fbpx
Wikipedia

Analytic philosophy

Analytic philosophy is a broad, contemporary movement or tradition within Western philosophy and especially anglophone philosophy, focused on analysis.[a][b] Analytic philosophy is characterized by a style of clarity of prose and rigor in arguments, making use of formal logic and mathematics, and, to a lesser degree, the natural sciences.[3][4][c][d][e] It is further characterized by an interest in language and meaning known as the linguistic turn.[8][f][g][h] It has developed several new branches of philosophy and logic, notably philosophy of language, philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of science, modern predicate logic and mathematical logic.[12]

The proliferation of analysis in philosophy began around the turn of the 20th century and has been dominant since the latter half of the 20th century.[13][14][15][i] Central figures in its historical development are Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, G. E. Moore, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Other important figures in its history include Franz Brentano, the logical positivists (particularly Rudolf Carnap), the ordinary language philosophers, W. V. O. Quine, and Karl Popper. After the decline of logical positivism, Saul Kripke, David Lewis, and others led a revival in metaphysics.

Analytic philosophy is often contrasted with continental philosophy,[j] coined as a catch-all term for other methods, prominent in continental Europe,[k] most notably existentialism, phenomenology, and Hegelianism.[l][m][n] There is widespread influence and debate between the analytic and continental traditions; some philosophers see the differences between the two traditions as being based on institutions, relationships, and ideology rather than anything of significant philosophical substance.[22][23] The distinction has also been drawn as analytic is academic or technical philosophy, while continental is literary philosophy.[o][p]

History of analytic philosophy edit

Austrian realism edit

 
Franz Brentano gave to philosophy the problem of intentionality.

Analytic philosophy was deeply influenced by what is called Austrian realism in the former state of Austria-Hungary, so much so that Michael Dummett has remarked that analytic philosophy is better characterized as Anglo-Austrian rather than the usual Anglo-American.[28]

Brentano edit

University of Vienna philosopher and psychologist Franz Brentano in Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (1874), through the subsequent influence of the School of Brentano and its members, such as Edmund Husserl and Alexius Meinong, gave to analytic philosophy the problem of intentionality or of aboutness.[29] For Brentano, all mental events have a real, non-mental intentional object which the thinking is directed at or "about".

Meinong edit

Meinong is known for his unique ontology of real nonexistent objects as a solution to the problem of empty names.[30] The Graz School followed Meinong.

Lwów–Warsaw edit

The Polish Lwów–Warsaw school, founded by Kazimierz Twardowski in 1895, grew as a further offshoot of the Graz School. It was closely associated with the Warsaw School of Mathematics.

Frege edit

 
Gottlob Frege, the father of analytic philosophy.

Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) was a German geometry professor at the University of Jena who is understood as the father of analytic philosophy. Frege proved influential as a philosopher of mathematics in Germany at the beginning of the 20th century. He advocated logicism, the project of reducing arithmetic to pure logic.

Logic edit

As a result of his logicist project, Frege developed predicate logic in the Begriffsschrift (English: Concept-script, 1879), which allowed a much greater range of sentences to be parsed into logical form than was possible using the ancient Aristotelian logic.[q] An example of this is the problem of multiple generality.

Number edit

Neo-Kantianism dominated the late 19th century in German philosophy. Edmund Husserl's 1891 book Philosophie der Arithmetik argued that the concept of the cardinal number derived from psychical acts of grouping objects and counting them.[32]

In contrast to this "psychologism," Frege in The Foundations of Arithmetic (1884) and The Basic Laws of Arithmetic (German: Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, 1893–1903), argued similar to Plato or Bolzano that mathematics and logic have their own public objects, independent of the private judgments or mental states of individual mathematicians and logicians. Following Frege, the logicists tended to advocate a kind of mathematical platonism.

Language edit

Frege also proved influential in the philosophy of language and analytic philosophy's interest in meaning.[33] Michael Dummett traces the linguistic turn to Frege's Foundations of Arithmetic and his context principle.[34]

Frege's paper On Sense and Reference (1892) is seminal, containing Frege's puzzles and providing a mediated reference theory. His paper The Thought: A Logical Inquiry (1918) reflects both his anti-idealism or anti-psychologism and his interest in language. In the paper he argues for a platonist account of propositions or thoughts.

Russell edit

 
Russell in 1907.

British philosophy in the 19th century had seen a revival of logic started by Richard Whately, in reaction to the anti-logical tradition of British empiricism. The major figure of this period is English mathematician George Boole. Other figures include William Hamilton, Augustus de Morgan, William Stanley Jevons, Alice's Adventures in Wonderland author Lewis Carroll,[r] Hugh MacColl, and American pragmatist Charles Sanders Peirce.[35]

British philosophy in the late 19th century was dominated by British idealism, a neo-Hegelian movement, as taught by philosophers such as F. H. Bradley (1846–1924) and T. H. Green (1836–1882).

Analytic philosophy in the narrower sense of 20th and 21st century anglophone philosophy is usually thought to begin with Cambridge philosophers Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore's rejection of Hegelianism for being obscure; or the "revolt against idealism"—see for example Moore's "A Defence of Common Sense".[36][s]

Paradox edit

Bertrand Russell, during his early career, was much influenced by Frege. Russell famously discovered the paradox in Basic Law V which undermined Frege's logicist project. However, like Frege, Russell argued that mathematics is reducible to logical fundamentals in The Principles of Mathematics (1903). He also argued for Meinongianism.[38]

On Denoting edit

Russell sought to resolve various philosophical problems by applying Frege's new logical apparatus, most famously in his theory of definite descriptions in "On Denoting", published in Mind in 1905.[39] Russell here argues against Meinongianism. He argues all names (aside from demonstratives like "this" or "that") are disguised definite descriptions, using this to solve ascriptions of nonexistence. This position came to be called descriptivism.

Principia Mathematica edit

Later, his book written with Alfred North Whitehead, Principia Mathematica (1910–1913), the seminal text of classical logic and of the logicist project, encouraged many philosophers to renew their interest in the development of symbolic logic. It used a notation from Italian logician Giuseppe Peano, and it uses a theory of types to avoid the pitfalls of Russell's paradox. Whitehead developed process metaphysics in Process and Reality.[40]

Ideal language edit

Additionally, Russell adopted Frege's predicate logic as his primary philosophical method, a method Russell thought could expose the underlying structure of philosophical problems. Logical form would be made clear by syntax. For example, the English word "is" has three distinct meanings which predicate logic can express as follows:

  • For the sentence 'the cat is asleep', the is of predication means that "x is P" (denoted as P(x)).
  • For the sentence 'there is a cat', the is of existence means that "there is an x" (∃x).
  • For the sentence 'three is half of six', the is of identity means that "x is the same as y" (x=y).

From about 1910 to 1930, analytic philosophers like Frege, Russell, Moore, and Russell's student Ludwig Wittgenstein emphasized creating an ideal language for philosophical analysis, which would be free from the ambiguities of ordinary language that, in their opinion, often made philosophy invalid. During this phase, they sought to understand language (and hence philosophical problems) by using logic to formalize how philosophical statements are made.

Logical atomism edit

 
Ludwig Wittgenstein

An important aspect of Hegelianism and British idealism was logical holism—the opinion that there are aspects of the world that can be known only by knowing the whole world. This is closely related to the doctrine of internal relations, the opinion that relations between items are internal relations, that is, essential properties of the nature of those items.

Russell and Moore in response promulgated logical atomism and the doctrine of external relations—the belief that the world consists of independent facts.[41][t] Inspired by developments in modern formal logic, the early Russell claimed that the problems of philosophy can be solved by showing the simple constituents of complex notions.[4]

Early Wittgenstein edit

Wittgenstein developed a comprehensive system of logical atomism with a picture theory of meaning in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (German: Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung, 1921) sometimes known as simply the Tractatus. He claimed the universe is the totality of actual states of affairs and that these states of affairs can be expressed and mirrored by the language of first-order predicate logic. Thus a picture of the universe can be constructed by expressing facts in the form of atomic propositions and linking them using logical operators.

Wittgenstein thought he had solved all the problems of philosophy with the Tractatus. The work further ultimately concludes all of its propositions are meaningless, illustrated with a ladder one must toss away after climbing up it.

Logical positivism edit

 
(1)
 
(2)
 
(3)
Members of the Vienna Circle. From left to right:
(1) Moritz Schlick
(2) Otto Neurath;
(3) Hans Hahn

During the late 1920s to 1940s, a group of philosophers known as the Vienna Circle, and another one known as the Berlin Circle, developed Russell and Wittgenstein's philosophy into a doctrine known as "logical positivism" (or logical empiricism). The Vienna Circle was led by Moritz Schlick and included Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath.[43] The Berlin Circle was led by Hans Reichenbach and included Carl Hempel and mathematician David Hilbert.

Logical positivists used formal logical methods to develop an empiricist account of knowledge.[44] They adopted the verification principle, according to which every meaningful statement is either analytic or synthetic. The truths of logic and mathematics were tautologies, and those of science were verifiable empirical claims. These two constituted the entire universe of meaningful judgments; anything else was nonsense.

This led the logical positivists to reject many traditional problems of philosophy, especially those of metaphysics, as meaningless. It had the additional effect of making (ethical and aesthetic) value judgments (as well as religious statements and beliefs) meaningless.

Logical positivists therefore typically considered philosophy as having a minimal function. For them, philosophy concerned the clarification of thoughts, rather than having a distinct subject matter of its own.

Several logical positivists were Jewish such as Neurath, Hans Hahn, Philipp Frank, Friedrich Waissmann, and Reichenbach. Others, like Carnap, were gentiles but socialists or pacifists. With the coming to power of Adolf Hitler and Nazism in 1933, many members of the Vienna and Berlin Circles fled to Britain and the USA, which helped to reinforce the dominance of logical positivism and analytic philosophy in anglophone countries.

In 1936, Schlick was murdered in Vienna by his former student Hans Nelböck. The same year, A. J. Ayer's work Language Truth and Logic introduced the English speaking world to logical positivism.[u]

The logical positivists saw their rejection of metaphysics in some ways as a recapitulation of a quote by David Hume:

"If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion."[45]

Ordinary language edit

After World War II, during the late 1940s and 1950s, analytic philosophy became involved with ordinary-language analysis. This resulted in two main trends.

Later Wittgenstein edit

One strain continued Wittgenstein's later philosophy from the Philosophical Investigations (1953), which differed dramatically from his early work of the Tractatus.[v] The criticisms of Frank P. Ramsey on color and logical form in the Tractatus led to some of Wittgenstein's first doubts with his early philosophy. Philosophers refer to them like two different philosophers: "early Wittgenstein" and "later Wittgenstein". In his later philosophy, Wittgenstein develops the concept of a "language-game" and rather than his prior picture theory of meaning, advocates a theory of meaning as use. It also contains the private language argument and the notion of family resemblance.

Oxford philosophy edit

The other trend, known as "Oxford philosophy" in contrast to earlier analytic Cambridge philosophers (including the early Wittgenstein) who thought philosophers should avoid the deceptive trappings of natural language by constructing ideal languages. Influenced by Moore's common sense and what they perceived as the later Wittgenstein's quietism, the Oxford philosophers claimed that ordinary language already represents many subtle distinctions not recognized in the formulation of traditional philosophical theories or problems.

 
Portrait of Gilbert Ryle

While schools such as logical positivism emphasize logical terms, supposed to be universal and separate from contingent factors (such as culture, language, historical conditions), ordinary-language philosophy emphasizes the use of language by ordinary people. The most prominent ordinary-language philosophers during the 1950s were P. F. Strawson, J. L. Austin and Gilbert Ryle.[47]

Ordinary-language philosophers often sought to dissolve philosophical problems by showing them to be the result of ordinary misunderstanding language. Ryle in The Concept of Mind (1949) criticized Cartesian dualism, arguing in favor of disposing "Descartes' myth" via recognizing "category errors".

Strawson first became well known with his article "On Referring" (1950), a criticism of Russell's theory of descriptions explained in the famous "On Denoting" article. In his book Individuals (1959), Strawson examines our conceptions of basic particulars. Austin in the posthumously published How to Do Things with Words (1962) emphasized the theory of speech acts and the ability of words to do things (e. g. "I promise") and not just say things. This influenced several fields in what is called the performative turn. In Sense and Sensibilia (1962), Austin criticized sense-data theories.

Spread of Analytic philosophy edit

Australia and New Zealand edit

The school known as Australian realism began when John Anderson accepted the Challis Chair of Philosophy at the University of Sydney in 1927. His elder brother was William Anderson, Professor of Philosophy at Auckland University College, 1921 to his death in 1955, and described as "the most dominant figure in New Zealand philosophy."[48] J. N. Findlay was a student of Ernst Mally of the Austrian realists and taught at the University of Otago.

Finland edit

The Finnish Georg Henrik von Wright succeeded Wittgenstein at Cambridge in 1948.[49]

Contemporary analytic philosophy edit

Metaphysics edit

One striking difference with respect to early analytic philosophy was the revival of metaphysical theorizing during the second half of the 20th century, and metaphysics remains a fertile topic of research. Although many discussions are continuations of old ones from previous decades and centuries, the debates remains active.[50]

Decline of logical positivism edit

The rise of metaphysics mirrored the decline in logical positivism, first challenged by the later Wittgenstein.

Sellars edit

Wilfred Sellars's "Myth of the Given" in "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind" (1956) challenged logical positivism by arguing against sense-data theories. In his "Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man" (1962), Sellars distinguishes between the "manifest image" and the "scientific image" of the world. Sellars's goal of a synoptic philosophy that unites the everyday and scientific views of reality is the foundation and archetype of what is sometimes called the Pittsburgh School, whose members include Robert Brandom, John McDowell, and John Haugeland.

Quine edit
 
W. V. O. Quine helped to undermine logical positivism.

Also among the developments that resulted in the decline of logical positivism and the revival of metaphysical theorizing was Harvard philosopher W. V. O. Quine's attack on the analytic–synthetic distinction in "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", published in 1951 in the Philosophical Review and republished in Quine's book From A Logical Point of View (1953), a paper "sometimes regarded as the most important in all of twentieth-century philosophy".[51][52][53]

From a Logical Point of View also contains Quine's essay On What There Is (1948) which elucidates Russell's theory of descriptions and contains Quine's famous dictum of ontological commitment, "To be is to be the value of a variable". He also dubbed the problem of nonexistence Plato's beard.

Quine sought to naturalize philosophy and saw philosophy as continuous with science, but instead of logical positivism advocated a kind of semantic holism and ontological relativity, which explained that every term in any statement has its meaning contingent on a vast network of knowledge and belief, the speaker's conception of the entire world. In his magnum opus Word and Object (1960), Quine introduces the idea of radical translation, an introduction to his theory of the indeterminacy of translation, and specifically to prove the inscrutability of reference.

Kripke edit
 
Saul Kripke helped to revive interest in metaphysics among analytic philosophers.

Important also for the revival of metaphysics was the further development of modal logic, first introduced by pragmatist C. I. Lewis, especially the work of Saul Kripke and his Naming and Necessity (1980).[w]

According to one author, Naming and Necessity "played a large role in the implicit, but widespread, rejection of the view—so popular among ordinary language philosophers—that philosophy is nothing more than the analysis of language."[54]

Kripke argued influentially that flaws in common theories of descriptions and proper names are indicative of larger misunderstandings of the metaphysics of necessity and possibility. Kripke also argued necessity is a metaphysical notion distinct from the epistemic notion of a priori, and that there are necessary truths that are known a posteriori, such as that water is H2O.[55]

Kripke is widely regarded as reviving theories of essence and identity as respectable topics of philosophical discussion.[55] Kripke and Hilary Putnam argued for realism about natural kinds. Kripke holds that it is essential that water is H2O, or for gold to be atomic number 79. Putnam's Twin Earth thought experiment can be used to illustrate the same point with water.[56]

David Lewis edit
 
David Lewis developed an elaborate metaphysics

American philosopher David Lewis defended a number of elaborate metaphysical theories. In works like On the Plurality of Worlds (1986) and Counterfactuals (1973) he argued for modal realism and counterpart theory – the belief in real, concrete possible worlds. According to Lewis, "actual" is merely an indexical label we give a world when we are in it. Lewis also defended what he called Humean supervenience, a counterfactual theory of causation,[57] and contributed to abstract object theory.[58] He became closely associated with Australia, whose philosophical community he visited almost annually for more than 30 years.

