau 1999 pp 282 283 Bouleau 1999 p 285 1 4 The Lotka Volterra Predator Prey Model Mathematics LibreTexts January 5 2022 Retrieved December 29 2022 Bouleau 1999 p 287 a b Zak Paul J December 16 2010 Moral Markets The Critical Role of Values in the Economy Princeton University Press p 158 ISBN 978 1 4008 3736 6 a b c d Kim Oliver W May 29 2014 Meet Homo Economicus The Harvard Crimson Retrieved December 29 2022 Kondratiev Nikolai Dmitrievich Encyclopedia com www encyclopedia com Retrieved December 29 2022 Dictionnaire en economie et science sociale Ed Nathan Paris dictionnaire Larousse en 3 vol Paris Les definitions des cycles sont nombreuses entre autres en sciences evolution de systemes qui les ramenent a leur etat initial ou en sociologie mouvement s recurrent s d activite s politique s et economique s full citation needed Cliodynamics a science for predicting the future ZDNET Retrieved December 29 2022 Wolchover Natalie August 3 2012 Will the US Really Experience a Violent Upheaval in 2020 Live Science Retrieved December 29 2022 Beaujouan Guy 1994 Comprendre et maitriser la nature au Moyen Age melanges d histoire des sciences offerts a Guy Beaujouan in French Librairie Droz p 130 ISBN 978 2 600 00040 6 Dahan Dalmedico A Peiffer J 1986 Une histoire des mathematiques Routes et dedales p 47 Platon Le Timee 53 c 56c full citation needed L astrologie a l epreuve ca ne marche pas ca n a jamais marche Afis Science Association francaise pour l information scientifique Afis Science Association francaise pour l information scientifique in French Retrieved December 28 2022 Balaguer Mark 2016 Platonism in Metaphysics In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on January 30 2022 Retrieved April 2 2022 See White L 1947 The locus of mathematical reality An anthropological footnote Philosophy of Science 14 4 289 303 doi 10 1086 286957 S2CID 119887253 189303 also in Newman J R 1956 The World of Mathematics Vol 4 New York Simon and Schuster pp 2348 2364 Dorato Mauro 2005 Why are laws mathematical PDF The Software of the Universe An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Laws of Nature Ashgate pp 31 66 ISBN 9780754639947 Retrieved December 5 2022 a b c Mura Roberta December 1993 Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences Educational Studies in Mathematics 25 4 375 85 doi 10 1007 BF01273907 JSTOR 3482762 S2CID 122351146 a b Tobies Renate Neunzert Helmut 2012 Iris Runge A Life at the Crossroads of Mathematics Science and Industry Springer p 9 ISBN 978 3 0348 0229 1 I t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science a branch of the humanities or an art form Ziegler Gunter M Loos Andreas November 2 2017 Kaiser G ed What is Mathematics and why we should ask where one should experience and learn that and how to teach it Proceedings of the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education ICME 13 Monographs Springer pp 63 77 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 62597 3 5 ISBN 978 3 319 62596 6 Franklin James July 8 2009 Philosophy of Mathematics pp 104 106 ISBN 978 0 08 093058 9 Cajori Florian 1893 A History of Mathematics American Mathematical Society 1991 reprint pp 285 286 ISBN 978 0 8218 2102 2 Brown Ronald Porter Timothy January 2000 The Methodology of Mathematics The Mathematical Gazette 79 485 321 334 doi 10 2307 3618304 JSTOR 3618304 S2CID 178923299 Strauss Danie 2011 Defining mathematics Acta Academica 43 4 1 28 Retrieved November 25 2022 Hamami Yacin June 2022 Mathematical Rigor and Proof PDF The Review of Symbolic Logic 15 2 409 449 doi 10 1017 S1755020319000443 S2CID 209980693 Retrieved November 21 2022 Peterson Ivars 1988 The Mathematical Tourist Freeman p 4 ISBN 978 0 7167 1953 3 A few complain that the computer program can t be verified properly in reference to the Haken Apple proof of the Four Color Theorem Perminov V Ya 1988 On the Reliability of Mathematical Proofs Philosophy of Mathematics Revue Internationale de Philosophie 42 167 4 500 508 Davis Jon D McDuffie Amy Roth Drake Corey Seiwelld Amanda L 2019 Teachers perceptions of the official curriculum Problem solving and rigor International