fbpx
Wikipedia

Gödel's incompleteness theorems

Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of provability in formal axiomatic theories. These results, published by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the philosophy of mathematics. The theorems are widely, but not universally, interpreted as showing that Hilbert's program to find a complete and consistent set of axioms for all mathematics is impossible.

The first incompleteness theorem states that no consistent system of axioms whose theorems can be listed by an effective procedure (i.e., an algorithm) is capable of proving all truths about the arithmetic of natural numbers. For any such consistent formal system, there will always be statements about natural numbers that are true, but that are unprovable within the system.

The second incompleteness theorem, an extension of the first, shows that the system cannot demonstrate its own consistency.

Employing a diagonal argument, Gödel's incompleteness theorems were the first of several closely related theorems on the limitations of formal systems. They were followed by Tarski's undefinability theorem on the formal undefinability of truth, Church's proof that Hilbert's Entscheidungsproblem is unsolvable, and Turing's theorem that there is no algorithm to solve the halting problem.

Formal systems: completeness, consistency, and effective axiomatization Edit

The incompleteness theorems apply to formal systems that are of sufficient complexity to express the basic arithmetic of the natural numbers and which are consistent and effectively axiomatized. Particularly in the context of first-order logic, formal systems are also called formal theories. In general, a formal system is a deductive apparatus that consists of a particular set of axioms along with rules of symbolic manipulation (or rules of inference) that allow for the derivation of new theorems from the axioms. One example of such a system is first-order Peano arithmetic, a system in which all variables are intended to denote natural numbers. In other systems, such as set theory, only some sentences of the formal system express statements about the natural numbers. The incompleteness theorems are about formal provability within these systems, rather than about "provability" in an informal sense.

There are several properties that a formal system may have, including completeness, consistency, and the existence of an effective axiomatization. The incompleteness theorems show that systems which contain a sufficient amount of arithmetic cannot possess all three of these properties.

Effective axiomatization Edit

A formal system is said to be effectively axiomatized (also called effectively generated) if its set of theorems is recursively enumerable (Franzén 2005, p. 112).

This means that there is a computer program that, in principle, could enumerate all the theorems of the system without listing any statements that are not theorems. Examples of effectively generated theories include Peano arithmetic and Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC).

The theory known as true arithmetic consists of all true statements about the standard integers in the language of Peano arithmetic. This theory is consistent and complete, and contains a sufficient amount of arithmetic. However it does not have a recursively enumerable set of axioms, and thus does not satisfy the hypotheses of the incompleteness theorems.

Completeness Edit

A set of axioms is (syntactically, or negation-) complete if, for any statement in the axioms' language, that statement or its negation is provable from the axioms (Smith 2007, p. 24). This is the notion relevant for Gödel's first Incompleteness theorem. It is not to be confused with semantic completeness, which means that the set of axioms proves all the semantic tautologies of the given language. In his completeness theorem (not to be confused with the incompleteness theorems described here), Gödel proved that first order logic is semantically complete. But it is not syntactically complete, since there are sentences expressible in the language of first order logic that can be neither proved nor disproved from the axioms of logic alone.

In a system of mathematics, thinkers such as Hilbert had believed that it is just a matter of time to find such an axiomatization that would allow one to either prove or disprove (by proving its negation) each and every mathematical formula.

A formal system might be syntactically incomplete by design, as logics generally are. Or it may be incomplete simply because not all the necessary axioms have been discovered or included. For example, Euclidean geometry without the parallel postulate is incomplete, because some statements in the language (such as the parallel postulate itself) can not be proved from the remaining axioms. Similarly, the theory of dense linear orders is not complete, but becomes complete with an extra axiom stating that there are no endpoints in the order. The continuum hypothesis is a statement in the language of ZFC that is not provable within ZFC, so ZFC is not complete. In this case, there is no obvious candidate for a new axiom that resolves the issue.

The theory of first order Peano arithmetic seems to be consistent. Assuming this is indeed the case, note that it has an infinite but recursively enumerable set of axioms, and can encode enough arithmetic for the hypotheses of the incompleteness theorem. Thus by the first incompleteness theorem, Peano Arithmetic is not complete. The theorem gives an explicit example of a statement of arithmetic that is neither provable nor disprovable in Peano's arithmetic. Moreover, this statement is true in the usual model. In addition, no effectively axiomatized, consistent extension of Peano arithmetic can be complete.

Consistency Edit

A set of axioms is (simply) consistent if there is no statement such that both the statement and its negation are provable from the axioms, and inconsistent otherwise. That is to say, a consistent axiomatic system is one that is free from contradiction.

Peano arithmetic is provably consistent from ZFC, but not from within itself. Similarly, ZFC is not provably consistent from within itself, but ZFC + "there exists an inaccessible cardinal" proves ZFC is consistent because if κ is the least such cardinal, then Vκ sitting inside the von Neumann universe is a model of ZFC, and a theory is consistent if and only if it has a model.

If one takes all statements in the language of Peano arithmetic as axioms, then this theory is complete, has a recursively enumerable set of axioms, and can describe addition and multiplication. However, it is not consistent.

Additional examples of inconsistent theories arise from the paradoxes that result when the axiom schema of unrestricted comprehension is assumed in set theory.

Systems which contain arithmetic Edit

The incompleteness theorems apply only to formal systems which are able to prove a sufficient collection of facts about the natural numbers. One sufficient collection is the set of theorems of Robinson arithmetic Q. Some systems, such as Peano arithmetic, can directly express statements about natural numbers. Others, such as ZFC set theory, are able to interpret statements about natural numbers into their language. Either of these options is appropriate for the incompleteness theorems.

The theory of algebraically closed fields of a given characteristic is complete, consistent, and has an infinite but recursively enumerable set of axioms. However it is not possible to encode the integers into this theory, and the theory cannot describe arithmetic of integers. A similar example is the theory of real closed fields, which is essentially equivalent to Tarski's axioms for Euclidean geometry. So Euclidean geometry itself (in Tarski's formulation) is an example of a complete, consistent, effectively axiomatized theory.

The system of Presburger arithmetic consists of a set of axioms for the natural numbers with just the addition operation (multiplication is omitted). Presburger arithmetic is complete, consistent, and recursively enumerable and can encode addition but not multiplication of natural numbers, showing that for Gödel's theorems one needs the theory to encode not just addition but also multiplication.

Dan Willard (2001) has studied some weak families of arithmetic systems which allow enough arithmetic as relations to formalise Gödel numbering, but which are not strong enough to have multiplication as a function, and so fail to prove the second incompleteness theorem; that is to say, these systems are consistent and capable of proving their own consistency (see self-verifying theories).

Conflicting goals Edit

In choosing a set of axioms, one goal is to be able to prove as many correct results as possible, without proving any incorrect results. For example, we could imagine a set of true axioms which allow us to prove every true arithmetical claim about the natural numbers (Smith 2007, p. 2). In the standard system of first-order logic, an inconsistent set of axioms will prove every statement in its language (this is sometimes called the principle of explosion), and is thus automatically complete. A set of axioms that is both complete and consistent, however, proves a maximal set of non-contradictory theorems.[citation needed]

The pattern illustrated in the previous sections with Peano arithmetic, ZFC, and ZFC + "there exists an inaccessible cardinal" cannot generally be broken. Here ZFC + "there exists an inaccessible cardinal" cannot from itself, be proved consistent. It is also not complete, as illustrated by the continuum hypothesis, which is unresolvable[1] in ZFC + "there exists an inaccessible cardinal".

The first incompleteness theorem shows that, in formal systems that can express basic arithmetic, a complete and consistent finite list of axioms can never be created: each time an additional, consistent statement is added as an axiom, there are other true statements that still cannot be proved, even with the new axiom. If an axiom is ever added that makes the system complete, it does so at the cost of making the system inconsistent. It is not even possible for an infinite list of axioms to be complete, consistent, and effectively axiomatized.

First incompleteness theorem Edit

Gödel's first incompleteness theorem first appeared as "Theorem VI" in Gödel's 1931 paper "On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I". The hypotheses of the theorem were improved shortly thereafter by J. Barkley Rosser (1936) using Rosser's trick. The resulting theorem (incorporating Rosser's improvement) may be paraphrased in English as follows, where "formal system" includes the assumption that the system is effectively generated.

First Incompleteness Theorem: "Any consistent formal system F within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out is incomplete; i.e., there are statements of the language of F which can neither be proved nor disproved in F." (Raatikainen 2020)

The unprovable statement GF referred to by the theorem is often referred to as "the Gödel sentence" for the system F. The proof constructs a particular Gödel sentence for the system F, but there are infinitely many statements in the language of the system that share the same properties, such as the conjunction of the Gödel sentence and any logically valid sentence.

Each effectively generated system has its own Gödel sentence. It is possible to define a larger system F' that contains the whole of F plus GF as an additional axiom. This will not result in a complete system, because Gödel's theorem will also apply to F', and thus F' also cannot be complete. In this case, GF is indeed a theorem in F', because it is an axiom. Because GF states only that it is not provable in F, no contradiction is presented by its provability within F'. However, because the incompleteness theorem applies to F', there will be a new Gödel statement GF' for F', showing that F' is also incomplete. GF' will differ from GF in that GF' will refer to F', rather than F.

Syntactic form of the Gödel sentence Edit

The Gödel sentence is designed to refer, indirectly, to itself. The sentence states that, when a particular sequence of steps is used to construct another sentence, that constructed sentence will not be provable in F. However, the sequence of steps is such that the constructed sentence turns out to be GF itself. In this way, the Gödel sentence GF indirectly states its own unprovability within F (Smith 2007, p. 135).

To prove the first incompleteness theorem, Gödel demonstrated that the notion of provability within a system could be expressed purely in terms of arithmetical functions that operate on Gödel numbers of sentences of the system. Therefore, the system, which can prove certain facts about numbers, can also indirectly prove facts about its own statements, provided that it is effectively generated. Questions about the provability of statements within the system are represented as questions about the arithmetical properties of numbers themselves, which would be decidable by the system if it were complete.

Thus, although the Gödel sentence refers indirectly to sentences of the system F, when read as an arithmetical statement the Gödel sentence directly refers only to natural numbers. It asserts that no natural number has a particular property, where that property is given by a primitive recursive relation (Smith 2007, p. 141). As such, the Gödel sentence can be written in the language of arithmetic with a simple syntactic form. In particular, it can be expressed as a formula in the language of arithmetic consisting of a number of leading universal quantifiers followed by a quantifier-free body (these formulas are at level   of the arithmetical hierarchy). Via the MRDP theorem, the Gödel sentence can be re-written as a statement that a particular polynomial in many variables with integer coefficients never takes the value zero when integers are substituted for its variables (Franzén 2005, p. 71).

Truth of the Gödel sentence Edit

The first incompleteness theorem shows that the Gödel sentence GF of an appropriate formal theory F is unprovable in F. Because, when interpreted as a statement about arithmetic, this unprovability is exactly what the sentence (indirectly) asserts, the Gödel sentence is, in fact, true (Smoryński 1977, p. 825; also see Franzén 2005, pp. 28–33). For this reason, the sentence GF is often said to be "true but unprovable." (Raatikainen 2020). However, since the Gödel sentence cannot itself formally specify its intended interpretation, the truth of the sentence GF may only be arrived at via a meta-analysis from outside the system. In general, this meta-analysis can be carried out within the weak formal system known as primitive recursive arithmetic, which proves the implication Con(F)→GF, where Con(F) is a canonical sentence asserting the consistency of F (Smoryński 1977, p. 840, Kikuchi & Tanaka 1994, p. 403).

Although the Gödel sentence of a consistent theory is true as a statement about the intended interpretation of arithmetic, the Gödel sentence will be false in some nonstandard models of arithmetic, as a consequence of Gödel's completeness theorem (Franzén 2005, p. 135). That theorem shows that, when a sentence is independent of a theory, the theory will have models in which the sentence is true and models in which the sentence is false. As described earlier, the Gödel sentence of a system F is an arithmetical statement which claims that no number exists with a particular property. The incompleteness theorem shows that this claim will be independent of the system F, and the truth of the Gödel sentence follows from the fact that no standard natural number has the property in question. Any model in which the Gödel sentence is false must contain some element which satisfies the property within that model. Such a model must be "nonstandard" – it must contain elements that do not correspond to any standard natural number (Raatikainen 2020, Franzén 2005, p. 135).

Relationship with the liar paradox Edit

Gödel specifically cites Richard's paradox and the liar paradox as semantical analogues to his syntactical incompleteness result in the introductory section of "On Formally Undecidable Propositions in Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I". The liar paradox is the sentence "This sentence is false." An analysis of the liar sentence shows that it cannot be true (for then, as it asserts, it is false), nor can it be false (for then, it is true). A Gödel sentence G for a system F makes a similar assertion to the liar sentence, but with truth replaced by provability: G says "G is not provable in the system F." The analysis of the truth and provability of G is a formalized version of the analysis of the truth of the liar sentence.

It is not possible to replace "not provable" with "false" in a Gödel sentence because the predicate "Q is the Gödel number of a false formula" cannot be represented as a formula of arithmetic. This result, known as Tarski's undefinability theorem, was discovered independently both by Gödel, when he was working on the proof of the incompleteness theorem, and by the theorem's namesake, Alfred Tarski.

Extensions of Gödel's original result Edit

Compared to the theorems stated in Gödel's 1931 paper, many contemporary statements of the incompleteness theorems are more general in two ways. These generalized statements are phrased to apply to a broader class of systems, and they are phrased to incorporate weaker consistency assumptions.

Gödel demonstrated the incompleteness of the system of Principia Mathematica, a particular system of arithmetic, but a parallel demonstration could be given for any effective system of a certain expressiveness. Gödel commented on this fact in the introduction to his paper, but restricted the proof to one system for concreteness. In modern statements of the theorem, it is common to state the effectiveness and expressiveness conditions as hypotheses for the incompleteness theorem, so that it is not limited to any particular formal system. The terminology used to state these conditions was not yet developed in 1931 when Gödel published his results.

Gödel's original statement and proof of the incompleteness theorem requires the assumption that the system is not just consistent but ω-consistent. A system is ω-consistent if it is not ω-inconsistent, and is ω-inconsistent if there is a predicate P such that for every specific natural number m the system proves ~P(m), and yet the system also proves that there exists a natural number n such that P(n). That is, the system says that a number with property P exists while denying that it has any specific value. The ω-consistency of a system implies its consistency, but consistency does not imply ω-consistency. J. Barkley Rosser (1936) strengthened the incompleteness theorem by finding a variation of the proof (Rosser's trick) that only requires the system to be consistent, rather than ω-consistent. This is mostly of technical interest, because all true formal theories of arithmetic (theories whose axioms are all true statements about natural numbers) are ω-consistent, and thus Gödel's theorem as originally stated applies to them. The stronger version of the incompleteness theorem that only assumes consistency, rather than ω-consistency, is now commonly known as Gödel's incompleteness theorem and as the Gödel–Rosser theorem.

