fbpx
Wikipedia

T. H. Green

Thomas Hill Green (7 April 1836 – 26 March 1882), known as T. H. Green, was an English philosopher, political radical and temperance reformer, and a member of the British idealism movement. Like all the British idealists, Green was influenced by the metaphysical historicism of G. W. F. Hegel. He was one of the thinkers behind the philosophy of social liberalism.

T. H. Green
Born
Thomas Hill Green

(1836-04-07)7 April 1836
Birkin, England
Died26 March 1882(1882-03-26) (aged 45)
Oxford, England
Alma materBalliol College, Oxford
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
InstitutionsBalliol College, Oxford
Academic advisorsBenjamin Jowett[1]
Notable studentsJohn Cook Wilson[2]
Main interests
Political philosophy
Notable ideas
Social liberalism
(Classical radicalism)

Life edit

Green was born on 7 April 1836 at Birkin, in the West Riding of Yorkshire, England, where his father was rector. On his paternal side, he was descended from Oliver Cromwell.[4][5] His education was conducted entirely at home until, at the age of 14, he entered Rugby, where he remained for five years.[6]

In 1855, he became an undergraduate member of Balliol College, Oxford, and was elected fellow in 1860. He began a life of teaching (mainly philosophical) in the university—first as college tutor, afterwards, from 1878 until his death, as Whyte's Professor of Moral Philosophy.[6]

The lectures he delivered as professor form the substance of his two most important works, viz., the Prolegomena to Ethics[7] and the Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation, which contain the whole of his positive constructive teaching. These works were not published until after his death, but Green's views were previously known indirectly through the Introduction to the standard edition of David Hume's works by Green and T. H. Grose, fellow of Queen's College, in which the doctrine of the "English" or "empirical" philosophy was exhaustively examined.[6][8]

In 1871 he married Charlotte Byron Symonds who was known as a promoter of women's education.[9] In 1879, Green sat in the committee which was formed to create an Oxford women's college "in which no distinction will be made between students on the ground of their belonging to different religious denominations." Green and his wife's work resulted in the founding of Somerville Hall (later Somerville College).[9]

Green was involved in local politics for many years, through the university, temperance societies and the local Oxford Liberal association. During the passage of the Second Reform Act, he campaigned for the franchise to be extended to all men living in boroughs even if they did not own real property. In that sense, Green's position was more radical than that of most other Advanced Liberals, including William Ewart Gladstone.

It was in the context of his Liberal Party activities that in 1881, Green gave what became one of his most famous statements of his liberal political philosophy, the "Lecture on Liberal Legislation and Freedom of Contract".[10] At this time, he was also lecturing on religion, epistemology, ethics and political philosophy.

Most of his major works were published posthumously, including his lay sermons on Faith and The Witness of God, the essay "On the Different Senses of 'Freedom' as Applied to Will and the Moral Progress of Man", Prolegomena to Ethics, Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation, and the "Lecture on Liberal Legislation and Freedom of Contract".

Green died of blood poisoning at the age of 45 on 26 March 1882. In addition to friends from his academic life, approximately 2,000 local townspeople attended his funeral.

He helped to found the City of Oxford High School for Boys.

Thought edit

Hume's empiricism and biological evolution (including Herbert Spencer) were chief features in English thought during the third quarter of the 19th century. Green represents primarily the reaction against such doctrines. Green argued that when these doctrines were carried to their logical conclusion, they not only "rendered all philosophy futile", but were fatal to practical life. By reducing the human mind to a series of unrelated atomic sensations, these related teachings destroyed the possibility of knowledge, he argued.[6] These teachings were especially important for Green to refute because they had underpinned the conception of mind that was held by the nascent science of psychology. Green tried to deflate the pretensions of psychologists who had claimed that their young field would provide a scientific replacement for traditional epistemology and metaphysics.[11]

Green further objected that such empiricists represented a person as a "being who is simply the result of natural forces", and thereby made conduct, or any theory of conduct, meaningless; for life in any human, intelligible sense implies a personal self that (1) knows what to do, and (2) has power to do it. Green was thus driven, not theoretically, but as a practical necessity, to raise again the whole question of humankind in relation to nature. When (he held) we have discovered what a person in themselves are, and what their relation to their environment is, we shall then know their function—what they are fitted to do. In the light of this knowledge, we shall be able to formulate the moral code, which, in turn, will serve as a criterion of actual civic and social institutions. These form, naturally and necessarily, the objective expression of moral ideas, and it is in some civic or social whole that the moral ideal must finally take concrete shape.[6]

