fbpx
Wikipedia

Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant (UK: /kænt/,[20][21] US: /kɑːnt/,[22][23] German: [ɪˈmaːnu̯eːl ˈkant];[24][25] 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers.[26][27] Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western philosophy.[26][28]

Immanuel Kant
Portrait by Johann Gottlieb Becker, 1768
Born(1724-04-22)22 April 1724
Died12 February 1804(1804-02-12) (aged 79)
Königsberg, East Prussia, Kingdom of Prussia
EducationCollegium Fridericianum
University of Königsberg
(BA; MA, April 1755; PhD, September 1755; PhD,[1] August 1770)
EraAge of Enlightenment
RegionWestern philosophy
School
InstitutionsUniversity of Königsberg
Theses
  • Principiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio (September 1755)
  • De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis (August 1770)
Academic advisorsMartin Knutzen, Johann Gottfried Teske (M.A. advisor), Konrad Gottlieb Marquardt[11]
Notable studentsJakob Sigismund Beck, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Johann Gottfried Herder, Karl Leonhard Reinhold (epistolary correspondent)[19]
Main interests
Aesthetics, cosmogony, epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, systematic philosophy
Notable ideas
Influences
Influenced
Signature

In his doctrine of transcendental idealism, Kant argued that space and time are mere "forms of intuition" which structure all experience, and therefore, while "things-in-themselves" exist and contribute to experience, they are nonetheless distinct from the objects of experience. From this it follows that the objects of experience are mere "appearances" and that the nature of things as they are in themselves is unknowable to us.[29][30] In an attempt to counter the skepticism he found in the writings of philosopher David Hume,[31] he wrote the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787),[32] his most well-known work. In it, he developed his theory of experience to answer the question of whether synthetic a priori knowledge is possible, which would in turn make it possible to determine the limits of metaphysical inquiry. Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal to think of the objects of the senses as conforming to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition, so that we have a priori cognition of those objects.[b]

Kant believed that reason is also the source of morality, and that aesthetics arise from a faculty of disinterested judgment. Kant's views continue to have a major influence on contemporary philosophy, especially the fields of epistemology, ethics, political theory, and post-modern aesthetics.[28] He attempted to explain the relationship between reason and human experience and to move beyond what he believed to be the failures of traditional philosophy and metaphysics. He wanted to put an end to what he saw as an era of futile and speculative theories of human experience, while resisting the skepticism of thinkers such as Hume. He regarded himself as showing the way past the impasse between rationalists and empiricists,[34] and is widely held to have synthesized both traditions in his thought.[35]

Kant was an exponent of the idea that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation, and that perhaps this could be the culminating stage of world history.[36] The nature of Kant's religious views continues to be the subject of scholarly dispute, with viewpoints ranging from the impression that he shifted from an early defense of an ontological argument for the existence of God to a principled agnosticism, to more critical treatments epitomized by Schopenhauer, who criticized the imperative form of Kantian ethics as "theological morals" and the "Mosaic Decalogue in disguise",[37] and Friedrich Nietzsche, who claimed that Kant had "theologian blood"[38] and was merely a sophisticated apologist for traditional Christian faith.[c] Beyond his religious views, Kant has also been criticized for the racism presented in some of his lesser-known papers, such as "On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy" and "On the Different Races of Man".[40][41][42][43] Although he was a proponent of scientific racism for much of his career, Kant's views on race changed significantly in the last decade of his life, and he ultimately rejected racial hierarchies and European colonialism in Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795).[44]

Kant published other important works on ethics, religion, law, aesthetics, astronomy, and history during his lifetime. These include the Universal Natural History (1755), the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), the Critique of Judgment (1790), Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason (1793), and the Metaphysics of Morals (1797).[27]

Biography

Kant was born on 22 April 1724 into a Prussian German family of Lutheran Protestant faith in Königsberg, East Prussia (since 1946 the Russian city of Kaliningrad). His mother, Anna Regina Reuter[45] (1697–1737), was born in Königsberg to a father from Nuremberg.[citation needed] Her surname is sometimes erroneously given as Porter. Kant's father, Johann Georg Kant (1682–1746), was a German harness maker from Memel, at the time Prussia's most northeastern city (now Klaipėda, Lithuania). Kant believed that his paternal grandfather Hans Kant was of Scottish origin.[46] While scholars of Kant's life long accepted the claim, modern scholarship challenges it. It is possible that Kants got their name from the village of Kantvainiai (German: Kantwaggen – today part of Priekulė) and were of Kursenieki origin.[47][48] Kant was the fourth of nine children (six of whom reached adulthood).[49]

Baptized Emanuel, he later changed the spelling of his name to Immanuel[50] after learning Hebrew. He was brought up in a pietist household that stressed religious devotion, humility, and a literal interpretation of the Bible.[51][citation needed] His education was strict, punitive and disciplinary, and focused on Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science.[52] In his Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, he reveals a belief in immortality as the necessary condition of humanity's approach to the highest morality possible.[53][54] However, as Kant was skeptical about some of the arguments used prior to him in defence of theism and maintained that human understanding is limited and can never attain knowledge about God or the soul, various commentators have labelled him a philosophical agnostic,[55][56][57][58][59][60] even though it has also been suggested that Kant intends other people to think of him as a "pure rationalist", who is defined by Kant as someone who recognizes revelation but asserts that to know and accept it as real is not a necessary requisite to religion.[61]

Kant apparently lived a strict and disciplined life; it was said that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks. He never married[62] but seems to have had a rewarding social life—he was a popular teacher as well as a modestly successful author even before starting on his major philosophical works. He had a circle of friends with whom he frequently met—among them Joseph Green, an English merchant in Königsberg, whom reportedly he first spoke to in an argument in 1763 or before. According to the story, Kant was strolling in the Dänhofscher Garten when he saw one of his acquaintances speaking to a group of men he did not know. He joined the conversation, which soon turned to unusual current events in the world. The topic of the disagreement between the British and the Americans came up. Kant took the side of the Americans, and this upset Green. He challenged Kant to a fight. Kant reportedly explained that patriotism did not get in the way of his view, and that any cosmopolitan citizen could take his position if he held Kant's political principles, which Kant explained to Green. Green was so stunned by Kant's ability to express his views, that Green offered to become friends with Kant and invited him to his apartment that evening.[63] Many myths grew about Kant's personal mannerisms; these are listed, explained, and refuted in Goldthwait's introduction to his translation of Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime.[64]

Between 1750 and 1754 Kant worked as a tutor (Hauslehrer) in the Lithuanian village of Jučiai (German: Judtschen;[65] approximately 20 km east of Königsberg, and in Groß-Arnsdorf[66] (now Jarnołtowo near Morąg (German: Mohrungen), Poland), approximately 145 km east of Königsberg.

Young scholar

Kant showed a great aptitude for study at an early age. He first attended the Collegium Fridericianum from which he graduated at the end of the summer of 1740. In 1740, aged 16, he enrolled at the University of Königsberg, where he spent his whole career.[67] He studied the philosophy of Gottfried Leibniz and Christian Wolff under Martin Knutzen (Associate Professor of Logic and Metaphysics from 1734 until his death in 1751), a rationalist who was also familiar with developments in British philosophy and science and introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of Isaac Newton. Knutzen dissuaded Kant from the theory of pre-established harmony, which he regarded as "the pillow for the lazy mind".[68] He also dissuaded Kant from idealism, the idea that reality is purely mental, which most philosophers in the 18th century regarded in a negative light. The theory of transcendental idealism that Kant later included in the Critique of Pure Reason was developed partially in opposition to traditional idealism.

His father's stroke and subsequent death in 1746 interrupted his studies. Kant left Königsberg shortly after August 1748[69]—he would return there in August 1754.[70] He became a private tutor in the towns surrounding Königsberg, but continued his scholarly research. In 1749, he published his first philosophical work, Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces (written in 1745–47).[71]

Early work

Kant is best known for his work in the philosophy of ethics and metaphysics,[26] but he made significant contributions to other disciplines. In 1754, while contemplating on a prize question by the Berlin Academy about the problem of Earth's rotation, he argued that the Moon's gravity would slow down Earth's spin and he also put forth the argument that gravity would eventually cause the Moon's tidal locking to coincide with the Earth's rotation.[d][73] The next year, he expanded this reasoning to the formation and evolution of the Solar System in his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens.[73] In 1755, Kant received a license to lecture in the University of Königsberg and began lecturing on a variety of topics including mathematics, physics, logic and metaphysics. In his 1756 essay on the theory of winds, Kant laid out an original insight into the Coriolis force.

In 1756 Kant also published three papers on the 1755 Lisbon earthquake.[74] Kant's theory, which involved shifts in huge caverns filled with hot gases, though inaccurate, was one of the first systematic attempts to explain earthquakes in natural rather than supernatural terms. According to Walter Benjamin, Kant's slim early book on the earthquake "probably represents the beginnings of scientific geography in Germany. And certainly the beginnings of seismology".

In 1757, Kant began lecturing on geography making him one of the first lecturers to explicitly teach geography as its own subject.[75][76] Geography was one of Kant's most popular lecturing topics and in 1802 a compilation by Friedrich Theodor Rink of Kant's lecturing notes, Physical Geography, was released. After Kant became a professor in 1770, he expanded the topics of his lectures to include lectures on natural law, ethics, and anthropology, along with other topics.[75]

 
Kant's house in Königsberg

In the Universal Natural History, Kant laid out the Nebular hypothesis, in which he deduced that the Solar System had formed from a large cloud of gas, a nebula. Kant also correctly deduced that the Milky Way was a large disk of stars, which he theorized formed from a much larger spinning gas cloud. He further suggested that other distant "nebulae" might be other galaxies. These postulations opened new horizons for astronomy, for the first time extending it beyond the Solar System to galactic and intergalactic realms.[77] According to Thomas Huxley (1867), Kant also made contributions to geology in his Universal Natural History.[78][79]

From then on, Kant turned increasingly to philosophical issues, although he continued to write on the sciences throughout his life. In the early 1760s, Kant produced a series of important works in philosophy. The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures, a work in logic, was published in 1762. Two more works appeared the following year: Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy and The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God. By 1764, Kant had become a notable popular author, and wrote Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime;[80] he was second to Moses Mendelssohn in a Berlin Academy prize competition with his Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality (often referred to as "The Prize Essay"). In 1766 Kant wrote Dreams of a Spirit-Seer which dealt with the writings of Emanuel Swedenborg. The exact influence of Swedenborg on Kant, as well as the extent of Kant's belief in mysticism according to Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, remain controversial. On the face of it, Dreams of a Spirit-Seer argued against the ideas of Swedenborg. Kant poked holes in the logic of Swedenborg's view of the nature of spirits,[81] but also communicated his curiosity about Swedenborg's mysticism.[82] On 31 March 1770, aged 45, Kant was finally appointed Full Professor of Logic and Metaphysics (Professor Ordinarius der Logic und Metaphysic) at the University of Königsberg. In defense of this appointment, Kant wrote his inaugural dissertation (Inaugural-Dissertation) De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis (On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World).[1] This work saw the emergence of several central themes of his mature work, including the distinction between the faculties of intellectual thought and sensible receptivity. To miss this distinction would mean to commit the error of subreption, and, as he says in the last chapter of the dissertation, only in avoiding this error does metaphysics flourish.

The issue that vexed Kant was central to what 20th-century scholars called "the philosophy of mind". The flowering of the natural sciences had led to an understanding of how data reaches the brain. Sunlight falling on an object is reflected from its surface in a way that maps the surface features (color, texture, etc.). The reflected light reaches the human eye, passes through the cornea, is focused by the lens onto the retina where it forms an image similar to that formed by light passing through a pinhole into a camera obscura. The retinal cells send impulses through the optic nerve and then they form a mapping in the brain of the visual features of the object. The interior mapping is not the exterior object, and our belief that there is a meaningful relationship between the object and the mapping in the brain depends on a chain of reasoning that is not fully grounded. But the uncertainty aroused by these considerations, by optical illusions, misperceptions, delusions, etc., is not the end of the problem.

Kant saw that the mind could not function as an empty container that simply receives data from outside. Something must be giving order to the incoming data. Images of external objects must be kept in the same sequence in which they were received. This ordering occurs through the mind's intuition of time. The same considerations apply to the mind's function of constituting space for ordering mappings of visual and tactile signals arriving via the already described chains of physical causation.

It is often claimed that Kant was a late developer, that he only became an important philosopher in his mid-50s after rejecting his earlier views. While it is true that Kant wrote his greatest works relatively late in life, there is a tendency to underestimate the value of his earlier works. Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these "pre-critical" writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work.[83]

Publication of The Critique of Pure Reason

At age 46, Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher, and much was expected of him. In correspondence with his ex-student and friend Markus Herz, Kant admitted that, in the inaugural dissertation, he had failed to account for the relation between our sensible and intellectual faculties.[84] He needed to explain how we combine what is known as sensory knowledge with the other type of knowledge—i.e. reasoned knowledge—these two being related but having very different processes.

 
Portrait of philosopher David Hume

Kant also credited David Hume with awakening him from a "dogmatic slumber" in which he had unquestioningly accepted the tenets of both religion and natural philosophy.[85][86] Hume in his 1739 Treatise on Human Nature had argued that we only know the mind through a subjective—essentially illusory—series of perceptions.[85] Ideas such as causality, morality, and objects are not evident in experience, so their reality may be questioned. Kant felt that reason could remove this skepticism, and he set himself to solving these problems. Although fond of company and conversation with others, Kant isolated himself, and resisted friends' attempts to bring him out of his isolation.[e] When Kant emerged from his silence in 1781, the result was the Critique of Pure Reason. Kant countered Hume's empiricism by claiming that some knowledge exists inherently in the mind, independent of experience.[85] He drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal that worldly objects can be intuited a priori ('beforehand'), and that intuition is consequently distinct from objective reality.[b] He acquiesced to Hume somewhat by defining causality as a "regular, constant sequence of events in time, and nothing more."[88]

Although now uniformly recognized as one of the greatest works in the history of philosophy, this Critique disappointed Kant's readers upon its initial publication.[89] The book was long, over 800 pages in the original German edition, and written in a convoluted style. It received few reviews, and these granted it no significance.[citation needed] Kant's former student, Johann Gottfried Herder criticized it for placing reason as an entity worthy of criticism instead of considering the process of reasoning within the context of language and one's entire personality.[90] Similar to Christian Garve and Johann Georg Heinrich Feder, he rejected Kant's position that space and time possessed a form that could be analyzed. Additionally, Garve and Feder also faulted Kant's Critique for not explaining differences in perception of sensations.[91] Its density made it, as Herder said in a letter to Johann Georg Hamann, a "tough nut to crack", obscured by "all this heavy gossamer".[92] Its reception stood in stark contrast to the praise Kant had received for earlier works, such as his Prize Essay and shorter works that preceded the first Critique. These well-received and readable tracts include one on the earthquake in Lisbon that was so popular that it was sold by the page.[93] Prior to the change in course documented in the first Critique, his books had sold well.[80] Kant was disappointed with the first Critique's reception. Recognizing the need to clarify the original treatise, Kant wrote the Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics in 1783 as a summary of its main views. Shortly thereafter, Kant's friend Johann Friedrich Schultz (1739–1805) (professor of mathematics) published Erläuterungen über des Herrn Professor Kant Critik der reinen Vernunft (Königsberg, 1784), which was a brief but very accurate commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.