Second incompleteness theorem Edit

For each formal system F containing basic arithmetic, it is possible to canonically define a formula Cons(F) expressing the consistency of F. This formula expresses the property that "there does not exist a natural number coding a formal derivation within the system F whose conclusion is a syntactic contradiction." The syntactic contradiction is often taken to be "0=1", in which case Cons(F) states "there is no natural number that codes a derivation of '0=1' from the axioms of F."

Gödel's second incompleteness theorem shows that, under general assumptions, this canonical consistency statement Cons(F) will not be provable in F. The theorem first appeared as "Theorem XI" in Gödel's 1931 paper "On Formally Undecidable Propositions in Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I". In the following statement, the term "formalized system" also includes an assumption that F is effectively axiomatized.

Second Incompleteness Theorem: "For any consistent system F within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out, the consistency of F cannot be proved in F itself." (Raatikainen 2020)

can also be written as

"Assume F is a consistent formalized system which contains elementary arithmetic. Then  ." (Raatikainen 2020) (Then F does not prove consistency of F)

This theorem is stronger than the first incompleteness theorem because the statement constructed in the first incompleteness theorem does not directly express the consistency of the system. The proof of the second incompleteness theorem is obtained by formalizing the proof of the first incompleteness theorem within the system F itself.

Expressing consistency Edit

There is a technical subtlety in the second incompleteness theorem regarding the method of expressing the consistency of F as a formula in the language of F. There are many ways to express the consistency of a system, and not all of them lead to the same result. The formula Cons(F) from the second incompleteness theorem is a particular expression of consistency.

Other formalizations of the claim that F is consistent may be inequivalent in F, and some may even be provable. For example, first-order Peano arithmetic (PA) can prove that "the largest consistent subset of PA" is consistent. But, because PA is consistent, the largest consistent subset of PA is just PA, so in this sense PA "proves that it is consistent". What PA does not prove is that the largest consistent subset of PA is, in fact, the whole of PA. (The term "largest consistent subset of PA" is meant here to be the largest consistent initial segment of the axioms of PA under some particular effective enumeration.)

The Hilbert–Bernays conditions Edit

The standard proof of the second incompleteness theorem assumes that the provability predicate ProvA(P) satisfies the Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions. Letting #(P) represent the Gödel number of a formula P, the provability conditions say:

  1. If F proves P, then F proves ProvA(#(P)).
  2. F proves 1.; that is, F proves ProvA(#(P)) → ProvA(#(ProvA(#(P)))).
  3. F proves ProvA(#(PQ)) ∧ ProvA(#(P)) → ProvA(#(Q))   (analogue of modus ponens).

There are systems, such as Robinson arithmetic, which are strong enough to meet the assumptions of the first incompleteness theorem, but which do not prove the Hilbert–Bernays conditions. Peano arithmetic, however, is strong enough to verify these conditions, as are all theories stronger than Peano arithmetic.

Implications for consistency proofs Edit

Gödel's second incompleteness theorem also implies that a system F1 satisfying the technical conditions outlined above cannot prove the consistency of any system F2 that proves the consistency of F1. This is because such a system F1 can prove that if F2 proves the consistency of F1, then F1 is in fact consistent. For the claim that F1 is consistent has form "for all numbers n, n has the decidable property of not being a code for a proof of contradiction in F1". If F1 were in fact inconsistent, then F2 would prove for some n that n is the code of a contradiction in F1. But if F2 also proved that F1 is consistent (that is, that there is no such n), then it would itself be inconsistent. This reasoning can be formalized in F1 to show that if F2 is consistent, then F1 is consistent. Since, by second incompleteness theorem, F1 does not prove its consistency, it cannot prove the consistency of F2 either.

This corollary of the second incompleteness theorem shows that there is no hope of proving, for example, the consistency of Peano arithmetic using any finitistic means that can be formalized in a system the consistency of which is provable in Peano arithmetic (PA). For example, the system of primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA), which is widely accepted as an accurate formalization of finitistic mathematics, is provably consistent in PA. Thus PRA cannot prove the consistency of PA. This fact is generally seen to imply that Hilbert's program, which aimed to justify the use of "ideal" (infinitistic) mathematical principles in the proofs of "real" (finitistic) mathematical statements by giving a finitistic proof that the ideal principles are consistent, cannot be carried out (Franzén 2005, p. 106).

The corollary also indicates the epistemological relevance of the second incompleteness theorem. It would actually provide no interesting information if a system F proved its consistency. This is because inconsistent theories prove everything, including their consistency. Thus a consistency proof of F in F would give us no clue as to whether F really is consistent; no doubts about the consistency of F would be resolved by such a consistency proof. The interest in consistency proofs lies in the possibility of proving the consistency of a system F in some system F' that is in some sense less doubtful than F itself, for example weaker than F. For many naturally occurring theories F and F', such as F = Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory and F' = primitive recursive arithmetic, the consistency of F' is provable in F, and thus F' cannot prove the consistency of F by the above corollary of the second incompleteness theorem.

The second incompleteness theorem does not rule out altogether the possibility of proving the consistency of some theory T, only doing so in a theory that T itself can prove to be consistent. For example, Gerhard Gentzen proved the consistency of Peano arithmetic in a different system that includes an axiom asserting that the ordinal called ε0 is wellfounded; see Gentzen's consistency proof. Gentzen's theorem spurred the development of ordinal analysis in proof theory.

Examples of undecidable statements Edit

There are two distinct senses of the word "undecidable" in mathematics and computer science. The first of these is the proof-theoretic sense used in relation to Gödel's theorems, that of a statement being neither provable nor refutable in a specified deductive system. The second sense, which will not be discussed here, is used in relation to computability theory and applies not to statements but to decision problems, which are countably infinite sets of questions each requiring a yes or no answer. Such a problem is said to be undecidable if there is no computable function that correctly answers every question in the problem set (see undecidable problem).

Because of the two meanings of the word undecidable, the term independent is sometimes used instead of undecidable for the "neither provable nor refutable" sense.

Undecidability of a statement in a particular deductive system does not, in and of itself, address the question of whether the truth value of the statement is well-defined, or whether it can be determined by other means. Undecidability only implies that the particular deductive system being considered does not prove the truth or falsity of the statement. Whether there exist so-called "absolutely undecidable" statements, whose truth value can never be known or is ill-specified, is a controversial point in the philosophy of mathematics.

The combined work of Gödel and Paul Cohen has given two concrete examples of undecidable statements (in the first sense of the term): The continuum hypothesis can neither be proved nor refuted in ZFC (the standard axiomatization of set theory), and the axiom of choice can neither be proved nor refuted in ZF (which is all the ZFC axioms except the axiom of choice). These results do not require the incompleteness theorem. Gödel proved in 1940 that neither of these statements could be disproved in ZF or ZFC set theory. In the 1960s, Cohen proved that neither is provable from ZF, and the continuum hypothesis cannot be proved from ZFC.

In 1973, Saharon Shelah showed that the Whitehead problem in group theory is undecidable, in the first sense of the term, in standard set theory.[2]

Gregory Chaitin produced undecidable statements in algorithmic information theory and proved another incompleteness theorem in that setting. Chaitin's incompleteness theorem states that for any system that can represent enough arithmetic, there is an upper bound c such that no specific number can be proved in that system to have Kolmogorov complexity greater than c. While Gödel's theorem is related to the liar paradox, Chaitin's result is related to Berry's paradox.

Undecidable statements provable in larger systems Edit

These are natural mathematical equivalents of the Gödel "true but undecidable" sentence. They can be proved in a larger system which is generally accepted as a valid form of reasoning, but are undecidable in a more limited system such as Peano Arithmetic.

In 1977, Paris and Harrington proved that the Paris–Harrington principle, a version of the infinite Ramsey theorem, is undecidable in (first-order) Peano arithmetic, but can be proved in the stronger system of second-order arithmetic. Kirby and Paris later showed that Goodstein's theorem, a statement about sequences of natural numbers somewhat simpler than the Paris–Harrington principle, is also undecidable in Peano arithmetic.

Kruskal's tree theorem, which has applications in computer science, is also undecidable from Peano arithmetic but provable in set theory. In fact Kruskal's tree theorem (or its finite form) is undecidable in a much stronger system ATR0 codifying the principles acceptable based on a philosophy of mathematics called predicativism.[3] The related but more general graph minor theorem (2003) has consequences for computational complexity theory.

Relationship with computability Edit

The incompleteness theorem is closely related to several results about undecidable sets in recursion theory.

Stephen Cole Kleene (1943) presented a proof of Gödel's incompleteness theorem using basic results of computability theory. One such result shows that the halting problem is undecidable: there is no computer program that can correctly determine, given any program P as input, whether P eventually halts when run with a particular given input. Kleene showed that the existence of a complete effective system of arithmetic with certain consistency properties would force the halting problem to be decidable, a contradiction. This method of proof has also been presented by Shoenfield (1967, p. 132); Charlesworth (1981); and Hopcroft & Ullman (1979).

Franzén (2005, p. 73) explains how Matiyasevich's solution to Hilbert's 10th problem can be used to obtain a proof to Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. Matiyasevich proved that there is no algorithm that, given a multivariate polynomial p(x1, x2,...,xk) with integer coefficients, determines whether there is an integer solution to the equation p = 0. Because polynomials with integer coefficients, and integers themselves, are directly expressible in the language of arithmetic, if a multivariate integer polynomial equation p = 0 does have a solution in the integers then any sufficiently strong system of arithmetic T will prove this. Moreover, if the system T is ω-consistent, then it will never prove that a particular polynomial equation has a solution when in fact there is no solution in the integers. Thus, if T were complete and ω-consistent, it would be possible to determine algorithmically whether a polynomial equation has a solution by merely enumerating proofs of T until either "p has a solution" or "p has no solution" is found, in contradiction to Matiyasevich's theorem. Hence it follows that T cannot be ω-consistent and complete. Moreover, for each consistent effectively generated system T, it is possible to effectively generate a multivariate polynomial p over the integers such that the equation p = 0 has no solutions over the integers, but the lack of solutions cannot be proved in T (Davis 2006, p. 416; Jones 1980).

Smoryński (1977, p. 842) shows how the existence of recursively inseparable sets can be used to prove the first incompleteness theorem. This proof is often extended to show that systems such as Peano arithmetic are essentially undecidable (see Kleene 1967, p. 274).

Chaitin's incompleteness theorem gives a different method of producing independent sentences, based on Kolmogorov complexity. Like the proof presented by Kleene that was mentioned above, Chaitin's theorem only applies to theories with the additional property that all their axioms are true in the standard model of the natural numbers. Gödel's incompleteness theorem is distinguished by its applicability to consistent theories that nonetheless include statements that are false in the standard model; these theories are known as ω-inconsistent.

Proof sketch for the first theorem Edit

The proof by contradiction has three essential parts. To begin, choose a formal system that meets the proposed criteria:

  1. Statements in the system can be represented by natural numbers (known as Gödel numbers). The significance of this is that properties of statements—such as their truth and falsehood—will be equivalent to determining whether their Gödel numbers have certain properties, and that properties of the statements can therefore be demonstrated by examining their Gödel numbers. This part culminates in the construction of a formula expressing the idea that "statement S is provable in the system" (which can be applied to any statement "S" in the system).
  2. In the formal system it is possible to construct a number whose matching statement, when interpreted, is self-referential and essentially says that it (i.e. the statement itself) is unprovable. This is done using a technique called "diagonalization" (so-called because of its origins as Cantor's diagonal argument).
  3. Within the formal system this statement permits a demonstration that it is neither provable nor disprovable in the system, and therefore the system cannot in fact be ω-consistent. Hence the original assumption that the proposed system met the criteria is false.

Arithmetization of syntax Edit

The main problem in fleshing out the proof described above is that it seems at first that to construct a statement p that is equivalent to "p cannot be proved", p would somehow have to contain a reference to p, which could easily give rise to an infinite regress. Gödel's technique is to show that statements can be matched with numbers (often called the arithmetization of syntax) in such a way that "proving a statement" can be replaced with "testing whether a number has a given property". This allows a self-referential formula to be constructed in a way that avoids any infinite regress of definitions. The same technique was later used by Alan Turing in his work on the Entscheidungsproblem.

In simple terms, a method can be devised so that every formula or statement that can be formulated in the system gets a unique number, called its Gödel number, in such a way that it is possible to mechanically convert back and forth between formulas and Gödel numbers. The numbers involved might be very long indeed (in terms of number of digits), but this is not a barrier; all that matters is that such numbers can be constructed. A simple example is how English can be stored as a sequence of numbers for each letter and then combined into a single larger number:

  • The word hello is encoded as 104-101-108-108-111 in ASCII, which can be converted into the number 104101108108111.
  • The logical statement x=y => y=x is encoded as 120-061-121-032-061-062-032-121-061-120 in ASCII, which can be converted into the number 120061121032061062032121061120.

In principle, proving a statement true or false can be shown to be equivalent to proving that the number matching the statement does or does not have a given property. Because the formal system is strong enough to support reasoning about numbers in general, it can support reasoning about numbers that represent formulae and statements as well. Crucially, because the system can support reasoning about properties of numbers, the results are equivalent to reasoning about provability of their equivalent statements.

Construction of a statement about "provability" Edit

Having shown that in principle the system can indirectly make statements about provability, by analyzing properties of those numbers representing statements it is now possible to show how to create a statement that actually does this.

A formula F(x) that contains exactly one free variable x is called a statement form or class-sign. As soon as x is replaced by a specific number, the statement form turns into a bona fide statement, and it is then either provable in the system, or not. For certain formulas one can show that for every natural number n,   is true if and only if it can be proved (the precise requirement in the original proof is weaker, but for the proof sketch this will suffice). In particular, this is true for every specific arithmetic operation between a finite number of natural numbers, such as "2 × 3 = 6".

Statement forms themselves are not statements and therefore cannot be proved or disproved. But every statement form F(x) can be assigned a Gödel number denoted by G(F). The choice of the free variable used in the form F(x) is not relevant to the assignment of the Gödel number G(F).

The notion of provability itself can also be encoded by Gödel numbers, in the following way: since a proof is a list of statements which obey certain rules, the Gödel number of a proof can be defined. Now, for every statement p, one may ask whether a number x is the Gödel number of its proof. The relation between the Gödel number of p and x, the potential Gödel number of its proof, is an arithmetical relation between two numbers. Therefore, there is a statement form Bew(y) that uses this arithmetical relation to state that a Gödel number of a proof of y exists:

Bew(y) = ∃ x (y is the Gödel number of a formula and x is the Gödel number of a proof of the formula encoded by y).

