fbpx
Wikipedia

John Roemer

John E. Roemer (/ˈrmər/; born February 1, 1945 in Washington, D.C., to Ruth Roemer and Milton Roemer, namesake of Roemer's law) is an American economist and political scientist. He is the Elizabeth S. and A. Varick Stout Professor of Political Science and Economics at Yale University. Before Yale, he was on the economics faculty at the University of California, Davis, and before entering academia Roemer worked for several years as a labor organizer. He is married to Natasha Roemer, with whom he has two daughters.

Roemer received his A.B. in mathematics summa cum laude from Harvard in 1966. He then enrolled as a graduate student in mathematics at the University of California, Berkeley. He became intensely involved in the anti-Vietnam-War movement, transferred to the doctoral program in economics, and was suspended by the university for his political activities. He taught mathematics in San Francisco secondary schools for five years. Eventually he returned to Berkeley and received his Ph.D. in economics in 1974.

Roemer is fellow of the Econometric Society, a past Guggenheim fellow and Russell Sage fellow, a member of American Academy of Arts and Sciences, and a corresponding fellow of the British Academy. He was past president of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare, and served on the editorial boards of many journals in economics, political science, and philosophy. Roemer served on the advisory board of Academics Stand Against Poverty (ASAP).

Academic contributions

Roemer has contributed mainly to five areas: Marxian economics, distributive justice, political competition, equity and climate change, and the theory of cooperation.

Marxian economics

Roemer's early work was an attempt to state the main themes of Marxian economics using the tools of general equilibrium and game theory. In Roemer (1982), he proposed a model of agents who were differentiated by their endowments, and had to choose occupations—involving either selling labor, hiring labor, or working on one's own capital stock. In optimizing with respect to market prices, agents choose one of five class positions, each consisting of various combinations of these three activities. This gives rise to a class structure, whose agricultural nomenclature would be landlords (who only hire labor), rich peasants (who hire labor and work themselves on their fields), middle peasants (who only work for themselves and do not participate in the labor market), poor peasants (who work on their own plot and sell labor), and landless laborers (who only sell labor). Independently of this taxonomy, individuals are either exploiters or exploited, depending upon whether they consume goods embodying more or less labor than they expend. The central result, the Class Exploitation Correspondence Principle (CECP), states that individuals who optimize by hiring labor are necessarily exploiters, and those who optimize by selling labor are exploited. Thus, a classical Marxian principle, taken as an observed fact in Marx's writings, emerges here as a theorem. Microfoundations are provided for the relationship between exploitation and class.

In simple models (e.g., that of Leontief), the definition of 'labor embodied in goods' is straightforward. With more complicated production sets, it is not, and hence the definition of exploition is not obvious. Roemer's program was then to propose definitions of embodied labor time, for economies with more general production sets, which would preserve the CECP. This led to the observation that, for general production sets, embodied labor time cannot be defined before one knows equilibrium prices. Thus, contrary to Marx, labor value is not a concept which is more fundamental than prices.

Distributive justice

Roemer's work on exploitation led him to believe that the fundamental cause of exploitation was inequality of ownership of productive assets, rather than the kind of oppression that occurs in the labor process at the point of production—the latter view was held by many in the 'New Left' (see, e.g., Braverman 1974). While writing A General Theory of Exploitation and Class (1982), Roemer met the philosopher G. A. Cohen and the political theorist Jon Elster: they and others had formed a group of like-minded Marxists, young social scientists and philosophers who saw their task as reconstructing Marxism on solid analytical foundations, using modern techniques. Roemer joined this group in 1981. He was strongly influenced by Cohen, whose work Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defence (1978) was to become the gold standard of analytical Marxism. Having decided that inequality of asset ownership was the key culprit in capitalist inequality, Roemer, under Cohen's influence, began reading philosophical work on equality. He was impressed with Ronald Dworkin's (1981a, 1981b) writings, advocating a kind of resource egalitarianism. But in Roemer (1985), he showed that the hypothetical insurance market which Dworkin postulated to take place behind a veil of ignorance did not suffice to compensate those with a poor endowment of natural talents or bad luck in the birth lottery, as Dworkin had intended. In fact, pathologically, Dworkin's insurance market could transfer wealth from disabled to able persons. Influenced as well by Richard Arneson's (1989) proposal, Roemer (1993) proposed a conception of equality of opportunity, which attempted to carry out Dworkin's and Arneson's program—that is, to compensate persons for bad luck in the birth lottery, but to hold them responsible for their choices, or effort. He expanded this theory in Roemer (1996, 1998, 2012), where he proposed an algorithm whereby a society could equalize opportunities for a given objective (wage earning capacity, income, health), consonant with its own view of what factors individuals should be held responsible for, and what factors demanded compensation. Roemer and collaborators have produced a number of applications of this approach (Roemer et al. 2001; Llavador and Roemer 2001; Betts and Roemer 2007; Keane and Roemer 2009; Bjorkund, Jantti, and Roemer 2012). The World Bank (2006, 2009) has employed this approach to evaluate inequality of opportunity in developing countries.

