fbpx
Wikipedia

Philosophical skepticism

Philosophical skepticism (UK spelling: scepticism; from Greek σκέψις skepsis, "inquiry") is a family of philosophical views that question the possibility of knowledge.[1][2] It differs from other forms of skepticism in that it even rejects very plausible knowledge claims that belong to basic common sense. Philosophical skeptics are often classified into two general categories: Those who deny all possibility of knowledge, and those who advocate for the suspension of judgment due to the inadequacy of evidence.[3] This distinction is modeled after the differences between the Academic skeptics and the Pyrrhonian skeptics in ancient Greek philosophy. In the latter sense, skepticism is understood as a way of life that helps the practitioner achieve inner peace. Some types of philosophical skepticism reject all forms of knowledge while others limit this rejection to certain fields, for example, to knowledge about moral doctrines or about the external world. Some theorists criticize philosophical skepticism based on the claim that it is a self-refuting idea since its proponents seem to claim to know that there is no knowledge. Other objections focus on its implausibility and distance from regular life.

Overview

Philosophical skepticism is a doubtful attitude toward commonly accepted knowledge claims. It is an important form of skepticism. Skepticism in general is a questioning attitude toward all kinds of knowledge claims. In this wide sense, it is quite common in everyday life: many people are ordinary skeptics about parapsychology or about astrology because they doubt the claims made by proponents of these fields.[4] But the same people are not skeptical about other knowledge claims like the ones found in regular school books. Philosophical skepticism differs from ordinary skepticism in that it even rejects knowledge claims that belong to basic common sense and seem to be very certain.[4] For this reason, it is sometimes referred to as radical doubt.[5] In some cases, it is even proclaimed that one does not know that "I have two hands" or that "the sun will come out tomorrow".[6][7] In this regard, philosophical skepticism is not a position commonly adopted by regular people in everyday life.[8][9] This denial of knowledge is usually associated with the demand that one should suspend one's beliefs about the doubted proposition. This means that one should neither believe nor disbelieve it but keep an open mind without committing oneself one way or the other.[10] Philosophical skepticism is often based on the idea that no matter how certain one is about a given belief, one could still be wrong about it.[11][7] From this observation, it is argued that the belief does not amount to knowledge. Philosophical skepticism follows from the consideration that this might be the case for most or all beliefs.[12] Because of its wide-ranging consequences, it is of central interest to theories of knowledge since it questions their very foundations.[10]

According to some definitions, philosophical skepticism is not just the rejection of some forms of commonly accepted knowledge but the rejection of all forms of knowledge.[4][10][13] In this regard, we may have relatively secure beliefs in some cases but these beliefs never amount to knowledge. Weaker forms of philosophical skepticism restrict this rejection to specific fields, like the external world or moral doctrines. In some cases, knowledge per se is not rejected but it is still denied that one can ever be absolutely certain.[9][14]

There are only few defenders of philosophical skepticism in the strong sense.[4] In this regard, it is much more commonly used as a theoretical tool to test theories.[5][4][12][15] On this view, it is a philosophical methodology that can be utilized to probe a theory to find its weak points, either to expose it or to modify it in order to arrive at a better version of it.[5] However, some theorists distinguish philosophical skepticism from methodological skepticism in that philosophical skepticism is an approach that questions the possibility of certainty in knowledge, whereas methodological skepticism is an approach that subjects all knowledge claims to scrutiny with the goal of sorting out true from false claims.[citation needed] Similarly, scientific skepticism differs from philosophical skepticism in that scientific skepticism is an epistemological position in which one questions the veracity of claims lacking empirical evidence. In practice, the term most commonly references the examination of claims and theories that appear to be pseudoscience, rather than the routine discussions and challenges among scientists.[16]

In ancient philosophy, skepticism was seen not just as a theory about the existence of knowledge but as a way of life. This outlook is motivated by the idea that suspending one's judgment on all kinds of issues brings with it inner peace and thereby contributes to the skeptic's happiness.[14][17][18]

Classification

Skepticism can be classified according to its scope. Local skepticism involves being skeptical about particular areas of knowledge (e.g. moral skepticism, skepticism about the external world, or skepticism about other minds), whereas radical skepticism claims that one cannot know anything—including that one cannot know about knowing anything.

Skepticism can also be classified according to its method. Western philosophy has two basic approaches to skepticism.[19] Cartesian skepticism—named somewhat misleadingly after René Descartes, who was not a skeptic but used some traditional skeptical arguments in his Meditations to help establish his rationalist approach to knowledge—attempts to show that any proposed knowledge claim can be doubted. Agrippan skepticism focuses on justification rather than the possibility of doubt. According to this view, none of the ways in which one might attempt to justify a claim are adequate. One can justify a claim based on other claims, but this leads to an infinite regress of justifications. One can use a dogmatic assertion, but this is not a justification. One can use circular reasoning, but this fails to justify the conclusion.

Skeptical scenarios

A skeptical scenario is a hypothetical situation which can be used in an argument for skepticism about a particular claim or class of claims. Usually the scenario posits the existence of a deceptive power that deceives our senses and undermines the justification of knowledge otherwise accepted as justified, and is proposed in order to call into question our ordinary claims to knowledge on the grounds that we cannot exclude the possibility of skeptical scenarios being true. Skeptical scenarios have received a great deal of attention in modern Western philosophy.

The first major skeptical scenario in modern Western philosophy appears in René Descartes' Meditations on First Philosophy. At the end of the first Meditation Descartes writes: "I will suppose... that some evil demon of the utmost power and cunning has employed all his energies to deceive me."

  • The "evil demon problem", also known as "Descartes' evil demon", was first proposed by René Descartes. It invokes the possibility of a being who could deliberately mislead one into falsely believing everything that you take to be true.
  • The "brain in a vat" hypothesis is cast in contemporary scientific terms. It supposes that one might be a disembodied brain kept alive in a vat and fed false sensory signals by a mad scientist. Further, it asserts that since a brain in a vat would have no way of knowing that it was a brain in a vat, you cannot prove that you are not a brain in a vat.
  • The "dream argument", proposed by both René Descartes and Zhuangzi, supposes reality to be indistinguishable from a dream.
  • The "five minute hypothesis", most notably proposed by Bertrand Russell, suggests that we cannot prove that the world was not created five minutes ago (along with false memories and false evidence suggesting that it was not only five minutes old).
  • The "simulated reality hypothesis" or "Matrix hypothesis" suggests that everyone, or even the entire universe, might be inside a computer simulation or virtual reality.
  • The "Solipsistic" theory that claims that knowledge of the world is an illusion of the Self.

Epistemological skepticism

Skepticism, as an epistemological view, calls into question whether knowledge is possible at all. This is distinct from other known skeptical practices, including Cartesian skepticism, as it targets knowledge in general instead of individual types of knowledge.

Skeptics argue that belief in something does not justify an assertion of knowledge of it. In this, skeptics oppose foundationalism, which states that there are basic positions that are self-justified or beyond justification, without reference to others. (One example of such foundationalism may be found in Spinoza's Ethics.) The skeptical response to this can take several approaches. First, claiming that "basic positions" must exist amounts to the logical fallacy of argument from ignorance combined with the slippery slope.[citation needed]

Among other arguments, skeptics use the Münchhausen trilemma and the problem of the criterion to claim that no certain belief can be achieved. This position is known as "global skepticism" or "radical skepticism." Foundationalists have used the same trilemma as a justification for demanding the validity of basic beliefs.[citation needed] Epistemological nihilism rejects the possibility of human knowledge, but not necessarily knowledge in general.

There are two different categories of epistemological skepticism, which can be referred to as mitigated and unmitigated skepticism. The two forms are contrasting but are still true forms of skepticism. Mitigated skepticism does not accept "strong" or "strict" knowledge claims but does, however, approve specific weaker ones. These weaker claims can be assigned the title of "virtual knowledge", but must be to justified belief. Some mitigated skeptics are also fallibilists, arguing that knowledge does not require certainty. Mitigated skeptics hold that knowledge does not require certainty and that many beliefs are, in practice, certain to the point that they can be safely acted upon in order to live significant and meaningful lives. Unmitigated skepticism rejects both claims of virtual knowledge and strong knowledge.[20] Characterising knowledge as strong, weak, virtual or genuine can be determined differently depending on a person's viewpoint as well as their characterisation of knowledge. Unmitigated skeptics believe that objective truths are unknowable and that man should live in an isolated environment in order to win mental peace. This is because everything, according to them, is changing and relative. The refusal to make judgments is of uttermost importance since there is no knowledge; only probable opinions.[20]

Criticism

Philosophical skepticism has been criticized in various ways. Some criticisms see it as a self-refuting idea while others point out that it is implausible, psychologically impossible, or a pointless intellectual game. One of the strongest criticisms claims that philosophical skepticism is contradictory or self-refuting. This position is based on the idea that it not only rejects the existence of knowledge but seems to make knowledge claims itself at the same time.[9][21][22] For example, to claim that there is no knowledge seems to be itself a knowledge claim. This problem is particularly relevant for versions of philosophical skepticism that deny any form of knowledge. So the global skeptic denies that any claim is rationally justified but then goes on to provide arguments in an attempt to rationally justify their denial.[21] Some philosophical skeptics have responded to this objection by restricting the denial of knowledge to certain fields without denying the existence of knowledge in general. Another defense consists in understanding philosophical skepticism not as a theory but as a tool or a methodology. In this case, it may be used fruitfully to reject and improve philosophical systems despite its shortcomings as a theory.[9][15]

Another criticism holds that philosophical skepticism is highly counterintuitive by pointing out how far removed it is from regular life.[8][9] For example, it seems very impractical, if not psychologically impossible, to suspend all beliefs at the same time. And even if it was possible, it would not be advisable since "the complete skeptic would wind up starving to death or walking into walls or out of windows".[9] This criticism can allow that there are some arguments that support philosophical skepticism. However, it has been claimed that they are not nearly strong enough to support such a radical conclusion.[8] Common-sense philosophers follow this line of thought by arguing that regular common-sense beliefs are much more reliable than the skeptics' intricate arguments.[8] George Edward Moore, for example, tried to refute skepticism about the existence of the external world, not by engaging with its complex arguments, but by using a simple observation: that he has two hands. For Moore, this observation is a reliable source of knowledge incompatible with external world skepticism since it entails that at least two physical objects exist.[23][8]

A closely related objection sees philosophical skepticism as an "idle academic exercise" or a "waste of time".[10] This is often based on the idea that, because of its initial implausibility and distance from everyday life, it has little or no practical value.[9][15] In this regard, Arthur Schopenhauer compares the position of radical skepticism to a border fortress that is best ignored: it is impregnable but its garrison does not pose any threat since it never sets foot outside the fortress.[24] One defense of philosophical skepticism is that it has had important impacts on the history of philosophy at large and not just among skeptical philosophers. This is due to its critical attitude, which remains a constant challenge to the epistemic foundations of various philosophical theories. It has often provoked creative responses from other philosophers when trying to modify the affected theory to avoid the problem of skepticism.[9][14]

According to Pierre Le Morvan, there are two very common negative responses to philosophical skepticism. The first understands it as a threat to all kinds of philosophical theories and strives to disprove it. According to the second, philosophical skepticism is a useless distraction and should better be avoided altogether. Le Morvan himself proposes a positive third alternative: to use it as a philosophical tool in a few selected cases to overcome prejudices and foster practical wisdom.[15]

History of Western skepticism

 
Skeptics in Raphael's School of Athens painting. 1. Pythodorus 2. Arcesilaus of Pitane 3. Carneades of Cyrene 4. Pyrrho of Elis 5. Timon of Phlius 6. Theodorus the Atheist of Cyrene

Ancient Greek skepticism

 
Pyrrho of Elis, marble head, Roman copy, Archeological Museum of Corfu

Ancient Greek skeptics were not "skeptics" in the contemporary sense of selective, localized doubt. Their concerns were epistemological, noting that truth claims could not be adequately supported, and psychotherapeutic, noting that beliefs caused mental perturbation.

The Western tradition of systematic skepticism goes back at least as far as Pyrrho of Elis (b. c. 360 BCE) and arguably to Xenophanes (b. c. 570 BCE). Parts of skepticism also appear among the "5th century sophists [who] develop forms of debate which are ancestors of skeptical argumentation. They take pride in arguing in a persuasive fashion for both sides of an issue."[25]

In Hellenistic philosophy, Pyrrhonism and Academic Skepticism were the two schools of skeptical philosophy. Subsequently, the words Academic and Pyrrhonist were often be used to mean skeptic.

