fbpx
Wikipedia

Infinity

Infinity is something which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is often denoted by the infinity symbol .

Due to the constant light reflection between opposing mirrors, it seems that there is a boundless amount of space and repetition inside of them.

Since the time of the ancient Greeks, the philosophical nature of infinity was the subject of many discussions among philosophers. In the 17th century, with the introduction of the infinity symbol[1] and the infinitesimal calculus, mathematicians began to work with infinite series and what some mathematicians (including l'Hôpital and Bernoulli)[2] regarded as infinitely small quantities, but infinity continued to be associated with endless processes. As mathematicians struggled with the foundation of calculus, it remained unclear whether infinity could be considered as a number or magnitude and, if so, how this could be done.[1] At the end of the 19th century, Georg Cantor enlarged the mathematical study of infinity by studying infinite sets and infinite numbers, showing that they can be of various sizes.[1][3] For example, if a line is viewed as the set of all of its points, their infinite number (i.e., the cardinality of the line) is larger than the number of integers.[4] In this usage, infinity is a mathematical concept, and infinite mathematical objects can be studied, manipulated, and used just like any other mathematical object.

The mathematical concept of infinity refines and extends the old philosophical concept, in particular by introducing infinitely many different sizes of infinite sets. Among the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, on which most of modern mathematics can be developed, is the axiom of infinity, which guarantees the existence of infinite sets.[1] The mathematical concept of infinity and the manipulation of infinite sets are widely used in mathematics, even in areas such as combinatorics that may seem to have nothing to do with them. For example, Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem implicitly relies on the existence of Grothendieck universes, very large infinite sets,[5] for solving a long-standing problem that is stated in terms of elementary arithmetic.

In physics and cosmology, whether the Universe is spatially infinite is an open question.

History edit

Ancient cultures had various ideas about the nature of infinity. The ancient Indians and the Greeks did not define infinity in precise formalism as does modern mathematics, and instead approached infinity as a philosophical concept.

Early Greek edit

The earliest recorded idea of infinity in Greece may be that of Anaximander (c. 610 – c. 546 BC) a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher. He used the word apeiron, which means "unbounded", "indefinite", and perhaps can be translated as "infinite".[1][6]

Aristotle (350 BC) distinguished potential infinity from actual infinity, which he regarded as impossible due to the various paradoxes it seemed to produce.[7] It has been argued that, in line with this view, the Hellenistic Greeks had a "horror of the infinite"[8][9] which would, for example, explain why Euclid (c. 300 BC) did not say that there are an infinity of primes but rather "Prime numbers are more than any assigned multitude of prime numbers."[10] It has also been maintained, that, in proving the infinitude of the prime numbers, Euclid "was the first to overcome the horror of the infinite".[11] There is a similar controversy concerning Euclid's parallel postulate, sometimes translated:

If a straight line falling across two [other] straight lines makes internal angles on the same side [of itself whose sum is] less than two right angles, then the two [other] straight lines, being produced to infinity, meet on that side [of the original straight line] that the [sum of the internal angles] is less than two right angles.[12]

Other translators, however, prefer the translation "the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely ...",[13] thus avoiding the implication that Euclid was comfortable with the notion of infinity. Finally, it has been maintained that a reflection on infinity, far from eliciting a "horror of the infinite", underlay all of early Greek philosophy and that Aristotle's "potential infinity" is an aberration from the general trend of this period.[14]

Zeno: Achilles and the tortoise edit

Zeno of Elea (c. 495 – c. 430 BC) did not advance any views concerning the infinite. Nevertheless, his paradoxes,[15] especially "Achilles and the Tortoise", were important contributions in that they made clear the inadequacy of popular conceptions. The paradoxes were described by Bertrand Russell as "immeasurably subtle and profound".[16]

Achilles races a tortoise, giving the latter a head start.

  • Step #1: Achilles runs to the tortoise's starting point while the tortoise walks forward.
  • Step #2: Achilles advances to where the tortoise was at the end of Step #1 while the tortoise goes yet further.
  • Step #3: Achilles advances to where the tortoise was at the end of Step #2 while the tortoise goes yet further.
  • Step #4: Achilles advances to where the tortoise was at the end of Step #3 while the tortoise goes yet further.

Etc.

Apparently, Achilles never overtakes the tortoise, since however many steps he completes, the tortoise remains ahead of him.

Zeno was not attempting to make a point about infinity. As a member of the Eleatics school which regarded motion as an illusion, he saw it as a mistake to suppose that Achilles could run at all. Subsequent thinkers, finding this solution unacceptable, struggled for over two millennia to find other weaknesses in the argument.

Finally, in 1821, Augustin-Louis Cauchy provided both a satisfactory definition of a limit and a proof that, for 0 < x < 1,[17]

 

Suppose that Achilles is running at 10 meters per second, the tortoise is walking at 0.1 meters per second, and the latter has a 100-meter head start. The duration of the chase fits Cauchy's pattern with a = 10 seconds and x = 0.01. Achilles does overtake the tortoise; it takes him

 

Early Indian edit

The Jain mathematical text Surya Prajnapti (c. 4th–3rd century BCE) classifies all numbers into three sets: enumerable, innumerable, and infinite. Each of these was further subdivided into three orders:[18]

  • Enumerable: lowest, intermediate, and highest
  • Innumerable: nearly innumerable, truly innumerable, and innumerably innumerable
  • Infinite: nearly infinite, truly infinite, infinitely infinite

17th century edit

In the 17th century, European mathematicians started using infinite numbers and infinite expressions in a systematic fashion. In 1655, John Wallis first used the notation   for such a number in his De sectionibus conicis,[19] and exploited it in area calculations by dividing the region into infinitesimal strips of width on the order of  [20] But in Arithmetica infinitorum (1656),[21] he indicates infinite series, infinite products and infinite continued fractions by writing down a few terms or factors and then appending "&c.", as in "1, 6, 12, 18, 24, &c."[22]

In 1699, Isaac Newton wrote about equations with an infinite number of terms in his work De analysi per aequationes numero terminorum infinitas.[23]

Mathematics edit

Hermann Weyl opened a mathematico-philosophic address given in 1930 with:[24]

Mathematics is the science of the infinite.

Symbol edit

The infinity symbol   (sometimes called the lemniscate) is a mathematical symbol representing the concept of infinity. The symbol is encoded in Unicode at U+221E INFINITY (&infin;)[25] and in LaTeX as \infty.[26]

It was introduced in 1655 by John Wallis,[27][28] and since its introduction, it has also been used outside mathematics in modern mysticism[29] and literary symbology.[30]

Calculus edit

Gottfried Leibniz, one of the co-inventors of infinitesimal calculus, speculated widely about infinite numbers and their use in mathematics. To Leibniz, both infinitesimals and infinite quantities were ideal entities, not of the same nature as appreciable quantities, but enjoying the same properties in accordance with the Law of continuity.[31][2]

Real analysis edit

In real analysis, the symbol  , called "infinity", is used to denote an unbounded limit.[32] The notation   means that   increases without bound, and   means that   decreases without bound. For example, if   for every  , then[33]

  •   means that   does not bound a finite area from   to  
  •   means that the area under   is infinite.
  •   means that the total area under   is finite, and is equal to  

Infinity can also be used to describe infinite series, as follows:

  •   means that the sum of the infinite series converges to some real value  
  •   means that the sum of the infinite series properly diverges to infinity, in the sense that the partial sums increase without bound.[34]

In addition to defining a limit, infinity can be also used as a value in the extended real number system. Points labeled   and   can be added to the topological space of the real numbers, producing the two-point compactification of the real numbers. Adding algebraic properties to this gives us the extended real numbers.[35] We can also treat   and   as the same, leading to the one-point compactification of the real numbers, which is the real projective line.[36] Projective geometry also refers to a line at infinity in plane geometry, a plane at infinity in three-dimensional space, and a hyperplane at infinity for general dimensions, each consisting of points at infinity.[37]

Complex analysis edit

 
By stereographic projection, the complex plane can be "wrapped" onto a sphere, with the top point of the sphere corresponding to infinity. This is called the Riemann sphere.