What is man? edit

To ask "What is man?" is to ask "What is experience?" for experience means that of which I am conscious. The facts of consciousness are the only facts that, to begin with, we are justified in asserting to exist. On the other hand, they are valid evidence for whatever is necessary to their own explanation, i.e. for whatever is logically involved in them. Now the most striking characteristic of humans, that in fact which marks them specially, as contrasted with other animals, is self-consciousness. The simplest mental act into which we can analyse the operations of the human mind—the act of sense-perception—is never merely a change, physical or psychical, but is the consciousness of a change.[6]

Human experience consists, not of processes in an animal organism, but of these processes recognised as such. That which we perceive is from the outset an apprehended fact—that is to say, it cannot be analysed into isolated elements (so-called sensations) which, as such, are not constituents of consciousness at all, but exist from the first as a synthesis of relations in a consciousness which keeps distinct the "self" and the various elements of the "object," though holding all together in the unity of the act of perception. In other words, the whole mental structure we call knowledge consists, in its simplest equally with its most complex constituents, of the "work of the mind." Locke and Hume held that the work of the mind was eo ipso [by that very act] unreal because it was "made by" humans and not "given to" humans. It thus represented a subjective creation, not an objective fact. But this consequence follows only upon the assumption that the work of the mind is arbitrary, an assumption shown to be unjustified by the results of exact science, with the distinction, universally recognised, which such science draws between truth and falsehood, between the real and "mere ideas." This (obviously valid) distinction logically involves the consequence that the object, or content, of knowledge, viz., reality, is an intelligible ideal reality, a system of thought relations, a spiritual cosmos. How is the existence of this ideal whole to be accounted for? Only by the existence of some "principle which renders all relations possible and is itself determined by none of them"; an eternal self-consciousness which knows in whole what we know in part. To God the world is, to humans the world becomes. Human experience is God gradually made manifest.[6]

Moral philosophy edit

Carrying on the same method into the area of moral philosophy, Green argued that ethics applies to the conditions of social life—that investigation into human nature which metaphysics began. The faculty employed in this further investigation is no "separate moral faculty", but that same reason which is the source of all our knowledge—ethical and other.[6]

Self-reflection gradually reveals to us human capacity, human function, with, consequently, human responsibility. It brings out into clear consciousness certain potentialities in the realisation of which human's true good must consist. As the result of this analysis, combined with an investigation into the surroundings humans live in, a "content"—a moral code—becomes gradually evolved. Personal good is perceived to be realisable only by making real and actual the conceptions thus arrived at. So long as these remain potential or ideal, they form the motive of action; motive consisting always in the idea of some "end" or "good" that humans present to themselves as an end in the attainment of which he would be satisfied; that is, in the realisation of which he would find his true self.[6]

The determination to realise the self in some definite way constitutes an "act of will", which, as thus constituted, is neither arbitrary nor externally determined. For the motive which may be said to be its cause lies in the person himself, and the identification of the self with such a motive is a self-determination, which is at once both rational and free. The "freedom of man" is constituted, not by a supposed ability to do anything he may choose, but in the power to identify himself with that true good that reason reveals to him as his true good.[6]

This good consists in the realisation of personal character; hence the final good, i.e. the moral ideal, as a whole, can be realised only in some society of persons who, while remaining ends to themselves in the sense that their individuality is not lost but rendered more perfect, find this perfection attainable only when the separate individualities are integrated as part of a social whole.[6]

Society is as necessary to form persons as persons are to constitute society. Social union is the indispensable condition of the development of the special capacities of its individual members. Human self-perfection cannot be gained in isolation; it is attainable only in inter-relation with fellow-citizens in the social community.[6]

The law of our being, so revealed, involves in its turn civic or political duties. Moral goodness cannot be limited to, still less constituted by, the cultivation of self-regarding virtues, but consists in the attempt to realise in practice that moral ideal that self-analysis has revealed to us as our ideal. From this fact arises the ground of political obligation, because the institutions of political or civic life are the concrete embodiment of moral ideas in terms of our day and generation. But, since society exists only for the proper development of Persons, we have a criterion by which to test these institutions—namely, do they, or do they not, contribute to the development of moral character in the individual citizens?[6]

It is obvious that the final moral ideal is not realised in any body of civic institutions actually existing, but the same analysis that demonstrates this deficiency points out the direction that a true development will take.[6]