Political competition

Roemer was naturally interested in the 'democratic class struggle,' that is, the manner in which classes in democracies contest their opposing interests. He was dissatisfied with the reigning concept of political equilibrium, Hotelling-Downs equilibrium, for several reasons: first, it conceptualizes political actors as caring only about winning elections, rather than representing constituents, and second, the concept is extremely fragile, as equilibrium exists, generically, only if the policy space is uni-dimensional. In Roemer (1999), he proposed a concept of political equilibrium in party competition, which exploited the idea that party organizations consist of factions. In one variant of the proposal, each party organization comprises three factions—the Militants, who wish to propose a policy which maximizes the average utility of the party's constituents, the Opportunists, who wish only to maximize the probability of victory, and the Reformists, who wish the maximize the expected utility of their constituents. An equilibrium consists of a policy proposal by each party, such that no party can deviate to another policy that would increase the payoffs of all three of its factions. This concept, called Party Unanimity Nash Equilibrium (PUNE), can be viewed as involving Nash bargaining among factions within each party, and Nash equilibrium between parties. As well as capturing what appears to happen in party competition, PUNE has the virtue that it exists regardless of the dimension of the policy space. (In fact, with two parties, a two-dimensional set or manifold of equilibria generically exist, under reasonable conditions.) This theory was extended, and applied to a number of examples in Roemer (2001). In Roemer, Lee and Van der Straeten (2006), it was applied to analyze elections in four countries, where the two dimensions of policy were postulated to be taxes and immigration (or the race question). In Roemer (2006), a dynamic model was studied, where the question posed is whether political competition over the long period would tend to produce more economic equality, through democratically chosen policies of educational finance.

Equity and climate change

With collaborators Humberto Llavador and Joaquim Silvestre, Roemer has elaborated a formal theory of sustainability, which the authors apply to the problem of climate change (Llavador, Roemer, and Silvestre 2010 and 2011).[1] Rather than maximizing a sum of discounted generational utilities into the future, which is the virtually ubiquitous practice of economists working on climate change, the authors maximize an objective which sustains welfare at the highest feasible level, or sustains growth in welfare at a chosen growth rate. Roemer (2011) critiques the discounted utilitarian approach. In Llavador, Roemer, and Silvestre (2012) the authors propose how the bargaining problem between the global North and South can be resolved, over the allocation of rights to emit greenhouse gases. The proposal does not begin from an ethical position which postulates an a priori distribution of pollution rights to nations, but rather with a politically motivated postulate that the authors argue is necessary and sufficient for an agreement to be reached.

Cooperation

Although evolutionary biologists, anthropologists, and behavioral economists increasingly view Homo sapiens as a cooperative species, almost all of economic theory assumes non-cooperative behavior: general equilibrium theory and non-cooperative game theory are the main tools. Even 'cooperative' game theory does not model cooperation, but treats it as a black box: the values of coalitions in a cooperative game are taken as given, and it is not explained how coalitions produce these values. In Roemer and Silvestre (1993), the authors proved the existence, for quite general economic environments, of an allocation they called the proportional solution (PS): an allocation of goods and labor which is Pareto efficient, and in which each receives goods whose value (at supporting efficiency prices) is proportional to the value of their expended labor. In particular, if such an allocation could be realized, it would rectify the inefficiencies exhibited in the Nash equilibrium known as the tragedy of the commons. But how could it be realized? Roemer (1996) showed that the proportional solution is a 'Kantian equilibrium' of a natural game. In Nash equilibrium a player asks, autarkically, whether he can improve his payoff by altering his action, assuming all others' actions remain fixed. In Kantian equilibrium, a player only alters his labor supply by a certain multiple, if he would prefer that all players alter their labor supplies by the same multiple. In other words, he takes an action only if he prefers the situation in which his action is 'universalized.' A Kantian equilibrium is a vector of labor offers such that no player would like to multiply all offers by any non-negative number. This captures a kind of cooperation—agents do not contemplate deviating independently of others, but only in concert with others. In Roemer (2011), it is shown that, in a variety of games, Kantian equilibria deliver Pareto efficient allocations—they rectify the inefficiencies associated with Nash equilibrium. In particular, if a tribe of fishers, who live on a lake, learn to optimize in the Kantian manner, they will use the lake in an efficient manner, avoiding the tragedy of the commons.

