fbpx
Wikipedia

Non-cognitivism

Non-cognitivism is the meta-ethical view that ethical sentences do not express propositions (i.e., statements) and thus cannot be true or false (they are not truth-apt). A noncognitivist denies the cognitivist claim that "moral judgments are capable of being objectively true, because they describe some feature of the world".[1] If moral statements cannot be true, and if one cannot know something that is not true, noncognitivism implies that moral knowledge is impossible.[1]

Non-cognitivism entails that non-cognitive attitudes underlie moral discourse and this discourse therefore consists of non-declarative speech acts, although accepting that its surface features may consistently and efficiently work as if moral discourse were cognitive. The point of interpreting moral claims as non-declarative speech acts is to explain what moral claims mean if they are neither true nor false (as philosophies such as logical positivism entail). Utterances like "Boo to killing!" and "Don't kill" are not candidates for truth or falsity, but have non-cognitive meaning.

Varieties

Emotivism, associated with A. J. Ayer, the Vienna Circle and C. L. Stevenson, suggests that ethical sentences are primarily emotional expressions of one's own attitudes and are intended to influence the actions of the listener. Under this view, "Killing is wrong" is translated as "Killing, boo!" or "I disapprove of killing."

A close cousin of emotivism, developed by R. M. Hare, is called universal prescriptivism. Prescriptivists interpret ethical statements as being universal imperatives, prescribing behavior for all to follow. According to prescriptivism, phrases like "Thou shalt not murder!" or "Do not steal!" are the clearest expressions of morality, while reformulations like "Killing is wrong" tend to obscure the meaning of moral sentences.

Other forms of non-cognitivism include Simon Blackburn's quasi-realism and Allan Gibbard's norm-expressivism.

Arguments in favour

As with other anti-realist meta-ethical theories, non-cognitivism is largely supported by the argument from queerness: ethical properties, if they existed, would be different from any other thing in the universe, since they have no observable effect on the world. People generally have a negative attitude towards murder, which presumably keeps most of us from murdering. But does the actual wrongness of murder play an independent role? Is there any evidence that there is a property of wrongness that some types of acts have? Some people might think that the strong feelings we have when we see or consider a murder provide evidence of murder's wrongness. But it is not difficult to explain these feelings without saying that wrongness was their cause. Thus there is no way of discerning which, if any, ethical properties exist; by Occam's razor, the simplest assumption is that none do. The non-cognitivist then asserts that, since a proposition about an ethical property would have no referent, ethical statements must be something else.

Universal prescriptivism

Arguments for prescriptivism focus on the function of normative statements.

Prescriptivists argue that factual statements and prescriptions are totally different, because of different expectations of change in cases of a clash between word and world. In a descriptive sentence, if one premises that "red is a number" then according to the rules of English grammar said statement would be false. Since said premise describes the objects "red" and "number", anyone with an adequate understanding of English would notice the falseness of such description and the falseness of said statement. However, if the norm "thou shalt not kill!" is uttered, and this premise is negated (by the fact of a person being murdered), the speaker is not to change his sentence upon observation of this into "kill other people!", but is to reiterate the moral outrage of the act of killing. Adjusting statements based upon objective reality and adjusting reality based upon statements are contrary uses of language; that is to say, descriptive statements are a different kind of sentence to normative statements. If truth is understood according to correspondence theory, the question of the truth or falsity of sentences not contingent upon external phenomena cannot be tested (see tautologies).

Some cognitivists argue that some expressions like "courageous" have both a factual as well as a normative component which cannot be distinguished by analysis. Prescriptivists argue that according to context, either the factual or the normative component of the meaning is dominant. The sentence "Hero A behaved courageously" is wrong, if A ran away in the face of danger. But the sentence "Be brave and fight for the glory of your country!" has no truth value and cannot be falsified by someone who doesn't join the army.

Prescriptivism is also supported by the actual way of speaking. Many moral statements are de facto uttered as recommendations or commands, e.g. when parents or teachers forbid children to do wrong actions. The most famous moral ideas are prescriptions: the Ten Commandments, the command of charity, the categorical imperative, and the Golden Rule command to do or not to do something rather than state that something is or is not the case.

