fbpx
Wikipedia

Ontological commitment

In formal semantics, an ontological commitment of a language is one or more objects postulated to exist by that language. The 'existence' referred to need not be 'real', but exist only in a universe of discourse. As an example, legal systems use vocabulary referring to 'legal persons' that are collective entities that have rights. One says the legal doctrine has an ontological commitment to non-singular individuals.[1]

In information systems and artificial intelligence, where an ontology refers to a specific vocabulary and a set of explicit assumptions about the meaning and usage of these words, an ontological commitment is an agreement to use the shared vocabulary in a coherent and consistent manner within a specific context.[2]

In philosophy, a "theory is ontologically committed to an object only if that object occurs in all the ontologies of that theory."[3]

Background edit

The sentence “Napoleon is one of my ancestors” apparently commits us only to the existence of two individuals (i.e., Napoleon and the speaker) and a line of ancestry between them. The fact that no other people or objects are mentioned seems to limit the “commitment” of the sentence. However, it is well known that sentences of this kind cannot be interpreted in first-order logic, where individual variables stand for individual things. Instead, they must be represented in some second-order form. In ordinary language, such second-order forms use either grammatical plurals or terms such as “set of” or “group of”.

For example, the sentence involving Napoleon can be rewritten as “any group of people that includes me and the parents of each person in the group must also include Napoleon,” which is easily interpreted as a statement in second-order logic (one would naturally start by assigning a name, such as G, to the group of people under consideration). Formally, collective noun forms such as “a group of people” are represented by second-order variables, or by first-order variables standing for sets (which are well-defined objects in mathematics and logic). Since these variables do not stand for individual objects, it seems we are “ontologically committed” to entities other than individuals — sets, classes, and so on. As Quine puts it,

the general adoption of class variables of quantification ushers in a theory whose laws were not in general expressible in the antecedent levels of logic. The price paid for this increased power is ontological: objects of a special and abstract kind, viz. classes, are now presupposed. Formally it is precisely in allowing quantification over class variables α, β, etc., that we assume a range of values for these variables to refer to. To be assumed as an entity is to be assumed as a value of a variable. (Methods of Logic, 1950, p. 228)

Another statement about individuals that appears “ontologically innocent” is the well-known Geach–Kaplan sentence: Some critics admire only one another.

Quine's criterion edit

Willard Van Orman Quine provided an early and influential formulation of ontological commitment:[4]

If one affirms a statement using a name or other singular term, or an initial phrase of 'existential quantification', like 'There are some so-and-sos', then one must either (1) admit that one is committed to the existence of things answering to the singular term or satisfying the descriptions, or (2) provide a 'paraphrase' of the statement that eschews singular terms and quantification over so-and sos. Quine's criterion can be seen as a logical development of the methods of Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore, who assumed that one must accept the existence of entities corresponding to the singular terms used in statements one accepts, unless and until one finds systematic methods of paraphrase that eliminate these terms.[5]

— Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman, The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, 2003, p. 4

The purpose of Quine's strategy is to determine just how the ontological commitment of a theory is to be found. Quine argued that the only ontologically committing expressions are variables bound by a first-order existential quantifier, and natural language expressions which were formalized using variables bound by first-order existential quantifiers.[6][7]

Attempts have been made to argue that predicates are also ontologically committing, and thus that subject-predicate sentences bear additional ontological commitment to abstract objects such as universals, sets, or classes. It has been suggested that the use of meaningful names in nonexistence statements such as "Pegasus does not exist" brings with it an ontological commitment to empty names like Pegasus, a quandary referred to as Plato's beard and escaped by using quantifiers.[8]

This discussion has a connection to the Carnap–Quine argument over analytic and synthetic objects.[9] Although Quine refers to 'ontological commitment' in this connection,[10] in his rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction he does not rely upon the formal translation of any particular theory along the lines he has suggested.[11] Instead, Quine argues by using examples that although there are tautological statements in a formal theory, like "all squares are rectangles", a formal theory necessarily contains references to objects that are not tautological, but have external connections. That is, there is an ontological commitment to such external objects. In addition, the terms used to interpret the application of the theory are not simply descriptions of sensory input, but are statements in a context. That is, inversely, there is an ontological commitment of these observational objects to the formal theory. As Ryan puts it: "Rather than being divided between contingent synthetic claims and indubitable analytic propositions, our beliefs constitute a continuous range from a periphery of sense-reports to interior concepts that are comparatively theory-laden and general."[9] Thus we end up with Quine's 'flat' ontology that does not see a distinction between analytic and synthetic objects.[12][13]