Universals edit

In response to the problem of universals, Australian David Malet Armstrong defended a kind of moderate realism.[59][60] Quine and Lewis defended nominalism.[58]

Mereology edit

Polish philosopher Stanisław Leśniewski coined the term mereology meaning the formal study of parts and wholes, a subject which arguably goes back to the time of the pre-Socratics.[61] David Lewis believed in perdurantism and introduced the term gunk. Peter Van Inwagen believes in mereological nihilism except for living beings, a view called organicism.

Free will and determinism edit

Peter van Inwagen's 1983 monograph An Essay on Free Will[62] played an important role in rehabilitating libertarianism with respect to free will in mainstream analytical philosophy.[63] In the book, he introduces the consequence argument and the term incompatibilism about free will and determinism, to stand in contrast to compatibilism—the view that free will is compatible with determinism. Charlie Broad had previously made similar arguments.

Personal identity edit

Since John Locke philosophers have been concerned with the issue of personal identity. Derek Parfit in Reasons and Persons (1984) defends a kind of bundle theory, while David Lewis again defends perdurantism. Bernard Williams in The Self and the Future (1970) argues personal identity is bodily identity rather than mental continuity.[64]

Principle of sufficient reason edit

Since Leibniz philosophers have discussed the principle of sufficient reason or PSR. Van Inwagen criticizes the PSR.[62] Alexander Pruss defends it.[65]

Philosophy of time edit

Analytic philosophy of time traces its roots to the British idealist J. M. E. McTaggart's article "The Unreality of Time" (1908). In it, McTaggart distinguishes between the dynamic, A theory of time or tensed theory of time (past, present, future) in which time flows; and the static or tenseless B theory of time (earlier than, simultaneous with, later than). Eternalism holds that past, present, and future are equally real while according to presentists, only entities in the present exist.[66]

The theory of special relativity seems to advocate a B theory of time. David Lewis's perdurantism or four-dimensionalism requires a B theory of time.[67] A. N. Prior, who invented tense logic, advocated the A-theory of time.

Logical pluralism edit

Many valued and nonclassical logics have been popular since Polish logician Jan Lukasiewicz. Graham Priest is a dialetheist, seeing it as the most natural solution to problems like the liar paradox. JC Beall, together with Greg Restall, is a pioneer of a widely discussed version of logical pluralism.[68]

Epistemology edit

Justification edit

Gettier edit
 
Edmund Gettier helped to revitalize analytic epistemology.

Owing largely to Edmund Gettier's 1963 paper "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?",[69] and so called Gettier problem, epistemology resurged as a topic of analytic philosophy during the last 50 years. A large portion of current epistemological research is intended to resolve the problems that Gettier's examples presented to the traditional "justified true belief" model of knowledge found as early as Plato's dialogue Theaetetus. These include developing theories of justification to deal with Gettier's examples, or giving alternatives to the justified true belief model.

Theories edit

Chisholm defended foundationalism. Quine defended coherentism, a "web of belief."[70] Quine proposed naturalized epistemology.

Internalism and externalism edit

The debate between internalism and externalism still exists in analytic philosophy.[71] Alvin Goldman is an externalist known for developing a popular form of externalism called reliabilism. Most externalists reject the KK thesis, which has been disputed since the introduction of the epistemic logic by Jaakko Hintikka in 1962.[72]

Problem of the Criterion edit

While a problem since antiquity, American philosopher Roderick Chisholm in his Theory of Knowledge details the problem of the criterion with two sets of questions:

  1. What do we know? or What is the extent of our knowledge?
  2. How do we know? or What is the criterion for deciding whether we have knowledge in any particular case?

An answer to either set of questions will allow us to devise a means of answering the other. Answering the former question set first is called particularism, whereas answering the latter set first is called methodism. A third solution is skepticism, or doubting there is such a thing as knowledge.

Truth edit

 
Alfred Tarski has an influential theory of truth.

Frege questioned standard theories of truth, and sometimes advocated a redundancy theory of truth. Frank Ramsey also advocated a redundancy theory. Alfred Tarski put forward a semantic theory of truth.[73][74]

In Truth-Makers (1984), Kevin Mulligan, Peter Simons and Barry Smith introduced the truth-maker idea as a contribution to the correspondence theory of truth.[75] A truth-maker is contrasted with a truth-bearer.

Closure edit

 
"Here is one hand"

Epistemic closure is the claim knowledge is closed under entailment; in other words epistemic closure is a property or the principle that if a subject   knows  , and   knows that   entails  , then   can thereby come to know  .[76] Most epistemological theories involve a closure principle and many skeptical arguments assume a closure principle. G. E. Moore's famous anti-skeptical "Here is one hand" in "Proof of An External World" argument uses closure. Shortly before his death, Wittgenstein wrote On Certainty in response to Moore.

While the principle of epistemic closure is generally regarded as intuitive,[77] philosophers such as Fred Dretske and Robert Nozick in Philosophical Explanations have argued against it.

Induction edit

 
All emeralds are "grue"

In his book Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, Nelson Goodman introduced the "new riddle of induction", so-called by analogy with Hume's classical problem of induction. Goodman's famous example was to introduce the predicates grue and bleen. "Grue" applies to all things before a certain time t just in case they are green, but also just in case they are blue after time t; and "bleen" applies before a certain time t just in the case they are blue, but also just in they are green after time t.

Other topics edit

Other and related topics of contemporary research include debates between basic knowledge, the nature of evidence, the value of knowledge, epistemic luck, virtue epistemology, the role of intuitions in justification, and treating knowledge as a primitive concept.

Ethics edit

Due to the commitments to empiricism and symbolic logic in the early analytic period, early analytic philosophers often thought that inquiry in the ethical domain could not be made rigorous enough to merit any attention.[78] It was only with the emergence of ordinary language philosophers that ethics started to become an acceptable area of inquiry for analytic philosophers.[78] Philosophers working with the analytic tradition have gradually come to distinguish three major types of moral philosophy.

  • Meta-ethics which investigates moral terms and concepts;[79]
  • Normative ethics which examines and produces normative ethical judgments;
  • Applied ethics, which investigates how existing normative principles should be applied to difficult or borderline cases, often cases created by new technology or new scientific knowledge.

Meta-ethics edit

As well as Hume's famous is/ought distinction, twentieth-century meta-ethics has two original strains.

Principia Ethica edit
 
G. E. Moore was an ethical non-naturalist.

The first is G.E. Moore's investigation into the nature of ethical terms (e.g., good) in his Principia Ethica (1903), which advances a kind of moral realism called ethical non-naturalism and is known for the open question argument and identifying the naturalistic fallacy, a major topic of investigation for analytical philosophers. According to G. E. Moore, "Goodness is a simple, undefinable, non-natural property."

Contemporary philosophers like Russ Shafer-Landau in Moral Realism: A Defence defend ethical non-naturalism.

Emotivism edit

The second is founded in logical positivism and its attitude that unverifiable statements are meaningless. As a result, they avoided normative ethics and instead began meta-ethical investigations into the nature of moral terms, statements, and judgments.

The logical positivists opined that statements about value—including all ethical and aesthetic judgments—are non-cognitive; that is, they cannot be objectively verified or falsified. Instead, the logical positivists adopted an emotivist theory, which was that value judgments expressed the attitude of the speaker. It is also known as the boo/hurrah theory. For example, in this view, saying, "Murder is wrong", is equivalent to saying, "Boo to murder", or saying the word "murder" with a particular tone of disapproval.

While analytic philosophers generally accepted non-cognitivism, emotivism had many deficiencies. It evolved into more sophisticated non-cognitivist theories such as the expressivism of Charles Stevenson, and the universal prescriptivism of R.M. Hare, which was based on J. L. Austin's philosophy of speech acts.

Critics edit
 
Philippa Foot was an ethical naturalist.

As non-cognitivism, the is/ought distinction, and the naturalistic fallacy were questioned, analytic philosophers showed a renewed interest in the traditional questions of moral philosophy.

Philippa Foot defended naturalist moral realism and contributed several essays attacking other theories.[x] Foot introduced the famous "trolley problem" into the ethical discourse.[80]

Perhaps the most influential critic was Elizabeth Anscombe, whose monograph Intention was called by Donald Davidson "the most important treatment of action since Aristotle".[81] A favorite student and friend of Ludwig Wittgenstein, her 1958 article "Modern Moral Philosophy" declared the "is-ought" impasse to be unproductive. J.O. Urmson's article "On Grading" also called the is/ought distinction into question.

Australian J. L. Mackie in Ethics: Inventing Right And Wrong defended anti-realist error theory. Bernard Williams also influenced ethics by advocating a kind of moral relativism rejecting all other theories.[82]

Normative ethics edit

The first half of the 20th century was marked by skepticism toward and neglect of normative ethics. However today, contemporary normative ethics is dominated by three schools: consequentialism, virtue ethics, and deontology.[y]

Consequentialism edit
Utilitarianism edit

During the early 20th century, utilitarianism was the only non-skeptical type of ethics to remain popular among analytic philosophers. However, as the influence of logical positivism declined mid-century, analytic philosophers had a renewed interest in ethics. Utilitarianism: For and Against was written with J. J. C. Smart arguing for and Bernard Williams arguing against.

Virtue ethics edit

Anscombe, Foot, and Alasdair Macintyre's After Virtue sparked a revival of Aristotle's virtue ethical approach. This increased interest in virtue ethics has been dubbed the "aretaic turn" mimicking the linguistic turn.

Deontology edit

John Rawls's 1971 A Theory of Justice restored interest in Kantian ethical philosophy.

Applied ethics edit

A significant feature of analytic philosophy since approximately 1970 has been the emergence of applied ethics—an interest in the application of moral principles to specific practical issues. The philosophers following this orientation view ethics as involving humanistic values, which involve practical implications and applications in the way people interact and lead their lives socially.[83]

Topics of special interest for applied ethics include environmental ethics, animal rights, and the many challenges created by advancing medical science.[84][85][86] In education, applied ethics addressed themes such as punishment in schools, equality of educational opportunity, and education for democracy.[87]

Political philosophy edit

Liberalism edit

 
John Rawls

Isaiah Berlin had a lasting influence on both analytic political philosophy and liberalism with his lecture "Two Concepts of Liberty."[citation needed] Berlin defined 'negative liberty' as absence of coercion or interference in private actions. 'Positive liberty' Berlin maintained, could be thought of as self-mastery, which asks not what we are free from, but what we are free to do.

Current analytic political philosophy owes much to John Rawls, who in a series of papers from the 1950s onward (most notably "Two Concepts of Rules" and "Justice as Fairness") and his 1971 book A Theory of Justice, produced a sophisticated defense of a generally liberal egalitarian account of distributive justice. Rawls introduced the term the veil of ignorance.

This was followed soon by Rawls's colleague Robert Nozick's book Anarchy, State, and Utopia, a defense of free-market libertarianism. Consequentialist libertarianism also derives from the analytic tradition [citation needed].

During recent decades there have also been several critics of liberalism, including the feminist critiques of Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin, the multiculturalist critiques of Amy Gutmann and Charles Taylor, and the communitarian critiques of Michael Sandel and Alasdair MacIntyre (although neither of them endorses the term).

Analytical Marxism edit

Another development of political philosophy was the emergence of the school of analytical Marxism. Members of this school seek to apply techniques of analytic philosophy and modern social science to clarify the theories of Karl Marx and his successors. The best-known member of this school is G. A. Cohen, whose 1978 work, Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defence, is generally considered to represent the genesis of this school. In that book, Cohen used logical and linguistic analysis to clarify and defend Marx's materialist conception of history. Other prominent analytical Marxists include the economist John Roemer, the social scientist Jon Elster, and the sociologist Erik Olin Wright. The work of these later philosophers have furthered Cohen's work by bringing to bear modern social science methods, such as rational choice theory, to supplement Cohen's use of analytic philosophical techniques in the interpretation of Marxian theory.

Cohen himself would later engage directly with Rawlsian political philosophy to advance a socialist theory of justice that contrasts with both traditional Marxism and the theories advanced by Rawls and Nozick. In particular, he indicates Marx's principle of from each according to his ability, to each according to his need.

Although not an analytic philosopher, Jürgen Habermas is another influential—if controversial—author in contemporary analytic political philosophy, whose social theory is a blend of social science, Marxism, neo-Kantianism, and American pragmatism.[citation needed]

Communitarianism edit

 
Alasdair MacIntyre

Communitarians such as Alasdair MacIntyre, Charles Taylor, Michael Walzer, and Michael Sandel advance a critique of liberalism that uses analytic techniques to isolate the main assumptions of liberal individualists, such as Rawls, and then challenges these assumptions. In particular, communitarians challenge the liberal assumption that the individual can be considered as fully autonomous from the community in which he lives and is brought up. Instead, they argue for a conception of the individual that emphasizes the role that the community plays in forming his or her values, thought processes and opinions. While in the analytic tradition, its major exponents often also engage at length with figures generally considered continental, notably G. W. F. Hegel and Friedrich Nietzsche.

Aesthetics edit

As a result of logical positivism as well as what seemed like rejections of the traditional aesthetic notions of beauty and sublimity from post-modern thinkers, analytic philosophers were slow to consider art and aesthetic judgment. Susanne Langer[88] and Nelson Goodman[89] addressed these problems in an analytic style during the 1950s and 1960s. Since Goodman, aesthetics as a discipline for analytic philosophers has flourished.[90]

Arthur Danto argued for a "institutional definition of art" in the 1964 essay "The Artworld" in which Danto coined the term "artworld" (as opposed to the existing "art world", though they mean the same), by which he meant cultural context or "an atmosphere of art theory",[91]

Rigorous efforts to pursue analyses of traditional aesthetic concepts were performed by Guy Sircello in the 1970s and 1980s, resulting in new analytic theories of love,[92] sublimity,[93] and beauty.[94] In the opinion of Władysław Tatarkiewicz, there are six conditions for the presentation of art: beauty, form, representation, reproduction of reality, artistic expression and innovation. However, one may not be able to pin down these qualities in a work of art.[95]

George Dickie was an influential philosopher of art. Dickie's student Noël Carroll is a leading philosopher of art.

Philosophy of language edit

Given the linguistic turn, it can be hard to separate logic, metaphysics, and the philosophy of language in analytic philosophy. Philosophy of language is a topic that has decreased in activity during the last four decades, as evidenced by the fact that few major philosophers today treat it as a primary research topic. While the debate remains fierce, it is still strongly influenced by those authors from the first half of the century e. g. Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Austin, Tarski, and Quine.

Semantics edit

Kripke provided a semantics for modal logic. In Saul Kripke's publication Naming and Necessity, Kripke challenges the descriptivist theory with a causal theory of reference. In it he introduced the term rigid designator. According to one author, "In the philosophy of language, Naming and Necessity is among the most important works ever."[54] Ruth Barcan Marcus also challenged descriptivism. So did Keith Donnellan.[96]

Hilary Putnam used the Twin Earth thought experiment to argue for semantic externalism, or the view that the meanings of words are not psychological. Donald Davidson uses the thought experiment of Swampman to advocate semantic externalism.