 
Engraving of Immanuel Kant

Kant's reputation gradually rose through the latter portion of the 1780s, sparked by a series of important works: the 1784 essay, "Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?"; 1785's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (his first work on moral philosophy); and, from 1786, Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. But Kant's fame ultimately arrived from an unexpected source. In 1786, Karl Leonhard Reinhold published a series of public letters on Kantian philosophy.[94] In these letters, Reinhold framed Kant's philosophy as a response to the central intellectual controversy of the era: the pantheism controversy. Friedrich Jacobi had accused the recently deceased Gotthold Ephraim Lessing (a distinguished dramatist and philosophical essayist) of Spinozism. Such a charge, tantamount to atheism, was vigorously denied by Lessing's friend Moses Mendelssohn, leading to a bitter public dispute among partisans. The controversy gradually escalated into a debate about the values of the Enlightenment and the value of reason.

Reinhold maintained in his letters that Kant's Critique of Pure Reason could settle this dispute by defending the authority and bounds of reason. Reinhold's letters were widely read and made Kant the most famous philosopher of his era.

Later work

Kant published a second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787, heavily revising the first parts of the book. Most of his subsequent work focused on other areas of philosophy. He continued to develop his moral philosophy, notably in 1788's Critique of Practical Reason (known as the second Critique) and 1797's Metaphysics of Morals. The 1790 Critique of Judgment (the third Critique) applied the Kantian system to aesthetics and teleology.

In 1792, Kant's attempt to publish the Second of the four Pieces of Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason,[95] in the journal Berlinische Monatsschrift, met with opposition from the King's censorship commission, which had been established that same year in the context of the French Revolution.[96] Kant then arranged to have all four pieces published as a book, routing it through the philosophy department at the University of Jena to avoid the need for theological censorship.[96] This insubordination earned him a now famous reprimand from the King.[96] When he nevertheless published a second edition in 1794, the censor was so irate that he arranged for a royal order that required Kant never to publish or even speak publicly about religion.[96] Kant then published his response to the King's reprimand and explained himself, in the preface of The Conflict of the Faculties.[96]

He also wrote a number of semi-popular essays on history, religion, politics and other topics. These works were well received by Kant's contemporaries and confirmed his preeminent status in 18th-century philosophy. There were several journals devoted solely to defending and criticizing Kantian philosophy. Despite his success, philosophical trends were moving in another direction. Many of Kant's most important disciples and followers (including Reinhold, Beck and Fichte) transformed the Kantian position into increasingly radical forms of idealism. The progressive stages of revision of Kant's teachings marked the emergence of German idealism. Kant opposed these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in 1799.[97] It was one of his final acts expounding a stance on philosophical questions. In 1800, a student of Kant named Gottlob Benjamin Jäsche (1762–1842) published a manual of logic for teachers called Logik, which he had prepared at Kant's request. Jäsche prepared the Logik using a copy of a textbook in logic by Georg Friedrich Meier entitled Auszug aus der Vernunftlehre, in which Kant had written copious notes and annotations. The Logik has been considered of fundamental importance to Kant's philosophy, and the understanding of it. The great 19th-century logician Charles Sanders Peirce remarked, in an incomplete review of Thomas Kingsmill Abbott's English translation of the introduction to Logik, that "Kant's whole philosophy turns upon his logic."[98] Also, Robert Schirokauer Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz, wrote in the translators' introduction to their English translation of the Logik, "Its importance lies not only in its significance for the Critique of Pure Reason, the second part of which is a restatement of fundamental tenets of the Logic, but in its position within the whole of Kant's work."[99]

Death and burial

Kant's health, long poor, worsened and he died at Königsberg on 12 February 1804, uttering "Es ist gut" (It is good) before expiring.[100] His unfinished final work was published as Opus Postumum. Kant always cut a curious figure in his lifetime for his modest, rigorously scheduled habits, which have been referred to as clocklike. However, Heinrich Heine noted the magnitude of "his destructive, world-crushing thoughts" and considered him a sort of philosophical "executioner", comparing him to Robespierre with the observation that both men "represented in the highest the type of provincial bourgeois. Nature had destined them to weigh coffee and sugar, but Fate determined that they should weigh other things and placed on the scales of the one a king, on the scales of the other a god."[101]

When his body was transferred to a new burial spot, his skull was measured during the exhumation and found to be larger than the average German male's with a "high and broad" forehead.[102] His forehead has been an object of interest ever since it became well-known through his portraits: "In Döbler's portrait and in Kiefer's faithful if expressionistic reproduction of it—as well as in many of the other late eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century portraits of Kant—the forehead is remarkably large and decidedly retreating. Was Kant's forehead shaped this way in these images because he was a philosopher, or, to follow the implications of Lavater's system, was he a philosopher because of the intellectual acuity manifested by his forehead? Kant and Johann Kaspar Lavater were correspondents on theological matters, and Lavater refers to Kant in his work "Physiognomic Fragments, for the Education of Human Knowledge and Love of People" (Leipzig & Winterthur, 1775–1778).[103]

 
Kant's tomb in Kaliningrad, Russia

Kant's mausoleum adjoins the northeast corner of Königsberg Cathedral in Kaliningrad, Russia. The mausoleum was constructed by the architect Friedrich Lahrs and was finished in 1924 in time for the bicentenary of Kant's birth. Originally, Kant was buried inside the cathedral, but in 1880 his remains were moved to a neo-Gothic chapel adjoining the northeast corner of the cathedral. Over the years, the chapel became dilapidated and was demolished to make way for the mausoleum, which was built on the same location.

The tomb and its mausoleum are among the few artifacts of German times preserved by the Soviets after they captured the city.[104] Today, many newlyweds bring flowers to the mausoleum. Artifacts previously owned by Kant, known as Kantiana, were included in the Königsberg City Museum. However, the museum was destroyed during World War II. A replica of the statue of Kant that in German times stood in front of the main University of Königsberg building was donated by a German entity in the early 1990s and placed in the same grounds.

After the expulsion of Königsberg's German population at the end of World War II, the University of Königsberg where Kant taught was replaced by the Russian-language Kaliningrad State University, which appropriated the campus and surviving buildings. In 2005, the university was renamed Immanuel Kant State University of Russia. The name change was announced at a ceremony attended by President Vladimir Putin of Russia and Chancellor Gerhard Schröder of Germany, and the university formed a Kant Society, dedicated to the study of Kantianism. The university was again renamed in the 2010s, to Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University.[105]

In 2018, his tomb and statue were vandalized with paint by unknown assailants, who also scattered leaflets glorifying Rus' and denouncing Kant as a "traitor". The incident was apparently connected with a recent vote to rename Khrabrovo Airport, where Kant was in the lead for a while, prompting Russian nationalist resentment.[106]

Philosophy

In Kant's essay "Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment?", he defined the Enlightenment as an age shaped by the Latin motto Sapere aude ("Dare to be wise"). Kant maintained that one ought to think autonomously, free of the dictates of external authority. His work reconciled many of the differences between the rationalist and empiricist traditions of the 18th century. He had a decisive impact on the Romantic and German Idealist philosophies of the 19th century. His work has also been a starting point for many 20th century philosophers.

Kant asserted that, because of the limitations of argumentation in the absence of irrefutable evidence, no one could really know whether there is a God and an afterlife or not. For the sake of morality and as a ground for reason, Kant asserted, people are justified in believing in God, even though they could never know God's presence empirically.

Thus the entire armament of reason, in the undertaking that one can call pure philosophy, is in fact directed only at the three problems that have been mentioned [God, the soul, and freedom]. These themselves, however, have in turn their more remote aim, namely, what is to be done if the will is free, if there is a God, and if there is a future world. Now since these concern our conduct in relation to the highest end, the ultimate aim of nature which provides for us wisely in the disposition of reason is properly directed only to what is moral.[33]: 674–5 (A 800–1/B 828–9) 

 
Immanuel Kant by Carle Vernet (1758–1836)

The sense of an enlightened approach and the critical method required that "If one cannot prove that a thing is, he may try to prove that it is not. If he fails to do either (as often occurs), he may still ask whether it is in his interest to accept one or the other of the alternatives hypothetically, from the theoretical or the practical point of view. Hence the question no longer is as to whether perpetual peace is a real thing or not a real thing, or as to whether we may not be deceiving ourselves when we adopt the former alternative, but we must act on the supposition of its being real."[107] The presupposition of God, soul, and freedom was then a practical concern, for

Morality in itself constitutes a system, but happiness does not, except insofar as it is distributed precisely in accordance with morality. This, however, is possible only in the intelligible world, under a wise author and regent. Reason sees itself as compelled either to assume such a thing, together with life in such a world, which we must regard as a future one, or else to regard the moral laws as empty figments of the brain ...[33]: 680 (A 811/B 839) 

Kant drew a parallel between the Copernican revolution and the epistemology of his new transcendental philosophy, involving two interconnected foundations of his "critical philosophy":

These teachings placed the active, rational human subject at the center of the cognitive and moral worlds. Kant argued that the rational order of the world as known by science was not just the accidental accumulation of sense perceptions.

Conceptual unification and integration is carried out by the mind through concepts or the "categories of the understanding" operating on the perceptual manifold within space and time. The latter are not concepts,[108] but are forms of sensibility that are a priori necessary conditions for any possible experience. Thus the objective order of nature and the causal necessity that operates within it depend on the mind's processes, the product of the rule-based activity that Kant called "synthesis". There is much discussion among Kant scholars about the correct interpretation of this train of thought.

The 'two-world' interpretation regards Kant's position as a statement of epistemological limitation, that we are not able to transcend the bounds of our own mind, meaning that we cannot access the "thing-in-itself". However, Kant also speaks of the thing in itself or transcendental object as a product of the (human) understanding as it attempts to conceive of objects in abstraction from the conditions of sensibility. Following this line of thought, some interpreters have argued that the thing in itself does not represent a separate ontological domain but simply a way of considering objects by means of the understanding alone—this is known as the two-aspect view.

The notion of the "thing in itself" was much discussed by philosophers after Kant. It was argued that, because the "thing in itself" was unknowable, its existence must not be assumed. Rather than arbitrarily switching to an account that was ungrounded in anything supposed to be the "real", as did the German Idealists, another group arose who asked how our (presumably reliable) accounts of a coherent and rule-abiding universe were actually grounded. This new kind of philosophy became known as Phenomenology, and its founder was Edmund Husserl.

With regard to morality, Kant argued that the source of the good lies not in anything outside the human subject, either in nature or given by God, but rather is only the good will itself. A good will is one that acts from duty in accordance with the universal moral law that the autonomous human being freely gives itself. This law obliges one to treat humanity – understood as rational agency, and represented through oneself as well as others – as an end in itself rather than (merely) as means to other ends the individual might hold. This necessitates practical self-reflection in which we universalize our reasons.

These ideas have largely framed or influenced all subsequent philosophical discussion and analysis. The specifics of Kant's account generated immediate and lasting controversy. Nevertheless, his theses – that the mind itself necessarily makes a constitutive contribution to its knowledge, that this contribution is transcendental rather than psychological, that philosophy involves self-critical activity, that morality is rooted in human freedom, and that to act autonomously is to act according to rational moral principles – have all had a lasting effect on subsequent philosophy.

Epistemology

 
Bust of Immanuel Kant

Theory of perception

Kant defines his theory of perception in his very influential 1781 work the Critique of Pure Reason, which has often been cited as the most significant volume of metaphysics and epistemology in modern philosophy.[109] Kant maintains that understanding of the external world had its foundations not merely in experience, but in both experience and a priori concepts, thus offering a non-empiricist critique of rationalist philosophy, which is what has been referred to as his Copernican revolution.[110]

Firstly, Kant distinguishes between analytic and synthetic propositions:

  1. Analytic proposition: a proposition whose predicate concept is contained in its subject concept; e.g., "All bachelors are unmarried," or, "All bodies take up space."
  2. Synthetic proposition: a proposition whose predicate concept is not contained in its subject concept; e.g., "All bachelors are alone," or, "All bodies have weight."

An analytic proposition is true by nature of the meaning of the words in the sentence—we require no further knowledge than a grasp of the language to understand this proposition. On the other hand, a synthetic statement is one that tells us something about the world. The truth or falsehood of synthetic statements derives from something outside their linguistic content. In this instance, weight is not a necessary predicate of the body; until we are told the heaviness of the body we do not know that it has weight. In this case, experience of the body is required before its heaviness becomes clear. Before Kant's first Critique, empiricists (cf. Hume) and rationalists (cf. Leibniz) assumed that all synthetic statements required experience to be known.

Kant contests this assumption by claiming that elementary mathematics, like arithmetic, is synthetic a priori, in that its statements provide new knowledge not derived from experience. This becomes part of his over-all argument for transcendental idealism. That is, he argues that the possibility of experience depends on certain necessary conditions—which he calls a priori forms—and that these conditions structure and hold true of the world of experience. His main claims in the "Transcendental Aesthetic" are that mathematic judgments are synthetic a priori and that space and time are not derived from experience but rather are its preconditions.

Once we have grasped the functions of basic arithmetic, we do not need empirical experience to know that 100 + 100 = 200, and so it appears that arithmetic is analytic. However, that it is analytic can be disproved by considering the calculation 5 + 7 = 12: there is nothing in the numbers 5 and 7 by which the number 12 can be inferred.[111] Thus "5 + 7" and "the cube root of 1,728" or "12" are not analytic because their reference is the same but their sense is not—the statement "5 + 7 = 12" tells us something new about the world. It is self-evident, and undeniably a priori, but at the same time it is synthetic. Thus Kant argued that a proposition can be synthetic and a priori. This statement is synthetic because it supposes both quantity in general which is a conceit from our understanding and succession which is a mode of time that belongs to our sensibility. To produce 12 from 5, one needs to add unity to unity seven time. Thus to add is not an operation of pure reason but a process that needs time : one and then one, and again one, etc.[112]

Kant asserts that experience is based on the perception of external objects and a priori knowledge.[113] The external world, he writes, provides those things that we sense. But our mind processes this information and gives it order, allowing us to comprehend it. Our mind supplies the conditions of space and time to experience objects. According to the "transcendental unity of apperception", the concepts of the mind (Understanding) and perceptions or intuitions that garner information from phenomena (Sensibility) are synthesized by comprehension. Without concepts, perceptions are nondescript; without perceptions, concepts are meaningless. Thus the famous statement: "Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions [perceptions] without concepts are blind."[33]: 193–194 (A 51/B 75) 

Kant also claims that an external environment is necessary for the establishment of the self. Although Kant would want to argue that there is no empirical way of observing the self, we can see the logical necessity of the self when we observe that we can have different perceptions of the external environment over time. By uniting these general representations into one global representation, we can see how a transcendental self emerges. "I am therefore conscious of the identical self in regard to the manifold of the representations that are given to me in an intuition because I call them all together my representations, which constitute one."[33]: 248 (B 135) 

According to Guillaume Pigeard de Gurbert, Kant's philosophy has its unity in the conceit of time, which different uses – speculative, practical, pragmatical, historical or teleogical – is crucial.[114]

Time and space

The Kantian revolution breaks with previous conceptions of time, either metaphysical (Leibniz) or empirical ones (Hume), in its relation to space. Against metaphysical time and space Kant explains they are not things in themselves but mere shape of the way we feel things. Against empiricism he says that these subjective shapes are a priori—are not given by experience, since any experience of such or such time and space supposes that we are feeling things in the way of time and space. The word "transcendental" qualifies this space and this time lying within the subject that make possible any sensible experience. Kant adds that space itself depends on time, because nothing can be in space without being within time.