The name Bew is short for beweisbar, the German word for "provable"; this name was originally used by Gödel to denote the provability formula just described. Note that "Bew(y)" is merely an abbreviation that represents a particular, very long, formula in the original language of T; the string "Bew" itself is not claimed to be part of this language.

An important feature of the formula Bew(y) is that if a statement p is provable in the system then Bew(G(p)) is also provable. This is because any proof of p would have a corresponding Gödel number, the existence of which causes Bew(G(p)) to be satisfied.

Diagonalization Edit

The next step in the proof is to obtain a statement which, indirectly, asserts its own unprovability. Although Gödel constructed this statement directly, the existence of at least one such statement follows from the diagonal lemma, which says that for any sufficiently strong formal system and any statement form F there is a statement p such that the system proves

pF(G(p)).

By letting F be the negation of Bew(x), we obtain the theorem

p ↔ ~Bew(G(p))

and the p defined by this roughly states that its own Gödel number is the Gödel number of an unprovable formula.

The statement p is not literally equal to ~Bew(G(p)); rather, p states that if a certain calculation is performed, the resulting Gödel number will be that of an unprovable statement. But when this calculation is performed, the resulting Gödel number turns out to be the Gödel number of p itself. This is similar to the following sentence in English:

", when preceded by itself in quotes, is unprovable.", when preceded by itself in quotes, is unprovable.

This sentence does not directly refer to itself, but when the stated transformation is made the original sentence is obtained as a result, and thus this sentence indirectly asserts its own unprovability. The proof of the diagonal lemma employs a similar method.

Now, assume that the axiomatic system is ω-consistent, and let p be the statement obtained in the previous section.

If p were provable, then Bew(G(p)) would be provable, as argued above. But p asserts the negation of Bew(G(p)). Thus the system would be inconsistent, proving both a statement and its negation. This contradiction shows that p cannot be provable.

If the negation of p were provable, then Bew(G(p)) would be provable (because p was constructed to be equivalent to the negation of Bew(G(p))). However, for each specific number x, x cannot be the Gödel number of the proof of p, because p is not provable (from the previous paragraph). Thus on one hand the system proves there is a number with a certain property (that it is the Gödel number of the proof of p), but on the other hand, for every specific number x, we can prove that it does not have this property. This is impossible in an ω-consistent system. Thus the negation of p is not provable.

Thus the statement p is undecidable in our axiomatic system: it can neither be proved nor disproved within the system.

In fact, to show that p is not provable only requires the assumption that the system is consistent. The stronger assumption of ω-consistency is required to show that the negation of p is not provable. Thus, if p is constructed for a particular system:

  • If the system is ω-consistent, it can prove neither p nor its negation, and so p is undecidable.
  • If the system is consistent, it may have the same situation, or it may prove the negation of p. In the later case, we have a statement ("not p") which is false but provable, and the system is not ω-consistent.

If one tries to "add the missing axioms" to avoid the incompleteness of the system, then one has to add either p or "not p" as axioms. But then the definition of "being a Gödel number of a proof" of a statement changes. which means that the formula Bew(x) is now different. Thus when we apply the diagonal lemma to this new Bew, we obtain a new statement p, different from the previous one, which will be undecidable in the new system if it is ω-consistent.

Proof via Berry's paradox Edit

George Boolos (1989) sketches an alternative proof of the first incompleteness theorem that uses Berry's paradox rather than the liar paradox to construct a true but unprovable formula. A similar proof method was independently discovered by Saul Kripke (Boolos 1998, p. 383). Boolos's proof proceeds by constructing, for any computably enumerable set S of true sentences of arithmetic, another sentence which is true but not contained in S. This gives the first incompleteness theorem as a corollary. According to Boolos, this proof is interesting because it provides a "different sort of reason" for the incompleteness of effective, consistent theories of arithmetic (Boolos 1998, p. 388).

Computer verified proofs Edit

The incompleteness theorems are among a relatively small number of nontrivial theorems that have been transformed into formalized theorems that can be completely verified by proof assistant software. Gödel's original proofs of the incompleteness theorems, like most mathematical proofs, were written in natural language intended for human readers.

Computer-verified proofs of versions of the first incompleteness theorem were announced by Natarajan Shankar in 1986 using Nqthm (Shankar 1994), by Russell O'Connor in 2003 using Coq (O'Connor 2005) and by John Harrison in 2009 using HOL Light (Harrison 2009). A computer-verified proof of both incompleteness theorems was announced by Lawrence Paulson in 2013 using Isabelle (Paulson 2014).

Proof sketch for the second theorem Edit

The main difficulty in proving the second incompleteness theorem is to show that various facts about provability used in the proof of the first incompleteness theorem can be formalized within a system S using a formal predicate P for provability. Once this is done, the second incompleteness theorem follows by formalizing the entire proof of the first incompleteness theorem within the system S itself.

Let p stand for the undecidable sentence constructed above, and assume for purposes of obtaining a contradiction that the consistency of the system S can be proved from within the system S itself. This is equivalent to proving the statement "System S is consistent". Now consider the statement c, where c = "If the system S is consistent, then p is not provable". The proof of sentence c can be formalized within the system S, and therefore the statement c, "p is not provable", (or identically, "not P(p)") can be proved in the system S.

Observe then, that if we can prove that the system S is consistent (ie. the statement in the hypothesis of c), then we have proved that p is not provable. But this is a contradiction since by the 1st Incompleteness Theorem, this sentence (ie. what is implied in the sentence c, ""p" is not provable") is what we construct to be unprovable. Notice that this is why we require formalizing the first Incompleteness Theorem in S: to prove the 2nd Incompleteness Theorem, we obtain a contradiction with the 1st Incompleteness Theorem which can do only by showing that the theorem holds in S. So we cannot prove that the system S is consistent. And the 2nd Incompleteness Theorem statement follows.

Discussion and implications Edit

The incompleteness results affect the philosophy of mathematics, particularly versions of formalism, which use a single system of formal logic to define their principles.

Consequences for logicism and Hilbert's second problem Edit

The incompleteness theorem is sometimes thought to have severe consequences for the program of logicism proposed by Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell, which aimed to define the natural numbers in terms of logic (Hellman 1981, pp. 451–468). Bob Hale and Crispin Wright argue that it is not a problem for logicism because the incompleteness theorems apply equally to first order logic as they do to arithmetic. They argue that only those who believe that the natural numbers are to be defined in terms of first order logic have this problem.

Many logicians believe that Gödel's incompleteness theorems struck a fatal blow to David Hilbert's second problem, which asked for a finitary consistency proof for mathematics. The second incompleteness theorem, in particular, is often viewed as making the problem impossible. Not all mathematicians agree with this analysis, however, and the status of Hilbert's second problem is not yet decided (see "Modern viewpoints on the status of the problem").

Minds and machines Edit

Authors including the philosopher J. R. Lucas and physicist Roger Penrose have debated what, if anything, Gödel's incompleteness theorems imply about human intelligence. Much of the debate centers on whether the human mind is equivalent to a Turing machine, or by the Church–Turing thesis, any finite machine at all. If it is, and if the machine is consistent, then Gödel's incompleteness theorems would apply to it.

Hilary Putnam (1960) suggested that while Gödel's theorems cannot be applied to humans, since they make mistakes and are therefore inconsistent, it may be applied to the human faculty of science or mathematics in general. Assuming that it is consistent, either its consistency cannot be proved or it cannot be represented by a Turing machine.

Avi Wigderson (2010) has proposed that the concept of mathematical "knowability" should be based on computational complexity rather than logical decidability. He writes that "when knowability is interpreted by modern standards, namely via computational complexity, the Gödel phenomena are very much with us."

Douglas Hofstadter, in his books Gödel, Escher, Bach and I Am a Strange Loop, cites Gödel's theorems as an example of what he calls a strange loop, a hierarchical, self-referential structure existing within an axiomatic formal system. He argues that this is the same kind of structure which gives rise to consciousness, the sense of "I", in the human mind. While the self-reference in Gödel's theorem comes from the Gödel sentence asserting its own unprovability within the formal system of Principia Mathematica, the self-reference in the human mind comes from the way in which the brain abstracts and categorises stimuli into "symbols", or groups of neurons which respond to concepts, in what is effectively also a formal system, eventually giving rise to symbols modelling the concept of the very entity doing the perception. Hofstadter argues that a strange loop in a sufficiently complex formal system can give rise to a "downward" or "upside-down" causality, a situation in which the normal hierarchy of cause-and-effect is flipped upside-down. In the case of Gödel's theorem, this manifests, in short, as the following:

"Merely from knowing the formula's meaning, one can infer its truth or falsity without any effort to derive it in the old-fashioned way, which requires one to trudge methodically "upwards" from the axioms. This is not just peculiar; it is astonishing. Normally, one cannot merely look at what a mathematical conjecture says and simply appeal to the content of that statement on its own to deduce whether the statement is true or false." (I Am a Strange Loop.)[4]

In the case of the mind, a far more complex formal system, this "downward causality" manifests, in Hofstadter's view, as the ineffable human instinct that the causality of our minds lies on the high level of desires, concepts, personalities, thoughts and ideas, rather than on the low level of interactions between neurons or even fundamental particles, even though according to physics the latter seems to possess the causal power.

"There is thus a curious upside-downness to our normal human way of perceiving the world: we are built to perceive “big stuff” rather than “small stuff”, even though the domain of the tiny seems to be where the actual motors driving reality reside." (I Am a Strange Loop.)[4]

Paraconsistent logic Edit

Although Gödel's theorems are usually studied in the context of classical logic, they also have a role in the study of paraconsistent logic and of inherently contradictory statements (dialetheia). Graham Priest (1984, 2006) argues that replacing the notion of formal proof in Gödel's theorem with the usual notion of informal proof can be used to show that naive mathematics is inconsistent, and uses this as evidence for dialetheism. The cause of this inconsistency is the inclusion of a truth predicate for a system within the language of the system (Priest 2006, p. 47). Stewart Shapiro (2002) gives a more mixed appraisal of the applications of Gödel's theorems to dialetheism.

Appeals to the incompleteness theorems in other fields Edit

Appeals and analogies are sometimes made to the incompleteness theorems in support of arguments that go beyond mathematics and logic. Several authors have commented negatively on such extensions and interpretations, including Torkel Franzén (2005); Panu Raatikainen (2005); Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont (1999); and Ophelia Benson and Jeremy Stangroom (2006). Sokal & Bricmont (1999), and Stangroom & Benson (2006, p. 10), for example, quote from Rebecca Goldstein's comments on the disparity between Gödel's avowed Platonism and the anti-realist uses to which his ideas are sometimes put. Sokal & Bricmont (1999, p. 187) criticize Régis Debray's invocation of the theorem in the context of sociology; Debray has defended this use as metaphorical (ibid.).

History Edit

After Gödel published his proof of the completeness theorem as his doctoral thesis in 1929, he turned to a second problem for his habilitation. His original goal was to obtain a positive solution to Hilbert's second problem (Dawson 1997, p. 63). At the time, theories of the natural numbers and real numbers similar to second-order arithmetic were known as "analysis", while theories of the natural numbers alone were known as "arithmetic".

Gödel was not the only person working on the consistency problem. Ackermann had published a flawed consistency proof for analysis in 1925, in which he attempted to use the method of ε-substitution originally developed by Hilbert. Later that year, von Neumann was able to correct the proof for a system of arithmetic without any axioms of induction. By 1928, Ackermann had communicated a modified proof to Bernays; this modified proof led Hilbert to announce his belief in 1929 that the consistency of arithmetic had been demonstrated and that a consistency proof of analysis would likely soon follow. After the publication of the incompleteness theorems showed that Ackermann's modified proof must be erroneous, von Neumann produced a concrete example showing that its main technique was unsound (Zach 2007, p. 418; Zach 2003, p. 33).

In the course of his research, Gödel discovered that although a sentence which asserts its own falsehood leads to paradox, a sentence that asserts its own non-provability does not. In particular, Gödel was aware of the result now called Tarski's indefinability theorem, although he never published it. Gödel announced his first incompleteness theorem to Carnap, Feigel and Waismann on August 26, 1930; all four would attend the Second Conference on the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences, a key conference in Königsberg the following week.

Announcement Edit

The 1930 Königsberg conference was a joint meeting of three academic societies, with many of the key logicians of the time in attendance. Carnap, Heyting, and von Neumann delivered one-hour addresses on the mathematical philosophies of logicism, intuitionism, and formalism, respectively (Dawson 1996, p. 69). The conference also included Hilbert's retirement address, as he was leaving his position at the University of Göttingen. Hilbert used the speech to argue his belief that all mathematical problems can be solved. He ended his address by saying,

For the mathematician there is no Ignorabimus, and, in my opinion, not at all for natural science either. ... The true reason why [no one] has succeeded in finding an unsolvable problem is, in my opinion, that there is no unsolvable problem. In contrast to the foolish Ignorabimus, our credo avers: We must know. We shall know!

This speech quickly became known as a summary of Hilbert's beliefs on mathematics (its final six words, "Wir müssen wissen. Wir werden wissen!", were used as Hilbert's epitaph in 1943). Although Gödel was likely in attendance for Hilbert's address, the two never met face to face (Dawson 1996, p. 72).

Gödel announced his first incompleteness theorem at a roundtable discussion session on the third day of the conference. The announcement drew little attention apart from that of von Neumann, who pulled Gödel aside for conversation. Later that year, working independently with knowledge of the first incompleteness theorem, von Neumann obtained a proof of the second incompleteness theorem, which he announced to Gödel in a letter dated November 20, 1930 (Dawson 1996, p. 70). Gödel had independently obtained the second incompleteness theorem and included it in his submitted manuscript, which was received by Monatshefte für Mathematik on November 17, 1930.

Gödel's paper was published in the Monatshefte in 1931 under the title "Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I" ("On Formally Undecidable Propositions in Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I"). As the title implies, Gödel originally planned to publish a second part of the paper in the next volume of the Monatshefte; the prompt acceptance of the first paper was one reason he changed his plans (van Heijenoort 1967, page 328, footnote 68a).

Generalization and acceptance Edit

Gödel gave a series of lectures on his theorems at Princeton in 1933–1934 to an audience that included Church, Kleene, and Rosser. By this time, Gödel had grasped that the key property his theorems required is that the system must be effective (at the time, the term "general recursive" was used). Rosser proved in 1936 that the hypothesis of ω-consistency, which was an integral part of Gödel's original proof, could be replaced by simple consistency, if the Gödel sentence was changed in an appropriate way. These developments left the incompleteness theorems in essentially their modern form.

Gentzen published his consistency proof for first-order arithmetic in 1936. Hilbert accepted this proof as "finitary" although (as Gödel's theorem had already shown) it cannot be formalized within the system of arithmetic that is being proved consistent.