Quine further made a distinction between the ontological commitments of a theory (what the theory says exists) and the ideological commitments of a theory (those concepts, logical or non-logical, that are expressible within the theory).[14]

Ontological parsimony edit

Whatever process one uses to determine the ontological commitments of a theory, that does not prescribe what ontological commitments one should have. Quine regarded this as a matter of epistemology, which theory one should accept. "Appeal is made to [concerns of] explanatory power, parsimony, conservatism, precision, and so on".[15]

Ontological parsimony can be defined in various ways, and often is equated to versions of Occam's razor, a "rule of thumb, which obliges us to favor theories or hypotheses that make the fewest unwarranted, or ad hoc, assumptions about the data from which they are derived."[16] Glock regards 'ontological parsimony' as one of the 'five main points' of Quine's conception of ontology.[17]

Following Quine,[18] Baker states that a theory, T, is ontologically committed to items F if and only if T entails that F′s exist. If two theories, T1 and T2, have the same ontological commitments except that T2 is ontologically committed to F′s while T1 is not, then T1 is more parsimonious than T2. More generally, a sufficient condition for T1 being more parsimonious than T2 is for the ontological commitments of T1 to be a proper subset of those of T2.[19]

These ideas lead to the following particular formulation of Occam's razor: 'Other things being equal, if T1 is more ontologically parsimonious than T2 then it is rational to prefer T1 to T2.' While a common formulation stipulates only that entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity, this version by contrast, states that entities should not be multiplied other things being equal, and this is compatible with parsimony being a comparatively weak theoretical virtue.[19]

Recent controversies edit

The standard approach to ontological commitment has been that, once a theory has been regimented and/or "paraphrased" into an agreed "canonical" version,[20] which may indeed be in formal logical notation rather than the original language of the theory, ontological commitments can be read off straightforwardly from the presence of certain ontologically committing expressions (e.g. bound variables of existential quantification). Although there is substantial debate about which expressions are ontologically committing,[21][22] parties to that debate generally agree that the expressions they prefer are reliable bearers of ontological commitment, imparting ontological commitment to all regimented sentences in which they occur. This assumption has been challenged.

Inwagen has taken issue with Quine's methodology,[23] claiming that this process did not lead to a unique set of fundamental objects, but to several possible sets, and one never could be certain that all the possible sets had been found. He also took issue with Quine's notion of a theory, which he felt was tantamount to suggesting a 'theory' was just a collection of sentences. Inwagen suggested that Quine's approach provided useful tools for discovering what entities were ontological commitments, but that he had not been successful. His attempts are comparable to an "attempt to reach the moon by climbing ever higher trees..."[24]

It has been suggested that the ontological commitments of a theory cannot be discerned by analysis of the syntax of sentences, looking for ontologically committing expressions, because the true ontological commitments of a sentence (or theory) are restricted to the entities needed to serve as truthmakers for that sentence, and the syntax of even a regimented or formalized sentence is not a reliable guide to what entities are needed to make it true.[25] However, this view has been attacked by Jonathan Schaffer, who has argued that truthmaking is not an adequate test for ontological commitment: at best, the search for the truthmakers of our theory will tell us what is "fundamental", but not what our theory is ontologically committed to, and hence will not serve as a good way of deciding what exists.[26]