Pyrrhonism

Like other Hellenistic philosophies, the goal of Pyrrhonism was eudaimonia, which the Pyrrhonists sought through achieving ataraxia (an untroubled state of mind), which they found could be induced by producing a state of epoché (suspension of judgment) regarding non-evident matters. Epoché could be produced by pitting one dogma against another to undermine belief, and by questioning whether a belief could be justified. In support of this questioning Pyrrhonists developed the skeptical arguments cited above (the Ten Modes of Aenesidemus and the Five Modes of Agrippa)[26] demonstrating that beliefs cannot be justified:[27]

Pyrrho of Elis

According to an account of Pyrrho's life by his student Timon of Phlius, Pyrrho extolled a way to become happy and tranquil:

'The things themselves are equally indifferent, and unstable, and indeterminate, and therefore neither our senses nor our opinions are either true or false. For this reason then we must not trust them, but be without opinions, and without bias, and without wavering, saying of every single thing that it no more is than is not, or both is and is not, or neither is nor is not.[28]

Aenesidemus

Pyrrhonism faded as a movement following the death of Pyrrho's student Timon.[29] The Academy became slowly more dogmatic[30] such that in the first century BCE Aenesidemus denounced the Academics as "Stoics fighting against Stoics," breaking with the Academy to revive Pyrrhonism.[30] Aenesidemus's best known contribution to skepticism was his now-lost book, Pyrrhonian Discourses, which is only known to us through Photius, Sextus Empiricus, and to a lesser extent Diogenes Laërtius. The skeptical arguments most closely associated with Aenesidemus are the ten modes described above designed to induce epoche. [26]

Sextus Empiricus
 
Sextus Empiricus

The works of Sextus Empiricus (c. 200 CE) are the main surviving account of ancient Pyrrhonism. Long before Sextus' time, the Academy had abandoned skepticism and had been destroyed as a formal institution.[30][31][32] Sextus compiled and further developed the Pyrrhonists' skeptical arguments, most of which were directed against the Stoics but included arguments against all of the schools of Hellenistic philosophy, including the Academic skeptics.

Sextus, as the most systematic author of the works by Hellenistic skeptics which have survived, noted that there are at least ten modes of skepticism. These modes may be broken down into three categories: one may be skeptical of the subjective perceiver, of the objective world, and the relation between perceiver and the world.[33] His arguments are as follows.

Subjectively, both the powers of the senses and of reasoning may vary among different people. And since knowledge is a product of one or the other, and since neither are reliable, knowledge would seem to be in trouble. For instance, a color-blind person sees the world quite differently from everyone else. Moreover, one cannot even give preference on the basis of the power of reason, i.e., by treating the rational animal as a carrier of greater knowledge than the irrational animal, since the irrational animal is still adept at navigating their environment, which suggests the ability to "know" about some aspects of the environment.

Secondly, the personality of the individual might also influence what they observe, since (it is argued) preferences are based on sense-impressions, differences in preferences can be attributed to differences in the way that people are affected by the object. (Empiricus:56)

Third, the perceptions of each individual sense seemingly have nothing in common with the other senses: i.e., the color "red" has little to do with the feeling of touching a red object. This is manifest when our senses "disagree" with each other: for example, a mirage presents certain visible features, but is not responsive to any other kind of sense. In that case, our other senses defeat the impressions of sight. But one may also be lacking enough powers of sense to understand the world in its entirety: if one had an extra sense, then one might know of things in a way that the present five senses are unable to advise us of. Given that our senses can be shown to be unreliable by appealing to other senses, and so our senses may be incomplete (relative to some more perfect sense that one lacks), then it follows that all of our senses may be unreliable. (Empiricus:58)

Fourth, our circumstances when one perceives anything may be either natural or unnatural, i.e., one may be either in a state of wakefulness or sleep. But it is entirely possible that things in the world really are exactly as they appear to be to those in unnatural states (i.e., if everything were an elaborate dream). (Empiricus:59)

One can have reasons for doubt that are based on the relationship between objective "facts" and subjective experience. The positions, distances, and places of objects would seem to affect how they are perceived by the person: for instance, the portico may appear tapered when viewed from one end, but symmetrical when viewed at the other; and these features are different. Because they are different features, to believe the object has both properties at the same time is to believe it has two contradictory properties. Since this is absurd, one must suspend judgment about what properties it possesses due to the contradictory experiences. (Empiricus:63)

One may also observe that the things one perceives are, in a sense, polluted by experience. Any given perception—say, of a chair—will always be perceived within some context or other (i.e., next to a table, on a mat, etc.) Since this is the case, one often only speaks of ideas as they occur in the context of the other things that are paired with it, and therefore, one can never know of the true nature of the thing, but only how it appears to us in context. (Empiricus: 64)

Along the same lines, the skeptic may insist that all things are relative, by arguing that:

  1. Absolute appearances either differ from relative appearances, or they do not.
  2. If absolutes do not differ from relatives, then they are themselves relative.
  3. But if absolutes do differ from relatives, then they are relative, because all things that differ must differ from something; and to "differ" from something is to be relative to something. (Empiricus:67)

Finally, one has reason to disbelieve that one knows anything by looking at problems in understanding objects by themselves. Things, when taken individually, may appear to be very different from when they are in mass quantities: for instance, the shavings of a goat's horn are white when taken alone, yet the horn intact is black.[citation needed]

Skeptical arguments

The ancient Greek Pyrrhonists developed sets of arguments to demonstrate that claims about reality cannot be adequately justified. Two sets of these arguments are well known. The oldest set is known as the ten tropes of Aenesidemus—although whether he invented the tropes or just systematized them from prior Pyrrhonist works is unknown. The tropes represent reasons for epoché (suspension of judgment). These are as follows:

  1. Different animals manifest different modes of perception;
  2. Similar differences are seen among individual men;
  3. For the same man, information perceived with the senses is self-contradictory
  4. Furthermore, it varies from time to time with physical changes
  5. In addition, this data differs according to local relations
  6. Objects are known only indirectly through the medium of air, moisture, etc.
  7. These objects are in a condition of perpetual change in color, temperature, size and motion
  8. All perceptions are relative and interact one upon another
  9. Our impressions become less critical through repetition and custom
  10. All men are brought up with different beliefs, under different laws and social conditions

Another set are known as the five tropes of Agrippa:

  1. Dissent – The uncertainty demonstrated by the differences of opinions among philosophers and people in general.
  2. Progress ad infinitum – All proof rests on matters themselves in need of proof, and so on to infinity, i.e, the regress argument.
  3. Relation – All things are changed as their relations become changed, or, as we look upon them from different points of view.
  4. Assumption – The truth asserted is based on an unsupported assumption.
  5. Circularity – The truth asserted involves a circularity of proofs.

According to Victor Brochard "the five tropes can be regarded as the most radical and most precise formulation of philosophical skepticism that has ever been given. In a sense, they are still irresistible today."[34]

Academic skepticism

Pyrrho's thinking subsequently influenced the Platonic Academy, arising first in the Academic skepticism of the Middle Academy under Arcesilaus (c. 315 – 241 BCE) and then the New Academy under Carneades (c. 213–129 BCE). Clitomachus, a student of Carneades, interpreted his teacher's philosophy as suggesting an account of knowledge based on truth-likeness. The Roman politician and philosopher, Cicero, was also an adherent of the skepticism of the New Academy, even though a return to a more dogmatic orientation of the school was already beginning to take place.

Augustine on skepticism

 
Augustine of Hippo

In 386 CE, Augustine published Contra Academicos (Against the Academic Skeptics), which argued against claims made by the Academic Skeptics (266–90 BCE) on the following grounds:

  • Objection from Error: Through logic, Augustine argues that philosophical skepticism does not lead to happiness like the Academic Skeptics claim. His arguments is summarized as:
    1. A wise man lives according to reason, and thus is able to be happy.
    2. One who is searching for knowledge but never finds it is in error.
    3. Imperfection objection: People in error are not happy, because being in error is an imperfection, and people cannot be happy with an imperfection.
    4. Conclusion: One who is still seeking knowledge cannot be happy.[35][36]
  • Error of Non-Assent: Augustine's argument that suspending belief does not fully prevent one from error. His argument is summarized below.
    1. Introduction of the error: Let P be true. If a person fails to believe P due to suspension of belief in order to avoid error, the person is also committing an error.
    2. The Anecdote of the Two Travelers: Travelers A and B are trying to reach the same destination. At a fork in the road, a poor shepherd tells them to go left. Traveler A immediately believes him and reaches the correct destination. Traveler B suspends belief, and instead believes in the advice of a well-dressed townsman to go right, because his advice seems more persuasive. However, the townsman is actually a samardocus (con man) so Traveler B never reaches the correct destination.
    3. The Anecdote of the Adulterer: A man suspends belief that adultery is bad, and commits adultery with another man's wife because it is persuasive to him. Under Academic Skepticism, this man cannot be charged because he acted on what was persuasive to him without assenting belief.
    4. Conclusion: Suspending belief exposes individuals to an error as defined by the Academic Skeptics.[35]

Skepticism's revival in the sixteenth century

Francisco Sanches's That Nothing is Known (published in 1581 as Quod nihil scitur) is one of the crucial texts of Renaissance skepticism.[37]

Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592)

 
Michel de Montaigne

The most notable figure of the Skepticism revival in the 1500s, Michel de Montaigne wrote about his studies of Academic Skepticism and Pyrrhonism through his Essais.

His most notable writings on skepticism occurred in an essay written mostly in 1575–1576, "Apologie de Raimond Sebond," when he was reading Sextus Empiricus and trying to translate Raimond Sebond's writing, including his proof of Christianity's natural existence. The reception to Montaigne's translations included some criticisms of Sebond's proof. Montaigne responded to some of them in Apologie, including a defense for Sebond's logic that is skeptical in nature and similar to Pyrrhonism.[38][39] His refutation is as follows:

  1. Critics claiming Sebond's arguments are weak show how egoistic humans believe that their logic is superior to others’.
  2. Many animals can be observed to be superior to humans in certain respects. To argue this point, Montaigne even writes about dogs who are logical and creates their own syllogisms to understand the world around them. This was an example used in Sextus Empiricus.
  3. Since animals also have rationality, the over-glorification of man's mental capabilities is a trap—man's folly. One man's reason cannot be assuredly better than another's as a result.
  4. Ignorance is even recommended by religion so that an individual can reach faith through obediently following divine instructions to learn, not by one's logic.[3]

Marin Mersenne (1588–1648)

 
Marin Mersenne

Marin Mersenne was an author, mathematician, scientist, and philosopher. He wrote in defense of science and Christianity against atheists and Pyrrhonists before retiring to encourage development of science and the "new philosophy," which includes philosophers like Gassendi, Descartes, Galileo, and Hobbes. A major work of his in relation to Skepticism is La Verité des Sciences, in which he argues that although we may not be able to know the true nature of things, we can still formulate certain laws and rules for sense-perceptions through science.[3][39][40]

Additionally, he points out that we do not doubt everything because:

  • Humans do agree about some things, for example, an ant is smaller than an elephant
  • There are natural laws governing our sense-perceptions, such as optics, which allow us to eliminate inaccuracies
  • Man created tools such as rulers and scales to measure things and eliminate doubts such as bent oars, pigeons’ necks, and round towers.

A Pyrrhonist might refute these points by saying that senses deceive, and thus knowledge turns into infinite regress or circular logic. Thus Mersenne argues that this cannot be the case, since commonly agreed upon rules of thumb can be hypothesized and tested over time to ensure that they continue to hold.[41]

Furthermore, if everything can be doubted, the doubt can also be doubted, so on and so forth. Thus, according to Mersenne, something has to be true. Finally, Mersenne writes about all the mathematical, physical, and other scientific knowledge that is true by repeated testing, and has practical use value. Notably, Mersenne was one of the few philosophers who accepted Hobbes' radical ideology—he saw it as a new science of man.[3]

Skepticism in the seventeenth century

 
Thomas Hobbes

Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679)

During his long stay in Paris, Thomas Hobbes was actively involved in the circle of major skeptics like Gassendi and Mersenne who focus on the study of skepticism and epistemology. Unlike his fellow skeptic friends, Hobbes never treated skepticism as a main topic for discussion in his works. Nonetheless, Hobbes was still labeled as a religious skeptic by his contemporaries for raising doubts about Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch and his political and psychological explanation of the religions. Although Hobbes himself did not go further to challenge other religious principles, his suspicion for the Mosaic authorship did significant damage to the religious traditions and paved the way for later religious skeptics like Spinoza and Isaac La Peyrère to further question some of the fundamental beliefs of the Judeo-Christian religious system. Hobbes' answer to skepticism and epistemology was innovatively political: he believed that moral knowledge and religious knowledge were in their nature relative, and there was no absolute standard of truth governing them. As a result, it was out of political reasons that certain truth standards about religions and ethics were devised and established in order to form a functioning government and stable society.[3][42][43][44]

 
Baruch Spinoza

Baruch Spinoza and religious skepticism

Baruch Spinoza was among the first European philosophers who were religious skeptics. He was quite familiar with the philosophy of Descartes and unprecedentedly extended the application of the Cartesian method to the religious context by analyzing religious texts with it. Spinoza sought to dispute the knowledge-claims of the Judeo-Christian-Islamic religious system by examining its two foundations: the Scripture and the Miracles. He claimed that all Cartesian knowledge, or the rational knowledge should be accessible to the entire population. Therefore, the Scriptures, aside from those by Jesus, should not be considered the secret knowledge attained from God but just the imagination of the prophets. The Scriptures, as a result of this claim, could not serve as a base for knowledge and were reduced to simple ancient historical texts. Moreover, Spinoza also rejected the possibility for the Miracles by simply asserting that people only considered them miraculous due to their lack of understanding of the nature. By rejecting the validity of the Scriptures and the Miracles, Spinoza demolished the foundation for religious knowledge-claim and established his understanding of the Cartesian knowledge as the sole authority of knowledge-claims. Despite being deeply skeptical of the religions, Spinoza was in fact exceedingly anti-skeptical towards reason and rationality. He steadfastly confirmed the legitimacy of reason by associating it with the acknowledgement of God, and thereby skepticism with the rational approach to knowledge was not due to problems with the rational knowledge but from the fundamental lack of understanding of God. Spinoza's religious skepticism and anti-skepticism with reason thus helped him transform epistemology by separating the theological knowledge-claims and the rational knowledge-claims.[3][45]

Pierre Bayle (1647–1706)

 
Pierre Bayle by Louis Ferdinand Elle

Pierre Bayle was a French philosopher in the late 17th century that was described by Richard Popkin to be a "supersceptic" who carried out the sceptic tradition to the extreme. Bayle was born in a Calvinist family in Carla-Bayle, and during the early stage of his life, he converted into Catholicism before returning to Calvinism. This conversion between religions caused him to leave France for the more religiously tolerant Holland where he stayed and worked for the rest of his life.[3]

Bayle believed that truth cannot be obtained through reason and that all human endeavor to acquire absolute knowledge would inevitably lead to failure. Bayle's main approach was highly skeptical and destructive: he sought to examine and analyze all existing theories in all fields of human knowledge in order to show the faults in their reasoning and thus the absurdity of the theories themselves. In his magnum opus, Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (Historical and Critical Dictionary), Bayle painstakingly identified the logical flaws in several works throughout the history in order to emphasize the absolute futility of rationality. Bayle's complete nullification of reason led him to conclude that faith is the final and only way to truth.[3][46][47]

Bayle's real intention behind his extremely destructive works remained controversial. Some described him to be a Fideist, while others speculated him to be a secret Atheist. However, no matter what his original intention was, Bayle did cast significant influence on the upcoming Age of Enlightenment with his destruction of some of the most essential theological ideas and his justification of religious tolerance Atheism in his works.[3][46][47]

Skepticism in the Age of Enlightenment

David Hume (1711–1776)

David Hume was among the most influential proponents of philosophical skepticism during the Age of Enlightenment and one of the most notable voices of the Scottish Enlightenment and British Empiricism.[48][49] He especially espoused skepticism regarding inductive reasoning, and questioned what the foundation of morality was, creating the is–ought problem. His approach to skepticism is considered even more radical than that of Descartes.[according to whom?]