The impact of the incompleteness theorems on Hilbert's program was quickly realized. Bernays included a full proof of the incompleteness theorems in the second volume of Grundlagen der Mathematik (1939), along with additional results of Ackermann on the ε-substitution method and Gentzen's consistency proof of arithmetic. This was the first full published proof of the second incompleteness theorem.

Criticisms Edit

Finsler Edit

Paul Finsler (1926) used a version of Richard's paradox to construct an expression that was false but unprovable in a particular, informal framework he had developed. Gödel was unaware of this paper when he proved the incompleteness theorems (Collected Works Vol. IV., p. 9). Finsler wrote to Gödel in 1931 to inform him about this paper, which Finsler felt had priority for an incompleteness theorem. Finsler's methods did not rely on formalized provability, and had only a superficial resemblance to Gödel's work (van Heijenoort 1967, p. 328). Gödel read the paper but found it deeply flawed, and his response to Finsler laid out concerns about the lack of formalization (Dawson 1996, p. 89). Finsler continued to argue for his philosophy of mathematics, which eschewed formalization, for the remainder of his career.

Zermelo Edit

In September 1931, Ernst Zermelo wrote to Gödel to announce what he described as an "essential gap" in Gödel's argument (Dawson 1996, p. 76). In October, Gödel replied with a 10-page letter (Dawson 1996, p. 76, Grattan-Guinness 2005, pp. 512–513), where he pointed out that Zermelo mistakenly assumed that the notion of truth in a system is definable in that system (which is not true in general by Tarski's undefinability theorem). But Zermelo did not relent and published his criticisms in print with "a rather scathing paragraph on his young competitor" (Grattan-Guinness 2005, pp. 513). Gödel decided that to pursue the matter further was pointless, and Carnap agreed (Dawson 1996, p. 77). Much of Zermelo's subsequent work was related to logics stronger than first-order logic, with which he hoped to show both the consistency and categoricity of mathematical theories.

Wittgenstein Edit

Ludwig Wittgenstein wrote several passages about the incompleteness theorems that were published posthumously in his 1953 Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, in particular one section sometimes called the "notorious paragraph" where he seems to confuse the notions of "true" and "provable" in Russell's system. Gödel was a member of the Vienna Circle during the period in which Wittgenstein's early ideal language philosophy and Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus dominated the circle's thinking. There has been some controversy about whether Wittgenstein misunderstood the incompleteness theorem or just expressed himself unclearly. Writings in Gödel's Nachlass express the belief that Wittgenstein misread his ideas.

Multiple commentators have read Wittgenstein as misunderstanding Gödel (Rodych 2003), although Juliet Floyd and Hilary Putnam (2000), as well as Graham Priest (2004) have provided textual readings arguing that most commentary misunderstands Wittgenstein. On their release, Bernays, Dummett, and Kreisel wrote separate reviews on Wittgenstein's remarks, all of which were extremely negative (Berto 2009, p. 208). The unanimity of this criticism caused Wittgenstein's remarks on the incompleteness theorems to have little impact on the logic community. In 1972, Gödel stated: "Has Wittgenstein lost his mind? Does he mean it seriously? He intentionally utters trivially nonsensical statements" (Wang 1996, p. 179), and wrote to Karl Menger that Wittgenstein's comments demonstrate a misunderstanding of the incompleteness theorems writing:

It is clear from the passages you cite that Wittgenstein did not understand [the first incompleteness theorem] (or pretended not to understand it). He interpreted it as a kind of logical paradox, while in fact is just the opposite, namely a mathematical theorem within an absolutely uncontroversial part of mathematics (finitary number theory or combinatorics). (Wang 1996, p. 179)

Since the publication of Wittgenstein's Nachlass in 2000, a series of papers in philosophy have sought to evaluate whether the original criticism of Wittgenstein's remarks was justified. Floyd & Putnam (2000) argue that Wittgenstein had a more complete understanding of the incompleteness theorem than was previously assumed. They are particularly concerned with the interpretation of a Gödel sentence for an ω-inconsistent system as actually saying "I am not provable", since the system has no models in which the provability predicate corresponds to actual provability. Rodych (2003) argues that their interpretation of Wittgenstein is not historically justified. Berto (2009) explores the relationship between Wittgenstein's writing and theories of paraconsistent logic.

See also Edit

References Edit

Citations Edit

  1. ^ in technical terms: independent; see Continuum hypothesis#Independence from ZFC
  2. ^ Shelah, Saharon (1974). "Infinite Abelian groups, Whitehead problem and some constructions". Israel Journal of Mathematics. 18 (3): 243–256. doi:10.1007/BF02757281. MR 0357114.
  3. ^ S. G. Simpson, Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic (2009). Perspectives in Logic, ISBN 9780521884396.
  4. ^ a b Hofstadter, Douglas R. (2007) [2003]. "Chapter 12. On Downward Causality". I Am a Strange Loop. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-03078-1.

Articles by Gödel Edit

  • Kurt Gödel, 1931, "Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme, I", Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, v. 38 n. 1, pp. 173–198. doi:10.1007/BF01700692
  • —, 1931, "Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme, I", in Solomon Feferman, ed., 1986. Kurt Gödel Collected works, Vol. I. Oxford University Press, pp. 144–195. ISBN 978-0195147209. The original German with a facing English translation, preceded by an introductory note by Stephen Cole Kleene.
  • —, 1951, "Some basic theorems on the foundations of mathematics and their implications", in Solomon Feferman, ed., 1995. Kurt Gödel Collected works, Vol. III, Oxford University Press, pp. 304–323. ISBN 978-0195147223.

Translations, during his lifetime, of Gödel's paper into English Edit

None of the following agree in all translated words and in typography. The typography is a serious matter, because Gödel expressly wished to emphasize "those metamathematical notions that had been defined in their usual sense before . . ." (van Heijenoort 1967, p. 595). Three translations exist. Of the first John Dawson states that: "The Meltzer translation was seriously deficient and received a devastating review in the Journal of Symbolic Logic; "Gödel also complained about Braithwaite's commentary (Dawson 1997, p. 216). "Fortunately, the Meltzer translation was soon supplanted by a better one prepared by Elliott Mendelson for Martin Davis's anthology The Undecidable . . . he found the translation "not quite so good" as he had expected . . . [but because of time constraints he] agreed to its publication" (ibid). (In a footnote Dawson states that "he would regret his compliance, for the published volume was marred throughout by sloppy typography and numerous misprints" (ibid)). Dawson states that "The translation that Gödel favored was that by Jean van Heijenoort" (ibid). For the serious student another version exists as a set of lecture notes recorded by Stephen Kleene and J. B. Rosser "during lectures given by Gödel at to the Institute for Advanced Study during the spring of 1934" (cf commentary by Davis 1965, p. 39 and beginning on p. 41); this version is titled "On Undecidable Propositions of Formal Mathematical Systems". In their order of publication:

  • B. Meltzer (translation) and R. B. Braithwaite (Introduction), 1962. On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems, Dover Publications, New York (Dover edition 1992), ISBN 0-486-66980-7 (pbk.) This contains a useful translation of Gödel's German abbreviations on pp. 33–34. As noted above, typography, translation and commentary is suspect. Unfortunately, this translation was reprinted with all its suspect content by
  • Stephen Hawking editor, 2005. God Created the Integers: The Mathematical Breakthroughs That Changed History, Running Press, Philadelphia, ISBN 0-7624-1922-9. Gödel's paper appears starting on p. 1097, with Hawking's commentary starting on p. 1089.
  • Martin Davis editor, 1965. The Undecidable: Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable problems and Computable Functions, Raven Press, New York, no ISBN. Gödel's paper begins on page 5, preceded by one page of commentary.
  • Jean van Heijenoort editor, 1967, 3rd edition 1967. From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass., ISBN 0-674-32449-8 (pbk). van Heijenoort did the translation. He states that "Professor Gödel approved the translation, which in many places was accommodated to his wishes." (p. 595). Gödel's paper begins on p. 595; van Heijenoort's commentary begins on p. 592.
  • Martin Davis editor, 1965, ibid. "On Undecidable Propositions of Formal Mathematical Systems." A copy with Gödel's corrections of errata and Gödel's added notes begins on page 41, preceded by two pages of Davis's commentary. Until Davis included this in his volume this lecture existed only as mimeographed notes.

Articles by others Edit

  • George Boolos, 1989, "A New Proof of the Gödel Incompleteness Theorem", Notices of the American Mathematical Society, v, 36, pp. 388–390 and p. 676, reprinted in Boolos, George (1998). Logic, logic, and logic. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-53766-1.
  • Bernd Buldt, 2014, "The Scope of Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem 2016-03-06 at the Wayback Machine", Logica Universalis, v. 8, pp. 499–552. doi:10.1007/s11787-014-0107-3
  • Charlesworth, Arthur (1981). "A Proof of Godel's Theorem in Terms of Computer Programs". Mathematics Magazine. 54 (3): 109–121. doi:10.2307/2689794. JSTOR 2689794.
  • Davis, Martin (1965). The Undecidable: Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems and Computable Functions. Raven Press. ISBN 978-0-911216-01-1.
  • Davis, Martin (2006). "The Incompleteness Theorem" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 53 (4): 414.
  • Grattan-Guinness, Ivor, ed. (2005). Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640-1940. Elsevier. ISBN 9780444508713.
  • van Heijenoort, Jean (1967). "Gödel's Theorem". In Edwards, Paul (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 3. Macmillan. pp. 348–357.
  • Hellman, Geoffrey (1981). "How to Gödel a Frege-Russell: Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems and Logicism". Noûs. 15 (4 - Special Issue on Philosophy of Mathematics): 451–468. doi:10.2307/2214847. ISSN 0029-4624. JSTOR 2214847.
  • David Hilbert, 1900, "Mathematical Problems." English translation of a lecture delivered before the International Congress of Mathematicians at Paris, containing Hilbert's statement of his Second Problem.
  • Martin Hirzel, 2000, "." An English translation of Gödel's paper. Archived from the original. Sept. 16, 2004.
  • Kikuchi, Makoto; Tanaka, Kazuyuki (July 1994). "On Formalization of Model-Theoretic Proofs of Gödel's Theorems". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 35 (3): 403–412. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1040511346. MR 1326122.
  • Stephen Cole Kleene, 1943, "Recursive predicates and quantifiers", reprinted from Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, v. 53 n. 1, pp. 41–73 in Martin Davis 1965, The Undecidable (loc. cit.) pp. 255–287.
  • Raatikainen, Panu (2020). "Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 7, 2022.
  • Raatikainen, Panu (2005). "On the philosophical relevance of Gödel's incompleteness theorems". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 59 (4): 513–534. doi:10.3917/rip.234.0513. S2CID 52083793.
  • John Barkley Rosser, 1936, "Extensions of some theorems of Gödel and Church", reprinted from the Journal of Symbolic Logic, v. 1 (1936) pp. 87–91, in Martin Davis 1965, The Undecidable (loc. cit.) pp. 230–235.
  • —, 1939, "An Informal Exposition of proofs of Gödel's Theorem and Church's Theorem", Reprinted from the Journal of Symbolic Logic, v. 4 (1939) pp. 53–60, in Martin Davis 1965, The Undecidable (loc. cit.) pp. 223–230
  • Smoryński, C. (1977). "The incompleteness theorems". In Jon Barwise (ed.). Handbook of mathematical logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co. pp. 821–866. ISBN 978-0-444-86388-1.
  • Dan E. Willard, 2001, "Self-Verifying Axiom Systems, the Incompleteness Theorem and Related Reflection Principles", Journal of Symbolic Logic, v. 66 n. 2, pp. 536–596. doi:10.2307/2695030 JSTOR 2695030
  • Zach, Richard (2003). "The Practice of Finitism: Epsilon Calculus and Consistency Proofs in Hilbert's Program" (PDF). Synthese. Springer Science and Business Media LLC. 137 (1): 211–259. arXiv:math/0102189. doi:10.1023/a:1026247421383. ISSN 0039-7857. S2CID 16657040.
  • Zach, Richard (2005). "Kurt Gödel, paper on the incompleteness theorems (1931)". In Grattan-Guinness, Ivor (ed.). Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640-1940. Elsevier. pp. 917–925. doi:10.1016/b978-044450871-3/50152-2. ISBN 9780444508713.