Categories of the Faculty of Understanding

 
Kant statue in the School of Philosophy and Human Sciences (FAFICH) in the Federal University of Minas Gerais (UFMG), Belo Horizonte, Brazil

Kant deemed it obvious that we have some objective knowledge of the world, such as, say, Newtonian physics. But this knowledge relies on synthetic, a priori laws of nature, like causality and substance. How is this possible? Kant's solution was that the subject must supply laws that make experience of objects possible, and that these laws are synthetic, a priori laws of nature that apply to all objects before we experience them. To deduce all these laws, Kant examined experience in general, dissecting in it what is supplied by the mind from what is supplied by the given intuitions. This is commonly called a transcendental deduction.[115]

To begin with, Kant's distinction between the a posteriori being contingent and particular knowledge, and the a priori being universal and necessary knowledge, must be kept in mind. If we merely connect two intuitions together in a perceiving subject, the knowledge is always subjective because it is derived a posteriori, when what is desired is for the knowledge to be objective, that is, for the two intuitions to refer to the object and hold good of it for anyone at any time, not just the perceiving subject in its current condition. What else is equivalent to objective knowledge besides the a priori (universal and necessary knowledge)? Before knowledge can be objective, it must be incorporated under an a priori category of understanding.[115][116]

For example, if one says "The sun shines on the stone; the stone grows warm", all that one perceives is phenomena. One's judgment is contingent and holds no necessity. But, if one says "The sunshine causes the stone to warm", one subsumes the perception under the category of causality, which is not found in the perception, and one necessarily synthesizes the concept sunshine with the concept heat, producing a necessarily universally true judgment.[115]

To explain the categories in more detail, they are the preconditions of the construction of objects in the mind. Indeed, to even think of the sun and stone presupposes the category of subsistence, that is, substance. For the categories synthesize the random data of the sensory manifold into intelligible objects. This means that the categories are also the most abstract things one can say of any object whatsoever, and hence one can have an a priori cognition of the totality of all objects of experience if one can list all of them. To do so, Kant formulates another transcendental deduction.[115]

Judgments are, for Kant, the preconditions of any thought. Man thinks via judgments, so all possible judgments must be listed and the perceptions connected within them put aside, so as to make it possible to examine the moments when the understanding is engaged in constructing judgments. For the categories are equivalent to these moments, in that they are concepts of intuitions in general, so far as they are determined by these moments universally and necessarily. Thus by listing all the moments, one can deduce from them all of the categories.[115]

One may now ask: How many possible judgments are there? Kant believed that all the possible propositions within Aristotle's syllogistic logic are equivalent to all possible judgments, and that all the logical operators within the propositions are equivalent to the moments of the understanding within judgments. Thus he listed Aristotle's system in four groups of three: quantity (universal, particular, singular), quality (affirmative, negative, infinite), relation (categorical, hypothetical, disjunctive) and modality (problematic, assertoric, apodeictic). The parallelism with Kant's categories is obvious: quantity (unity, plurality, totality), quality (reality, negation, limitation), relation (substance, cause, community) and modality (possibility, existence, necessity).[115]

The fundamental building blocks of experience, i.e. objective knowledge, are now in place. First there is the sensibility, which supplies the mind with intuitions, and then there is the understanding, which produces judgments of these intuitions and can subsume them under categories. These categories lift the intuitions up out of the subject's current state of consciousness and place them within consciousness in general, producing universally necessary knowledge. For the categories are innate in any rational being, so any intuition thought within a category in one mind is necessarily subsumed and understood identically in any mind. In other words, we filter what we see and hear.[115]

Transcendental schema doctrine

Kant ran into a problem with his theory that the mind plays a part in producing objective knowledge. Intuitions and categories are entirely disparate, so how can they interact? Kant's solution is the (transcendental) schema: a priori principles by which the transcendental imagination connects concepts with intuitions through time. All the principles are temporally bound, for if a concept is purely a priori, as the categories are, then they must apply for all times. Hence there are principles such as substance is that which endures through time, and the cause must always be prior to the effect.[115][117] In the context of transcendental schema the concept of transcendental reflection is of a great importance.[118]

Ethics

 
Immanuel Kant

Kant developed his ethics, or moral philosophy, in three works: Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals (1785), Critique of Practical Reason (1788), and Metaphysics of Morals (1797).

In Groundwork, Kant tries to convert our everyday, obvious, rational[119] knowledge of morality into philosophical knowledge. The latter two works used "practical reason", which is based only on things about which reason can tell us, and not deriving any principles from experience, to reach conclusions which can be applied to the world of experience (in the second part of The Metaphysics of Morals).

Kant is known for his theory that there is a single moral obligation, which he called the "Categorical Imperative", and is derived from the concept of duty. Kant defines the demands of moral law as "categorical imperatives". Categorical imperatives are principles that are intrinsically valid; they are good in and of themselves; they must be obeyed in all situations and circumstances, if our behavior is to observe the moral law. The Categorical Imperative provides a test against which moral statements can be assessed. Kant also stated that the moral means and ends can be applied to the categorical imperative, that rational beings can pursue certain "ends" using the appropriate "means". Ends based on physical needs or wants create hypothetical imperatives. The categorical imperative can only be based on something that is an "end in itself", that is, an end that is not a means to some other need, desire, or purpose.[120] Kant believed that the moral law is a principle of reason itself, and is not based on contingent facts about the world, such as what would make us happy, but to act on the moral law which has no other motive than "worthiness to be happy".[33]: 677 (A 806/B 834)  Accordingly, he believed that moral obligation applies only to rational agents.[121]

Unlike a hypothetical imperative, a categorical imperative is an unconditional obligation; it has the force of an obligation regardless of our will or desires[122] In Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals (1785) Kant enumerated three formulations of the categorical imperative that he believed to be roughly equivalent.[123] In the same book, Kant stated:

Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law.[124]

According to Kant, one cannot make exceptions for oneself. The philosophical maxim on which one acts should always be considered to be a universal law without exception. One cannot allow oneself to do a particular action unless one thinks it appropriate that the reason for the action should become a universal law. For example, one should not steal, however dire the circumstances—because, by permitting oneself to steal, one makes stealing a universally acceptable act. This is the first formulation of the categorical imperative, often known as the universalizability principle.

Kant believed that, if an action is not done with the motive of duty, then it is without moral value. He thought that every action should have pure intention behind it; otherwise, it is meaningless. The final result is not the most important aspect of an action; rather, how the person feels while carrying out the action is the time when value is attached to the result.

In Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, Kant also posited the "counter-utilitarian idea that there is a difference between preferences and values, and that considerations of individual rights temper calculations of aggregate utility", a concept that is an axiom in economics:[125]

Everything has either a price or a dignity. Whatever has a price can be replaced by something else as its equivalent; on the other hand, whatever is above all price, and therefore admits of no equivalent, has a dignity. But that which constitutes the condition under which alone something can be an end in itself does not have mere relative worth, i.e., price, but an intrinsic worth, i.e., a dignity. (p. 53, italics in original).

A phrase quoted by Kant, which is used to summarize the counter-utilitarian nature of his moral philosophy, is Fiat justitia, pereat mundus ("Let justice be done, though the world perish"), which he translates loosely as "Let justice reign even if all the rascals in the world should perish from it". This appears in his 1795 Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch ("Zum ewigen Frieden. Ein philosophischer Entwurf"), Appendix 1.[126][127][128]

First formulation

 
In his Metaphysics, Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative: "Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law."

The first formulation (Formula of Universal Law) of the moral imperative "requires that the maxims be chosen as though they should hold as universal laws of nature".[123] This formulation in principle has as its supreme law the creed "Always act according to that maxim whose universality as a law you can at the same time will" and is the "only condition under which a will can never come into conflict with itself [....]"[129]

One interpretation of the first formulation is called the "universalizability test".[130] An agent's maxim, according to Kant, is his "subjective principle of human actions": that is, what the agent believes is his reason to act.[131] The universalisability test has five steps:

  1. Find the agent's maxim (i.e., an action paired with its motivation). Take, for example, the declaration "I will lie for personal benefit". Lying is the action; the motivation is to fulfill some sort of desire. Together, they form the maxim.
  2. Imagine a possible world in which everyone in a similar position to the real-world agent followed that maxim.
  3. Decide if contradictions or irrationalities would arise in the possible world as a result of following the maxim.
  4. If a contradiction or irrationality would arise, acting on that maxim is not allowed in the real world.
  5. If there is no contradiction, then acting on that maxim is permissible, and is sometimes required.

(For a modern parallel, see John Rawls' hypothetical situation, the original position.)

Second formulation

The second formulation (or Formula of the End in Itself) holds that "the rational being, as by its nature an end and thus as an end in itself, must serve in every maxim as the condition restricting all merely relative and arbitrary ends".[123] The principle dictates that you "[a]ct with reference to every rational being (whether yourself or another) so that it is an end in itself in your maxim", meaning that the rational being is "the basis of all maxims of action" and "must be treated never as a mere means but as the supreme limiting condition in the use of all means, i.e., as an end at the same time".[132]

Third formulation

The third formulation (i.e. Formula of Autonomy) is a synthesis of the first two and is the basis for the "complete determination of all maxims". It states "that all maxims which stem from autonomous legislation ought to harmonize with a possible realm of ends as with a realm of nature".[123]

In principle, "So act as if your maxims should serve at the same time as the universal law (of all rational beings)", meaning that we should so act that we may think of ourselves as "a member in the universal realm of ends", legislating universal laws through our maxims (that is, a universal code of conduct), in a "possible realm of ends".[133] No one may elevate themselves above the universal law, therefore it is one's duty to follow the maxim(s).

Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason

Commentators, starting in the 20th century, have tended to see Kant as having a strained relationship with religion, though this was not the prevalent view in the 19th century. Karl Leonhard Reinhold, whose letters first made Kant famous, wrote "I believe that I may infer without reservation that the interest of religion, and of Christianity in particular, accords completely with the result of the Critique of Reason."[134] Johann Schultz, who wrote one of the first Kant commentaries, wrote "And does not this system itself cohere most splendidly with the Christian religion? Do not the divinity and beneficence of the latter become all the more evident?"[135] This view continued throughout the 19th century, as noted by Friedrich Nietzsche, who said "Kant's success is merely a theologian's success."[136] The reason for these views was Kant's moral theology, and the widespread belief that his philosophy was the great antithesis to Spinozism, which had been convulsing the European academy for much of the 18th century. Spinozism was widely seen as the cause of the Pantheism controversy, and as a form of sophisticated pantheism or even atheism. As Kant's philosophy disregarded the possibility of arguing for God through pure reason alone, for the same reasons it also disregarded the possibility of arguing against God through pure reason alone. This, coupled with his moral philosophy (his argument that the existence of morality is a rational reason why God and an afterlife do and must exist), was the reason he was seen by many, at least through the end of the 19th century, as a great defender of religion in general and Christianity in particular.[citation needed]

Kant articulates his strongest criticisms of the organization and practices of religious organizations to those that encourage what he sees as a religion of counterfeit service to God.[137] Among the major targets of his criticism are external ritual, superstition and a hierarchical church order. He sees these as efforts to make oneself pleasing to God in ways other than conscientious adherence to the principle of moral rightness in choosing and acting upon one's maxims. Kant's criticisms on these matters, along with his rejection of certain theoretical proofs grounded in pure reason (particularly the ontological argument) for the existence of God and his philosophical commentary on some Christian doctrines, have resulted in interpretations that see Kant as hostile to religion in general and Christianity in particular (e.g., Walsh 1967). Nevertheless, other interpreters consider that Kant was trying to mark off defensible from indefensible Christian belief.[138] Kant sees in Jesus Christ the affirmation of a "pure moral disposition of the heart" that "can make man well-pleasing to God".[137] Regarding Kant's conception of religion, some critics have argued that he was sympathetic to deism.[139] Other critics have argued that Kant's moral conception moves from deism to theism (as moral theism), for example Allen W. Wood[140] and Merold Westphal.[141] As for Kant's book Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason,[95] it was emphasized that Kant reduced religiosity to rationality, religion to morality and Christianity to ethics.[142] However, many interpreters, including Allen W. Wood[143] and Lawrence Pasternack,[144] now agree with Stephen Palmquist's claim that a better way of reading Kant's Religion is to see him as raising morality to the status of religion.[145]

Idea of freedom

In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant distinguishes between the transcendental idea of freedom, which as a psychological concept is "mainly empirical" and refers to "whether a faculty of beginning a series of successive things or states from itself is to be assumed"[33]: 486 (A 448/B 467)  and the practical concept of freedom as the independence of our will from the "coercion" or "necessitation through sensuous impulses". Kant finds it a source of difficulty that the practical idea of freedom is founded on the transcendental idea of freedom,[33]: 533 (A 533–4/B 561–2)  but for the sake of practical interests uses the practical meaning, taking "no account of... its transcendental meaning," which he feels was properly "disposed of" in the Third Antinomy, and as an element in the question of the freedom of the will is for philosophy "a real stumbling block" that has embarrassed speculative reason.[33]: 486 (A 448/B 467) 

Kant calls practical "everything that is possible through freedom", and the pure practical laws that are never given through sensuous conditions but are held analogously with the universal law of causality are moral laws. Reason can give us only the "pragmatic laws of free action through the senses", but pure practical laws given by reason a priori[33]: 486 (A 448/B 467)  dictate "what is to be done".[33]: 674–676 (A 800–2/B 828–30)  (The same distinction of transcendental and practical meaning can be applied to the idea of God, with the proviso that the practical concept of freedom can be experienced.[146])

Categories of freedom

In the Critique of Practical Reason, at the end of the second Main Part of the Analytics,[147] Kant introduces the categories of freedom, in analogy with the categories of understanding their practical counterparts. Kant's categories of freedom apparently function primarily as conditions for the possibility for actions (i) to be free, (ii) to be understood as free and (iii) to be morally evaluated. For Kant, although actions as theoretical objects are constituted by means of the theoretical categories, actions as practical objects (objects of practical use of reason, and which can be good or bad) are constituted by means of the categories of freedom. Only in this way can actions, as phenomena, be a consequence of freedom, and be understood and evaluated as such.[148]

Aesthetic philosophy

Kant discusses the subjective nature of aesthetic qualities and experiences in Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime (1764). Kant's contribution to aesthetic theory is developed in the Critique of Judgment (1790) where he investigates the possibility and logical status of "judgments of taste." In the "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment," the first major division of the Critique of Judgment, Kant used the term "aesthetic" in a manner that, according to Kant scholar W.H. Walsh, differs from its modern sense.[149] In the Critique of Pure Reason, to note essential differences between judgments of taste, moral judgments, and scientific judgments, Kant abandoned the term "aesthetic" as "designating the critique of taste," noting that judgments of taste could never be "directed" by "laws a priori."[150] After A. G. Baumgarten, who wrote Aesthetica (1750–58),[151] Kant was one of the first philosophers to develop and integrate aesthetic theory into a unified and comprehensive philosophical system, utilizing ideas that played an integral role throughout his philosophy.[152]