Hume argued that any coherent idea must be either a mental copy of an impression (a direct sensory perception) or copies of multiple impressions innovatively combined. Since certain human activities like religion, superstition, and metaphysics are not premised on any actual sense-impressions, their claims to knowledge are logically unjustified. Furthermore, Hume even demonstrates that science is merely a psychological phenomenon based on the association of ideas: often, specifically, an assumption of cause-and-effect relationships that is itself not grounded in any sense-impressions. Thus, even scientific knowledge is logically unjustified, being not actually objective or provable but, rather, mere conjecture flimsily based on our minds perceiving regular correlations between distinct events. Hume thus falls into extreme skepticism regarding the possibility of any certain knowledge. Ultimately, he offers that, at best, a science of human nature is the "only solid foundation for the other sciences".[50]

Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)

 
Kant

Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) tried to provide a ground for empirical science against David Hume's skeptical treatment of the notion of cause and effect. Hume (1711–1776) argued that for the notion of cause and effect no analysis is possible which is also acceptable to the empiricist program primarily outlined by John Locke (1632–1704).[51] But, Kant's attempt to give a ground to knowledge in the empirical sciences at the same time cut off the possibility of knowledge of any other knowledge, especially what Kant called "metaphysical knowledge". So, for Kant, empirical science was legitimate, but metaphysics and philosophy was mostly illegitimate. The most important exception to this demarcation of the legitimate from the illegitimate was ethics, the principles of which Kant argued can be known by pure reason without appeal to the principles required for empirical knowledge. Thus, with respect to metaphysics and philosophy in general (ethics being the exception), Kant was a skeptic. This skepticism as well as the explicit skepticism of G. E. Schulze[52] gave rise to a robust discussion of skepticism in German idealistic philosophy, especially by Hegel.[53] Kant's idea was that the real world (the noumenon or thing-in-itself) was inaccessible to human reason (though the empirical world of nature can be known to human understanding) and therefore we can never know anything about the ultimate reality of the world. Hegel argued against Kant that although Kant was right that using what Hegel called "finite" concepts of "the understanding" precluded knowledge of reality, we were not constrained to use only "finite" concepts and could actually acquire knowledge of reality using "infinite concepts" that arise from self-consciousness.[54]

Skepticism in the 20th century and contemporary philosophy

G. E. Moore famously presented the "Here is one hand" argument against skepticism in his 1925 paper, "A Defence of Common Sense".[1] Moore claimed that he could prove that the external world exists by simply presenting the following argument while holding up his hands: "Here is one hand; here is another hand; therefore, there are at least two objects; therefore, external-world skepticism fails". His argument was developed for the purpose of vindicating common sense and refuting skepticism.[1] Ludwig Wittgenstein later argued in his On Certainty (posthumously published in 1969) that Moore's argument rested on the way that ordinary language is used, rather than on anything about knowledge.[55]

In contemporary philosophy, Richard Popkin was a particularly influential scholar on the topic of skepticism. His account of the history of skepticism given in The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle (first edition published as The History of Scepticism From Erasmus to Descartes) was accepted as the standard for contemporary scholarship in the area for decades after its release in 1960.[56] Barry Stroud also published a number of works on philosophical skepticism, most notably his 1984 monograph, The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism.[57] From the mid-1990s, Stroud, alongside Richard Fumerton, put forward influential anti-externalist arguments in favour of a position called "metaepistemological scepticism".[58] Other contemporary philosophers known for their work on skepticism include James Pryor, Keith DeRose, and Peter Klein.[1]

History of skepticism in non-Western philosophy

Ancient Indian skepticism

 
Indian skepticism towards dogmatic statements is illustrated by the famous tale of the Blind men and an elephant, common in Buddhism and Jainism.

Ajñana

Ajñana (literally 'non-knowledge') were the skeptical school of ancient Indian philosophy. It was a śramaṇa movement and a major rival of early Buddhism and Jainism. They have been recorded in Buddhist and Jain texts. They held that it was impossible to obtain knowledge of metaphysical nature or ascertain the truth value of philosophical propositions; and even if knowledge was possible, it was useless and disadvantageous for final salvation.

Buddhism

The historical Buddha asserted certain doctrines as true, such as the possibility of nirvana; however, he also upheld a form of skepticism with regards to certain questions which he left "un-expounded" (avyākata) and some he saw as "incomprehensible" (acinteyya). Because the Buddha saw these questions (which tend to be of metaphysical topics) as unhelpful on the path and merely leading to confusion and "a thicket of views", he promoted suspension of judgment towards them. This allowed him to carve out an epistemic middle way between what he saw as the extremes of claiming absolute objectivity (associated with the claims to omniscience of the Jain Mahavira) and extreme skepticism (associated with the Ajñana thinker Sanjaya Belatthiputta).[59]

Later Buddhist philosophy remained highly skeptical of Indian metaphysical arguments. The Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna in particular has been seen as the founder of the Madhyamaka school, which has been in turn compared with Greek Skepticism. Nagarjuna's statement that he has "no thesis" (pratijña) has parallels in the statements of Sextus Empiricus of having "no position".[60] Nagarjuna famously opens his magnum opus, the Mulamadhyamakakarika, with the statement that the Buddha claimed that true happiness was found through dispelling 'vain thinking' (prapañca, also "conceptual proliferation").[61]

According to Richard P. Hayes, the Buddhist philosopher Dignaga is also a kind of skeptic, which is in line with most early Buddhist philosophy. Hayes writes:

...in both early Buddhism and in the Skeptics one can find the view put forward that man's pursuit of happiness, the highest good, is obstructed by his tenacity in holding ungrounded and unnecessary opinions about all manner of things. Much of Buddhist philosophy, I shall argue, can be seen as an attempt to break this habit of holding on to opinions.[62]

Scholars like Adrian Kuzminski have argued that Pyrrho of Elis (ca. 365–270) might have been influenced by Indian Buddhists during his journey with Alexander the Great.[63]

Cārvāka philosophy

The Cārvāka (Sanskrit: चार्वाक) school of materialism, also known as Lokāyata, is a distinct branch of Indian philosophy. The school is named after Cārvāka, author of the Bārhaspatya-sūtras and was founded in approximately 500 BCE. Cārvāka is classified as a "heterodox" (nāstika) system, characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of thought. This school was also known for being strongly skeptical of the claims of Indian religions, such as reincarnation and karma.

Jainism

While Jain philosophy claims that is it possible to achieve omniscience, absolute knowledge (Kevala Jnana), at the moment of enlightenment, their theory of anekāntavāda or 'many sided-ness', also known as the principle of relative pluralism, allows for a practical form of skeptical thought regarding philosophical and religious doctrines (for un-enlightened beings, not all-knowing arihants).

According to this theory, the truth or the reality is perceived differently from different points of view, and that no single point of view is the complete truth.[64][65] Jain doctrine states that, an object has infinite modes of existence and qualities and, as such, they cannot be completely perceived in all its aspects and manifestations, due to inherent limitations of the humans. Anekāntavāda is literally the doctrine of non-onesidedness or manifoldness; it is often translated as "non-absolutism". Syādvāda is the theory of conditioned predication which provides an expression to anekānta by recommending that epithet “Syād” be attached to every expression.[66] Syādvāda is not only an extension of Anekānta ontology, but a separate system of logic capable of standing on its own force. As reality is complex, no single proposition can express the nature of reality fully. Thus the term “syāt” should be prefixed before each proposition giving it a conditional point of view and thus removing any dogmatism in the statement.[65] For Jains, fully enlightened beings are able to see reality from all sides and thus have ultimate knowledge of all things. This idea of omniscience was criticized by Buddhists such as Dharmakirti.

Ancient Chinese philosophy

 
A painting of Zhuangzi and his Butterfly Dream

Zhuang Zhou (c. 369 – c. 286 BCE)

Zhuang Zhou (莊子,"Master Zhuang") was a famous ancient Chinese Taoism philosopher during the Hundred Schools of Thought period. Zhuang Zhou demonstrated his skeptical thinking through several anecdotes in the preeminent work Zhuangzi attributed to him:

  • "The Debate on the Joy of Fish" (知魚之樂) : In this anecdote, Zhuang Zhou argued with his fellow philosopher Hui Shi whether they knew the fish in the pond were happy or not, and Zhuang Zhou made the famous observation that "You are not I. How do you know that I do not know that the fish are happy?" [67] (Autumn Floods 秋水篇, Zhuangzi)
  • "The Butterfly of the Dream"(周公夢蝶) : The paradox of "Butterfly Dream" described Zhuang Zhou's confusion after dreaming himself to be a butterfly: "But he didn't know if he was Zhuang Zhou who had dreamt he was a butterfly, or a butterfly dreaming that he was Zhuang Zhou."[67] (Discussion on Making All Things Equal 齊物篇, Zhuangzi)

Through these anecdotes in Zhuangzi, Zhuang Zhou indicated his belief in the limitation of language and human communication and the inaccessibility of universal truth. This establishes him as a skeptic. But he was by no means a radical skeptic: he only applied skeptical methods partially, in arguments demonstrating his Taoist beliefs. He held the Taoist beliefs themselves dogmatically.[68]

Wang Chong (27 – c. 100 CE)

Wang Chong (王充) was the leading figure of the skeptic branch of the Confucianism school in China during the first century CE. He introduced a method of rational critique and applied it to the widespread dogmatism thinking of his age like phenomenology (the main contemporary Confucianism ideology that linked all natural phenomena with human ethics), state-led cults, and popular superstition. His own philosophy incorporated both Taoism and Confucianism thinkings, and it was based on a secular, rational practice of developing hypotheses based on natural events to explain the universe which exemplified a form of naturalism that resembled the philosophical idea of Epicureans like Lucretius.[69][70]

Medieval Islamic philosophy

The Incoherence of the Philosophers, written by the scholar Al-Ghazali (1058–1111), marks a major turn in Islamic epistemology. His encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological occasionalism, or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of God.[citation needed]

In the autobiography Ghazali wrote towards the end of his life, The Deliverance From Error (Al-munqidh min al-ḍalāl [71]), Ghazali recounts how, once a crisis of epistemological skepticism was resolved by "a light which God Most High cast into my breast...the key to most knowledge,"[72] he studied and mastered the arguments of Kalam, Islamic philosophy, and Ismailism. Though appreciating what was valid in the first two of these, at least, he determined that all three approaches were inadequate and found ultimate value only in the mystical experience and spiritual insight he attained as a result of following Sufi practices. William James, in Varieties of Religious Experience, considered the autobiography an important document for "the purely literary student who would like to become acquainted with the inwardness of religions other than the Christian", comparing it to recorded personal religious confessions and autobiographical literature in the Christian tradition.[73]