In complex analysis the symbol  , called "infinity", denotes an unsigned infinite limit. The expression   means that the magnitude   of   grows beyond any assigned value. A point labeled   can be added to the complex plane as a topological space giving the one-point compactification of the complex plane. When this is done, the resulting space is a one-dimensional complex manifold, or Riemann surface, called the extended complex plane or the Riemann sphere.[38] Arithmetic operations similar to those given above for the extended real numbers can also be defined, though there is no distinction in the signs (which leads to the one exception that infinity cannot be added to itself). On the other hand, this kind of infinity enables division by zero, namely   for any nonzero complex number  . In this context, it is often useful to consider meromorphic functions as maps into the Riemann sphere taking the value of   at the poles. The domain of a complex-valued function may be extended to include the point at infinity as well. One important example of such functions is the group of Möbius transformations (see Möbius transformation § Overview).

Nonstandard analysis edit

 
Infinitesimals (ε) and infinities (ω) on the hyperreal number line (1/ε = ω/1)

The original formulation of infinitesimal calculus by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz used infinitesimal quantities. In the second half of the 20th century, it was shown that this treatment could be put on a rigorous footing through various logical systems, including smooth infinitesimal analysis and nonstandard analysis. In the latter, infinitesimals are invertible, and their inverses are infinite numbers. The infinities in this sense are part of a hyperreal field; there is no equivalence between them as with the Cantorian transfinites. For example, if H is an infinite number in this sense, then H + H = 2H and H + 1 are distinct infinite numbers. This approach to non-standard calculus is fully developed in Keisler (1986).

Set theory edit

 
One-to-one correspondence between an infinite set and its proper subset

A different form of "infinity" are the ordinal and cardinal infinities of set theory—a system of transfinite numbers first developed by Georg Cantor. In this system, the first transfinite cardinal is aleph-null (0), the cardinality of the set of natural numbers. This modern mathematical conception of the quantitative infinite developed in the late 19th century from works by Cantor, Gottlob Frege, Richard Dedekind and others—using the idea of collections or sets.[1]

Dedekind's approach was essentially to adopt the idea of one-to-one correspondence as a standard for comparing the size of sets, and to reject the view of Galileo (derived from Euclid) that the whole cannot be the same size as the part. (However, see Galileo's paradox where Galileo concludes that positive integers cannot be compared to the subset of positive square integers since both are infinite sets.) An infinite set can simply be defined as one having the same size as at least one of its proper parts; this notion of infinity is called Dedekind infinite. The diagram to the right gives an example: viewing lines as infinite sets of points, the left half of the lower blue line can be mapped in a one-to-one manner (green correspondences) to the higher blue line, and, in turn, to the whole lower blue line (red correspondences); therefore the whole lower blue line and its left half have the same cardinality, i.e. "size".[citation needed]

Cantor defined two kinds of infinite numbers: ordinal numbers and cardinal numbers. Ordinal numbers characterize well-ordered sets, or counting carried on to any stopping point, including points after an infinite number have already been counted. Generalizing finite and (ordinary) infinite sequences which are maps from the positive integers leads to mappings from ordinal numbers to transfinite sequences. Cardinal numbers define the size of sets, meaning how many members they contain, and can be standardized by choosing the first ordinal number of a certain size to represent the cardinal number of that size. The smallest ordinal infinity is that of the positive integers, and any set which has the cardinality of the integers is countably infinite. If a set is too large to be put in one-to-one correspondence with the positive integers, it is called uncountable. Cantor's views prevailed and modern mathematics accepts actual infinity as part of a consistent and coherent theory.[39][40][page needed] Certain extended number systems, such as the hyperreal numbers, incorporate the ordinary (finite) numbers and infinite numbers of different sizes.[citation needed]

Cardinality of the continuum edit

One of Cantor's most important results was that the cardinality of the continuum   is greater than that of the natural numbers  ; that is, there are more real numbers R than natural numbers N. Namely, Cantor showed that  .[41]

The continuum hypothesis states that there is no cardinal number between the cardinality of the reals and the cardinality of the natural numbers, that is,  .

This hypothesis cannot be proved or disproved within the widely accepted Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, even assuming the Axiom of Choice.[42]

Cardinal arithmetic can be used to show not only that the number of points in a real number line is equal to the number of points in any segment of that line, but also that this is equal to the number of points on a plane and, indeed, in any finite-dimensional space.[citation needed]

 
The first three steps of a fractal construction whose limit is a space-filling curve, showing that there are as many points in a one-dimensional line as in a two-dimensional square

The first of these results is apparent by considering, for instance, the tangent function, which provides a one-to-one correspondence between the interval (π/2, π/2) and R.

The second result was proved by Cantor in 1878, but only became intuitively apparent in 1890, when Giuseppe Peano introduced the space-filling curves, curved lines that twist and turn enough to fill the whole of any square, or cube, or hypercube, or finite-dimensional space. These curves can be used to define a one-to-one correspondence between the points on one side of a square and the points in the square.[43]

Geometry edit

Until the end of the 19th century, infinity was rarely discussed in geometry, except in the context of processes that could be continued without any limit. For example, a line was what is now called a line segment, with the proviso that one can extend it as far as one wants; but extending it infinitely was out of the question. Similarly, a line was usually not considered to be composed of infinitely many points, but was a location where a point may be placed. Even if there are infinitely many possible positions, only a finite number of points could be placed on a line. A witness of this is the expression "the locus of a point that satisfies some property" (singular), where modern mathematicians would generally say "the set of the points that have the property" (plural).

One of the rare exceptions of a mathematical concept involving actual infinity was projective geometry, where points at infinity are added to the Euclidean space for modeling the perspective effect that shows parallel lines intersecting "at infinity". Mathematically, points at infinity have the advantage of allowing one to not consider some special cases. For example, in a projective plane, two distinct lines intersect in exactly one point, whereas without points at infinity, there are no intersection points for parallel lines. So, parallel and non-parallel lines must be studied separately in classical geometry, while they need not to be distinguished in projective geometry.

Before the use of set theory for the foundation of mathematics, points and lines were viewed as distinct entities, and a point could be located on a line. With the universal use of set theory in mathematics, the point of view has dramatically changed: a line is now considered as the set of its points, and one says that a point belongs to a line instead of is located on a line (however, the latter phrase is still used).

In particular, in modern mathematics, lines are infinite sets.

Infinite dimension edit

The vector spaces that occur in classical geometry have always a finite dimension, generally two or three. However, this is not implied by the abstract definition of a vector space, and vector spaces of infinite dimension can be considered. This is typically the case in functional analysis where function spaces are generally vector spaces of infinite dimension.

In topology, some constructions can generate topological spaces of infinite dimension. In particular, this is the case of iterated loop spaces.

Fractals edit

The structure of a fractal object is reiterated in its magnifications. Fractals can be magnified indefinitely without losing their structure and becoming "smooth"; they have infinite perimeters, and can have infinite or finite areas. One such fractal curve with an infinite perimeter and finite area is the Koch snowflake.[citation needed]

Mathematics without infinity edit

Leopold Kronecker was skeptical of the notion of infinity and how his fellow mathematicians were using it in the 1870s and 1880s. This skepticism was developed in the philosophy of mathematics called finitism, an extreme form of mathematical philosophy in the general philosophical and mathematical schools of constructivism and intuitionism.[44]

Physics edit

In physics, approximations of real numbers are used for continuous measurements and natural numbers are used for discrete measurements (i.e., counting). Concepts of infinite things such as an infinite plane wave exist, but there are no experimental means to generate them.[45]

Cosmology edit

The first published proposal that the universe is infinite came from Thomas Digges in 1576.[46] Eight years later, in 1584, the Italian philosopher and astronomer Giordano Bruno proposed an unbounded universe in On the Infinite Universe and Worlds: "Innumerable suns exist; innumerable earths revolve around these suns in a manner similar to the way the seven planets revolve around our sun. Living beings inhabit these worlds."[47]

Cosmologists have long sought to discover whether infinity exists in our physical universe: Are there an infinite number of stars? Does the universe have infinite volume? Does space "go on forever"? This is still an open question of cosmology. The question of being infinite is logically separate from the question of having boundaries. The two-dimensional surface of the Earth, for example, is finite, yet has no edge. By travelling in a straight line with respect to the Earth's curvature, one will eventually return to the exact spot one started from. The universe, at least in principle, might have a similar topology. If so, one might eventually return to one's starting point after travelling in a straight line through the universe for long enough.[48]