Kripke in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language provides a rule-following paradox that undermines the possibility of our ever following rules in our use of language and so calls into question the idea of meaning. Kripke writes that this paradox is "the most radical and original skeptical problem that philosophy has seen to date". The portmanteau "Kripkenstein" has been coined as a term for a fictional person who holds the views expressed by Kripke's reading of Wittgenstein.

Another influential philosopher, Pavel Tichý initiated Transparent Intensional Logic, an original theory of the logical analysis of natural languages—the theory is devoted to the problem of saying exactly what it is that we learn, know and can communicate when we come to understand what a sentence means.

Pragmatics edit

Paul Grice and his maxims and theory of implicature established the discipline of pragmatics.

Philosophy of mind and cognitive science edit

 
John Searle

John Searle suggests that the obsession with the philosophy of language during the 20th century has been superseded by an emphasis on the philosophy of mind.[97]

Physicalism edit

Motivated by the logical positivists' interest in verificationism, logical behaviorism was the most prominent theory of mind of analytic philosophy for the first half of the 20th century.[98] Behaviorism later became much less popular, in favor of either type physicalism or functionalism. During this period, topics of the philosophy of mind were often related strongly to topics of cognitive science such as modularity or innateness.

Behaviorism edit

Behaviorists like B. F. Skinner tended to opine either that statements about the mind were equivalent to statements about behavior and dispositions to behave in particular ways or that mental states were directly equivalent to behavior and dispositions to behave.

 
Hilary Putnam

Hilary Putnam criticized behaviorism by arguing that it confuses the symptoms of mental states with the mental states themselves, positing "super Spartans" who never display signs of pain.[99]

Type Identity edit

Type physicalism or type identity theory identified mental states with brain states. Former students of Ryle at the University of Adelaide J. J. C. Smart and Ullin Place argued for type physicalism.

Functionalism edit

Functionalism remains the dominant theory. Type identity was criticized using multiple realizability.

Searle's Chinese room argument criticized functionalism and holds that while a computer can understand syntax, it could never understand semantics.

Eliminativism edit

The view of eliminative materialism is most closely associated with the Paul and Patricia Churchland, who deny the existence of propositional attitudes, and with Daniel Dennett, who is generally considered an eliminativist about qualia and phenomenal aspects of consciousness.

Dualism edit

 
David Chalmers

Finally, analytic philosophy has featured a certain number of philosophers who were dualists, and recently forms of property dualism have had a resurgence; the most prominent representative is David Chalmers.[100] Kripke also has a notable argument for dualism.[101]

Thomas Nagel's "What is it like to be a bat?" challenged a physicalist account of mind. So did Frank Jackson's Knowledge argument, which argues for qualia.

Theories of consciousness edit

In recent years, a central focus of research in the philosophy of mind has been consciousness and the philosophy of perception. While there is a general consensus for the global neuronal workspace model of consciousness,[102] there are many opinions as to the specifics. The best known theories are Searle's naive realism, Fred Dretske and Michael Tye's representationalism, Daniel Dennett's heterophenomenology, and the higher-order theories of either David M. Rosenthal—who advocates a higher-order thought (HOT) model—or David Armstrong and William Lycan—who advocate a higher-order perception (HOP) model. An alternative higher-order theory, the higher-order global states (HOGS) model, is offered by Robert van Gulick.[103]

Philosophy of mathematics edit

 
Kurt Gödel

Since the beginning, analytic philosophy has had an interest in the philosophy of mathematics. Kurt Gödel, a student of Hans Hahn of the Vienna Circle, produced his incompleteness theorems showing Principia Mathematica also failed to reduce arithmetic to logic. Gödel has been ranked as one of the four greatest logicians of all time, along with Aristotle, Frege, and Tarski.[104] Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel established Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory. Quine developed his own system dubbed New Foundations.

Physicist Eugene Wigner's seminal paper the Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences poses the question why a formal pursuit like mathematics can have real utility.[105] José Benardete argued for the reality of infinity.[106]

Akin to the medieval debate on universals between realists, idealists and nominalists; philosophy of mathematics has the debate between logicists or platonists, conceptualists or intuitionists, and formalists.[107]

Platonism edit

Gödel was a platonist who postulated a special kind of mathematical intuition that lets us perceive mathematical objects directly. Quine and Putnam argued for platonism with the indispensability argument. Crispin Wright along with Bob Hale led a Neo-Fregean revival with his work Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects.[108]

Critics edit

Paul Benacerraf gives an epistemological objection to mathematical platonism. Benacerraf is a structuralist.

Intuitionism edit

The intuitionists were led by L. E. J. Brouwer, a constructivist school of mathematics which argues that math is a cognitive construct rather than a type of objective truth.

Formalism edit

The formalists were best exemplified by David Hilbert and considered mathematics to be merely the investigation of formal axiom systems. Hartry Field defended mathematical fictionalism.

Philosophy of religion edit

In Analytic Philosophy of Religion, James Franklin Harris noted that

analytic philosophy has been a very heterogeneous 'movement'.... some forms of analytic philosophy have proven very sympathetic to the philosophy of religion and have provided a philosophical mechanism for responding to other more radical and hostile forms of analytic philosophy.[109]: 3 

As with the study of ethics, early analytic philosophy tended to avoid the study of philosophy of religion, largely dismissing (as per the logical positivists) the subject as part of metaphysics and therefore meaningless.[z] The demise of logical positivism renewed interest in philosophy of religion, prompting philosophers not only to introduce new problems, but to re-study classical topics such as the existence of God, the nature of miracles, the problem of evil, the rationality of belief in God, concepts of the nature of God, and several others.[110] The Society of Christian Philosophers was established in 1978.

Reformed epistemology edit

Analytic philosophy formed the basis for some sophisticated Christian arguments, such as those of the reformed epistemologists like Alvin Plantinga, William Alston, and Nicholas Wolterstorff.

 
Alvin Plantinga

Plantinga was awarded the Templeton Prize in 2017 and was once described by Time magazine as "America's leading orthodox Protestant philosopher of God".[111] His seminal work God and Other Minds (1967) argues that belief in God is a properly basic belief akin to the belief in other minds. Plantinga also developed a modal ontological argument in The Nature of Necessity (1974).

Plantinga, J. L. Mackie and Antony Flew debated the use of the free will defense as a way to solve the problem of evil.[112] Plantinga's evolutionary argument against naturalism contends a skeptical problem with asserting both evolution and naturalism. Plantinga further issued a trilogy on epistemology and especially justification, Warrant: The Current Debate, Warrant and Proper Function, and Warranted Christian Belief.

Alston defended divine command theory and applied analytic philosophy of language to religious language. Robert Merrihew Adams also defended divine command theory, and worked on the relationship of faith and morality.[113] William Lane Craig defends the Kalam cosmological argument in the book of the same name.

Analytic Thomism edit

Catholic philosophers in the analytic tradition such as Elizabeth Anscombe, Peter Geach, Anthony Kenny, Alasdair MacIntyre, John Haldane, Eleonore Stump, and others developed an analytic approach to Thomism.

Orthodox edit

Richard Swinburne wrote a trilogy of books arguing for God consisting of The Coherence of Theism, The Existence of God, and Faith and Reason.

Wittgenstein and religion edit

Analytic philosophy of religion has been preoccupied with Wittgenstein, as well as his interpretation of Søren Kierkegaard's philosophy of religion.[114] Wittgenstein fought for the Austrian army in the First World War and came upon a copy of Leo Tolstoy's Gospel in Brief. At this time, he underwent some kind of religious conversion.[115]

Using first-hand remarks (which was later published in Philosophical Investigations, Culture and Value, and other works), philosophers such as Peter Winch and Norman Malcolm developed what has come to be known as contemplative philosophy, a Wittgensteinian school of thought rooted in the "Swansea school", and which includes Wittgensteinians such as Rush Rhees, Peter Winch, and D.Z. Phillips, among others.

The name "contemplative philosophy" was coined by D.Z. Phillips in Philosophy's Cool Place, which rests on an interpretation of a passage from Wittgenstein's Culture and Value.[116] This interpretation was first labeled "Wittgensteinian Fideism" by Kai Nielsen, but those who consider themselves members of the Swansea school have relentlessly and repeatedly rejected this construal as a caricature of Wittgenstein's position; this is especially true of D.Z. Phillips.[117] Responding to this interpretation, Kai Nielsen and D.Z. Phillips became two of the most prominent philosophers on Wittgenstein's philosophy of religion.[118]

Philosophy of science edit

Science and the philosophy of science has also had an increasingly significant role in analytic metaphysics. The theory of special relativity has had a profound effect on the philosophy of time, and quantum physics is routinely discussed in the free will debate.[50] The weight given to scientific evidence is largely due to commitments among philosophers to scientific realism and naturalism. Others will see a commitment to using science in philosophy as scientism.

Confirmation theory edit

Carl Hempel advocated confirmation theory or Bayesian epistemology. He introduced the famous raven's paradox.[119]

Falsification edit

 
Karl Popper

In reaction to what he considered excesses of logical positivism, Karl Popper in The Logic of Scientific Discovery insisted on the role of falsification in the philosophy of science, using it to solve the demarcation problem.[120]

Confirmation holism edit

The Duhem-Quine thesis or problem of underdetermination posits no scientific hypothesis can be understood in isolation, a viewpoint called confirmation holism.[51]

Constructivism edit

In reaction to both the logical positivists and Popper, discussions of philosophy of science during the last 40 years were dominated by social constructivist and cognitive relativist theories of science. Following Quine and Duhem, subsequent theories emphasized theory-ladenness. Thomas Samuel Kuhn with his formulation of paradigm shifts and Paul Feyerabend with his epistemological anarchism are significant for these discussions.[121]

Biology edit

The philosophy of biology has also undergone considerable growth, particularly due to the considerable debate in recent years over the nature of evolution, particularly natural selection.[122] Daniel Dennett and his 1995 book Darwin's Dangerous Idea, which defends Neo-Darwinism, stand at the foreground of this debate.[123] Jerry Fodor criticizes natural selection.

Notes edit

  1. ^ A.P. Martinich draws an analogy between analytic philosophy and analytic chemistry, which aims to determine chemical compositions.[1]
  2. ^ "Without exception, the best philosophy departments in the United States are dominated by analytic philosophy, and among the leading philosophers in the United States, all but a tiny handful would be classified as analytic philosophers. Practitioners of types of philosophizing that are not in the analytic tradition—such as phenomenology, classical pragmatism, existentialism, or Marxism—feel it necessary to define their position in relation to analytic philosophy."[2]
  3. ^ Quote on the definition: "'Analytic' philosophy today names a style of doing philosophy, not a philosophical program or a set of substantive views. Analytic philosophers, crudely speaking, aim for argumentative clarity and precision; draw freely on the tools of logic; and often identify, professionally and intellectually, more closely with the sciences and mathematics, than with the humanities."[5]
  4. ^ "analytical philosophy [is] too narrow a label, since [it] is not generally a matter of taking a word or concept and analyzing it (whatever exactly that might be). [...] This tradition emphasizes clarity, rigor, argument, theory, truth. It is not a tradition that aims primarily for inspiration or consolation or ideology. Nor is it particularly concerned with 'philosophy of life', though parts of it are. This kind of philosophy is more like science than religion, more like mathematics than poetry—though it is neither science nor mathematics."[6]
  5. ^ According to Scott Soames, "an implicit commitment—albeit faltering and imperfect—to the ideals of clarity, rigor and argumentation" and it "aims at truth and knowledge, as opposed to moral or spiritual improvement [...] the goal in analytic philosophy is to discover what is true, not to provide a useful recipe for living one's life". Soames also states that analytic philosophy is characterized by "a more piecemeal approach. There is, I think, a widespread presumption within the tradition that it is often possible to make philosophical progress by intensively investigating a small, circumscribed range of philosophical issues while holding broader, systematic questions in abeyance".[7]
  6. ^ "[I]t is difficult to give a precise definition of 'analytic philosophy' since it is not so much a specific doctrine as a loose concatenation of approaches to problems."[9]
  7. ^ "I think Sluga is right in saying 'it may be hopeless to try to determine the essence of analytic philosophy.' Nearly every proposed definition has been challenged by some scholar. [...] [W]e are dealing with a family resemblance concept."[10]
  8. ^ "The answer to the title question, then, is that analytic philosophy is a tradition held together both by ties of mutual influence and by family resemblances."[11]
  9. ^ The 1950s saw challenges to much which had been taken for granted, and roughly by 1960 anglophone philosophy began to incorporate a wider range of interests, opinions, and methods.[16] Despite this, most philosophers in Britain and America still consider themselves "analytic philosophers".[5] They have done so largely by expanding the notion of "analytic philosophy" from the specific programs that dominated anglophone philosophy before 1960 to a much more general notion of an "analytic" style,[5][16] characterized by mathematical precision and thoroughness about a specific topic, and resistance to "imprecise or cavalier discussions of broad topics".[16]
  10. ^ "Most non-analytic philosophers of the twentieth century do not belong to continental philosophy."[17]
  11. ^ The distinction rests upon a confusion of geographical and methodological terms, as if one were to classify cars into front-wheel drive and Japanese. [...] the distinction between analytic and Continental philosophy rests upon a confused comparison of methodological and geographical categories.[18]
  12. ^ "Analytic philosophy is mainly associated with the contemporary English-speaking world, but it is by no means the only important philosophical tradition. In this volume two other immensely rich and important such traditions are introduced: Indian philosophy, and philosophical thought in Europe from the time of Hegel."[19]
  13. ^ "So, despite a few overlaps, analytical philosophy is not difficult to distinguish broadly [...] from other modern movements, like phenomenology, say, or existentialism, or from the large amount of philosophizing that has also gone on in the present century within frameworks deriving from other influential thinkers like Aquinas, Hegel, or Marx."[20]
  14. ^ Steven D. Hales described analytic philosophy as one of three types of philosophical method practiced in the West: "[i]n roughly reverse order by number of proponents, they are phenomenology, ideological philosophy, and analytic philosophy".[21]
  15. ^ "The distinction which Russell sets up between 'technical' philosophy and 'literary' philosophy has had many incarnations, from Plato's 'ancient quarrel between poetry and philosophy'..."[24]
  16. ^ The tradition has also been criticized for excessive formalism, ahistoricism, and aloofness towards alternative disciplines and outsiders.[25][26][27] Some have tried to develop a postanalytic philosophy.
  17. ^ It has recently been argued Frege plagiarized Stoic logic.[31]
  18. ^ Carroll's paper "What The Tortoise Said To Achilles" humorously shows an infinite regress paradox at the heart of logic.
  19. ^ "Analytic philosophy opposed right from its beginning English neo-Hegelianism of Bradley's sort and similar ones. It did not only criticize the latter's denial of the existence of an external world (anyway an unjust criticism), but also the bombastic, obscure style of Hegel's writings."[37]
  20. ^ Russell once explained "Hegel had maintained that all separateness is illusory and that the universe is more like a pot of treacle than a heap of shot. I therefore said, "The universe is exactly like a heap of shot."[42]
  21. ^ Named in reference to Waismann's Logik, Sprache, Philosophie
  22. ^ A survey among American university and college teachers ranked the Investigations as the most important philosophical book of the 20th century.[46]
  23. ^ Named in reference to Carnap's Meaning and Necessity.
  24. ^ Foot was the granddaughter of former US President Grover Cleveland.
  25. ^ Anscombe introduced the term "consequentialism" into the philosophical lexicon.
  26. ^ A notable exception is the series of Michael B. Foster's 1934–36 Mind articles involving the Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern science.