It also has been argued that the syntax of sentences is not a reliable guide to their ontological commitments because English has no form of words which reliably functions to make an existence-claim in every context in which it is used. For example, Jody Azzouni suggests that "There is" does not make any kind of genuine existence-claim when it is used in a sentence such as "There are mice that talk". Since the meaning of the existential quantifier in formal notation is usually explained in terms of its equivalence to English expressions such as "there is" and "there exist", and since these English expressions are not reliably ontologically committing, it comes to seem that we cannot be sure of our theory's ontological commitments even after it has been regimented into a canonical formulation.[27] This argument has been attacked by Howard Peacock,[28] who suggests that Azzouni's strategy conflates two different kinds of ontological commitment – one which is intended as a measure of what a theory explicitly claims to exist, and one which is intended as a measure of what is required for the theory to be true; what the ontological costs of the theory are. If ontological commitment is thought of as a matter of the ontological costs of a theory, then it is possible that a sentence may be ontologically committed to an entity even though competent speakers of the language do not recognize the sentence as asserting the existence of that entity. Ontological commitment is not a matter of what commitments one explicitly recognizes, but rather a matter of what commitments are actually incurred.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Burkhard Schäfer (1998). "Invariance principles and the community of heirs". In N Guarino (ed.). Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Proceedings of the 1st International Conference June 6-8, 1998, Trento, Italy. IOS Press. pp. 108 ff. ISBN 9051993994.
  2. ^ Nicola Guarino (1998). "Formal ontology and information systems". Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Proceedings of the First International Conference (FIOS'98), June 6–8, Trento, Italy. IOS Press. pp. 3 ff. ISBN 9051993994.
  3. ^ Robert Audi, ed. (1999). "Ontological commitment". The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (Paperback 2nd ed.). p. 631. ISBN 0521637228. A shortened version of that definition is as follows:
    The ontological commitments of a theory are those things which occur in all the ontologies of that theory. To explain further, the ontology of a theory consists of the objects the theory makes use of. A dependence of a theory upon an object is indicated if the theory fails when the object is omitted. However, the ontology of a theory is not necessarily unique. A theory is ontologically committed to an object only if that object occurs in all the ontologies of that theory. A theory also can be ontologically committed to a class of objects if that class is populated (not necessarily by the same objects) in all its ontologies.
  4. ^ Quine, W. V. (1948). "On What There Is". Review of Metaphysics. 2: 21–38.. Reprinted in From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-philosophical Essays (2nd ed.). Harvard University Press. 1980. pp. 1–19. ISBN 0674323513. See Wikisource.
  5. ^ Michael J. Loux; Dean W. Zimmerman (2005). "Introduction". In Michael J. Loux; Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics. Oxford Handbooks Online. ISBN 0199284229.
  6. ^ Willard Van Orman Quine (1983). "Chapter 22: Ontology and ideology revisited". Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist: And Other Essays. Harvard University Press. pp. 315 ff. ISBN 0674030842.
  7. ^ Of course, this description is not understandable unless one knows what first-order existential quantifiers are and what is meant by saying they are bound. An approachable discussion of these matters is found in Jan Dejnožka (1996). "Chapter 1: Introduction". The Ontology of the Analytic Tradition and Its Origins: Realism, Possibility, and Identity in Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, and Quine. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1 ff. ISBN 0822630532.
  8. ^ Robert J Fogelin (2004). The Cambridge Companion to Quine. Cambridge University Press. p. 36. ISBN 0521639492.