In the chapter "Analytic of the Beautiful" in the Critique of Judgment, Kant states that beauty is not a property of an artwork or natural phenomenon, but is instead consciousness of the pleasure that attends the 'free play' of the imagination and the understanding. Even though it appears that we are using reason to decide what is beautiful, the judgment is not a cognitive judgment,[153] "and is consequently not logical, but aesthetical" (§ 1). A pure judgement of taste is subjective since it refers to the emotional response of the subject and is based upon nothing but esteem for an object itself: it is a disinterested pleasure, and we feel that pure judgements of taste (i.e. judgements of beauty), lay claim to universal validity (§§ 20–22). It is important to note that this universal validity is not derived from a determinate concept of beauty but from common sense (§40). Kant also believed that a judgement of taste shares characteristics engaged in a moral judgement: both are disinterested, and we hold them to be universal. In the chapter "Analytic of the Sublime" Kant identifies the sublime as an aesthetic quality that, like beauty, is subjective, but unlike beauty refers to an indeterminate relationship between the faculties of the imagination and of reason, and shares the character of moral judgments in the use of reason. The feeling of the sublime, divided into two distinct modes (the mathematical and the dynamical sublime), describes two subjective moments that concern the relationship of the faculty of the imagination to reason. Some commentators[154] argue that Kant's critical philosophy contains a third kind of the sublime, the moral sublime, which is the aesthetic response to the moral law or a representation, and a development of the "noble" sublime in Kant's theory of 1764. The mathematical sublime results from the failure of the imagination to comprehend natural objects that appear boundless and formless, or appear "absolutely great" (§§ 23–25). This imaginative failure is then recuperated through the pleasure taken in reason's assertion of the concept of infinity. In this move the faculty of reason proves itself superior to our fallible sensible self (§§ 25–26). In the dynamical sublime there is the sense of annihilation of the sensible self as the imagination tries to comprehend a vast might. This power of nature threatens us but through the resistance of reason to such sensible annihilation, the subject feels a pleasure and a sense of the human moral vocation. This appreciation of moral feeling through exposure to the sublime helps to develop moral character.

Kant developed a theory of humor (§ 54) that has been interpreted as an "incongruity" theory. He illustrated his theory of humor by telling three narrative jokes in the Critique of Judgment. He thought that the physiological impact of humor is akin to that of music.[155] His knowledge of music, however, has been reported to be much weaker than his sense of humor: He told many more jokes throughout his lectures and writings.[156]

Kant developed a distinction between an object of art as a material value subject to the conventions of society and the transcendental condition of the judgment of taste as a "refined" value in his Idea of A Universal History (1784). In the Fourth and Fifth Theses of that work he identified all art as the "fruits of unsociableness" due to men's "antagonism in society"[157] and, in the Seventh Thesis, asserted that while such material property is indicative of a civilized state, only the ideal of morality and the universalization of refined value through the improvement of the mind "belongs to culture".[158]

Political philosophy

In Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch,[159] Kant listed several conditions that he thought necessary for ending wars and creating a lasting peace. They included a world of constitutional republics.[160] His classical republican theory was extended in the Science of Right, the first part of the Metaphysics of Morals (1797).[161] Kant believed that universal history leads to the ultimate world of republican states at peace, but his theory was not pragmatic. The process was described in "Perpetual Peace" as natural rather than rational:

The guarantee of perpetual peace is nothing less than that great artist, nature...In her mechanical course we see that her aim is to produce a harmony among men, against their will, and indeed through their discord. As a necessity working according to laws we do not know, we call it destiny. But, considering its designs in universal history, we call it "providence," inasmuch as we discern in it the profound wisdom of a higher cause which predetermines the course of nature and directs it to the objective final end of the human race.[162]

Kant's political thought can be summarized as republican government and international organization. "In more characteristically Kantian terms, it is doctrine of the state based upon the law (Rechtsstaat) and of eternal peace. Indeed, in each of these formulations, both terms express the same idea: that of legal constitution or of 'peace through law'. Kant's political philosophy, being essentially a legal doctrine, rejects by definition the opposition between moral education and the play of passions as alternate foundations for social life. The state is defined as the union of men under law. The state is constituted by laws which are necessary a priori because they flow from the very concept of law. "A regime can be judged by no other criteria nor be assigned any other functions, than those proper to the lawful order as such."[163]

He opposed "democracy," which at his time meant direct democracy, believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty. He stated, "...democracy is, properly speaking, necessarily a despotism, because it establishes an executive power in which 'all' decide for or even against one who does not agree; that is, 'all,' who are not quite all, decide, and this is a contradiction of the general will with itself and with freedom."[164] As with most writers at the time, he distinguished three forms of government i.e. democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy with mixed government as the most ideal form of it.

Anthropology

 
5 DM 1974 D silver coin commemorating the 250th birthday of Immanuel Kant in Königsberg

Kant lectured on anthropology, the study of human nature, for twenty-three and a half years.[165] His Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View was published in 1798. (This was the subject of Michel Foucault's secondary dissertation for his State doctorate, Introduction to Kant's Anthropology.) Kant's Lectures on Anthropology were published for the first time in 1997 in German.[166] Introduction to Kant's Anthropology was translated into English and published by the Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy series in 2006.[167]

Kant was among the first people of his time to introduce anthropology as an intellectual area of study, long before the field gained popularity, and his texts are considered to have advanced the field. His point of view was to influence the works of later philosophers such as Martin Heidegger and Paul Ricoeur.

Kant was also the first to suggest using a dimensionality approach to human diversity. He analyzed the nature of the Hippocrates-Galen four temperaments and plotted them in two dimensions: (1) "activation", or energetic aspect of behaviour, and (2) "orientation on emotionality".[168] Cholerics were described as emotional and energetic; Phlegmatics as balanced and weak; Sanguines as balanced and energetic, and Melancholics as emotional and weak. These two dimensions reappeared in all subsequent models of temperament and personality traits.

Kant viewed anthropology in two broad categories: (1) the physiological approach, which he referred to as "what nature makes of the human being"; and (2) the pragmatic approach, which explored the things that a human "can and should make of himself."[169]

Racism

Kant was one of the most notable Enlightenment thinkers to defend racism, and some have claimed that he was one of the central figures in the birth of modern scientific racism. Where figures such as Carl Linnaeus and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach had supposed only "empirical" observation for racism, Kant produced a fully developed theory of race. Using the Four Temperaments of ancient Greece, he proposed a hierarchy of four racial categories: white Europeans, yellow Asians, black Africans, and red Amerindians.[43][41][40][42][170][171]

Kant wrote that "[Whites] contain all the impulses of nature in affects and passions, all talents, all dispositions to culture and civilization and can as readily obey as govern. They are the only ones who always advance to perfection.” He describes South Asians as "educated to the highest degree but only in the arts and not in the sciences". He goes on that Hindustanis can never reach the level of abstract concepts and that a "great hindustani man" is one who has "gone far in the art of deception and has much money". He stated that the Hindus always stay the way they are and can never advance. About black Africans, Kant wrote that "they can be educated but only as servants, that is they allow themselves to be trained". He quotes David Hume as challenging anyone to "cite a [single] example in which a Negro has shown talents" and asserts that, among the "hundreds of thousands" of blacks transported during the Atlantic slave trade, even among the freed "still not a single one was ever found who presented anything great in art or science or any other praiseworthy quality". To Kant, "the Negro can be disciplined and cultivated, but is never genuinely civilized. He falls of his own accord into savagery." Native Americans, Kant opined, "cannot be educated". He calls them unmotivated, lacking affect, passion and love, describing them as too weak for labor, unfit for any culture, and too phlegmatic for diligence. He said the Native Americans are "far below the Negro, who undoubtedly holds the lowest of all remaining levels by which we designate the different races". Kant stated that "Americans and Blacks cannot govern themselves. They thus serve only for slaves."[171][41][40][172]

J Sai Deepak states that Kant's views on race were consistent from 1764, when he was 40 years of age, until 1795. In Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime (1764), he wrote that the black colour of a 'negro carpenter' proved the stupidity of whatever he said and that the difference in the mental faculties of the Whites and Blacks was as large as the difference in their colors.[173]

Kant was an opponent of miscegenation, believing that whites would be "degraded" and the "fusing of races" is undesirable, for "not every race adopts the morals and customs of the Europeans". He stated that "instead of assimilation, which was intended by the melting together of the various races, Nature has here made a law of just the opposite".[174] He believed that in the future all races would be extinguished, except that of the whites.[171]

Kant was also an antisemite, believing that Jews were incapable of transcending material forces, which a moral order required. In this way, Jews are the opposite of autonomous, rational Christians, and are therefore incapable of being incorporated into an ethical Christian society. In his “Anthropology,” Kant called the Jews “a nation of cheaters” and portrayed them as “a group that has followed not the path of transcendental freedom but that of enslavement to the material world.”[175]

Charles W. Mills wrote that Kant has been "sanitized for public consumption", his racist works conveniently ignored.[171] Robert Bernasconi stated that Kant "supplied the first scientific definition of race". Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze is credited with bringing Kant's contributions to racism to light in the 1990s among Western philosophers, who often gloss over this part of his life and works.[42] He wrote about Kant's ideas of race:

Kant's position on the importance of skin color not only as encoding but as proof of this codification of rational superiority or inferiority is evident in a comment he made on the subject of the reasoning capacity of a "black" person. When he evaluated a statement made by an African, Kant dismissed the statement with the comment: "this fellow was quite black from head to foot, a clear proof that what he said was stupid." It cannot, therefore, be argued that skin color for Kant was merely a physical characteristic. It is, rather, evidence of an unchanging and unchangeable moral quality.

— Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze, "The Color of Reason: The Idea of 'Race' in Kant's Anthropology", Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader (1997)[40]

Pauline Kleingeld argues that while Kant was indeed a staunch advocate of scientific racism for much of his career, his views on race changed significantly in works published in the last decade of his life.[44] In particular, she argues that Kant unambiguously rejected past views related to racial hierarchies and the diminished rights or moral status of non-whites in Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795). This work also saw him providing extended arguments against European colonialism, which he claimed was morally unjust and incompatible with the equal rights held by indigenous populations. Kleingeld argues that this shift in Kant's views later in life has often been forgotten or ignored in the literature on Kant's racist anthropology, and that the shift suggests a belated recognition of the fact that racial hierarchy was incompatible with a universalized moral framework.[44] While Kant's perspective on the topic of European colonialism became more balanced, he still considered Europeans "civilized" to the exception of others:

But to this perfection compare the inhospitable actions of the civilized and especially of the commercial states of our part of the world. The injustice which they show to lands and peoples they visit (which is equivalent to conquering them) is carried by them to terrifying lengths. America, the lands inhabited by the Negro, the Spice Islands, the Cape, etc., were at the time of their discovery considered by these civilized intruders as lands without owners, for they counted the inhabitants as nothing. In East India (Hindustan), under the pretense of establishing economic undertakings, they brought in foreign soldiers and used them to oppress the natives, excited widespread wars among the various states, spread famine, rebellion, perfidy, and the whole litany of evils which afflict mankind.

— Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch" (1795)[176]

Women

Many authors have criticised Kant's negative views on women.[177][178][179][180][181][182][183][184]

Influence and legacy

Kant's influence on Western thought has been profound.[185] Although the basic tenets of Kant's transcendental idealism (i.e. that space and time are a priori forms of human perception rather than real properties and the claim that formal logic and transcendental logic coincide) have been claimed to be falsified by modern science and logic,[186][187][188] and no longer set the intellectual agenda of contemporary philosophers, Kant is credited with having innovated the way philosophical inquiry has been carried at least up to the early nineteenth century. This shift consisted in several closely related innovations that, although highly contentious in themselves, have become important in postmodern philosophy and in the social sciences broadly construed:

  • The human subject seen as the centre of inquiry into human knowledge, such that it is impossible to philosophize about things as they exist independently of human perception or of how they are for us;[189]
  • The notion that is possible to discover and systematically explore the inherent limits to our ability to know entirely a priori;
  • The notion of the "categorical imperative", an assertion that people are naturally endowed with the ability and obligation toward right reason and acting. Perhaps his most famous quote is drawn from the Critique of Practical Reason: "Two things fill my mind with ever-increasing wonder and awe . . . : the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me."
  • The concept of "conditions of possibility", as in his notion of "the conditions of possible experience" – that is that things, knowledge, and forms of consciousness rest on prior conditions that make them possible, so that, to understand or to know them, we must first understand these conditions;
  • The theory that objective experience is actively constituted or constructed by the functioning of the human mind;
  • His notion of moral autonomy as central to humanity;
  • His assertion of the principle that human beings should be treated as ends rather than as means.

Kant's ideas have been incorporated into a variety of schools of thought. These include German idealism, Marxism, positivism, phenomenology, existentialism, critical theory, linguistic philosophy, structuralism, post-structuralism, and deconstruction.[citation needed]

Historical influence

During his own life, much critical attention was paid to his thought. He influenced Reinhold, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel and Novalis during the 1780s and 1790s. The school of thinking known as German idealism developed from his writings. The German idealists Fichte and Schelling, for example, tried to bring traditional "metaphysically" laden notions like "the Absolute", "God", and "Being" into the scope of Kant's critical thought.[190] In so doing, the German idealists tried to reverse Kant's view that we cannot know what we cannot observe.

 
Statue of Immanuel Kant in Kaliningrad (Königsberg), Russia. Replica by Harald Haacke [de] of the original by Christian Daniel Rauch lost in 1945.

The influential English Romantic poet and aesthetic philosopher Samuel Taylor Coleridge was greatly influenced by Kant and helped to spread awareness of him, and of German idealism generally, in the UK and the USA. In his Biographia Literaria (1817), he credits Kant's ideas in coming to believe that the mind is not a passive but an active agent in the apprehension of reality.

Hegel was one of Kant's first major critics. The main accusations Hegel charged Kant's philosophy with were formalism (or "abstractism") and irrationality. In Hegel's view the entire project of setting a "transcendental subject" (i.e. human consciousness) apart from nature, history, and society was fundamentally flawed,[191] although parts of that very project could be put to good use in a new direction, that Hegel called the "absolute idealism". Similar concerns moved Hegel's criticisms to Kant's concept of moral autonomy, to which Hegel opposed an ethic focused on the "ethical life" of the community.[192] In a sense, Hegel's notion of "ethical life" is meant to subsume, rather than replace, Kantian ethics. And Hegel can be seen as trying to defend Kant's idea of freedom as going beyond finite "desires", by means of reason. Thus, in contrast to later critics like Nietzsche or Russell, Hegel shares some of Kant's concerns.[193]

Kant's thinking on religion was used in Britain to challenge the decline in religious faith in the nineteenth century. British Catholic writers, notably G. K. Chesterton and Hilaire Belloc, followed this approach. Ronald Englefield debated this movement, and Kant's use of language.[f] Criticisms of Kant were common in the realist views of the new positivism at that time.