References edit

  1. ^ "A Companion to Analytic Philosophy".
  2. ^ John Searle (2003), Contemporary Philosophy in the United States in N. Bunnin and E. P. Tsui-James (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, 2nd ed., (Blackwell, 2003), p. 1.
  3. ^ Glock, H.J. (2004). "Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher?". Metaphilosophy. 35 (4): 419–444. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.2004.00329.x.
  4. ^ a b Mautner, Thomas (editor) (2005) The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, entry for "Analytic philosophy", pp. 22–23
  5. ^ a b c Brian Leiter (2006) webpage
  6. ^ Colin McGinn, The Making of a Philosopher: My Journey through Twentieth-Century Philosophy (HarperCollins, 2002), p. xi.
  7. ^ Soames, Scott (2003). The dawn of analysis (2nd print., 1st papers. print ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press. pp. xiii–xvii. ISBN 978-0-691-11573-3.
  8. ^ Dummett 1993, p. 4, 22
  9. ^ See, e.g., Avrum Stroll, Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy (Columbia University Press, 2000), p. 5
  10. ^ see Stroll (2000), p. 7
  11. ^ See Hans-Johann Glock, What Is Analytic Philosophy? (Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 205
  12. ^ Koopman, Colin. "Bernard Williams on Philosophy's Need for History" (PDF). pages.uoregon.edu. Retrieved 1 March 2022.
  13. ^ Vienne, J.M. (1997). Philosophie analytique et histoire de la philosophie: actes du colloque (Université de Nantes, 1991). Problèmes et controverses (in French). J. Vrin. p. 140. ISBN 978-2-7116-1312-0. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  14. ^ Luft, S. (2019). Philosophie lehren: Ein Buch zur philosophischen Hochschuldidaktik (in German). Felix Meiner Verlag. p. 258. ISBN 978-3-7873-3766-8. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  15. ^ Glock, H.J. (2008). What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge University Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-521-87267-6. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  16. ^ a b c "Analytic Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Iep.utm.edu. from the original on 3 July 2009. Retrieved 13 April 2018.
  17. ^ H.-J. Glock, What Is Analytic Philosophy? (Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 86
  18. ^ Critchley, Simon (2001). Continental philosophy a very short introduction. Oxford University Press. OCLC 1200924441.
  19. ^ A.C. Grayling (ed.), Philosophy 2: Further through the Subject (Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 2
  20. ^ L.J. Cohen, The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 5:
  21. ^ Hales, Steven D. (2002). Analytic philosophy : classic readings. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thomson Learning. pp. 1–10. ISBN 978-0-534-51277-4.
  22. ^ Rinofner-Kreidl, S.; Wiltsche, H.A. (2016). Analytic and Continental Philosophy: Methods and Perspectives. Proceedings of the 37th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society – New Series. De Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-044887-0. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  23. ^ Glock, H.J. (2008). What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-87267-6. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  24. ^ Luchte, James (3 November 2011). Nietzsche's Thus Spoke Zarathustra: Before Sunrise. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4411-1845-5.
  25. ^ Glock, H.J. (2008). What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge University Press. p. 231. ISBN 978-0-521-87267-6. Retrieved 28 August 2023.
  26. ^ Akehurst, Thomas L. (1 March 2009). "Writing history for the ahistorical: Analytic philosophy and its past". History of European Ideas. 35 (1): 116–121. doi:10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2008.09.002. ISSN 0191-6599. S2CID 143566283.
  27. ^ Beaney, Michael (20 June 2013). Beaney, Michael (ed.). "The Historiography of Analytic Philosophy". The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199238842.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-923884-2. Retrieved 18 February 2022.
  28. ^ Dummett 1993, p. 2
  29. ^ Dummett 1993, p. 28
  30. ^ Everett, Anthony and Thomas Hofweber (eds.) (2000), Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-Existence.
  31. ^ Bobzien, Susanne (2021). Frege plagiarized the Stoics. In Fiona Leigh (ed.), Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy, Keeling Lectures 2011–2018, OPEN ACCESS. University of Chicago Press. pp. 149–206.
  32. ^ Willard, Dallas (1980). "Husserl on a Logic that Failed". Philosophical Review. 89 (1): 52–53. doi:10.2307/2184863. JSTOR 2184863.
  33. ^ Jeff Speaks, "Frege's theory of reference" (2011)
  34. ^ Dummett 1993, p. 5
  35. ^ "History of Logic", by Arthur Prior, Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) p. 541
  36. ^ Michael Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2013, p. 383.
  37. ^ Jonkers, Peter (2003). "Perspectives on Twentieth Century Philosophy: A Reply to Tom Rockmore". Ars Disputandi. 3. doi:10.1080/15665399.2003.10819802. ISSN 1566-5399. S2CID 70060684.
  38. ^ p. 449
  39. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1905). "On Denoting". Mind. 14: 473–493. from the original on 31 March 2006.
  40. ^
  41. ^ Baillie, James, "Introduction to Bertrand Russell" in Contemporary Analytic Philosophy, Second Edition (Prentice Hall, 1997), p. 25.
  42. ^ Ryan, Alan. Bertrand Russell: A Political Life. United States, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1981. p. 23
  43. ^ "Savants Move to Abandon Metaphysical Philosophy". Baltimore Sun. 31 December 1935.
  44. ^ Carnap, R. (1928). The Logical Structure of the World. Felix Meiner Verlag. ISBN 978-0-8126-9523-6. LCCN 66013604.
  45. ^ An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748) sect. 12, pt. 3
  46. ^ Lackey, Douglas P. (1999). "What Are the Modern Classics? The Baruch Poll of Great Philosophy in the Twentieth Century". The Philosophical Forum. 30 (4): 329–346. doi:10.1111/0031-806X.00022. ISSN 1467-9191.
  47. ^ Longworth, Guy (2017), "John Langshaw Austin", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 21 July 2020
  48. ^ Weblin, Mark "Idealism in Australia and New Zealand" The Northern Line No. 3 May 2007, p 6. Retrieved 17 January 2011
  49. ^ Hacker, P. M. S. (4 July 2003). "Obituary: Georg Henrik von Wright". The Guardian. Retrieved 5 July 2020.
  50. ^ a b Van Inwagen, Peter, and Dean Zimmerman (eds.) (1998), Metaphysics: The Big Questions.
  51. ^ a b Quine, W. V. O. (1951). "Two Dogmas of Empiricism". The Philosophical Review. 60 (1): 20–43. doi:10.2307/2181906. JSTOR 2181906. Reprinted in his 1953 From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press.
  52. ^ S. Yablo and A. Gallois, Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 72, (1998), pp. 229–261, 263–283 first part 12 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine
  53. ^ Peter Godfrey-Smith, Theory and Reality, 2003, University of Chicago, ISBN 0-226-30062-5, pages 30–33 (section 2.4 "Problems and Changes")
  54. ^ a b Soames, Scott. 2005. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume 2: The Age of Meaning. Princeton University Press. Cited in Byrne, Alex and Hall, Ned. 2004. 'Necessary Truths'. Boston Review October/November 2004.
  55. ^ a b Zimmerman, Dean W., "Prologue" in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1 (Oxford University Press, 2004), p. xix.
  56. ^ Bird, Alexander; Tobin, Emma (2024), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Natural Kinds", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 22 April 2024
  57. ^ Hitchcock, Christopher (6 March 2015), "Lewis on Causation", A Companion to David Lewis, Oxford, UK: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, pp. 295–311, doi:10.1002/9781118398593.ch19, ISBN 978-1-118-39859-3
  58. ^ a b Lewis, David (March 1986). "Against structural universals". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 64 (1): 25–46. doi:10.1080/00048408612342211. ISSN 0004-8402.
  59. ^ Jackson, Frank (2016), "Armstrong, David Malet (1926–2014)", Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1 ed.), London: Routledge, doi:10.4324/9780415249126-v035-1, ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6, retrieved 21 July 2020
  60. ^ Armstrong, David Malet (1995). Universals and scientific realism. Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 0-521-28033-8. OCLC 174240749.
  61. ^ Cotnoir, A. J., and Varzi, Achille C.. Mereology. United Kingdom, OUP Oxford, 2021. p. 2
  62. ^ a b van Inwagen 1983.
  63. ^ Kane 2005, p. 23.
  64. ^ Identity, Personal Identity, and the Self. p. 103.
  65. ^ Pruss, "Leibnizian Cosmological Arguments"
  66. ^ Loux & Crisp 2017, pp. 206, 214–215
  67. ^ Personal Identity and Resurrection
  68. ^ "Logical Pluralism". global.oup.com. Retrieved 5 February 2017.
  69. ^ Gettier, Edmund (15 July 2020), "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?" (PDF), Arguing About Knowledge, Routledge, pp. 14–15, doi:10.4324/9781003061038-5, ISBN 978-1-003-06103-8, S2CID 243290967
  70. ^ The Web of Belief
  71. ^ Bonjour, Laurence, "Recent Work on the Internalism–Externalism Controversy" in Dancy, Sosa, and Steup (eds.), A Companion to Epistemology, Second Edition (Wiley-Blackwell, 2010), p. 33.
  72. ^ Rahman, Shahid; Symons, John; Gabbay, Dov M.; bendegem, jean paul van (2009). Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media. p. 92. ISBN 978-1-4020-2807-6.
  73. ^ Vaught, Robert L. (December 1986). "Alfred Tarski's Work in Model Theory". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 51 (4). ASL: 869–882. doi:10.2307/2273900. JSTOR 2273900.
  74. ^ Feferman & Feferman, p. 1
  75. ^ Mulligan, Kevin; Simons, Peter; Smith, Barry (1984). "Truth-Makers". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 44 (3): 287–321. doi:10.2307/2107686. JSTOR 2107686.
  76. ^ Luper, Steven (31 December 2001). "Epistemic Closure". The Epistemic Closure Principle. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  77. ^ Brady, Michael; Pritchard, Duncan (2005). "Epistemological Contextualism: Problems and Prospects". The Philosophical Quarterly. 55 (219): 161–171. doi:10.1111/j.0031-8094.2005.00393.x.
  78. ^ a b Schwartz, Stephen P. (2012). A Brief History of Analytic Philosophy: From Russell to Rawls. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-27172-8.
  79. ^ Kuusela, Oskari (2011). Key Terms in Ethics. London: Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 61. ISBN 978-1-4411-6610-4.
  80. ^ Philippa Foot, The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect 24 August 2019 at the Wayback Machine in Virtues and Vices (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978) (originally in the Oxford Review, No. 5, 1967).
  81. ^ From the cover of the 2000 Harvard University Press edition of Intention.
  82. ^ Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
  83. ^ Ikuenobe, Polycarp (2006). Philosophical Perspectives on Communalism and Morality in African Traditions. Oxford: Lexington Books. p. 104. ISBN 978-0-7391-1131-4.
  84. ^ Brennan, Andrew and Yeuk-Sze Lo (2002). "Environmental Ethics" §2 1 August 2013 at the Wayback Machine, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  85. ^ Gruen, Lori (2003). "The Moral Status of Animals," in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  86. ^ See Hursthouse, Rosalind (2003). "Virtue Ethics" §3, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and Donchin, Anne (2004). "Feminist Bioethics" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  87. ^ Heyting, Frieda; Lenzen, Dieter; White, John (2002). Methods in Philosophy of Education. New York: Routledge. pp. 18. ISBN 978-0-415-24260-8.
  88. ^ Susanne Langer, Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art (1953)
  89. ^ Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1968. 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1976. Based on his 1960–61 John Locke lectures.
  90. ^ Kivy, Peter, "Introduction: Aesthetics Today" in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics (Blackwell Publishing, 2004), p. 4.
  91. ^ Adajian, Thomas. "The Definition of Art", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London, Oct 23, 2007.
  92. ^ Guy Sircello, Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
  93. ^ Guy Sircello "How Is a Theory of the Sublime Possible?" The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn, 1993), pp. 541–550
  94. ^ Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.
  95. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Władysław (1980). A History of Six Ideas: an essay in aesthetics. PWN/Polish Scientific Publishers. ISBN 978-8301008246.
  96. ^ Keith Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions,”
  97. ^ Postrel and Feser, February 2000, Reality Principles: An Interview with John R. Searle at . February 2000. Archived from the original on 29 September 2008. Retrieved 23 September 2008.
  98. ^ Graham, George, "Behaviorism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). [1]
  99. ^ Brains and Behavior, Hilary Putnam
  100. ^ Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Dualism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  101. ^ "Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body". www3.nd.edu. Retrieved 22 April 2024.
  102. ^ Dennett, D. (2001). "Are we explaining consciousness yet?". Cognition. 79 (1–2): 221–237. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00130-X. PMID 11164029. S2CID 2235514.
  103. ^ For summaries and some criticism of the different higher-order theories, see Van Gulick, Robert (2006) "Mirror Mirror – Is That All?" In Kriegel & Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. The final draft is also available here (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2 October 2008. Retrieved 23 September 2008.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link). For Van Gulick's own view, see Van Gulick, Robert. "Higher-Order Global States HOGS: An Alternative Higher-Order Model of Consciousness." In Gennaro, R.J., (ed.) Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
  104. ^ Restall, Greg (2002–2006). "Great Moments in Logic". from the original on 6 December 2008. Retrieved 3 January 2009.
  105. ^ Wigner, E. P. (1960). . Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics. 13 (1): 1–14. Bibcode:1960CPAM...13....1W. doi:10.1002/cpa.3160130102. S2CID 6112252. Archived from the original on 12 February 2021.
  106. ^ Infinity: An Essay In Metaphysics
  107. ^ Quine, On What There Is
  108. ^ The Reason's Proper Study: Essays Towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics
  109. ^ Harris, James Franklin (2002). Analytic philosophy of religion. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ISBN 978-1-4020-0530-5. (432 pages) (volume 3 of Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, ISSN 1568-1556)
  110. ^ Peterson, Michael et al. (2003). Reason and Religious Belief
  111. ^ . Archived from the original on 31 August 2013.
  112. ^ Mackie, John L. (1982). The Miracle of Theism: Arguments For and Against the Existence of God
  113. ^ Adams, Robert M. (1987). The Virtue of Faith And Other Essays in Philosophical Theology
  114. ^ Creegan, Charles. (1989). Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard: Religion, Individuality and Philosophical Method
  115. ^ "Wittgenstein Tolstoy and the Gospel in Brief (2001)". Retrieved 11 April 2024.
  116. ^ Phillips, D.Z. (1999). Philosophy's Cool Place. Cornell University Press. The quote is from Wittgenstein's Culture and Value (2e): "My ideal is a certain coolness. A temple providing a setting for the passions without meddling with them.
  117. ^ Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Fideism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  118. ^ Nielsen, Kai and D.Z. Phillips. (2005). Wittgensteinian Fideism?
  119. ^ Fitelson, Branden; Hawthorne, James (2010). "How Bayesian Confirmation Theory Handles the Paradox of the Ravens". The Place of Probability in Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 284. Springer. pp. 247–275. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-3615-5_11. ISBN 978-90-481-3614-8.
  120. ^ Popper, Karl R. (2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7.
  121. ^ Glock 2008, p. 47.
  122. ^ Hull, David L. and Ruse, Michael, "Preface" in The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology (Cambridge University Press, 2007), pp. xix, xx.
  123. ^ Lennox, James G., "Darwinism and Neo-Darwinism" in Sakar and Plutynski (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology (Blackwell Publishing, 2008), p. 89.