See also

References

  • Arneson, R. 1989. "Equality and equal opportunity for welfare," Phil. Stud.93, 77-112
  • Björklund, A., M. Jäntti, and J. Roemer, 2012. “Equality of opportunity and the distribution of long-run income in Sweden,” Social choice and welfare 39, 675-696
  • Braverman, H. 1974. Labor and Monopoly Capital, Monthly Review Press
  • Cohen, G. A. 1978. Karl Marx's theory of history: A defence, Oxford University Press
  • Betts, J. and J. Roemer, 2007. “Equalizing Opportunity for Racial and Socioeconomic Groups in the United States through Educational Finance Reform,” in P. Peterson (ed.), Schools and the equal opportunity problem, MIT Press
  • Dworkin, R. 1981a. "What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare," Phil.& Public Affairs 10, 185-246
  • Dworkin, R. 1981b. "What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources," Phil. & Public Affairs 10, 283-345
  • Keane, M. and J. Roemer, 2009. "Assessing policies to equalize opportunity using an equilibrium model of educational and occupational choice," J. Pub. Econ. 093, 879-898
  • Llavador, H. and J. Roemer, 2001. “An equal-opportunity approach to the allocation of international aid”, J. Development Econ. 64, 147-171
  • Llavador, H., J. Roemer, and J. Silvestre, 2010. “Intergenerational justice when future worlds are uncertain,” J. Math. Economics 46, 728-761
  • Llavador, H., J. Roemer, and J. Silvestre, 2011. “A dynamic analysis of human welfare in a warming planet,” J. Public Econ. 95, 1607-1620
  • Llavador, H., J. Roemer, and J. Silvestre, 2012. “North-South convergence and the allocation of CO2 emissions,” Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper
  • Roemer, John E. (1981). Analytical Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-23047-6.
  • Roemer, John E. 1982. A general theory of exploitation and class, Harvard Univ. Press
  • Roemer, John E. 1985. "Equality of talent," Economics & Phil. 1, 155-188
  • Roemer, John E. 1993. "A pragmatic theory of responsibility for the egalitarian planner," Phil. & Public Affairs 10, 146-166
  • Roemer, John E. 1996. Theories of distributive justice. Description and scrollable chapter-preview links. Harvard Univ. Press
  • Roemer, John E. 1998. Equality of opportunity. Description and preview. Harvard Univ. Press
  • Roemer, John E. 1999. "The democratic political economy of progressive taxation," Econometrica 67, 1-19–2001. Political Competition. Description and preview. Harvard Univ. Press
  • Roemer, John E. 2006. Democracy, education, and equality. Description and prreview. Cambridge Univ. Press
  • Roemer, John E. 2008. In The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. For the following, 1st-sentence links; TOC and Abstract links:
    "equality of opportunity"
    "Marxian value analysis." TOC
    "socialism (new perspectives)"
  • Roemer, John E. 2010. "Kantian equilibrium," Scandinavian J. Econ.112, 1-24–2011. “The ethics of intergenerational distribution in a warming planet,” Environmental and resource economics 48, 363-390–2012. "On several approaches to equality of opportunity," Econ. & Phil. 28, 165-200
  • Roemer, J. et al., 2001. " To what extent do fiscal systems equalize opportunities for income acquisition among citizens?" J. Pub. Econ. 87, 539-565
  • Roemer, J. and J. Silvestre, 1993. “The proportional solution in economies with private and public ownership,” J. Econ. Theory 59, 426-444
  • Roemer, J., W. Lee and K. Van der Staeten, 2007. Racism, xenophobia, and distribution: Multi-issue politics in advanced democracies, Harvard Univ. Press
  • World Bank, 2006. World Development Report: Equity and Development
  • Paes de Barros, R. et al. 2009. Measuring inequality of opportunities in Latin America and the Caribbean, Washington D.C.:World Bank

Notes

  1. ^ Humberto Llavador; John E. Roemer; Joaquim Silvestre (2015). Sustainability for a Warming Planet. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-74409-7.

