fbpx
Wikipedia

David Hilbert

David Hilbert (/ˈhɪlbərt/;[3] German: [ˈdaːvɪt ˈhɪlbɐt]; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and one of the most influential mathematicians of the 19th and early 20th centuries. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental ideas in many areas, including invariant theory, the calculus of variations, commutative algebra, algebraic number theory, the foundations of geometry, spectral theory of operators and its application to integral equations, mathematical physics, and the foundations of mathematics (particularly proof theory).

David Hilbert
Hilbert in 1912
Born(1862-01-23)23 January 1862
Died14 February 1943(1943-02-14) (aged 81)
NationalityGerman
EducationUniversity of Königsberg (PhD)
Known forHilbert's basis theorem
Hilbert's axioms
Hilbert's problems
Hilbert's program
Einstein–Hilbert action
Hilbert space
Epsilon calculus
SpouseKäthe Jerosch
ChildrenFranz (b. 1893)
AwardsLobachevsky Prize (1903)
Bolyai Prize (1910)
ForMemRS[1]
Scientific career
FieldsMathematics, Physics and Philosophy
InstitutionsUniversity of Königsberg
Göttingen University
ThesisOn Invariant Properties of Special Binary Forms, Especially of Spherical Functions (1885)
Doctoral advisorFerdinand von Lindemann[2]
Doctoral students
Other notable studentsEdward Kasner
John von Neumann

Hilbert adopted and defended Georg Cantor's set theory and transfinite numbers. In 1900, he presented a collection of problems that set the course for much of the mathematical research of the 20th century.[4][5]

Hilbert and his students contributed significantly to establishing rigor and developed important tools used in modern mathematical physics. Hilbert is known as one of the founders of proof theory and mathematical logic.[6]

Life Edit

Early life and education Edit

Hilbert, the first of two children and only son of Otto and Maria Therese (Erdtmann) Hilbert, was born in the Province of Prussia, Kingdom of Prussia, either in Königsberg (according to Hilbert's own statement) or in Wehlau (known since 1946 as Znamensk) near Königsberg where his father worked at the time of his birth.[7]

In late 1872, Hilbert entered the Friedrichskolleg Gymnasium (Collegium fridericianum, the same school that Immanuel Kant had attended 140 years before); but, after an unhappy period, he transferred to (late 1879) and graduated from (early 1880) the more science-oriented Wilhelm Gymnasium.[8] Upon graduation, in autumn 1880, Hilbert enrolled at the University of Königsberg, the "Albertina". In early 1882, Hermann Minkowski (two years younger than Hilbert and also a native of Königsberg but had gone to Berlin for three semesters),[9] returned to Königsberg and entered the university. Hilbert developed a lifelong friendship with the shy, gifted Minkowski.[10][11]

Career Edit

 
Hilbert in 1886
 
Hilbert in 1907

In 1884, Adolf Hurwitz arrived from Göttingen as an Extraordinarius (i.e., an associate professor). An intense and fruitful scientific exchange among the three began, and Minkowski and Hilbert especially would exercise a reciprocal influence over each other at various times in their scientific careers. Hilbert obtained his doctorate in 1885, with a dissertation, written under Ferdinand von Lindemann,[2] titled Über invariante Eigenschaften spezieller binärer Formen, insbesondere der Kugelfunktionen ("On the invariant properties of special binary forms, in particular the spherical harmonic functions").

Hilbert remained at the University of Königsberg as a Privatdozent (senior lecturer) from 1886 to 1895. In 1895, as a result of intervention on his behalf by Felix Klein, he obtained the position of Professor of Mathematics at the University of Göttingen. During the Klein and Hilbert years, Göttingen became the preeminent institution in the mathematical world.[12] He remained there for the rest of his life.

 
The Mathematical Institute in Göttingen. Its new building, constructed with funds from the Rockefeller Foundation, was opened by Hilbert and Courant in 1930.

Göttingen school Edit

Among Hilbert's students were Hermann Weyl, chess champion Emanuel Lasker, Ernst Zermelo, and Carl Gustav Hempel. John von Neumann was his assistant. At the University of Göttingen, Hilbert was surrounded by a social circle of some of the most important mathematicians of the 20th century, such as Emmy Noether and Alonzo Church.

Among his 69 Ph.D. students in Göttingen were many who later became famous mathematicians, including (with date of thesis): Otto Blumenthal (1898), Felix Bernstein (1901), Hermann Weyl (1908), Richard Courant (1910), Erich Hecke (1910), Hugo Steinhaus (1911), and Wilhelm Ackermann (1925).[13] Between 1902 and 1939 Hilbert was editor of the Mathematische Annalen, the leading mathematical journal of the time. He was elected an International Member of the United States National Academy of Sciences in 1907.[14]

Good, he did not have enough imagination to become a mathematician.

— Hilbert's response upon hearing that one of his students had dropped out to study poetry.[15]

Personal life Edit

 
Käthe Hilbert with Constantin Carathéodory, before 1932
 
Hilbert and his wife Käthe Jerosch (1892)
 
Franz Hilbert

In 1892, Hilbert married Käthe Jerosch (1864–1945), who was the daughter of a Königsberg merchant, "an outspoken young lady with an independence of mind that matched [Hilbert's]."[16] While at Königsberg they had their one child, Franz Hilbert [de] (1893–1969). Franz suffered throughout his life from an undiagnosed mental illness. His inferior intellect was a terrible disappointment to his father and this misfortune was a matter of distress to the mathematicians and students at Göttingen.[17]

Hilbert considered the mathematician Hermann Minkowski to be his "best and truest friend".[18]

Hilbert was baptized and raised a Calvinist in the Prussian Evangelical Church.[a] He later left the Church and became an agnostic.[b] He also argued that mathematical truth was independent of the existence of God or other a priori assumptions.[c][d] When Galileo Galilei was criticized for failing to stand up for his convictions on the Heliocentric theory, Hilbert objected: "But [Galileo] was not an idiot. Only an idiot could believe that scientific truth needs martyrdom; that may be necessary in religion, but scientific results prove themselves in due time."[e]

Later years Edit

Like Albert Einstein, Hilbert had closest contacts with the Berlin Group whose leading founders had studied under Hilbert in Göttingen (Kurt Grelling, Hans Reichenbach and Walter Dubislav).[19]

Around 1925, Hilbert developed pernicious anemia, a then-untreatable vitamin deficiency whose primary symptom is exhaustion; his assistant Eugene Wigner described him as subject to "enormous fatigue" and how he "seemed quite old," and that even after eventually being diagnosed and treated, he "was hardly a scientist after 1925, and certainly not a Hilbert."[20]

Hilbert was elected to the American Philosophical Society in 1932.[21]

Hilbert lived to see the Nazis purge many of the prominent faculty members at University of Göttingen in 1933.[22] Those forced out included Hermann Weyl (who had taken Hilbert's chair when he retired in 1930), Emmy Noether and Edmund Landau. One who had to leave Germany, Paul Bernays, had collaborated with Hilbert in mathematical logic, and co-authored with him the important book Grundlagen der Mathematik (which eventually appeared in two volumes, in 1934 and 1939). This was a sequel to the Hilbert–Ackermann book Principles of Mathematical Logic from 1928. Hermann Weyl's successor was Helmut Hasse.

About a year later, Hilbert attended a banquet and was seated next to the new Minister of Education, Bernhard Rust. Rust asked whether "the Mathematical Institute really suffered so much because of the departure of the Jews." Hilbert replied, "Suffered? It doesn't exist any longer, does it?"[23][24]

Death Edit

 
Hilbert's tomb:
Wir müssen wissen
Wir werden wissen

By the time Hilbert died in 1943, the Nazis had nearly completely restaffed the university, as many of the former faculty had either been Jewish or married to Jews. Hilbert's funeral was attended by fewer than a dozen people, only two of whom were fellow academics, among them Arnold Sommerfeld, a theoretical physicist and also a native of Königsberg.[25] News of his death only became known to the wider world several months after he died.[26]

The epitaph on his tombstone in Göttingen consists of the famous lines he spoke at the conclusion of his retirement address to the Society of German Scientists and Physicians on 8 September 1930. The words were given in response to the Latin maxim: "Ignoramus et ignorabimus" or "We do not know and we shall not know":[27]

The day before Hilbert pronounced these phrases at the 1930 annual meeting of the Society of German Scientists and Physicians, Kurt Gödel—in a round table discussion during the Conference on Epistemology held jointly with the Society meetings—tentatively announced the first expression of his incompleteness theorem.[f] Gödel's incompleteness theorems show that even elementary axiomatic systems such as Peano arithmetic are either self-contradicting or contain logical propositions that are impossible to prove or disprove within that system.

Contributions to mathematics and physics Edit

Hilbert solves Gordan's Problem Edit

Hilbert's first work on invariant functions led him to the demonstration in 1888 of his famous finiteness theorem. Twenty years earlier, Paul Gordan had demonstrated the theorem of the finiteness of generators for binary forms using a complex computational approach. Attempts to generalize his method to functions with more than two variables failed because of the enormous difficulty of the calculations involved. To solve what had become known in some circles as Gordan's Problem, Hilbert realized that it was necessary to take a completely different path. As a result, he demonstrated Hilbert's basis theorem, showing the existence of a finite set of generators, for the invariants of quantics in any number of variables, but in an abstract form. That is, while demonstrating the existence of such a set, it was not a constructive proof—it did not display "an object"—but rather, it was an existence proof[28] and relied on use of the law of excluded middle in an infinite extension.