  9. ^ a b Frank X Ryan (2004). "Analytic: Analytic/Synthetic". In John Lachs; Robert B. Talisse (eds.). American Philosophy: An Encyclopedia. Psychology Press. pp. 36–39. ISBN 020349279X.
  10. ^ Quine, W. V. (1951). "On Carnap's views on ontology". Philosophical Studies. 2 (5): 65–72. doi:10.1007/bf02199422. S2CID 170241527. Reprinted in Willard Van Orman Quine (1976). "Chapter 9: On Carnap's views on ontology". The Ways of Paradox (2nd ed.). Harvard University Press. pp. 203–211. ISBN 0674948378.
  11. ^ Willard Van Orman Quine (1980). "Chapter 2: Two dogmas of empiricism". From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-philosophical Essays (2nd ed.). Harvard University Press. pp. 20 'ff. ISBN 0674323513. See this
  12. ^ Jonathan Schaffer (2009). "On What Grounds What Metametaphysics". In Chalmers; Manley; Wasserman (eds.). Metametaphysics (PDF). Oxford University Press. pp. 347–83. ISBN 978-0199546046. Reprinted by Philosopher’s Annual 29, eds. Grim, Charlow, Gallow, and Herold; also reprinted in Metaphysics: An Anthology, 2nd edition, eds. Kim, Korman, and Sosa (2011), 73-96: Blackwell.) Contains an analysis of Quine and proposes that questions of existence are not fundamental.
  13. ^ See for example, Hilary Putnam (2001) [1962]. "The analytic and the synthetic". In Dagfinn Fllesdal (ed.). Philosophy of Quine: General, reviews, and analytic/synthetic, Volume 1. Taylor & Francis. pp. 252 ff. ISBN 0815337388.
  14. ^ "Ontological Commitment". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  15. ^ Alex Orenstein (1998). "Quine, Willard Van Orman". In Edward Craig (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 8. pp. 8 ff. ISBN 0415073103. See also Choice of a theory.
  16. ^ Kaila E Folinsbee; et al. (2007). "Quantitative approaches to phylogenetics; §5.2: Fount of stability and confusion: A synopsis of parsimony in systematics". In Winfried Henke (ed.). Handbook of Paleoanthropology: Primate evolution and human origins: Volume 2. Springer. p. 168. ISBN 978-3540324744.
  17. ^ Hans-Johann Glock (2004). "§1: Ontological commitment and ontological parsimony". Quine and Davidson on Language, Thought, and Reality. Cambridge University Press. pp. 41–47. ISBN 1139436732.
  18. ^ Willard Van Quine (1981). Theories and Things (3rd ed.). Harvard University Press. pp. 144ff. ISBN 0674879260. Cited by Alan Baker.
  19. ^ a b This section is a slightly modified version of the discussion by Baker, Alan (Feb 25, 2010). "Simplicity". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition).
  20. ^ Alex Ornstein (2008). "Quine vs. Quine: Canonical notation, paraphrase, and regimentation". In Chase B Wrenn (ed.). Naturalism, Reference and Ontology: Essays in Honor of Roger F. Gibson. Peter Lang Publishing, Inc. p. 171. ISBN 978-1433102295.
  21. ^ Marion David (2008). "Quine's Ladder: Two and a half pages from the Philosophy of Logic". In Peter A. French; Howard Wettstein (eds.). Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Truth and its Deformities (Volume XXXII). Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 274 ff. ISBN 978-1405191456.
  22. ^ Mark Colyvan (2001). "§4.2 What is it to be indispensable?". The Indispensability of Mathematics. Oxford University Press. pp. 76 ff. ISBN 0198031440.
  23. ^ Peter Van Inwagen (1998). "Meta-ontology" (PDF). Erkenntnis. 48 (2/3): 233–250. doi:10.1023/a:1005323618026.
  24. ^ Peter van Inwagen (2008). "Chapter 6: Quine's 1946 lecture on nominalism". In Dean Zimmerman (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaphysics : Volume 4. Oxford University Press. pp. 125 ff. ISBN 978-0191562310. Quine has endorsed several closely related theses that I have referred to, collectively, as his "meta-ontology". These are...those of his theses that pertain to the topic "ontological commitment" or "ontic commitment".
  25. ^ Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  26. ^ Shaffer, Jonathan. "Truthmaker Commitments" (PDF).
  27. ^ Azzouni, Jody (2004). Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  28. ^ Peacock, Howard (2011). "Two Kinds of Ontological Commitment". The Philosophical Quarterly. 61 (242): 79–104. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9213.2010.665.x.