External links

  • Official website  
  • John Roemer publications indexed by Google Scholar
  • Podcast of lecture for the Foundation for Law, Justice and Society, Oxford, 29 April 2009

john, roemer, this, article, about, american, economist, from, washington, assassinated, wisconsin, judge, john, pier, roemer, this, article, includes, list, general, references, lacks, sufficient, corresponding, inline, citations, please, help, improve, this,. This article is about the American economist from Washington D C For the assassinated Wisconsin judge see John Pier Roemer This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations June 2018 Learn how and when to remove this template message John E Roemer ˈ r oʊ m er born February 1 1945 in Washington D C to Ruth Roemer and Milton Roemer namesake of Roemer s law is an American economist and political scientist He is the Elizabeth S and A Varick Stout Professor of Political Science and Economics at Yale University Before Yale he was on the economics faculty at the University of California Davis and before entering academia Roemer worked for several years as a labor organizer He is married to Natasha Roemer with whom he has two daughters Roemer received his A B in mathematics summa cum laude from Harvard in 1966 He then enrolled as a graduate student in mathematics at the University of California Berkeley He became intensely involved in the anti Vietnam War movement transferred to the doctoral program in economics and was suspended by the university for his political activities He taught mathematics in San Francisco secondary schools for five years Eventually he returned to Berkeley and received his Ph D in economics in 1974 Roemer is fellow of the Econometric Society a past Guggenheim fellow and Russell Sage fellow a member of American Academy of Arts and Sciences and a corresponding fellow of the British Academy He was past president of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare and served on the editorial boards of many journals in economics political science and philosophy Roemer served on the advisory board of Academics Stand Against Poverty ASAP Contents 1 Academic contributions 1 1 Marxian economics 1 2 Distributive justice 1 3 Political competition 1 4 Equity and climate change 1 5 Cooperation 2 See also 3 References 4 Notes 5 External linksAcademic contributions EditRoemer has contributed mainly to five areas Marxian economics distributive justice political competition equity and climate change and the theory of cooperation Marxian economics Edit Roemer s early work was an attempt to state the main themes of Marxian economics using the tools of general equilibrium and game theory In Roemer 1982 he proposed a model of agents who were differentiated by their endowments and had to choose occupations involving either selling labor hiring labor or working on one s own capital stock In optimizing with respect to market prices agents choose one of five class positions each consisting of various combinations of these three activities This gives rise to a class structure whose agricultural nomenclature would be landlords who only hire labor rich peasants who hire labor and work themselves on their fields middle peasants who only work for themselves and do not participate in the labor market poor peasants who work on their own plot and sell labor and landless laborers who only sell labor Independently of this taxonomy individuals are either exploiters or exploited depending upon whether they consume goods embodying more or less labor than they expend The central result the Class Exploitation Correspondence Principle CECP states that individuals who optimize by hiring labor are necessarily exploiters and those who optimize by selling labor are exploited Thus a classical Marxian principle taken as an observed fact in Marx s writings emerges here as a theorem Microfoundations are provided for the relationship between exploitation and class In simple models e g that of Leontief the definition of labor embodied in goods is straightforward With more complicated production sets it is not and hence the definition of exploition is not obvious Roemer s program was then to propose definitions of embodied labor time for economies with more general production sets which would preserve the CECP This led to the observation that for general production sets embodied labor time cannot be defined before one knows equilibrium prices Thus contrary to Marx labor value is not a concept which is more fundamental than prices Distributive justice Edit Roemer s work on exploitation led him to believe that the fundamental cause of exploitation was inequality of ownership of productive assets rather than the kind of oppression that occurs in the labor process at the point of production the latter view was held by many in the New Left see e g Braverman 1974 While writing A General Theory of Exploitation and Class 1982 Roemer met the philosopher G A Cohen and the political theorist Jon Elster they and others had formed a group of like minded Marxists young social scientists and philosophers who saw their task as reconstructing Marxism on solid analytical foundations using modern techniques Roemer joined this group in 1981 He was strongly influenced by Cohen whose work Karl Marx s Theory of History A Defence 1978 was to become the gold standard of analytical Marxism Having decided that inequality of asset ownership was the