Hilbert sent his results to the Mathematische Annalen. Gordan, the house expert on the theory of invariants for the Mathematische Annalen, could not appreciate the revolutionary nature of Hilbert's theorem and rejected the article, criticizing the exposition because it was insufficiently comprehensive. His comment was:

Klein, on the other hand, recognized the importance of the work, and guaranteed that it would be published without any alterations. Encouraged by Klein, Hilbert extended his method in a second article, providing estimations on the maximum degree of the minimum set of generators, and he sent it once more to the Annalen. After having read the manuscript, Klein wrote to him, saying:

Without doubt this is the most important work on general algebra that the Annalen has ever published.[30]

Later, after the usefulness of Hilbert's method was universally recognized, Gordan himself would say:

I have convinced myself that even theology has its merits.[31]

For all his successes, the nature of his proof created more trouble than Hilbert could have imagined. Although Kronecker had conceded, Hilbert would later respond to others' similar criticisms that "many different constructions are subsumed under one fundamental idea"—in other words (to quote Reid): "Through a proof of existence, Hilbert had been able to obtain a construction"; "the proof" (i.e. the symbols on the page) was "the object".[31] Not all were convinced. While Kronecker would die soon afterwards, his constructivist philosophy would continue with the young Brouwer and his developing intuitionist "school", much to Hilbert's torment in his later years.[32] Indeed, Hilbert would lose his "gifted pupil" Weyl to intuitionism—"Hilbert was disturbed by his former student's fascination with the ideas of Brouwer, which aroused in Hilbert the memory of Kronecker".[33] Brouwer the intuitionist in particular opposed the use of the Law of Excluded Middle over infinite sets (as Hilbert had used it). Hilbert responded:

Taking the Principle of the Excluded Middle from the mathematician ... is the same as ... prohibiting the boxer the use of his fists.[34]

Axiomatization of geometry Edit

The text Grundlagen der Geometrie (tr.: Foundations of Geometry) published by Hilbert in 1899 proposes a formal set, called Hilbert's axioms, substituting for the traditional axioms of Euclid. They avoid weaknesses identified in those of Euclid, whose works at the time were still used textbook-fashion. It is difficult to specify the axioms used by Hilbert without referring to the publication history of the Grundlagen since Hilbert changed and modified them several times. The original monograph was quickly followed by a French translation, in which Hilbert added V.2, the Completeness Axiom. An English translation, authorized by Hilbert, was made by E.J. Townsend and copyrighted in 1902.[35][36] This translation incorporated the changes made in the French translation and so is considered to be a translation of the 2nd edition. Hilbert continued to make changes in the text and several editions appeared in German. The 7th edition was the last to appear in Hilbert's lifetime. New editions followed the 7th, but the main text was essentially not revised.[g]

Hilbert's approach signaled the shift to the modern axiomatic method. In this, Hilbert was anticipated by Moritz Pasch's work from 1882. Axioms are not taken as self-evident truths. Geometry may treat things, about which we have powerful intuitions, but it is not necessary to assign any explicit meaning to the undefined concepts. The elements, such as point, line, plane, and others, could be substituted, as Hilbert is reported to have said to Schoenflies and Kötter, by tables, chairs, glasses of beer and other such objects.[37] It is their defined relationships that are discussed.

Hilbert first enumerates the undefined concepts: point, line, plane, lying on (a relation between points and lines, points and planes, and lines and planes), betweenness, congruence of pairs of points (line segments), and congruence of angles. The axioms unify both the plane geometry and solid geometry of Euclid in a single system.

The 23 problems Edit

Hilbert put forth the most influential list consisting of 23 unsolved problems at the International Congress of Mathematicians in Paris in 1900. This is generally reckoned as the most successful and deeply considered compilation of open problems ever to be produced by an individual mathematician.[by whom?]

After re-working the foundations of classical geometry, Hilbert could have extrapolated to the rest of mathematics. His approach differed, however, from the later "foundationalist" Russell–Whitehead or "encyclopedist" Nicolas Bourbaki, and from his contemporary Giuseppe Peano. The mathematical community as a whole could engage in problems of which he had identified as crucial aspects of important areas of mathematics.

The problem set was launched as a talk "The Problems of Mathematics" presented during the course of the Second International Congress of Mathematicians held in Paris. The introduction of the speech that Hilbert gave said:

Who among us would not be happy to lift the veil behind which is hidden the future; to gaze at the coming developments of our science and at the secrets of its development in the centuries to come? What will be the ends toward which the spirit of future generations of mathematicians will tend? What methods, what new facts will the new century reveal in the vast and rich field of mathematical thought?[38]

He presented fewer than half the problems at the Congress, which were published in the acts of the Congress. In a subsequent publication, he extended the panorama, and arrived at the formulation of the now-canonical 23 Problems of Hilbert. See also Hilbert's twenty-fourth problem. The full text is important, since the exegesis of the questions still can be a matter of inevitable debate, whenever it is asked how many have been solved.

Some of these were solved within a short time. Others have been discussed throughout the 20th century, with a few now taken to be unsuitably open-ended to come to closure. Some continue to remain challenges.

Formalism Edit

In an account that had become standard by the mid-century, Hilbert's problem set was also a kind of manifesto that opened the way for the development of the formalist school, one of three major schools of mathematics of the 20th century. According to the formalist, mathematics is manipulation of symbols according to agreed upon formal rules. It is therefore an autonomous activity of thought. There is, however, room to doubt whether Hilbert's own views were simplistically formalist in this sense.

Hilbert's program Edit

In 1920, Hilbert proposed a research project in metamathematics that became known as Hilbert's program. He wanted mathematics to be formulated on a solid and complete logical foundation. He believed that in principle this could be done by showing that:

  1. all of mathematics follows from a correctly chosen finite system of axioms; and
  2. that some such axiom system is provably consistent through some means such as the epsilon calculus.

He seems to have had both technical and philosophical reasons for formulating this proposal. It affirmed his dislike of what had become known as the ignorabimus, still an active issue in his time in German thought, and traced back in that formulation to Emil du Bois-Reymond.

This program is still recognizable in the most popular philosophy of mathematics, where it is usually called formalism. For example, the Bourbaki group adopted a watered-down and selective version of it as adequate to the requirements of their twin projects of (a) writing encyclopedic foundational works, and (b) supporting the axiomatic method as a research tool. This approach has been successful and influential in relation with Hilbert's work in algebra and functional analysis, but has failed to engage in the same way with his interests in physics and logic.

Hilbert wrote in 1919:

We are not speaking here of arbitrariness in any sense. Mathematics is not like a game whose tasks are determined by arbitrarily stipulated rules. Rather, it is a conceptual system possessing internal necessity that can only be so and by no means otherwise.[39]

Hilbert published his views on the foundations of mathematics in the 2-volume work, Grundlagen der Mathematik.

Gödel's work Edit

Hilbert and the mathematicians who worked with him in his enterprise were committed to the project. His attempt to support axiomatized mathematics with definitive principles, which could banish theoretical uncertainties, ended in failure.

Gödel demonstrated that any non-contradictory formal system, which was comprehensive enough to include at least arithmetic, cannot demonstrate its completeness by way of its own axioms. In 1931 his incompleteness theorem showed that Hilbert's grand plan was impossible as stated. The second point cannot in any reasonable way be combined with the first point, as long as the axiom system is genuinely finitary.

Nevertheless, the subsequent achievements of proof theory at the very least clarified consistency as it relates to theories of central concern to mathematicians. Hilbert's work had started logic on this course of clarification; the need to understand Gödel's work then led to the development of recursion theory and then mathematical logic as an autonomous discipline in the 1930s. The basis for later theoretical computer science, in the work of Alonzo Church and Alan Turing, also grew directly out of this "debate".[40]

Functional analysis Edit

Around 1909, Hilbert dedicated himself to the study of differential and integral equations; his work had direct consequences for important parts of modern functional analysis. In order to carry out these studies, Hilbert introduced the concept of an infinite dimensional Euclidean space, later called Hilbert space. His work in this part of analysis provided the basis for important contributions to the mathematics of physics in the next two decades, though from an unanticipated direction. Later on, Stefan Banach amplified the concept, defining Banach spaces. Hilbert spaces are an important class of objects in the area of functional analysis, particularly of the spectral theory of self-adjoint linear operators, that grew up around it during the 20th century.

Physics Edit

Until 1912, Hilbert was almost exclusively a pure mathematician. When planning a visit from Bonn, where he was immersed in studying physics, his fellow mathematician and friend Hermann Minkowski joked he had to spend 10 days in quarantine before being able to visit Hilbert. In fact, Minkowski seems responsible for most of Hilbert's physics investigations prior to 1912, including their joint seminar on the subject in 1905.