Aztec philosophy

Recordings of Aztec philosophy suggest that the elite classes believed in an essentially panentheistic worldview, in which teotl represents a unified, underlying universal force. Human beings cannot truly perceive teotl due to its chaotic, constantly changing nature, just the "masks"/facets it is manifested as.[74][75]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b c d "Skepticism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved July 12, 2020.
  2. ^ "Certainty". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved July 12, 2020.
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i Popkin, Richard Henry (2003). The history of scepticism : from Savonarola to Bayle. Popkin, Richard Henry (Rev. and expanded ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0195355390. OCLC 65192690.
  4. ^ a b c d e Goldstick, D. (May 1, 1983). "Four Forms of Philosophical Scepticism". University of Toronto Quarterly. 52 (3): 235–240. doi:10.3138/utq.52.3.235. S2CID 170733016.
  5. ^ a b c Hansson, Sven Ove (September 2017). "The Uses and Misuses of Philosophical Scepticism: Editorial". Theoria. 83 (3): 169–174. doi:10.1111/theo.12123.
  6. ^ Olsson, Erik J. (2005). "Not Giving the Skeptic a Hearing: "Pragmatism and Radical Doubt"". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 70 (1): 98–126. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00507.x. ISSN 0031-8205. JSTOR 40040781.
  7. ^ a b Comesaña, Juan; Klein, Peter (2019). "Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved August 24, 2022.
  8. ^ a b c d e DeRose, Keith; Warfield, Ted A. (1999). "1. Introduction: Responding to Skepticism". Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511827-8.
  9. ^ a b c d e f g h Popkin, Richard H. "skepticism". www.britannica.com. Retrieved August 23, 2022.
  10. ^ a b c d Stroud, Barry; Stroud, Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry (July 5, 1984). "Preface". The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-824761-6.
  11. ^ Cohen, Stewart (1996). Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
  12. ^ a b Stroud, Barry; Stroud, Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry (July 5, 1984). "II Philosophical Scepticism and Everyday Life". The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-824761-6.
  13. ^ Hinton, J. M. (1989). "Scepticism: Philosophical and Everyday". Philosophy. 64 (248): 219–243. doi:10.1017/S0031819100044491. ISSN 0031-8191. JSTOR 3751409. S2CID 144250265.
  14. ^ a b c Greco, John (September 2, 2009). "Introduction". The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (1 ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 3–7. ISBN 978-0-19-518321-4.
  15. ^ a b c d Le Morvan, Pierre (2011). "Healthy Skepticism and Practical Wisdom". Logos & Episteme. 2 (1): 87–102. doi:10.5840/logos-episteme20112151.
  16. ^ Merton, R. K. (1942). "The Normative Structure of Science". in Merton, Robert King (1973). The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226520919.
  17. ^ Vogt, Katja (2021). "Ancient Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved August 30, 2022.
  18. ^ Reed, Baron (December 11, 2018). Skepticism as a Way of Life. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-39353-0.
  19. ^ Williams, Michael (2001). "Chapter 5: Agrippa's Trilemma". Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. Oxford University Press. p. 61. ISBN 978-0192892560.
  20. ^ a b "SKEPTICISM". Encyclopedia of Empiricism. 1997.
  21. ^ a b Bailey, Alan (1990). "Pyrrhonean Scepticism and the Self-Refutation Argument". The Philosophical Quarterly. 40 (158): 27–44. doi:10.2307/2219965. ISSN 0031-8094. JSTOR 2219965.
  22. ^ Kreeft p. 373
  23. ^ Baldwin, Tom (2010). "George Edward Moore: 6. Common Sense and Certainty". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved September 1, 2022.
  24. ^ Schulte, Günter (2007). "Gehirnfunktion Und Willensfreiheit. Schopenhauers Neurophilosophische Wende". Schopenhauer Jahrbuch. 88: 51–70.
  25. ^ Vogt, Katja (2019). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  26. ^ a b Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [UK]: Acumen. pp. 108–109. ISBN 978-1844654093. OCLC 715184861. Undecidability and the ten modes As part of his Pyrrhonian revival Aenesidemus assembled various kinds of skeptical arguments, or modes, designed to induce epoche.
  27. ^ Diogenes Laërtius 9:80–88
  28. ^ Eusebius. "Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV". Tertullian Project. Retrieved January 27, 2023.
  29. ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [UK]: Acumen. pp. 120–121. ISBN 978-1844654093. OCLC 715184861. Pyrrhonism, in whatever form it might have taken after Timon's death in 230 BCE, was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention
  30. ^ a b c Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [UK]: Acumen. pp. 102–103. ISBN 978-1844654093. OCLC 715184861. Aenesidemus criticized his fellow Academics for being dogmatic...Aenesidemus committed his scepticism to writing probably some time in the early-to-mid first century BCE...leading Aenesidemus to dismiss them as "Stoics fighting against Stoics."
  31. ^ Sextus, Empiricus (1990). Outlines of pyrrhonism. Robert Gregg Bury. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. ISBN 0879755970. OCLC 23367477. Those who believe they have discovered it are the "dogmatists," specially so called - Aristotle, for example, and Epicurus and the Stoics and certain others; Cleitomachus and Carneades and other Academics treat it as inapprehensible:the skeptics keep on searching. Hence it seems reasonable to hold the main types of philosophy are three - the dogmatic, the Academic, and the skeptic.
  32. ^ Plutarch, Sulla 12; cf. Appian, Roman History xii, 5.30 September 12, 2015, at the Wayback Machine
  33. ^ On the ten modes, see Sextus Empiricus. Outlines of Skepticism I.35–164.
  34. ^ Brochard, V., The Greek Skeptics.
  35. ^ a b Dutton, Blake D. (2016). Augustine and academic skepticism : a philosophical study. Ithaca. ISBN 978-1501703553. OCLC 951625897.
  36. ^ Hick, John (1970). Classical and contemporary readings in the philosophy of religion (2nd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. ISBN 978-0131352698. OCLC 90682.
  37. ^ Francisco Sanchez, That Nothing is Known, Cambridge University Press, 1989.
  38. ^ M., Clarke, Desmond (2016). French philosophy, 1572–1675 (First ed.). Oxford, United Kingdom. ISBN 978-0198749578. OCLC 923850410.
  39. ^ a b Maia Neto, José Raimundo; Paganini, Gianni; Laursen, John Christian, "Skepticism from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment: a Conference in Memory of Richard H. Popkin (1923–2005)" (2007 : Belo Horizonte, Brazil), eds. (2009). Skepticism in the modern age : building on the work of Richard Popkin. Leiden: Brill. ISBN 978-9047431909. OCLC 700517388.
  40. ^ Nadler, Steven M., ed. (2002). A companion to early modern philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell Pub. ISBN 978-0631218005. OCLC 49394201.
  41. ^ Chappell, Vere Claiborne, ed. (1992). Grotius to Gassendi. New York: Garland Pub. ISBN 978-0815305767. OCLC 24846343.
  42. ^ Missner, Marshall (1983). "Skepticism and Hobbes's Political Philosophy". Journal of the History of Ideas. 44 (3): 407–427. doi:10.2307/2709174. JSTOR 2709174.
  43. ^ Black, Sam (1997). "Science and Moral Skepticism in Hobbes". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 27 (2): 173–207. doi:10.1080/00455091.1997.10717477. JSTOR 40231980. S2CID 170567466.
  44. ^ Laursen, John Christian; Paganini, Gianni (2015). Skepticism and political thought in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Laursen, John Christian; Paganini, Gianni. Toronto. ISBN 978-1442649217. OCLC 904548214.
  45. ^ Batnitzky, Leora (December 2003). "Spinoza's Critique of Religious Authority: Spinoza's Critique of Miracles". Cardozo Law Review. 25: 57.
  46. ^ a b Matytsin, Anton M. (2016). The specter of skepticism in the age of Enlightenment. Baltimore. ISBN 978-1421420523. OCLC 960048885.
  47. ^ a b Lennon, Thomas M. (2002). "What Kind of a Skeptic Was Bayle?". Midwest Studies in Philosophy. 26–1: 258–279. doi:10.1111/1475-4975.261066.
  48. ^ Morris, William Edward, and Charlotte R. Brown. 2019 [2001]. "David Hume May 3, 1998, at the Wayback Machine." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved 10 August 2020.
  49. ^ Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 [1999] "David Hume June 21, 2015, at the Wayback Machine." Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 10 August 2020.
  50. ^ Hume, David. 1739. . London: John Noon. Retrieved 19 May 2020. p. 7.
  51. ^ David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739), Book I, "Of the Understanding" and David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748).
  52. ^ See G. E. Schulze, Aenesidemus (1792), excerpted in Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 2000. See also Frederick C. Beiser, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1987; Chapter 9, "Schulze's Skepticism".
  53. ^ See (1) H. S. Harris, "Skepticism, Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal" (1985), in Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 2000; (2) G. W. F. Hegel, "On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One", Translated by H. S. Harris, in di Giovanni and Harris (2000) (cited just above); and (3) Michael N. Forster, Hegel and Skepticism, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1989.
  54. ^ Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, The Encyclopedia Logic (1830), § 28, pp. 65–68, Translated by T. F. Garaets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 1991.
  55. ^ Jesús Padilla Gálvez, Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative, in: Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition, António Marques & Rui Bertrand Romao (Eds.), Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Wien: Peter Lang, 2020, pp. 113–122. ISBN 978-3034315951.
  56. ^ Sedley, David Louis (2005). Sublimity and skepticism in Montaigne and Milton. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. ISBN 978-0472115280. OCLC 60715259.
  57. ^ Stroud, Barry (1984). "The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism". Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198247613.001.0001. ISBN 978-0198247616. Retrieved August 11, 2020.
  58. ^ Pritchard, Duncan; Ranalli, Chris (2016). "On Metaepistemological Scepticism". In Bergmann, Michael; Coppenger, Brett (eds.). Intellectual Assurance: Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism. Oxford University Press.
  59. ^ Kalupahana, David J. A History of Buddhist Philosophy: Continuities and Discontinuities, page 21.
  60. ^ The Cowherds. Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2011, pp. 115–116.
  61. ^ Hayes, Richard P. Dignāga on the interpretation of signs, page 53.
  62. ^ Hayes, Richard P. Dignāga on the interpretation of signs, page 35.
  63. ^ Kuzminski, Adrian. Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism (Studies in Comparative Philosophy and Religion), 2008.
  64. ^ Dundas, Paul; John Hinnels ed. (2002). The Jains. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0415266062. {{cite book}}: |author2= has generic name (help)
  65. ^ a b Koller, John M. (July 2000). "Syādvāda as the epistemological key to the Jaina middle way metaphysics of Anekāntavāda". Philosophy East and West. 50 (3): 400–407. ISSN 0031-8221. JSTOR 1400182. ProQuest 216882163.
  66. ^ Chatterjea, Tara (2001). Knowledge and Freedom in Indian Philosophy. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. pp. 77–87. ISBN 978-0739106921.
  67. ^ a b Zhuangzi (2017) [2013]. The Complete works of Zhuangzi. Watson, Burton. New York. ISBN 978-0231164740. OCLC 826640070.
  68. ^ Berthel, Ken (December 1, 2015). "Language in Zhuangzi: A Theme that Reveals the Nature of its Relativism and Skepticism". Journal of Chinese Philosophy. 42: 562–576. doi:10.1111/1540-6253.12215. ISSN 1540-6253.
  69. ^ Xuerong, Ouyang (December 2003). "略论王充的怀疑主义". Journal of Kaifeng University. 17–04: 11–13.
  70. ^ Needham, Joseph (1978). The shorter Science and civilisation in China : an abridgement of Joseph Needham's original text. Ronan, Colin A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521235822. OCLC 3345021.
  71. ^ Annotated translations by Richard Joseph McCarthy (Freedom and Fulfillment, Boston: Twayne, 1980; Deliverance From Error, Louisville, Ky.: Fons Vitae, 1999) and George F. McLean (Deliverance from error and mystical union with the Almighty, Washington, D.C.: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy, 2001). An earlier translation by William Montgomery Watt was first published in 1953 (The faith and practice of al-Ghazālī, London: G. Allen and Unwin).
  72. ^ McCarthy 1980, p. 66
  73. ^ William James, Varieties of Religious Experience, Harvard University Press, 1985, p. 319 [= 2002 Modern Library Paperback Edition, p. 438].
  74. ^ James Maffie (2005). "Aztec Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  75. ^ James Maffie (2014). Aztec Philosophy: Understanding a World in Motion. University Press of Colorado[page needed][ISBN missing]

Further reading

  • Popkin, Richard H. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Popkin, Richard H. and J. R. Maia Neto, eds. 2007. Skepticism: An Anthology. New York: Prometheus Books.
  • Beiser, Frederick C. 1987. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Breker, Christian. 2011. Einführender Kommentar zu Sextus Empiricus' "Grundriss der pyrrhonischen Skepsis", Mainz, 2011: electr. publication, University of Mainz. available online (comment on Sextus Empiricus’ “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” in German language)
  • di Giovanni, George and H. S. Harris, eds. 2000. Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism. Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.
  • Forster, Michael N. 1989. Hegel and Skepticism. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
  • Harris, H. S. 1985. "Skepticism, Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal". In di Giovanni and Harris 2000.
  • Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel. 1802. "On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One". Translated by H. S. Harris. In di Giovanni and Harris 2000.
  • Leavitt, Fred. 2021. “If Ignorance is Bliss We Should All be Ecstatic.” Open Books.
  • Jesús Padilla Gálvez, Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative, in: Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition, António Marques & Rui Bertrand Romao (Eds.), Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Wien: Peter Lang, 2020, pp. 113–122.
  • François-Xavier de Peretti, « Stop Doubting with Descartes », dans M. Garcia-Valdecasas, J. Milburn, J.-B. Guillon (éds.), « Anti-skepticism », Topoi. An International Review of Philosophy, Springer Nature, on line 3.11.2022 [1]
  • François-Xavier de Peretti, « Descartes sceptique malgré lui ? », International Journal for the Study of Skepticism, 11 (3), 2021, Brill, Leyde, pp. 177-192. Online publication date: 15 octobre 2020. Doi:https://doi.org/10.1163/22105700-bja10016
  • Thorsrud, Harald. 2009. Ancient Scepticism. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Unger, Peter. 1975. Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. 2002.
  • Zeller, Eduard and Oswald J. Reichel. 1892. The Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.