Prescriptivism can fit the theist idea of morality as obedience towards god. It is however different from the cognitivist supernaturalism which interprets morality as subjective will of god, while prescriptivism claims that moral rules are universal and can be found by reason alone without reference to a god.

According to Hare, prescriptivists cannot argue that amoralists are logically wrong or contradictory. Everyone can choose to follow moral commands or not. This is the human condition according to the Christian reinterpretation of the Choice of Heracles. According to prescriptivism, morality is not about knowledge (of moral facts), but about character (to choose to do the right thing). Actors cannot externalize their responsibility and freedom of will towards some moral truth in the world, virtuous people don't need to wait for some cognition to choose what's right.

Prescriptivism is also supported by imperative logic, in which there are no truth values for imperatives, and by the idea of the naturalistic fallacy: even if someone could prove the existence of an ethical property and express it in a factual statement, he could never derive any command from this statement, so the search for ethical properties is pointless.

Emotivism

Arguments for emotivism focus on what normative statements express when uttered by a speaker. A person who says that killing is wrong certainly expresses her disapproval of killing. Emotivists claim that this is all she does, that the statement "killing is wrong" is not a truth-apt declaration, and that the burden of evidence is on the cognitivists who want to show that in addition to expressing disapproval, the claim "killing is wrong" is also true. Emotivists ask whether there really is evidence that killing is wrong. We have evidence that Jupiter has a magnetic field and that birds are oviparous, but as yet, we do not seem to have found evidence of moral properties, such as "goodness". Emotivists ask why, without such evidence, we should think there is such a property. Ethical intuitionists think the evidence comes not from science or reason but from our own feelings: good deeds make us feel a certain way and bad deeds make us feel very differently. But is this enough to show that there are genuinely good and bad deeds? Emotivists think not, claiming that we do not need to postulate the existence of moral "badness" or "wrongness" to explain why considering certain deeds makes us feel disapproval; that all we really observe when we introspect are feelings of disapproval. Thus the emotivist asks why not adopt the simple explanation and say that this is all there is, rather than insist that some intrinsic "badness" (of murder, for example) must be causing feelings when a simpler explanation is available.

Arguments against

One argument against non-cognitivism is that it ignores the external causes of emotional and prescriptive reactions. If someone says, "John is a good person," something about John must have inspired that reaction. If John gives to the poor, takes care of his sick grandmother, and is friendly to others, and these are what inspire the speaker to think well of him, it is plausible to say, "John is a good person because he gives to the poor, takes care of his sick grandmother, and is friendly to others."[2] If, in turn, the speaker responds positively to the idea of giving to the poor, then some aspect of that idea must have inspired a positive response; one could argue that that aspect is also the basis of its goodness.

Another argument is the "embedding problem" in which ethical sentences are embedded into more complex sentences. Consider the following examples:

  • Eating meat is not wrong.
  • Is eating meat wrong?
  • I think that eating meat is wrong.
  • Mike doesn't think that eating meat is wrong.
  • I once thought that eating meat was wrong.
  • She does not realize that eating meat is wrong.

Attempts to translate these sentences in an emotivist framework seem to fail (e.g. "She does not realize 'Boo to eating meat!'"). Prescriptivist translations fare only slightly better ("She does not realize that she is not to eat meat"). Even the act of forming such a construction indicates some sort of cognition in the process.

According to some non-cognitivist points of view, these sentences simply assume the false premise that ethical statements are either true or false. They might be literally translated as:

  • "Eating meat is wrong" is a false statement.
  • Is "eating meat is wrong" a true statement?
  • I think that "eating meat is wrong" is a true statement.
  • Mike doesn't think that "eating meat is wrong" is a true statement.
  • I once thought that "eating meat is wrong" was a true statement.
  • She does not realize that "eating meat is wrong" is a true statement.