Arthur Schopenhauer was strongly influenced by Kant's transcendental idealism. He, like G. E. Schulze, Jacobi and Fichte before him, was critical of Kant's theory of the thing in itself. Things in themselves, they argued, are neither the cause of what we observe nor are they completely beyond our access. Ever since the first Critique of Pure Reason philosophers have been critical of Kant's theory of the thing in itself. Many have argued, if such a thing exists beyond experience then one cannot posit that it affects us causally, since that would entail stretching the category "causality" beyond the realm of experience.[g] For Schopenhauer things in themselves do not exist outside the non-rational will. The world, as Schopenhauer would have it, is the striving and largely unconscious will. Michael Kelly, in the preface to his 1910 book Kant's Ethics and Schopenhauer's Criticism, stated: "Of Kant it may be said that what is good and true in his philosophy would have been buried with him, were it not for Schopenhauer...."

With the success and wide influence of Hegel's writings, Kant's influence began to wane, though there was in Germany a movement that hailed a return to Kant in the 1860s, beginning with the publication of Kant und die Epigonen in 1865 by Otto Liebmann. His motto was "Back to Kant", and a re-examination of his ideas began (see Neo-Kantianism). During the turn of the 20th century there was an important revival of Kant's theoretical philosophy, known as the Marburg School, represented in the work of Hermann Cohen, Paul Natorp, Ernst Cassirer,[194] and anti-Neo-Kantian Nicolai Hartmann.[195]

Kant's notion of "Critique" has been quite influential. The early German Romantics, especially Friedrich Schlegel in his "Athenaeum Fragments", used Kant's self-reflexive conception of criticism in their Romantic theory of poetry.[196] Also in aesthetics, Clement Greenberg, in his classic essay "Modernist Painting", uses Kantian criticism, what Greenberg refers to as "immanent criticism", to justify the aims of abstract painting, a movement Greenberg saw as aware of the key limitation—flatness—that makes up the medium of painting.[197] French philosopher Michel Foucault was also greatly influenced by Kant's notion of "Critique" and wrote several pieces on Kant for a re-thinking of the Enlightenment as a form of "critical thought". He went so far as to classify his own philosophy as a "critical history of modernity, rooted in Kant".[198]

Kant believed that mathematical truths were forms of synthetic a priori knowledge, which means they are necessary and universal, yet known through the apriori 'intuition' of space and time, as transcendental preconditions of all phenomenal sense experience.[199] Kant's often brief remarks about mathematics influenced the mathematical school known as intuitionism, a movement in philosophy of mathematics opposed to Hilbert's formalism, and Frege and Bertrand Russell's logicism.[200]

Influence on modern thinkers

 
West German postage stamp, 1974, commemorating the 250th anniversary of Kant's birth

With his Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch, Kant is considered to have foreshadowed many of the ideas that have come to form the democratic peace theory, one of the main controversies in political science.[201]

Prominent recent Kantians include the British philosophers P. F. Strawson,[202] Onora O'Neill[203] and Quassim Cassam,[204] and the American philosophers Wilfrid Sellars[205] and Christine Korsgaard.[206] Due to the influence of Strawson and Sellars, among others, there has been a renewed interest in Kant's view of the mind. Central to many debates in philosophy of psychology and cognitive science is Kant's conception of the unity of consciousness.[207]

Jürgen Habermas and John Rawls are two significant political and moral philosophers whose work is strongly influenced by Kant's moral philosophy.[208] They argued against relativism,[209] supporting the Kantian view that universality is essential to any viable moral philosophy. Jean-François Lyotard, however, emphasized the indeterminacy in the nature of thought and language and has engaged in debates with Habermas based on the effects this indeterminacy has on philosophical and political debates.[210]

Mou Zongsan's study of Kant has been cited as a highly crucial part in the development of Mou's personal philosophy, namely New Confucianism. Widely regarded as the most influential Kant scholar in China, Mou's rigorous critique of Kant's philosophy—having translated all three of Kant's critiques—served as an ardent attempt to reconcile Chinese and Western philosophy whilst increasing pressure to westernize in China.[211][212]

Kant's influence also has extended to the social, behavioral, and physical sciences, as in the sociology of Max Weber, the psychology of Jean Piaget and Carl Gustav Jung,[213][214] and the linguistics of Noam Chomsky. Kant's work on mathematics and synthetic a priori knowledge is also cited by theoretical physicist Albert Einstein as an early influence on his intellectual development, but which he later criticised heavily and rejected.[215] He held the view that "if one does not want to assert that relativity theory goes against reason, one cannot retain the a priori concepts and norms of Kant's system".[216] However, Kant scholar Stephen Palmquist has argued that Einstein's rejection of Kant's influence was primarily "a response to mistaken interpretations of Kant being adopted by contemporary philosophers", when in fact Kant's transcendental perspective informed Einstein's early worldview and led to his insights regarding simultaneity, and eventually to his proposal of the theory of relativity.[217] Because of the thoroughness of the Kantian paradigm shift, his influence extends to thinkers who neither specifically refer to his work nor use his terminology.

In recent years, there has been renewed interest in Kant's theory of mind from the point of view of formal logic and computer science.[218]

Joshua Greene's 2008 article "The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul"[219] argues that Kantian/deontological ethics is best understood as rationalization rather than rationalism—an attempt to justify intuitive moral judgments post-hoc. Several philosophers have written critical responses.[220][221][222][223]

Film/television

Kant and his work was heavily referenced in the comedy television show The Good Place, as the show deals with the subject of ethics and moral philosophy.[224]

Bibliography

List of major works

Collected works in German

Printed version

Wilhelm Dilthey inaugurated the Academy edition (the Akademie-Ausgabe abbreviated as AA or Ak) of Kant's writings (Gesammelte Schriften, Königlich-Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin, 1902–38) in 1895,[251] and served as its first editor. The volumes are grouped into four sections:

  • I. Kant's published writings (vols. 1–9),
  • II. Kant's correspondence (vols. 10–13),
  • III. Kant's literary remains, or Nachlass (vols. 14–23), and
  • IV. Student notes from Kant's lectures (vols. 24–29).

Electronic version

  • (vols. 1–23).

See also

Notes

  1. ^ However, Kant has also been interpreted as a defender of the coherence theory of truth.[2]
  2. ^ a b "Up to now it has been assumed that all our cognition must conform to the objects; but all attempts to find out something about them a priori through concepts that would extend our cognition have, on this presupposition, come to nothing. Hence let us once try whether we do not get farther with the problems of metaphysics by assuming that the objects must conform to our cognition, which would agree better with the requested possibility of an a priori cognition of them, which is to establish something about objects before they are given to us. This would be just like the first thoughts of Copernicus, who, when he did not make good progress in the explanation of the celestial motions if he assumed that the entire celestial host revolves around the observer, tried to see if he might not have greater success if he made the observer revolve and left the stars at rest. Now in metaphysics we can try in a similar way regarding the intuition of objects. If intuition has to conform to the constitution of the objects, then I do not see how we can know anything of them a priori; but if the object (as an object of the senses) conforms to the constitution of our faculty of intuition, then I can very well represent this possibility to myself."[33]: 110 (B xvi–vii) 
  3. ^ Nietzsche wrote that "Kant wanted to prove, in a way that would dumbfound the common man, that the common man was right: that was the secret joke of this soul."[39]
  4. ^ Kant himself seems to have found his contribution not significant enough that he published his arguments in a newspaper commentary on the prize question and did not submit them to the Academy: "Whether the Earth has Undergone an Alteration of its Axial Rotation". Kant's Cosmogony. Translated by Hastie, William. Glasgow: James Maclehose. 1900 [1754]. pp. 1–11. Retrieved 29 March 2022.. The prize was instead awarded in 1756 to P. Frisi, who incorrectly argued against the slowing down of the spin.[72]
  5. ^ It has been noted that in 1778, in response to one of these offers by a former pupil, Kant wrote:

    Any change makes me apprehensive, even if it offers the greatest promise of improving my condition, and I am persuaded by this natural instinct of mine that I must take heed if I wish that the threads which the Fates spin so thin and weak in my case to be spun to any length. My great thanks, to my well-wishers and friends, who think so kindly of me as to undertake my welfare, but at the same time a most humble request to protect me in my current condition from any disturbance.[87]

  6. ^ See Englefield's article "Kant as Defender of the Faith in Nineteenth-century England", Question, 12, 16–27 (London, Pemberton) reprinted in Critique of Pure Verbiage, Essays on Abuses of Language in Literary, Religious, and Philosophical Writings, edited by G. A. Wells and D. R. Oppenheimer, Open Court, 1990.
  7. ^ For a review of this problem and the relevant literature see The Thing in Itself and the Problem of Affection in the revised edition of Henry Allison's Kant's Transcendental Idealism.