key culprit in capitalist inequality Roemer under Cohen s influence began reading philosophical work on equality He was impressed with Ronald Dworkin s 1981a 1981b writings advocating a kind of resource egalitarianism But in Roemer 1985 he showed that the hypothetical insurance market which Dworkin postulated to take place behind a veil of ignorance did not suffice to compensate those with a poor endowment of natural talents or bad luck in the birth lottery as Dworkin had intended In fact pathologically Dworkin s insurance market could transfer wealth from disabled to able persons Influenced as well by Richard Arneson s 1989 proposal Roemer 1993 proposed a conception of equality of opportunity which attempted to carry out Dworkin s and Arneson s program that is to compensate persons for bad luck in the birth lottery but to hold them responsible for their choices or effort He expanded this theory in Roemer 1996 1998 2012 where he proposed an algorithm whereby a society could equalize opportunities for a given objective wage earning capacity income health consonant with its own view of what factors individuals should be held responsible for and what factors demanded compensation Roemer and collaborators have produced a number of applications of this approach Roemer et al 2001 Llavador and Roemer 2001 Betts and Roemer 2007 Keane and Roemer 2009 Bjorkund Jantti and Roemer 2012 The World Bank 2006 2009 has employed this approach to evaluate inequality of opportunity in developing countries Political competition Edit Roemer was naturally interested in the democratic class struggle that is the manner in which classes in democracies contest their opposing interests He was dissatisfied with the reigning concept of political equilibrium Hotelling Downs equilibrium for several reasons first it conceptualizes political actors as caring only about winning elections rather than representing constituents and second the concept is extremely fragile as equilibrium exists generically only if the policy space is uni dimensional In Roemer 1999 he proposed a concept of political equilibrium in party competition which exploited the idea that party organizations consist of factions In one variant of the proposal each party organization comprises three factions the Militants who wish to propose a policy which maximizes the average utility of the party s constituents the Opportunists who wish only to maximize the probability of victory and the Reformists who wish the maximize the expected utility of their constituents An equilibrium consists of a policy proposal by each party such that no party can deviate to another policy that would increase the payoffs of all three of its factions This concept called Party Unanimity Nash Equilibrium PUNE can be viewed as involving Nash bargaining among factions within each party and Nash equilibrium between parties As well as capturing what appears to happen in party competition PUNE has the virtue that it exists regardless of the dimension of the policy space In fact with two parties a two dimensional set or manifold of equilibria generically exist under reasonable conditions This theory was extended and applied to a number of examples in Roemer 2001 In Roemer Lee and Van der Straeten 2006 it was applied to analyze elections in four countries where the two dimensions of policy were postulated to be taxes and immigration or the race question In Roemer 2006 a dynamic model was studied where the question posed is whether political competition over the long period would tend to produce more economic equality through democratically chosen policies of educational finance Equity and climate change Edit With collaborators Humberto Llavador and Joaquim Silvestre Roemer has elaborated a formal theory of sustainability which the authors apply to the problem of climate change Llavador Roemer and Silvestre 2010 and 2011 1 Rather than maximizing a sum of discounted generational utilities into the future which is the virtually ubiquitous practice of economists working on climate change the authors maximize an objective which sustains welfare at the highest feasible level or sustains growth in welfare at a chosen growth rate Roemer 2011 critiques the discounted utilitarian approach In Llavador Roemer and Silvestre 2012 the authors propose how the bargaining problem between the global North and South can be resolved over the allocation of rights to emit greenhouse gases The proposal does not begin from an ethical position which postulates an a priori distribution of pollution rights to nations but rather with a politically motivated postulate that the authors argue is necessary and sufficient for an agreement to be reached Cooperation Edit Although evolutionary biologists anthropologists and behavioral economists increasingly view Homo sapiens as a cooperative species almost all of economic theory assumes non cooperative behavior general equilibrium theory and non cooperative game theory are the main tools Even cooperative game theory does not model cooperation but treats it as a black box the values of coalitions in a cooperative game are taken as given and it is not explained how coalitions produce these values In Roemer and Silvestre 1993 the authors proved the existence for quite general economic environments of an allocation they called the proportional solution PS an allocation of goods and labor which is Pareto efficient and in which each receives