Hence arises the conception of rights and duties that should be maintained by law, as opposed to those actually maintained; with the further consequence that it may become occasionally a moral duty to rebel against the state in the interest of the state itself—that is, in order better to subserve that end or function that constitutes the raison d'être of the state.[6] There exists a "general will" that is a desire for a common good that cannot be easily reconciled as there is an antagonism between the "common good" and the "private good": such as: "... interest in the common good, in some of its various forms, is necessary to produce that good, and to neutralise or render useful other desires and interests". Its basis is can be conceived as coercive authority imposed upon the citizens from without or it can be seen as a necessary restriction of individual liberty in light of a social contract, but this consists in the spiritual recognition or metaphysics, on the part of the citizens, of what constitutes their true nature, some conceptions and complicating factors are elaborating questions concerning: "Will, not force, is the basis of the state.",[6] "Citizen Rights Against the State", "Private Rights. The Right to Life and Liberty", "The Right of the State Over the Individual in War", "The Right of the State to Punish", "The Right of the State to Promote Morality ", "The Right of the State in Regard to Property", and "The Right of the State in Regard to the Family".

Philosophy of state action edit

Green believed that the state should foster and protect the social, political and economic environments in which individuals will have the best chance of acting according to their consciences. But the state must be careful when deciding which liberties to curtail and in which ways to curtail them. Over-enthusiastic or clumsy state intervention could easily close down opportunities for conscientious action thereby stifling the moral development of the individual. The state should intervene only where there is a clear, proven and strong tendency of a liberty to enslave the individual. Even when such a hazard had been identified, Green tended to favour action by the affected community itself rather than national state action itself—local councils and municipal authorities tended to produce measures that were more imaginative and better suited to the daily reality of a social problem. Hence he favoured the "local option" where local people decided on the issuing of liquor licences in their area, through their town councils.[12]

Green stressed the need for specific solutions to be tailored to fit specific problems. He stressed that there are no eternal solutions, no timeless division of responsibilities between national and local governmental units. The distribution of responsibilities should be guided by the imperative to enable as many individuals as possible to exercise their conscientious wills in particular contingent circumstances, as only in this way was it possible to foster individual self-realisation in the long-run. Deciding on the distribution of responsibilities was more a matter for practical politics than for ethical or political philosophy. Experience may show that the local and municipal levels are unable to control the harmful influences of, say, the brewery industry. When it did show this, the national state should take responsibility for this area of public policy.

Green argued that the ultimate power to decide on the allocation of such tasks should rest with the national state (in Britain, for instance, embodied in Parliament). The national state itself is legitimate for Green to the extent that it upholds a system of rights and obligations that is most likely to foster individual self-realisation. Yet, the most appropriate structure of this system is determined neither by purely political calculation nor by philosophical speculation. It is more accurate to say that it arose from the underlying conceptual and normative structure of one's particular society.

Influence of Green's thought edit

Green's teaching was, directly and indirectly, the most potent philosophical influence in England during the last quarter of the 19th century, while his enthusiasm for a common citizenship, and his personal example in practical municipal life, inspired much of the effort made in the years succeeding his death to bring the universities more into touch with the people, and to break down the rigour of class distinctions.[6] His ideas spread to the University of St Andrews through the influence of David George Ritchie, a former student of his, who eventually helped found the Aristotelian Society. John Dewey wrote a number of early essays on Green's thought, including Self-Realization as the Moral Ideal.

Green was directly cited by many social liberal politicians, such as Herbert Samuel and H. H. Asquith, as an influence on their thought. It is no coincidence that these politicians were educated at Balliol College, Oxford. Roy Hattersley called for Green's work to be applied to the problems of 21st century Britain.[13]

Works and commentary edit

An extensive bibliography of works by and about T.H. Green has been produced by Colin Tyler (Centre for Idealism and the New Liberalism at the University of Hull, UK). It can be downloaded at: https://idealismandnewliberalism.org/bibliographies/

Green's most important treatise—the Prolegomena to Ethics 9 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine, practically complete in manuscript at his death—was published in the year following, under the editorship of A. C. Bradley (4th ed., 1899). Shortly afterwards, R. L. Nettleship's standard edition of his Works (exclusive of the Prolegomena) appeared in three volumes:[6]

  1. Reprints of Green's criticism of Hume, Spencer, G. H. Lewes
  2. Lectures on Kant, on Logic, on the
  3. Miscellanies, preceded by a full Memoir by the Editor.[6]

All three volumes are available for download at Internet Archive

The Principles of Political Obligation was afterwards published in separate form. A criticism of Neo-Hegelianism will be found in Andrew Seth (Pringle Pattison), Hegelianism and Personality (1887).[6]

  • Hume and Locke, Apollo Editions, 425 Park Avenue South, New York, NY 10016, 1968 (Reprint of Thomas Y. Crowell Company edition). Contains Green's "Introductions to Hume's Treatise of Human Nature" and also Green's "Introduction to the Moral Part of Hume's Treatise"