Books and articles edit

  • Aristotle, Metaphysics
  • Desmet, Ronald; Irvine, Andrew David (2022). "Alfred North Whitehead". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 April 2024.
  • Dummett, Michael (1993). The Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Geach, P., Mental Acts, London 1957
  • Kane, Robert (2005). A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-514970-8. Retrieved 13 April 2020.
  • Kenny, A.J.P., Wittgenstein, London 1973.
  • Loux, Michael J.; Crisp, Thomas M. (2017). Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction (4 ed.). Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-63933-1.
  • Palmer, Clare (1998). Environmental Ethics and Process Thinking. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-826952-6. from the original on 2 April 2024. Retrieved 4 April 2024.
  • Aaron Preston. "Analytic philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Soames, Scott. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume 1, The Dawn of Analysis. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003.
  • van Inwagen, Peter (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824924-5. Retrieved 27 December 2012.
  • Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus

Further reading edit

  • The London Philosophy Study Guide 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject: Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein
  • Hirschberger, Johannes. A Short History of Western Philosophy, ed. Clare Hay. . ISBN 978-0-7188-3092-2
  • Hylton, Peter. Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.
  • Passmore, John. A Hundred Years of Philosophy, revised ed. New York: Basic Books, 1966.
  • Weitz, Morris, ed. Twentieth Century Philosophy: The Analytic Tradition. New York: Free Press, 1966.