goods whose value at supporting efficiency prices is proportional to the value of their expended labor In particular if such an allocation could be realized it would rectify the inefficiencies exhibited in the Nash equilibrium known as the tragedy of the commons But how could it be realized Roemer 1996 showed that the proportional solution is a Kantian equilibrium of a natural game In Nash equilibrium a player asks autarkically whether he can improve his payoff by altering his action assuming all others actions remain fixed In Kantian equilibrium a player only alters his labor supply by a certain multiple if he would prefer that all players alter their labor supplies by the same multiple In other words he takes an action only if he prefers the situation in which his action is universalized A Kantian equilibrium is a vector of labor offers such that no player would like to multiply all offers by any non negative number This captures a kind of cooperation agents do not contemplate deviating independently of others but only in concert with others In Roemer 2011 it is shown that in a variety of games Kantian equilibria deliver Pareto efficient allocations they rectify the inefficiencies associated with Nash equilibrium In particular if a tribe of fishers who live on a lake learn to optimize in the Kantian manner they will use the lake in an efficient manner avoiding the tragedy of the commons See also EditRoemer model of political competition other marxian economists Marc Fleurbaey Philippe MonginReferences EditArneson R 1989 Equality and equal opportunity for welfare Phil Stud 93 77 112 Bjorklund A M Jantti and J Roemer 2012 Equality of opportunity and the distribution of long run income in Sweden Social choice and welfare 39 675 696 Braverman H 1974 Labor and Monopoly Capital Monthly Review Press Cohen G A 1978 Karl Marx s theory of history A defence Oxford University Press Betts J and J Roemer 2007 Equalizing Opportunity for Racial and Socioeconomic Groups in the United States through Educational Finance Reform in P Peterson ed Schools and the equal opportunity problem MIT Press Dworkin R 1981a What is equality Part 1 Equality of welfare Phil amp Public Affairs 10 185 246 Dworkin R 1981b What is equality Part 2 Equality of resources Phil amp Public Affairs 10 283 345 Keane M and J Roemer 2009 Assessing policies to equalize opportunity using an equilibrium model of educational and occupational choice J Pub Econ 093 879 898 Llavador H and J Roemer 2001 An equal opportunity approach to the allocation of international aid J Development Econ 64 147 171 Llavador H J Roemer and J Silvestre 2010 Intergenerational justice when future worlds are uncertain J Math Economics 46 728 761 Llavador H J Roemer and J Silvestre 2011 A dynamic analysis of human welfare in a warming planet J Public Econ 95 1607 1620 Llavador H J Roemer and J Silvestre 2012 North South convergence and the allocation of CO2 emissions Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper Roemer John E 1981 Analytical Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 23047 6 Roemer John E 1982 A general theory of exploitation and class Harvard Univ Press Roemer John E 1985 Equality of talent Economics amp Phil 1 155 188 Roemer John E 1993 A pragmatic theory of responsibility for the egalitarian planner Phil amp Public Affairs 10 146 166 Roemer John E 1996 Theories of distributive justice Description and scrollable chapter preview links Harvard Univ Press Roemer John E 1998 Equality of opportunity Description and preview Harvard Univ Press Roemer John E 1999 The democratic political economy of progressive taxation Econometrica 67 1 19 2001 Political Competition Description and preview Harvard Univ Press Roemer John E 2006 Democracy education and equality Description and prreview Cambridge Univ Press Roemer John E 2008 In The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition For the following 1st sentence links TOC and Abstract links equality of opportunity Marxian value analysis TOC socialism new perspectives Roemer John E 2010 Kantian equilibrium Scandinavian J Econ 112 1 24 2011 The ethics of intergenerational distribution in a warming planet Environmental and resource economics 48 363 390 2012 On several approaches to equality of opportunity Econ amp Phil 28 165 200 Roemer J et al 2001 To what extent do fiscal systems equalize opportunities for income acquisition among citizens J Pub Econ 87 539 565 Roemer J and J Silvestre 1993 The proportional solution in economies with private and public ownership J Econ Theory 59 426 444 Roemer J W Lee and K Van der Staeten 2007 Racism xenophobia and distribution Multi issue politics in advanced democracies Harvard Univ Press World Bank 2006 World Development Report Equity and Development Paes de Barros R et al 2009 Measuring inequality of opportunities in Latin America and the Caribbean Washington D C World BankNotes Edit Humberto Llavador John E Roemer Joaquim Silvestre 2015 Sustainability for a Warming Planet Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 74409 7 External links EditOfficial website John Roemer publications indexed by Google Scholar Professor Roemer on Equality in an Era of Responsibility Podcast of lecture for the Foundation for Law Justice and Society Oxford 29 April 2009 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title John Roemer amp oldid 1100939480, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.