External links edit

ontological, commitment, formal, semantics, ontological, commitment, language, more, objects, postulated, exist, that, language, existence, referred, need, real, exist, only, universe, discourse, example, legal, systems, vocabulary, referring, legal, persons, . In formal semantics an ontological commitment of a language is one or more objects postulated to exist by that language The existence referred to need not be real but exist only in a universe of discourse As an example legal systems use vocabulary referring to legal persons that are collective entities that have rights One says the legal doctrine has an ontological commitment to non singular individuals 1 In information systems and artificial intelligence where an ontology refers to a specific vocabulary and a set of explicit assumptions about the meaning and usage of these words an ontological commitment is an agreement to use the shared vocabulary in a coherent and consistent manner within a specific context 2 In philosophy a theory is ontologically committed to an object only if that object occurs in all the ontologies of that theory 3 Contents 1 Background 2 Quine s criterion 2 1 Ontological parsimony 3 Recent controversies 4 See also 5 References 6 External linksBackground editThe sentence Napoleon is one of my ancestors apparently commits us only to the existence of two individuals i e Napoleon and the speaker and a line of ancestry between them The fact that no other people or objects are mentioned seems to limit the commitment of the sentence However it is well known that sentences of this kind cannot be interpreted in first order logic where individual variables stand for individual things Instead they must be represented in some second order form In ordinary language such second order forms use either grammatical plurals or terms such as set of or group of For example the sentence involving Napoleon can be rewritten as any group of people that includes me and the parents of each person in the group must also include Napoleon which is easily interpreted as a statement in second order logic one would naturally start by assigning a name such as G to the group of people under consideration Formally collective noun forms such as a group of people are represented by second order variables or by first order variables standing for sets which are well defined objects in mathematics and logic Since these variables do not stand for individual objects it seems we are ontologically committed to entities other than individuals sets classes and so on As Quine puts it the general adoption of class variables of quantification ushers in a theory whose laws were not in general expressible in the antecedent levels of logic The price paid for this increased power is ontological objects of a special and abstract kind viz classes are now presupposed Formally it is precisely in allowing quantification over class variables a b etc that we assume a range of values for these variables to refer to To be assumed as an entity is to be assumed as a value of a variable Methods of Logic 1950 p 228 Another statement about individuals that appears ontologically innocent is the well known Geach Kaplan sentence Some critics admire only one another Quine s criterion editWillard Van Orman Quine provided an early and influential formulation of ontological commitment 4 If one affirms a statement using a name or other singular term or an initial phrase of existential quantification like There are some so and sos then one must either 1 admit that one is committed to the existence of things answering to the singular term or satisfying the descriptions or 2 provide a paraphrase of the statement that eschews singular terms and quantification over so and sos Quine s criterion can be seen as a logical development of the methods of Bertrand Russell and G E Moore who assumed that one must accept the existence of entities corresponding to the singular terms used in statements one accepts unless and until one finds systematic methods of paraphrase that eliminate these terms 5 Michael J Loux amp Dean W Zimmerman The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics 2003 p 4 The purpose of Quine s strategy is to determine just how the ontological commitment of a theory is to be found Quine argued that the only ontologically committing expressions are variables bound by a first order existential quantifier and natural language expressions which were formalized using variables bound by first order existential quantifiers 6 7 Attempts have been made to argue that predicates are also ontologically committing and thus that subject predicate sentences bear additional ontological commitment to abstract objects such as universals sets or classes It has been suggested that the use of meaningful names in nonexistence statements such as Pegasus does not exist brings with it an ontological commitment to empty names like Pegasus a quandary referred to as Plato s beard and escaped by using quantifiers 8 This discussion has a connection to the Carnap Quine argument over analytic and synthetic objects 9 Although Quine refers to ontological commitment in this connection 10 in his rejection of the analytic synthetic distinction he does not rely upon the formal translation of any particular theory along the lines he has suggested 11 Instead Quine argues by using examples that although there are tautological statements in a formal theory like all squares are rectangles a formal theory necessarily contains references to objects that are not tautological but have external connections That is there is an ontological commitment to such external objects In addition the terms used to interpret the application of the theory are not simply descriptions of sensory input but are statements in a context That is inversely there is an ontological commitment of these observational objects to the formal theory As Ryan puts it Rather than being divided between contingent synthetic claims and indubitable analytic propositions our beliefs constitute a continuous range from a periphery of sense reports to interior concepts that are comparatively theory laden and general 