In 1912, three years after his friend's death, Hilbert turned his focus to the subject almost exclusively. He arranged to have a "physics tutor" for himself.[41] He started studying kinetic gas theory and moved on to elementary radiation theory and the molecular theory of matter. Even after the war started in 1914, he continued seminars and classes where the works of Albert Einstein and others were followed closely.

By 1907, Einstein had framed the fundamentals of the theory of gravity, but then struggled for nearly 8 years to put the theory into its final form.[42] By early summer 1915, Hilbert's interest in physics had focused on general relativity, and he invited Einstein to Göttingen to deliver a week of lectures on the subject.[43] Einstein received an enthusiastic reception at Göttingen.[44] Over the summer, Einstein learned that Hilbert was also working on the field equations and redoubled his own efforts. During November 1915, Einstein published several papers culminating in The Field Equations of Gravitation (see Einstein field equations).[h] Nearly simultaneously, Hilbert published "The Foundations of Physics", an axiomatic derivation of the field equations (see Einstein–Hilbert action). Hilbert fully credited Einstein as the originator of the theory and no public priority dispute concerning the field equations ever arose between the two men during their lives.[i] See more at priority.

Additionally, Hilbert's work anticipated and assisted several advances in the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics. His work was a key aspect of Hermann Weyl and John von Neumann's work on the mathematical equivalence of Werner Heisenberg's matrix mechanics and Erwin Schrödinger's wave equation, and his namesake Hilbert space plays an important part in quantum theory. In 1926, von Neumann showed that, if quantum states were understood as vectors in Hilbert space, they would correspond with both Schrödinger's wave function theory and Heisenberg's matrices.[j]

Throughout this immersion in physics, Hilbert worked on putting rigor into the mathematics of physics. While highly dependent on higher mathematics, physicists tended to be "sloppy" with it. To a pure mathematician like Hilbert, this was both ugly, and difficult to understand. As he began to understand physics and how physicists were using mathematics, he developed a coherent mathematical theory for what he found – most importantly in the area of integral equations. When his colleague Richard Courant wrote the now classic Methoden der mathematischen Physik (Methods of Mathematical Physics) including some of Hilbert's ideas, he added Hilbert's name as author even though Hilbert had not directly contributed to the writing. Hilbert said "Physics is too hard for physicists", implying that the necessary mathematics was generally beyond them; the Courant-Hilbert book made it easier for them.

Number theory Edit

Hilbert unified the field of algebraic number theory with his 1897 treatise Zahlbericht (literally "report on numbers"). He also resolved a significant number-theory problem formulated by Waring in 1770. As with the finiteness theorem, he used an existence proof that shows there must be solutions for the problem rather than providing a mechanism to produce the answers.[45] He then had little more to publish on the subject; but the emergence of Hilbert modular forms in the dissertation of a student means his name is further attached to a major area.

He made a series of conjectures on class field theory. The concepts were highly influential, and his own contribution lives on in the names of the Hilbert class field and of the Hilbert symbol of local class field theory. Results were mostly proved by 1930, after work by Teiji Takagi.[k]

Hilbert did not work in the central areas of analytic number theory, but his name has become known for the Hilbert–Pólya conjecture, for reasons that are anecdotal.

Works Edit

His collected works (Gesammelte Abhandlungen) have been published several times. The original versions of his papers contained "many technical errors of varying degree";[46] when the collection was first published, the errors were corrected and it was found that this could be done without major changes in the statements of the theorems, with one exception—a claimed proof of the continuum hypothesis.[47][48] The errors were nonetheless so numerous and significant that it took Olga Taussky-Todd three years to make the corrections.[48]

See also Edit

Concepts Edit

Footnotes Edit

  1. ^ The Hilberts had, by this time, left the Calvinist Protestant church in which they had been baptized and married. – Reid 1996, p.91
  2. ^ David Hilbert seemed to be agnostic and had nothing to do with theology proper or even religion. Constance Reid tells a story on the subject:

    The Hilberts had by this time [around 1902] left the Reformed Protestant Church in which they had been baptized and married. It was told in Göttingen that when [David Hilbert's son] Franz had started to school he could not answer the question, "What religion are you?" (1970, p. 91)

    In the 1927 Hamburg address, Hilbert asserted: "mathematics is pre-suppositionless science (die Mathematik ist eine voraussetzungslose Wissenschaft)" and "to found it I do not need a good God ([z]u ihrer Begründung brauche ich weder den lieben Gott)" (1928, S. 85; van Heijenoort, 1967, p. 479). However, from Mathematische Probleme (1900) to Naturerkennen und Logik (1930) he placed his quasi-religious faith in the human spirit and in the power of pure thought with its beloved child– mathematics. He was deeply convinced that every mathematical problem could be solved by pure reason: in both mathematics and any part of natural science (through mathematics) there was "no ignorabimus" (Hilbert, 1900, S. 262; 1930, S. 963; Ewald, 1996, pp. 1102, 1165). That is why finding an inner absolute grounding for mathematics turned into Hilbert's life-work. He never gave up this position, and it is symbolic that his words "wir müssen wissen, wir werden wissen" ("we must know, we shall know") from his 1930 Königsberg address were engraved on his tombstone. Here, we meet a ghost of departed theology (to modify George Berkeley's words), for to absolutize human cognition means to identify it tacitly with a divine one. —Shaposhnikov, Vladislav (2016). "Theological Underpinnings of the Modern Philosophy of Mathematics. Part II: The Quest for Autonomous Foundations". Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric. 44 (1): 147–168. doi:10.1515/slgr-2016-0009.
  3. ^ "Mathematics is a presuppositionless science. To found it I do not need God, as does Kronecker, or the assumption of a special faculty of our understanding attuned to the principle of mathematical induction, as does Poincaré, or the primal intuition of Brouwer, or, finally, as do Russell and Whitehead, axioms of infinity, reducibility, or completeness, which in fact are actual, contentual assumptions that cannot be compensated for by consistency proofs." David Hilbert, Die Grundlagen der Mathematik, Hilbert's program, 22C:096, University of Iowa.
  4. ^ Michael R. Matthews (2009). Science, Worldviews and Education. Springer. p. 129. ISBN 978-90-481-2779-5. As is well known, Hilbert rejected Leopold Kronecker's God for the solution of the problem of the foundations of mathematics.
  5. ^ Constance Reid; Hermann Weyl (1970). Hilbert. Springer-Verlag. p. 92. ISBN 978-0-387-04999-1. Perhaps the guests would be discussing Galileo's trial and someone would blame Galileo for failing to stand up for his convictions. "But he was not an idiot," Hilbert would object. "Only an idiot could believe that scientific truth needs martyrdom; that may be necessary in religion, but scientific results prove themselves in due time."
  6. ^ "The Conference on Epistemology of the Exact Sciences ran for three days, from 5 to 7 September" (Dawson 1997:68). "It ... was held in conjunction with and just before the ninety-first annual meeting of the Society of German Scientists and Physicians ... and the sixth Assembly of German Physicists and Mathematicians.... Gödel's contributed talk took place on Saturday, 6 September [1930], from 3 until 3:20 in the afternoon, and on Sunday the meeting concluded with a round table discussion of the first day's addresses. During the latter event, without warning and almost offhandedly, Gödel quietly announced that "one can even give examples of propositions (and in fact of those of the type of Goldbach or Fermat) that, while contentually true, are unprovable in the formal system of classical mathematics [153]" (Dawson:69) "... As it happened, Hilbert himself was present at Königsberg, though apparently not at the Conference on Epistemology. The day after the roundtable discussion he delivered the opening address before the Society of German Scientists and Physicians – his famous lecture Naturerkennen und Logik (Logic and the knowledge of nature), at the end of which he declared: 'For the mathematician there is no Ignorabimus, and, in my opinion, not at all for natural science either. ... The true reason why [no-one] has succeeded in finding an unsolvable problem is, in my opinion, that there is no unsolvable problem. In contrast to the foolish Ignorabimus, our credo avers: We must know, We shall know [159]'"(Dawson:71). Gödel's paper was received on November 17, 1930 (cf Reid p. 197, van Heijenoort 1976:592) and published on 25 March 1931 (Dawson 1997:74). But Gödel had given a talk about it beforehand... "An abstract had been presented in October 1930 to the Vienna Academy of Sciences by Hans Hahn" (van Heijenoort:592); this abstract and the full paper both appear in van Heijenoort:583ff.
  7. ^ Independently and contemporaneously, a 19 year-old American student named Robert Lee Moore published an equivalent set of axioms. Some of the axioms coincide, while some of the axioms in Moore's system are theorems in Hilbert's and vice versa.[citation needed]
  8. ^ In time, associating the gravitational field equations with Hilbert's name became less and less common. A noticeable exception is P. Jordan (Schwerkraft und Weltall, Braunschweig, Vieweg, 1952), who called the equations of gravitation in the vacuum the Einstein–Hilbert equations. (Leo Corry, David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics, p. 437)
  9. ^ Since 1971 there have been some spirited and scholarly discussions about which of the two men first presented the now accepted form of the field equations. "Hilbert freely admitted, and frequently stated in lectures, that the great idea was Einstein's: "Every boy in the streets of Gottingen understands more about four dimensional geometry than Einstein," he once remarked. "Yet, in spite of that, Einstein did the work and not the mathematicians." (Reid 1996, pp. 141–142, also Isaacson 2007:222 quoting Thorne p. 119).
  10. ^ In 1926, the year after the matrix mechanics formulation of quantum theory by Max Born and Werner Heisenberg, the mathematician John von Neumann became an assistant to Hilbert at Göttingen. When von Neumann left in 1932, von Neumann's book on the mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics, based on Hilbert's mathematics, was published under the title Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik. See: Norman Macrae (1999) John von Neumann: The Scientific Genius Who Pioneered the Modern Computer, Game Theory, Nuclear Deterrence, and Much More (reprinted by the American Mathematical Society) and Reid (1996).
  11. ^ This work established Takagi as Japan's first mathematician of international stature.