These translations, however, seem divorced from the way people actually use language. A non-cognitivist would have to disagree with someone saying, "'Eating meat is wrong' is a false statement" (since "Eating meat is wrong" is not truth-apt at all), but may be tempted to agree with a person saying, "Eating meat is not wrong."

One might more constructively interpret these statements to describe the underlying emotional statement that they express, i.e.: I disapprove/do not disapprove of eating meat, I used to, he doesn't, I do and she doesn't, etc.; however, this interpretation is closer to ethical subjectivism than to non-cognitivism proper.

A similar argument against non-cognitivism is that of ethical argument. A common argument might be, "If killing an innocent human is always wrong, and all fetuses are innocent humans, then killing a fetus is always wrong." Most people would consider such an utterance to represent an analytic proposition which is true a priori. However, if ethical statements do not represent cognitions, it seems odd to use them as premises in an argument, and even odder to assume they follow the same rules of syllogism as true propositions. However, R.M. Hare, proponent of universal prescriptivism, has argued that the rules of logic are independent of grammatical mood, and thus the same logical relations may hold between imperatives as hold between indicatives.

Many objections to non-cognitivism based on the linguistic characteristics of what purport to be moral judgments were originally raised by Peter Glassen in "The Cognitivity of Moral Judgments", published in Mind in January 1959, and in Glassen's follow-up article in the January 1963 issue of the same journal.[3]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b Garner, Richard T.; Bernard Rosen (1967). Moral Philosophy: A Systematic Introduction to Normative Ethics and Meta-ethics. New York: Macmillan. pp. 219–220. ISBN 0-02-340580-5.
  2. ^ selfstudyhistory, Author (2015-03-22). "(GS PAPER-4) Introduction to Ethics, Essence, determinants and consequences of Ethics in human actions". SELF STUDY HISTORY. Retrieved 2020-05-28. {{cite web}}: |first= has generic name (help)
  3. ^ Glassen, P., "The Cognitivity of Moral Judgments", Mind 68:57-72 (1959); id. "The Cognitivity of Moral Judgments: A Rejoinder to Miss Schuster", Mind 72:137-140 (1963).