Books about the theorems Edit

Miscellaneous references Edit

External links Edit

`

gödel, incompleteness, theorems, redirects, here, other, uses, disambiguation, theorems, mathematical, logic, that, concerned, with, limits, provability, formal, axiomatic, theories, these, results, published, kurt, gödel, 1931, important, both, mathematical, . Bew redirects here For other uses see Bew disambiguation Godel s incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of provability in formal axiomatic theories These results published by Kurt Godel in 1931 are important both in mathematical logic and in the philosophy of mathematics The theorems are widely but not universally interpreted as showing that Hilbert s program to find a complete and consistent set of axioms for all mathematics is impossible The first incompleteness theorem states that no consistent system of axioms whose theorems can be listed by an effective procedure i e an algorithm is capable of proving all truths about the arithmetic of natural numbers For any such consistent formal system there will always be statements about natural numbers that are true but that are unprovable within the system The second incompleteness theorem an extension of the first shows that the system cannot demonstrate its own consistency Employing a diagonal argument Godel s incompleteness theorems were the first of several closely related theorems on the limitations of formal systems They were followed by Tarski s undefinability theorem on the formal undefinability of truth Church s proof that Hilbert s Entscheidungsproblem is unsolvable and Turing s theorem that there is no algorithm to solve the halting problem Contents 1 Formal systems completeness consistency and effective axiomatization 1 1 Effective axiomatization 1 2 Completeness 1 3 Consistency 1 4 Systems which contain arithmetic 1 5 Conflicting goals 2 First incompleteness theorem 2 1 Syntactic form of the Godel sentence 2 2 Truth of the Godel sentence 2 3 Relationship with the liar paradox 2 4 Extensions of Godel s original result 3 Second incompleteness theorem 3 1 Expressing consistency 3 2 The Hilbert Bernays conditions 3 3 Implications for consistency proofs 4 Examples of undecidable statements 4 1 Undecidable statements provable in larger systems 5 Relationship with computability 6 Proof sketch for the first theorem 6 1 Arithmetization of syntax 6 2 Construction of a statement about provability 6 3 Diagonalization 6 4 Proof via Berry s paradox 6 5 Computer verified proofs 7 Proof sketch for the second theorem 8 Discussion and implications 8 1 Consequences for logicism and Hilbert s second problem 8 2 Minds and machines 8 3 Paraconsistent logic 8 4 Appeals to the incompleteness theorems in other fields 9 History 9 1 Announcement 9 2 Generalization and acceptance 9 3 Criticisms 9 3 1 Finsler 9 3 2 Zermelo 9 3 3 Wittgenstein 10 See also 11 References 11 1 Citations 11 2 Articles by Godel 11 3 Translations during his lifetime of Godel s paper into English 11 4 Articles by others 11 5 Books about the theorems 11 6 Miscellaneous references 12 External linksFormal systems completeness consistency and effective axiomatization EditThe incompleteness theorems apply to formal systems that are of sufficient complexity to express the basic arithmetic of the natural numbers and which are consistent and effectively axiomatized Particularly in the context of first order logic formal systems are also called formal theories In general a formal system is a deductive apparatus that consists of a particular set of axioms along with rules of symbolic manipulation or rules of inference that allow for the derivation of new theorems from the axioms One example of such a system is first order Peano arithmetic a system in which all variables are intended to denote natural numbers In other systems such as set theory only some sentences of the formal system express statements about the natural numbers The incompleteness theorems are about formal provability within these systems rather than about provability in an informal sense There are several properties that a formal system may have including completeness consistency and the existence of an effective axiomatization The incompleteness theorems show that systems which contain a sufficient amount of arithmetic cannot possess all three of these properties Effective axiomatization Edit A formal system is said to be effectively axiomatized also called effectively generated if its set of theorems is recursively enumerable Franzen 2005 p 112 This means that there is a computer program that in principle could enumerate all the theorems of the system without listing any statements that are not theorems Examples of effectively generated theories include Peano arithmetic and Zermelo Fraenkel set theory ZFC The theory known as true arithmetic consists of all true statements about the standard integers in the language of Peano arithmetic This theory is consistent and complete and contains a sufficient amount of arithmetic However it does not have a recursively enumerable set of axioms and thus does not satisfy the hypotheses of the incompleteness theorems Completeness Edit A set of axioms is syntactically or negation complete if for any statement in the axioms language that statement or its negation is provable from the axioms Smith 2007 p 24 This is the notion relevant for Godel s first Incompleteness theorem It is not to be confused with semantic completeness which means that the set of axioms proves all the semantic tautologies of the given language In his completeness theorem not to be confused with the incompleteness theorems described here Godel proved that first order logic is semantically complete But it is not syntactically complete since there are sentences expressible in the language of first order logic that can be neither proved nor disproved from the axioms of logic alone In a system of mathematics thinkers such as Hilbert had believed that it is just a matter of time to find such an axiomatization that would allow one to either prove or disprove by proving its negation each and every mathematical formula A formal system might be syntactically incomplete by design as logics generally are Or it may be incomplete simply because not all the necessary axioms have been discovered or included For example Euclidean geometry without the parallel postulate is incomplete because some statements in the language such as the parallel postulate itself can not be proved from the remaining axioms Similarly the theory of dense linear orders is not complete but becomes complete with an extra axiom stating that there are no endpoints in the order The continuum hypothesis is a statement in the language of ZFC that is not provable within ZFC so ZFC is not complete In this case there is no obvious candidate for a new axiom that resolves the issue The theory of first order Peano arithmetic seems to be consistent Assuming this is indeed the case note that it has an infinite but recursively enumerable set of axioms and can encode enough arithmetic for the hypotheses of the incompleteness theorem Thus by the first incompleteness theorem Peano Arithmetic is not complete The theorem gives an explicit example of a statement of arithmetic that is neither provable nor disprovable in Peano s arithmetic Moreover this statement is true in the usual model In addition no effectively axiomatized consistent extension of Peano arithmetic can be complete Consistency Edit A set of axioms is simply consistent if there is no statement such that both the statement and its negation are provable from the axioms and inconsistent otherwise That is to say a consistent axiomatic system is one that is free from contradiction Peano arithmetic is provably consistent from ZFC but not from within itself Similarly ZFC is not provably consistent from within itself but ZFC there exists an inaccessible cardinal proves ZFC is consistent because if k is the least such cardinal then Vk sitting inside the von Neumann universe is a model of ZFC and a theory is consistent if and only if it has a model If one takes all statements in the language of Peano arithmetic as axioms then this theory is complete has a recursively enumerable set of axioms and can describe addition and multiplication However it is not consistent Additional examples of inconsistent theories arise from the paradoxes that result when the axiom schema of unrestricted comprehension is assumed in set theory Systems which contain arithmetic Edit The incompleteness theorems apply only to formal systems which are able to prove a sufficient collection of facts about the natural numbers One sufficient collection is the set of theorems of Robinson arithmetic Q Some systems such as Peano arithmetic can directly express statements about natural numbers Others such as ZFC set theory are able to interpret statements about natural numbers into their language Either of these options is appropriate for the incompleteness theorems The theory of algebraically closed fields of a given characteristic is complete consistent and has an infinite but recursively enumerable set of axioms However it is not possible to encode the integers into this theory and the theory cannot describe arithmetic of integers A similar example is the theory of real closed fields which is essentially equivalent to Tarski s axioms for Euclidean geometry So Euclidean geometry itself in Tarski s formulation is an example of a complete consistent effectively axiomatized theory The system of Presburger arithmetic consists of a set of axioms for the natural numbers with just the addition operation multiplication is omitted Presburger arithmetic is complete consistent and recursively enumerable and can encode addition but not multiplication of natural numbers showing that for Godel s theorems one needs the theory to encode not just addition but also multiplication Dan Willard 2001 has studied some weak families of arithmetic systems which allow enough arithmetic as relations to formalise Godel numbering but which are not strong enough to have multiplication as a function and so fail to prove the second incompleteness theorem that is to say these systems are consistent and capable of proving their own consistency see self verifying theories Conflicting goals Edit In choosing a set of axioms one goal is to be able to prove as many correct results as possible without proving any incorrect results For example we could imagine a set of true axioms which allow us to prove every true arithmetical claim about the natural numbers Smith 2007 p 2 In the standard system of first order logic an inconsistent set of axioms will prove every statement in its language this is sometimes called the principle of explosion and is thus automatically complete A set of axioms that is both complete and consistent however proves a maximal set of non contradictory theorems citation needed The pattern illustrated in the previous sections with Peano arithmetic ZFC and ZFC there exists an inaccessible cardinal cannot generally be broken Here ZFC there exists an inaccessible cardinal cannot from itself be proved consistent It is also not complete as illustrated by the continuum hypothesis which is unresolvable 1 in ZFC there exists an inaccessible cardinal The first incompleteness theorem shows that in formal systems that can express basic arithmetic a complete and consistent finite list of axioms can never be created each time an additional consistent statement is added as an axiom there are other true statements that still cannot be proved even with the new axiom If an axiom is ever added that makes the system complete it does so at the cost of making the system inconsistent It is not even possible for an infinite list of axioms to be complete consistent and effectively axiomatized First incompleteness theorem EditSee also Proof sketch for Godel s first incompleteness theorem Godel s first incompleteness theorem first appeared as Theorem VI in Godel s 1931 paper On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I The hypotheses of the theorem were improved shortly thereafter by J Barkley Rosser 1936 using Rosser s trick The resulting theorem incorporating Rosser s improvement may be paraphrased in English as follows where formal system includes the assumption that the system is effectively generated First Incompleteness Theorem Any consistent formal system F within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out is incomplete i e there are statements of the language of F which can neither be proved nor disproved in F Raatikainen 2020 The unprovable statement GF referred to by the theorem is often referred to as the Godel sentence for the system F The proof constructs a particular Godel sentence for the system F but there are infinitely many statements in the language of the system that share the same properties such as the conjunction of the Godel sentence and any logically valid sentence Each effectively generated system has its own Godel sentence It is possible to define a larger system F that contains the whole of F plus GF as an additional axiom This will not result in a complete system because Godel s theorem will also apply to F and thus F also cannot be complete In this case GF is indeed a theorem in F because it is an axiom Because GF states only that it is not provable in F no contradiction is presented by its provability within F However because the incompleteness theorem applies to F there will be a new Godel statement GF for F showing that F is also incomplete GF will differ from GF in that GF will refer to F rather than F Syntactic form of the Godel sentence Edit The Godel sentence is designed to refer indirectly to itself The sentence states that when a particular sequence of steps is used to construct another sentence that constructed sentence will not be provable in F However the sequence of steps is such that the constructed sentence turns out to be GF itself In this way the Godel sentence GF indirectly states its own unprovability within F Smith 2007 p 135 To prove the first incompleteness theorem Godel demonstrated that the notion of provability within a system could be expressed purely in terms of arithmetical functions that operate on Godel numbers of sentences of the system Therefore the system which can prove certain facts about numbers can also indirectly prove facts about its own statements provided that it is effectively generated Questions about the provability of statements within the system are represented as questions about the arithmetical properties of numbers themselves which would be decidable by the system if it were complete Thus although the Godel sentence refers indirectly to sentences of the system F when read as an arithmetical statement the Godel sentence directly refers only to natural numbers It asserts that no natural number has a particular property where that property is given by a primitive recursive relation Smith 2007 p 141 As such the Godel sentence can be written in the language of arithmetic with a simple syntactic form In particular it can be expressed as a formula in the language of arithmetic consisting of a number of leading universal quantifiers followed by a quantifier free body these formulas are at level P 1 0 displaystyle Pi 1 0 nbsp of the arithmetical hierarchy Via the MRDP theorem the Godel sentence can be re written as a statement that a particular polynomial in many variables with integer coefficients never takes the value zero when integers are substituted for its variables Franzen 2005 p 71 Truth of the Godel sentence Edit The first incompleteness theorem shows that the Godel sentence GF of an appropriate formal theory F is unprovable in F Because when interpreted as a statement about arithmetic this unprovability is exactly what the sentence indirectly asserts the Godel sentence is in fact true Smorynski 1977 p 825 also see Franzen 2005 pp 28 33 For this reason the sentence GF is often said to be true but unprovable Raatikainen 2020 However since the Godel sentence cannot itself formally specify its intended interpretation the truth of the sentence GF may only be arrived at via a meta analysis from outside the system In general this meta analysis can be carried out within the weak formal system known as primitive recursive arithmetic which proves the implication Con F GF where Con F is a canonical sentence asserting the consistency of F Smorynski 1977 p 840 Kikuchi amp Tanaka 1994 p 403 Although the Godel sentence of a consistent theory is true as a statement about the intended interpretation of arithmetic the Godel sentence will be false in some nonstandard models of arithmetic as a consequence of Godel s completeness theorem Franzen 2005 p 135 That theorem shows that when a sentence is independent of a theory the theory will have models in which the sentence is true and models in which the sentence is false As described earlier the Godel sentence of a system F is an arithmetical statement which claims that no number exists with a particular property The incompleteness theorem shows that this claim will be independent of the system F and the truth of the Godel sentence follows from the fact that no standard natural number has the property in question Any model in which the Godel sentence is false must contain some element which satisfies the property within that model Such a model must be nonstandard it must contain elements that do not correspond to any standard natural number Raatikainen 2020 Franzen 2005 p 135 Relationship with the liar paradox Edit Godel specifically cites Richard s paradox and the liar paradox as semantical analogues to his syntactical incompleteness result in the introductory section of On Formally Undecidable Propositions in Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I The liar paradox is the sentence This sentence is false An analysis of the liar sentence shows that it cannot be true for then as it asserts it is false nor can it be false for then it is true A Godel sentence G for a system F makes a similar assertion to the liar sentence but with truth replaced by provability G says G is not provable in the system F The analysis of the truth and provability of G is a formalized version of the analysis of the truth of the liar sentence It is not possible to replace not provable with false in a Godel sentence because the predicate Q is the Godel number of a false formula cannot be represented as a formula of arithmetic This result known as Tarski s undefinability theorem was discovered independently both by Godel when he was working on the proof of the incompleteness theorem and by the theorem s namesake Alfred Tarski Extensions of Godel s original result Edit Compared to the theorems stated in Godel s 1931 paper many contemporary statements of the incompleteness theorems are more general in two ways These generalized statements are phrased to apply to a broader class of systems and they are phrased to incorporate weaker consistency assumptions Godel demonstrated the incompleteness of the system of Principia Mathematica a particular system of arithmetic but a parallel demonstration could be given for any effective system of a certain expressiveness Godel commented on this fact in the introduction to his