External links

  • Klein, Peter. "Skepticism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Ancient Greek Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Renaissance Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Contemporary Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Responses to skepticism by Keith DeRose
  • Article: Skepticism and Denial by Stephen Novella MD, The New England Journal of Skepticism
  • Classical Skepticism by Peter Suber
  • Review and summary of Skepticism and the Veil of Perception by Michael Huemer
  • Sullivan, Margaret (December 5, 2019). "Wall-to-wall impeachment coverage is not changing any minds. Here's how journalists can reach the undecided". The Washington Post. Columnist Michelle Goldberg of the New York Times offered a name Wednesday for one aspect of what's happening before our eyes. Responding to the absurd statement of Rep. Douglas A. Collins (R-Ga.) — "there are no set facts here" — she said it summed up the long-term Republican strategy: "epistemological nihilism."

philosophical, skepticism, more, general, discussion, skepticism, skepticism, spelling, scepticism, from, greek, σκέψις, skepsis, inquiry, family, philosophical, views, that, question, possibility, knowledge, differs, from, other, forms, skepticism, that, even. For a more general discussion of skepticism see Skepticism Philosophical skepticism UK spelling scepticism from Greek skepsis skepsis inquiry is a family of philosophical views that question the possibility of knowledge 1 2 It differs from other forms of skepticism in that it even rejects very plausible knowledge claims that belong to basic common sense Philosophical skeptics are often classified into two general categories Those who deny all possibility of knowledge and those who advocate for the suspension of judgment due to the inadequacy of evidence 3 This distinction is modeled after the differences between the Academic skeptics and the Pyrrhonian skeptics in ancient Greek philosophy In the latter sense skepticism is understood as a way of life that helps the practitioner achieve inner peace Some types of philosophical skepticism reject all forms of knowledge while others limit this rejection to certain fields for example to knowledge about moral doctrines or about the external world Some theorists criticize philosophical skepticism based on the claim that it is a self refuting idea since its proponents seem to claim to know that there is no knowledge Other objections focus on its implausibility and distance from regular life Contents 1 Overview 1 1 Classification 1 2 Skeptical scenarios 1 3 Epistemological skepticism 1 4 Criticism 2 History of Western skepticism 2 1 Ancient Greek skepticism 2 1 1 Pyrrhonism 2 1 1 1 Pyrrho of Elis 2 1 1 2 Aenesidemus 2 1 1 3 Sextus Empiricus 2 1 1 4 Skeptical arguments 2 1 2 Academic skepticism 2 1 3 Augustine on skepticism 2 2 Skepticism s revival in the sixteenth century 2 2 1 Michel de Montaigne 1533 1592 2 2 2 Marin Mersenne 1588 1648 2 3 Skepticism in the seventeenth century 2 3 1 Thomas Hobbes 1588 1679 2 3 2 Baruch Spinoza and religious skepticism 2 3 3 Pierre Bayle 1647 1706 2 4 Skepticism in the Age of Enlightenment 2 4 1 David Hume 1711 1776 2 4 2 Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 2 5 Skepticism in the 20th century and contemporary philosophy 3 History of skepticism in non Western philosophy 3 1 Ancient Indian skepticism 3 1 1 Ajnana 3 1 2 Buddhism 3 1 3 Carvaka philosophy 3 1 4 Jainism 3 2 Ancient Chinese philosophy 3 2 1 Zhuang Zhou c 369 c 286 BCE 3 2 2 Wang Chong 27 c 100 CE 3 3 Medieval Islamic philosophy 3 4 Aztec philosophy 4 See also 5 References 6 Further reading 7 External linksOverview EditThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed July 2020 Learn how and when to remove this template message Philosophical skepticism is a doubtful attitude toward commonly accepted knowledge claims It is an important form of skepticism Skepticism in general is a questioning attitude toward all kinds of knowledge claims In this wide sense it is quite common in everyday life many people are ordinary skeptics about parapsychology or about astrology because they doubt the claims made by proponents of these fields 4 But the same people are not skeptical about other knowledge claims like the ones found in regular school books Philosophical skepticism differs from ordinary skepticism in that it even rejects knowledge claims that belong to basic common sense and seem to be very certain 4 For this reason it is sometimes referred to as radical doubt 5 In some cases it is even proclaimed that one does not know that I have two hands or that the sun will come out tomorrow 6 7 In this regard philosophical skepticism is not a position commonly adopted by regular people in everyday life 8 9 This denial of knowledge is usually associated with the demand that one should suspend one s beliefs about the doubted proposition This means that one should neither believe nor disbelieve it but keep an open mind without committing oneself one way or the other 10 Philosophical skepticism is often based on the idea that no matter how certain one is about a given belief one could still be wrong about it 11 7 From this observation it is argued that the belief does not amount to knowledge Philosophical skepticism follows from the consideration that this might be the case for most or all beliefs 12 Because of its wide ranging consequences it is of central interest to theories of knowledge since it questions their very foundations 10 According to some definitions philosophical skepticism is not just the rejection of some forms of commonly accepted knowledge but the rejection of all forms of knowledge 4 10 13 In this regard we may have relatively secure beliefs in some cases but these beliefs never amount to knowledge Weaker forms of philosophical skepticism restrict this rejection to specific fields like the external world or moral doctrines In some cases knowledge per se is not rejected but it is still denied that one can ever be absolutely certain 9 14 There are only few defenders of philosophical skepticism in the strong sense 4 In this regard it is much more commonly used as a theoretical tool to test theories 5 4 12 15 On this view it is a philosophical methodology that can be utilized to probe a theory to find its weak points either to expose it or to modify it in order to arrive at a better version of it 5 However some theorists distinguish philosophical skepticism from methodological skepticism in that philosophical skepticism is an approach that questions the possibility of certainty in knowledge whereas methodological skepticism is an approach that subjects all knowledge claims to scrutiny with the goal of sorting out true from false claims citation needed Similarly scientific skepticism differs from philosophical skepticism in that scientific skepticism is an epistemological position in which one questions the veracity of claims lacking empirical evidence In practice the term most commonly references the examination of claims and theories that appear to be pseudoscience rather than the routine discussions and challenges among scientists 16 In ancient philosophy skepticism was seen not just as a theory about the existence of knowledge but as a way of life This outlook is motivated by the idea that suspending one s judgment on all kinds of issues brings with it inner peace and thereby contributes to the skeptic s happiness 14 17 18 Classification Edit Skepticism can be classified according to its scope Local skepticism involves being skeptical about particular areas of knowledge e g moral skepticism skepticism about the external world or skepticism about other minds whereas radical skepticism claims that one cannot know anything including that one cannot know about knowing anything Skepticism can also be classified according to its method Western philosophy has two basic approaches to skepticism 19 Cartesian skepticism named somewhat misleadingly after Rene Descartes who was not a skeptic but used some traditional skeptical arguments in his Meditations to help establish his rationalist approach to knowledge attempts to show that any proposed knowledge claim can be doubted Agrippan skepticism focuses on justification rather than the possibility of doubt According to this view none of the ways in which one might attempt to justify a claim are adequate One can justify a claim based on other claims but this leads to an infinite regress of justifications One can use a dogmatic assertion but this is not a justification One can use circular reasoning but this fails to justify the conclusion Skeptical scenarios Edit A skeptical scenario is a hypothetical situation which can be used in an argument for skepticism about a particular claim or class of claims Usually the scenario posits the existence of a deceptive power that deceives our senses and undermines the justification of knowledge otherwise accepted as justified and is proposed in order to call into question our ordinary claims to knowledge on the grounds that we cannot exclude the possibility of skeptical scenarios being true Skeptical scenarios have received a great deal of attention in modern Western philosophy The first major skeptical scenario in modern Western philosophy appears in Rene Descartes Meditations on First Philosophy At the end of the first Meditation Descartes writes I will suppose that some evil demon of the utmost power and cunning has employed all his energies to deceive me The evil demon problem also known as Descartes evil demon was first proposed by Rene Descartes It invokes the possibility of a being who could deliberately mislead one into falsely believing everything that you take to be true The brain in a vat hypothesis is cast in contemporary scientific terms It supposes that one might be a disembodied brain kept alive in a vat and fed false sensory signals by a mad scientist Further it asserts that since a brain in a vat would have no way of knowing that it was a brain in a vat you cannot prove that you are not a brain in a vat The dream argument proposed by both Rene Descartes and Zhuangzi supposes reality to be indistinguishable from a dream The five minute hypothesis most notably proposed by Bertrand Russell suggests that we cannot prove that the world was not created five minutes ago along with false memories and false evidence suggesting that it was not only five minutes old The simulated reality hypothesis or Matrix hypothesis suggests that everyone or even the entire universe might be inside a computer simulation or virtual reality The Solipsistic theory that claims that knowledge of the world is an illusion of the Self Epistemological skepticism Edit Skepticism as an epistemological view calls into question whether knowledge is possible at all This is distinct from other known skeptical practices including Cartesian skepticism as it targets knowledge in general instead of individual types of knowledge Skeptics argue that belief in something does not justify an assertion of knowledge of it In this skeptics oppose foundationalism which states that there are basic positions that are self justified or beyond justification without reference to others One example of such foundationalism may be found in Spinoza s Ethics The skeptical response to this can take several approaches First claiming that basic positions must exist amounts to the logical fallacy of argument from ignorance combined with the slippery slope citation needed Among other arguments skeptics use the Munchhausen trilemma and the problem of the criterion to claim that no certain belief can be achieved This position is known as global skepticism or radical skepticism Foundationalists have used the same trilemma as a justification for demanding the validity of basic beliefs citation needed Epistemological nihilism rejects the possibility of human knowledge but not necessarily knowledge in general There are two different categories of epistemological skepticism which can be referred to as mitigated and unmitigated skepticism The two forms are contrasting but are still true forms of skepticism Mitigated skepticism does not accept strong or strict knowledge claims but does however approve specific weaker ones These weaker claims can be assigned the title of virtual knowledge but must be to justified belief Some mitigated skeptics are also fallibilists arguing that knowledge does not require certainty Mitigated skeptics hold that knowledge does not require certainty and that many beliefs are in practice certain to the point that they can be safely acted upon in order to live significant and meaningful lives Unmitigated skepticism rejects both claims of virtual knowledge and strong knowledge 20 Characterising knowledge as strong weak virtual or genuine can be determined differently depending on a person s viewpoint as well as their characterisation of knowledge Unmitigated skeptics believe that objective truths are unknowable and that man should live in an isolated environment in order to win mental peace This is because everything according to them is changing and relative The refusal to make judgments is of uttermost importance since there is no knowledge only probable opinions 20 Criticism Edit Philosophical skepticism has been criticized in various ways Some criticisms see it as a self refuting idea while others point out that it is implausible psychologically impossible or a pointless intellectual game One of the strongest criticisms claims that philosophical skepticism is contradictory or self refuting This position is based on the idea that it not only rejects the existence of knowledge but seems to make knowledge claims itself at the same time 9 21 22 For example to claim that there is no knowledge seems to be itself a knowledge claim This problem is particularly relevant for versions of philosophical skepticism that deny any form of knowledge So the global skeptic denies that any claim is rationally justified but then goes on to provide arguments in an attempt to rationally justify their denial 21 Some philosophical skeptics have responded to this objection by restricting the denial of knowledge to certain fields without denying the existence of knowledge in general Another defense consists in understanding philosophical skepticism not as a theory but as a tool or a methodology In this case it may be used fruitfully to reject and improve philosophical systems despite its shortcomings as a theory 9 15 Another criticism holds that philosophical skepticism is highly counterintuitive by pointing out how far removed it is from regular life 8 9 For example it seems very impractical if not psychologically impossible to suspend all beliefs at the same time And even if it was possible it would not be advisable since the complete skeptic would wind up starving to death or walking into walls or out of windows 9 This criticism can allow that there are some arguments that support philosophical skepticism However it has been claimed that they are not nearly strong enough to support such a radical conclusion 8 Common sense philosophers follow this line of thought by arguing that regular common sense beliefs are much more reliable than the skeptics intricate arguments 8 George Edward Moore for example tried to refute skepticism about the existence of the external world not by engaging with its complex arguments but by using a simple observation that he has two hands For Moore this observation is a reliable source of knowledge incompatible with external world skepticism since it entails that at least two physical objects exist 23 8 A closely related objection sees philosophical skepticism as an idle academic exercise or a waste of time 10 This is often based on the idea that because of its initial implausibility and distance from everyday life it has little or no practical value 9 15 In this regard Arthur Schopenhauer compares the position of radical skepticism to a border fortress that is best ignored it is impregnable but its garrison does not pose any threat since it never sets foot outside the fortress 24 One defense of philosophical skepticism is that it has had important impacts on the history of philosophy at large and not just among skeptical philosophers This is due to its critical attitude which remains a constant challenge to the epistemic foundations of various philosophical theories It has often provoked creative responses from other philosophers when trying to modify the affected theory to avoid the problem of skepticism 9 14 According to Pierre Le Morvan there are two very common negative responses to philosophical skepticism The first understands