Journal of Educational Research 93 91 100 doi 10 1016 j ijer 2018 10 002 S2CID 149753721 Endsley Kezia 2021 Mathematicians and Statisticians A Practical Career Guide Practical Career Guides Rowman amp Littlefield pp 1 3 ISBN 9781538145173 Robson Eleanor 2009 Mathematics education in an Old Babylonian scribal school In Robson Eleanor Stedall Jacqueline eds The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics OUP Oxford ISBN 9780199213122 Bernard Alain Proust Christine Ross Micah 2014 Mathematics Education in Antiquity In Karp A Schubring G eds Handbook on the History of Mathematics Education New York Springer pp 27 53 doi 10 1007 978 1 4614 9155 2 3 ISBN 978 1 4614 9154 5 Dudley Underwood April 2002 The World s First Mathematics Textbook Math Horizons Taylor amp Francis Ltd 9 4 8 11 doi 10 1080 10724117 2002 11975154 JSTOR 25678363 S2CID 126067145 Subramarian F Indian pedagogy and problem solving in ancient Thamizhakam PDF History and Pedagogy of Mathematics conference 16 20 July 2012 Retrieved November 29 2022 Siu Man Keung 2004 Official Curriculum in Mathematics in Ancient China How did Candidates Study for the Examination How Chinese Learn Mathematics PDF Series on Mathematics Education Vol 1 pp 157 185 doi 10 1142 9789812562241 0006 ISBN 978 981 256 014 8 Retrieved November 26 2022 Jones Phillip S 1967 The History of Mathematical Education The American Mathematical Monthly Taylor amp Francis Ltd 74 1 38 55 doi 10 2307 2314867 JSTOR 2314867 Schubring Gert Furinghetti Fulvia Siu Man Keung August 2012 Introduction the history of mathematics teaching Indicators for modernization processes in societies ZDM Mathematics Education 44 4 457 459 doi 10 1007 s11858 012 0445 7 S2CID 145507519 von Davier Matthias Foy Pierre Martin Michael O Mullis Ina V S 2020 Examining eTIMSS Country Differences Between eTIMSS Data and Bridge Data A Look at Country Level Mode of Administration Effects TIMSS 2019 International Results in Mathematics and Science PDF TIMSS amp PIRLS International Study Center Lynch School of Education and Human Development Boston College and International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement p 13 1 ISBN 978 1 889938 54 7 Retrieved November 29 2022 Rowan Kenyon Heather T Swan Amy K Creager Marie F March 2012 Social Cognitive Factors Support and Engagement Early Adolescents Math Interests as Precursors to Choice of Career PDF The Career Development Quarterly 60 1 2 15 doi 10 1002 j 2161 0045 2012 00001 x Retrieved November 29 2022 Luttenberger Silke Wimmer Sigrid Paechter Manuela 2018 Spotlight on math anxiety Psychology Research and Behavior Management 11 311 322 doi 10 2147 PRBM S141421 PMC 6087017 PMID 30123014 Yaftian Narges June 2 2015 The Outlook of the Mathematicians Creative Processes Procedia Social and Behavioral Sciences 191 2519 2525 doi 10 1016 j sbspro 2015 04 617 Nadjafikhah Mehdi Yaftian Narges October 10 2013 The Frontage of Creativity and Mathematical Creativity Procedia Social and Behavioral Sciences 90 344 350 doi 10 1016 j sbspro 2013 07 101 van der Poorten A 1979 A proof that Euler missed Apery s Proof of the irrationality of z 3 PDF The Mathematical Intelligencer 1 4 195 203 doi 10 1007 BF03028234 S2CID 121589323 Retrieved November 22 2022 Petkovi Miodrag September 2 2009 Famous Puzzles of Great Mathematicians American Mathematical Society pp xiii xiv ISBN 9780821848142 Hardy G H 1940 A Mathematician s Apology Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 42706 7 Retrieved November 22 2022 See also A Mathematician s Apology Alon Noga Goldston Dan Sarkozy Andras Szabados Jozsef Tenenbaum Gerald Garcia Stephan Ramon Shoemaker Amy L March 2015 Alladi Krishnaswami Krantz Steven G eds Reflections on Paul Erdos on His Birth Centenary Part II Notices of the American Mathematical Society 62 3 226 247 doi 10 1090 noti1223 See for example Bertrand Russell s statement Mathematics rightly viewed possesses not only truth but supreme beauty in his History of Western Philosophy 1919 p 60 a b Iemhoff Rosalie 2020 Intuitionism in the Philosophy of Mathematics In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on