The curvature of the universe can be measured through multipole moments in the spectrum of the cosmic background radiation. To date, analysis of the radiation patterns recorded by the WMAP spacecraft hints that the universe has a flat topology. This would be consistent with an infinite physical universe.[49][50][51]

However, the universe could be finite, even if its curvature is flat. An easy way to understand this is to consider two-dimensional examples, such as video games where items that leave one edge of the screen reappear on the other. The topology of such games is toroidal and the geometry is flat. Many possible bounded, flat possibilities also exist for three-dimensional space.[52]

The concept of infinity also extends to the multiverse hypothesis, which, when explained by astrophysicists such as Michio Kaku, posits that there are an infinite number and variety of universes.[53] Also, cyclic models posit an infinite amount of Big Bangs, resulting in an infinite variety of universes after each Big Bang event in an infinite cycle.[54]

Logic edit

In logic, an infinite regress argument is "a distinctively philosophical kind of argument purporting to show that a thesis is defective because it generates an infinite series when either (form A) no such series exists or (form B) were it to exist, the thesis would lack the role (e.g., of justification) that it is supposed to play."[55]

Computing edit

The IEEE floating-point standard (IEEE 754) specifies a positive and a negative infinity value (and also indefinite values). These are defined as the result of arithmetic overflow, division by zero, and other exceptional operations.[56]

Some programming languages, such as Java[57] and J,[58] allow the programmer an explicit access to the positive and negative infinity values as language constants. These can be used as greatest and least elements, as they compare (respectively) greater than or less than all other values. They have uses as sentinel values in algorithms involving sorting, searching, or windowing.[citation needed]

In languages that do not have greatest and least elements, but do allow overloading of relational operators, it is possible for a programmer to create the greatest and least elements. In languages that do not provide explicit access to such values from the initial state of the program, but do implement the floating-point data type, the infinity values may still be accessible and usable as the result of certain operations.[citation needed]

In programming, an infinite loop is a loop whose exit condition is never satisfied, thus executing indefinitely.

Arts, games, and cognitive sciences edit

Perspective artwork uses the concept of vanishing points, roughly corresponding to mathematical points at infinity, located at an infinite distance from the observer. This allows artists to create paintings that realistically render space, distances, and forms.[59] Artist M.C. Escher is specifically known for employing the concept of infinity in his work in this and other ways.[citation needed]

Variations of chess played on an unbounded board are called infinite chess.[60][61]

Cognitive scientist George Lakoff considers the concept of infinity in mathematics and the sciences as a metaphor. This perspective is based on the basic metaphor of infinity (BMI), defined as the ever-increasing sequence <1,2,3,...>.[62]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f Allen, Donald (2003). "The History of Infinity" (PDF). Texas A&M Mathematics. Retrieved Nov 15, 2019.
  2. ^ a b Jesseph, Douglas Michael (Spring–Summer 1998). . Perspectives on Science. 6 (1&2): 6–40. doi:10.1162/posc_a_00543. ISSN 1063-6145. OCLC 42413222. S2CID 118227996. Archived from the original on 11 January 2012. Retrieved 1 November 2019 – via Project MUSE.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  3. ^ Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June (2008). The Princeton companion to mathematics. Imre Leader, Princeton University. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-3039-8. OCLC 659590835.
  4. ^ Maddox 2002, pp. 113–117
  5. ^ McLarty, Colin (15 January 2014) [September 2010]. "What Does it Take to Prove Fermat's Last Theorem? Grothendieck and the Logic of Number Theory". The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 16 (3): 359–377. doi:10.2178/bsl/1286284558. S2CID 13475845 – via Cambridge University Press.
  6. ^ Wallace 2004, p. 44
  7. ^ Aristotle. Physics. Translated by Hardie, R. P.; Gaye, R. K. The Internet Classics Archive. Book 3, Chapters 5–8.
  8. ^ Goodman, Nicolas D. (1981). "Reflections on Bishop's philosophy of mathematics". In Richman, F. (ed.). Constructive Mathematics. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Vol. 873. Springer. pp. 135–145. doi:10.1007/BFb0090732. ISBN 978-3-540-10850-4.
  9. ^ Maor, p. 3
  10. ^ Sarton, George (March 1928). "The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements. Thomas L. Heath, Heiberg". Isis. 10 (1): 60–62. doi:10.1086/346308. ISSN 0021-1753 – via The University of Chicago Press Journals.
  11. ^ Hutten, Ernest Hirschlaff (1962). The origins of science; an inquiry into the foundations of Western thought. Internet Archive. London, Allen and Unwin. pp. 1–241. ISBN 978-0-04-946007-2. Retrieved 2020-01-09.
  12. ^ Euclid (2008) [c. 300 BC]. Euclid's Elements of Geometry (PDF). Translated by Fitzpatrick, Richard. Lulu.com. p. 6 (Book I, Postulate 5). ISBN 978-0-6151-7984-1.
  13. ^ Heath, Sir Thomas Little; Heiberg, Johan Ludvig (1908). The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements. Vol. v. 1. The University Press. p. 212.
  14. ^ Drozdek, Adam (2008). In the Beginning Was the Apeiron: Infinity in Greek Philosophy. Stuttgart, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag. ISBN 978-3-515-09258-6.
  15. ^ "Zeno's Paradoxes". Stanford University. October 15, 2010. Retrieved April 3, 2017.
  16. ^ Russell 1996, p. 347
  17. ^ Cauchy, Augustin-Louis (1821). Cours d'Analyse de l'École Royale Polytechnique. Libraires du Roi & de la Bibliothèque du Roi. p. 124. Retrieved October 12, 2019.
  18. ^ Ian Stewart (2017). Infinity: a Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 117. ISBN 978-0-19-875523-4. from the original on April 3, 2017.
  19. ^ Cajori, Florian (2007). A History of Mathematical Notations. Vol. 1. Cosimo, Inc. p. 214. ISBN 9781602066854.
  20. ^ Cajori 1993, Sec. 421, Vol. II, p. 44
  21. ^ "Arithmetica Infinitorum".
  22. ^ Cajori 1993, Sec. 435, Vol. II, p. 58
  23. ^ Grattan-Guinness, Ivor (2005). Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640-1940. Elsevier. p. 62. ISBN 978-0-08-045744-4. from the original on 2016-06-03. Extract of p. 62
  24. ^ Weyl, Hermann (2012), Peter Pesic (ed.), Levels of Infinity / Selected Writings on Mathematics and Philosophy, Dover, p. 17, ISBN 978-0-486-48903-2
  25. ^ AG, Compart. "Unicode Character "∞" (U+221E)". Compart.com. Retrieved 2019-11-15.
  26. ^ "List of LaTeX mathematical symbols - OeisWiki". oeis.org. Retrieved 2019-11-15.
  27. ^ Scott, Joseph Frederick (1981), The mathematical work of John Wallis, D.D., F.R.S., (1616–1703) (2 ed.), American Mathematical Society, p. 24, ISBN 978-0-8284-0314-6, from the original on 2016-05-09
  28. ^ Martin-Löf, Per (1990), "Mathematics of infinity", COLOG-88 (Tallinn, 1988), Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 417, Berlin: Springer, pp. 146–197, doi:10.1007/3-540-52335-9_54, ISBN 978-3-540-52335-2, MR 1064143
  29. ^ O'Flaherty, Wendy Doniger (1986), Dreams, Illusion, and Other Realities, University of Chicago Press, p. 243, ISBN 978-0-226-61855-5, from the original on 2016-06-29
  30. ^ Toker, Leona (1989), Nabokov: The Mystery of Literary Structures, Cornell University Press, p. 159, ISBN 978-0-8014-2211-9, from the original on 2016-05-09
  31. ^ Bell, John Lane. "Continuity and Infinitesimals". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  32. ^ Taylor 1955, p. 63
  33. ^ These uses of infinity for integrals and series can be found in any standard calculus text, such as, Swokowski 1983, pp. 468–510
  34. ^ "Properly Divergent Sequences - Mathonline". mathonline.wikidot.com. Retrieved 2019-11-15.
  35. ^ Aliprantis, Charalambos D.; Burkinshaw, Owen (1998), Principles of Real Analysis (3rd ed.), San Diego, CA: Academic Press, Inc., p. 29, ISBN 978-0-12-050257-8, MR 1669668, from the original on 2015-05-15
  36. ^ Gemignani 1990, p. 177
  37. ^ Beutelspacher, Albrecht; Rosenbaum, Ute (1998), Projective Geometry / from foundations to applications, Cambridge University Press, p. 27, ISBN 978-0-521-48364-3
  38. ^ Rao, Murali; Stetkær, Henrik (1991). Complex Analysis: An Invitation : a Concise Introduction to Complex Function Theory. World Scientific. p. 113. ISBN 9789810203757.
  39. ^ "Infinity". math.dartmouth.edu. Retrieved 2019-11-16.
  40. ^ Moore, A.W. (1991). The Infinite. Routledge.
  41. ^ Dauben, Joseph (1993). "Georg Cantor and the Battle for Transfinite Set Theory" (PDF). 9th ACMS Conference Proceedings: 4.
  42. ^ Cohen 1963, p. 1143
  43. ^ Sagan 1994, pp. 10–12
  44. ^ Kline 1972, pp. 1197–1198
  45. ^ Doric Lenses 2013-01-24 at the Wayback Machine – Application Note – Axicons – 2. Intensity Distribution. Retrieved 7 April 2014.
  46. ^ John Gribbin (2009), In Search of the Multiverse: Parallel Worlds, Hidden Dimensions, and the Ultimate Quest for the Frontiers of Reality, ISBN 978-0-470-61352-8. p. 88
  47. ^ Brake, Mark (2013). Alien Life Imagined: Communicating the Science and Culture of Astrobiology (illustrated ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 63. ISBN 978-0-521-49129-7.
  48. ^ Koupelis, Theo; Kuhn, Karl F. (2007). In Quest of the Universe (illustrated ed.). Jones & Bartlett Learning. p. 553. ISBN 978-0-7637-4387-1. Extract of p. 553
  49. ^ "Will the Universe expand forever?". NASA. 24 January 2014. from the original on 1 June 2012. Retrieved 16 March 2015.
  50. ^ "Our universe is Flat". FermiLab/SLAC. 7 April 2015. from the original on 10 April 2015.
  51. ^ Marcus Y. Yoo (2011). "Unexpected connections". Engineering & Science. LXXIV1: 30.
  52. ^ Weeks, Jeffrey (2001). The Shape of Space. CRC Press. ISBN 978-0-8247-0709-5.
  53. ^ Kaku, M. (2006). Parallel worlds. Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.
  54. ^ McKee, Maggie (25 September 2014). "Ingenious: Paul J. Steinhardt – The Princeton physicist on what's wrong with inflation theory and his view of the Big Bang". Nautilus. No. 17. NautilusThink Inc. Retrieved 31 March 2017.
  55. ^ Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Second Edition, p. 429
  56. ^ "Infinity and NaN (The GNU C Library)". www.gnu.org. Retrieved 2021-03-15.
  57. ^ Gosling, James; et al. (27 July 2012). "4.2.3.". The Java Language Specification (Java SE 7 ed.). California: Oracle America, Inc. from the original on 9 June 2012. Retrieved 6 September 2012.
  58. ^ Stokes, Roger (July 2012). . Learning J. Archived from the original on 25 March 2012. Retrieved 6 September 2012.
  59. ^ Kline, Morris (1985). Mathematics for the nonmathematician. Courier Dover Publications. p. 229. ISBN 978-0-486-24823-3., Section 10-7, p. 229 2016-05-16 at the Wayback Machine
  60. ^ Infinite chess at the Chess Variant Pages 2017-04-02 at the Wayback Machine An infinite chess scheme.
  61. ^ "Infinite Chess, PBS Infinite Series" 2017-04-07 at the Wayback Machine PBS Infinite Series, with academic sources by J. Hamkins (infinite chess: Evans, C.D.A; Joel David Hamkins (2013). "Transfinite game values in infinite chess". arXiv:1302.4377 [math.LO]. and Evans, C.D.A; Joel David Hamkins; Norman Lewis Perlmutter (2015). "A position in infinite chess with game value $ω^4$". arXiv:1510.08155 [math.LO].).
  62. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-02-26. Retrieved 2021-03-25.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)