it as a threat to all kinds of philosophical theories and strives to disprove it According to the second philosophical skepticism is a useless distraction and should better be avoided altogether Le Morvan himself proposes a positive third alternative to use it as a philosophical tool in a few selected cases to overcome prejudices and foster practical wisdom 15 History of Western skepticism Edit Skeptics in Raphael s School of Athens painting 1 Pythodorus 2 Arcesilaus of Pitane 3 Carneades of Cyrene 4 Pyrrho of Elis 5 Timon of Phlius 6 Theodorus the Atheist of Cyrene Ancient Greek skepticism Edit Pyrrho of Elis marble head Roman copy Archeological Museum of CorfuAncient Greek skeptics were not skeptics in the contemporary sense of selective localized doubt Their concerns were epistemological noting that truth claims could not be adequately supported and psychotherapeutic noting that beliefs caused mental perturbation The Western tradition of systematic skepticism goes back at least as far as Pyrrho of Elis b c 360 BCE and arguably to Xenophanes b c 570 BCE Parts of skepticism also appear among the 5th century sophists who develop forms of debate which are ancestors of skeptical argumentation They take pride in arguing in a persuasive fashion for both sides of an issue 25 In Hellenistic philosophy Pyrrhonism and Academic Skepticism were the two schools of skeptical philosophy Subsequently the words Academic and Pyrrhonist were often be used to mean skeptic Pyrrhonism Edit Main article Pyrrhonism Like other Hellenistic philosophies the goal of Pyrrhonism was eudaimonia which the Pyrrhonists sought through achieving ataraxia an untroubled state of mind which they found could be induced by producing a state of epoche suspension of judgment regarding non evident matters Epoche could be produced by pitting one dogma against another to undermine belief and by questioning whether a belief could be justified In support of this questioning Pyrrhonists developed the skeptical arguments cited above the Ten Modes of Aenesidemus and the Five Modes of Agrippa 26 demonstrating that beliefs cannot be justified 27 Pyrrho of Elis Edit Main article Pyrrho According to an account of Pyrrho s life by his student Timon of Phlius Pyrrho extolled a way to become happy and tranquil The things themselves are equally indifferent and unstable and indeterminate and therefore neither our senses nor our opinions are either true or false For this reason then we must not trust them but be without opinions and without bias and without wavering saying of every single thing that it no more is than is not or both is and is not or neither is nor is not 28 Aenesidemus Edit Main article Aenesidemus Pyrrhonism faded as a movement following the death of Pyrrho s student Timon 29 The Academy became slowly more dogmatic 30 such that in the first century BCE Aenesidemus denounced the Academics as Stoics fighting against Stoics breaking with the Academy to revive Pyrrhonism 30 Aenesidemus s best known contribution to skepticism was his now lost book Pyrrhonian Discourses which is only known to us through Photius Sextus Empiricus and to a lesser extent Diogenes Laertius The skeptical arguments most closely associated with Aenesidemus are the ten modes described above designed to induce epoche 26 Sextus Empiricus Edit Sextus Empiricus Main article Sextus Empiricus The works of Sextus Empiricus c 200 CE are the main surviving account of ancient Pyrrhonism Long before Sextus time the Academy had abandoned skepticism and had been destroyed as a formal institution 30 31 32 Sextus compiled and further developed the Pyrrhonists skeptical arguments most of which were directed against the Stoics but included arguments against all of the schools of Hellenistic philosophy including the Academic skeptics Sextus as the most systematic author of the works by Hellenistic skeptics which have survived noted that there are at least ten modes of skepticism These modes may be broken down into three categories one may be skeptical of the subjective perceiver of the objective world and the relation between perceiver and the world 33 His arguments are as follows Subjectively both the powers of the senses and of reasoning may vary among different people And since knowledge is a product of one or the other and since neither are reliable knowledge would seem to be in trouble For instance a color blind person sees the world quite differently from everyone else Moreover one cannot even give preference on the basis of the power of reason i e by treating the rational animal as a carrier of greater knowledge than the irrational animal since the irrational animal is still adept at navigating their environment which suggests the ability to know about some aspects of the environment Secondly the personality of the individual might also influence what they observe since it is argued preferences are based on sense impressions differences in preferences can be attributed to differences in the way that people are affected by the object Empiricus 56 Third the perceptions of each individual sense seemingly have nothing in common with the other senses i e the color red has little to do with the feeling of touching a red object This is manifest when our senses disagree with each other for example a mirage presents certain visible features but is not responsive to any other kind of sense In that case our other senses defeat the impressions of sight But one may also be lacking enough powers of sense to understand the world in its entirety if one had an extra sense then one might know of things in a way that the present five senses are unable to advise us of Given that our senses can be shown to be unreliable by appealing to other senses and so our senses may be incomplete relative to some more perfect sense that one lacks then it follows that all of our senses may be unreliable Empiricus 58 Fourth our circumstances when one perceives anything may be either natural or unnatural i e one may be either in a state of wakefulness or sleep But it is entirely possible that things in the world really are exactly as they appear to be to those in unnatural states i e if everything were an elaborate dream Empiricus 59 One can have reasons for doubt that are based on the relationship between objective facts and subjective experience The positions distances and places of objects would seem to affect how they are perceived by the person for instance the portico may appear tapered when viewed from one end but symmetrical when viewed at the other and these features are different Because they are different features to believe the object has both properties at the same time is to believe it has two contradictory properties Since this is absurd one must suspend judgment about what properties it possesses due to the contradictory experiences Empiricus 63 One may also observe that the things one perceives are in a sense polluted by experience Any given perception say of a chair will always be perceived within some context or other i e next to a table on a mat etc Since this is the case one often only speaks of ideas as they occur in the context of the other things that are paired with it and therefore one can never know of the true nature of the thing but only how it appears to us in context Empiricus 64 Along the same lines the skeptic may insist that all things are relative by arguing that Absolute appearances either differ from relative appearances or they do not If absolutes do not differ from relatives then they are themselves relative But if absolutes do differ from relatives then they are relative because all things that differ must differ from something and to differ from something is to be relative to something Empiricus 67 Finally one has reason to disbelieve that one knows anything by looking at problems in understanding objects by themselves Things when taken individually may appear to be very different from when they are in mass quantities for instance the shavings of a goat s horn are white when taken alone yet the horn intact is black citation needed Skeptical arguments Edit The ancient Greek Pyrrhonists developed sets of arguments to demonstrate that claims about reality cannot be adequately justified Two sets of these arguments are well known The oldest set is known as the ten tropes of Aenesidemus although whether he invented the tropes or just systematized them from prior Pyrrhonist works is unknown The tropes represent reasons for epoche suspension of judgment These are as follows Different animals manifest different modes of perception Similar differences are seen among individual men For the same man information perceived with the senses is self contradictory Furthermore it varies from time to time with physical changes In addition this data differs according to local relations Objects are known only indirectly through the medium of air moisture etc These objects are in a condition of perpetual change in color temperature size and motion All perceptions are relative and interact one upon another Our impressions become less critical through repetition and custom All men are brought up with different beliefs under different laws and social conditionsAnother set are known as the five tropes of Agrippa Dissent The uncertainty demonstrated by the differences of opinions among philosophers and people in general Progress ad infinitum All proof rests on matters themselves in need of proof and so on to infinity i e the regress argument Relation All things are changed as their relations become changed or as we look upon them from different points of view Assumption The truth asserted is based on an unsupported assumption Circularity The truth asserted involves a circularity of proofs According to Victor Brochard the five tropes can be regarded as the most radical and most precise formulation of philosophical skepticism that has ever been given In a sense they are still irresistible today 34 Academic skepticism Edit Main article Academic skepticism Pyrrho s thinking subsequently influenced the Platonic Academy arising first in the Academic skepticism of the Middle Academy under Arcesilaus c 315 241 BCE and then the New Academy under Carneades c 213 129 BCE Clitomachus a student of Carneades interpreted his teacher s philosophy as suggesting an account of knowledge based on truth likeness The Roman politician and philosopher Cicero was also an adherent of the skepticism of the New Academy even though a return to a more dogmatic orientation of the school was already beginning to take place Augustine on skepticism Edit Augustine of Hippo In 386 CE Augustine published Contra Academicos Against the Academic Skeptics which argued against claims made by the Academic Skeptics 266 90 BCE on the following grounds Objection from Error Through logic Augustine argues that philosophical skepticism does not lead to happiness like the Academic Skeptics claim His arguments is summarized as A wise man lives according to reason and thus is able to be happy One who is searching for knowledge but never finds it is in error Imperfection objection People in error are not happy because being in error is an imperfection and people cannot be happy with an imperfection Conclusion One who is still seeking knowledge cannot be happy 35 36 Error of Non Assent Augustine s argument that suspending belief does not fully prevent one from error His argument is summarized below Introduction of the error Let P be true If a person fails to believe P due to suspension of belief in order to avoid error the person is also committing an error The Anecdote of the Two Travelers Travelers A and B are trying to reach the same destination At a fork in the road a poor shepherd tells them to go left Traveler A immediately believes him and reaches the correct destination Traveler B suspends belief and instead believes in the advice of a well dressed townsman to go right because his advice seems more persuasive However the townsman is actually a samardocus con man so Traveler B never reaches the correct destination The Anecdote of the Adulterer A man suspends belief that adultery is bad and commits adultery with another man s wife because it is persuasive to him Under Academic Skepticism this man cannot be charged because he acted on what was persuasive to him without assenting belief Conclusion Suspending belief exposes individuals to an error as defined by the Academic Skeptics 35 Skepticism s revival in the sixteenth century Edit Francisco Sanches s That Nothing is Known published in 1581 as Quod nihil scitur is one of the crucial texts of Renaissance skepticism 37 Michel de Montaigne 1533 1592 Edit Michel de Montaigne The most notable figure of the Skepticism revival in the 1500s Michel de Montaigne wrote about his studies of Academic Skepticism and Pyrrhonism through his Essais His most notable writings on skepticism occurred in an essay written mostly in 1575 1576 Apologie de Raimond Sebond when he was reading Sextus Empiricus and trying to translate Raimond Sebond s writing including his proof of Christianity s natural existence The reception to Montaigne s translations included some criticisms of Sebond s proof Montaigne responded to some of them in Apologie including a defense for Sebond s logic that is skeptical in nature and similar to Pyrrhonism 38 39 His refutation is as follows Critics claiming Sebond s arguments are weak show how egoistic humans believe that their logic is superior to others Many animals can be observed to be superior to humans in certain respects To argue this point Montaigne even writes about dogs who are logical and creates their own syllogisms to understand the world around them This was an example used in Sextus Empiricus Since animals also have rationality the over glorification of man s mental capabilities is a trap man s folly One man s reason cannot be assuredly better than another s as a result Ignorance is even recommended by religion so that an individual can reach faith through obediently following divine instructions to learn not by one s logic 3 Marin Mersenne 1588 1648 Edit Marin Mersenne Marin Mersenne was an author mathematician scientist and philosopher He wrote in defense of science and Christianity against atheists and Pyrrhonists before retiring to encourage development of science and the new philosophy which includes philosophers like Gassendi Descartes Galileo and Hobbes A major work of his in relation to Skepticism is La Verite des Sciences in which he argues that although we may not be able to know the true nature of things we can still formulate certain laws and rules for sense perceptions through science 3 39 40 Additionally he points out that we do not doubt everything because Humans do agree about some things for example an ant is smaller than an elephant There are natural laws governing our sense perceptions such as optics which allow us to eliminate inaccuracies Man created tools such as rulers and scales to measure things and eliminate doubts such as bent oars pigeons necks and round towers A Pyrrhonist might refute these points by saying that senses deceive and thus knowledge turns into infinite regress or circular logic Thus Mersenne argues that this cannot be the case since commonly agreed upon rules of thumb can be hypothesized and tested over time to ensure that they continue to hold 41 Furthermore if everything can be doubted the doubt can also be doubted so on and so forth Thus according to Mersenne something has to be true Finally Mersenne writes about all the mathematical physical and other scientific knowledge that is true by repeated testing and has practical use value Notably Mersenne was one of the few philosophers who accepted Hobbes radical ideology he saw it as a new science of man 3 Skepticism in the seventeenth century Edit Thomas Hobbes Thomas Hobbes 1588 1679 EditDuring his long stay in Paris Thomas Hobbes was actively involved in the circle of major skeptics like Gassendi and Mersenne who focus on the study of skepticism and epistemology Unlike his fellow skeptic friends Hobbes never treated skepticism as a main topic for discussion in his works Nonetheless Hobbes was still labeled as a religious skeptic by his contemporaries for raising doubts about Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch and his political and psychological explanation of the religions Although Hobbes himself did not go further to challenge other religious principles his suspicion for the Mosaic authorship did significant damage to the religious traditions and paved the way for later religious skeptics like Spinoza and Isaac La Peyrere to further question some of the fundamental beliefs of the