Citations Edit

  1. ^ Weyl, H. (1944). "David Hilbert. 1862–1943". Obituary Notices of Fellows of the Royal Society. 4 (13): 547–553. doi:10.1098/rsbm.1944.0006. S2CID 161435959.
  2. ^ a b David Hilbert at the Mathematics Genealogy Project
  3. ^ "Hilbert". Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary.
  4. ^ Joyce, David. "The Mathematical Problems of David Hilbert". Clark University. Retrieved 15 January 2021.
  5. ^ Hilbert, David. "Mathematical Problems". Retrieved 15 January 2021.
  6. ^ Zach, Richard (31 July 2003). "Hilbert's Program". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 23 March 2009.
  7. ^ Reid 1996, pp. 1–2; also on p. 8, Reid notes that there is some ambiguity as to exactly where Hilbert was born. Hilbert himself stated that he was born in Königsberg.
  8. ^ Reid 1996, p. 4–7.
  9. ^ Reid 1996, p. 11.
  10. ^ Reid 1996, p. 12.
  11. ^ Weyl, Hermann (2012), "David Hilbert and his Mathematical Work", in Peter Pesic (ed.), Levels of Infinity/Selected writings on Mathematics and Philosophy, Dover, p. 94, ISBN 978-0-486-48903-2
  12. ^ Suzuki, Jeff (2009), Mathematics in Historical Context, Mathematical Association of America, p. 342, ISBN 978-0-88385-570-6
  13. ^ "The Mathematics Genealogy Project – David Hilbert". Retrieved 7 July 2007.
  14. ^ "David Hilbert". www.nasonline.org. Retrieved 30 June 2023.
  15. ^ David J. Darling (2004). The Universal Book of Mathematics. John Wiley and Sons. p. 151. ISBN 978-0-471-27047-8.
  16. ^ Reid 1996, p. 36.
  17. ^ Reid 1996, p. 139.
  18. ^ Reid 1996, p. 121.
  19. ^ Milkov, Nikolay; Peckhaus, Volker (1 January 2013). "The Berlin Group and the Vienna Circle: Affinities and Divergences". The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism (PDF). Boston Studies un the Philosophy and History of Science. Vol. 273. p. 20. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-5485-0_1. ISBN 978-94-007-5485-0. OCLC 7325392474. (PDF) from the original on 20 August 2014. Retrieved 19 May 2021.
  20. ^ 1992 (as told to Andrew Szanton). The Recollections of Eugene P. Wigner. Plenum. ISBN 0-306-44326-0
  21. ^ "APS Member History". search.amphilsoc.org. Retrieved 30 June 2023.
  22. ^ . Archived from the original on 5 November 2013. Retrieved 5 June 2013. (Hilbert's colleagues exiled)
  23. ^ Eckart Menzler-Trott: Gentzens Problem. Mathematische Logik im nationalsozialistischen Deutschland., Birkhäuser, 2001, ISBN 3-764-36574-9, Birkhäuser; Auflage: 2001 p. 142.
  24. ^ Hajo G. Meyer: Tragisches Schicksal. Das deutsche Judentum und die Wirkung historischer Kräfte: Eine Übung in angewandter Geschichtsphilosophie, Frank & Timme, 2008, ISBN 3-865-96174-6, p. 202.
  25. ^ Reid 1996, p. 213.
  26. ^ Reid 1996, p. 214.
  27. ^ Reid 1996, p. 192.
  28. ^ Reid 1996, p. 36–37.
  29. ^ Reid 1996, p. 34.
  30. ^ Reid 1996, p. 195.
  31. ^ a b Reid 1996, p. 37.
  32. ^ cf. Reid 1996, pp. 148–149.
  33. ^ Reid 1996, p. 148.
  34. ^ Reid 1996, p. 150.
  35. ^ Hilbert 1950
  36. ^ G. B. Mathews(1909) The Foundations of Geometry from Nature 80:394,5 (#2066)
  37. ^ Otto Blumenthal (1935). David Hilbert (ed.). . Gesammelte Abhandlungen. Vol. 3. Julius Springer. pp. 388–429. Archived from the original on 4 March 2016. Retrieved 6 September 2018. Here: p.402-403
  38. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original on 30 May 2009. Retrieved 11 September 2012.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link) CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link), archived from [www.seas.harvard.edu/courses/cs121/handouts/Hilbert.pdf]
  39. ^ Hilbert, D. (1919–20), Natur und Mathematisches Erkennen: Vorlesungen, gehalten 1919–1920 in G\"ottingen. Nach der Ausarbeitung von Paul Bernays (Edited and with an English introduction by David E. Rowe), Basel, Birkh\"auser (1992).
  40. ^ Reichenberger, Andrea (31 January 2019). "From Solvability to Formal Decidability: Revisiting Hilbert's "Non-Ignorabimus"". Journal of Humanistic Mathematics. 9 (1): 49–80. doi:10.5642/jhummath.201901.05. ISSN 2159-8118. S2CID 127398451.
  41. ^ Reid 1996, p. 129.
  42. ^ Isaacson 2007:218
  43. ^ Sauer 1999; Fölsing 1998[page needed]; Isaacson 2007:212
  44. ^ Isaacson 2007:213
  45. ^ Reid 1996, p. 114.
  46. ^ Reid 1996, chap. 13.
  47. ^ Sieg 2013, p. 284-285.
  48. ^ a b Rota G.-C. (1997), "Ten lessons I wish I had been taught", Notices of the AMS, 44: 22–25.

Sources Edit

Primary literature in English translation Edit

  • Ewald, William B., ed. (1996). From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    • 1918. "Axiomatic thought," 1114–1115.
    • 1922. "The new grounding of mathematics: First report," 1115–1133.
    • 1923. "The logical foundations of mathematics," 1134–1147.
    • 1930. "Logic and the knowledge of nature," 1157–1165.
    • 1931. "The grounding of elementary number theory," 1148–1156.
    • 1904. "On the foundations of logic and arithmetic," 129–138.
    • 1925. "On the infinite," 367–392.
    • 1927. "The foundations of mathematics," with comment by Weyl and Appendix by Bernays, 464–489.
  • van Heijenoort, Jean (1967). From Frege to Gödel: A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press.
  • Hilbert, David (1950) [1902]. The Foundations of Geometry [Grundlagen der Geometrie] (PDF). Translated by Townsend, E.J. (2nd ed.). La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing. (PDF) from the original on 28 December 2005.
  • Hilbert, David (1990) [1971]. Foundations of Geometry [Grundlagen der Geometrie]. Translated by Unger, Leo (2nd English ed.). La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing. ISBN 978-0-87548-164-7. translated from the 10th German edition
  • Hilbert, David; Cohn-Vossen, Stephan (1999). Geometry and Imagination. American Mathematical Society. ISBN 978-0-8218-1998-2. An accessible set of lectures originally for the citizens of Göttingen.
  • Hilbert, David (2004). Hallett, Michael; Majer, Ulrich (eds.). David Hilbert's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics and Physics, 1891–1933. Berlin & Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-540-64373-9.