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Brink, David (29 December 2021). "Thomas Hill Green". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  2. ^ a b Robin George Collingwood, R. G. Collingwood: An Autobiography and Other Writings, Oxford UP, 2013, p. 220.
  3. ^ Goldman, Lawrence, ed. (2019). "Welfare and Social Policy in Britain Since 1870". Welfare and Social Policy in Britain Since 1870: Essays in Honour of Jose Harris. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198833048.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-883304-8.
  4. ^ Thomas, Geoffrey, "Thomas Hill Green", 1836-1882
  5. ^ Ian Adams and R. W. Dyson, Fifty Major Political Thinkers (2007). p. 143.
  6. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainFlower, William Henry (1911). "Green, Thomas Hill". In Chisholm, Hugh (ed.). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 12 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 535–536.
  7. ^ . Fair Use Repository. Archived from the original on 9 August 2020. Retrieved 11 August 2020.
  8. ^ The Philosophical Works of David Hume, ed. by T. H. Green and T. H. Grose, 4 vols. (1882–1886)
  9. ^ a b "Green [née Symonds], Charlotte Byron (1842–1929), promoter of women's education". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. 2004. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/48416. Retrieved 11 August 2020. (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
  10. ^ Hanover Historical Texts Project
  11. ^ Alexander Klein, The Rise of Empiricism: William James, Thomas Hill Green, and the Struggle over Psychology 4 November 2007 at the Wayback Machine
  12. ^ Nicholson, P. P., "T. H. Green and State Action: Liquor Legislation", History of Political Thought, 6 (1985), 517–50. Reprinted in A. Vincent, ed., The Philosophy of T. H. Green (Aldershot: Gower, 1986), pp. 76–103
  13. ^ Forgotten favourites - Politics of aspiration. T H Green was the first philosopher of social justice. Today’s cabinet ministers would do well to read him, writes Roy Hattersley

Further reading edit

  • Articles in Mind (January and April 1884) by A. J. Balfour and Henry Sidgwick
  • In the Academy (xxviii. 242 and xxv. 297) by S. Alexander
  • David George Ritchie, The Principles of State Interference (London, 1891)
  • W. H. Fairbrother, Philosophy of T.H. Green (London and New York, 1896)
  • S. S. Laurie The Metaphysics of T H Green an article in the Philosophical Review (Volume vi, March 1897) pages 113 to 131
  • Henry Sidgwick, Lectures on the ethics of T.H. Green, Mr. Herbert Spencer, and J. Martineau (London, 1902)
  • Henry Sidgwick, Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant (London, 1905)
  • A. W. Benn, The History of English Rationalism in the Nineteenth Century (1906), volume ii, pp. 401 foll.
  • H. Sturt, Idola theatri, a criticism of Oxford thought and thinkers from the standpoint of personal idealism, 1906.
  • J. H. Muirhead, The Service of the State: Four Lectures on the Political Teaching of T. H. Green (1908)
  • W. D. Lamont, Introduction to Green's moral philosophy, 1934.
  • J. Pucelle, La nature et l'esprit dans la philosophie de T.H. Green; la renaissance de l'idéalisme en Angleterre au 19e siècle, 1960.
  • M. Freeden (1978) The New Liberalism: An ideology of Social Reform, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
  • I.M. Greengarten (1981) Thomas Hill-Green and the Development of Liberal-Democratic Thought, University of Toronto Press.
  • Geoffrey Thomas (1988) The Moral Philosophy of T. H. Green (Oxford and New York).
  • Avital Simhony (1993) "T.H. Green: the common good society", History of Political Thought 14(2):225–247.
  • Dimova-Cookson, Maria (2001). T.H. Green's Moral and Political Philosophy: A Phenomenological Perspective. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-333-91445-8.
  • Bauman, Richard (2002). Human Rights in Ancient Rome. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-17320-9.
  • David O. Brink (2003) Perfectionism and the Common Good: Themes in the Philosophy of T. H. Green, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Carter, Matt (2003). T.H.Green and the Development of Ethical Socialism. ISBN 978-0-907845-32-4.
  • Dimova-Cookson, Maria; Mander, William J. (2006). T. H. Green: Ethics, Metaphysics, and Political Philosophy. Oxford University Press on Demand. ISBN 978-0-19-927166-5.
  • Morrow, John (2007). T.H. Green. Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-2554-4.