Judeo Christian religious system Hobbes answer to skepticism and epistemology was innovatively political he believed that moral knowledge and religious knowledge were in their nature relative and there was no absolute standard of truth governing them As a result it was out of political reasons that certain truth standards about religions and ethics were devised and established in order to form a functioning government and stable society 3 42 43 44 Baruch Spinoza Baruch Spinoza and religious skepticism Edit Baruch Spinoza was among the first European philosophers who were religious skeptics He was quite familiar with the philosophy of Descartes and unprecedentedly extended the application of the Cartesian method to the religious context by analyzing religious texts with it Spinoza sought to dispute the knowledge claims of the Judeo Christian Islamic religious system by examining its two foundations the Scripture and the Miracles He claimed that all Cartesian knowledge or the rational knowledge should be accessible to the entire population Therefore the Scriptures aside from those by Jesus should not be considered the secret knowledge attained from God but just the imagination of the prophets The Scriptures as a result of this claim could not serve as a base for knowledge and were reduced to simple ancient historical texts Moreover Spinoza also rejected the possibility for the Miracles by simply asserting that people only considered them miraculous due to their lack of understanding of the nature By rejecting the validity of the Scriptures and the Miracles Spinoza demolished the foundation for religious knowledge claim and established his understanding of the Cartesian knowledge as the sole authority of knowledge claims Despite being deeply skeptical of the religions Spinoza was in fact exceedingly anti skeptical towards reason and rationality He steadfastly confirmed the legitimacy of reason by associating it with the acknowledgement of God and thereby skepticism with the rational approach to knowledge was not due to problems with the rational knowledge but from the fundamental lack of understanding of God Spinoza s religious skepticism and anti skepticism with reason thus helped him transform epistemology by separating the theological knowledge claims and the rational knowledge claims 3 45 Pierre Bayle 1647 1706 Edit Pierre Bayle by Louis Ferdinand Elle Pierre Bayle was a French philosopher in the late 17th century that was described by Richard Popkin to be a supersceptic who carried out the sceptic tradition to the extreme Bayle was born in a Calvinist family in Carla Bayle and during the early stage of his life he converted into Catholicism before returning to Calvinism This conversion between religions caused him to leave France for the more religiously tolerant Holland where he stayed and worked for the rest of his life 3 Bayle believed that truth cannot be obtained through reason and that all human endeavor to acquire absolute knowledge would inevitably lead to failure Bayle s main approach was highly skeptical and destructive he sought to examine and analyze all existing theories in all fields of human knowledge in order to show the faults in their reasoning and thus the absurdity of the theories themselves In his magnum opus Dictionnaire Historique et Critique Historical and Critical Dictionary Bayle painstakingly identified the logical flaws in several works throughout the history in order to emphasize the absolute futility of rationality Bayle s complete nullification of reason led him to conclude that faith is the final and only way to truth 3 46 47 Bayle s real intention behind his extremely destructive works remained controversial Some described him to be a Fideist while others speculated him to be a secret Atheist However no matter what his original intention was Bayle did cast significant influence on the upcoming Age of Enlightenment with his destruction of some of the most essential theological ideas and his justification of religious tolerance Atheism in his works 3 46 47 Skepticism in the Age of Enlightenment Edit David Hume 1711 1776 Edit David Hume was among the most influential proponents of philosophical skepticism during the Age of Enlightenment and one of the most notable voices of the Scottish Enlightenment and British Empiricism 48 49 He especially espoused skepticism regarding inductive reasoning and questioned what the foundation of morality was creating the is ought problem His approach to skepticism is considered even more radical than that of Descartes according to whom Hume argued that any coherent idea must be either a mental copy of an impression a direct sensory perception or copies of multiple impressions innovatively combined Since certain human activities like religion superstition and metaphysics are not premised on any actual sense impressions their claims to knowledge are logically unjustified Furthermore Hume even demonstrates that science is merely a psychological phenomenon based on the association of ideas often specifically an assumption of cause and effect relationships that is itself not grounded in any sense impressions Thus even scientific knowledge is logically unjustified being not actually objective or provable but rather mere conjecture flimsily based on our minds perceiving regular correlations between distinct events Hume thus falls into extreme skepticism regarding the possibility of any certain knowledge Ultimately he offers that at best a science of human nature is the only solid foundation for the other sciences 50 Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 Edit This article may need to be rewritten to comply with Wikipedia s quality standards You can help The talk page may contain suggestions August 2020 Kant Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 tried to provide a ground for empirical science against David Hume s skeptical treatment of the notion of cause and effect Hume 1711 1776 argued that for the notion of cause and effect no analysis is possible which is also acceptable to the empiricist program primarily outlined by John Locke 1632 1704 51 But Kant s attempt to give a ground to knowledge in the empirical sciences at the same time cut off the possibility of knowledge of any other knowledge especially what Kant called metaphysical knowledge So for Kant empirical science was legitimate but metaphysics and philosophy was mostly illegitimate The most important exception to this demarcation of the legitimate from the illegitimate was ethics the principles of which Kant argued can be known by pure reason without appeal to the principles required for empirical knowledge Thus with respect to metaphysics and philosophy in general ethics being the exception Kant was a skeptic This skepticism as well as the explicit skepticism of G E Schulze 52 gave rise to a robust discussion of skepticism in German idealistic philosophy especially by Hegel 53 Kant s idea was that the real world the noumenon or thing in itself was inaccessible to human reason though the empirical world of nature can be known to human understanding and therefore we can never know anything about the ultimate reality of the world Hegel argued against Kant that although Kant was right that using what Hegel called finite concepts of the understanding precluded knowledge of reality we were not constrained to use only finite concepts and could actually acquire knowledge of reality using infinite concepts that arise from self consciousness 54 Skepticism in the 20th century and contemporary philosophy Edit G E Moore famously presented the Here is one hand argument against skepticism in his 1925 paper A Defence of Common Sense 1 Moore claimed that he could prove that the external world exists by simply presenting the following argument while holding up his hands Here is one hand here is another hand therefore there are at least two objects therefore external world skepticism fails His argument was developed for the purpose of vindicating common sense and refuting skepticism 1 Ludwig Wittgenstein later argued in his On Certainty posthumously published in 1969 that Moore s argument rested on the way that ordinary language is used rather than on anything about knowledge 55 In contemporary philosophy Richard Popkin was a particularly influential scholar on the topic of skepticism His account of the history of skepticism given in The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle first edition published as The History of Scepticism From Erasmus to Descartes was accepted as the standard for contemporary scholarship in the area for decades after its release in 1960 56 Barry Stroud also published a number of works on philosophical skepticism most notably his 1984 monograph The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism 57 From the mid 1990s Stroud alongside Richard Fumerton put forward influential anti externalist arguments in favour of a position called metaepistemological scepticism 58 Other contemporary philosophers known for their work on skepticism include James Pryor Keith DeRose and Peter Klein 1 History of skepticism in non Western philosophy EditAncient Indian skepticism Edit Indian skepticism towards dogmatic statements is illustrated by the famous tale of the Blind men and an elephant common in Buddhism and Jainism Ajnana Edit Main article Ajnana Ajnana literally non knowledge were the skeptical school of ancient Indian philosophy It was a sramaṇa movement and a major rival of early Buddhism and Jainism They have been recorded in Buddhist and Jain texts They held that it was impossible to obtain knowledge of metaphysical nature or ascertain the truth value of philosophical propositions and even if knowledge was possible it was useless and disadvantageous for final salvation Buddhism Edit Main article Buddhist philosophy The historical Buddha asserted certain doctrines as true such as the possibility of nirvana however he also upheld a form of skepticism with regards to certain questions which he left un expounded avyakata and some he saw as incomprehensible acinteyya Because the Buddha saw these questions which tend to be of metaphysical topics as unhelpful on the path and merely leading to confusion and a thicket of views he promoted suspension of judgment towards them This allowed him to carve out an epistemic middle way between what he saw as the extremes of claiming absolute objectivity associated with the claims to omniscience of the Jain Mahavira and extreme skepticism associated with the Ajnana thinker Sanjaya Belatthiputta 59 Later Buddhist philosophy remained highly skeptical of Indian metaphysical arguments The Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna in particular has been seen as the founder of the Madhyamaka school which has been in turn compared with Greek Skepticism Nagarjuna s statement that he has no thesis pratijna has parallels in the statements of Sextus Empiricus of having no position 60 Nagarjuna famously opens his magnum opus the Mulamadhyamakakarika with the statement that the Buddha claimed that true happiness was found through dispelling vain thinking prapanca also conceptual proliferation 61 According to Richard P Hayes the Buddhist philosopher Dignaga is also a kind of skeptic which is in line with most early Buddhist philosophy Hayes writes in both early Buddhism and in the Skeptics one can find the view put forward that man s pursuit of happiness the highest good is obstructed by his tenacity in holding ungrounded and unnecessary opinions about all manner of things Much of Buddhist philosophy I shall argue can be seen as an attempt to break this habit of holding on to opinions 62 Scholars like Adrian Kuzminski have argued that Pyrrho of Elis ca 365 270 might have been influenced by Indian Buddhists during his journey with Alexander the Great 63 Carvaka philosophy Edit Main article Carvaka The Carvaka Sanskrit च र व क school of materialism also known as Lokayata is a distinct branch of Indian philosophy The school is named after Carvaka author of the Barhaspatya sutras and was founded in approximately 500 BCE Carvaka is classified as a heterodox nastika system characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of thought This school was also known for being strongly skeptical of the claims of Indian religions such as reincarnation and karma Jainism Edit Main articles Anekantavada and Syadvada While Jain philosophy claims that is it possible to achieve omniscience absolute knowledge Kevala Jnana at the moment of enlightenment their theory of anekantavada or many sided ness also known as the principle of relative pluralism allows for a practical form of skeptical thought regarding philosophical and religious doctrines for un enlightened beings not all knowing arihants According to this theory the truth or the reality is perceived differently from different points of view and that no single point of view is the complete truth 64 65 Jain doctrine states that an object has infinite modes of existence and qualities and as such they cannot be completely perceived in all its aspects and manifestations due to inherent limitations of the humans Anekantavada is literally the doctrine of non onesidedness or manifoldness it is often translated as non absolutism Syadvada is the theory of conditioned predication which provides an expression to anekanta by recommending that epithet Syad be attached to every expression 66 Syadvada is not only an extension of Anekanta ontology but a separate system of logic capable of standing on its own force As reality is complex no single proposition can express the nature of reality fully Thus the term syat should be prefixed before each proposition giving it a conditional point of view and thus removing any dogmatism in the statement 65 For Jains fully enlightened beings are able to see reality from all sides and thus have ultimate knowledge of all things This idea of omniscience was criticized by Buddhists such as Dharmakirti Ancient Chinese philosophy Edit A painting of Zhuangzi and his Butterfly Dream Zhuang Zhou c 369 c 286 BCE Edit Zhuang Zhou 莊子 Master Zhuang was a famous ancient Chinese Taoism philosopher during the Hundred Schools of Thought period Zhuang Zhou demonstrated his skeptical thinking through several anecdotes in the preeminent work Zhuangzi attributed to him The Debate on the Joy of Fish 知魚之樂 In this anecdote Zhuang Zhou argued with his fellow philosopher Hui Shi whether they knew the fish in the pond were happy or not and Zhuang Zhou made the famous observation that You are not I How do you know that I do not know that the fish are happy 67 Autumn Floods 秋水篇 Zhuangzi The Butterfly of the Dream 周公夢蝶 The paradox of Butterfly Dream described Zhuang Zhou s confusion after dreaming himself to be a butterfly But he didn t know if he was Zhuang Zhou who had dreamt he was a butterfly or a butterfly dreaming that he was Zhuang Zhou 67 Discussion on Making All Things Equal 齊物篇 Zhuangzi Through these anecdotes in Zhuangzi Zhuang Zhou indicated his belief in the limitation of language and human communication and the inaccessibility of universal truth This establishes him as a skeptic But he was by no means a radical skeptic he only applied skeptical methods partially in arguments demonstrating his Taoist beliefs He held the Taoist beliefs themselves dogmatically 68 Wang Chong 27 c 100 CE Edit Wang Chong 王充 was the leading figure of the skeptic branch of the Confucianism school in China during the first century CE He introduced a method of rational critique and applied it to the widespread dogmatism thinking of his age like phenomenology the main contemporary Confucianism ideology that linked all natural phenomena with human ethics state led cults and popular superstition His own philosophy incorporated both Taoism and Confucianism thinkings and it was based on a secular rational practice of developing hypotheses based on natural events to explain the universe which exemplified a form of naturalism that resembled the philosophical idea of Epicureans like Lucretius 69 70 Medieval Islamic philosophy Edit The Incoherence of the Philosophers written by the scholar Al Ghazali 1058 1111 marks a major turn in Islamic epistemology His encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological occasionalism or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of God citation needed In the autobiography Ghazali wrote towards the end of his life The Deliverance From Error Al munqidh min al ḍalal 71 Ghazali recounts how once a crisis of epistemological skepticism was resolved by a light which God Most High cast into my breast the key to most knowledge 72 he studied and mastered the