Bibliography edit

Sources edit

  • Aczel, Amir D. (2001). The Mystery of the Aleph: Mathematics, the Kabbalah, and the Search for Infinity. New York: Pocket Books. ISBN 978-0-7434-2299-4.
  • D.P. Agrawal (2000). Ancient Jaina Mathematics: an Introduction, Infinity Foundation.
  • Bell, J.L.: Continuity and infinitesimals. Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy. Revised 2009.
  • Cohen, Paul (1963), "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis", Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 50 (6): 1143–1148, Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C, doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143, PMC 221287, PMID 16578557.
  • Jain, L.C. (1982). Exact Sciences from Jaina Sources.
  • Jain, L.C. (1973). "Set theory in the Jaina school of mathematics", Indian Journal of History of Science.
  • Joseph, George G. (2000). The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics (2nd ed.). Penguin Books. ISBN 978-0-14-027778-4.
  • H. Jerome Keisler: Elementary Calculus: An Approach Using Infinitesimals. First edition 1976; 2nd edition 1986. This book is now out of print. The publisher has reverted the copyright to the author, who has made available the 2nd edition in .pdf format available for downloading at http://www.math.wisc.edu/~keisler/calc.html
  • Eli Maor (1991). To Infinity and Beyond. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02511-7.
  • O'Connor, John J. and Edmund F. Robertson (1998). 'Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor' 2006-09-16 at the Wayback Machine, MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • O'Connor, John J. and Edmund F. Robertson (2000). 'Jaina mathematics' 2008-12-20 at the Wayback Machine, MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • Pearce, Ian. (2002). 'Jainism', MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • Rucker, Rudy (1995). Infinity and the Mind: The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-00172-2.
  • Singh, Navjyoti (1988). "Jaina Theory of Actual Infinity and Transfinite Numbers". Journal of the Asiatic Society. 30.

External links edit

  • "The Infinite". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Infinity on In Our Time at the BBC
  • A Crash Course in the Mathematics of Infinite Sets 2010-02-27 at the Wayback Machine, by Peter Suber. From the St. John's Review, XLIV, 2 (1998) 1–59. The stand-alone appendix to Infinite Reflections, below. A concise introduction to Cantor's mathematics of infinite sets.
  • Infinite Reflections 2009-11-05 at the Wayback Machine, by Peter Suber. How Cantor's mathematics of the infinite solves a handful of ancient philosophical problems of the infinite. From the St. John's Review, XLIV, 2 (1998) 1–59.
  • Grime, James. . Numberphile. Brady Haran. Archived from the original on 2017-10-22. Retrieved 2013-04-06.
  • John J. O'Connor and Edmund F. Robertson (1998). 'Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor' 2006-09-16 at the Wayback Machine, MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • John J. O'Connor and Edmund F. Robertson (2000). 'Jaina mathematics' 2008-12-20 at the Wayback Machine, MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • Ian Pearce (2002). 'Jainism', MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • The Mystery Of The Aleph: Mathematics, the Kabbalah, and the Search for Infinity
  • Dictionary of the Infinite (compilation of articles about infinity in physics, mathematics, and philosophy)