9 Thus we end up with Quine s flat ontology that does not see a distinction between analytic and synthetic objects 12 13 Quine further made a distinction between the ontological commitments of a theory what the theory says exists and the ideological commitments of a theory those concepts logical or non logical that are expressible within the theory 14 Ontological parsimony edit Whatever process one uses to determine the ontological commitments of a theory that does not prescribe what ontological commitments one should have Quine regarded this as a matter of epistemology which theory one should accept Appeal is made to concerns of explanatory power parsimony conservatism precision and so on 15 Ontological parsimony can be defined in various ways and often is equated to versions of Occam s razor a rule of thumb which obliges us to favor theories or hypotheses that make the fewest unwarranted or ad hoc assumptions about the data from which they are derived 16 Glock regards ontological parsimony as one of the five main points of Quine s conception of ontology 17 Following Quine 18 Baker states that a theory T is ontologically committed to items F if and only if T entails that F s exist If two theories T1 and T2 have the same ontological commitments except that T2 is ontologically committed to F s while T1 is not then T1 is more parsimonious than T2 More generally a sufficient condition for T1 being more parsimonious than T2 is for the ontological commitments of T1 to be a proper subset of those of T2 19 These ideas lead to the following particular formulation of Occam s razor Other things being equal if T1 is more ontologically parsimonious than T2 then it is rational to prefer T1 to T2 While a common formulation stipulates only that entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity this version by contrast states that entities should not be multiplied other things being equal and this is compatible with parsimony being a comparatively weak theoretical virtue 19 Recent controversies editThe standard approach to ontological commitment has been that once a theory has been regimented and or paraphrased into an agreed canonical version 20 which may indeed be in formal logical notation rather than the original language of the theory ontological commitments can be read off straightforwardly from the presence of certain ontologically committing expressions e g bound variables of existential quantification Although there is substantial debate about which expressions are ontologically committing 21 22 parties to that debate generally agree that the expressions they prefer are reliable bearers of ontological commitment imparting ontological commitment to all regimented sentences in which they occur This assumption has been challenged Inwagen has taken issue with Quine s methodology 23 claiming that this process did not lead to a unique set of fundamental objects but to several possible sets and one never could be certain that all the possible sets had been found He also took issue with Quine s notion of a theory which he felt was tantamount to suggesting a theory was just a collection of sentences Inwagen suggested that Quine s approach provided useful tools for discovering what entities were ontological commitments but that he had not been successful His attempts are comparable to an attempt to reach the moon by climbing ever higher trees 24 It has been suggested that the ontological commitments of a theory cannot be discerned by analysis of the syntax of sentences looking for ontologically committing expressions because the true ontological commitments of a sentence or theory are restricted to the entities needed to serve as truthmakers for that sentence and the syntax of even a regimented or formalized sentence is not a reliable guide to what entities are needed to make it true 25 However this view has been attacked by Jonathan Schaffer who has argued that truthmaking is not an adequate test for ontological commitment at best the search for the truthmakers of our theory will tell us what is fundamental but not what our theory is ontologically committed to and hence will not serve as a good way of deciding what exists 26 It also has been argued that the syntax of sentences is not a reliable guide to their ontological commitments because English has no form of words which reliably functions to make an existence claim in every context in which it is used For example Jody Azzouni suggests that There is does not make any kind of genuine existence claim when it is used in a sentence such as There are mice that talk Since the meaning of the existential quantifier in formal notation is usually explained in terms of its equivalence to English expressions such as there is and there exist and since these English expressions are not reliably ontologically committing it comes to seem that we cannot be sure of our theory s ontological commitments even after it has been regimented into a canonical formulation 27 This argument has been attacked by Howard Peacock 28 who suggests that Azzouni s strategy conflates two different kinds of ontological commitment one which is intended as a measure of what a theory explicitly claims to exist and one which is intended as a measure of what is required for the theory to be true what the ontological costs of the theory are If ontological commitment is thought of as a matter of the ontological costs of a theory then it is possible that a sentence may be ontologically committed to an entity even though competent speakers of the language do not recognize the sentence as asserting the existence of that entity Ontological commitment is not a matter of what commitments one explicitly recognizes but rather a matter of what commitments are actually incurred See also editConceptualization information science Holophrastic indeterminacy Indeterminacy of translationReferences edit Burkhard Schafer 1998 Invariance principles and the community of heirs In N Guarino ed Formal Ontology in Information Systems Proceedings of the 1st International Conference June 6 8 1998 Trento Italy IOS Press pp 108 ff ISBN 9051993994 Nicola Guarino 1998 Formal ontology and