References

  1. ^ a b c Since he had written his last habilitation thesis 14 years earlier, a new habilitation thesis was required (see S.J. McGrath, Joseph Carew (eds.), Rethinking German Idealism, Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, p. 24).
  2. ^ "The Coherence Theory of Truth (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". from the original on 1 November 2019. Retrieved 29 April 2020.
  3. ^ David, Marian. "The Correspondence Theory of Truth". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Archived copy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 14 February 2014. Retrieved 18 October 2019.{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  4. ^ Rockmore, Tom (2004). On Foundationalism: A Strategy for Metaphysical Realism. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 65. ISBN 978-0-7425-3427-8.
  5. ^ Frederick C. Beiser, German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781–1801, Harvard University Press, 2002, part I.
  6. ^ Santos, Robinson dos; Schmidt, Elke Elisabeth (2017). Realism and Antirealism in Kant's Moral Philosophy: New Essays. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. p. 199. ISBN 978-3-11-057451-7. Kant is an indirect realist.
  7. ^ Hanna, Robert, Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Clarendon Press, 2006, p. 16.
  8. ^ Oberst, Michael (2015). "Kant on Universals". History of Philosophy Quarterly. 32 (4): 335–352.
  9. ^ Hanna, Robert (January 2008). "Kantian non-conceptualism". Philosophical Studies. 137 (1): 41–64. doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9166-0. S2CID 170296391.
  10. ^ The application of the term "perceptual non-conceptualism" to Kant's philosophy of perception is debatable (see Hanna, Robert. "The Togetherness Principle, Kant's Conceptualism, and Kant's Non-Conceptualism: Supplement to Kant's Theory of Judgment". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Kant's Theory of Judgment > the Togetherness Principle, Kant's Conceptualism, and Kant's Non-Conceptualism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 11 June 2018. Retrieved 20 August 2018.).
  11. ^ Biographies: Königsberg Professors – Manchester University 26 December 2016 at the Wayback Machine: "His lectures on logic and metaphysics were quite popular, and he still taught theology, philosophy, and mathematics when Kant studied at the university. The only textbook found in Kant's library that stems from his student years was Marquardt's book on astronomy."
  12. ^ KrV A51/B75–6. See also: Edward Willatt, Kant, Deleuze and Architectonics, Continuum, 2010 p. 17: "Kant argues that cognition can only come about as a result of the union of the abstract work of the understanding and the concrete input of sensation."
  13. ^ Burnham, Douglas. "Immanuel Kant: Aesthetics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 20 February 2018. Retrieved 18 October 2019.
  14. ^ KpV 101–102 (=Ak V, 121–22). See also: Paul Saurette, The Kantian Imperative: Humiliation, Common Sense, Politics, University of Toronto Press, 2005, p. 255 n. 32.
  15. ^ "Meet Mr Green". The Economist. Retrieved 11 December 2022.
  16. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 24 September 2015. Retrieved 11 December 2022.
  17. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 251.
  18. ^ I. Kant, Theoretical Philosophy: 1755–1770, Cambridge University Press, p. 496
  19. ^ Immanuel Kant, Philosophical Correspondence, 1759–1799, University of Chicago Press, 1967, p. 18.
  20. ^ "Kant" 27 September 2019 at the Wayback Machine. Collins English Dictionary.
  21. ^ "Kant" 23 October 2014 at the Wayback Machine. Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary.
  22. ^ Wells, John C. (2008). Longman Pronunciation Dictionary (3rd ed.). Longman. ISBN 978-1-4058-8118-0.
  23. ^ Jones, Daniel (2011). Roach, Peter; Setter, Jane; Esling, John (eds.). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (18th ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-15255-6.
  24. ^ "Immanuel". Duden (in German). from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 20 October 2018.
  25. ^ "Kant". Duden (in German). from the original on 20 October 2018. Retrieved 20 October 2018.
  26. ^ a b c McCormick, Matt. "Immanuel Kant: Metaphysics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 15 February 2019. Retrieved 20 February 2019.
  27. ^ a b Rohlf, Michael (2020), "Immanuel Kant", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, from the original on 3 September 2020, retrieved 27 May 2020
  28. ^ a b "Immanuel Kant | Biography, Philosophy, Books, & Facts". Encyclopedia Britannica. from the original on 16 June 2015. Retrieved 27 May 2020.
  29. ^ Durant, Will; Durant, Ariel (1967). The Story of Civilization: Rousseau and Revolution. MJF Books. pp. 571, 574. ISBN 978-1-56731-021-4. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 22 August 2020.
  30. ^ Nigel Warburton (2011). "Chapter 19: Rose-tinted reality: Immanuel Kant". A little history of philosophy. Yale University Press. p. 134. ISBN 978-0-300-15208-1.
  31. ^ Kitcher, Patrica (1996) [First edition originally published in 1781; second edition originally published in 1787]. "Introduction by Patricia Kitcher, C. The Analytic of Principles". Critique of Pure Reason. By Kant, Immanuel. Translated by Pluhar, Werner S. (Unified Edition with all variants from the 1781 and 1787 editions ed.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. p. l. ISBN 0-87220-257-7. Although Hume's name is not mentioned in either version of this section, from the beginning, Kant's readers have understood that his purpose was to vindicate the causal concept after Hume's devastating attack […] Kant's "reply to Hume" was to argue we could have no cognition of events, of objects changing by acquiring or losing a property, unless we used a concept of causation that included both the offending and related properties of universality and necessity.
  32. ^ There are two relatively recent translations:
    • Kant, Immanuel (1999). Critique of Pure Reason. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Translated by Guyer, Paul; Wood, Allen W. Cambridge: Cambridge U.P. ISBN 978-0-5216-5729-7. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 22 August 2020.
    • Kant, Immanuel (1996). Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Pluhar, Werner S. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 978-0-87220-257-3.
    Both translations have their virtues and both are better than earlier translations: McLaughlin, Peter (1999). "Review". Erkenntnis. 51 (2/3): 357. doi:10.1023/a:1005483714722. Page references to the Critique of Pure Reason are commonly given to the first (1781) and second (1787) editions, as published in the Prussian Academy series, as respectively "A [page number]" and "B [page number]".
  33. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Kant, Immanuel (1999). Critique of Pure Reason. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge U.P. ISBN 978-0-5216-5729-7.
  34. ^ Vanzo, Alberto (January 2013). "Kant on Empiricism and Rationalism". History of Philosophy Quarterly. 30 (1): 53–74. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 17 December 2015.
  35. ^ Rohlf, Michael. "Immanuel Kant". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 12 January 2012. Retrieved 6 October 2015.
  36. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1784). "Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose".
  37. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer, On the Basis of Morals, in The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, trans. Chris Janaway (2009), sections 4–5.
  38. ^ Friedrich Nietzsche, The Anti-Christ (1895), para. 10 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine.
  39. ^ Friedrich Nietzsche (trans. Walter Arnold Kaufmann), The Portable Nietzsche, 1976, p. 96.
  40. ^ a b c d Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (1997). Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader. Wiley. pp. 103–131. ISBN 978-0-631-20339-1. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  41. ^ a b c Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi (1997). Race and the Enlightenment: A Reader. Wiley. pp. 39–48. ISBN 978-0-631-20136-6. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  42. ^ a b c Bouie, Jamelle (5 June 2018). "How the Enlightenment Created Modern Race Thinking and Why We Should Confront It". Slate Magazine. from the original on 15 June 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  43. ^ a b Bernasconi, Robert (2010). "Defining Race Scientifically: A response to Michael Banton". Ethnicities. 10 (1): 141–148. doi:10.1177/14687968100100010802. ISSN 1468-7968. JSTOR 23890861. S2CID 143925406.
  44. ^ a b c Kleingeld, Pauline (October 2007). "Kant's Second Thoughts on Race" (PDF). The Philosophical Quarterly. 57 (229): 573–592. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.498.x. hdl:11370/e15b6815-5eab-42d6-a789-24a2f6ecb946. S2CID 55185762. (PDF) from the original on 16 February 2019. Retrieved 14 December 2020.
  45. ^ "Cosmopolis". Koenigsberg-is-dead.de. 23 April 2001. from the original on 22 March 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  46. ^ Mortensen, Hans and Gertrud, Kants väterliche Ahnen und ihre Umwelt, Rede von 1952 in Jahrbuch der Albertus-Universität zu Königsberg, Pr., Holzner-Verlag, Kitzingen, Main 1953, Vol. 3, p. 26.
  47. ^ R.K. Murray, "The Origin of Immanuel Kant's Family Name", Kantian Review 13(1), March 2008, pp. 190-93.
  48. ^ Rosa Kohlheim, Volker Kohlheim, Duden – Familiennamen: Herkunft und Bedeutung von 20.000 Nachnamen, Bibliographisches Institut & F.A. Brockhaus AG, Mannheim 2005, p. 365.
  49. ^ Haupt, Viktor. (PDF). freunde-kants.com (in German). p. 7. Archived from the original on 25 September 2015.
  50. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 26.
  51. ^ Pasternack, Lawrence; Fugate, Courtney (2020), "Kant's Philosophy of Religion", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 25 February 2021
  52. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 47.
  53. ^ Metaphysics, p. 131
  54. ^ "Immanuel Kant". Christian Research Institute. 30 September 2010. from the original on 20 June 2017. Retrieved 15 June 2017.
  55. ^ "While this sounds skeptical, Kant is only agnostic about our knowledge of metaphysical objects such as God. And, as noted above, Kant's agnosticism leads to the conclusion that we can neither affirm nor deny claims made by traditional metaphysics." Andrew Fiala, J.M.D. Meiklejohn, Critique of Pure Reason – Introduction, p. xi.
  56. ^ Edward J. Verstraete (2008). "The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics". In Ed Hindson; Ergun Caner (eds.). The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics: Surveying the Evidence for the Truth of Christianity. Harvest House Publishers. p. 82. ISBN 978-0-7369-2084-1. It is in this sense that modern atheism rests heavily upon the skepticism of David Hume and the agnosticism of Immanuel Kant.
  57. ^ Norman L. Geisler; Frank Turek (2004). "Kant's Agnosticism: Should We Be Agnostic About It?". I Don't Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist. Crossway. pp. 59–60. ISBN 978-1-58134-561-2. Immanuel Kant's impact has been even more devastating to the Christian worldview than David Hume's. For if Kant's philosophy is right, then there is no way to know anything about the real world, even empirically verifiable things!
  58. ^ Gary D. Badcock (1997). Light of Truth and Fire of Love: A Theology of the Holy Spirit. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. p. 113. ISBN 978-0-8028-4288-6. Kant has no interest in prayer or worship, and is in fact agnostic when it comes to such classical theological questions as the doctrine of God or of the Holy Spirit.
  59. ^ Norman L. Geisler, Paul K. Hoffman, ed. (2006). "The Agnosticism of Immanuel Kant". Why I Am a Christian: Leading Thinkers Explain Why They Believe. Baker Books. p. 45. ISBN 978-0-8010-6712-9.
  60. ^ Flinn, Frank K. (2007). Encyclopedia of Catholicism. Infobase Publishing. p. 10. ISBN 978-0-8160-7565-2. Following Locke, the classic agnostic claims not to accept more propositions than are warranted by empirical evidence. In this sense an agnostic appeals to Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), who claims in his Critique of Pure Reason that since God, freedom, immortality, and the soul can be both proved and disproved by theoretical reason, we ought to suspend judgement about them.
  61. ^ Hare, John E. (1996). The Moral Gap: Kantian Ethics, Human Limits, and God's Assistance. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 42. Hare further suggests that Kant is not, in the ordinary sense, an agnostic about God. In his view, Kant thinks that there are good moral grounds for theistic belief. A person who already understands the claims of duty will find the teachings of Christianity worthy of love, even though they are not objectively necessary (p. 47).
  62. ^ Kuehn, M. (2001). Kant: A biography. New York: Cambridge University Press. p 169
  63. ^ "Immanuel Kant, Joseph Green, Robert".
  64. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime. Trans. John T. Goldthwait. University of California Press, 1961, 2003. ISBN 978-0-520-24078-0
  65. ^ Vorländer, Karl (1924). "Bei Pfarrer Andersch in Judtschen". Immanuel Kant: Der Mann und das Werk (in German). from the original on 18 October 2019. Retrieved 18 October 2019.
  66. ^ Vorländer, Karl (1924). "Bei Major von Hülsen in Arnsdorf". Immanuel Kant: Der Mann und das Werk (in German). from the original on 1 August 2020. Retrieved 18 October 2019.
  67. ^ The American International Encyclopedia (New York: J.J. Little & Ives, 1954), Vol. IX.
  68. ^ Porter, Burton (2010). What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. p. 133.
  69. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 94.
  70. ^ Kuehn 2001, p. 98.
  71. ^ Eric Watkins (ed.), Immanuel Kant: Natural Science, Cambridge University Press, 2012: "Thoughts on the true estimation..." 7 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  72. ^ Schönfeld, Martin (2000). The Philosophy of the Young Kant: The Precritical Project. Oxford University Press. p. 84. ISBN 978-0-19-513218-2.
  73. ^ a b Brush, Stephen G. (2014). A History of Modern Planetary Physics: Nebulous Earth. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-521-44171-1.
  74. ^ See:
    • Kant, I. (1756a) "Von den Ursachen der Erderschütterungen bei Gelegenheit des Unglücks, welches die westliche Länder von Europa gegen das Ende des vorigen Jahres betroffen hat" [On the causes of the earthquakes on the occasion of the disaster which affected the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year] In: Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences), ed.s (1902) Kant's gesammelte Schriften [Kant's collected writings] (in German) Berlin, Germany: G. Reimer. vol. 1, pp. 417–427.
    • Kant, I. (1756b) "Geschichte und Naturbeschreibung der merkwürdigsten Vorfälle des Erdbebens, welches an dem Ende des 1755sten Jahres einen großen Theil der Erde erschüttert hat" [History and description of the nature of the most remarkable events of the earthquake which shook a large part of the Earth at the end of the year 1755], ibid. pp. 429–461.
    • Kant, I. (1756c) "Immanuel Kants fortgesetzte Betrachtung der seit einiger Zeit wahrgenommenen Erderschütterungen" [Immanuel Kant's continued consideration of the earthquakes that were felt some time ago], ibid. pp. 463–472.
    • Amador, Filomena (2004) "The causes of 1755 Lisbon earthquake on Kant" In: Escribano Benito, J.J.; Español González, L.; Martínez García, M.A., ed.s. Actas VIII Congreso de la Sociedad Española de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Técnicas [Proceedings of the Eighth Congress of the Spanish Society of the History of the Sciences and Technology] (in English) Logroño, Spain: Sociedad Española de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Técnicas (Universidad de la Rioja), vol. 2, pp. 485–495.
  75. ^ a b Richards, Paul (1974). "Kant's Geography and Mental Maps". Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers (61): 1–16. doi:10.2307/621596. JSTOR 621596.
  76. ^ Elden, Stuart (2009). "Reassessing Kant's geography" (PDF). Journal of Historical Geography. 35 (1): 3–25. doi:10.1016/j.jhg.2008.06.001. (PDF) from the original on 1 August 2020. Retrieved 27 September 2019.
  77. ^ Gamow, George (1947). One Two Three... Infinity. New York: Viking P. pp. 300ff.
  78. ^ "Address of the President of the Geological Society 1869". mathcs.clarku.edu. Retrieved 11 May 2022.
  79. ^ "On the causes of earthquakes on the occasion of the calamity that befell the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year (1756)". Kant: Natural Science. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge University Press. 2012. pp. 327–336. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139014380.009. ISBN 9780521363945.
  80. ^ a b Gulyga, Arsenij. Immanuel Kant: His Life and Thought. Trans., Marijan Despaltović. Boston: Birkhäuser, 1987, p. 62.
  81. ^ "Dreams of a Spirit-Seer". en.wikisource.org. Retrieved 10 December 2022.
  82. ^ "A Commentary on Kant's "Dreams of a Spirit-Seer". philpapers.org. Retrieved 10 December 2022.
  83. ^ Cf., for example, Susan Shell, The Embodiment of Reason (Chicago, 1996)
  84. ^ Kuehn, Manfred (2009). Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Background Source Materials. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. p. 276. ISBN 978-0-521-78162-6.
  85. ^ a b c Smith, Homer W. (1952). Man and His Gods. New York: Grosset & Dunlap. p. 404.
  86. ^ Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, p. 57 (Ak. 4:260)
  87. ^ Christopher Kul-Want and Andrzej Klimowski, Introducing Kant (Cambridge: Icon Books, 2005).[page needed] ISBN 978-1-84046-664-5
  88. ^ Smith, Homer W. (1952). Man and His Gods. New York: Grosset & Dunlap. p. 416.
  89. ^ Dorrien, Gary (2012). Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit: The Idealistic Logic of Modern Theology. Malden, MA: John Wiley & Sons. p. 37. ISBN 978-0-470-67331-7.
  90. ^ Copleston, Frederick Charles (2003). The Enlightenment: Voltaire to Kant. p. 146.
  91. ^ Sassen, Brigitte. Kant's Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy. 2000.
  92. ^ Ein Jahrhundert deutscher Literaturkritik, vol. III, Der Aufstieg zur Klassik in der Kritik der Zeit (Berlin, 1959), p. 315; as quoted in Gulyga, Arsenij. Immanuel Kant: His Life and Thought. Trans., Marijan Despaltović. Boston: Birkhäuser, 1987.
  93. ^ Gulyga, Arsenij. Immanuel Kant: His Life and Thought. Trans., Marijan Despaltović. Boston: Birkhäuser, 1987 pp. 28–29.
  94. ^ Guyer, Paul (2006). The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. p. 631. ISBN 978-0-521-82303-6.
  95. ^ a b c Werner S. Pluhar, Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 4 March 2020 at the Wayback Machine. 2009. Description 1 February 2020 at the Wayback Machine & Contents. With an Introduction 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine by Stephen Palmquist. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,
  96. ^ a b c d e Derrida, Vacant Chair p. 44.
  97. ^ "Open letter by Kant denouncing Fichte's Philosophy". Korpora.org (in German). from the original on 19 July 2011. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  98. ^ Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 1, (HUP, 1960), 'Kant and his Refutation of Idealism' p. 15
  99. ^ Kant, Immanuel, Logic, G.B. Jäsche (ed), R.S. Hartman, W. Schwarz (translators), Indianapolis, 1984, p. xv.
  100. ^ Karl Vorländer, Immanuel Kant: Der Mann und das Werk, Hamburg: Meiner, 1992, p. II 332.
  101. ^ "Heine on Immanuel Kant" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 23 November 2015. Retrieved 10 July 2015.
  102. ^ Examined Lives, From Socrates to Nietzsche, James Miller p. 284
  103. ^ Immanuel Kant and the Bo(a)rders of Art History Mark Cheetham, in The Subjects of Art History: Historical Objects in Contemporary Perspectives, p. 16
  104. ^ Beyer, Susanne (25 July 2014). "Resurrecting Königsberg: Russian City Looks to German Roots". Spiegel Online. from the original on 4 February 2018. Retrieved 3 February 2018.
  105. ^ "Executive order on establishing Immanuel Kant University".
  106. ^ Kishkovsky, Sophia (28 November 2018). "Kant monument splashed with pink paint in Kaliningrad". The Art Newspaper. from the original on 4 December 2018. Retrieved 3 December 2018.
  107. ^ The Science of Right, Conclusion.
  108. ^ In the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason Kant refers to space as "no discursive or...general conception of the relation of things, but a pure intuition" and maintained that "We can only represent to ourselves one space". The "general notion of spaces...depends solely upon limitations" (Meikeljohn trans., A25). In the second edition of the CPR, Kant adds, "The original representation of space is an a priori intuition, not a concept" (Kemp Smith trans., B40). In regard to time, Kant states that "Time is not a discursive, or what is called a general concept, but a pure form of sensible intuition. Different times are but parts of one and the same time; and the representation which can be given only through a single object is intuition" (A31/B47). For the differences in the discursive use of reason according to concepts and its intuitive use through the construction of concepts, see Critique of Pure Reason (A719/B747 ff. and A837/B865). On "One and the same thing in space and time" and the mathematical construction of concepts, see A724/B752.
  109. ^ "Immanuel Kant (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". from the original on 14 November 2019. Retrieved 29 May 2019.
  110. ^ "Kant, Immanuel definition of Kant, Immanuel in the Free Online Encyclopedia". Encyclopedia2.thefreedictionary.com. from the original on 2 March 2014. Retrieved 26 February 2014.
  111. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. § 2. from the original on 1 August 2020. Retrieved 22 March 2020.
  112. ^ Pigeard de Gurbert, Guillaume (2015). Kant et le temps (in French). Paris: Kimé. p. 57. ISBN 978-2-84174-708-5.
  113. ^ The German word Anschauung, which Kant used, literally means 'looking at' and generally means what in philosophy in English is called "perception". However it sometimes is rendered as "intuition": not, however, with the vernacular meaning of an indescribable or mystical experience or sixth sense, but rather with the meaning of the direct perception or grasping of sensory phenomena. In this article, both terms, "perception" and "intuition" are used to stand for Kant's Anschauung.