infinity, symbol, symbol, other, uses, infinite, disambiguation, confused, with, infiniti, something, which, boundless, endless, larger, than, natural, number, often, denoted, infinity, symbol, displaystyle, infty, constant, light, reflection, between, opposin. For the symbol see Infinity symbol For other uses of Infinity and Infinite see Infinity disambiguation Not to be confused with Infiniti Infinity is something which is boundless endless or larger than any natural number It is often denoted by the infinity symbol displaystyle infty Due to the constant light reflection between opposing mirrors it seems that there is a boundless amount of space and repetition inside of them Since the time of the ancient Greeks the philosophical nature of infinity was the subject of many discussions among philosophers In the 17th century with the introduction of the infinity symbol 1 and the infinitesimal calculus mathematicians began to work with infinite series and what some mathematicians including l Hopital and Bernoulli 2 regarded as infinitely small quantities but infinity continued to be associated with endless processes As mathematicians struggled with the foundation of calculus it remained unclear whether infinity could be considered as a number or magnitude and if so how this could be done 1 At the end of the 19th century Georg Cantor enlarged the mathematical study of infinity by studying infinite sets and infinite numbers showing that they can be of various sizes 1 3 For example if a line is viewed as the set of all of its points their infinite number i e the cardinality of the line is larger than the number of integers 4 In this usage infinity is a mathematical concept and infinite mathematical objects can be studied manipulated and used just like any other mathematical object The mathematical concept of infinity refines and extends the old philosophical concept in particular by introducing infinitely many different sizes of infinite sets Among the axioms of Zermelo Fraenkel set theory on which most of modern mathematics can be developed is the axiom of infinity which guarantees the existence of infinite sets 1 The mathematical concept of infinity and the manipulation of infinite sets are widely used in mathematics even in areas such as combinatorics that may seem to have nothing to do with them For example Wiles s proof of Fermat s Last Theorem implicitly relies on the existence of Grothendieck universes very large infinite sets 5 for solving a long standing problem that is stated in terms of elementary arithmetic In physics and cosmology whether the Universe is spatially infinite is an open question Contents 1 History 1 1 Early Greek 1 2 Zeno Achilles and the tortoise 1 3 Early Indian 1 4 17th century 2 Mathematics 2 1 Symbol 2 2 Calculus 2 2 1 Real analysis 2 2 2 Complex analysis 2 3 Nonstandard analysis 2 4 Set theory 2 4 1 Cardinality of the continuum 2 5 Geometry 2 6 Infinite dimension 2 7 Fractals 2 8 Mathematics without infinity 3 Physics 3 1 Cosmology 4 Logic 5 Computing 6 Arts games and cognitive sciences 7 See also 8 References 8 1 Bibliography 8 2 Sources 9 External linksHistory editFurther information Infinity philosophy Ancient cultures had various ideas about the nature of infinity The ancient Indians and the Greeks did not define infinity in precise formalism as does modern mathematics and instead approached infinity as a philosophical concept Early Greek edit The earliest recorded idea of infinity in Greece may be that of Anaximander c 610 c 546 BC a pre Socratic Greek philosopher He used the word apeiron which means unbounded indefinite and perhaps can be translated as infinite 1 6 Aristotle 350 BC distinguished potential infinity from actual infinity which he regarded as impossible due to the various paradoxes it seemed to produce 7 It has been argued that in line with this view the Hellenistic Greeks had a horror of the infinite 8 9 which would for example explain why Euclid c 300 BC did not say that there are an infinity of primes but rather Prime numbers are more than any assigned multitude of prime numbers 10 It has also been maintained that in proving the infinitude of the prime numbers Euclid was the first to overcome the horror of the infinite 11 There is a similar controversy concerning Euclid s parallel postulate sometimes translated If a straight line falling across two other straight lines makes internal angles on the same side of itself whose sum is less than two right angles then the two other straight lines being produced to infinity meet on that side of the original straight line that the sum of the internal angles is less than two right angles 12 Other translators however prefer the translation the two straight lines if produced indefinitely 13 thus avoiding the implication that Euclid was comfortable with the notion of infinity Finally it has been maintained that a reflection on infinity far from eliciting a horror of the infinite underlay all of early Greek philosophy and that Aristotle s potential infinity is an aberration from the general trend of this period 14 Zeno Achilles and the tortoise edit Main article Zeno s paradoxes Achilles and the tortoise Zeno of Elea c 495 c 430 BC did not advance any views concerning the infinite Nevertheless his paradoxes 15 especially Achilles and the Tortoise were important contributions in that they made clear the inadequacy of popular conceptions The paradoxes were described by Bertrand Russell as immeasurably subtle and profound 16 Achilles races a tortoise giving the latter a head start Step 1 Achilles runs to the tortoise s starting point while the tortoise walks forward Step 2 Achilles advances to where the tortoise was at the end of Step 1 while the tortoise goes yet further Step 3 Achilles advances to where the tortoise was at the end of Step 2 while the tortoise goes yet further Step 4 Achilles advances to where the tortoise was at the end of Step 3 while the tortoise goes yet further Etc Apparently Achilles never overtakes the tortoise since however many steps he completes the tortoise remains ahead of him Zeno was not attempting to make a point about infinity As a member of the Eleatics school which regarded motion as an illusion he saw it as a mistake to suppose that Achilles could run at all Subsequent thinkers finding this solution unacceptable struggled for over two millennia to find other weaknesses in the argument Finally in 1821 Augustin Louis Cauchy provided both a satisfactory definition of a limit and a proof that for 0 lt x lt 1 17 a a x a x 2 a x 3 a x 4 a x 5 a 1 x displaystyle a ax ax 2 ax 3 ax 4 ax 5 cdots frac a 1 x nbsp Suppose that Achilles is running at 10 meters per second the tortoise is walking at 0 1 meters per second and the latter has a 100 meter head start The duration of the chase fits Cauchy s pattern with a 10 seconds and x 0 01 Achilles does overtake the tortoise it takes him10 0 1 0 001 0 00001 10 1 0 01 10 0 99 10 10101 seconds displaystyle 10 0 1 0 001 0 00001 cdots frac 10 1 0 01 frac 10 0 99 10 10101 ldots text seconds nbsp Early Indian edit The Jain mathematical text Surya Prajnapti c 4th 3rd century BCE classifies all numbers into three sets enumerable innumerable and infinite Each of these was further subdivided into three orders 18 Enumerable lowest intermediate and highest Innumerable nearly innumerable truly innumerable and innumerably innumerable Infinite nearly infinite truly infinite infinitely infinite17th century edit In the 17th century European mathematicians started using infinite numbers and infinite expressions in a systematic fashion In 1655 John Wallis first used the notation displaystyle infty nbsp for such a number in his De sectionibus conicis 19 and exploited it in area calculations by dividing the region into infinitesimal strips of width on the order of 1 displaystyle tfrac 1 infty nbsp 20 But in Arithmetica infinitorum 1656 21 he indicates infinite series infinite products and infinite continued fractions by writing down a few terms or factors and then appending amp c as in 1 6 12 18 24 amp c 22 In 1699 Isaac Newton wrote about equations with an infinite number of terms in his work De analysi per aequationes numero terminorum infinitas 23 Mathematics editHermann Weyl opened a mathematico philosophic address given in 1930 with 24 Mathematics is the science of the infinite Symbol edit Main article Infinity symbol The infinity symbol displaystyle infty nbsp sometimes called the lemniscate is a mathematical symbol representing the concept of infinity The symbol is encoded in Unicode at U 221E INFINITY amp infin 25 and in LaTeX as infty 26 It was introduced in 1655 by John Wallis 27 28 and since its introduction it has also been used outside mathematics in modern mysticism 29 and literary symbology 30 Calculus edit Gottfried Leibniz one of the co inventors of infinitesimal calculus speculated widely about infinite numbers and their use in mathematics To Leibniz both infinitesimals and infinite quantities were ideal entities not of the same nature as appreciable quantities but enjoying the same properties in accordance with the Law of continuity 31 2 Real analysis edit In real analysis the symbol displaystyle infty nbsp called infinity is used to denote an unbounded limit 32 The notation x displaystyle x rightarrow infty nbsp means that x displaystyle x nbsp increases without bound and x displaystyle x to infty nbsp means that x displaystyle x nbsp decreases without bound For example if f t 0 displaystyle f t geq 0 nbsp for every t displaystyle t nbsp then 33 a b f t d t displaystyle int a b