Secondary literature Edit

External links Edit

david, hilbert, hilbert, redirects, here, other, uses, hilbert, disambiguation, german, ˈdaːvɪt, ˈhɪlbɐt, january, 1862, february, 1943, german, mathematician, most, influential, mathematicians, 19th, early, 20th, centuries, hilbert, discovered, developed, bro. Hilbert redirects here For other uses see Hilbert disambiguation David Hilbert ˈ h ɪ l b er t 3 German ˈdaːvɪt ˈhɪlbɐt 23 January 1862 14 February 1943 was a German mathematician and one of the most influential mathematicians of the 19th and early 20th centuries Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental ideas in many areas including invariant theory the calculus of variations commutative algebra algebraic number theory the foundations of geometry spectral theory of operators and its application to integral equations mathematical physics and the foundations of mathematics particularly proof theory David HilbertHilbert in 1912Born 1862 01 23 23 January 1862Konigsberg or Wehlau PrussiaDied14 February 1943 1943 02 14 aged 81 Gottingen GermanyNationalityGermanEducationUniversity of Konigsberg PhD Known forHilbert s basis theoremHilbert s axiomsHilbert s problemsHilbert s programEinstein Hilbert actionHilbert spaceEpsilon calculusSpouseKathe JeroschChildrenFranz b 1893 AwardsLobachevsky Prize 1903 Bolyai Prize 1910 ForMemRS 1 Scientific careerFieldsMathematics Physics and PhilosophyInstitutionsUniversity of KonigsbergGottingen UniversityThesisOn Invariant Properties of Special Binary Forms Especially of Spherical Functions 1885 Doctoral advisorFerdinand von Lindemann 2 Doctoral students Wilhelm AckermannHeinrich BehmannFelix BernsteinOtto BlumenthalAnne BosworthWerner BoyUgo BroggiRichard CourantHaskell CurryMax DehnLudwig FopplRudolf FueterPaul FunkKurt GrellingAlfred HaarErich HeckeEarle HedrickErnst HellingerWallie HurwitzMargarete KahnOliver KelloggHellmuth KneserRobert KonigEmanuel LaskerKlara LobensteinCharles Max MasonAlexander MyllerErhard SchmidtKurt SchutteAndreas SpeiserHugo SteinhausGabriel SudanTeiji TakagiHermann WeylErnst ZermeloOther notable studentsEdward KasnerJohn von NeumannHilbert adopted and defended Georg Cantor s set theory and transfinite numbers In 1900 he presented a collection of problems that set the course for much of the mathematical research of the 20th century 4 5 Hilbert and his students contributed significantly to establishing rigor and developed important tools used in modern mathematical physics Hilbert is known as one of the founders of proof theory and mathematical logic 6 Contents 1 Life 1 1 Early life and education 1 2 Career 1 3 Gottingen school 1 4 Personal life 1 5 Later years 1 6 Death 2 Contributions to mathematics and physics 2 1 Hilbert solves Gordan s Problem 2 2 Axiomatization of geometry 2 3 The 23 problems 2 4 Formalism 2 4 1 Hilbert s program 2 4 2 Godel s work 2 5 Functional analysis 2 6 Physics 2 7 Number theory 3 Works 4 See also 4 1 Concepts 4 2 Theorems 4 3 Other 5 Footnotes 6 Citations 7 Sources 7 1 Primary literature in English translation 7 2 Secondary literature 8 External linksLife EditEarly life and education Edit Hilbert the first of two children and only son of Otto and Maria Therese Erdtmann Hilbert was born in the Province of Prussia Kingdom of Prussia either in Konigsberg according to Hilbert s own statement or in Wehlau known since 1946 as Znamensk near Konigsberg where his father worked at the time of his birth 7 In late 1872 Hilbert entered the Friedrichskolleg Gymnasium Collegium fridericianum the same school that Immanuel Kant had attended 140 years before but after an unhappy period he transferred to late 1879 and graduated from early 1880 the more science oriented Wilhelm Gymnasium 8 Upon graduation in autumn 1880 Hilbert enrolled at the University of Konigsberg the Albertina In early 1882 Hermann Minkowski two years younger than Hilbert and also a native of Konigsberg but had gone to Berlin for three semesters 9 returned to Konigsberg and entered the university Hilbert developed a lifelong friendship with the shy gifted Minkowski 10 11 Career Edit nbsp Hilbert in 1886 nbsp Hilbert in 1907 In 1884 Adolf Hurwitz arrived from Gottingen as an Extraordinarius i e an associate professor An intense and fruitful scientific exchange among the three began and Minkowski and Hilbert especially would exercise a reciprocal influence over each other at various times in their scientific careers Hilbert obtained his doctorate in 1885 with a dissertation written under Ferdinand von Lindemann 2 titled Uber invariante Eigenschaften spezieller binarer Formen insbesondere der Kugelfunktionen On the invariant properties of special binary forms in particular the spherical harmonic functions Hilbert remained at the University of Konigsberg as a Privatdozent senior lecturer from 1886 to 1895 In 1895 as a result of intervention on his behalf by Felix Klein he obtained the position of Professor of Mathematics at the University of Gottingen During the Klein and Hilbert years Gottingen became the preeminent institution in the mathematical world 12 He remained there for the rest of his life nbsp The Mathematical Institute in Gottingen Its new building constructed with funds from the Rockefeller Foundation was opened by Hilbert and Courant in 1930 Gottingen school Edit Among Hilbert s students were Hermann Weyl chess champion Emanuel Lasker Ernst Zermelo and Carl Gustav Hempel John von Neumann was his assistant At the University of Gottingen Hilbert was surrounded by a social circle of some of the most important mathematicians of the 20th century such as Emmy Noether and Alonzo Church Among his 69 Ph D students in Gottingen were many who later became famous mathematicians including with date of thesis Otto Blumenthal 1898 Felix Bernstein 1901 Hermann Weyl 1908 Richard Courant 1910 Erich Hecke 1910 Hugo Steinhaus 1911 and Wilhelm Ackermann 1925 13 Between 1902 and 1939 Hilbert was editor of the Mathematische Annalen the leading mathematical journal of the time He was elected an International Member of the United States National Academy of Sciences in 1907 14 Good he did not have enough imagination to become a mathematician Hilbert s response upon hearing that one of his students had dropped out to study poetry 15 Personal life Edit nbsp Kathe Hilbert with Constantin Caratheodory before 1932 nbsp Hilbert and his wife Kathe Jerosch 1892 nbsp Franz Hilbert In 1892 Hilbert married Kathe Jerosch 1864 1945 who was the daughter of a Konigsberg merchant an outspoken young lady with an independence of mind that matched Hilbert s 16 While at Konigsberg they had their one child Franz Hilbert de 1893 1969 Franz suffered throughout his life from an undiagnosed mental illness His inferior intellect was a terrible disappointment to his father and this misfortune was a matter of distress to the mathematicians and students at Gottingen 17 Hilbert considered the mathematician Hermann Minkowski to be his best and truest friend 18 Hilbert was baptized and raised a Calvinist in the Prussian Evangelical Church a He later left the Church and became an agnostic b He also argued that mathematical truth was independent of the existence of God or other a priori assumptions c d When Galileo Galilei was criticized for failing to stand up for his convictions on the Heliocentric theory Hilbert objected But Galileo was not an idiot Only an idiot could believe that scientific truth needs martyrdom that may be necessary in religion but scientific results prove themselves in due time e Later years Edit Like Albert Einstein Hilbert had closest contacts with the Berlin Group whose leading founders had studied under Hilbert in Gottingen Kurt Grelling Hans Reichenbach and Walter Dubislav 19 Around 1925 Hilbert developed pernicious anemia a then untreatable vitamin deficiency whose primary symptom is exhaustion his assistant Eugene Wigner described him as subject to enormous fatigue and how he seemed quite old and that even after eventually being diagnosed and treated he was hardly a scientist after 1925 and certainly not a Hilbert 20 Hilbert was elected to the American Philosophical Society in 1932 21 Hilbert lived to see the Nazis purge many of the prominent faculty members at University of Gottingen in 1933 22 Those forced out included Hermann Weyl who had taken Hilbert s chair when he retired in 1930 Emmy Noether and Edmund Landau One who had to leave Germany Paul Bernays had collaborated with Hilbert in mathematical logic and co authored with him the important book Grundlagen der Mathematik which eventually appeared in two volumes in 1934 and 1939 This was a sequel to the Hilbert Ackermann book Principles of Mathematical Logic from 1928 Hermann Weyl s successor was Helmut Hasse About a year later Hilbert attended a banquet and was seated next to the new Minister of Education Bernhard Rust Rust asked whether the Mathematical Institute really suffered so much because of the departure of the Jews Hilbert replied Suffered It doesn t exist any longer does it 23 24 Death Edit nbsp Hilbert s tomb Wir mussen wissenWir werden wissenBy the time Hilbert died in 1943 the Nazis had nearly completely restaffed the university as many of the former faculty had either been Jewish or married to Jews Hilbert s funeral was attended by fewer than a dozen people only two of whom were fellow academics among them Arnold Sommerfeld a theoretical physicist and also a native of Konigsberg 25 News of his death only became known to the wider world several months after he died 26 The epitaph on his tombstone in Gottingen consists of the famous lines he spoke at the conclusion of his retirement address to the Society of German Scientists and Physicians on 8 September 1930 The words were given in response to the Latin maxim Ignoramus et ignorabimus or We do not know and we shall not know 27 Wir mussen wissen Wir werden wissen We must know We shall know The day before Hilbert pronounced these phrases at the 1930 annual meeting of the Society of German Scientists and Physicians Kurt Godel in a round table discussion during the Conference on Epistemology held jointly with the Society meetings tentatively announced the first expression of his incompleteness theorem f Godel s incompleteness theorems show that even elementary axiomatic systems such as Peano arithmetic are either self contradicting or contain logical propositions that are impossible to prove or disprove within that system Contributions to mathematics and physics EditHilbert solves Gordan s Problem Edit Hilbert s first work on invariant functions led him to the demonstration in 1888 of his famous finiteness theorem Twenty years earlier Paul Gordan had demonstrated the theorem of the finiteness of generators for binary forms using a complex computational approach Attempts