External links edit

  • Grave of Thomas Hill Green and Charlotte Byron Green in St Sepulchre's Cemetery, Oxford, with biography
Works online
  • Works by Thomas Hill Green at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by or about T. H. Green at Internet Archive
  • Prolegomena to Ethics 9 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine (1883)
  • (1883)
  • Works (excluding Prolegomena to Ethics) edited by R L Nettleship in three volumes (first published 1885): Volume 1: Introductions to Hume's Treatise; and Mr Herbert Spencer and Mr G H Lewes: their application of the doctrine of Evolution to Thought; Volume 2: Lectures: on (a) the Philosophy of Kant; (b) Logic, including J S Mill's System of Logic; (c) the different senses of freedom as applied to will and to moral progress; and (d) the Principles of Political Obligation; and Volume 3: Miscellanies and Memoir

green, american, military, officer, thomas, green, this, article, technical, most, readers, understand, please, help, improve, make, understandable, experts, without, removing, technical, details, september, 2010, learn, when, remove, this, template, message, . For the American military officer see Thomas H Green This article may be too technical for most readers to understand Please help improve it to make it understandable to non experts without removing the technical details September 2010 Learn how and when to remove this template message Thomas Hill Green 7 April 1836 26 March 1882 known as T H Green was an English philosopher political radical and temperance reformer and a member of the British idealism movement Like all the British idealists Green was influenced by the metaphysical historicism of G W F Hegel He was one of the thinkers behind the philosophy of social liberalism T H GreenBornThomas Hill Green 1836 04 07 7 April 1836Birkin EnglandDied26 March 1882 1882 03 26 aged 45 Oxford EnglandAlma materBalliol College OxfordEra19th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolBritish idealismsocial liberalismInstitutionsBalliol College OxfordAcademic advisorsBenjamin Jowett 1 Notable studentsJohn Cook Wilson 2 Main interestsPolitical philosophyNotable ideasSocial liberalism Classical radicalism Contents 1 Life 2 Thought 2 1 What is man 2 2 Moral philosophy 2 3 Philosophy of state action 2 4 Influence of Green s thought 3 Works and commentary 4 See also 5 References 6 Further reading 7 External linksLife editGreen was born on 7 April 1836 at Birkin in the West Riding of Yorkshire England where his father was rector On his paternal side he was descended from Oliver Cromwell 4 5 His education was conducted entirely at home until at the age of 14 he entered Rugby where he remained for five years 6 In 1855 he became an undergraduate member of Balliol College Oxford and was elected fellow in 1860 He began a life of teaching mainly philosophical in the university first as college tutor afterwards from 1878 until his death as Whyte s Professor of Moral Philosophy 6 The lectures he delivered as professor form the substance of his two most important works viz the Prolegomena to Ethics 7 and the Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation which contain the whole of his positive constructive teaching These works were not published until after his death but Green s views were previously known indirectly through the Introduction to the standard edition of David Hume s works by Green and T H Grose fellow of Queen s College in which the doctrine of the English or empirical philosophy was exhaustively examined 6 8 In 1871 he married Charlotte Byron Symonds who was known as a promoter of women s education 9 In 1879 Green sat in the committee which was formed to create an Oxford women s college in which no distinction will be made between students on the ground of their belonging to different religious denominations Green and his wife s work resulted in the founding of Somerville Hall later Somerville College 9 Green was involved in local politics for many years through the university temperance societies and the local Oxford Liberal association During the passage of the Second Reform Act he campaigned for the franchise to be extended to all men living in boroughs even if they did not own real property In that sense Green s position was more radical than that of most other Advanced Liberals including William Ewart Gladstone It was in the context of his Liberal Party activities that in 1881 Green gave what became one of his most famous statements of his liberal political philosophy the Lecture on Liberal Legislation and Freedom of Contract 10 At this time he was also lecturing on religion epistemology ethics and political philosophy Most of his major works were published posthumously including his lay sermons on Faith and The Witness of God the essay On the Different Senses of Freedom as Applied to Will and the Moral Progress of Man Prolegomena to Ethics Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation and the Lecture on Liberal Legislation and Freedom of Contract Green died of blood poisoning at the age of 45 on 26 March 1882 In addition to friends from his academic life approximately 2 000 local townspeople attended his funeral He helped to found the City of Oxford High School for Boys Thought editHume s empiricism and biological evolution including Herbert Spencer were chief features in English thought during the third quarter of the 19th century Green represents primarily the reaction against such doctrines Green argued that when these doctrines were carried to their logical conclusion they not only rendered all philosophy futile but were fatal to practical life By reducing the human mind to a series of unrelated atomic sensations these related teachings destroyed the possibility of knowledge he argued 6 These teachings were especially important for Green to refute because they had underpinned the conception of mind that was held by the nascent science of psychology Green tried to deflate the pretensions of psychologists who had claimed that their young field would provide a scientific replacement