External links edit

analytic, philosophy, broad, contemporary, movement, tradition, within, western, philosophy, especially, anglophone, philosophy, focused, analysis, characterized, style, clarity, prose, rigor, arguments, making, formal, logic, mathematics, lesser, degree, natu. Analytic philosophy is a broad contemporary movement or tradition within Western philosophy and especially anglophone philosophy focused on analysis a b Analytic philosophy is characterized by a style of clarity of prose and rigor in arguments making use of formal logic and mathematics and to a lesser degree the natural sciences 3 4 c d e It is further characterized by an interest in language and meaning known as the linguistic turn 8 f g h It has developed several new branches of philosophy and logic notably philosophy of language philosophy of mathematics philosophy of science modern predicate logic and mathematical logic 12 The proliferation of analysis in philosophy began around the turn of the 20th century and has been dominant since the latter half of the 20th century 13 14 15 i Central figures in its historical development are Gottlob Frege Bertrand Russell G E Moore and Ludwig Wittgenstein Other important figures in its history include Franz Brentano the logical positivists particularly Rudolf Carnap the ordinary language philosophers W V O Quine and Karl Popper After the decline of logical positivism Saul Kripke David Lewis and others led a revival in metaphysics Analytic philosophy is often contrasted with continental philosophy j coined as a catch all term for other methods prominent in continental Europe k most notably existentialism phenomenology and Hegelianism l m n There is widespread influence and debate between the analytic and continental traditions some philosophers see the differences between the two traditions as being based on institutions relationships and ideology rather than anything of significant philosophical substance 22 23 The distinction has also been drawn as analytic is academic or technical philosophy while continental is literary philosophy o p Contents 1 History of analytic philosophy 1 1 Austrian realism 1 1 1 Brentano 1 1 2 Meinong 1 1 3 Lwow Warsaw 1 2 Frege 1 2 1 Logic 1 2 2 Number 1 2 3 Language 1 3 Russell 1 3 1 Paradox 1 3 2 On Denoting 1 3 3 Principia Mathematica 1 4 Ideal language 1 4 1 Logical atomism 1 4 1 1 Early Wittgenstein 1 4 2 Logical positivism 1 5 Ordinary language 1 5 1 Later Wittgenstein 1 5 2 Oxford philosophy 1 6 Spread of Analytic philosophy 1 6 1 Australia and New Zealand 1 6 2 Finland 2 Contemporary analytic philosophy 2 1 Metaphysics 2 1 1 Decline of logical positivism 2 1 1 1 Sellars 2 1 1 2 Quine 2 1 1 3 Kripke 2 1 1 4 David Lewis 2 1 2 Universals 2 1 3 Mereology 2 1 4 Free will and determinism 2 1 5 Personal identity 2 1 6 Principle of sufficient reason 2 1 7 Philosophy of time 2 1 8 Logical pluralism 2 2 Epistemology 2 2 1 Justification 2 2 1 1 Gettier 2 2 1 2 Theories 2 2 1 2 1 Internalism and externalism 2 2 2 Problem of the Criterion 2 2 3 Truth 2 2 4 Closure 2 2 5 Induction 2 2 6 Other topics 2 3 Ethics 2 3 1 Meta ethics 2 3 1 1 Principia Ethica 2 3 1 2 Emotivism 2 3 1 3 Critics 2 3 2 Normative ethics 2 3 2 1 Consequentialism 2 3 2 1 1 Utilitarianism 2 3 2 2 Virtue ethics 2 3 2 3 Deontology 2 3 3 Applied ethics 2 4 Political philosophy 2 4 1 Liberalism 2 4 2 Analytical Marxism 2 4 3 Communitarianism 2 5 Aesthetics 2 6 Philosophy of language 2 6 1 Semantics 2 6 2 Pragmatics 2 7 Philosophy of mind and cognitive science 2 7 1 Physicalism 2 7 1 1 Behaviorism 2 7 1 2 Type Identity 2 7 1 3 Functionalism 2 7 1 4 Eliminativism 2 7 2 Dualism 2 7 3 Theories of consciousness 2 8 Philosophy of mathematics 2 8 1 Platonism 2 8 1 1 Critics 2 8 2 Intuitionism 2 8 3 Formalism 2 9 Philosophy of religion 2 9 1 Reformed epistemology 2 9 2 Analytic Thomism 2 9 3 Orthodox 2 9 4 Wittgenstein and religion 2 10 Philosophy of science 2 10 1 Confirmation theory 2 10 2 Falsification 2 10 3 Confirmation holism 2 10 4 Constructivism 2 10 5 Biology 3 Notes 4 References 5 Books and articles 6 Further reading 7 External linksHistory of analytic philosophy editAustrian realism edit nbsp Franz Brentano gave to philosophy the problem of intentionality Analytic philosophy was deeply influenced by what is called Austrian realism in the former state of Austria Hungary so much so that Michael Dummett has remarked that analytic philosophy is better characterized as Anglo Austrian rather than the usual Anglo American 28 Brentano edit University of Vienna philosopher and psychologist Franz Brentano in Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint 1874 through the subsequent influence of the School of Brentano and its members such as Edmund Husserl and Alexius Meinong gave to analytic philosophy the problem of intentionality or of aboutness 29 For Brentano all mental events have a real non mental intentional object which the thinking is directed at or about Meinong edit Meinong is known for his unique ontology of real nonexistent objects as a solution to the problem of empty names 30 The Graz School followed Meinong Lwow Warsaw edit The Polish Lwow Warsaw school founded by Kazimierz Twardowski in 1895 grew as a further offshoot of the Graz School It was closely associated with the Warsaw School of Mathematics Frege edit nbsp Gottlob Frege the father of analytic philosophy Gottlob Frege 1848 1925 was a German geometry professor at the University of Jena who is understood as the father of analytic philosophy Frege proved influential as a philosopher of mathematics in Germany at the beginning of the 20th century He advocated logicism the project of reducing arithmetic to pure logic Logic edit As a result of his logicist project Frege developed predicate logic in the Begriffsschrift English Concept script 1879 which allowed a much greater range of sentences to be parsed into logical form than was possible using the ancient Aristotelian logic q An example of this is the problem of multiple generality Number edit Neo Kantianism dominated the late 19th century in German philosophy Edmund Husserl s 1891 book Philosophie der Arithmetik argued that the concept of the cardinal number derived from psychical acts of grouping objects and counting them 32 In contrast to this psychologism Frege in The Foundations of Arithmetic 1884 and The Basic Laws of Arithmetic German Grundgesetze der Arithmetik 1893 1903 argued similar to Plato or Bolzano that mathematics and logic have their own public objects independent of the private judgments or mental states of individual mathematicians and logicians Following Frege the logicists tended to advocate a kind of mathematical platonism Language edit Frege also proved influential in the philosophy of language and analytic philosophy s interest in meaning 33 Michael Dummett traces the linguistic turn to Frege s Foundations of Arithmetic and his context principle 34 Frege s paper On Sense and Reference 1892 is seminal containing Frege s puzzles and providing a mediated reference theory His paper The Thought A Logical Inquiry 1918 reflects both his anti idealism or anti psychologism and his interest in language In the paper he argues for a platonist account of propositions or thoughts Russell edit nbsp Russell in 1907 British philosophy in the 19th century had seen a revival of logic started by Richard Whately in reaction to the anti logical tradition of British empiricism The major figure of this period is English mathematician George Boole Other figures include William Hamilton Augustus de Morgan William Stanley Jevons Alice s Adventures in Wonderland author Lewis Carroll r Hugh MacColl and American pragmatist Charles Sanders Peirce 35 British philosophy in the late 19th century was dominated by British idealism a neo Hegelian movement as taught by philosophers such as F H Bradley 1846 1924 and T H Green 1836 1882 Analytic philosophy in the narrower sense of 20th and 21st century anglophone philosophy is usually thought to begin with Cambridge philosophers Bertrand Russell and G E Moore s rejection of Hegelianism for being obscure or the revolt against idealism see for example Moore s A Defence of Common Sense 36 s Paradox edit Bertrand Russell during his early career was much influenced by Frege Russell famously discovered the paradox in Basic Law V which undermined Frege s logicist project However like Frege Russell argued that mathematics is reducible to logical fundamentals in The Principles of Mathematics 1903 He also argued for Meinongianism 38 On Denoting edit Russell sought to resolve various philosophical problems by applying Frege s new logical apparatus most famously in his theory of definite descriptions in On Denoting published in Mind in 1905 39 Russell here argues against Meinongianism He argues all names aside from demonstratives like this or that are disguised definite descriptions using this to solve ascriptions of nonexistence This position came to be called descriptivism Principia Mathematica edit Later his book written with Alfred North Whitehead Principia Mathematica 1910 1913 the seminal text of classical logic and of the logicist project encouraged many philosophers to renew their interest in the development of symbolic logic It used a notation from Italian logician Giuseppe Peano and it uses a theory of types to avoid the pitfalls of Russell s paradox Whitehead developed process metaphysics in Process and Reality 40 Ideal language edit Main article Ideal language philosophy Additionally Russell adopted Frege s predicate logic as his primary philosophical method a method Russell thought could expose the underlying structure of philosophical problems Logical form would be made clear by syntax For example the English word is has three distinct meanings which predicate logic can express as follows For the sentence the cat is asleep the is of predication means that x is P denoted as P x For the sentence there is a cat the is of existence means that there is an x x For the sentence three is half of six the is of identity means that x is the same as y x y From about 1910 to 1930 analytic philosophers like Frege Russell Moore and Russell s student Ludwig Wittgenstein emphasized creating an ideal language for philosophical analysis which would be free from the ambiguities of ordinary language that in their opinion often made philosophy invalid During this phase they sought to understand language and hence philosophical problems by using logic to formalize how philosophical statements are made Logical atomism edit nbsp Ludwig Wittgenstein An important aspect of Hegelianism and British idealism was logical holism the opinion that there are aspects of the world that can be known only by knowing the whole world This is closely related to the doctrine of internal relations the opinion that relations between items are internal relations that is essential properties of the nature of those items Russell and Moore in response promulgated logical atomism and the doctrine of external relations the belief that the world consists of independent facts 41 t Inspired by developments in modern formal logic the early Russell claimed that the problems of philosophy can be solved by showing the simple constituents of complex notions 4 Early Wittgenstein edit Wittgenstein developed a comprehensive system of logical atomism with a picture theory of meaning in his Tractatus Logico Philosophicus German Logisch Philosophische Abhandlung 1921 sometimes known as simply the Tractatus He claimed the universe is the totality of actual states of affairs and that these states of affairs can be expressed and mirrored by the language of first order predicate logic Thus a picture of the universe can be constructed by expressing facts in the form of atomic propositions and linking them using logical operators Wittgenstein thought he had solved all the problems of philosophy with the Tractatus The work further ultimately concludes all of its propositions are meaningless illustrated with a ladder one must toss away after climbing up it Logical positivism edit nbsp 1 nbsp 2 nbsp 3 Members of the Vienna Circle From left to right 1 Moritz Schlick 2 Otto Neurath 3 Hans Hahn Main article Logical positivism During the late 1920s to 1940s a group of philosophers known as the Vienna Circle and another one known as the Berlin Circle developed Russell and Wittgenstein s philosophy into a doctrine known as logical positivism or logical empiricism The Vienna Circle was led by Moritz Schlick and included Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath 43 The Berlin Circle was led by Hans Reichenbach and included Carl Hempel and mathematician David Hilbert Logical positivists used formal logical methods to develop an empiricist account of knowledge 44 They adopted the verification principle according to which every meaningful statement is either analytic or synthetic The truths of logic and mathematics were tautologies and those of science were verifiable empirical claims These two constituted the entire universe of meaningful judgments anything else was nonsense This led the logical positivists to reject many traditional problems of philosophy especially those of metaphysics as meaningless It had the additional effect of making ethical and aesthetic value judgments as well as religious statements and beliefs meaningless Logical positivists therefore typically considered philosophy as having a minimal function For them philosophy concerned the clarification of thoughts rather than having a distinct subject matter of its own Several logical positivists were Jewish such as Neurath Hans Hahn Philipp Frank Friedrich Waissmann and Reichenbach Others like Carnap were gentiles but socialists or pacifists With the coming to power of Adolf Hitler and Nazism in 1933 many members of the Vienna and Berlin Circles fled to Britain and the USA which helped to reinforce the dominance of logical positivism and analytic philosophy in anglophone countries In 1936 Schlick was murdered in Vienna by his former student Hans Nelbock The same year A J Ayer s work Language Truth and Logic introduced the English speaking world to logical positivism u The logical positivists saw their rejection of metaphysics in some ways as a recapitulation of a quote by David Hume If we take in our hand any volume of divinity or school metaphysics for instance let us ask Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number No Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence No Commit it then to the flames for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion 45 Ordinary language edit Main article Ordinary language philosophy After World War II during the late 1940s and 1950s analytic philosophy became involved with ordinary language analysis This resulted in two main trends Later Wittgenstein edit One strain continued Wittgenstein s later philosophy from the Philosophical Investigations 1953 which differed dramatically from his early work of the Tractatus v The criticisms of Frank P Ramsey on color and logical form in the Tractatus led to some of Wittgenstein s first doubts with his early philosophy Philosophers refer to them like two different philosophers early Wittgenstein and later Wittgenstein In his later philosophy Wittgenstein develops the concept of a language game and rather than his prior picture theory of meaning advocates a theory of meaning as use It also contains the private language argument and the notion of family resemblance Oxford philosophy editThe other trend known as Oxford philosophy in contrast to earlier analytic Cambridge philosophers including the early Wittgenstein who thought philosophers should avoid the deceptive trappings of natural language by constructing ideal languages Influenced by Moore s common sense and what they perceived as the later Wittgenstein s quietism the Oxford philosophers claimed that ordinary language already represents many subtle distinctions not recognized in the formulation of traditional philosophical theories or problems nbsp Portrait of Gilbert RyleWhile schools such as logical positivism emphasize logical terms supposed to be universal and separate from contingent factors such as culture language historical conditions ordinary language philosophy emphasizes the use of language by ordinary people The most prominent ordinary language philosophers during the 1950s were P F Strawson J L Austin and Gilbert Ryle 47 Ordinary language philosophers often sought to dissolve philosophical problems by showing them to be the result of ordinary misunderstanding language Ryle in The Concept of Mind 1949 criticized Cartesian dualism arguing in favor of disposing Descartes myth via recognizing category errors Strawson first became well known with his article On Referring 1950 a criticism of Russell s theory of descriptions explained in the famous On Denoting article In his book Individuals 1959 Strawson examines our conceptions of basic particulars Austin in the posthumously published How to Do Things with Words 1962 emphasized the theory of speech acts and the ability of words to do things e g I promise and not just say things This influenced several fields in what is called the performative turn In Sense and Sensibilia 1962 Austin criticized sense data theories Spread of Analytic philosophy edit Australia and New Zealand edit The school known as Australian realism began when John Anderson accepted the Challis Chair of Philosophy at the University of Sydney in 1927 His elder brother was William Anderson Professor of Philosophy at Auckland University College 1921 to his death in 1955 and described as the most dominant figure in New Zealand philosophy 48 J N Findlay was a student of Ernst Mally of the Austrian realists and taught at the University of Otago Finland edit The Finnish Georg Henrik von Wright succeeded Wittgenstein at Cambridge in 1948 49 Contemporary analytic philosophy editMetaphysics edit Main article Metaphysics One striking difference with respect to early analytic philosophy was the revival of metaphysical theorizing during the second half of the 20th century and metaphysics remains a fertile topic of research Although many discussions are continuations of old ones from previous decades and centuries the debates remains active 50 Decline of logical positivism edit The rise of metaphysics mirrored the decline in logical positivism first challenged by the later Wittgenstein Sellars edit Wilfred Sellars s Myth of the Given in Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind 1956 challenged logical positivism by arguing against sense data theories In his Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man 1962 Sellars distinguishes between the manifest image and the scientific image of the world Sellars s goal of a synoptic philosophy that unites the everyday and scientific views of reality is the foundation and archetype of what is sometimes called the Pittsburgh School whose members include Robert Brandom John McDowell and John Haugeland Quine edit nbsp W V O Quine helped to undermine logical positivism Also among the developments that resulted in the decline of logical positivism and the revival of metaphysical theorizing was Harvard philosopher W V O Quine s attack on the analytic synthetic distinction in Two Dogmas of Empiricism published in 1951 in the Philosophical Review and republished in Quine s book From A Logical Point of View 1953 a paper sometimes regarded as the most important in all of twentieth century philosophy 51 52 53 From a Logical Point of View also contains Quine s essay On What There Is 1948 which elucidates Russell s theory of descriptions and contains Quine s famous dictum of ontological commitment To be is to be the value of a variable He also dubbed the problem of nonexistence Plato s beard Quine sought to naturalize philosophy and saw philosophy as continuous with science but instead of logical positivism advocated a kind of semantic holism and ontological relativity which explained that every term in any statement has its meaning contingent on a vast network of knowledge and belief the speaker s conception of the entire world In his magnum opus Word and Object 1960 Quine introduces the idea of radical translation an introduction to his theory of the indeterminacy of translation and specifically to prove the inscrutability of reference Kripke edit nbsp Saul Kripke helped to revive interest in metaphysics among analytic philosophers Important also for the revival of metaphysics was the further development of modal logic first introduced by pragmatist C I Lewis especially the work of Saul Kripke and his Naming and Necessity 1980 w According to one author Naming and Necessity played a large role in the implicit but widespread rejection of the view so popular among ordinary language philosophers that philosophy is nothing more than the analysis of language 54 Kripke argued influentially that flaws in common theories of descriptions and proper names are indicative of larger misunderstandings of the metaphysics of necessity and possibility Kripke also argued necessity is a metaphysical notion distinct from the epistemic notion of a priori and that there are necessary truths that are known a posteriori such as that water is H2O 55 Kripke is widely regarded as reviving theories of essence and identity as respectable topics of philosophical discussion 55 Kripke and Hilary Putnam argued for realism about natural kinds Kripke holds that it is essential that water is H2O or for gold to be atomic number 79 Putnam s Twin Earth thought experiment can be used to illustrate the same point with water 56 David Lewis edit nbsp David Lewis developed an elaborate metaphysicsAmerican philosopher David Lewis defended a number of elaborate metaphysical theories In works like On the Plurality of Worlds 1986 and Counterfactuals 1973 he argued for modal realism and counterpart theory the belief in real concrete possible worlds According to Lewis actual is merely an indexical label we give a world when we are in it Lewis also defended what he called Humean supervenience a counterfactual theory of causation 57 and contributed to abstract object theory 58 He became closely associated with Australia whose philosophical community he visited almost annually for more than 30 years Universals edit In response to the problem of universals Australian David Malet Armstrong defended a kind of moderate realism 59 60 Quine and Lewis defended nominalism 58 Mereology edit Polish philosopher Stanislaw Lesniewski coined the term mereology meaning the formal study of parts and wholes a subject which arguably goes back to the time of the pre Socratics 61 David Lewis believed in perdurantism and introduced the term gunk Peter Van Inwagen believes in mereological nihilism except for living beings a view called organicism Free will and determinism edit Peter van Inwagen s 1983 monograph An Essay on Free Will 62 played an important role in rehabilitating libertarianism with respect to free will in mainstream analytical philosophy 63 In the book he introduces the consequence argument and the term incompatibilism about free will and determinism to stand in contrast to compatibilism the view that free will is compatible with determinism Charlie Broad had previously made similar arguments Personal identity edit Since John Locke philosophers have been concerned with the issue of personal identity Derek Parfit in Reasons and Persons 1984 defends a kind of bundle theory while David Lewis again defends perdurantism Bernard Williams in The Self and the Future 1970 argues personal identity is bodily identity rather than mental continuity 64 Principle of sufficient reason edit Since Leibniz philosophers have discussed the principle of sufficient reason or PSR Van Inwagen criticizes the PSR 62 Alexander Pruss defends it 65 Philosophy of time edit Analytic philosophy of time traces its roots to the British idealist J M E McTaggart s article The Unreality of Time 1908 In it McTaggart distinguishes between the dynamic A theory of time or tensed theory of time past present future in which time flows and the static or tenseless B theory of time earlier than simultaneous with later than Eternalism holds that past present and future are equally real while according to presentists only entities in the present exist 66 The theory of special relativity seems to advocate a B theory of time David Lewis s perdurantism or four dimensionalism requires a B theory of time 67 A N Prior who invented tense logic advocated the A theory of time Logical pluralism edit Many valued and nonclassical logics have been popular since Polish logician Jan Lukasiewicz Graham Priest is a dialetheist seeing it as the most natural solution to problems like the liar paradox JC Beall together with Greg Restall is a pioneer of a widely discussed version of logical pluralism 68 Epistemology edit Main article Epistemology Justification edit Gettier edit nbsp Edmund Gettier helped to revitalize analytic epistemology Owing largely to Edmund Gettier s 1963 paper Is Justified True Belief Knowledge 69 and so called Gettier problem epistemology resurged as a topic of analytic philosophy during the last 50 years A large portion