arguments of Kalam Islamic philosophy and Ismailism Though appreciating what was valid in the first two of these at least he determined that all three approaches were inadequate and found ultimate value only in the mystical experience and spiritual insight he attained as a result of following Sufi practices William James in Varieties of Religious Experience considered the autobiography an important document for the purely literary student who would like to become acquainted with the inwardness of religions other than the Christian comparing it to recorded personal religious confessions and autobiographical literature in the Christian tradition 73 Aztec philosophy Edit Recordings of Aztec philosophy suggest that the elite classes believed in an essentially panentheistic worldview in which teotl represents a unified underlying universal force Human beings cannot truly perceive teotl due to its chaotic constantly changing nature just the masks facets it is manifested as 74 75 See also EditAjnana Anti realism Benson Mates Brain in a vat Celia Green Fallibilism David Hume Dream argument Five minute hypothesis Munchhausen trilemma Nihilism Pierre Bayle Problem of the criterion Problem of induction Pseudoskepticism Pyrrho Pyrrhonism Sextus Empiricus Simulated reality Solipsism Trivialism opposite of skepticism Zhuang ZhouReferences Edit a b c d Skepticism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved July 12 2020 Certainty Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved July 12 2020 a b c d e f g h i Popkin Richard Henry 2003 The history of scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle Popkin Richard Henry Rev and expanded ed Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0195355390 OCLC 65192690 a b c d e Goldstick D May 1 1983 Four Forms of Philosophical Scepticism University of Toronto Quarterly 52 3 235 240 doi 10 3138 utq 52 3 235 S2CID 170733016 a b c Hansson Sven Ove September 2017 The Uses and Misuses of Philosophical Scepticism Editorial Theoria 83 3 169 174 doi 10 1111 theo 12123 Olsson Erik J 2005 Not Giving the Skeptic a Hearing Pragmatism and Radical Doubt Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 1 98 126 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2005 tb00507 x ISSN 0031 8205 JSTOR 40040781 a b Comesana Juan Klein Peter 2019 Skepticism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved August 24 2022 a b c d e DeRose Keith Warfield Ted A 1999 1 Introduction Responding to Skepticism Skepticism A Contemporary Reader Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 511827 8 a b c d e f g h Popkin Richard H skepticism www britannica com Retrieved August 23 2022 a b c d Stroud Barry Stroud Willis S and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry July 5 1984 Preface The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 824761 6 Cohen Stewart 1996 Craig Edward ed Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge a b Stroud Barry Stroud Willis S and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry July 5 1984 II Philosophical Scepticism and Everyday Life The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 824761 6 Hinton J M 1989 Scepticism Philosophical and Everyday Philosophy 64 248 219 243 doi 10 1017 S0031819100044491 ISSN 0031 8191 JSTOR 3751409 S2CID 144250265 a b c Greco John September 2 2009 Introduction The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism 1 ed Oxford University Press pp 3 7 ISBN 978 0 19 518321 4 a b c d Le Morvan Pierre 2011 Healthy Skepticism and Practical Wisdom Logos amp Episteme 2 1 87 102 doi 10 5840 logos episteme20112151 Merton R K 1942 The Normative Structure of Science in Merton Robert King 1973 The Sociology of Science Theoretical and Empirical Investigations Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0226520919 Vogt Katja 2021 Ancient Skepticism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved August 30 2022 Reed Baron December 11 2018 Skepticism as a Way of Life Brill ISBN 978 90 04 39353 0 Williams Michael 2001 Chapter 5 Agrippa s Trilemma Problems of Knowledge A Critical Introduction to Epistemology Oxford University Press p 61 ISBN 978 0192892560 a b SKEPTICISM Encyclopedia of Empiricism 1997 a b Bailey Alan 1990 Pyrrhonean Scepticism and the Self Refutation Argument The Philosophical Quarterly 40 158 27 44 doi 10 2307 2219965 ISSN 0031 8094 JSTOR 2219965 Kreeft p 373 Baldwin Tom 2010 George Edward Moore 6 Common Sense and Certainty The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved September 1 2022 Schulte Gunter 2007 Gehirnfunktion Und Willensfreiheit Schopenhauers Neurophilosophische Wende Schopenhauer Jahrbuch 88 51 70 Vogt Katja 2019 Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield UK Acumen pp 108 109 ISBN 978 1844654093 OCLC 715184861 Undecidability and the ten modes As part of his Pyrrhonian revival Aenesidemus assembled various kinds of skeptical arguments or modes designed to induce epoche Diogenes Laertius 9 80 88 Eusebius Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV Tertullian Project Retrieved January 27 2023 Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield UK Acumen pp 120 121 ISBN 978 1844654093 OCLC 715184861 Pyrrhonism in whatever form it might have taken after Timon s death in 230 BCE was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention a b c Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield UK Acumen pp 102 103 ISBN 978 1844654093 OCLC 715184861 Aenesidemus criticized his fellow Academics for being dogmatic Aenesidemus committed his scepticism to writing probably some time in the early to mid first century BCE leading Aenesidemus to dismiss them as Stoics fighting against Stoics Sextus Empiricus 1990 Outlines of pyrrhonism Robert Gregg Bury Buffalo N Y Prometheus Books ISBN 0879755970 OCLC 23367477 Those who believe they have discovered it are the dogmatists specially so called Aristotle for example and Epicurus and the Stoics and certain others Cleitomachus and Carneades and other Academics treat it as inapprehensible the skeptics keep on searching Hence it seems reasonable to hold the main types of philosophy are three the dogmatic the Academic and the skeptic Plutarch Sulla 12 cf Appian Roman History xii 5 30 Archived September 12 2015 at the Wayback Machine On the ten modes see Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Skepticism I 35 164 Brochard V The Greek Skeptics a b Dutton Blake D 2016 Augustine and academic skepticism a philosophical study Ithaca ISBN 978 1501703553 OCLC 951625897 Hick John 1970 Classical and contemporary readings in the philosophy of religion 2nd ed Englewood Cliffs NJ Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0131352698 OCLC 90682 Francisco Sanchez That Nothing is Known Cambridge University Press 1989 M Clarke Desmond 2016 French philosophy 1572 1675 First ed Oxford United Kingdom ISBN 978 0198749578 OCLC 923850410 a b Maia Neto Jose Raimundo Paganini Gianni Laursen John Christian Skepticism from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment a Conference in Memory of Richard H Popkin 1923 2005 2007 Belo Horizonte Brazil eds 2009 Skepticism in the modern age building on the work of Richard Popkin Leiden Brill ISBN 978 9047431909 OCLC 700517388 Nadler Steven M ed 2002 A companion to early modern philosophy Malden Mass Blackwell Pub ISBN 978 0631218005 OCLC 49394201 Chappell Vere Claiborne ed 1992 Grotius to Gassendi New York Garland Pub ISBN 978 0815305767 OCLC 24846343 Missner Marshall 1983 Skepticism and Hobbes s Political Philosophy Journal of the History of Ideas 44 3 407 427 doi 10 2307 2709174 JSTOR 2709174 Black Sam 1997 Science and Moral Skepticism in Hobbes Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 2 173 207 doi 10 1080 00455091 1997 10717477 JSTOR 40231980 S2CID 170567466 Laursen John Christian Paganini Gianni 2015 Skepticism and political thought in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries Laursen John Christian Paganini Gianni Toronto ISBN 978 1442649217 OCLC 904548214 Batnitzky Leora December 2003 Spinoza s Critique of Religious Authority Spinoza s Critique of Miracles Cardozo Law Review 25 57 a b Matytsin Anton M 2016 The specter of skepticism in the age of Enlightenment Baltimore ISBN 978 1421420523 OCLC 960048885 a b Lennon Thomas M 2002 What Kind of a Skeptic Was Bayle Midwest Studies in Philosophy 26 1 258 279 doi 10 1111 1475 4975 261066 Morris William Edward and Charlotte R Brown 2019 2001 David Hume Archived May 3 1998 at the Wayback Machine Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford Metaphysics Research Lab Retrieved 10 August 2020 Cranston Maurice and Thomas Edmund Jessop 2020 1999 David Hume Archived June 21 2015 at the Wayback Machine Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 10 August 2020 Hume David 1739 A Treatise of Human Nature 1 London John Noon Retrieved 19 May 2020 p 7 David Hume A Treatise of Human Nature 1739 Book I Of the Understanding and David Hume An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 1748 See G E Schulze Aenesidemus 1792 excerpted in Between Kant and Hegel Texts in the Development of Post Kantian Idealism Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H S Harris Indianapolis Indiana Hackett Publishing 2000 See also Frederick C Beiser The Fate of Reason German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1987 Chapter 9 Schulze s Skepticism See 1 H S Harris Skepticism Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal 1985 in Between Kant and Hegel Texts in the Development of Post Kantian Idealism Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H S Harris Indianapolis Indiana Hackett Publishing 2000 2 G W F Hegel On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One Translated by H S Harris in di Giovanni and Harris 2000 cited just above and 3 Michael N Forster Hegel and Skepticism Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1989 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel The Encyclopedia Logic 1830 28 pp 65 68 Translated by T F Garaets W A Suchting and H S Harris Indianapolis Indiana Hackett Publishing 1991 Jesus Padilla Galvez Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative in Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition Antonio Marques amp Rui Bertrand Romao Eds Bern Berlin Bruxelles New York Oxford Wien Peter Lang 2020 pp 113 122 ISBN 978 3034315951 Sedley David Louis 2005 Sublimity and skepticism in Montaigne and Milton Ann Arbor University of Michigan Press ISBN 978 0472115280 OCLC 60715259 Stroud Barry 1984 The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 0198247613 001 0001 ISBN 978 0198247616 Retrieved August 11 2020 Pritchard Duncan Ranalli Chris 2016 On Metaepistemological Scepticism In Bergmann Michael Coppenger Brett eds Intellectual Assurance Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism Oxford University Press Kalupahana David J A History of Buddhist Philosophy Continuities and Discontinuities page 21 The Cowherds Moonshadows Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy Oxford University Press 2011 pp 115 116 Hayes Richard P Dignaga on the interpretation of signs page 53 Hayes Richard P Dignaga on the interpretation of signs page 35 Kuzminski Adrian Pyrrhonism How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism Studies in Comparative Philosophy and Religion 2008 Dundas Paul John Hinnels ed 2002 The Jains London Routledge ISBN 978 0415266062 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a author2 has generic name help a b Koller John M July 2000 Syadvada as the epistemological key to the Jaina middle way metaphysics of Anekantavada Philosophy East and West 50 3 400 407 ISSN 0031 8221 JSTOR 1400182 ProQuest 216882163 Chatterjea Tara 2001 Knowledge and Freedom in Indian Philosophy Lanham MD Lexington Books pp 77 87 ISBN 978 0739106921 a b Zhuangzi 2017 2013 The Complete works of Zhuangzi Watson Burton New York ISBN 978 0231164740 OCLC 826640070 Berthel Ken December 1 2015 Language in Zhuangzi A Theme that Reveals the Nature of its Relativism and Skepticism Journal of Chinese Philosophy 42 562 576 doi 10 1111 1540 6253 12215 ISSN 1540 6253 Xuerong Ouyang December 2003 略论王充的怀疑主义 Journal of Kaifeng University 17 04 11 13 Needham Joseph 1978 The shorter Science and civilisation in China an abridgement of Joseph Needham s original text Ronan Colin A Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521235822 OCLC 3345021 Annotated translations by Richard Joseph McCarthy Freedom and Fulfillment Boston Twayne 1980 Deliverance From Error Louisville Ky Fons Vitae 1999 and George F McLean Deliverance from error and mystical union with the Almighty Washington D C Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 2001 An earlier translation by William Montgomery Watt was first published in 1953 The faith and practice of al Ghazali London G Allen and Unwin McCarthy 1980 p 66 William James Varieties of Religious Experience Harvard University Press 1985 p 319 2002 Modern Library Paperback Edition p 438 James Maffie 2005 Aztec Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy James Maffie 2014 Aztec Philosophy Understanding a World in Motion University Press of Colorado page needed ISBN missing Further reading EditPopkin Richard H 2003 The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle New York Oxford University Press Popkin Richard H and J R Maia Neto eds 2007 Skepticism An Anthology New York Prometheus Books Beiser Frederick C 1987 The Fate of Reason German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte Cambridge Harvard University Press Breker Christian 2011 Einfuhrender Kommentar zu Sextus Empiricus Grundriss der pyrrhonischen Skepsis Mainz 2011 electr publication University of Mainz available online comment on Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism in German language di Giovanni George and H S Harris eds 2000 Between Kant and Hegel Texts in the Development of Post Kantian Idealism Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H S Harris Indianapolis IN Hackett Publishing Forster Michael N 1989 Hegel and Skepticism Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press Harris H S 1985 Skepticism Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal In di Giovanni and Harris 2000 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 1802 On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One Translated by H S Harris In di Giovanni and Harris 2000 Leavitt Fred 2021 If Ignorance is Bliss We Should All be Ecstatic Open Books Jesus Padilla Galvez Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative in Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition Antonio Marques amp Rui Bertrand Romao Eds Bern Berlin Bruxelles New York Oxford Wien Peter Lang 2020 pp 113 122 Francois Xavier de Peretti Stop Doubting with Descartes dans M Garcia Valdecasas J Milburn J B Guillon eds Anti skepticism Topoi An International Review of Philosophy Springer Nature on line 3 11 2022 1 Francois Xavier de Peretti Descartes sceptique malgre lui International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 11 3 2021 Brill Leyde pp 177 192 Online publication date 15 octobre 2020 Doi https doi org 10 1163 22105700 bja10016 Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient Scepticism Berkeley University of California Press Unger Peter 1975 Ignorance A Case for Scepticism Oxford England Oxford University Press 2002 Zeller Eduard and Oswald J Reichel 1892 The Stoics Epicureans and Sceptics London Longmans Green and Co External links EditKlein Peter Skepticism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ancient Greek Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Renaissance Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Contemporary Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Responses to skepticism by Keith DeRose Article Skepticism and Denial by Stephen Novella MD The New England Journal of Skepticism Classical Skepticism by Peter Suber Review and summary of Skepticism and the Veil of Perception by Michael Huemer Sullivan Margaret December 5 2019 Wall to wall impeachment coverage is not changing any minds Here s how journalists can reach the undecided The Washington Post Columnist Michelle Goldberg of the New York Times offered a name Wednesday for one aspect of what s happening before our eyes Responding to the absurd statement of Rep Douglas A Collins R Ga there are no set facts here she said it summed up the long term Republican strategy epistemological nihilism Portals Philosophy Psychology Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Philosophical skepticism amp oldid 1152207465, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.