for traditional epistemology and metaphysics 11 Green further objected that such empiricists represented a person as a being who is simply the result of natural forces and thereby made conduct or any theory of conduct meaningless for life in any human intelligible sense implies a personal self that 1 knows what to do and 2 has power to do it Green was thus driven not theoretically but as a practical necessity to raise again the whole question of humankind in relation to nature When he held we have discovered what a person in themselves are and what their relation to their environment is we shall then know their function what they are fitted to do In the light of this knowledge we shall be able to formulate the moral code which in turn will serve as a criterion of actual civic and social institutions These form naturally and necessarily the objective expression of moral ideas and it is in some civic or social whole that the moral ideal must finally take concrete shape 6 What is man edit To ask What is man is to ask What is experience for experience means that of which I am conscious The facts of consciousness are the only facts that to begin with we are justified in asserting to exist On the other hand they are valid evidence for whatever is necessary to their own explanation i e for whatever is logically involved in them Now the most striking characteristic of humans that in fact which marks them specially as contrasted with other animals is self consciousness The simplest mental act into which we can analyse the operations of the human mind the act of sense perception is never merely a change physical or psychical but is the consciousness of a change 6 Human experience consists not of processes in an animal organism but of these processes recognised as such That which we perceive is from the outset an apprehended fact that is to say it cannot be analysed into isolated elements so called sensations which as such are not constituents of consciousness at all but exist from the first as a synthesis of relations in a consciousness which keeps distinct the self and the various elements of the object though holding all together in the unity of the act of perception In other words the whole mental structure we call knowledge consists in its simplest equally with its most complex constituents of the work of the mind Locke and Hume held that the work of the mind was eo ipso by that very act unreal because it was made by humans and not given to humans It thus represented a subjective creation not an objective fact But this consequence follows only upon the assumption that the work of the mind is arbitrary an assumption shown to be unjustified by the results of exact science with the distinction universally recognised which such science draws between truth and falsehood between the real and mere ideas This obviously valid distinction logically involves the consequence that the object or content of knowledge viz reality is an intelligible ideal reality a system of thought relations a spiritual cosmos How is the existence of this ideal whole to be accounted for Only by the existence of some principle which renders all relations possible and is itself determined by none of them an eternal self consciousness which knows in whole what we know in part To God the world is to humans the world becomes Human experience is God gradually made manifest 6 Moral philosophy edit Carrying on the same method into the area of moral philosophy Green argued that ethics applies to the conditions of social life that investigation into human nature which metaphysics began The faculty employed in this further investigation is no separate moral faculty but that same reason which is the source of all our knowledge ethical and other 6 Self reflection gradually reveals to us human capacity human function with consequently human responsibility It brings out into clear consciousness certain potentialities in the realisation of which human s true good must consist As the result of this analysis combined with an investigation into the surroundings humans live in a content a moral code becomes gradually evolved Personal good is perceived to be realisable only by making real and actual the conceptions thus arrived at So long as these remain potential or ideal they form the motive of action motive consisting always in the idea of some end or good that humans present to themselves as an end in the attainment of which he would be satisfied that is in the realisation of which he would find his true self 6 The determination to realise the self in some definite way constitutes an act of will which as thus constituted is neither arbitrary nor externally determined For the motive which may be said to be its cause lies in the person himself and the identification of the self with such a motive is a self determination which is at once both rational and free The freedom of man is constituted not by a supposed ability to do anything he may choose but in the power to identify himself with that true good that reason reveals to him as his true good 6 This good consists in the realisation of personal character hence the final good i e the moral ideal as a whole can be realised only in some society of persons who while remaining ends to themselves in the sense that their individuality is not lost but rendered more perfect find this perfection attainable only when the separate individualities are integrated as part of a social whole 6 Society is as necessary to form persons as persons are to constitute society Social union is the indispensable condition of the development of the special capacities of its individual members Human self perfection cannot be gained in isolation it is attainable only in inter relation with fellow citizens in the social community 6 The law of our being so revealed involves in its turn civic or political duties Moral goodness cannot be limited to still less constituted by the cultivation of self regarding virtues but consists in the attempt to realise in practice that moral ideal that self analysis has revealed to us as our