f t dt infty nbsp means that f t displaystyle f t nbsp does not bound a finite area from a displaystyle a nbsp to b displaystyle b nbsp f t d t displaystyle int infty infty f t dt infty nbsp means that the area under f t displaystyle f t nbsp is infinite f t d t a displaystyle int infty infty f t dt a nbsp means that the total area under f t displaystyle f t nbsp is finite and is equal to a displaystyle a nbsp Infinity can also be used to describe infinite series as follows i 0 f i a displaystyle sum i 0 infty f i a nbsp means that the sum of the infinite series converges to some real value a displaystyle a nbsp i 0 f i displaystyle sum i 0 infty f i infty nbsp means that the sum of the infinite series properly diverges to infinity in the sense that the partial sums increase without bound 34 In addition to defining a limit infinity can be also used as a value in the extended real number system Points labeled displaystyle infty nbsp and displaystyle infty nbsp can be added to the topological space of the real numbers producing the two point compactification of the real numbers Adding algebraic properties to this gives us the extended real numbers 35 We can also treat displaystyle infty nbsp and displaystyle infty nbsp as the same leading to the one point compactification of the real numbers which is the real projective line 36 Projective geometry also refers to a line at infinity in plane geometry a plane at infinity in three dimensional space and a hyperplane at infinity for general dimensions each consisting of points at infinity 37 Complex analysis edit nbsp By stereographic projection the complex plane can be wrapped onto a sphere with the top point of the sphere corresponding to infinity This is called the Riemann sphere In complex analysis the symbol displaystyle infty nbsp called infinity denotes an unsigned infinite limit The expression x displaystyle x rightarrow infty nbsp means that the magnitude x displaystyle x nbsp of x displaystyle x nbsp grows beyond any assigned value A point labeled displaystyle infty nbsp can be added to the complex plane as a topological space giving the one point compactification of the complex plane When this is done the resulting space is a one dimensional complex manifold or Riemann surface called the extended complex plane or the Riemann sphere 38 Arithmetic operations similar to those given above for the extended real numbers can also be defined though there is no distinction in the signs which leads to the one exception that infinity cannot be added to itself On the other hand this kind of infinity enables division by zero namely z 0 displaystyle z 0 infty nbsp for any nonzero complex number z displaystyle z nbsp In this context it is often useful to consider meromorphic functions as maps into the Riemann sphere taking the value of displaystyle infty nbsp at the poles The domain of a complex valued function may be extended to include the point at infinity as well One important example of such functions is the group of Mobius transformations see Mobius transformation Overview Nonstandard analysis edit nbsp Infinitesimals e and infinities w on the hyperreal number line 1 e w 1 The original formulation of infinitesimal calculus by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz used infinitesimal quantities In the second half of the 20th century it was shown that this treatment could be put on a rigorous footing through various logical systems including smooth infinitesimal analysis and nonstandard analysis In the latter infinitesimals are invertible and their inverses are infinite numbers The infinities in this sense are part of a hyperreal field there is no equivalence between them as with the Cantorian transfinites For example if H is an infinite number in this sense then H H 2H and H 1 are distinct infinite numbers This approach to non standard calculus is fully developed in Keisler 1986 Set theory edit Main articles Cardinality and Ordinal number nbsp One to one correspondence between an infinite set and its proper subsetA different form of infinity are the ordinal and cardinal infinities of set theory a system of transfinite numbers first developed by Georg Cantor In this system the first transfinite cardinal is aleph null ℵ0 the cardinality of the set of natural numbers This modern mathematical conception of the quantitative infinite developed in the late 19th century from works by Cantor Gottlob Frege Richard Dedekind and others using the idea of collections or sets 1 Dedekind s approach was essentially to adopt the idea of one to one correspondence as a standard for comparing the size of sets and to reject the view of Galileo derived from Euclid that the whole cannot be the same size as the part However see Galileo s paradox where Galileo concludes that positive integers cannot be compared to the subset of positive square integers since both are infinite sets An infinite set can simply be defined as one having the same size as at least one of its proper parts this notion of infinity is called Dedekind infinite The diagram to the right gives an example viewing lines as infinite sets of points the left half of the lower blue line can be mapped in a one to one manner green correspondences to the higher blue line and in turn to the whole lower blue line red correspondences therefore the whole lower blue line and its left half have the same cardinality i e size citation needed Cantor defined two kinds of infinite numbers ordinal numbers and cardinal numbers Ordinal numbers characterize well ordered sets or counting carried on to any stopping point including points after an infinite number have already been counted Generalizing finite and ordinary infinite sequences which are maps from the positive integers leads to mappings from ordinal numbers to transfinite sequences Cardinal numbers define the size of sets meaning how many members they contain and can be standardized by choosing the first ordinal number of a certain size to represent the cardinal number of that size The smallest ordinal infinity is that of the positive integers and any set which has the cardinality of the integers is countably infinite If a set is too large to be put in one to one correspondence with the positive integers it is called uncountable Cantor s views prevailed and modern mathematics accepts actual infinity as part of a consistent and coherent theory 39 40 page needed Certain extended number systems such as the hyperreal numbers incorporate the ordinary finite numbers and infinite numbers of different sizes citation needed Cardinality of the continuum edit Main article Cardinality of the continuumOne of Cantor s most important results was that the cardinality of the continuum c displaystyle mathbf c nbsp is greater than that of the natural numbers ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 nbsp that is there are more real numbers R than natural numbers N Namely Cantor showed that c 2 ℵ 0 gt ℵ 0 displaystyle mathbf c 2 aleph 0 gt aleph 0 nbsp 41 Further information Cantor s diagonal argument and Cantor s first set theory articleThe continuum hypothesis states that there is no cardinal number between the cardinality of the reals and the cardinality of the natural numbers that is c ℵ 1 ℶ 1 displaystyle mathbf c aleph 1 beth 1 nbsp Further information Beth number Beth oneThis hypothesis cannot be proved or disproved within the widely accepted Zermelo Fraenkel set theory even assuming the Axiom of Choice 42 Cardinal arithmetic can be used to show not only that the number of points in a real number line is equal to the number of points in any segment of that line but also that this is equal to the number of points on a plane and indeed in any finite dimensional space citation needed nbsp The first three steps of a fractal construction whose limit is a space filling curve showing that there are as many points in a one dimensional line as in a two dimensional squareThe first of these results is apparent by considering for instance the tangent function which provides a one to one correspondence between the interval p 2 p 2 andR See also Hilbert s paradox of the Grand HotelThe second result was proved by Cantor in 1878 but only became intuitively apparent in 1890 when Giuseppe Peano introduced the space filling curves curved lines that twist and turn enough to fill the whole of any square or cube or hypercube or finite dimensional space These curves can be used to define a one to one correspondence between the points on one side of a square and the points in the square 43 Geometry edit Until the end of the 19th century infinity was rarely discussed in geometry except in the context of processes that could be continued without any limit For example a line was what is now called a line segment with the proviso that one can extend it as far as one wants but extending it infinitely was out of the question Similarly a line was usually not considered to be composed of infinitely many points but was a location where a point may be placed Even if there are infinitely many possible positions only a finite number of points could be placed on a line A witness of this is the expression the locus of a point that satisfies some property singular where modern mathematicians would generally say the set of the points that have the property plural One of the rare exceptions of a mathematical concept involving actual infinity was projective geometry where points at infinity are added to the Euclidean space for modeling the perspective effect that shows parallel lines intersecting at infinity Mathematically points at