  114. ^ Pigeard de Gurbert, Guillaume (2015). Kant et le temps (in French). Paris: Kimé. ISBN 978-2-84174-708-5.
  115. ^ a b c d e f g h Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, pp. 35–43.
  116. ^ Deleuze on Kant 14 November 2007 at the Wayback Machine, from where the definitions of a priori and a posteriori were obtained.
  117. ^ Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, the Introduction to the Hackett edition.
  118. ^ Balanovskiy, Valentin (2018). "What is Kant's Transcendental Reflection?". Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy. 75: 17–27. doi:10.5840/wcp232018751730. ISBN 978-1-63435-038-9. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 29 May 2020.
  119. ^ The distinction between rational and philosophical knowledge is given in the Preface to the Groundwork, 1785.
  120. ^ Kant, Foundations, p. 421.
  121. ^ Kant, Foundations, p. 408.
  122. ^ Kant, Foundations, pp. 420–421.
  123. ^ a b c d Kant, Foundations, p. 436.
  124. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1993) [1785]. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Ellington, James W. (3rd ed.). Hackett. p. 30. ISBN 978-0-87220-166-8.. It is standard to also reference the Akademie Ausgabe of Kant's works. The Groundwork occurs in the fourth volume. The above citation is taken from 4:421.
  125. ^ Millennium Ecosystem Assessment (2003) Ecosystems and Well-being: A Framework for Assessment. Washington, DC: Island Press, p. 142.
  126. ^ "Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch: Appendix 1". Constitution.org. from the original on 2 May 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  127. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1796). Project for a Perpetual Peace, p. 61. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  128. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1838). Hartenstein, G. (ed.). Immanuel Kant's Werke, revidirte Gesammtausg (in German). p. 456. Retrieved 24 July 2009. pereat mundus Kant.
  129. ^ Kant, Foundations, p. 437.
  130. ^ "Kant and the German Enlightenment" in "History of Ethics". Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 3, pp. 95–96. MacMillan, 1973.
  131. ^ Kant, Foundations, pp. 400, 429.
  132. ^ Kant, Foundations, pp. 437–38.
  133. ^ Kant, Foundations, pp. 438–439. See also Kingdom of Ends
  134. ^ Karl Leonhard Reinhold, Letters on the Kantian Philosophy (1786), 3rd Letter
  135. ^ Johann Schultz, Exposition of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1784), 141.
  136. ^ "The Protestant pastor is the grandfather of German philosophy...German philosophy is at bottom—a cunning theology...Why the rejoicing heard through the German academic world—three-quarters composed of the sons of pastors and teachers-at the appearance of Kant? Why the Germans' conviction, which still find echo even today, that with Kant things were taking a turn of the better? Kant's success is merely a theologian's success". Nietzsche, The Antichrist, 10
  137. ^ a b Immanuel Kant. Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone (1793), Book IV, Part 1, Section 1, "The Christian religion as a natural religion."
  138. ^ Pasternack, Lawrence; Rossi, Philip. "Kant's Philosophy of Religion". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 9 July 2010. Retrieved 18 October 2019.
  139. ^ For example Peter Byrne, who wrote about Kant's relationship with deism. Byrne, Peter (2007), Kant on God, London: Ashgate, p. 159.
  140. ^ Wood, Allen W. (1970), Kant's moral religion, London and Ithaca: Cornell University Press, p. 16.
  141. ^ Westphal, Merold (2010),The Emerge of Modern Philosophy of Religion, in Taliaferro, Charles, Draper, Paul and Quinn, Philip (editors), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Oxford: Blackwell, p. 135.
  142. ^ Iţu, Mircia (2004), Dumnezeu şi religia în concepţia lui Immanuel Kant din Religia în limitele raţiunii, in Boboc, Alexandru and Mariş, N.I. (editors), Studii de istoria filosofiei universale, volume 12, Bucharest: Romanian Academy.
  143. ^ Wood, Allen W. (2020), Kant and Religion, Cambridge University Press, p.2.
  144. ^ See e.g., Lawrence Pasternack, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason (New York, Routledge, 2014), pp.239-240.
  145. ^ Palmquist, Stephen (1992), "Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality?", Kant-Studien 83.2, pp. 129–148.
  146. ^ The concept of freedom is also handled in the third section of the Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals; in the Critique of Practical Reason see § VII and § VIII.
  147. ^ 5:65–67
  148. ^ Susanne Bobzien, 'Die Kategorien der Freiheit bei Kant', in Kant: Analysen, Probleme, Kritik Vol. 1, 1988, 193–220.
  149. ^ Critique of Judgment in "Kant, Immanuel" Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol 4. Macmillan, 1973.
  150. ^ Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A22/B36.
  151. ^ Beardsley, Monroe. "History of Aesthetics". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 1, section on "Toward a unified aesthetics", p. 25, Macmillan 1973. Baumgarten coined the term "aesthetics" and expanded, clarified, and unified Wolffian aesthetic theory, but had left the Aesthetica unfinished (See also: Tonelli, Giorgio. "Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 1, Macmillan 1973). In Bernard's translation of the Critique of Judgment he indicates in the notes that Kant's reference in § 15 in regard to the identification of perfection and beauty is probably a reference to Baumgarten.
  152. ^ German Idealism in "History of Aesthetics" Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol 1. Macmillan, 1973.
  153. ^ Kant's general discussions of the distinction between "cognition" and "conscious of" are also given in the Critique of Pure Reason (notably A320/B376), and section V and the conclusion of section VIII of his Introduction in Logic.
  154. ^ Clewis, Robert (2009). "The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom". Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. from the original on 20 October 2012. Retrieved 8 December 2011.
  155. ^ Jakobidze-Gitman, Alexander (2020). "Kant's Situated Approach to Musicking and Joking". Journal of Interdisciplinary Music Studies. 10: 17–33. doi:10.25364/24.10:2020.2.
  156. ^ Clewis, Robert (2020). Kant's Humorous Writings: An Illustrated Guide. London: Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-350-11279-7.
  157. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Idea for a Universal History. Trans. Lewis White Beck (20, 22).
  158. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Idea for a Universal History. Trans. Lewis White Beck (26).
  159. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch 6 April 2019 at the Wayback Machine (1795)
  160. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Perpetual Peace. Trans. Lewis White Beck (377).
  161. ^ Manfred Riedel Between Tradition and Revolution: The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy, Cambridge 1984
  162. ^ On History, (ed. L.W. Beck, New York: Bobbs Merill, 1963, p. 106).
  163. ^ History of Political Philosophy, edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, The University of Chicago Press, 1987, pp. 581–582, 603
  164. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Perpetual Peace. Trans. Lewis White Beck (352).
  165. ^ Wilson, Holly (2006). Kant's Pragmatic Anthropology. Albany: State University of New York Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-7914-6849-4.
  166. ^ Thomas Sturm, Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen (Paderborn: Mentis Verlag, 2009).
  167. ^ Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, ed. Robert B. Louden, introduction by Manfred Kuehn, Cambridge University Press, 2006
  168. ^ Kant, I. (1798). Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view. trans. Mary Gregor). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974 (VII).
  169. ^ Gregor, Brian. "Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. By Immanuel Kant. Translated and edited by Robert B. Louden". Heythrop. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  170. ^ Kant, Immanuel. "Kant on the Different Races of Man" (PDF). UMass Amherst. (PDF) from the original on 1 August 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  171. ^ a b c d Mills, Charles W. (2017). Black Rights/White Wrongs: The Critique of Racial Liberalism. Oxford University Press. pp. 169–193. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190245412.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-024545-0. from the original on 16 June 2020. Retrieved 15 June 2020.
  172. ^ "Kant on the different human races (1777)". Black Central Europe. 4 February 2016. from the original on 16 June 2020. Retrieved 16 June 2020.
  173. ^ Deepak, J Sai (2021). India, that is Bharat: Coloniality, Civilisation, Constitution (1st ed.). USA: Bloomsbury. p. 107. ISBN 9789354352508.
  174. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1798). Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. p. 236.
  175. ^ Shrage, Laurie (18 March 2019). "Should we continue to teach thinkers like Kant, Voltaire and Hume without mention of the harmful prejudices they helped legitimize?". The New York Times. Retrieved 10 November 2022.
  176. ^ "Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace"". www.mtholyoke.edu. Retrieved 3 March 2021.
  177. ^ Hay, Carol (9 December 2013). "A Feminist Kant". Opinionator.
  178. ^ Huseyinzadegan, Dilek; Pascoe, Jordan (7 April 2021). "Dismantling Kantian Frames: Notes toward a Feminist Politics of Location and Accountability".
  179. ^ Gould, Timothy (1990). "Intensity and Its Audiences: Notes towards a Feminist Perspective on the Kantian Sublime". The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 48 (4): 305–315. doi:10.2307/431568. JSTOR 431568 – via JSTOR.
  180. ^ https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/232845343.pdf
  181. ^ https://philpapers.org/archive/MIKKOM.pdf
  182. ^ Hay, Carol (27 January 2013). Hay, Carol (ed.). Kantianism, Liberalism, and Feminism: Resisting Oppression. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 50–88. doi:10.1057/9781137003904_2 – via Springer Link.
  183. ^ https://philarchive.org/archive/VARKAW-10
  184. ^ "A Feminist Defence of Kant".
  185. ^ Prof. Oliver A. Johnson claims that, "With the possible exception of Plato's Republic, (Critique of Pure Reason) is the most important philosophical book ever written." Article on Kant within the collection "Great thinkers of the Western World", Ian P. McGreal, Ed., HarperCollins, 1992.
  186. ^ Strawson, Peter. Bounds of Sense: Essay on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason". ASIN 0415040302.
  187. ^ "Einstein on Kant". www.pitt.edu. from the original on 9 August 2020. Retrieved 2 September 2020.
  188. ^ Perrick, Michael (1985). "Kant and Kripke on Necessary Empirical Truths". Mind. 94 (376): 596–598. doi:10.1093/mind/XCIV.376.596. ISSN 0026-4423. JSTOR 2254731.
  189. ^ See Stephen Palmquist, "The Architectonic Form of Kant's Copernican Logic", Metaphilosophy 17:4 (October 1986), pp. 266–288; revised and reprinted as Chapter III of Kant's System of Perspectives 14 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine: An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  190. ^ There is much debate in the recent scholarship about the extent to which Fichte and Schelling actually overstep the boundaries of Kant's critical philosophy, thus entering the realm of dogmatic or pre-Critical philosophy. Beiser's German Idealism discusses some of these issues. Beiser, Frederick C. German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism, 1781–1801. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2002.
  191. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1827). Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline. Heidelberg. pp. 14–15.
  192. ^ Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Natural Law: The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, Its Place in Moral Philosophy, and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences. trans. T. M. Knox. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1975. Hegel's mature view and his concept of "ethical life" is elaborated in his Philosophy of Right. Hegel, Philosophy of Right. trans. T. M. Knox. Oxford University Press, 1967.
  193. ^ Robert Pippin's Hegel's Idealism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) emphasizes the continuity of Hegel's concerns with Kant's. Robert Wallace, Hegel's Philosophy of Reality, Freedom, and God (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) explains how Hegel's Science of Logic defends Kant's idea of freedom as going beyond finite "inclinations", contra skeptics such as David Hume.
  194. ^ Beck, Lewis White. "Neo-Kantianism". In Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 5–6. Macmillan, 1973. Article on Neo-Kantianism by a translator and scholar of Kant.
  195. ^ Cerf, Walter. "Nicolai Hartmann". In Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 3–4. Macmillan, 1973. Nicolai was a realist who later rejected the idealism of Neo-Kantianism, his anti-Neo-Kantian views emerging with the publication of the second volume of Hegel (1929).
  196. ^ Schlegel, Friedrich. "Athenaeum Fragments", in Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Peter Firchow. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1991. See especially fragments Nos. 1, 43, 44.
  197. ^ Greenberg, Clement. "Modernist Painting", in The Philosophy of Art, ed. Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley, McGraw-Hill, 1995.
  198. ^ See "Essential Works of Foucault: 1954–1984 vol. 2: Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology." Ed. by James Faubion, Trans. Robert Hurley et al. New York City: The New Press, 1998 (2010 reprint). See "Foucault, Michel, 1926 –" entry by Maurice Florence.
  199. ^ For a discussion and qualified defense of this position, see Stephen Palmquist, "A Priori Knowledge in Perspective: (I) Mathematics, Method and Pure Intuition", The Review of Metaphysics 41:1 (September 1987), pp. 3–22.
  200. ^ Körner, Stephan, The Philosophy of Mathematics, Dover, 1986. For an analysis of Kant's writings on mathematics see, Friedman, Michael, Kant and the Exact Sciences, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1992.
  201. ^ Ray, James Lee (1998). . Annual Review of Political Science. 1: 27–46. doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.1.1.27. Archived from the original on 17 February 2008.
  202. ^ Strawson, P. F., The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Routledge: 2004. When first published in 1966, this book forced many Anglo-American philosophers to reconsider Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.
  203. ^ Aridi, Sara (14 March 2017). "Onora O'Neill Wins Holberg Prize for Academic Research". The New York Times. from the original on 9 January 2019. Retrieved 9 January 2019.
  204. ^ Cassam, Q., "The Possibility of Knowledge" Oxford: 2009
  205. ^ Sellars, Wilfrid, Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes. Ridgeview Publishing Company, 1967
  206. ^ Korsgaard, Christine. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 978-0-521-49644-5 Not a commentary, but a defense of a broadly Kantian approach to ethics
  207. ^ Brook, Andrew. Kant and the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. See also, Meerbote, R. "Kant's Functionalism". In: J. C. Smith, ed. Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel, 1991. Brook has an article on Kant's View of the Mind in the Stanford Encyclopedia 9 July 2010 at the Wayback Machine
  208. ^ See Habermas, J. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1996. For Rawls see, Rawls, John. Theory of Justice Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1971. Rawls has a well-known essay on Kant's concept of good. See, Rawls, "Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy" in Kant's Transcendental Deductions. Ed. Eckart Förster. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989.
  209. ^ Habermas, J. (1994): The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of Its Voices. In: Habermas, J. (Eds.): Postmetaphysical Thinking. Political Essays, Cambridge, Massachusetts: 115–148.
  210. ^ Rorty, R. (2984) Habermas and Lyotard on postmodernity. Praxis International (32–44)
  211. ^ Palmquist, Stephen (19 November 2010). Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy (1st ed.). Hong Kong: De Gruyter, Inc. pp. 25. ISBN 978-3-11-022624-9.
  212. ^ Wing‐Cheuk, Chan (21 February 2006). "Mou Zongsan's Transformation of Kant's Philosophy". Journal of Chinese Philosophy. 33 (1): 1. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.2006.00340.x.
  213. ^ Balanovskiy, Valentin (2016). "Whether jung was a kantian?". Con-Textos Kantianos (4): 118–126. doi:10.5281/zenodo.2550828. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 29 May 2020.
  214. ^ Balanovskiy, Valentin (2017). "Kant and Jung on the prospects of Scientific Psychology". Estudos Kantianos. 5 (1): 357–390. doi:10.36311/2318-0501.2017.v5n1.26.p375. from the original on 20 December 2020. Retrieved 29 May 2020.
  215. ^ Issacson, Walter. "Einstein: His Life and Universe." p. 20.
  216. ^ "Einstein on Kant". www.pitt.edu. Retrieved 13 March 2021.
  217. ^ Palmquist, S. (2010), "The Kantian grounding of Einstein's worldview: (I) The early influence of Kant's system of perspectives", Polish Journal of Philosophy, 4 (1), 45–64.
  218. ^ Theodora Achourioti & Michiel van Lambalgen, 'A Formalization of Kant's Transcendental Logic', The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4 (2011), 254–289.
  219. ^ Moral psychology. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. 2008–2014. ISBN 978-0-262-33728-1. OCLC 605120795.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  220. ^ Lott, Micah (October 2016). "Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science? No Clear Route". Ethics. 127 (1): 241–256. doi:10.1086/687337. S2CID 151940241.
  221. ^ Königs, Peter (3 April 2018). "Two types of debunking arguments". Philosophical Psychology. 31 (3): 383–402. doi:10.1080/09515089.2018.1426100. S2CID 148678250.
  222. ^ Meyers, C. D. (19 May 2015). "Brains, trolleys, and intuitions: Defending deontology from the Greene/Singer argument". Philosophical Psychology. 28 (4): 466–486. doi:10.1080/09515089.2013.849381. S2CID 146547149.
  223. ^ Kahane, Guy (2012). "On the Wrong Track: Process and Content in Moral Psychology". Mind & Language. 27 (5): 519–545. doi:10.1111/mila.12001. PMC 3546390. PMID 23335831.
  224. ^ Wansbrough, Aleks. "Kantian comedy: the philosophy of The Good Place". The Conversation. Retrieved 20 February 2022.
  225. ^ The thesis was submitted on 17 April 1755. "The public examination was held four weeks later on 13 May, and the degree was formally awarded on 12 June" (Eric Watkins, Kant: Natural Science, Cambridge University Press, 2012, p. 309).
  226. ^ Eric Watkins (ed.), Kant and the Sciences, Oxford University Press, 2001, p. 27.
  227. ^ Martin Schonfeld, The Philosophy of the Young Kant: The Precritical Project, Oxford University Press, 2000, p. 74.
  228. ^ Available online at Bonner Kant-Korpus 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  229. ^ The thesis was publicly disputed on 27 September 1755 (Kuehn 2001, p. 100).
  230. ^ Available online at Bonner Kant-Korpus 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  231. ^ Kant's application for the position was unsuccessful. He defended it on 10 April 1756 (Kuehn 2001, p. 102).
  232. ^ Available online at Archive.org.
  233. ^ Immanuel Kant, "Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space" 16 July 2018 at the Wayback Machine.
  234. ^ The thesis was publicly disputed on 21 August 1770 (Kuehn 2001, p. 189).
  235. ^ Available online at Google Books 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine.
  236. ^ English translation available online at Wikisource.
  237. ^ Immanuel Kant. . Etext.library.adelaide.edu.au. Archived from the original on 2 December 2008. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  238. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft – 1. Auflage – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. from the original on 9 June 2007. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  239. ^ Frank-Christian Lilienweihs (10 June 1999). "Immanuel Kant: Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklaerung?". Prometheusonline.de. from the original on 1 August 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  240. ^ "Critique of Pure Reason". Hkbu.edu.hk. 31 October 2003. from the original on 27 April 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  241. ^ "Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft – 2. Auflage – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. 20 July 2009. from the original on 26 December 2005. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  242. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Immanuel Kant: Kritik der praktischen Vernunft – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. from the original on 9 June 2007. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  243. ^ s:The Critique of Judgment
  244. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone by Immanuel Kant 1793". Marxists.org. from the original on 1 June 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  245. ^ "Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace"". Mtholyoke.edu. from the original on 6 April 2019. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  246. ^ "Immanuel Kant: Zum ewigen Frieden, 12.02.2004 (Friedensratschlag)". Uni-kassel.de. from the original on 23 September 2009. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  247. ^ "Kant, The Contest of Faculties". Chnm.gmu.edu. 1798. from the original on 4 August 2011. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  248. ^ Immanuel Kant. "Immanuel Kant: Der Streit der Facultäten – Kapitel 1" (in German). Projekt Gutenberg-DE. from the original on 9 June 2007. Retrieved 24 July 2009.
  249. ^ Available online at DeutschesTextArchiv.de 10 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  250. ^ As noted by Allen W. Wood in his Introduction, p. 12. Wood further speculates that the lectures themselves were delivered in the Winter of 1783–84.
  251. ^ Immanuel Kant, Notes and Fragments, Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. xvi.