ideal From this fact arises the ground of political obligation because the institutions of political or civic life are the concrete embodiment of moral ideas in terms of our day and generation But since society exists only for the proper development of Persons we have a criterion by which to test these institutions namely do they or do they not contribute to the development of moral character in the individual citizens 6 It is obvious that the final moral ideal is not realised in any body of civic institutions actually existing but the same analysis that demonstrates this deficiency points out the direction that a true development will take 6 Hence arises the conception of rights and duties that should be maintained by law as opposed to those actually maintained with the further consequence that it may become occasionally a moral duty to rebel against the state in the interest of the state itself that is in order better to subserve that end or function that constitutes the raison d etre of the state 6 There exists a general will that is a desire for a common good that cannot be easily reconciled as there is an antagonism between the common good and the private good such as interest in the common good in some of its various forms is necessary to produce that good and to neutralise or render useful other desires and interests Its basis is can be conceived as coercive authority imposed upon the citizens from without or it can be seen as a necessary restriction of individual liberty in light of a social contract but this consists in the spiritual recognition or metaphysics on the part of the citizens of what constitutes their true nature some conceptions and complicating factors are elaborating questions concerning Will not force is the basis of the state 6 Citizen Rights Against the State Private Rights The Right to Life and Liberty The Right of the State Over the Individual in War The Right of the State to Punish The Right of the State to Promote Morality The Right of the State in Regard to Property and The Right of the State in Regard to the Family Philosophy of state action edit Green believed that the state should foster and protect the social political and economic environments in which individuals will have the best chance of acting according to their consciences But the state must be careful when deciding which liberties to curtail and in which ways to curtail them Over enthusiastic or clumsy state intervention could easily close down opportunities for conscientious action thereby stifling the moral development of the individual The state should intervene only where there is a clear proven and strong tendency of a liberty to enslave the individual Even when such a hazard had been identified Green tended to favour action by the affected community itself rather than national state action itself local councils and municipal authorities tended to produce measures that were more imaginative and better suited to the daily reality of a social problem Hence he favoured the local option where local people decided on the issuing of liquor licences in their area through their town councils 12 Green stressed the need for specific solutions to be tailored to fit specific problems He stressed that there are no eternal solutions no timeless division of responsibilities between national and local governmental units The distribution of responsibilities should be guided by the imperative to enable as many individuals as possible to exercise their conscientious wills in particular contingent circumstances as only in this way was it possible to foster individual self realisation in the long run Deciding on the distribution of responsibilities was more a matter for practical politics than for ethical or political philosophy Experience may show that the local and municipal levels are unable to control the harmful influences of say the brewery industry When it did show this the national state should take responsibility for this area of public policy Green argued that the ultimate power to decide on the allocation of such tasks should rest with the national state in Britain for instance embodied in Parliament The national state itself is legitimate for Green to the extent that it upholds a system of rights and obligations that is most likely to foster individual self realisation Yet the most appropriate structure of this system is determined neither by purely political calculation nor by philosophical speculation It is more accurate to say that it arose from the underlying conceptual and normative structure of one s particular society Influence of Green s thought edit Green s teaching was directly and indirectly the most potent philosophical influence in England during the last quarter of the 19th century while his enthusiasm for a common citizenship and his personal example in practical municipal life inspired much of the effort made in the years succeeding his death to bring the universities more into touch with the people and to break down the rigour of class distinctions 6 His ideas spread to the University of St Andrews through the influence of David George Ritchie a former student of his who eventually helped found the Aristotelian Society John Dewey wrote a number of early essays on Green s thought including Self Realization as the Moral Ideal Green was directly cited by many social liberal politicians such as Herbert Samuel and H H Asquith as an influence on their thought It is no coincidence that these politicians were educated at Balliol College Oxford Roy Hattersley called for Green s work to be applied to the problems of 21st century Britain 13 Works and commentary editAn extensive bibliography of works by and about T H Green has been produced by Colin Tyler Centre for Idealism and the New Liberalism at the University of Hull UK It can be downloaded at https idealismandnewliberalism org bibliographies Green s most important treatise the Prolegomena to Ethics Archived 9 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine practically complete in manuscript at his death was published in the year