External links

cognitivism, this, article, about, meta, ethical, theory, cognitivism, regarding, religious, language, theological, noncognitivism, meta, ethical, view, that, ethical, sentences, express, propositions, statements, thus, cannot, true, false, they, truth, noncog. This article is about the meta ethical theory For non cognitivism regarding religious language see theological noncognitivism Non cognitivism is the meta ethical view that ethical sentences do not express propositions i e statements and thus cannot be true or false they are not truth apt A noncognitivist denies the cognitivist claim that moral judgments are capable of being objectively true because they describe some feature of the world 1 If moral statements cannot be true and if one cannot know something that is not true noncognitivism implies that moral knowledge is impossible 1 Non cognitivism entails that non cognitive attitudes underlie moral discourse and this discourse therefore consists of non declarative speech acts although accepting that its surface features may consistently and efficiently work as if moral discourse were cognitive The point of interpreting moral claims as non declarative speech acts is to explain what moral claims mean if they are neither true nor false as philosophies such as logical positivism entail Utterances like Boo to killing and Don t kill are not candidates for truth or falsity but have non cognitive meaning Contents 1 Varieties 2 Arguments in favour 2 1 Universal prescriptivism 2 2 Emotivism 3 Arguments against 4 See also 5 References 6 External linksVarieties EditEmotivism associated with A J Ayer the Vienna Circle and C L Stevenson suggests that ethical sentences are primarily emotional expressions of one s own attitudes and are intended to influence the actions of the listener Under this view Killing is wrong is translated as Killing boo or I disapprove of killing A close cousin of emotivism developed by R M Hare is called universal prescriptivism Prescriptivists interpret ethical statements as being universal imperatives prescribing behavior for all to follow According to prescriptivism phrases like Thou shalt not murder or Do not steal are the clearest expressions of morality while reformulations like Killing is wrong tend to obscure the meaning of moral sentences Other forms of non cognitivism include Simon Blackburn s quasi realism and Allan Gibbard s norm expressivism Arguments in favour EditThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed March 2007 Learn how and when to remove this template message As with other anti realist meta ethical theories non cognitivism is largely supported by the argument from queerness ethical properties if they existed would be different from any other thing in the universe since they have no observable effect on the world People generally have a negative attitude towards murder which presumably keeps most of us from murdering But does the actual wrongness of murder play an independent role Is there any evidence that there is a property of wrongness that some types of acts have Some people might think that the strong feelings we have when we see or consider a murder provide evidence of murder s wrongness But it is not difficult to explain these feelings without saying that wrongness was their cause Thus there is no way of discerning which if any ethical properties exist by Occam s razor the simplest assumption is that none do The non cognitivist then asserts that since a proposition about an ethical property would have no referent ethical statements must be something else Universal prescriptivism Edit Arguments for prescriptivism focus on the function of normative statements Prescriptivists argue that factual statements and prescriptions are totally different because of different expectations of change in cases of a clash between word and world In a descriptive sentence if one premises that red is a number then according to the rules of English grammar said statement would be false Since said premise describes the objects red and number anyone with an adequate understanding of English would notice the falseness of such description and the falseness of said statement However if the norm thou shalt not kill is uttered and this premise is negated by the fact of a person being murdered the speaker is not to change his sentence upon observation of this into kill other people but is to reiterate the moral outrage of the act of killing Adjusting statements based upon objective reality and adjusting reality based upon statements are contrary uses of language that is to say descriptive statements are a different kind of sentence to normative statements If truth is understood according to correspondence theory the question of the truth or falsity of sentences not contingent upon external phenomena cannot be tested see tautologies Some cognitivists argue that some expressions like courageous have both a factual as well as a normative component which cannot be distinguished by analysis Prescriptivists argue that according to context either the factual or the normative component of the meaning is dominant The sentence Hero A behaved courageously is wrong if A ran away in the face of danger But the sentence Be brave and fight for the glory of your country has no truth value and cannot be falsified by someone who doesn t join the army Prescriptivism is also supported by the actual way of speaking Many moral statements are de facto uttered as recommendations or commands e g when parents or teachers forbid children to do wrong actions The most famous moral ideas are prescriptions the Ten Commandments the command of charity the categorical imperative and the Golden Rule command to do or not to do something rather than state that something is or is not the case Prescriptivism can fit the theist idea of morality as obedience towards god It is however different from the cognitivist supernaturalism which interprets morality as subjective will of god while prescriptivism claims that moral rules are universal and can be found by reason alone without reference to a god According to Hare prescriptivists cannot argue that amoralists are logically wrong or contradictory Everyone can choose to follow moral commands or not This is the human condition according to the Christian reinterpretation of the Choice of Heracles According to prescriptivism morality is not about knowledge of moral facts but about character to choose to do the right thing Actors cannot externalize their responsibility and freedom of will towards some moral truth in the world virtuous people don t need to wait for some cognition to choose what s right Prescriptivism is also supported by imperative logic in which