April 21 2022 Retrieved April 2 2022 Musical Mathematics Just Intonation The Chrysalis Foundation www chrysalis foundation org Retrieved December 29 2022 Just Intonation Explained www kylegann com Retrieved December 29 2022 Rameau Jean Philippe 1986 1722 Traite de l harmonie reduite a ses principes naturels Collection de musicologie Paris Meridiens Klincksieck fr p 432 ISBN 978 2 86563 157 5 Enquist Magnus Arak Anthony November 1994 Symmetry beauty and evolution Nature 372 6502 169 172 doi 10 1038 372169a0 ISSN 1476 4687 Hestenes David 1999 Symmetry Groups PDF geocalc clas asu edu Retrieved December 29 2022 Bradley Larry 2010 Fractals Chaos amp Fractals www stsci edu Retrieved December 29 2022 Self similarity math bu edu Retrieved December 29 2022 Kissane Barry July 2009 Popular mathematics 22nd Biennial Conference of The Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers Fremantle Western Australia Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers pp 125 126 Steen L A December 6 2012 Mathematics Today Twelve Informal Essays Springer Science amp Business Media p 2 ISBN 978 1 4613 9435 8 Pitici Mircea February 14 2017 The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016 Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 8560 2 a b Dan January 23 2022 12 Best Mathematical Science Fiction Books The Best Sci Fi Books Retrieved December 29 2022 Chung Catherine November 6 2019 From Alice in Wonderland to the Hitchhiker s Guide top 10 books about mathematics the Guardian Retrieved December 29 2022 a b Mathematics in Movies people math harvard edu Retrieved December 29 2022 a b c Top 8 movies about mathematicians Mathematics University of Waterloo August 13 2021 Retrieved December 29 2022 a b The Mathematical TV Database www qedcat com Retrieved December 29 2022 Monastyrsky 2001 p 1 The Fields Medal is now indisputably the best known and most influential award in mathematics Riehm 2002 pp 778 82 Fields Medal International Mathematical Union IMU www mathunion org Archived from the original on December 26 2018 Retrieved February 21 2022 a b Fields Medal Maths History Archived from the original on March 22 2019 Retrieved February 21 2022 Mathematics Prizes Wolfram MathWorld Retrieved November 17 2022 About the Abel Prize The Abel Prize Archived from the original on April 14 2022 Retrieved January 23 2022 Abel Prize mathematics award Encyclopedia Britannica Archived from the original on January 26 2020 Retrieved January 23 2022 CHERN MEDAL AWARD PDF www mathunion org June 1 2009 Archived PDF from the original on June 17 2009 Retrieved February 21 2022 Chern Medal Award International Mathematical Union IMU Archived from the original on August 25 2010 Retrieved January 23 2022 The Leroy P Steele Prize of the AMS School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Retrieved November 17 2022 Chern S S Hirzebruch F September 2000 Wolf Prize in Mathematics doi 10 1142 4149 ISBN 978 981 02 3945 9 Archived from the original on February 21 2022 Retrieved February 21 2022 The Wolf Prize Wolf Foundation Archived from the original on January 12 2020 Retrieved January 23 2022 Hilbert s Problems 23 and Math Simons Foundation May 6 2020 Archived from the original on January 23 2022 Retrieved January 23 2022 Feferman Solomon 1998 Deciding the undecidable Wrestling with Hilbert s problems PDF In the Light of Logic Logic and Computation in Philosophy series Oxford University Press pp 3 27 ISBN 0 19 508030 0 Retrieved November 29 2022 Hilbert s Problems 23 and Math Simons Foundation May 6 2020 Retrieved January 23 2022 The Millennium Prize Problems Clay Mathematics Institute Archived from the original on July 3 2015 Retrieved January 23 2022 Millennium Problems Clay Mathematics Institute Archived from the original on December 20 2018 Retrieved January 23 2022 BibliographyBouleau Nicolas 1999 Philosophie des mathematiques et de la modelisation Du chercheur a l ingenieur L Harmattan ISBN 9782738481252 Boyer Carl Benjamin 1991 A History of Mathematics 2nd ed New York Wiley ISBN 978 0 471 54397 8 Eves Howard 1990 An Introduction to the History of Mathematics 6th ed Saunders