paper but restricted the proof to one system for concreteness In modern statements of the theorem it is common to state the effectiveness and expressiveness conditions as hypotheses for the incompleteness theorem so that it is not limited to any particular formal system The terminology used to state these conditions was not yet developed in 1931 when Godel published his results Godel s original statement and proof of the incompleteness theorem requires the assumption that the system is not just consistent but w consistent A system is w consistent if it is not w inconsistent and is w inconsistent if there is a predicate P such that for every specific natural number m the system proves P m and yet the system also proves that there exists a natural number n such that P n That is the system says that a number with property P exists while denying that it has any specific value The w consistency of a system implies its consistency but consistency does not imply w consistency J Barkley Rosser 1936 strengthened the incompleteness theorem by finding a variation of the proof Rosser s trick that only requires the system to be consistent rather than w consistent This is mostly of technical interest because all true formal theories of arithmetic theories whose axioms are all true statements about natural numbers are w consistent and thus Godel s theorem as originally stated applies to them The stronger version of the incompleteness theorem that only assumes consistency rather than w consistency is now commonly known as Godel s incompleteness theorem and as the Godel Rosser theorem Second incompleteness theorem EditFor each formal system F containing basic arithmetic it is possible to canonically define a formula Cons F expressing the consistency of F This formula expresses the property that there does not exist a natural number coding a formal derivation within the system F whose conclusion is a syntactic contradiction The syntactic contradiction is often taken to be 0 1 in which case Cons F states there is no natural number that codes a derivation of 0 1 from the axioms of F Godel s second incompleteness theorem shows that under general assumptions this canonical consistency statement Cons F will not be provable in F The theorem first appeared as Theorem XI in Godel s 1931 paper On Formally Undecidable Propositions in Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I In the following statement the term formalized system also includes an assumption that F is effectively axiomatized Second Incompleteness Theorem For any consistent system F within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out the consistency of F cannot be proved in F itself Raatikainen 2020 can also be written as Assume F is a consistent formalized system which contains elementary arithmetic Then F Cons F displaystyle F not vdash text Cons F nbsp Raatikainen 2020 Then F does not prove consistency of F This theorem is stronger than the first incompleteness theorem because the statement constructed in the first incompleteness theorem does not directly express the consistency of the system The proof of the second incompleteness theorem is obtained by formalizing the proof of the first incompleteness theorem within the system F itself Expressing consistency Edit There is a technical subtlety in the second incompleteness theorem regarding the method of expressing the consistency of F as a formula in the language of F There are many ways to express the consistency of a system and not all of them lead to the same result The formula Cons F from the second incompleteness theorem is a particular expression of consistency Other formalizations of the claim that F is consistent may be inequivalent in F and some may even be provable For example first order Peano arithmetic PA can prove that the largest consistent subset of PA is consistent But because PA is consistent the largest consistent subset of PA is just PA so in this sense PA proves that it is consistent What PA does not prove is that the largest consistent subset of PA is in fact the whole of PA The term largest consistent subset of PA is meant here to be the largest consistent initial segment of the axioms of PA under some particular effective enumeration The Hilbert Bernays conditions Edit The standard proof of the second incompleteness theorem assumes that the provability predicate ProvA P satisfies the Hilbert Bernays provability conditions Letting P represent the Godel number of a formula P the provability conditions say If F proves P then F proves ProvA P F proves 1 that is F proves ProvA P ProvA ProvA P F proves ProvA P Q ProvA P ProvA Q analogue of modus ponens There are systems such as Robinson arithmetic which are strong enough to meet the assumptions of the first incompleteness theorem but which do not prove the Hilbert Bernays conditions Peano arithmetic however is strong enough to verify these conditions as are all theories stronger than Peano arithmetic Implications for consistency proofs Edit Godel s second incompleteness theorem also implies that a system F1 satisfying the technical conditions outlined above cannot prove the consistency of any system F2 that proves the consistency of F1 This is because such a system F1 can prove that if F2 proves the consistency of F1 then F1 is in fact consistent For the claim that F1 is consistent has form for all numbers n n has the decidable property of not being a code for a proof of contradiction in F1 If F1 were in fact inconsistent then F2 would prove for some n that n is the code of a contradiction in F1 But if F2 also proved that F1 is consistent that is that there is no such n then it would itself be inconsistent This reasoning can be formalized in F1 to show that if F2 is consistent then F1 is consistent Since by second incompleteness theorem F1 does not prove its consistency it cannot prove the consistency of F2 either This corollary of the second incompleteness theorem shows that there is no hope of proving for example the consistency of Peano arithmetic using any finitistic means that can be formalized in a system the consistency of which is provable in Peano arithmetic PA For example the system of primitive recursive arithmetic PRA which is widely accepted as an accurate formalization of finitistic mathematics is provably consistent in PA Thus PRA cannot prove the consistency of PA This fact is generally seen to imply that Hilbert s program which aimed to justify the use of ideal infinitistic mathematical principles in the proofs of real finitistic mathematical statements by giving a finitistic proof that the ideal principles are consistent cannot be carried out Franzen 2005 p 106 The corollary also indicates the epistemological relevance of the second incompleteness theorem It would actually provide no interesting information if a system F proved its consistency This is because inconsistent theories prove everything including their consistency Thus a consistency proof of F in F would give us no clue as to whether F really is consistent no doubts about the consistency of F would be resolved by such a consistency proof The interest in consistency proofs lies in the possibility of proving the consistency of a system F in some system F that is in some sense less doubtful than F itself for example weaker than F For many naturally occurring theories F and F such as F Zermelo Fraenkel set theory and F primitive recursive arithmetic the consistency of F is provable in F and thus F cannot prove the consistency of F by the above corollary of the second incompleteness theorem The second incompleteness theorem does not rule out altogether the possibility of proving the consistency of some theory T only doing so in a theory that T itself can prove to be consistent For example Gerhard Gentzen proved the consistency of Peano arithmetic in a different system that includes an axiom asserting that the ordinal called e0 is wellfounded see Gentzen s consistency proof Gentzen s theorem spurred the development of ordinal analysis in proof theory Examples of undecidable statements EditSee also List of statements independent of ZFC There are two distinct senses of the word undecidable in mathematics and computer science The first of these is the proof theoretic sense used in relation to Godel s theorems that of a statement being neither provable nor refutable in a specified deductive system The second sense which will not be discussed here is used in relation to computability theory and applies not to statements but to decision problems which are countably infinite sets of questions each requiring a yes or no answer Such a problem is said to be undecidable if there is no computable function that correctly answers every question in the problem set see undecidable problem Because of the two meanings of the word undecidable the term independent is sometimes used instead of undecidable for the neither provable nor refutable sense Undecidability of a statement in a particular deductive system does not in and of itself address the question of whether the truth value of the statement is well defined or whether it can be determined by other means Undecidability only implies that the particular deductive system being considered does not prove the truth or falsity of the statement Whether there exist so called absolutely undecidable statements whose truth value can never be known or is ill specified is a controversial point in the philosophy of mathematics The combined work of Godel and Paul Cohen has given two concrete examples of undecidable statements in the first sense of the term The continuum hypothesis can neither be proved nor refuted in ZFC the standard axiomatization of set theory and the axiom of choice can neither be proved nor refuted in ZF which is all the ZFC axioms except the axiom of choice These results do not require the incompleteness theorem Godel proved in 1940 that neither of these statements could be disproved in ZF or ZFC set theory In the 1960s Cohen proved that neither is provable from ZF and the continuum hypothesis cannot be proved from ZFC In 1973 Saharon Shelah showed that the Whitehead problem in group theory is undecidable in the first sense of the term in standard set theory 2 Gregory Chaitin produced undecidable statements in algorithmic information theory and proved another incompleteness theorem in that setting Chaitin s incompleteness theorem states that for any system that can represent enough arithmetic there is an upper bound c such that no specific number can be proved in that system to have Kolmogorov complexity greater than c While Godel s theorem is related to the liar paradox Chaitin s result is related to Berry s paradox Undecidable statements provable in larger systems Edit These are natural mathematical equivalents of the Godel true but undecidable sentence They can be proved in a larger system which is generally accepted as a valid form of reasoning but are undecidable in a more limited system such as Peano Arithmetic In 1977 Paris and Harrington proved that the Paris Harrington principle a version of the infinite Ramsey theorem is undecidable in first order Peano arithmetic but can be proved in the stronger system of second order arithmetic Kirby and Paris later showed that Goodstein s theorem a statement about sequences of natural numbers somewhat simpler than the Paris Harrington principle is also undecidable in Peano arithmetic Kruskal s tree theorem which has applications in computer science is also undecidable from Peano arithmetic but provable in set theory In fact Kruskal s tree theorem or its finite form is undecidable in a much stronger system ATR0 codifying the principles acceptable based on a philosophy of mathematics called predicativism 3 The related but more general graph minor theorem 2003 has consequences for computational complexity theory Relationship with computability EditSee also Halting problem Godel s incompleteness theorems The incompleteness theorem is closely related to several results about undecidable sets in recursion theory Stephen Cole Kleene 1943 presented a proof of Godel s incompleteness theorem using basic results of computability theory One such result shows that the halting problem is undecidable there is no computer program that can correctly determine given any program P as input whether P eventually halts when run with a particular given input Kleene showed that the existence of a complete effective system of arithmetic with certain consistency properties would force the halting problem to be decidable a contradiction This method of proof has also been presented by Shoenfield 1967 p 132 Charlesworth 1981 and Hopcroft amp Ullman 1979 Franzen 2005 p 73 explains how Matiyasevich s solution to Hilbert s 10th problem can be used to obtain a proof to Godel s first incompleteness theorem Matiyasevich proved that there is no algorithm that given a multivariate polynomial p x1 x2 xk with integer coefficients determines whether there is an integer solution to the equation p 0 Because polynomials with integer coefficients and integers themselves are directly expressible in the language of arithmetic if a multivariate integer polynomial equation p 0 does have a solution in the integers then any sufficiently strong system of arithmetic T will prove this Moreover if the system T is w consistent then it will never prove that a particular polynomial equation has a solution when in fact there is no solution in the integers Thus if T were complete and w consistent it would be possible to determine algorithmically whether a polynomial equation has a solution by merely enumerating proofs of T until either p has a solution or p has no solution is found in contradiction to Matiyasevich s theorem Hence it follows that T cannot be w consistent and complete Moreover for each consistent effectively generated system T it is possible to effectively generate a multivariate polynomial p over the integers such that the equation p 0 has no solutions over the integers but the lack of solutions cannot be proved in T Davis 2006 p 416 Jones 1980 Smorynski 1977 p 842 shows how the existence of recursively inseparable sets can be used to prove the first incompleteness theorem This proof is often extended to show that systems such as Peano arithmetic are essentially undecidable see Kleene 1967 p 274 Chaitin s incompleteness theorem gives a different method of producing independent sentences based on Kolmogorov complexity Like the proof presented by Kleene that was mentioned above Chaitin s theorem only applies to theories with the additional property that all their axioms are true in the standard model of the natural numbers Godel s incompleteness theorem is distinguished by its applicability to consistent theories that nonetheless include statements that are false in the standard model these theories are known as w inconsistent Proof sketch for the first theorem EditMain article Proof sketch for Godel s first incompleteness theorem The proof by contradiction has three essential parts To begin choose a formal system that meets the proposed criteria Statements in the system can be represented by natural numbers known as Godel numbers The significance of this is that properties of statements such as their truth and falsehood will be equivalent to determining whether their Godel numbers have certain properties and that properties of the statements can therefore be demonstrated by examining their Godel numbers This part culminates in the construction of a formula expressing the idea that statement S is provable in the system which can be applied to any statement S in the system In the formal system it is possible to construct a number whose matching statement when interpreted is self referential and essentially says that it i e the statement itself is unprovable This is done using a technique called diagonalization so called because of its origins as Cantor s diagonal argument Within the formal system this statement permits a demonstration that it is neither provable nor disprovable in the system and therefore the system cannot in fact be w consistent Hence the original assumption that the proposed system met the criteria is false Arithmetization of syntax Edit The main problem in fleshing out the proof described above is that it seems at first that to construct a statement p that is equivalent to p cannot be proved p would somehow have to contain a reference to p which could easily give rise to an infinite regress Godel s technique is to show that statements can be matched with numbers often called the arithmetization of syntax in such a way that proving a statement can be replaced with testing whether a number has a given property This allows a self referential formula to be constructed in a way that avoids any infinite regress of definitions The same technique was later used by Alan Turing in his work on the Entscheidungsproblem In simple terms a method can be devised so that every formula or statement that can be formulated in the system gets a unique number called its Godel number in such a way that it is possible to mechanically convert back and forth between formulas and Godel numbers The numbers involved might be very long indeed in terms of number of digits but this is not a barrier all that matters is that such numbers can be constructed A simple example is how English can be stored as a sequence of numbers for each letter and then combined into a single larger number The word hello is encoded as 104 101 108 108 111 in ASCII which can be converted into the number 104101108108111 The logical statement x y gt y x is encoded as 120 061 121 032 061 062 032 121 061 120 in ASCII which can be converted into the number 120061121032061062032121061120 In principle proving a statement true or false can be shown to be equivalent to proving that the number matching the statement does or does not have a given property Because the formal system is strong enough to support reasoning about numbers in general it can support reasoning about numbers that represent formulae and statements as well Crucially because the system can support reasoning about properties of numbers the results are equivalent to reasoning about provability of their equivalent statements Construction of a statement about provability Edit Having shown that in principle the system can indirectly make statements about provability by analyzing properties of those numbers representing statements it is now possible to show how to create a statement that actually does this A formula F x that contains exactly one free variable x is called a statement form or class sign As soon as x is replaced by a specific number the statement form turns into a bona fide statement and it is then either provable in the system or not For certain formulas one can show that for every natural number n F n displaystyle F n nbsp is true if and only if it can be proved the precise requirement in the original proof is weaker but for the proof sketch this will suffice In particular this is true for every specific arithmetic operation between a finite number of natural numbers such as 2 3 6 Statement forms themselves are not statements and therefore cannot be proved or disproved But every statement form F x can be assigned a Godel number denoted by