infinity have the advantage of allowing one to not consider some special cases For example in a projective plane two distinct lines intersect in exactly one point whereas without points at infinity there are no intersection points for parallel lines So parallel and non parallel lines must be studied separately in classical geometry while they need not to be distinguished in projective geometry Before the use of set theory for the foundation of mathematics points and lines were viewed as distinct entities and a point could be located on a line With the universal use of set theory in mathematics the point of view has dramatically changed a line is now considered as the set of its points and one says that a point belongs to a line instead of is located on a line however the latter phrase is still used In particular in modern mathematics lines are infinite sets Infinite dimension edit The vector spaces that occur in classical geometry have always a finite dimension generally two or three However this is not implied by the abstract definition of a vector space and vector spaces of infinite dimension can be considered This is typically the case in functional analysis where function spaces are generally vector spaces of infinite dimension In topology some constructions can generate topological spaces of infinite dimension In particular this is the case of iterated loop spaces Fractals edit The structure of a fractal object is reiterated in its magnifications Fractals can be magnified indefinitely without losing their structure and becoming smooth they have infinite perimeters and can have infinite or finite areas One such fractal curve with an infinite perimeter and finite area is the Koch snowflake citation needed Mathematics without infinity edit Leopold Kronecker was skeptical of the notion of infinity and how his fellow mathematicians were using it in the 1870s and 1880s This skepticism was developed in the philosophy of mathematics called finitism an extreme form of mathematical philosophy in the general philosophical and mathematical schools of constructivism and intuitionism 44 Physics editIn physics approximations of real numbers are used for continuous measurements and natural numbers are used for discrete measurements i e counting Concepts of infinite things such as an infinite plane wave exist but there are no experimental means to generate them 45 Cosmology edit The first published proposal that the universe is infinite came from Thomas Digges in 1576 46 Eight years later in 1584 the Italian philosopher and astronomer Giordano Bruno proposed an unbounded universe in On the Infinite Universe and Worlds Innumerable suns exist innumerable earths revolve around these suns in a manner similar to the way the seven planets revolve around our sun Living beings inhabit these worlds 47 Cosmologists have long sought to discover whether infinity exists in our physical universe Are there an infinite number of stars Does the universe have infinite volume Does space go on forever This is still an open question of cosmology The question of being infinite is logically separate from the question of having boundaries The two dimensional surface of the Earth for example is finite yet has no edge By travelling in a straight line with respect to the Earth s curvature one will eventually return to the exact spot one started from The universe at least in principle might have a similar topology If so one might eventually return to one s starting point after travelling in a straight line through the universe for long enough 48 The curvature of the universe can be measured through multipole moments in the spectrum of the cosmic background radiation To date analysis of the radiation patterns recorded by the WMAP spacecraft hints that the universe has a flat topology This would be consistent with an infinite physical universe 49 50 51 However the universe could be finite even if its curvature is flat An easy way to understand this is to consider two dimensional examples such as video games where items that leave one edge of the screen reappear on the other The topology of such games is toroidal and the geometry is flat Many possible bounded flat possibilities also exist for three dimensional space 52 The concept of infinity also extends to the multiverse hypothesis which when explained by astrophysicists such as Michio Kaku posits that there are an infinite number and variety of universes 53 Also cyclic models posit an infinite amount of Big Bangs resulting in an infinite variety of universes after each Big Bang event in an infinite cycle 54 Logic editIn logic an infinite regress argument is a distinctively philosophical kind of argument purporting to show that a thesis is defective because it generates an infinite series when either form A no such series exists or form B were it to exist the thesis would lack the role e g of justification that it is supposed to play 55 Computing editThe IEEE floating point standard IEEE 754 specifies a positive and a negative infinity value and also indefinite values These are defined as the result of arithmetic overflow division by zero and other exceptional operations 56 Some programming languages such as Java 57 and J 58 allow the programmer an explicit access to the positive and negative infinity values as language constants These can be used as greatest and least elements as they compare respectively greater than or less than all other values They have uses as sentinel values in algorithms involving sorting searching or windowing citation needed In languages that do not have greatest and least elements but do allow overloading of relational operators it is possible for a programmer to create the greatest and least elements In languages that do not provide explicit access to such values from the initial state of the program but do implement the floating point data type the infinity values may still be accessible and usable as the result of certain operations citation needed In programming an infinite loop is a loop whose exit condition is never satisfied thus executing indefinitely Arts games and cognitive sciences editPerspective artwork uses the concept of vanishing points roughly corresponding to mathematical points at infinity located at an infinite distance from the observer This allows artists to create paintings that realistically render space distances and forms 59 Artist M C Escher is specifically known for employing the concept of infinity in his work in this and other ways citation needed Variations of chess played on an unbounded board are called infinite chess 60 61 Cognitive scientist George Lakoff considers the concept of infinity in mathematics and the sciences as a metaphor This perspective is based on the basic metaphor of infinity BMI defined as the ever increasing sequence lt 1 2 3 gt 62 See also edit0 999 Aleph number Ananta Exponentiation Indeterminate form Infinite monkey theorem Infinite set Infinitesimal Paradoxes of infinity Supertask Surreal numberReferences edit a b c d e f Allen Donald 2003 The History of Infinity PDF Texas A amp M Mathematics Retrieved Nov 15 2019 a b Jesseph Douglas Michael Spring Summer 1998 Leibniz on the Foundations of the Calculus The Question of the Reality of Infinitesimal Magnitudes Perspectives on Science 6 1 amp 2 6 40 doi 10 1162 posc a 00543 ISSN 1063 6145 OCLC 42413222 S2CID 118227996 Archived from the original on 11 January 2012 Retrieved 1 November 2019 via Project MUSE a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint date and year link Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June 2008 The Princeton companion to mathematics Imre Leader Princeton University Princeton Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 3039 8 OCLC 659590835 Maddox 2002 pp 113 117 McLarty Colin 15 January 2014 September 2010 What Does it Take to Prove Fermat s Last Theorem Grothendieck and the Logic of Number Theory The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 3 359 377 doi 10 2178 bsl 1286284558 S2CID 13475845 via Cambridge University Press Wallace 2004 p 44 Aristotle Physics Translated by Hardie R P Gaye R K The Internet Classics Archive Book 3 Chapters 5 8 Goodman Nicolas D 1981 Reflections on Bishop s philosophy of mathematics In Richman F ed Constructive Mathematics Lecture Notes in Mathematics Vol 873 Springer pp 135 145 doi 10 1007 BFb0090732 ISBN 978 3 540 10850 4 Maor p 3 Sarton George March 1928 The Thirteen Books of Euclid s Elements Thomas L Heath Heiberg Isis 10 1 60 62 doi 10 1086 346308 ISSN 0021 1753 via The University of Chicago Press Journals Hutten Ernest Hirschlaff 1962 The origins of science an inquiry into the foundations of Western thought Internet Archive London Allen and Unwin pp 1 241 ISBN 978 0 04 946007 2 Retrieved 2020 01 09 Euclid 2008 c 300 BC Euclid s Elements of Geometry PDF Translated by Fitzpatrick Richard Lulu com p 6 Book I Postulate 5 ISBN 978 0 6151 7984 1 Heath Sir Thomas Little Heiberg Johan Ludvig 1908 The Thirteen Books of Euclid s Elements Vol v 1 The University Press p 212 Drozdek Adam 2008 In the Beginning Was theApeiron Infinity in Greek Philosophy Stuttgart Germany Franz Steiner Verlag ISBN 978 3 515 09258 6 Zeno s Paradoxes Stanford University October 15 2010 Retrieved April 3 2017 Russell 1996 p 347 Cauchy Augustin Louis 1821 Cours d Analyse de l Ecole Royale Polytechnique Libraires du Roi amp de la Bibliotheque du Roi p 124 Retrieved October 12 2019 Ian Stewart 2017 Infinity a Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press p 117 ISBN 978 0 19 875523 4 Archived from the original