ISBN 978 0 03 029558 4 Kleiner Izrail 2007 A History of Abstract Algebra Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 9780817646844 Kline Morris 1990 Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times Paperback ed New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 506135 2 Monastyrsky Michael 2001 Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal PDF CMS NOTES de la SMC Canadian Mathematical Society 33 2 3 Archived PDF from the original on August 13 2006 Retrieved July 28 2006 Oakley Barbara 2014 A Mind For Numbers How to Excel at Math and Science Even If You Flunked Algebra New York Penguin Random House ISBN 978 0 399 16524 5 A Mind for Numbers Peirce Benjamin 1881 Peirce Charles Sanders ed Linear associative algebra American Journal of Mathematics Corrected expanded and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B Peirce and annotations by his son C S Peirce of the 1872 lithograph ed 4 1 4 97 229 doi 10 2307 2369153 hdl 2027 hvd 32044030622997 JSTOR 2369153 Corrected expanded and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B Peirce and annotations by his son C S Peirce of the 1872 lithograph ed Google Eprint and as an extract D Van Nostrand 1882 Google Eprint Archived from the original on March 31 2021 Retrieved November 17 2020 Peterson Ivars 2001 Mathematical Tourist New and Updated Snapshots of Modern Mathematics Owl Books ISBN 978 0 8050 7159 7 Popper Karl R 1995 On knowledge In Search of a Better World Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years New York Routledge Bibcode 1992sbwl book P ISBN 978 0 415 13548 1 Riehm Carl August 2002 The Early History of the Fields Medal PDF Notices of the AMS 49 7 778 82 Archived PDF from the original on October 26 2006 Retrieved October 2 2006 Sevryuk Mikhail B January 2006 Book Reviews PDF Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 43 1 101 09 doi 10 1090 S0273 0979 05 01069 4 Archived PDF from the original on July 23 2006 Retrieved June 24 2006 Waltershausen Wolfgang Sartorius von 1965 first published 1856 Gauss zum Gedachtniss Sandig Reprint Verlag H R Wohlwend ISBN 978 3 253 01702 5 Whittle Peter 1994 Almost home In Kelly F P ed Probability statistics and optimisation A Tribute to Peter Whittle previously A realised path The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 revised 2002 ed Chichester John Wiley pp 1 28 ISBN 978 0 471 94829 2 Archived from the original on December 19 2013 Further reading Mathematics at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Media from Commons News from Wikinews Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Textbooks from Wikibooks Resources from Wikiversity At Wikiversity you can learn more and teach others about Mathematics at the School of Mathematics Benson Donald C 1999 The Moment of Proof Mathematical Epiphanies Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 513919 8 Davis Philip J Hersh Reuben 1999 The Mathematical Experience Reprint ed Boston New York Mariner Books ISBN 978 0 395 92968 1 Available online registration required Courant Richard Robbins Herbert 1996 What Is Mathematics An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods 2nd ed New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 510519 3 Gullberg Jan 1997 Mathematics From the Birth of Numbers W W Norton amp Company ISBN 978 0 393 04002 9 Hazewinkel Michiel ed 2000 Encyclopaedia of Mathematics Kluwer Academic Publishers A translated and expanded version of a Soviet mathematics encyclopedia in ten volumes Also in paperback and on CD ROM and online Archived July 3 2011 at the Wayback Machine Hodgkin Luke Howard 2005 A History of Mathematics From Mesopotamia to Modernity Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 152383 0 Jourdain Philip E B 2003 The Nature of Mathematics In James R Newman ed The World of Mathematics Dover Publications ISBN 978 0 486 43268 7 Pappas Theoni 1986 The Joy Of Mathematics San Carlos California Wide World Publishing ISBN 978 0 933174 65 8 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Mathematics amp oldid 1130877014, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.