to generalize his method to functions with more than two variables failed because of the enormous difficulty of the calculations involved To solve what had become known in some circles as Gordan s Problem Hilbert realized that it was necessary to take a completely different path As a result he demonstrated Hilbert s basis theorem showing the existence of a finite set of generators for the invariants of quantics in any number of variables but in an abstract form That is while demonstrating the existence of such a set it was not a constructive proof it did not display an object but rather it was an existence proof 28 and relied on use of the law of excluded middle in an infinite extension Hilbert sent his results to the Mathematische Annalen Gordan the house expert on the theory of invariants for the Mathematische Annalen could not appreciate the revolutionary nature of Hilbert s theorem and rejected the article criticizing the exposition because it was insufficiently comprehensive His comment was Das ist nicht Mathematik Das ist Theologie This is not Mathematics This is Theology 29 Klein on the other hand recognized the importance of the work and guaranteed that it would be published without any alterations Encouraged by Klein Hilbert extended his method in a second article providing estimations on the maximum degree of the minimum set of generators and he sent it once more to the Annalen After having read the manuscript Klein wrote to him saying Without doubt this is the most important work on general algebra that the Annalen has ever published 30 Later after the usefulness of Hilbert s method was universally recognized Gordan himself would say I have convinced myself that even theology has its merits 31 For all his successes the nature of his proof created more trouble than Hilbert could have imagined Although Kronecker had conceded Hilbert would later respond to others similar criticisms that many different constructions are subsumed under one fundamental idea in other words to quote Reid Through a proof of existence Hilbert had been able to obtain a construction the proof i e the symbols on the page was the object 31 Not all were convinced While Kronecker would die soon afterwards his constructivist philosophy would continue with the young Brouwer and his developing intuitionist school much to Hilbert s torment in his later years 32 Indeed Hilbert would lose his gifted pupil Weyl to intuitionism Hilbert was disturbed by his former student s fascination with the ideas of Brouwer which aroused in Hilbert the memory of Kronecker 33 Brouwer the intuitionist in particular opposed the use of the Law of Excluded Middle over infinite sets as Hilbert had used it Hilbert responded Taking the Principle of the Excluded Middle from the mathematician is the same as prohibiting the boxer the use of his fists 34 Axiomatization of geometry Edit Main article Hilbert s axioms The text Grundlagen der Geometrie tr Foundations of Geometry published by Hilbert in 1899 proposes a formal set called Hilbert s axioms substituting for the traditional axioms of Euclid They avoid weaknesses identified in those of Euclid whose works at the time were still used textbook fashion It is difficult to specify the axioms used by Hilbert without referring to the publication history of the Grundlagen since Hilbert changed and modified them several times The original monograph was quickly followed by a French translation in which Hilbert added V 2 the Completeness Axiom An English translation authorized by Hilbert was made by E J Townsend and copyrighted in 1902 35 36 This translation incorporated the changes made in the French translation and so is considered to be a translation of the 2nd edition Hilbert continued to make changes in the text and several editions appeared in German The 7th edition was the last to appear in Hilbert s lifetime New editions followed the 7th but the main text was essentially not revised g Hilbert s approach signaled the shift to the modern axiomatic method In this Hilbert was anticipated by Moritz Pasch s work from 1882 Axioms are not taken as self evident truths Geometry may treat things about which we have powerful intuitions but it is not necessary to assign any explicit meaning to the undefined concepts The elements such as point line plane and others could be substituted as Hilbert is reported to have said to Schoenflies and Kotter by tables chairs glasses of beer and other such objects 37 It is their defined relationships that are discussed Hilbert first enumerates the undefined concepts point line plane lying on a relation between points and lines points and planes and lines and planes betweenness congruence of pairs of points line segments and congruence of angles The axioms unify both the plane geometry and solid geometry of Euclid in a single system The 23 problems Edit Main article Hilbert s problems Hilbert put forth the most influential list consisting of 23 unsolved problems at the International Congress of Mathematicians in Paris in 1900 This is generally reckoned as the most successful and deeply considered compilation of open problems ever to be produced by an individual mathematician by whom After re working the foundations of classical geometry Hilbert could have extrapolated to the rest of mathematics His approach differed however from the later foundationalist Russell Whitehead or encyclopedist Nicolas Bourbaki and from his contemporary Giuseppe Peano The mathematical community as a whole could engage in problems of which he had identified as crucial aspects of important areas of mathematics The problem set was launched as a talk The Problems of Mathematics presented during the course of the Second International Congress of Mathematicians held in Paris The introduction of the speech that Hilbert gave said Who among us would not be happy to lift the veil behind which is hidden the future to gaze at the coming developments of our science and at the secrets of its development in the centuries to come What will be the ends toward which the spirit of future generations of mathematicians will tend What methods what new facts will the new century reveal in the vast and rich field of mathematical thought 38 He presented fewer than half the problems at the Congress which were published in the acts of the Congress In a subsequent publication he extended the panorama and arrived at the formulation of the now canonical 23 Problems of Hilbert See also Hilbert s twenty fourth problem The full text is important since the exegesis of the questions still can be a matter of inevitable debate whenever it is asked how many have been solved Some of these were solved within a short time Others have been discussed throughout the 20th century with a few now taken to be unsuitably open ended to come to closure Some continue to remain challenges Formalism Edit In an account that had become standard by the mid century Hilbert s problem set was also a kind of manifesto that opened the way for the development of the formalist school one of three major schools of mathematics of the 20th century According to the formalist mathematics is manipulation of symbols according to agreed upon formal rules It is therefore an autonomous activity of thought There is however room to doubt whether Hilbert s own views were simplistically formalist in this sense Hilbert s program Edit Main article Hilbert s program In 1920 Hilbert proposed a research project in metamathematics that became known as Hilbert s program He wanted mathematics to be formulated on a solid and complete logical foundation He believed that in principle this could be done by showing that all of mathematics follows from a correctly chosen finite system of axioms and that some such axiom system is provably consistent through some means such as the epsilon calculus He seems to have had both technical and philosophical reasons for formulating this proposal It affirmed his dislike of what had become known as the ignorabimus still an active issue in his time in German thought and traced back in that formulation to Emil du Bois Reymond This program is still recognizable in the most popular philosophy of mathematics where it is usually called formalism For example the Bourbaki group adopted a watered down and selective version of it as adequate to the requirements of their twin projects of a writing encyclopedic foundational works and b supporting the axiomatic method as a research tool This approach has been successful and influential in relation with Hilbert s work in algebra and functional analysis but has failed to engage in the same way with his interests in physics and logic Hilbert wrote in 1919 We are not speaking here of arbitrariness in any sense Mathematics is not like a game whose tasks are determined by arbitrarily stipulated rules Rather it is a conceptual system possessing internal necessity that can only be so and by no means otherwise 39 Hilbert published his views on the foundations of mathematics in the 2 volume work Grundlagen der Mathematik Godel s work Edit Hilbert and the mathematicians who worked with him in his enterprise were committed to the project His attempt to support axiomatized mathematics with definitive principles which could banish theoretical uncertainties ended in failure Godel demonstrated that any non contradictory formal system which was comprehensive enough to include at least arithmetic cannot demonstrate its completeness by way of its own axioms In 1931 his incompleteness theorem showed that Hilbert s grand plan was impossible as stated The second point cannot in any reasonable way be combined with the first point as long as the axiom system is genuinely finitary Nevertheless the subsequent achievements of proof theory at the very least clarified consistency as it relates to theories of central concern to mathematicians Hilbert s work had started logic on this course of clarification the need to understand Godel s work then led to the development of recursion theory and then mathematical logic as an autonomous discipline in the 1930s The basis for later theoretical computer science in the work of Alonzo Church and Alan Turing also grew directly out of this debate 40 Functional analysis Edit Around 1909 Hilbert dedicated himself to the study of differential and integral equations his work had direct consequences for important parts of modern functional analysis In order to carry out these studies Hilbert introduced the concept of an infinite dimensional Euclidean space later called Hilbert space His work in this part of analysis provided the basis for important contributions to the mathematics of physics in the next two decades though from an unanticipated direction Later on Stefan Banach amplified the concept defining Banach spaces Hilbert