of current epistemological research is intended to resolve the problems that Gettier s examples presented to the traditional justified true belief model of knowledge found as early as Plato s dialogue Theaetetus These include developing theories of justification to deal with Gettier s examples or giving alternatives to the justified true belief model Theories edit Chisholm defended foundationalism Quine defended coherentism a web of belief 70 Quine proposed naturalized epistemology Internalism and externalism edit The debate between internalism and externalism still exists in analytic philosophy 71 Alvin Goldman is an externalist known for developing a popular form of externalism called reliabilism Most externalists reject the KK thesis which has been disputed since the introduction of the epistemic logic by Jaakko Hintikka in 1962 72 Problem of the Criterion edit While a problem since antiquity American philosopher Roderick Chisholm in his Theory of Knowledge details the problem of the criterion with two sets of questions What do we know or What is the extent of our knowledge How do we know or What is the criterion for deciding whether we have knowledge in any particular case An answer to either set of questions will allow us to devise a means of answering the other Answering the former question set first is called particularism whereas answering the latter set first is called methodism A third solution is skepticism or doubting there is such a thing as knowledge Truth edit nbsp Alfred Tarski has an influential theory of truth Frege questioned standard theories of truth and sometimes advocated a redundancy theory of truth Frank Ramsey also advocated a redundancy theory Alfred Tarski put forward a semantic theory of truth 73 74 In Truth Makers 1984 Kevin Mulligan Peter Simons and Barry Smith introduced the truth maker idea as a contribution to the correspondence theory of truth 75 A truth maker is contrasted with a truth bearer Closure edit nbsp Here is one hand Epistemic closure is the claim knowledge is closed under entailment in other words epistemic closure is a property or the principle that if a subject S displaystyle S nbsp knows p displaystyle p nbsp and S displaystyle S nbsp knows that p displaystyle p nbsp entails q displaystyle q nbsp then S displaystyle S nbsp can thereby come to know q displaystyle q nbsp 76 Most epistemological theories involve a closure principle and many skeptical arguments assume a closure principle G E Moore s famous anti skeptical Here is one hand in Proof of An External World argument uses closure Shortly before his death Wittgenstein wrote On Certainty in response to Moore While the principle of epistemic closure is generally regarded as intuitive 77 philosophers such as Fred Dretske and Robert Nozick in Philosophical Explanations have argued against it Induction edit nbsp All emeralds are grue In his book Fact Fiction and Forecast Nelson Goodman introduced the new riddle of induction so called by analogy with Hume s classical problem of induction Goodman s famous example was to introduce the predicates grue and bleen Grue applies to all things before a certain time t just in case they are green but also just in case they are blue after time t and bleen applies before a certain time t just in the case they are blue but also just in they are green after time t Other topics edit Other and related topics of contemporary research include debates between basic knowledge the nature of evidence the value of knowledge epistemic luck virtue epistemology the role of intuitions in justification and treating knowledge as a primitive concept Ethics edit Due to the commitments to empiricism and symbolic logic in the early analytic period early analytic philosophers often thought that inquiry in the ethical domain could not be made rigorous enough to merit any attention 78 It was only with the emergence of ordinary language philosophers that ethics started to become an acceptable area of inquiry for analytic philosophers 78 Philosophers working with the analytic tradition have gradually come to distinguish three major types of moral philosophy Meta ethics which investigates moral terms and concepts 79 Normative ethics which examines and produces normative ethical judgments Applied ethics which investigates how existing normative principles should be applied to difficult or borderline cases often cases created by new technology or new scientific knowledge Meta ethics edit As well as Hume s famous is ought distinction twentieth century meta ethics has two original strains Principia Ethica edit nbsp G E Moore was an ethical non naturalist The first is G E Moore s investigation into the nature of ethical terms e g good in his Principia Ethica 1903 which advances a kind of moral realism called ethical non naturalism and is known for the open question argument and identifying the naturalistic fallacy a major topic of investigation for analytical philosophers According to G E Moore Goodness is a simple undefinable non natural property Contemporary philosophers like Russ Shafer Landau in Moral Realism A Defence defend ethical non naturalism Emotivism edit The second is founded in logical positivism and its attitude that unverifiable statements are meaningless As a result they avoided normative ethics and instead began meta ethical investigations into the nature of moral terms statements and judgments The logical positivists opined that statements about value including all ethical and aesthetic judgments are non cognitive that is they cannot be objectively verified or falsified Instead the logical positivists adopted an emotivist theory which was that value judgments expressed the attitude of the speaker It is also known as the boo hurrah theory For example in this view saying Murder is wrong is equivalent to saying Boo to murder or saying the word murder with a particular tone of disapproval While analytic philosophers generally accepted non cognitivism emotivism had many deficiencies It evolved into more sophisticated non cognitivist theories such as the expressivism of Charles Stevenson and the universal prescriptivism of R M Hare which was based on J L Austin s philosophy of speech acts Critics edit nbsp Philippa Foot was an ethical naturalist As non cognitivism the is ought distinction and the naturalistic fallacy were questioned analytic philosophers showed a renewed interest in the traditional questions of moral philosophy Philippa Foot defended naturalist moral realism and contributed several essays attacking other theories x Foot introduced the famous trolley problem into the ethical discourse 80 Perhaps the most influential critic was Elizabeth Anscombe whose monograph Intention was called by Donald Davidson the most important treatment of action since Aristotle 81 A favorite student and friend of Ludwig Wittgenstein her 1958 article Modern Moral Philosophy declared the is ought impasse to be unproductive J O Urmson s article On Grading also called the is ought distinction into question Australian J L Mackie in Ethics Inventing Right And Wrong defended anti realist error theory Bernard Williams also influenced ethics by advocating a kind of moral relativism rejecting all other theories 82 Normative ethics edit The first half of the 20th century was marked by skepticism toward and neglect of normative ethics However today contemporary normative ethics is dominated by three schools consequentialism virtue ethics and deontology y Consequentialism edit Utilitarianism edit During the early 20th century utilitarianism was the only non skeptical type of ethics to remain popular among analytic philosophers However as the influence of logical positivism declined mid century analytic philosophers had a renewed interest in ethics Utilitarianism For and Against was written with J J C Smart arguing for and Bernard Williams arguing against Virtue ethics edit Anscombe Foot and Alasdair Macintyre s After Virtue sparked a revival of Aristotle s virtue ethical approach This increased interest in virtue ethics has been dubbed the aretaic turn mimicking the linguistic turn Deontology edit John Rawls s 1971 A Theory of Justice restored interest in Kantian ethical philosophy Applied ethics edit A significant feature of analytic philosophy since approximately 1970 has been the emergence of applied ethics an interest in the application of moral principles to specific practical issues The philosophers following this orientation view ethics as involving humanistic values which involve practical implications and applications in the way people interact and lead their lives socially 83 Topics of special interest for applied ethics include environmental ethics animal rights and the many challenges created by advancing medical science 84 85 86 In education applied ethics addressed themes such as punishment in schools equality of educational opportunity and education for democracy 87 Political philosophy edit Liberalism edit nbsp John Rawls Isaiah Berlin had a lasting influence on both analytic political philosophy and liberalism with his lecture Two Concepts of Liberty citation needed Berlin defined negative liberty as absence of coercion or interference in private actions Positive liberty Berlin maintained could be thought of as self mastery which asks not what we are free from but what we are free to do Current analytic political philosophy owes much to John Rawls who in a series of papers from the 1950s onward most notably Two Concepts of Rules and Justice as Fairness and his 1971 book A Theory of Justice produced a sophisticated defense of a generally liberal egalitarian account of distributive justice Rawls introduced the term the veil of ignorance This was followed soon by Rawls s colleague Robert Nozick s book Anarchy State and Utopia a defense of free market libertarianism Consequentialist libertarianism also derives from the analytic tradition citation needed During recent decades there have also been several critics of liberalism including the feminist critiques of Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin the multiculturalist critiques of Amy Gutmann and Charles Taylor and the communitarian critiques of Michael Sandel and Alasdair MacIntyre although neither of them endorses the term Analytical Marxism edit Another development of political philosophy was the emergence of the school of analytical Marxism Members of this school seek to apply techniques of analytic philosophy and modern social science to clarify the theories of Karl Marx and his successors The best known member of this school is G A Cohen whose 1978 work Karl Marx s Theory of History A Defence is generally considered to represent the genesis of this school In that book Cohen used logical and linguistic analysis to clarify and defend Marx s materialist conception of history Other prominent analytical Marxists include the economist John Roemer the social scientist Jon Elster and the sociologist Erik Olin Wright The work of these later philosophers have furthered Cohen s work by bringing to bear modern social science methods such as rational choice theory to supplement Cohen s use of analytic philosophical techniques in the interpretation of Marxian theory Cohen himself would later engage directly with Rawlsian political philosophy to advance a socialist theory of justice that contrasts with both traditional Marxism and the theories advanced by Rawls and Nozick In particular he indicates Marx s principle of from each according to his ability to each according to his need Although not an analytic philosopher Jurgen Habermas is another influential if controversial author in contemporary analytic political philosophy whose social theory is a blend of social science Marxism neo Kantianism and American pragmatism citation needed Communitarianism edit nbsp Alasdair MacIntyre Communitarians such as Alasdair MacIntyre Charles Taylor Michael Walzer and Michael Sandel advance a critique of liberalism that uses analytic techniques to isolate the main assumptions of liberal individualists such as Rawls and then challenges these assumptions In particular communitarians challenge the liberal assumption that the individual can be considered as fully autonomous from the community in which he lives and is brought up Instead they argue for a conception of the individual that emphasizes the role that the community plays in forming his or her values thought processes and opinions While in the analytic tradition its major exponents often also engage at length with figures generally considered continental notably G W F Hegel and Friedrich Nietzsche Aesthetics edit Main article Aesthetics As a result of logical positivism as well as what seemed like rejections of the traditional aesthetic notions of beauty and sublimity from post modern thinkers analytic philosophers were slow to consider art and aesthetic judgment Susanne Langer 88 and Nelson Goodman 89 addressed these problems in an analytic style during the 1950s and 1960s Since Goodman aesthetics as a discipline for analytic philosophers has flourished 90 Arthur Danto argued for a institutional definition of art in the 1964 essay The Artworld in which Danto coined the term artworld as opposed to the existing art world though they mean the same by which he meant cultural context or an atmosphere of art theory 91 Rigorous efforts to pursue analyses of traditional aesthetic concepts were performed by Guy Sircello in the 1970s and 1980s resulting in new analytic theories of love 92 sublimity 93 and beauty 94 In the opinion of Wladyslaw Tatarkiewicz there are six conditions for the presentation of art beauty form representation reproduction of reality artistic expression and innovation However one may not be able to pin down these qualities in a work of art 95 George Dickie was an influential philosopher of art Dickie s student Noel Carroll is a leading philosopher of art Philosophy of language edit Main article Philosophy of language Given the linguistic turn it can be hard to separate logic metaphysics and the philosophy of language in analytic philosophy Philosophy of language is a topic that has decreased in activity during the last four decades as evidenced by the fact that few major philosophers today treat it as a primary research topic While the debate remains fierce it is still strongly influenced by those authors from the first half of the century e g Frege Russell Wittgenstein Austin Tarski and Quine Semantics edit Kripke provided a semantics for modal logic In Saul Kripke s publication Naming and Necessity Kripke challenges the descriptivist theory with a causal theory of reference In it he introduced the term rigid designator According to one author In the philosophy of language Naming and Necessity is among the most important works ever 54 Ruth Barcan Marcus also challenged descriptivism So did Keith Donnellan 96 Hilary Putnam used the Twin Earth thought experiment to argue for semantic externalism or the view that the meanings of words are not psychological Donald Davidson uses the thought experiment of Swampman to advocate semantic externalism Kripke in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language provides a rule following paradox that undermines the possibility of our ever following rules in our use of language and so calls into question the idea of meaning Kripke writes that this paradox is the most radical and original skeptical problem that philosophy has seen to date The portmanteau Kripkenstein has been coined as a term for a fictional person who holds the views expressed by Kripke s reading of Wittgenstein Another influential philosopher Pavel Tichy initiated Transparent Intensional Logic an original theory of the logical analysis of natural languages the theory is devoted to the problem of saying exactly what it is that we learn know and can communicate when we come to understand what a sentence means Pragmatics edit Paul Grice and his maxims and theory of implicature established the discipline of pragmatics Philosophy of mind and cognitive science edit nbsp John Searle John Searle suggests that the obsession with the philosophy of language during the 20th century has been superseded by an emphasis on the philosophy of mind 97 Physicalism edit Motivated by the logical positivists interest in verificationism logical behaviorism was the most prominent theory of mind of analytic philosophy for the first half of the 20th century 98 Behaviorism later became much less popular in favor of either type physicalism or functionalism During this period topics of the philosophy of mind were often related strongly to topics of cognitive science such as modularity or innateness Behaviorism edit Behaviorists like B F Skinner tended to opine either that statements about the mind were equivalent to statements about behavior and dispositions to behave in particular ways or that mental states were directly equivalent to behavior and dispositions to behave nbsp Hilary Putnam Hilary Putnam criticized behaviorism by arguing that it confuses the symptoms of mental states with the mental states themselves positing super Spartans who never display signs of pain 99 Type Identity edit Type physicalism or type identity theory identified mental states with brain states Former students of Ryle at the University of Adelaide J J C Smart and Ullin Place argued for type physicalism Functionalism edit Functionalism remains the dominant theory Type identity was criticized using multiple realizability Searle s Chinese room argument criticized functionalism and holds that while a computer can understand syntax it could never understand semantics Eliminativism edit The view of eliminative materialism is most closely associated with the Paul and Patricia Churchland who deny the existence of propositional attitudes and with Daniel Dennett who is generally considered an eliminativist about qualia and phenomenal aspects of consciousness Dualism edit nbsp David Chalmers Finally analytic philosophy has featured a certain number of philosophers who were dualists and recently forms of property dualism have had a resurgence the most prominent representative is David Chalmers 100 Kripke also has a notable argument for dualism 101 Thomas Nagel s What is it like to be a bat challenged a physicalist account of mind So did Frank Jackson s Knowledge argument which argues for qualia Theories of consciousness edit In recent years a central focus of research in the philosophy of mind has been consciousness and the philosophy of perception While there is a general consensus for the global neuronal workspace model of consciousness 102 there are many opinions as to the specifics The best known theories are Searle s naive realism Fred Dretske and Michael Tye s representationalism Daniel Dennett s heterophenomenology and the higher order theories of either David M Rosenthal who advocates a higher order thought HOT model or David Armstrong and William Lycan who advocate a higher order perception HOP model An alternative higher order theory the higher order global states HOGS model is offered by Robert van Gulick 103 Philosophy of mathematics edit nbsp Kurt Godel Since the beginning analytic philosophy has had an interest in the philosophy of mathematics Kurt Godel a student of Hans Hahn of the Vienna Circle produced his incompleteness theorems showing Principia Mathematica also failed to reduce arithmetic to logic Godel has been ranked as one of the four greatest logicians of all time along with Aristotle Frege and Tarski 104 Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel established Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory Quine developed his own system dubbed New Foundations Physicist Eugene Wigner s seminal paper the Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences poses the question why a formal pursuit like mathematics can have real utility 105 Jose Benardete argued for the reality of infinity 106 Akin to the medieval debate on universals between realists idealists and nominalists philosophy of mathematics has the debate between logicists or platonists conceptualists or intuitionists and formalists 107 Platonism edit Godel was a platonist who postulated a special kind of mathematical intuition that lets us perceive mathematical objects directly Quine and Putnam argued for platonism with the indispensability argument Crispin Wright along with Bob Hale led a Neo Fregean revival with his work Frege s Conception of Numbers as Objects 108 Critics edit Paul Benacerraf gives an epistemological objection to mathematical platonism Benacerraf is a structuralist Intuitionism edit The intuitionists were led by L E J Brouwer a constructivist school of mathematics which argues that math is a cognitive construct rather than a type of objective truth Formalism edit The formalists were best exemplified by David Hilbert and considered mathematics to be merely the investigation of formal axiom systems Hartry Field defended mathematical fictionalism Philosophy of religion edit In Analytic Philosophy of Religion James Franklin Harris noted that analytic philosophy has been a very heterogeneous movement some forms of analytic philosophy have proven very sympathetic to the philosophy of religion and have provided a philosophical mechanism for responding to other more radical and hostile forms of analytic philosophy 109 3 As with the study of ethics early analytic philosophy tended to avoid the study of philosophy of religion largely dismissing as per the logical positivists the subject as part of metaphysics and therefore meaningless z The demise of logical positivism renewed interest in philosophy of religion prompting philosophers not only to introduce new problems but to re study classical topics such as the existence of God the nature of miracles the problem of evil the rationality of belief in God concepts of the nature of God and several others 110 The Society of Christian Philosophers was established in 1978 Reformed epistemology editAnalytic philosophy formed the basis for some sophisticated Christian arguments such as those of the reformed epistemologists like Alvin Plantinga William Alston and Nicholas Wolterstorff nbsp Alvin PlantingaPlantinga was awarded the Templeton Prize in 2017 and was once described by Time magazine as America s leading orthodox Protestant philosopher of God 111 His seminal work God and Other Minds 1967 argues that belief in God is a properly basic belief akin to the belief in other minds Plantinga also developed a modal ontological argument in The Nature of Necessity 1974 Plantinga J L Mackie and Antony Flew debated the use of the free will defense as a way to solve the problem of evil 112 Plantinga s evolutionary argument against naturalism contends a skeptical problem with asserting both evolution and naturalism Plantinga further issued a trilogy on epistemology and especially justification Warrant The Current Debate Warrant and Proper Function and Warranted Christian Belief Alston defended divine command theory and applied analytic philosophy of language to religious language Robert Merrihew Adams also defended divine command theory and worked on the relationship of faith and morality 113 William Lane Craig defends the Kalam cosmological argument in the book of the same name Analytic Thomism edit Catholic philosophers in the analytic tradition such as Elizabeth Anscombe Peter Geach Anthony Kenny Alasdair MacIntyre John Haldane Eleonore Stump and others developed an analytic approach to Thomism Orthodox edit Richard Swinburne wrote a trilogy of books arguing for God consisting of The Coherence of Theism The Existence of God and Faith and Reason Wittgenstein and religion edit Analytic philosophy of religion has been preoccupied with Wittgenstein as well as his interpretation of Soren Kierkegaard s philosophy of religion 114 Wittgenstein fought for the Austrian army in the First World War and came upon a copy of Leo Tolstoy s Gospel in Brief At this time he underwent some kind of religious conversion 115 Using first hand remarks which was later published in Philosophical Investigations Culture and Value and other works philosophers such as Peter Winch and Norman Malcolm developed what has come to be known as contemplative philosophy a Wittgensteinian school of thought rooted in the Swansea school and which includes Wittgensteinians such as Rush Rhees Peter Winch and D Z Phillips among others The name contemplative philosophy was coined by D Z Phillips in Philosophy s Cool Place which rests on an interpretation of a passage from Wittgenstein s Culture and Value 116 This interpretation was first labeled Wittgensteinian Fideism by Kai Nielsen but those who consider themselves members of the Swansea school have relentlessly and repeatedly rejected this construal as a caricature of Wittgenstein s position this is especially true of D Z Phillips 117 Responding to this interpretation Kai Nielsen and D Z Phillips became two of the most prominent philosophers on Wittgenstein s philosophy of religion 118 Philosophy of science edit Main article Philosophy of science Science and the philosophy of science has also had an increasingly significant role in analytic metaphysics The theory of