information systems Formal Ontology in Information Systems Proceedings of the First International Conference FIOS 98 June 6 8 Trento Italy IOS Press pp 3 ff ISBN 9051993994 Robert Audi ed 1999 Ontological commitment The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Paperback 2nd ed p 631 ISBN 0521637228 A shortened version of that definition is as follows The ontological commitments of a theory are those things which occur in all the ontologies of that theory To explain further the ontology of a theory consists of the objects the theory makes use of A dependence of a theory upon an object is indicated if the theory fails when the object is omitted However the ontology of a theory is not necessarily unique A theory is ontologically committed to an object only if that object occurs in all the ontologies of that theory A theory also can be ontologically committed to a class of objects if that class is populated not necessarily by the same objects in all its ontologies Quine W V 1948 On What There Is Review of Metaphysics 2 21 38 Reprinted in From a Logical Point of View Nine Logico philosophical Essays 2nd ed Harvard University Press 1980 pp 1 19 ISBN 0674323513 See Wikisource Michael J Loux Dean W Zimmerman 2005 Introduction In Michael J Loux Dean W Zimmerman eds The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics Oxford Handbooks Online ISBN 0199284229 Willard Van Orman Quine 1983 Chapter 22 Ontology and ideology revisited Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist And Other Essays Harvard University Press pp 315 ff ISBN 0674030842 Of course this description is not understandable unless one knows what first order existential quantifiers are and what is meant by saying they are bound An approachable discussion of these matters is found in Jan Dejnozka 1996 Chapter 1 Introduction The Ontology of the Analytic Tradition and Its Origins Realism Possibility and Identity in Frege Russell Wittgenstein and Quine Rowman amp Littlefield pp 1 ff ISBN 0822630532 Robert J Fogelin 2004 The Cambridge Companion to Quine Cambridge University Press p 36 ISBN 0521639492 a b Frank X Ryan 2004 Analytic Analytic Synthetic In John Lachs Robert B Talisse eds American Philosophy An Encyclopedia Psychology Press pp 36 39 ISBN 020349279X Quine W V 1951 On Carnap s views on ontology Philosophical Studies 2 5 65 72 doi 10 1007 bf02199422 S2CID 170241527 Reprinted in Willard Van Orman Quine 1976 Chapter 9 On Carnap s views on ontology The Ways of Paradox 2nd ed Harvard University Press pp 203 211 ISBN 0674948378 Willard Van Orman Quine 1980 Chapter 2 Two dogmas of empiricism From a Logical Point of View Nine Logico philosophical Essays 2nd ed Harvard University Press pp 20 ff ISBN 0674323513 See this Jonathan Schaffer 2009 On What Grounds What Metametaphysics In Chalmers Manley Wasserman eds Metametaphysics PDF Oxford University Press pp 347 83 ISBN 978 0199546046 Reprinted by Philosopher s Annual 29 eds Grim Charlow Gallow and Herold also reprinted in Metaphysics An Anthology 2nd edition eds Kim Korman and Sosa 2011 73 96 Blackwell Contains an analysis of Quine and proposes that questions of existence are not fundamental See for example Hilary Putnam 2001 1962 The analytic and the synthetic In Dagfinn Fllesdal ed Philosophy of Quine General reviews and analytic synthetic Volume 1 Taylor amp Francis pp 252 ff ISBN 0815337388 Ontological Commitment Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Alex Orenstein 1998 Quine Willard Van Orman In Edward Craig ed Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 8 pp 8 ff ISBN 0415073103 See also Choice of a theory Kaila E Folinsbee et al 2007 Quantitative approaches to phylogenetics 5 2 Fount of stability and confusion A synopsis of parsimony in systematics In Winfried Henke ed Handbook of Paleoanthropology Primate evolution and human origins Volume 2 Springer p 168 ISBN 978 3540324744 Hans Johann Glock 2004 1 Ontological commitment and ontological parsimony Quine and Davidson on Language Thought and Reality Cambridge University Press pp 41 47 ISBN 1139436732 Willard Van Quine 1981 Theories and Things 3rd ed Harvard University Press pp 144ff ISBN 0674879260 Cited by Alan Baker a b This section is a slightly modified version of the discussion by Baker Alan Feb 25 2010 Simplicity In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition Alex Ornstein 2008 Quine vs Quine Canonical notation paraphrase and regimentation In Chase B Wrenn ed Naturalism Reference and Ontology Essays in Honor of Roger F Gibson Peter Lang Publishing Inc p 171 ISBN 978 1433102295 Marion David 2008 Quine s Ladder Two and a half pages from the Philosophy of Logic In Peter A French Howard Wettstein eds Midwest Studies in Philosophy Truth and its Deformities Volume XXXII Wiley Blackwell pp 274 ff ISBN 978 1405191456 Mark Colyvan 2001 4 2 What is it to be indispensable The Indispensability of Mathematics Oxford University Press pp 76 ff ISBN 0198031440 Peter Van Inwagen 1998 Meta ontology PDF Erkenntnis 48 2 3 233 250 doi 10 1023 a 1005323618026 Peter van Inwagen 2008 Chapter 6 Quine s 1946 lecture on nominalism In Dean Zimmerman ed Oxford Studies in Metaphysics Volume 4 Oxford University Press pp 125 ff ISBN 978 0191562310 Quine has endorsed several closely related theses that I have referred to collectively as his meta ontology These are those of his theses that pertain to the topic ontological commitment or ontic commitment Heil J 2003 From an ontological point of view Oxford Oxford University Press Shaffer Jonathan Truthmaker Commitments PDF Azzouni Jody 2004 Deflating Existential Consequence A Case for Nominalism Oxford Oxford University Press Peacock Howard 2011 Two Kinds of Ontological Commitment The Philosophical Quarterly 61 242 79 104 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9213 2010 665 x External links editBricker Phillip Ontological Commitment In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ontological commitment a category in Philosophical Papers maintained by Henry Laycock Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Ontological commitment amp oldid 1217840031, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.