spaces are an important class of objects in the area of functional analysis particularly of the spectral theory of self adjoint linear operators that grew up around it during the 20th century Physics Edit Until 1912 Hilbert was almost exclusively a pure mathematician When planning a visit from Bonn where he was immersed in studying physics his fellow mathematician and friend Hermann Minkowski joked he had to spend 10 days in quarantine before being able to visit Hilbert In fact Minkowski seems responsible for most of Hilbert s physics investigations prior to 1912 including their joint seminar on the subject in 1905 In 1912 three years after his friend s death Hilbert turned his focus to the subject almost exclusively He arranged to have a physics tutor for himself 41 He started studying kinetic gas theory and moved on to elementary radiation theory and the molecular theory of matter Even after the war started in 1914 he continued seminars and classes where the works of Albert Einstein and others were followed closely By 1907 Einstein had framed the fundamentals of the theory of gravity but then struggled for nearly 8 years to put the theory into its final form 42 By early summer 1915 Hilbert s interest in physics had focused on general relativity and he invited Einstein to Gottingen to deliver a week of lectures on the subject 43 Einstein received an enthusiastic reception at Gottingen 44 Over the summer Einstein learned that Hilbert was also working on the field equations and redoubled his own efforts During November 1915 Einstein published several papers culminating in The Field Equations of Gravitation see Einstein field equations h Nearly simultaneously Hilbert published The Foundations of Physics an axiomatic derivation of the field equations see Einstein Hilbert action Hilbert fully credited Einstein as the originator of the theory and no public priority dispute concerning the field equations ever arose between the two men during their lives i See more at priority Additionally Hilbert s work anticipated and assisted several advances in the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics His work was a key aspect of Hermann Weyl and John von Neumann s work on the mathematical equivalence of Werner Heisenberg s matrix mechanics and Erwin Schrodinger s wave equation and his namesake Hilbert space plays an important part in quantum theory In 1926 von Neumann showed that if quantum states were understood as vectors in Hilbert space they would correspond with both Schrodinger s wave function theory and Heisenberg s matrices j Throughout this immersion in physics Hilbert worked on putting rigor into the mathematics of physics While highly dependent on higher mathematics physicists tended to be sloppy with it To a pure mathematician like Hilbert this was both ugly and difficult to understand As he began to understand physics and how physicists were using mathematics he developed a coherent mathematical theory for what he found most importantly in the area of integral equations When his colleague Richard Courant wrote the now classic Methoden der mathematischen Physik Methods of Mathematical Physics including some of Hilbert s ideas he added Hilbert s name as author even though Hilbert had not directly contributed to the writing Hilbert said Physics is too hard for physicists implying that the necessary mathematics was generally beyond them the Courant Hilbert book made it easier for them Number theory Edit Hilbert unified the field of algebraic number theory with his 1897 treatise Zahlbericht literally report on numbers He also resolved a significant number theory problem formulated by Waring in 1770 As with the finiteness theorem he used an existence proof that shows there must be solutions for the problem rather than providing a mechanism to produce the answers 45 He then had little more to publish on the subject but the emergence of Hilbert modular forms in the dissertation of a student means his name is further attached to a major area He made a series of conjectures on class field theory The concepts were highly influential and his own contribution lives on in the names of the Hilbert class field and of the Hilbert symbol of local class field theory Results were mostly proved by 1930 after work by Teiji Takagi k Hilbert did not work in the central areas of analytic number theory but his name has become known for the Hilbert Polya conjecture for reasons that are anecdotal Works EditHis collected works Gesammelte Abhandlungen have been published several times The original versions of his papers contained many technical errors of varying degree 46 when the collection was first published the errors were corrected and it was found that this could be done without major changes in the statements of the theorems with one exception a claimed proof of the continuum hypothesis 47 48 The errors were nonetheless so numerous and significant that it took Olga Taussky Todd three years to make the corrections 48 See also Edit nbsp Biography portal nbsp Philosophy portalConcepts Edit List of things named after David Hilbert Foundations of geometry Hilbert C module Hilbert cube Hilbert curve Hilbert matrix Hilbert metric Hilbert Mumford criterion Hilbert number Hilbert ring Hilbert Poincare series Hilbert series and Hilbert polynomial Hilbert space Hilbert spectrum Hilbert system Hilbert transform Hilbert s arithmetic of ends Hilbert s paradox of the Grand Hotel Hilbert Schmidt operator Hilbert Smith conjectureTheorems Edit Hilbert Burch theorem Hilbert s irreducibility theorem Hilbert s Nullstellensatz Hilbert s theorem differential geometry Hilbert s Theorem 90 Hilbert s syzygy theorem Hilbert Speiser theoremOther Edit Brouwer Hilbert controversy Direct method in the calculus of variations Entscheidungsproblem Geometry and the Imagination General relativity priority disputeFootnotes Edit The Hilberts had by this time left the Calvinist Protestant church in which they had been baptized and married Reid 1996 p 91 David Hilbert seemed to be agnostic and had nothing to do with theology proper or even religion Constance Reid tells a story on the subject The Hilberts had by this time around 1902 left the Reformed Protestant Church in which they had been baptized and married It was told in Gottingen that when David Hilbert s son Franz had started to school he could not answer the question What religion are you 1970 p 91 In the 1927 Hamburg address Hilbert asserted mathematics is pre suppositionless science die Mathematik ist eine voraussetzungslose Wissenschaft and to found it I do not need a good God z u ihrer Begrundung brauche ich weder den lieben Gott 1928 S 85 van Heijenoort 1967 p 479 However from Mathematische Probleme 1900 to Naturerkennen und Logik 1930 he placed his quasi religious faith in the human spirit and in the power of pure thought with its beloved child mathematics He was deeply convinced that every mathematical problem could be solved by pure reason in both mathematics and any part of natural science through mathematics there was no ignorabimus Hilbert 1900 S 262 1930 S 963 Ewald 1996 pp 1102 1165 That is why finding an inner absolute grounding for mathematics turned into Hilbert s life work He never gave up this position and it is symbolic that his words wir mussen wissen wir werden wissen we must know we shall know from his 1930 Konigsberg address were engraved on his tombstone Here we meet a ghost of departed theology to modify George Berkeley s words for to absolutize human cognition means to identify it tacitly with a divine one Shaposhnikov Vladislav 2016 Theological Underpinnings of the Modern Philosophy of Mathematics Part II The Quest for Autonomous Foundations Studies in Logic Grammar and Rhetoric 44 1 147 168 doi 10 1515 slgr 2016 0009 Mathematics is a presuppositionless science To found it I do not need God as does Kronecker or the assumption of a special faculty of our understanding attuned to the principle of mathematical induction as does Poincare or the primal intuition of Brouwer or finally as do Russell and Whitehead axioms of infinity reducibility or completeness which in fact are actual contentual assumptions that cannot be compensated for by consistency proofs David Hilbert Die Grundlagen der Mathematik Hilbert s program 22C 096 University of Iowa Michael R Matthews 2009 Science Worldviews and Education Springer p 129 ISBN 978 90 481 2779 5 As is well known Hilbert rejected Leopold Kronecker s God for the solution of the problem of the foundations of mathematics Constance Reid Hermann Weyl 1970 Hilbert Springer Verlag p 92 ISBN 978 0 387 04999 1 Perhaps the guests would be discussing Galileo s trial and someone would blame Galileo for failing to stand up for his convictions But he was not an idiot Hilbert would object Only an idiot could believe that scientific truth needs martyrdom that may be necessary in religion but scientific results prove themselves in due time The Conference on Epistemology of the Exact Sciences ran for three days from 5 to 7 September Dawson 1997 68 It was held in conjunction with and just before the ninety first annual meeting of the Society of German Scientists and Physicians and the sixth Assembly of German Physicists and Mathematicians Godel s contributed talk took place on Saturday 6 September 1930 from 3 until 3 20 in the afternoon and on Sunday the meeting concluded with a round table discussion of the first day s addresses During the latter event without warning and almost offhandedly Godel quietly announced that one can even give examples of propositions and in fact of those of the type of Goldbach or Fermat that while contentually true are unprovable in the formal system of classical mathematics 153 Dawson 69 As it happened Hilbert himself was present at Konigsberg though apparently not at the Conference on Epistemology The day after the roundtable discussion he delivered the opening address before the Society of German Scientists and Physicians his famous lecture Naturerkennen und Logik Logic and the knowledge of nature at the end of which he declared For the mathematician there is no Ignorabimus and in my opinion not at all for natural science either The true reason why no one has succeeded in finding an unsolvable problem is in my opinion that there is no unsolvable problem In contrast to the foolish Ignorabimus our credo avers We must know We shall know 159 Dawson 71 Godel s paper was received on November 17 1930 cf Reid p 197 van Heijenoort 1976 592 and published on 25 March 1931 Dawson 1997 74 But Godel had given a talk about it beforehand An abstract had been presented in October 1930 to the Vienna Academy of Sciences by Hans Hahn van Heijenoort 592 this abstract and the full paper both appear in van Heijenoort 583ff Independently and contemporaneously