special relativity has had a profound effect on the philosophy of time and quantum physics is routinely discussed in the free will debate 50 The weight given to scientific evidence is largely due to commitments among philosophers to scientific realism and naturalism Others will see a commitment to using science in philosophy as scientism Confirmation theory edit Carl Hempel advocated confirmation theory or Bayesian epistemology He introduced the famous raven s paradox 119 Falsification edit nbsp Karl Popper In reaction to what he considered excesses of logical positivism Karl Popper in The Logic of Scientific Discovery insisted on the role of falsification in the philosophy of science using it to solve the demarcation problem 120 Confirmation holism edit The Duhem Quine thesis or problem of underdetermination posits no scientific hypothesis can be understood in isolation a viewpoint called confirmation holism 51 Constructivism edit In reaction to both the logical positivists and Popper discussions of philosophy of science during the last 40 years were dominated by social constructivist and cognitive relativist theories of science Following Quine and Duhem subsequent theories emphasized theory ladenness Thomas Samuel Kuhn with his formulation of paradigm shifts and Paul Feyerabend with his epistemological anarchism are significant for these discussions 121 Biology edit The philosophy of biology has also undergone considerable growth particularly due to the considerable debate in recent years over the nature of evolution particularly natural selection 122 Daniel Dennett and his 1995 book Darwin s Dangerous Idea which defends Neo Darwinism stand at the foreground of this debate 123 Jerry Fodor criticizes natural selection Notes edit A P Martinich draws an analogy between analytic philosophy and analytic chemistry which aims to determine chemical compositions 1 Without exception the best philosophy departments in the United States are dominated by analytic philosophy and among the leading philosophers in the United States all but a tiny handful would be classified as analytic philosophers Practitioners of types of philosophizing that are not in the analytic tradition such as phenomenology classical pragmatism existentialism or Marxism feel it necessary to define their position in relation to analytic philosophy 2 Quote on the definition Analytic philosophy today names a style of doing philosophy not a philosophical program or a set of substantive views Analytic philosophers crudely speaking aim for argumentative clarity and precision draw freely on the tools of logic and often identify professionally and intellectually more closely with the sciences and mathematics than with the humanities 5 analytical philosophy is too narrow a label since it is not generally a matter of taking a word or concept and analyzing it whatever exactly that might be This tradition emphasizes clarity rigor argument theory truth It is not a tradition that aims primarily for inspiration or consolation or ideology Nor is it particularly concerned with philosophy of life though parts of it are This kind of philosophy is more like science than religion more like mathematics than poetry though it is neither science nor mathematics 6 According to Scott Soames an implicit commitment albeit faltering and imperfect to the ideals of clarity rigor and argumentation and it aims at truth and knowledge as opposed to moral or spiritual improvement the goal in analytic philosophy is to discover what is true not to provide a useful recipe for living one s life Soames also states that analytic philosophy is characterized by a more piecemeal approach There is I think a widespread presumption within the tradition that it is often possible to make philosophical progress by intensively investigating a small circumscribed range of philosophical issues while holding broader systematic questions in abeyance 7 I t is difficult to give a precise definition of analytic philosophy since it is not so much a specific doctrine as a loose concatenation of approaches to problems 9 I think Sluga is right in saying it may be hopeless to try to determine the essence of analytic philosophy Nearly every proposed definition has been challenged by some scholar W e are dealing with a family resemblance concept 10 The answer to the title question then is that analytic philosophy is a tradition held together both by ties of mutual influence and by family resemblances 11 The 1950s saw challenges to much which had been taken for granted and roughly by 1960 anglophone philosophy began to incorporate a wider range of interests opinions and methods 16 Despite this most philosophers in Britain and America still consider themselves analytic philosophers 5 They have done so largely by expanding the notion of analytic philosophy from the specific programs that dominated anglophone philosophy before 1960 to a much more general notion of an analytic style 5 16 characterized by mathematical precision and thoroughness about a specific topic and resistance to imprecise or cavalier discussions of broad topics 16 Most non analytic philosophers of the twentieth century do not belong to continental philosophy 17 The distinction rests upon a confusion of geographical and methodological terms as if one were to classify cars into front wheel drive and Japanese the distinction between analytic and Continental philosophy rests upon a confused comparison of methodological and geographical categories 18 Analytic philosophy is mainly associated with the contemporary English speaking world but it is by no means the only important philosophical tradition In this volume two other immensely rich and important such traditions are introduced Indian philosophy and philosophical thought in Europe from the time of Hegel 19 So despite a few overlaps analytical philosophy is not difficult to distinguish broadly from other modern movements like phenomenology say or existentialism or from the large amount of philosophizing that has also gone on in the present century within frameworks deriving from other influential thinkers like Aquinas Hegel or Marx 20 Steven D Hales described analytic philosophy as one of three types of philosophical method practiced in the West i n roughly reverse order by number of proponents they are phenomenology ideological philosophy and analytic philosophy 21 The distinction which Russell sets up between technical philosophy and literary philosophy has had many incarnations from Plato s ancient quarrel between poetry and philosophy 24 The tradition has also been criticized for excessive formalism ahistoricism and aloofness towards alternative disciplines and outsiders 25 26 27 Some have tried to develop a postanalytic philosophy It has recently been argued Frege plagiarized Stoic logic 31 Carroll s paper What The Tortoise Said To Achilles humorously shows an infinite regress paradox at the heart of logic Analytic philosophy opposed right from its beginning English neo Hegelianism of Bradley s sort and similar ones It did not only criticize the latter s denial of the existence of an external world anyway an unjust criticism but also the bombastic obscure style of Hegel s writings 37 Russell once explained Hegel had maintained that all separateness is illusory and that the universe is more like a pot of treacle than a heap of shot I therefore said The universe is exactly like a heap of shot 42 Named in reference to Waismann s Logik Sprache Philosophie A survey among American university and college teachers ranked the Investigations as the most important philosophical book of the 20th century 46 Named in reference to Carnap s Meaning and Necessity Foot was the granddaughter of former US President Grover Cleveland Anscombe introduced the term consequentialism into the philosophical lexicon A notable exception is the series of Michael B Foster s 1934 36 Mind articles involving the Christian doctrine of creation and the rise of modern science References edit A Companion to Analytic Philosophy John Searle 2003 Contemporary Philosophy in the United States in N Bunnin and E P Tsui James eds The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy 2nd ed Blackwell 2003 p 1 Glock H J 2004 Was Wittgenstein an Analytic Philosopher Metaphilosophy 35 4 419 444 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9973 2004 00329 x a b Mautner Thomas editor 2005 The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy entry for Analytic philosophy pp 22 23 a b c Brian Leiter 2006 webpage Analytic and Continental Philosophy Colin McGinn The Making of a Philosopher My Journey through Twentieth Century Philosophy HarperCollins 2002 p xi Soames Scott 2003 The dawn of analysis 2nd print 1st papers print ed Princeton NJ Princeton Univ Press pp xiii xvii ISBN 978 0 691 11573 3 Dummett 1993 p 4 22 See e g Avrum Stroll Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy Columbia University Press 2000 p 5 see Stroll 2000 p 7 See Hans Johann Glock What Is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2008 p 205 Koopman Colin Bernard Williams on Philosophy s Need for History PDF pages uoregon edu Retrieved 1 March 2022 Vienne J M 1997 Philosophie analytique et histoire de la philosophie actes du colloque Universite de Nantes 1991 Problemes et controverses in French J Vrin p 140 ISBN 978 2 7116 1312 0 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Luft S 2019 Philosophie lehren Ein Buch zur philosophischen Hochschuldidaktik in German Felix Meiner Verlag p 258 ISBN 978 3 7873 3766 8 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Glock H J 2008 What is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 1 ISBN 978 0 521 87267 6 Retrieved 28 August 2023 a b c Analytic Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Iep utm edu Archived from the original on 3 July 2009 Retrieved 13 April 2018 H J Glock What Is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2008 p 86 Critchley Simon 2001 Continental philosophy a very short introduction Oxford University Press OCLC 1200924441 A C Grayling ed Philosophy 2 Further through the Subject Oxford University Press 1998 p 2 L J Cohen The Dialogue of Reason An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy Oxford University Press 1986 p 5 Hales Steven D 2002 Analytic philosophy classic readings Belmont CA Wadsworth Thomson Learning pp 1 10 ISBN 978 0 534 51277 4 Rinofner Kreidl S Wiltsche H A 2016 Analytic and Continental Philosophy Methods and Perspectives Proceedings of the 37th International Wittgenstein Symposium Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society New Series De Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 044887 0 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Glock H J 2008 What is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 87267 6 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Luchte James 3 November 2011 Nietzsche s Thus Spoke Zarathustra Before Sunrise Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 4411 1845 5 Glock H J 2008 What is Analytic Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 231 ISBN 978 0 521 87267 6 Retrieved 28 August 2023 Akehurst Thomas L 1 March 2009 Writing history for the ahistorical Analytic philosophy and its past History of European Ideas 35 1 116 121 doi 10 1016 j histeuroideas 2008 09 002 ISSN 0191 6599 S2CID 143566283 Beaney Michael 20 June 2013 Beaney Michael ed The Historiography of Analytic Philosophy The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199238842 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 923884 2 Retrieved 18 February 2022 Dummett 1993 p 2 Dummett 1993 p 28 Everett Anthony and Thomas Hofweber eds 2000 Empty Names Fiction and the Puzzles of Non Existence Bobzien Susanne 2021 Frege plagiarized the Stoics In Fiona Leigh ed Themes in Plato Aristotle and Hellenistic Philosophy Keeling Lectures 2011 2018 OPEN ACCESS University of Chicago Press pp 149 206 Willard Dallas 1980 Husserl on a Logic that Failed Philosophical Review 89 1 52 53 doi 10 2307 2184863 JSTOR 2184863 Jeff Speaks Frege s theory of reference 2011 Dummett 1993 p 5 History of Logic by Arthur Prior Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1961 p 541 Michael Beaney ed The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy Oxford University Press 2013 p 383 Jonkers Peter 2003 Perspectives on Twentieth Century Philosophy A Reply to Tom Rockmore Ars Disputandi 3 doi 10 1080 15665399 2003 10819802 ISSN 1566 5399 S2CID 70060684 p 449 Russell Bertrand 1905 On Denoting Mind 14 473 493 Archived from the original on 31 March 2006 Desmet amp Irvine 2022 6 MetaphysicsPalmer 1998 p 175 Baillie James Introduction to Bertrand Russell in Contemporary Analytic Philosophy Second Edition Prentice Hall 1997 p 25 Ryan Alan Bertrand Russell A Political Life United States Farrar Straus and Giroux 1981 p 23 Savants Move to Abandon Metaphysical Philosophy Baltimore Sun 31 December 1935 Carnap R 1928 The Logical Structure of the World Felix Meiner Verlag ISBN 978 0 8126 9523 6 LCCN 66013604 An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 1748 sect 12 pt 3 Lackey Douglas P 1999 What Are the Modern Classics The Baruch Poll of Great Philosophy in the Twentieth Century The Philosophical Forum 30 4 329 346 doi 10 1111 0031 806X 00022 ISSN 1467 9191 Longworth Guy 2017 John Langshaw Austin in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 21 July 2020 Weblin Mark Idealism in Australia and New Zealand The Northern Line No 3 May 2007 p 6 Retrieved 17 January 2011 Hacker P M S 4 July 2003 Obituary Georg Henrik von Wright The Guardian Retrieved 5 July 2020 a b Van Inwagen Peter and Dean Zimmerman eds 1998 Metaphysics The Big Questions a b Quine W V O 1951 Two Dogmas of Empiricism The Philosophical Review 60 1 20 43 doi 10 2307 2181906 JSTOR 2181906 Reprinted in his 1953 From a Logical Point of View Harvard University Press S Yablo and A Gallois Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes Vol 72 1998 pp 229 261 263 283 first part Archived 12 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine Peter Godfrey Smith Theory and Reality 2003 University of Chicago ISBN 0 226 30062 5 pages 30 33 section 2 4 Problems and Changes a b Soames Scott 2005 Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century Volume 2 The Age of Meaning Princeton University Press Cited in Byrne Alex and Hall Ned 2004 Necessary Truths Boston Review October November 2004 a b Zimmerman Dean W Prologue in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics Volume 1 Oxford University Press 2004 p xix Bird Alexander Tobin Emma 2024 Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds Natural Kinds The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2024 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 22 April 2024 Hitchcock Christopher 6 March 2015 Lewis on Causation A Companion to David Lewis Oxford UK John Wiley amp Sons Ltd pp 295 311 doi 10 1002 9781118398593 ch19 ISBN 978 1 118 39859 3 a b Lewis David March 1986 Against structural universals Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 1 25 46 doi 10 1080 00048408612342211 ISSN 0004 8402 Jackson Frank 2016 Armstrong David Malet 1926 2014 Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1 ed London Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 v035 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 retrieved 21 July 2020 Armstrong David Malet 1995 Universals and scientific realism Cambridge Univ Press ISBN 0 521 28033 8 OCLC 174240749 Cotnoir A J and Varzi Achille C Mereology United Kingdom OUP Oxford 2021 p 2 a b van Inwagen 1983 Kane 2005 p 23 Identity Personal Identity and the Self p 103 Pruss Leibnizian Cosmological Arguments Loux amp Crisp 2017 pp 206 214 215 Personal Identity and Resurrection Logical Pluralism global oup com Retrieved 5 February 2017 Gettier Edmund 15 July 2020 Is Justified True Belief Knowledge PDF Arguing About Knowledge Routledge pp 14 15 doi 10 4324 9781003061038 5 ISBN 978 1 003 06103 8 S2CID 243290967 The Web of Belief Bonjour Laurence Recent Work on the Internalism Externalism Controversy in Dancy Sosa and Steup eds A Companion to Epistemology Second Edition Wiley Blackwell 2010 p 33 Rahman Shahid Symons John Gabbay Dov M bendegem jean paul van 2009 Logic Epistemology and the Unity of Science Dordrecht Springer Science amp Business Media p 92 ISBN 978 1 4020 2807 6 Vaught Robert L December 1986 Alfred Tarski s Work in Model Theory Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 4 ASL 869 882 doi 10 2307 2273900 JSTOR 2273900 Feferman amp Feferman p 1 Mulligan Kevin Simons Peter Smith Barry 1984 Truth Makers Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 3 287 321 doi 10 2307 2107686 JSTOR 2107686 Luper Steven 31 December 2001 Epistemic Closure The Epistemic Closure Principle Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Brady Michael Pritchard Duncan 2005 Epistemological Contextualism Problems and Prospects The Philosophical Quarterly 55 219 161 171 doi 10 1111 j 0031 8094 2005 00393 x a b Schwartz Stephen P 2012 A Brief History of Analytic Philosophy From Russell to Rawls John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 27172 8 Kuusela Oskari 2011 Key Terms in Ethics London Continuum International Publishing Group p 61 ISBN 978 1 4411 6610 4 Philippa Foot The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect Archived 24 August 2019 at the Wayback Machine in Virtues and Vices Oxford Basil Blackwell 1978 originally in the Oxford Review No 5 1967 From the cover of the 2000 Harvard University Press edition of Intention Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy Ikuenobe Polycarp 2006 Philosophical Perspectives on Communalism and Morality in African Traditions Oxford Lexington Books p 104 ISBN 978 0 7391 1131 4 Brennan Andrew and Yeuk Sze Lo 2002 Environmental Ethics 2 Archived 1 August 2013 at the Wayback Machine in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Gruen Lori 2003 The Moral Status of Animals in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy See Hursthouse Rosalind 2003 Virtue Ethics 3 in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and Donchin Anne 2004 Feminist Bioethics in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Heyting Frieda Lenzen Dieter White John 2002 Methods in Philosophy of Education New York Routledge pp 18 ISBN 978 0 415 24260 8 Susanne Langer Feeling and Form A Theory of Art 1953 Nelson Goodman Languages of Art An Approach to a Theory of Symbols Indianapolis Bobbs Merrill 1968 2nd ed Indianapolis Hackett 1976 Based on his 1960 61 John Locke lectures Kivy Peter Introduction Aesthetics Today in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics Blackwell Publishing 2004 p 4 Adajian Thomas The Definition of Art The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy London Oct 23 2007 Guy Sircello Love and Beauty Princeton NJ Princeton University Press 1989 Guy Sircello How Is a Theory of the Sublime Possible The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Vol 51 No 4 Autumn 1993 pp 541 550 Guy Sircello A New Theory of Beauty Princeton Essays on the Arts 1 Princeton NJ Princeton University Press 1975 Tatarkiewicz Wladyslaw 1980 A History of Six Ideas an essay in aesthetics PWN Polish Scientific Publishers ISBN 978 8301008246 Keith Donnellan Reference and Definite Descriptions Postrel and Feser February 2000 Reality Principles An Interview with John R Searle at Reality Principles An Interview with John R Searle February 2000 Archived from the original on 29 September 2008 Retrieved 23 September 2008 Graham George Behaviorism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2010 Edition Edward N Zalta ed 1 Brains and Behavior Hilary Putnam Zalta Edward N ed Dualism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body www3 nd edu Retrieved 22 April 2024 Dennett D 2001 Are we explaining consciousness yet Cognition 79 1 2 221 237 doi 10 1016 S0010 0277 00 00130 X PMID 11164029 S2CID 2235514 For summaries and some criticism of the different higher order theories see Van Gulick Robert 2006 Mirror Mirror Is That All In Kriegel amp Williford eds Self Representational Approaches to Consciousness Cambridge MA MIT Press The final draft is also available here Archived copy PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2 October 2008 Retrieved 23 September 2008 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link For Van Gulick s own view see Van Gulick Robert Higher Order Global States HOGS An Alternative Higher Order Model of Consciousness In Gennaro R J ed Higher Order Theories of Consciousness An Anthology Amsterdam and Philadelphia John Benjamins Restall Greg 2002 2006 Great Moments in Logic Archived from the original on 6 December 2008 Retrieved 3 January 2009 Wigner E P 1960 The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences Richard Courant lecture in mathematical sciences delivered at New York University May 11 1959 Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13 1 1 14 Bibcode 1960CPAM 13 1W doi 10 1002 cpa 3160130102 S2CID 6112252 Archived from the original on 12 February 2021 Infinity An Essay In Metaphysics Quine On What There Is The Reason s Proper Study Essays Towards a Neo Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics Harris James Franklin 2002 Analytic philosophy of religion Dordrecht Kluwer ISBN 978 1 4020 0530 5 432 pages volume 3 of Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion ISSN 1568 1556 Peterson Michael et al 2003 Reason and Religious Belief Emeritae and Emeriti Department of Philosophy University of Notre Dame Archived from the original on 31 August 2013 Mackie John L 1982 The Miracle of Theism Arguments For and Against the Existence of God Adams Robert M 1987 The Virtue of Faith And Other Essays in Philosophical Theology Creegan Charles 1989 Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard Religion Individuality and Philosophical Method Wittgenstein Tolstoy and the Gospel in Brief 2001 Retrieved 11 April 2024 Phillips D Z 1999 Philosophy s Cool Place Cornell University Press The quote is from Wittgenstein s Culture and Value 2e My ideal is a certain coolness A temple providing a setting for the passions without meddling with them Zalta Edward N ed Fideism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Nielsen Kai and D Z Phillips 2005 Wittgensteinian Fideism Fitelson Branden Hawthorne James 2010 How Bayesian Confirmation Theory Handles the Paradox of the Ravens The Place of Probability in Science Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol 284 Springer pp 247 275 doi 10 1007 978 90 481 3615 5 11 ISBN 978 90 481 3614 8 Popper Karl R 2002 The Logic of Scientific Discovery Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 27844 7 Glock 2008 p 47 Hull David L and Ruse Michael Preface in The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Cambridge University Press 2007 pp xix xx Lennox James G Darwinism and Neo Darwinism in Sakar and Plutynski eds A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology Blackwell Publishing 2008 p 89 Books and articles editAristotle Metaphysics Desmet Ronald Irvine Andrew David 2022 Alfred North Whitehead The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 1 April 2024 Dummett Michael 1993 The Origins of Analytical Philosophy Cambridge MA Harvard University Press Geach P Mental Acts London 1957 Kane Robert 2005 A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 514970 8 Retrieved 13 April 2020 Kenny A J P Wittgenstein London 1973 Loux Michael J Crisp Thomas M 2017 Metaphysics A Contemporary Introduction 4 ed Routledge ISBN 978 1 138 63933 1 Palmer Clare 1998 Environmental Ethics and Process Thinking Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 826952 6 Archived from the original on 2 April 2024 Retrieved 4 April 2024 Aaron Preston Analytic philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Soames Scott Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century Volume 1 The Dawn of Analysis Princeton Princeton University Press 2003 van Inwagen Peter 1983 An Essay on Free Will Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824924 5 Retrieved 27 December 2012 Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico PhilosophicusFurther reading editThe London Philosophy Study Guide Archived 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read depending on the student s familiarity with the subject Frege Russell and Wittgenstein Hirschberger Johannes A Short History of Western Philosophy ed Clare Hay Short History of Western Philosophy A ISBN 978 0 7188 3092 2 Hylton Peter Russell Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press 1990 Passmore John A Hundred Years of Philosophy revised ed New York Basic Books 1966 Weitz Morris ed Twentieth Century Philosophy The Analytic Tradition New York Free Press 1966 External links edit Analytic philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Zalta Edward N ed Conceptions of Analysis in Analytic Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Analytic philosophy at Curlie Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Analytic philosophy amp oldid 1225133712 History, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.