following under the editorship of A C Bradley 4th ed 1899 Shortly afterwards R L Nettleship s standard edition of his Works exclusive of the Prolegomena appeared in three volumes 6 Reprints of Green s criticism of Hume Spencer G H Lewes Lectures on Kant on Logic on the Principles of Political Obligation Miscellanies preceded by a full Memoir by the Editor 6 All three volumes are available for download at Internet ArchiveThe Principles of Political Obligation was afterwards published in separate form A criticism of Neo Hegelianism will be found in Andrew Seth Pringle Pattison Hegelianism and Personality 1887 6 Hume and Locke Apollo Editions 425 Park Avenue South New York NY 10016 1968 Reprint of Thomas Y Crowell Company edition Contains Green s Introductions to Hume s Treatise of Human Nature and also Green s Introduction to the Moral Part of Hume s Treatise See also editConsent of the governed Liberalism in the United KingdomReferences edit a b Brink David 29 December 2021 Thomas Hill Green In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Robin George Collingwood R G Collingwood An Autobiography and Other Writings Oxford UP 2013 p 220 Goldman Lawrence ed 2019 Welfare and Social Policy in Britain Since 1870 Welfare and Social Policy in Britain Since 1870 Essays in Honour of Jose Harris Oxford Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oso 9780198833048 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 883304 8 Thomas Geoffrey Thomas Hill Green 1836 1882 Ian Adams and R W Dyson Fifty Major Political Thinkers 2007 p 143 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Flower William Henry 1911 Green Thomas Hill In Chisholm Hugh ed Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 12 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 535 536 PROLEGOMENA TO ETHICS 1883 by T H Green Fair Use Repository Archived from the original on 9 August 2020 Retrieved 11 August 2020 The Philosophical Works of David Hume ed by T H Green and T H Grose 4 vols 1882 1886 a b Green nee Symonds Charlotte Byron 1842 1929 promoter of women s education Oxford Dictionary of National Biography online ed Oxford University Press 2004 doi 10 1093 ref odnb 48416 Retrieved 11 August 2020 Subscription or UK public library membership required Hanover Historical Texts Project Alexander Klein The Rise of Empiricism William James Thomas Hill Green and the Struggle over Psychology Archived 4 November 2007 at the Wayback Machine Nicholson P P T H Green and State Action Liquor Legislation History of Political Thought 6 1985 517 50 Reprinted in A Vincent ed The Philosophy of T H Green Aldershot Gower 1986 pp 76 103 Forgotten favourites Politics of aspiration T H Green was the first philosopher of social justice Today s cabinet ministers would do well to read him writes Roy HattersleyFurther reading editArticles in Mind January and April 1884 by A J Balfour and Henry Sidgwick In the Academy xxviii 242 and xxv 297 by S Alexander David George Ritchie The Principles of State Interference London 1891 W H Fairbrother Philosophy of T H Green London and New York 1896 S S Laurie The Metaphysics of T H Green an article in the Philosophical Review Volume vi March 1897 pages 113 to 131 Henry Sidgwick Lectures on the ethics of T H Green Mr Herbert Spencer and J Martineau London 1902 Henry Sidgwick Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant London 1905 A W Benn The History of English Rationalism in the Nineteenth Century 1906 volume ii pp 401 foll H Sturt Idola theatri a criticism of Oxford thought and thinkers from the standpoint of personal idealism 1906 J H Muirhead The Service of the State Four Lectures on the Political Teaching of T H Green 1908 W D Lamont Introduction to Green s moral philosophy 1934 J Pucelle La nature et l esprit dans la philosophie de T H Green la renaissance de l idealisme en Angleterre au 19e siecle 1960 M Freeden 1978 The New Liberalism An ideology of Social Reform Oxford Clarendon Press I M Greengarten 1981 Thomas Hill Green and the Development of Liberal Democratic Thought University of Toronto Press Geoffrey Thomas 1988 The Moral Philosophy of T H Green Oxford and New York Avital Simhony 1993 T H Green the common good society History of Political Thought 14 2 225 247 Dimova Cookson Maria 2001 T H Green s Moral and Political Philosophy A Phenomenological Perspective Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 0 333 91445 8 Bauman Richard 2002 Human Rights in Ancient Rome Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 17320 9 David O Brink 2003 Perfectionism and the Common Good Themes in the Philosophy of T H Green Oxford Clarendon Press Carter Matt 2003 T H Green and the Development of Ethical Socialism ISBN 978 0 907845 32 4 Dimova Cookson Maria Mander William J 2006 T H Green Ethics Metaphysics and Political Philosophy Oxford University Press on Demand ISBN 978 0 19 927166 5 Morrow John 2007 T H Green Ashgate Publishing ISBN 978 0 7546 2554 4 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to T H Green Grave of Thomas Hill Green and Charlotte Byron Green in St Sepulchre s Cemetery Oxford with biographyWorks onlineWorks by Thomas Hill Green at Project Gutenberg Works by or about T H Green at Internet Archive Prolegomena to Ethics Archived 9 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine 1883 Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation 1883 Works excluding Prolegomena to Ethics edited by R L Nettleship in three volumes first published 1885 Volume 1 Introductions to Hume s Treatise and Mr Herbert Spencer and Mr G H Lewes their application of the doctrine of Evolution to Thought Volume 2 Lectures on a the Philosophy of Kant b Logic including J S Mill s System of Logic c the different senses of freedom as applied to will and to moral progress and d the Principles of Political Obligation and Volume 3 Miscellanies and Memoir Portals nbsp Biography nbsp Liberalism nbsp Philosophy nbsp University of Oxford Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title T H Green amp oldid 1176457930, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.