G F The choice of the free variable used in the form F x is not relevant to the assignment of the Godel number G F The notion of provability itself can also be encoded by Godel numbers in the following way since a proof is a list of statements which obey certain rules the Godel number of a proof can be defined Now for every statement p one may ask whether a number x is the Godel number of its proof The relation between the Godel number of p and x the potential Godel number of its proof is an arithmetical relation between two numbers Therefore there is a statement form Bew y that uses this arithmetical relation to state that a Godel number of a proof of y exists Bew y x y is the Godel number of a formula and x is the Godel number of a proof of the formula encoded by y The name Bew is short for beweisbar the German word for provable this name was originally used by Godel to denote the provability formula just described Note that Bew y is merely an abbreviation that represents a particular very long formula in the original language of T the string Bew itself is not claimed to be part of this language An important feature of the formula Bew y is that if a statement p is provable in the system then Bew G p is also provable This is because any proof of p would have a corresponding Godel number the existence of which causes Bew G p to be satisfied Diagonalization Edit The next step in the proof is to obtain a statement which indirectly asserts its own unprovability Although Godel constructed this statement directly the existence of at least one such statement follows from the diagonal lemma which says that for any sufficiently strong formal system and any statement form F there is a statement p such that the system proves p F G p By letting F be the negation of Bew x we obtain the theorem p Bew G p and the p defined by this roughly states that its own Godel number is the Godel number of an unprovable formula The statement p is not literally equal to Bew G p rather p states that if a certain calculation is performed the resulting Godel number will be that of an unprovable statement But when this calculation is performed the resulting Godel number turns out to be the Godel number of p itself This is similar to the following sentence in English when preceded by itself in quotes is unprovable when preceded by itself in quotes is unprovable This sentence does not directly refer to itself but when the stated transformation is made the original sentence is obtained as a result and thus this sentence indirectly asserts its own unprovability The proof of the diagonal lemma employs a similar method Now assume that the axiomatic system is w consistent and let p be the statement obtained in the previous section If p were provable then Bew G p would be provable as argued above But p asserts the negation of Bew G p Thus the system would be inconsistent proving both a statement and its negation This contradiction shows that p cannot be provable If the negation of p were provable then Bew G p would be provable because p was constructed to be equivalent to the negation of Bew G p However for each specific number x x cannot be the Godel number of the proof of p because p is not provable from the previous paragraph Thus on one hand the system proves there is a number with a certain property that it is the Godel number of the proof of p but on the other hand for every specific number x we can prove that it does not have this property This is impossible in an w consistent system Thus the negation of p is not provable Thus the statement p is undecidable in our axiomatic system it can neither be proved nor disproved within the system In fact to show that p is not provable only requires the assumption that the system is consistent The stronger assumption of w consistency is required to show that the negation of p is not provable Thus if p is constructed for a particular system If the system is w consistent it can prove neither p nor its negation and so p is undecidable If the system is consistent it may have the same situation or it may prove the negation of p In the later case we have a statement not p which is false but provable and the system is not w consistent If one tries to add the missing axioms to avoid the incompleteness of the system then one has to add either p or not p as axioms But then the definition of being a Godel number of a proof of a statement changes which means that the formula Bew x is now different Thus when we apply the diagonal lemma to this new Bew we obtain a new statement p different from the previous one which will be undecidable in the new system if it is w consistent Proof via Berry s paradox Edit George Boolos 1989 sketches an alternative proof of the first incompleteness theorem that uses Berry s paradox rather than the liar paradox to construct a true but unprovable formula A similar proof method was independently discovered by Saul Kripke Boolos 1998 p 383 Boolos s proof proceeds by constructing for any computably enumerable set S of true sentences of arithmetic another sentence which is true but not contained in S This gives the first incompleteness theorem as a corollary According to Boolos this proof is interesting because it provides a different sort of reason for the incompleteness of effective consistent theories of arithmetic Boolos 1998 p 388 Computer verified proofs Edit See also Automated theorem proving The incompleteness theorems are among a relatively small number of nontrivial theorems that have been transformed into formalized theorems that can be completely verified by proof assistant software Godel s original proofs of the incompleteness theorems like most mathematical proofs were written in natural language intended for human readers Computer verified proofs of versions of the first incompleteness theorem were announced by Natarajan Shankar in 1986 using Nqthm Shankar 1994 by Russell O Connor in 2003 using Coq O Connor 2005 and by John Harrison in 2009 using HOL Light Harrison 2009 A computer verified proof of both incompleteness theorems was announced by Lawrence Paulson in 2013 using Isabelle Paulson 2014 Proof sketch for the second theorem EditSee also Hilbert Bernays provability conditions The main difficulty in proving the second incompleteness theorem is to show that various facts about provability used in the proof of the first incompleteness theorem can be formalized within a system S using a formal predicate P for provability Once this is done the second incompleteness theorem follows by formalizing the entire proof of the first incompleteness theorem within the system S itself Let p stand for the undecidable sentence constructed above and assume for purposes of obtaining a contradiction that the consistency of the system S can be proved from within the system S itself This is equivalent to proving the statement System S is consistent Now consider the statement c where c If the system S is consistent then p is not provable The proof of sentence c can be formalized within the system S and therefore the statement c p is not provable or identically not P p can be proved in the system S Observe then that if we can prove that the system S is consistent ie the statement in the hypothesis of c then we have proved that p is not provable But this is a contradiction since by the 1st Incompleteness Theorem this sentence ie what is implied in the sentence c p is not provable is what we construct to be unprovable Notice that this is why we require formalizing the first Incompleteness Theorem in S to prove the 2nd Incompleteness Theorem we obtain a contradiction with the 1st Incompleteness Theorem which can do only by showing that the theorem holds in S So we cannot prove that the system S is consistent And the 2nd Incompleteness Theorem statement follows Discussion and implications EditThe incompleteness results affect the philosophy of mathematics particularly versions of formalism which use a single system of formal logic to define their principles Consequences for logicism and Hilbert s second problem Edit The incompleteness theorem is sometimes thought to have severe consequences for the program of logicism proposed by Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell which aimed to define the natural numbers in terms of logic Hellman 1981 pp 451 468 Bob Hale and Crispin Wright argue that it is not a problem for logicism because the incompleteness theorems apply equally to first order logic as they do to arithmetic They argue that only those who believe that the natural numbers are to be defined in terms of first order logic have this problem Many logicians believe that Godel s incompleteness theorems struck a fatal blow to David Hilbert s second problem which asked for a finitary consistency proof for mathematics The second incompleteness theorem in particular is often viewed as making the problem impossible Not all mathematicians agree with this analysis however and the status of Hilbert s second problem is not yet decided see Modern viewpoints on the status of the problem Minds and machines Edit Main article Mechanism philosophy Godelian arguments Authors including the philosopher J R Lucas and physicist Roger Penrose have debated what if anything Godel s incompleteness theorems imply about human intelligence Much of the debate centers on whether the human mind is equivalent to a Turing machine or by the Church Turing thesis any finite machine at all If it is and if the machine is consistent then Godel s incompleteness theorems would apply to it Hilary Putnam 1960 suggested that while Godel s theorems cannot be applied to humans since they make mistakes and are therefore inconsistent it may be applied to the human faculty of science or mathematics in general Assuming that it is consistent either its consistency cannot be proved or it cannot be represented by a Turing machine Avi Wigderson 2010 has proposed that the concept of mathematical knowability should be based on computational complexity rather than logical decidability He writes that when knowability is interpreted by modern standards namely via computational complexity the Godel phenomena are very much with us Douglas Hofstadter in his books Godel Escher Bach and I Am a Strange Loop cites Godel s theorems as an example of what he calls a strange loop a hierarchical self referential structure existing within an axiomatic formal system He argues that this is the same kind of structure which gives rise to consciousness the sense of I in the human mind While the self reference in Godel s theorem comes from the Godel sentence asserting its own unprovability within the formal system of Principia Mathematica the self reference in the human mind comes from the way in which the brain abstracts and categorises stimuli into symbols or groups of neurons which respond to concepts in what is effectively also a formal system eventually giving rise to symbols modelling the concept of the very entity doing the perception Hofstadter argues that a strange loop in a sufficiently complex formal system can give rise to a downward or upside down causality a situation in which the normal hierarchy of cause and effect is flipped upside down In the case of Godel s theorem this manifests in short as the following Merely from knowing the formula s meaning one can infer its truth or falsity without any effort to derive it in the old fashioned way which requires one to trudge methodically upwards from the axioms This is not just peculiar it is astonishing Normally one cannot merely look at what a mathematical conjecture says and simply appeal to the content of that statement on its own to deduce whether the statement is true or false I Am a Strange Loop 4 In the case of the mind a far more complex formal system this downward causality manifests in Hofstadter s view as the ineffable human instinct that the causality of our minds lies on the high level of desires concepts personalities thoughts and ideas rather than on the low level of interactions between neurons or even fundamental particles even though according to physics the latter seems to possess the causal power There is thus a curious upside downness to our normal human way of perceiving the world we are built to perceive big stuff rather than small stuff even though the domain of the tiny seems to be where the actual motors driving reality reside I Am a Strange Loop 4 Paraconsistent logic Edit Although Godel s theorems are usually studied in the context of classical logic they also have a role in the study of paraconsistent logic and of inherently contradictory statements dialetheia Graham Priest 1984 2006 argues that replacing the notion of formal proof in Godel s theorem with the usual notion of informal proof can be used to show that naive mathematics is inconsistent and uses this as evidence for dialetheism The cause of this inconsistency is the inclusion of a truth predicate for a system within the language of the system Priest 2006 p 47 Stewart Shapiro 2002 gives a more mixed appraisal of the applications of Godel s theorems to dialetheism Appeals to the incompleteness theorems in other fields Edit Appeals and analogies are sometimes made to the incompleteness theorems in support of arguments that go beyond mathematics and logic Several authors have commented negatively on such extensions and interpretations including Torkel Franzen 2005 Panu Raatikainen 2005 Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont 1999 and Ophelia Benson and Jeremy Stangroom 2006 Sokal amp Bricmont 1999 and Stangroom amp Benson 2006 p 10 for example quote from Rebecca Goldstein s comments on the disparity between Godel s avowed Platonism and the anti realist uses to which his ideas are sometimes put Sokal amp Bricmont 1999 p 187 criticize Regis Debray s invocation of the theorem in the context of sociology Debray has defended this use as metaphorical ibid History EditAfter Godel published his proof of the completeness theorem as his doctoral thesis in 1929 he turned to a second problem for his habilitation His original goal was to obtain a positive solution to Hilbert s second problem Dawson 1997 p 63 At the time theories of the natural numbers and real numbers similar to second order arithmetic were known as analysis while theories of the natural numbers alone were known as arithmetic Godel was not the only person working on the consistency problem Ackermann had published a flawed consistency proof for analysis in 1925 in which he attempted to use the method of e substitution originally developed by Hilbert Later that year von Neumann was able to correct the proof for a system of arithmetic without any axioms of induction By 1928 Ackermann had communicated a modified proof to Bernays this modified proof led Hilbert to announce his belief in 1929 that the consistency of arithmetic had been demonstrated and that a consistency proof of analysis would likely soon follow After the publication of the incompleteness theorems showed that Ackermann s modified proof must be erroneous von Neumann produced a concrete example showing that its main technique was unsound Zach 2007 p 418 Zach 2003 p 33 In the course of his research Godel discovered that although a sentence which asserts its own falsehood leads to paradox a sentence that asserts its own non provability does not In particular Godel was aware of the result now called Tarski s indefinability theorem although he never published it Godel announced his first incompleteness theorem to Carnap Feigel and Waismann on August 26 1930 all four would attend the Second Conference on the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences a key conference in Konigsberg the following week Announcement Edit The 1930 Konigsberg conference was a joint meeting of three academic societies with many of the key logicians of the time in attendance Carnap Heyting and von Neumann delivered one hour addresses on the mathematical philosophies of logicism intuitionism and formalism respectively Dawson 1996 p 69 The conference also included Hilbert s retirement address as he was leaving his position at the University of Gottingen Hilbert used the speech to argue his belief that all mathematical problems can be solved He ended his address by saying For the mathematician there is no Ignorabimus and in my opinion not at all for natural science either The true reason why no one has succeeded in finding an unsolvable problem is in my opinion that there is no unsolvable problem In contrast to the foolish Ignorabimus our credo avers We must know We shall know This speech quickly became known as a summary of Hilbert s beliefs on mathematics its final six words Wir mussen wissen Wir werden wissen were used as Hilbert s epitaph in 1943 Although Godel was likely in attendance for Hilbert s address the two never met face to face Dawson 1996 p 72 Godel announced his first incompleteness theorem at a roundtable discussion session on the third day of the conference The announcement drew little attention apart from that of von Neumann who pulled Godel aside for conversation Later that year working independently with knowledge of the first incompleteness theorem von Neumann obtained a proof of the second incompleteness theorem which he announced to Godel in a letter dated November 20 1930 Dawson 1996 p 70 Godel had independently obtained the second incompleteness theorem and included it in his submitted manuscript which was received by Monatshefte fur Mathematik on November 17 1930 Godel s paper was published in the Monatshefte in 1931 under the title Uber formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I On Formally Undecidable Propositions in Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I As the title implies Godel originally planned to publish a second part of the paper in the next volume of the Monatshefte the prompt acceptance of the first paper was one reason he changed his plans van Heijenoort 1967 page 328 footnote 68a Generalization and acceptance Edit Godel gave a series of lectures on his theorems at Princeton in 1933 1934 to an audience that included Church Kleene and Rosser By this time Godel had grasped that the key property his theorems required is that the system must be effective at the time the term general recursive was used Rosser proved in 1936 that the hypothesis of w consistency which was an integral part of Godel s original proof could be replaced by simple consistency if the Godel sentence was changed in an appropriate way These developments left the incompleteness theorems in essentially their modern form Gentzen published his consistency proof for first order arithmetic in 1936 Hilbert accepted this proof as finitary although as Godel s theorem had already shown it cannot be formalized within the system of arithmetic that is being proved consistent The impact of the incompleteness theorems on Hilbert s program was quickly realized Bernays included a full proof of the incompleteness theorems in the second volume of Grundlagen der Mathematik 1939 along with additional results of Ackermann on the e substitution method and Gentzen s consistency proof of arithmetic This was the first full published proof of the second incompleteness theorem Criticisms Edit Finsler Edit Paul Finsler 1926 used a version of Richard s