there are no truth values for imperatives and by the idea of the naturalistic fallacy even if someone could prove the existence of an ethical property and express it in a factual statement he could never derive any command from this statement so the search for ethical properties is pointless Emotivism Edit Arguments for emotivism focus on what normative statements express when uttered by a speaker A person who says that killing is wrong certainly expresses her disapproval of killing Emotivists claim that this is all she does that the statement killing is wrong is not a truth apt declaration and that the burden of evidence is on the cognitivists who want to show that in addition to expressing disapproval the claim killing is wrong is also true Emotivists ask whether there really is evidence that killing is wrong We have evidence that Jupiter has a magnetic field and that birds are oviparous but as yet we do not seem to have found evidence of moral properties such as goodness Emotivists ask why without such evidence we should think there is such a property Ethical intuitionists think the evidence comes not from science or reason but from our own feelings good deeds make us feel a certain way and bad deeds make us feel very differently But is this enough to show that there are genuinely good and bad deeds Emotivists think not claiming that we do not need to postulate the existence of moral badness or wrongness to explain why considering certain deeds makes us feel disapproval that all we really observe when we introspect are feelings of disapproval Thus the emotivist asks why not adopt the simple explanation and say that this is all there is rather than insist that some intrinsic badness of murder for example must be causing feelings when a simpler explanation is available Arguments against EditThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed March 2007 Learn how and when to remove this template message One argument against non cognitivism is that it ignores the external causes of emotional and prescriptive reactions If someone says John is a good person something about John must have inspired that reaction If John gives to the poor takes care of his sick grandmother and is friendly to others and these are what inspire the speaker to think well of him it is plausible to say John is a good person because he gives to the poor takes care of his sick grandmother and is friendly to others 2 If in turn the speaker responds positively to the idea of giving to the poor then some aspect of that idea must have inspired a positive response one could argue that that aspect is also the basis of its goodness Another argument is the embedding problem in which ethical sentences are embedded into more complex sentences Consider the following examples Eating meat is not wrong Is eating meat wrong I think that eating meat is wrong Mike doesn t think that eating meat is wrong I once thought that eating meat was wrong She does not realize that eating meat is wrong Attempts to translate these sentences in an emotivist framework seem to fail e g She does not realize Boo to eating meat Prescriptivist translations fare only slightly better She does not realize that she is not to eat meat Even the act of forming such a construction indicates some sort of cognition in the process According to some non cognitivist points of view these sentences simply assume the false premise that ethical statements are either true or false They might be literally translated as Eating meat is wrong is a false statement Is eating meat is wrong a true statement I think that eating meat is wrong is a true statement Mike doesn t think that eating meat is wrong is a true statement I once thought that eating meat is wrong was a true statement She does not realize that eating meat is wrong is a true statement These translations however seem divorced from the way people actually use language A non cognitivist would have to disagree with someone saying Eating meat is wrong is a false statement since Eating meat is wrong is not truth apt at all but may be tempted to agree with a person saying Eating meat is not wrong One might more constructively interpret these statements to describe the underlying emotional statement that they express i e I disapprove do not disapprove of eating meat I used to he doesn t I do and she doesn t etc however this interpretation is closer to ethical subjectivism than to non cognitivism proper A similar argument against non cognitivism is that of ethical argument A common argument might be If killing an innocent human is always wrong and all fetuses are innocent humans then killing a fetus is always wrong Most people would consider such an utterance to represent an analytic proposition which is true a priori However if ethical statements do not represent cognitions it seems odd to use them as premises in an argument and even odder to assume they follow the same rules of syllogism as true propositions However R M Hare proponent of universal prescriptivism has argued that the rules of logic are independent of grammatical mood and thus the same logical relations may hold between imperatives as hold between indicatives Many objections to non cognitivism based on the linguistic characteristics of what purport to be moral judgments were originally raised by Peter Glassen in The Cognitivity of Moral Judgments published in Mind in January 1959 and in Glassen s follow up article in the January 1963 issue of the same journal 3 See also EditAmoralism Expressivism Theological noncognitivism Moral realism Moral skepticism Rudolf Carnap Richard RortyReferences Edit a b Garner Richard T Bernard Rosen 1967 Moral Philosophy A Systematic Introduction to Normative Ethics and Meta ethics New York Macmillan pp 219 220 ISBN 0 02 340580 5 selfstudyhistory Author 2015 03 22 GS PAPER 4 Introduction to Ethics Essence determinants and consequences of Ethics in human actions SELF STUDY HISTORY Retrieved 2020 05 28 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a first has generic name help Glassen P The Cognitivity of Moral Judgments Mind 68 57 72 1959 id The Cognitivity of Moral Judgments A Rejoinder to Miss Schuster Mind 72 137 140 1963 External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Non cognitivism Moral Cognitivism vs Non Cognitivism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry by Mark van Roojen Non Cognitivism in Ethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy rsrevision com s pages on Metaethics Emotivism Intuitionism and Prescriptivism with explanations criticisms and links Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Non cognitivism amp oldid 1109427398, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.