on April 3 2017 Cajori Florian 2007 A History of Mathematical Notations Vol 1 Cosimo Inc p 214 ISBN 9781602066854 Cajori 1993 Sec 421 Vol II p 44 Arithmetica Infinitorum Cajori 1993 Sec 435 Vol II p 58 Grattan Guinness Ivor 2005 Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640 1940 Elsevier p 62 ISBN 978 0 08 045744 4 Archived from the original on 2016 06 03 Extract of p 62 Weyl Hermann 2012 Peter Pesic ed Levels of Infinity Selected Writings on Mathematics and Philosophy Dover p 17 ISBN 978 0 486 48903 2 AG Compart Unicode Character U 221E Compart com Retrieved 2019 11 15 List of LaTeX mathematical symbols OeisWiki oeis org Retrieved 2019 11 15 Scott Joseph Frederick 1981 The mathematical work of John Wallis D D F R S 1616 1703 2 ed American Mathematical Society p 24 ISBN 978 0 8284 0314 6 archived from the original on 2016 05 09 Martin Lof Per 1990 Mathematics of infinity COLOG 88 Tallinn 1988 Lecture Notes in Computer Science vol 417 Berlin Springer pp 146 197 doi 10 1007 3 540 52335 9 54 ISBN 978 3 540 52335 2 MR 1064143 O Flaherty Wendy Doniger 1986 Dreams Illusion and Other Realities University of Chicago Press p 243 ISBN 978 0 226 61855 5 archived from the original on 2016 06 29 Toker Leona 1989 Nabokov The Mystery of Literary Structures Cornell University Press p 159 ISBN 978 0 8014 2211 9 archived from the original on 2016 05 09 Bell John Lane Continuity and Infinitesimals In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Taylor 1955 p 63 These uses of infinity for integrals and series can be found in any standard calculus text such as Swokowski 1983 pp 468 510 Properly Divergent Sequences Mathonline mathonline wikidot com Retrieved 2019 11 15 Aliprantis Charalambos D Burkinshaw Owen 1998 Principles of Real Analysis 3rd ed San Diego CA Academic Press Inc p 29 ISBN 978 0 12 050257 8 MR 1669668 archived from the original on 2015 05 15 Gemignani 1990 p 177 Beutelspacher Albrecht Rosenbaum Ute 1998 Projective Geometry from foundations to applications Cambridge University Press p 27 ISBN 978 0 521 48364 3 Rao Murali Stetkaer Henrik 1991 Complex Analysis An Invitation a Concise Introduction to Complex Function Theory World Scientific p 113 ISBN 9789810203757 Infinity math dartmouth edu Retrieved 2019 11 16 Moore A W 1991 The Infinite Routledge Dauben Joseph 1993 Georg Cantor and the Battle for Transfinite Set Theory PDF 9th ACMS Conference Proceedings 4 Cohen 1963 p 1143 Sagan 1994 pp 10 12 Kline 1972 pp 1197 1198 Doric Lenses Archived 2013 01 24 at the Wayback Machine Application Note Axicons 2 Intensity Distribution Retrieved 7 April 2014 John Gribbin 2009 In Search of the Multiverse Parallel Worlds Hidden Dimensions and the Ultimate Quest for the Frontiers of Reality ISBN 978 0 470 61352 8 p 88 Brake Mark 2013 Alien Life Imagined Communicating the Science and Culture of Astrobiology illustrated ed Cambridge University Press p 63 ISBN 978 0 521 49129 7 Koupelis Theo Kuhn Karl F 2007 In Quest of the Universe illustrated ed Jones amp Bartlett Learning p 553 ISBN 978 0 7637 4387 1 Extract of p 553 Will the Universe expand forever NASA 24 January 2014 Archived from the original on 1 June 2012 Retrieved 16 March 2015 Our universe is Flat FermiLab SLAC 7 April 2015 Archived from the original on 10 April 2015 Marcus Y Yoo 2011 Unexpected connections Engineering amp Science LXXIV1 30 Weeks Jeffrey 2001 The Shape of Space CRC Press ISBN 978 0 8247 0709 5 Kaku M 2006 Parallel worlds Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group McKee Maggie 25 September 2014 Ingenious Paul J Steinhardt The Princeton physicist on what s wrong with inflation theory and his view of the Big Bang Nautilus No 17 NautilusThink Inc Retrieved 31 March 2017 Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Second Edition p 429 Infinity and NaN The GNU C Library www gnu org Retrieved 2021 03 15 Gosling James et al 27 July 2012 4 2 3 The Java Language Specification Java SE 7 ed California Oracle America Inc Archived from the original on 9 June 2012 Retrieved 6 September 2012 Stokes Roger July 2012 19 2 1 Learning J Archived from the original on 25 March 2012 Retrieved 6 September 2012 Kline Morris 1985 Mathematics for the nonmathematician Courier Dover Publications p 229 ISBN 978 0 486 24823 3 Section 10 7 p 229 Archived 2016 05 16 at the Wayback Machine Infinite chess at the Chess Variant Pages Archived 2017 04 02 at the Wayback Machine An infinite chess scheme Infinite Chess PBS Infinite Series Archived 2017 04 07 at the Wayback Machine PBS Infinite Series with academic sources by J Hamkins infinite chess Evans C D A Joel David Hamkins 2013 Transfinite game values in infinite chess arXiv 1302 4377 math LO and Evans C D A Joel David Hamkins Norman Lewis Perlmutter 2015 A position in infinite chess with game value w 4 arXiv 1510 08155 math LO Archived copy PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2020 02 26 Retrieved 2021 03 25 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link Bibliography edit Cajori Florian 1993 1928 amp 1929 A History of Mathematical Notations Two Volumes Bound as One Dover ISBN 978 0 486 67766 8 Gemignani Michael C 1990 Elementary Topology 2nd ed Dover ISBN 978 0 486 66522 1 Keisler H Jerome 1986 Elementary Calculus An Approach Using Infinitesimals 2nd ed Maddox Randall B 2002 Mathematical Thinking and Writing A Transition to Abstract Mathematics Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 464976 7 Kline Morris 1972 Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times New York Oxford University Press pp 1197 1198 ISBN 978 0 19 506135 2 Russell Bertrand 1996 1903 The Principles of Mathematics New York Norton ISBN 978 0 393 31404 5 OCLC 247299160 Sagan Hans 1994 Space Filling Curves Springer ISBN 978 1 4612 0871 6 Swokowski Earl W 1983 Calculus with Analytic Geometry Alternate ed Prindle Weber amp Schmidt ISBN 978 0 87150 341 1 Taylor Angus E 1955 Advanced Calculus Blaisdell Publishing Company Wallace David Foster 2004 Everything and More A Compact History of Infinity Norton W W amp Company Inc ISBN 978 0 393 32629 1 Sources edit Aczel Amir D 2001 The Mystery of the Aleph Mathematics the Kabbalah and the Search for Infinity New York Pocket Books ISBN 978 0 7434 2299 4 D P Agrawal 2000 Ancient Jaina Mathematics an Introduction Infinity Foundation Bell J L Continuity and infinitesimals Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy Revised 2009 Cohen Paul 1963 The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 50 6 1143 1148 Bibcode 1963PNAS 50 1143C doi 10 1073 pnas 50 6 1143 PMC 221287 PMID 16578557 Jain L C 1982 Exact Sciences from Jaina Sources Jain L C 1973 Set theory in the Jaina school of mathematics Indian Journal of History of Science Joseph George G 2000 The Crest of the Peacock Non European Roots of Mathematics 2nd ed Penguin Books ISBN 978 0 14 027778 4 H Jerome Keisler Elementary Calculus An Approach Using Infinitesimals First edition 1976 2nd edition 1986 This book is now out of print The publisher has reverted the copyright to the author who has made available the 2nd edition in pdf format available for downloading at http www math wisc edu keisler calc html Eli Maor 1991 To Infinity and Beyond Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 02511 7 O Connor John J and Edmund F Robertson 1998 Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor Archived 2006 09 16 at the Wayback Machine MacTutor History of Mathematics archive O Connor John J and Edmund F Robertson 2000 Jaina mathematics Archived 2008 12 20 at the Wayback Machine MacTutor History of Mathematics archive Pearce Ian 2002 Jainism MacTutor History of Mathematics archive Rucker Rudy 1995 Infinity and the Mind The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 00172 2 Singh Navjyoti 1988 Jaina Theory of Actual Infinity and Transfinite Numbers Journal of the Asiatic Society 30 External links edit nbsp Look up infinity in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikibooks has a book on the topic of Infinity is not a number nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Infinity nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Infinity The Infinite Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Infinity on In Our Time at the BBC A Crash Course in the Mathematics of Infinite Sets Archived 2010 02 27 at the Wayback Machine by Peter Suber From the St John s Review XLIV 2 1998 1 59 The stand alone appendix to Infinite Reflections below A concise introduction to Cantor s mathematics of infinite sets Infinite Reflections Archived 2009 11 05 at the Wayback Machine by Peter Suber How Cantor s mathematics of the infinite solves a handful of ancient philosophical problems of the infinite From the St John s Review XLIV 2 1998 1 59 Grime James Infinity is bigger than you think Numberphile Brady Haran Archived from the original on 2017 10 22 Retrieved 2013 04 06 Hotel Infinity John J O Connor and Edmund F Robertson 1998 Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor Archived 2006 09 16 at the Wayback Machine MacTutor History of Mathematics archive John J O Connor and Edmund F Robertson 2000 Jaina mathematics Archived 2008 12 20 at the Wayback Machine MacTutor History of Mathematics archive Ian Pearce 2002 Jainism MacTutor History of Mathematics archive The Mystery Of The Aleph Mathematics the Kabbalah and the Search for Infinity Dictionary of the Infinite compilation of articles about infinity in physics mathematics and philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Infinity amp oldid 1193163924, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.