paradox to construct an expression that was false but unprovable in a particular informal framework he had developed Godel was unaware of this paper when he proved the incompleteness theorems Collected Works Vol IV p 9 Finsler wrote to Godel in 1931 to inform him about this paper which Finsler felt had priority for an incompleteness theorem Finsler s methods did not rely on formalized provability and had only a superficial resemblance to Godel s work van Heijenoort 1967 p 328 Godel read the paper but found it deeply flawed and his response to Finsler laid out concerns about the lack of formalization Dawson 1996 p 89 Finsler continued to argue for his philosophy of mathematics which eschewed formalization for the remainder of his career Zermelo Edit In September 1931 Ernst Zermelo wrote to Godel to announce what he described as an essential gap in Godel s argument Dawson 1996 p 76 In October Godel replied with a 10 page letter Dawson 1996 p 76 Grattan Guinness 2005 pp 512 513 where he pointed out that Zermelo mistakenly assumed that the notion of truth in a system is definable in that system which is not true in general by Tarski s undefinability theorem But Zermelo did not relent and published his criticisms in print with a rather scathing paragraph on his young competitor Grattan Guinness 2005 pp 513 Godel decided that to pursue the matter further was pointless and Carnap agreed Dawson 1996 p 77 Much of Zermelo s subsequent work was related to logics stronger than first order logic with which he hoped to show both the consistency and categoricity of mathematical theories Wittgenstein Edit Ludwig Wittgenstein wrote several passages about the incompleteness theorems that were published posthumously in his 1953 Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics in particular one section sometimes called the notorious paragraph where he seems to confuse the notions of true and provable in Russell s system Godel was a member of the Vienna Circle during the period in which Wittgenstein s early ideal language philosophy and Tractatus Logico Philosophicus dominated the circle s thinking There has been some controversy about whether Wittgenstein misunderstood the incompleteness theorem or just expressed himself unclearly Writings in Godel s Nachlass express the belief that Wittgenstein misread his ideas Multiple commentators have read Wittgenstein as misunderstanding Godel Rodych 2003 although Juliet Floyd and Hilary Putnam 2000 as well as Graham Priest 2004 have provided textual readings arguing that most commentary misunderstands Wittgenstein On their release Bernays Dummett and Kreisel wrote separate reviews on Wittgenstein s remarks all of which were extremely negative Berto 2009 p 208 The unanimity of this criticism caused Wittgenstein s remarks on the incompleteness theorems to have little impact on the logic community In 1972 Godel stated Has Wittgenstein lost his mind Does he mean it seriously He intentionally utters trivially nonsensical statements Wang 1996 p 179 and wrote to Karl Menger that Wittgenstein s comments demonstrate a misunderstanding of the incompleteness theorems writing It is clear from the passages you cite that Wittgenstein did not understand the first incompleteness theorem or pretended not to understand it He interpreted it as a kind of logical paradox while in fact is just the opposite namely a mathematical theorem within an absolutely uncontroversial part of mathematics finitary number theory or combinatorics Wang 1996 p 179 Since the publication of Wittgenstein s Nachlass in 2000 a series of papers in philosophy have sought to evaluate whether the original criticism of Wittgenstein s remarks was justified Floyd amp Putnam 2000 argue that Wittgenstein had a more complete understanding of the incompleteness theorem than was previously assumed They are particularly concerned with the interpretation of a Godel sentence for an w inconsistent system as actually saying I am not provable since the system has no models in which the provability predicate corresponds to actual provability Rodych 2003 argues that their interpretation of Wittgenstein is not historically justified Berto 2009 explores the relationship between Wittgenstein s writing and theories of paraconsistent logic See also Edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Mathematics portalChaitin s incompleteness theorem Godel Escher Bach Godel machine Godel s completeness theorem Godel s speed up theorem Lob s Theorem Minds Machines and Godel Non standard model of arithmetic Proof theory Provability logic Quining Tarski s undefinability theorem Theory of everything Godel s incompleteness theorem Typographical Number TheoryReferences EditCitations Edit in technical terms independent see Continuum hypothesis Independence from ZFC Shelah Saharon 1974 Infinite Abelian groups Whitehead problem and some constructions Israel Journal of Mathematics 18 3 243 256 doi 10 1007 BF02757281 MR 0357114 S G Simpson Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic 2009 Perspectives in Logic ISBN 9780521884396 a b Hofstadter Douglas R 2007 2003 Chapter 12 On Downward Causality I Am a Strange Loop Basic Books ISBN 978 0 465 03078 1 Articles by Godel Edit Kurt Godel 1931 Uber formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I Monatshefte fur Mathematik und Physik v 38 n 1 pp 173 198 doi 10 1007 BF01700692 1931 Uber formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I in Solomon Feferman ed 1986 Kurt Godel Collected works Vol I Oxford University Press pp 144 195 ISBN 978 0195147209 The original German with a facing English translation preceded by an introductory note by Stephen Cole Kleene 1951 Some basic theorems on the foundations of mathematics and their implications in Solomon Feferman ed 1995 Kurt Godel Collected works Vol III Oxford University Press pp 304 323 ISBN 978 0195147223 Translations during his lifetime of Godel s paper into English Edit None of the following agree in all translated words and in typography The typography is a serious matter because Godel expressly wished to emphasize those metamathematical notions that had been defined in their usual sense before van Heijenoort 1967 p 595 Three translations exist Of the first John Dawson states that The Meltzer translation was seriously deficient and received a devastating review in the Journal of Symbolic Logic Godel also complained about Braithwaite s commentary Dawson 1997 p 216 Fortunately the Meltzer translation was soon supplanted by a better one prepared by Elliott Mendelson for Martin Davis s anthology The Undecidable he found the translation not quite so good as he had expected but because of time constraints he agreed to its publication ibid In a footnote Dawson states that he would regret his compliance for the published volume was marred throughout by sloppy typography and numerous misprints ibid Dawson states that The translation that Godel favored was that by Jean van Heijenoort ibid For the serious student another version exists as a set of lecture notes recorded by Stephen Kleene and J B Rosser during lectures given by Godel at to the Institute for Advanced Study during the spring of 1934 cf commentary by Davis 1965 p 39 and beginning on p 41 this version is titled On Undecidable Propositions of Formal Mathematical Systems In their order of publication B Meltzer translation and R B Braithwaite Introduction 1962 On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems Dover Publications New York Dover edition 1992 ISBN 0 486 66980 7 pbk This contains a useful translation of Godel s German abbreviations on pp 33 34 As noted above typography translation and commentary is suspect Unfortunately this translation was reprinted with all its suspect content byStephen Hawking editor 2005 God Created the Integers The Mathematical Breakthroughs That Changed History Running Press Philadelphia ISBN 0 7624 1922 9 Godel s paper appears starting on p 1097 with Hawking s commentary starting on p 1089 Martin Davis editor 1965 The Undecidable Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions Unsolvable problems and Computable Functions Raven Press New York no ISBN Godel s paper begins on page 5 preceded by one page of commentary Jean van Heijenoort editor 1967 3rd edition 1967 From Frege to Godel A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press Cambridge Mass ISBN 0 674 32449 8 pbk van Heijenoort did the translation He states that Professor Godel approved the translation which in many places was accommodated to his wishes p 595 Godel s paper begins on p 595 van Heijenoort s commentary begins on p 592 Martin Davis editor 1965 ibid On Undecidable Propositions of Formal Mathematical Systems A copy with Godel s corrections of errata and Godel s added notes begins on page 41 preceded by two pages of Davis s commentary Until Davis included this in his volume this lecture existed only as mimeographed notes Articles by others Edit George Boolos 1989 A New Proof of the Godel Incompleteness Theorem Notices of the American Mathematical Society v 36 pp 388 390 and p 676 reprinted in Boolos George 1998 Logic logic and logic Harvard University Press ISBN 0 674 53766 1 Bernd Buldt 2014 The Scope of Godel s First Incompleteness Theorem Archived 2016 03 06 at the Wayback Machine Logica Universalis v 8 pp 499 552 doi 10 1007 s11787 014 0107 3 Charlesworth Arthur 1981 A Proof of Godel s Theorem in Terms of Computer Programs Mathematics Magazine 54 3 109 121 doi 10 2307 2689794 JSTOR 2689794 Davis Martin 1965 The Undecidable Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions Unsolvable Problems and Computable Functions Raven Press ISBN 978 0 911216 01 1 Davis Martin 2006 The Incompleteness Theorem PDF Notices of the AMS 53 4 414 Grattan Guinness Ivor ed 2005 Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640 1940 Elsevier ISBN 9780444508713 van Heijenoort Jean 1967 Godel s Theorem In Edwards Paul ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3 Macmillan pp 348 357 Hellman Geoffrey 1981 How to Godel a Frege Russell Godel s Incompleteness Theorems and Logicism Nous 15 4 Special Issue on Philosophy of Mathematics 451 468 doi 10 2307 2214847 ISSN 0029 4624 JSTOR 2214847 David Hilbert 1900 Mathematical Problems English translation of a lecture delivered before the International Congress of Mathematicians at Paris containing Hilbert s statement of his Second Problem Martin Hirzel 2000 On formally undecidable propositions of Principia Mathematica and related systems I An English translation of Godel s paper Archived from the original Sept 16 2004 Kikuchi Makoto Tanaka Kazuyuki July 1994 On Formalization of Model Theoretic Proofs of Godel s Theorems Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 3 403 412 doi 10 1305 ndjfl 1040511346 MR 1326122 Stephen Cole Kleene 1943 Recursive predicates and quantifiers reprinted from Transactions of the American Mathematical Society v 53 n 1 pp 41 73 in Martin Davis 1965 The Undecidable loc cit pp 255 287 Raatikainen Panu 2020 Godel s Incompleteness Theorems Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved November 7 2022 Raatikainen Panu 2005 On the philosophical relevance of Godel s incompleteness theorems Revue Internationale de Philosophie 59 4 513 534 doi 10 3917 rip 234 0513 S2CID 52083793 John Barkley Rosser 1936 Extensions of some theorems of Godel and Church reprinted from the Journal of Symbolic Logic v 1 1936 pp 87 91 in Martin Davis 1965 The Undecidable loc cit pp 230 235 1939 An Informal Exposition of proofs of Godel s Theorem and Church s Theorem Reprinted from the Journal of Symbolic Logic v 4 1939 pp 53 60 in Martin Davis 1965 The Undecidable loc cit pp 223 230 Smorynski C 1977 The incompleteness theorems In Jon Barwise ed Handbook of mathematical logic Amsterdam North Holland Pub Co pp 821 866 ISBN 978 0 444 86388 1 Dan E Willard 2001 Self Verifying Axiom Systems the Incompleteness Theorem and Related Reflection Principles Journal of Symbolic Logic v 66 n 2 pp 536 596 doi 10 2307 2695030 JSTOR 2695030 Zach Richard 2003 The Practice of Finitism Epsilon Calculus and Consistency Proofs in Hilbert s Program PDF Synthese Springer Science and Business Media LLC 137 1 211 259 arXiv math 0102189 doi 10 1023 a 1026247421383 ISSN 0039 7857 S2CID 16657040 Zach Richard 2005 Kurt Godel paper on the incompleteness theorems 1931 In Grattan Guinness Ivor ed Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics 1640 1940 Elsevier pp 917 925 doi 10 1016 b978 044450871 3 50152 2 ISBN 9780444508713 Books about the theorems Edit Francesco Berto There s Something about Godel The Complete Guide to the Incompleteness Theorem John Wiley and Sons 2010 Norbert Domeisen 1990 Logik der Antinomien Bern Peter Lang 142 S 1990 ISBN 3 261 04214 1 Zbl 0724 03003 Franzen Torkel 2005 Godel s theorem an incomplete guide to its use and abuse Wellesley MA A K Peters ISBN 1 56881 238 8 MR 2146326 Douglas Hofstadter 1979 Godel Escher Bach An Eternal Golden Braid Vintage Books ISBN 0 465 02685 0 1999 reprint ISBN 0 465 02656 7 MR530196 2007 I Am a Strange Loop Basic Books ISBN 978 0 465 03078 1 ISBN 0 465 03078 5 MR2360307 Stanley Jaki OSB 2005 The drama of the quantities Real View Books Per Lindstrom 1997 Aspects of Incompleteness Lecture Notes in Logic v 10 J R Lucas FBA 1970 The Freedom of the Will Clarendon Press Oxford 1970 Adrian William Moore 2022 Godel s Theorem A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press Oxford 2022 Ernest Nagel James Roy Newman Douglas Hofstadter 2002 1958 Godel s Proof revised ed ISBN 0 8147 5816 9 MR1871678 Rudy Rucker 1995 1982 Infinity and the Mind The Science and Philosophy of the Infinite Princeton Univ Press MR658492 Smith Peter 2007 An introduction to Godel s Theorems Cambridge U K Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 67453 9 MR 2384958 Shankar N 1994 Metamathematics machines and Godel s proof Cambridge tracts in theoretical computer science Vol 38 Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 58533 3 Raymond Smullyan 1987 Forever Undecided ISBN 0192801414 puzzles based on undecidability in formal systems 1991 Godel s Incompleteness Theorems Oxford Univ Press 1994 Diagonalization and Self Reference Oxford Univ Press MR1318913 2013 The Godelian Puzzle Book Puzzles Paradoxes and Proofs Courier Corporation ISBN 978 0 486 49705 1 Wang Hao 1996 A Logical Journey From Godel to Philosophy MIT Press ISBN 0 262 23189 1 MR1433803Miscellaneous references Edit Berto Francesco 2009 The Godel Paradox and Wittgenstein s Reasons Philosophia Mathematica III 17 Dawson John W Jr 1996 Logical dilemmas The life and work of Kurt Godel Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 56881 025 6 Dawson John W Jr 1997 Logical dilemmas The life and work of Kurt Godel Wellesley Massachusetts A K Peters ISBN 978 1 56881 256 4 OCLC 36104240 Rebecca Goldstein 2005 Incompleteness the Proof and Paradox of Kurt Godel W W Norton amp Company ISBN 0 393 05169 2 Floyd Juliet Putnam Hilary 2000 A Note on Wittgenstein s Notorious Paragraph about the Godel Theorem The Journal of Philosophy JSTOR 97 11 624 632 doi 10 2307 2678455 ISSN 0022 362X JSTOR 2678455 Harrison J 2009 Handbook of practical logic and automated reasoning Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521899574 David Hilbert and Paul Bernays Grundlagen der Mathematik Springer Verlag Hopcroft John E Ullman Jeffrey 1979 Introduction to Automata Theory Languages and Computation Reading Mass Addison Wesley ISBN 0 201 02988 X Jones James P 1980 Undecidable Diophantine Equations PDF Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 3 2 859 862 doi 10 1090 S0273 0979 1980 14832 6 Kleene Stephen Cole 1967 Mathematical Logic Reprinted by Dover 2002 ISBN 0 486 42533 9 O Connor Russell 2005 Essential Incompleteness of Arithmetic Verified by Coq Theorem Proving in Higher Order Logics Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 3603 pp 245 260 arXiv cs 0505034 doi 10 1007 11541868 16 ISBN 978 3 540 28372 0 S2CID 15610367 Paulson Lawrence 2014 A machine assisted proof of Godel s incompleteness theorems for the theory of hereditarily finite sets Review of Symbolic Logic 7 3 484 498 doi 10 1017 S1755020314000112 S2CID 13913592 Graham Priest 1984 Logic of Paradox Revisited Journal of Philosophical Logic v 13 n 2 pp 153 179 2004 Wittgenstein s Remarks on Godel s Theorem in Max Kolbel ed Wittgenstein s lasting significance Psychology Press pp 207 227 Priest Graham 2006 In Contradiction A Study of the Transconsistent Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 926329 9 Hilary Putnam 1960 Minds and Machines in Sidney Hook ed Dimensions of Mind A Symposium New York University Press Reprinted in Anderson A R ed 1964 Minds and Machines Prentice Hall 77 Wolfgang Rautenberg 2010 A Concise Introduction to Mathematical Logic 3rd ed Springer ISBN 978 1 4419 1220 6 Rodych Victor 2003 Misunderstanding Godel New Arguments about Wittgenstein and New Remarks by Wittgenstein Dialectica 57 3 279 313 doi 10 1111 j 1746 8361 2003 tb00272 x doi 10 1111 j 1746 8361 2003 tb00272 x Stewart Shapiro 2002 Incompleteness and Inconsistency Mind v 111 pp 817 32 doi 10 1093 mind 111 444 817 Sokal Alan Bricmont Jean 1999 Fashionable Nonsense Postmodern Intellectuals Abuse of Science Picador ISBN 0 312 20407 8 Shoenfield Joseph R 1967 Mathematical logic Natick Mass Association for Symbolic Logic published 2001 ISBN 978 1 56881 135 2 Stangroom Jeremy Benson Ophelia 2006 Why Truth Matters Continuum ISBN 0 8264 9528 1 George Tourlakis Lectures in Logic and Set Theory Volume 1 Mathematical Logic Cambridge University Press 2003 ISBN 978 0 521 75373 9 Avi Wigderson 2010 The Godel Phenomena in Mathematics A Modern View in Kurt Godel and the Foundations of Mathematics Horizons of Truth Cambridge University Press Hao Wang 1996 A Logical Journey From Godel to Philosophy The MIT Press Cambridge MA ISBN 0 262 23189 1 Zach Richard 2007 Hilbert s Program Then and Now In Jacquette Dale ed Philosophy of logic Handbook of the Philosophy of Science Vol 5 Amsterdam Elsevier pp 411 447 arXiv math 0508572 doi 10 1016 b978 044451541 4 50014 2 ISBN 978 0 444 51541 4 OCLC 162131413 S2CID 291599 External links EditGodel s Incompleteness Theorems on In Our Time at the BBC Kurt Godel entry by Juliette Kennedy in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy July 5 2011 Godel s Incompleteness Theorems entry by Panu Raatikainen in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy November 11 2013 Paraconsistent Logic Arithmetic and Godel s Theorem entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy MacTutor biographies Kurt Godel Archived 2005 10 13 at the Wayback Machine Gerhard Gentzen What is Mathematics Godel s Theorem and Around by Karlis Podnieks An online free book World s shortest explanation of Godel s theorem using a printing machine as an example October 2011 RadioLab episode about including Godel s Incompleteness theorem Godel incompleteness theorem Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 How Godel s Proof Works by Natalie Wolchover Quanta Magazine July 14 2020 1 and 2 Godel s incompleteness theorems formalised in Isabelle HOL Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Godel 27s incompleteness theorems amp oldid 1172404802, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.