a 19 year old American student named Robert Lee Moore published an equivalent set of axioms Some of the axioms coincide while some of the axioms in Moore s system are theorems in Hilbert s and vice versa citation needed In time associating the gravitational field equations with Hilbert s name became less and less common A noticeable exception is P Jordan Schwerkraft und Weltall Braunschweig Vieweg 1952 who called the equations of gravitation in the vacuum the Einstein Hilbert equations Leo Corry David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics p 437 Since 1971 there have been some spirited and scholarly discussions about which of the two men first presented the now accepted form of the field equations Hilbert freely admitted and frequently stated in lectures that the great idea was Einstein s Every boy in the streets of Gottingen understands more about four dimensional geometry than Einstein he once remarked Yet in spite of that Einstein did the work and not the mathematicians Reid 1996 pp 141 142 also Isaacson 2007 222 quoting Thorne p 119 In 1926 the year after the matrix mechanics formulation of quantum theory by Max Born and Werner Heisenberg the mathematician John von Neumann became an assistant to Hilbert at Gottingen When von Neumann left in 1932 von Neumann s book on the mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics based on Hilbert s mathematics was published under the title Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik See Norman Macrae 1999 John von Neumann The Scientific Genius Who Pioneered the Modern Computer Game Theory Nuclear Deterrence and Much More reprinted by the American Mathematical Society and Reid 1996 This work established Takagi as Japan s first mathematician of international stature Citations Edit Weyl H 1944 David Hilbert 1862 1943 Obituary Notices of Fellows of the Royal Society 4 13 547 553 doi 10 1098 rsbm 1944 0006 S2CID 161435959 a b David Hilbert at the Mathematics Genealogy Project Hilbert Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary Joyce David The Mathematical Problems of David Hilbert Clark University Retrieved 15 January 2021 Hilbert David Mathematical Problems Retrieved 15 January 2021 Zach Richard 31 July 2003 Hilbert s Program Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 23 March 2009 Reid 1996 pp 1 2 also on p 8 Reid notes that there is some ambiguity as to exactly where Hilbert was born Hilbert himself stated that he was born in Konigsberg Reid 1996 p 4 7 Reid 1996 p 11 Reid 1996 p 12 Weyl Hermann 2012 David Hilbert and his Mathematical Work in Peter Pesic ed Levels of Infinity Selected writings on Mathematics and Philosophy Dover p 94 ISBN 978 0 486 48903 2 Suzuki Jeff 2009 Mathematics in Historical Context Mathematical Association of America p 342 ISBN 978 0 88385 570 6 The Mathematics Genealogy Project David Hilbert Retrieved 7 July 2007 David Hilbert www nasonline org Retrieved 30 June 2023 David J Darling 2004 The Universal Book of Mathematics John Wiley and Sons p 151 ISBN 978 0 471 27047 8 Reid 1996 p 36 Reid 1996 p 139 Reid 1996 p 121 Milkov Nikolay Peckhaus Volker 1 January 2013 The Berlin Group and the Vienna Circle Affinities and Divergences The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism PDF Boston Studies un the Philosophy and History of Science Vol 273 p 20 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 5485 0 1 ISBN 978 94 007 5485 0 OCLC 7325392474 Archived PDF from the original on 20 August 2014 Retrieved 19 May 2021 1992 as told to Andrew Szanton The Recollections of Eugene P Wigner Plenum ISBN 0 306 44326 0 APS Member History search amphilsoc org Retrieved 30 June 2023 Shame at Gottingen Archived from the original on 5 November 2013 Retrieved 5 June 2013 Hilbert s colleagues exiled Eckart Menzler Trott Gentzens Problem Mathematische Logik im nationalsozialistischen Deutschland Birkhauser 2001 ISBN 3 764 36574 9 Birkhauser Auflage 2001 p 142 Hajo G Meyer Tragisches Schicksal Das deutsche Judentum und die Wirkung historischer Krafte Eine Ubung in angewandter Geschichtsphilosophie Frank amp Timme 2008 ISBN 3 865 96174 6 p 202 Reid 1996 p 213 Reid 1996 p 214 Reid 1996 p 192 Reid 1996 p 36 37 Reid 1996 p 34 Reid 1996 p 195 a b Reid 1996 p 37 cf Reid 1996 pp 148 149 Reid 1996 p 148 Reid 1996 p 150 Hilbert 1950 G B Mathews 1909 The Foundations of Geometry from Nature 80 394 5 2066 Otto Blumenthal 1935 David Hilbert ed Lebensgeschichte Gesammelte Abhandlungen Vol 3 Julius Springer pp 388 429 Archived from the original on 4 March 2016 Retrieved 6 September 2018 Here p 402 403 Archived copy PDF Archived from the original on 30 May 2009 Retrieved 11 September 2012 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link CS1 maint bot original URL status unknown link archived from www seas harvard edu courses cs121 handouts Hilbert pdf Hilbert D 1919 20 Natur und Mathematisches Erkennen Vorlesungen gehalten 1919 1920 in G ottingen Nach der Ausarbeitung von Paul Bernays Edited and with an English introduction by David E Rowe Basel Birkh auser 1992 Reichenberger Andrea 31 January 2019 From Solvability to Formal Decidability Revisiting Hilbert s Non Ignorabimus Journal of Humanistic Mathematics 9 1 49 80 doi 10 5642 jhummath 201901 05 ISSN 2159 8118 S2CID 127398451 Reid 1996 p 129 Isaacson 2007 218 Sauer 1999 Folsing 1998 page needed Isaacson 2007 212 Isaacson 2007 213 Reid 1996 p 114 Reid 1996 chap 13 Sieg 2013 p 284 285 a b Rota G C 1997 Ten lessons I wish I had been taught Notices of the AMS 44 22 25 Sources EditPrimary literature in English translation Edit Ewald William B ed 1996 From Kant to Hilbert A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics Oxford UK Oxford University Press 1918 Axiomatic thought 1114 1115 1922 The new grounding of mathematics First report 1115 1133 1923 The logical foundations of mathematics 1134 1147 1930 Logic and the knowledge of nature 1157 1165 1931 The grounding of elementary number theory 1148 1156 1904 On the foundations of logic and arithmetic 129 138 1925 On the infinite 367 392 1927 The foundations of mathematics with comment by Weyl and Appendix by Bernays 464 489 van Heijenoort Jean 1967 From Frege to Godel A source book in mathematical logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press Hilbert David 1950 1902 The Foundations of Geometry Grundlagen der Geometrie PDF Translated by Townsend E J 2nd ed La Salle IL Open Court Publishing Archived PDF from the original on 28 December 2005 Hilbert David 1990 1971 Foundations of Geometry Grundlagen der Geometrie Translated by Unger Leo 2nd English ed La Salle IL Open Court Publishing ISBN 978 0 87548 164 7 translated from the 10th German edition Hilbert David Cohn Vossen Stephan 1999 Geometry and Imagination American Mathematical Society ISBN 978 0 8218 1998 2 An accessible set of lectures originally for the citizens of Gottingen Hilbert David 2004 Hallett Michael Majer Ulrich eds David Hilbert s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics and Physics 1891 1933 Berlin amp Heidelberg Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 540 64373 9 Secondary literature Edit Bertrand Gabriel 20 December 1943b Allocution Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des seances de l Academie des sciences in French Paris 217 625 640 available at Gallica The Address of Gabriel Bertrand of 20 December 1943 at the French Academy he gives biographical sketches of the lives of recently deceased members including Pieter Zeeman David Hilbert and Georges Giraud Bottazzini Umberto 2003 Il flauto di Hilbert Storia della matematica UTET ISBN 88 7750 852 3 Corry L Renn J and Stachel J 1997 Belated Decision in the Hilbert Einstein Priority Dispute Science 278 nn nn Corry Leo 2004 David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics 1898 1918 From Grundlagen der Geometrie to Grundlagen der Physik Springer ISBN 90 481 6719 1 Dawson John W Jr 1997 Logical Dilemmas The Life and Work of Kurt Godel Wellesley MA A K Peters ISBN 1 56881 256 6 Folsing Albrecht 1998 Albert Einstein Penguin Grattan Guinness Ivor 2000 The Search for Mathematical Roots 1870 1940 Princeton Univ Press Gray Jeremy 2000 The Hilbert Challenge ISBN 0 19 850651 1 Mancosu Paolo 1998 From Brouwer to Hilbert The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in 1920s Oxford Univ Press ISBN 978 0 19 509631 6 Mehra Jagdish 1974 Einstein Hilbert and the Theory of Gravitation Reidel Piergiorgio Odifreddi 2003 Divertimento Geometrico Le origini geometriche della logica da Euclide a Hilbert Bollati Boringhieri ISBN 88 339 5714 4 A clear exposition of the errors of Euclid and of the solutions presented in the Grundlagen der Geometrie with reference to non Euclidean geometry Reid Constance 1996 Hilbert New York Springer ISBN 0 387 94674 8 The definitive English language biography of Hilbert Rowe D E 1989 Klein Hilbert and the Gottingen Mathematical Tradition Osiris 5 186 213 doi 10 1086 368687 S2CID 121068952 Sauer Tilman 1999 The relativity of discovery Hilbert s first note on the foundations of physics Arch Hist Exact Sci 53 529 75 arXiv physics 9811050 Bibcode 1998physics 11050S Sieg Wilfried 2013 Hilbert s Programs and Beyond Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 537222 9 Sieg Wilfried and Ravaglia Mark 2005 Grundlagen der Mathematik in Grattan Guinness I ed Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics Elsevier 981 99 in English Thorne Kip 1995 Black Holes and Time Warps Einstein s Outrageous Legacy W W Norton amp Company Reprint edition ISBN 0 393 31276 3 External links Edit nbsp Wikisource has original works by or about David Hilbert nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to David Hilbert nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to David Hilbert Hilbert Bernays Project Hilbert s 23 Problems Address ICMM 2014 dedicated to the memory of D Hilbert Works by David Hilbert at Project Gutenberg Works by or about David Hilbert at Internet Archive Works by David Hilbert at LibriVox public domain audiobooks nbsp Hilbert s radio speech recorded in Konigsberg 1930 in German Archived 14 February 2006 at the Wayback Machine with English translation Archived 12 November 2020 at the Wayback Machine Wolfram MathWorld Hilbert Constant David Hilbert at the Mathematics Genealogy Project O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F David Hilbert MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews From Hilbert s Problems to the Future lecture by Professor Robin Wilson Gresham College 27 February 2008 available in text audio and video formats Newspaper clippings about David Hilbert in the 20th Century Press Archives of the ZBW Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title David Hilbert amp oldid 1181649488, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.