Works cited

  • Kant, Immanuel. Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. Lewis White Beck, Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill, 1969. Page numbers citing this work are Beck's marginal numbers that refer to the page numbers of the standard edition of Königlich-Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin, 1902–38).
  • Kuehn, Manfred. Kant: a Biography. Cambridge University Press, 2001. ISBN 978-0-521-49704-6.

Further reading

In Germany, one important contemporary interpreter of Kant and the movement of German Idealism he began is Dieter Henrich, who has work available in English. P. F. Strawson's The Bounds of Sense (1966) played a significant role in determining the contemporary reception of Kant in England and America. More recent interpreters in the English-speaking world include Lewis White Beck, Jonathan Bennett, Henry Allison, Paul Guyer, Christine Korsgaard, Stephen Palmquist, Robert B. Pippin, Roger Scruton, Rudolf Makkreel, and Béatrice Longuenesse.

General introductions to his thought

Biography and historical context

  • Bader, Ralph (2008). "Kant, Immanuel (1724–1804)". In Hamowy, Ronald (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage; Cato Institute. pp. 269–271. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n161. ISBN 978-1-4129-6580-4. LCCN 2008009151. OCLC 750831024.
  • Beck, Lewis White. Early German Philosophy: Kant and his Predecessors. Harvard University Press, 1969. (a survey of Kant's intellectual background)
  • Beiser, Frederick C. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Harvard University Press, 1987.
  • Chamberlain, Houston Stewart. Immanuel Kant – a study and a comparison with Goethe, Leonardo da Vinci, Bruno, Plato and Descartes, the authorised translation from the German by Lord Redesdale, with his 'Introduction', The Bodley Head, London, 1914, (2 volumes).
  • Johnson, G.R. (ed.). Kant on Swedenborg. Dreams of a Spirit-Seer and Other Writings. Swedenborg Foundation, 2002. (new translation and analysis, many supplementary texts)
  • Lehner, Ulrich L., Kants Vorsehungskonzept auf dem Hintergrund der deutschen Schulphilosophie und theologie 23 September 2006 at the Wayback Machine (Leiden: 2007) (Kant's concept of Providence and its background in German school philosophy and theology)
  • Pinkard, Terry. German Philosophy, 1760–1860: the Legacy of Idealism. Cambridge, 2002.
  • Schabert, Joseph A. "Kant's Influence on his Successors", The American Catholic Quarterly Review, Vol. XLVII, January 1922.

Collections of essays

  • Firestone, Chris L. and Palmquist, Stephen (eds.). Kant and the New Philosophy of Religion. Notre Dame: Indiana University Press, 2006. ISBN 978-0-253-21800-1
  • Förster, Eckart (ed.). Kant's Transcendental Deductions:. The Three 'Critiques' and the 'Opus Postumum' Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1989. Includes an essay by Dieter Henrich.
  • Mohanty, J.N. and Shahan, Robert W. (eds.). Essays on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1982. ISBN 978-0-8061-1782-9
  • Phillips, Dewi et al. (eds.). Kant and Kierkegaard on Religion. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2000, ISBN 978-0-312-23234-4 Collection of essays about Kantian religion and its influence on Kierkegaardian and contemporary philosophy of religion.
  • Proceedings of the International Kant Congresses. Several Congresses (numbered) edited by various publishers.

Theoretical philosophy

  • Ameriks, Karl. Kant's Theory of Mind: An Analysis of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982 (one of the first detailed studies of the Dialectic in English).
  • Banham, Gary. Kant's Transcendental Imagination. London and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006.
  • Gram, Moltke S. The Transcendental Turn: The Foundation of Kant's Idealism. Gainesville: University Presses of Florida, 1984. ISBN 978-0-8130-0787-8
  • Greenberg, Robert. Kant's Theory of A Priori Knowledge. Penn State Press, 2001 ISBN 978-0-271-02083-9
  • Guyer, Paul. Kant and the Claims of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987 (modern defense of the view that Kant's theoretical philosophy is a "patchwork" of ill-fitting arguments).
  • Heidegger, Martin. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. Trans., Richard Taft. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997. ISBN 978-0-253-21067-8
  • Henrich, Dieter. The Unity of Reason: Essays on Kant's Philosophy. Ed. with introduction by Richard L. Velkley; trans. Jeffrey Edwards et al. Harvard University Press, 1994. ISBN 978-0-674-92905-0
  • Kemp Smith, Norman. A Commentary to Kant's 'Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan, 1930 (influential commentary on the first Critique, recently reprinted).
  • Kitcher, Patricia. Kant's Transcendental Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.
  • Longuenesse, Béatrice. Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Princeton University Press, 1998. ISBN 978-0-691-04348-7. (argues that the notion of judgment provides the key to understanding the overall argument of the first Critique)
  • Melnick, Arthur. Kant's Analogies of Experience. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973. (important study of Kant's Analogies, including his defense of the principle of causality)
  • Paton, H.J. Kant's Metaphysic of Experience: a Commentary on the First Half of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Two volumes. London: Macmillan, 1936. (extensive study of Kant's theoretical philosophy)
  • Pippin, Robert B. Kant's Theory of Form: An Essay on the Critique of Pure Reason. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982. (influential examination of the formal character of Kant's work)
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur. Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung. Erster Band. Anhang. Kritik der Kantischen Philosophie. F.A. Brockhaus, Leipzig 1859 (In English: Arthur Schopenhauer, New York: Dover Press, Volume I, Appendix, "Critique of the Kantian Philosophy", ISBN 978-0-486-21761-1)
  • Schott, Robin May (1997). Feminist interpretations of Immanuel Kant. University Park, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press. ISBN 978-0-271-01676-4.
  • Seung, T.K. Kant's Transcendental Logic. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1969.
  • Tonelli, Giorgio. Kant's Critique of Pure Reason within the Tradition of Modern Logic. A Commentary on its History. Hildesheim, Olms 1994
  • Werkmeister, W.H., Kant: The Architectonic and Development of His Philosophy, Open Court Publishing Co., La Salle, Ill.; 1980 ISBN 978-0-87548-345-0 (it treats, as a whole, the architectonic and development of Kant's philosophy from 1755 through the Opus postumum.)
  • Wolff, Robert Paul. Kant's Theory of Mental Activity: A Commentary on the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1963. (detailed and influential commentary on the first part of the Critique of Pure Reason)
  • Yovel, Yirmiyahu. Kant and the Philosophy of History. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980. (review 4 January 2017 at the Wayback Machine)

Practical philosophy

  • Allison, Henry. Kant's Theory of Freedom. Cambridge University Press 1990.
  • Banham, Gary. Kant's Practical Philosophy: From Critique to Doctrine. Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.
  • Dorschel, Andreas. Die idealistische Kritik des Willens: Versuch über die Theorie der praktischen Subjektivität bei Kant und Hegel. Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1992 (Schriften zur Transzendentalphilosophie 10) ISBN 978-3-7873-1046-3.
  • Friedman, Michael (June 1998). "Kantian themes in contemporary philosophy". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. 72 (1): 111–130. doi:10.1111/1467-8349.00038. JSTOR 4107015.
  • Korsgaard, Christine M. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge University Press, 1996.
  • Michalson, Gordon E. Fallen Freedom: Kant on Radical Evil and Moral Regeneration. Cambridge University Press, 1990.
  • Michalson, Gordon E. Kant and the Problem of God. Blackwell Publishers, 1999.
  • Paton, H.J. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant's Moral Philosophy. University of Pennsylvania Press 1971.
  • Seung, T.K. Kant's Platonic Revolution in Moral and Political Philosophy. Johns Hopkins, 1994.
  • Wolff, Robert Paul. The Autonomy of Reason: A Commentary on Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. New York: HarperCollins, 1974. ISBN 978-0-06-131792-7.

Aesthetics

  • Allison, Henry. Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
  • Banham, Gary. Kant and the Ends of Aesthetics. London and New York: Macmillan Press, 2000.
  • Crawford, Donald. Kant's Aesthetic Theory. Wisconsin, 1974.
  • Doran, Robert. The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
  • Guyer, Paul. Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, 1979.
  • Hammermeister, Kai. The German Aesthetic Tradition. Cambridge University Press, 2002.
  • Immanuel Kant entry in Kelly, Michael (Editor in Chief) (1998) Encyclopedia of Aesthetics. New York, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
  • Kaplama, Erman. Cosmological Aesthetics through the Kantian Sublime and Nietzschean Dionysian. Lanham: UPA, Rowman & Littlefield, 2014.
  • McCloskey, Mary. Kant's Aesthetic. SUNY, 1987.
  • Schaper, Eva. Studies in Kant's Aesthetics. Edinburgh, 1979.
  • Zammito, John H. The Genesis of Kant's Critique of Judgment. Chicago and London: Chicago University Press, 1992.
  • Zupancic, Alenka. Ethics of the Real: Kant and Lacan. Verso, 2000.

Philosophy of religion

  • Palmquist, Stephen. Kant's Critical Religion 14 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine: Volume Two of Kant's System of Perspectives. Ashgate, 2000. ISBN 978-0-7546-1333-6
  • Perez, Daniel Omar. "Religión, Política y Medicina en Kant: El Conflicto de las Proposiciones". Cinta de Moebio. Revista de Epistemologia de Ciencias Sociales, v. 28, p. 91–103, 2007. Uchile.cl 20 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine (Spanish)

Perpetual peace and international relations

  • Sir Harry Hinsley, Power and the Pursuit of Peace, Cambridge University Press, 1962.
  • Martin Wight, Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant and Mazzini 29 November 2014 at the Wayback Machine ed. Gabriele Wight & Brian Porter (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).
  • Bennington, Geoffrey (December 2011). "Kant's open secret" (PDF). Theory, Culture & Society. 28 (7–8): 26–40. doi:10.1177/0263276411423036. S2CID 143513241. (PDF) from the original on 8 February 2020. Retrieved 31 May 2020.

Other works

  • Botul, Jean-Baptiste. La vie sexuelle d'Emmanuel Kant. Paris, Éd. Mille et une Nuits, 2008. ISBN 978-2-84205-424-3
  • Caygill, Howard. A Kant Dictionary. Oxford; Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell Reference, 1995. ISBN 978-0-631-17534-6
  • Derrida, Jacques. Mochlos; or, The Conflict of the Faculties. Columbia University, 1980
  • Mosser, Kurt. Necessity and Possibility; The Logical Strategy of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Catholic University of America Press, 2008. ISBN 978-0-8132-1532-7
  • White, Mark D. Kantian Ethics and Economics: Autonomy, Dignity, and Character 16 November 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Stanford University Press, 2011. ISBN 978-0-8047-6894-8.

Contemporary philosophy with a Kantian influence

External links

immanuel, kant, kant, redirects, here, other, uses, kant, disambiguation, ɑː, german, ɪˈmaːnu, eːl, ˈkant, april, 1724, february, 1804, german, philosopher, central, enlightenment, thinkers, born, königsberg, kant, comprehensive, systematic, works, epistemolog. Kant redirects here For other uses see Kant disambiguation Immanuel Kant UK k ae n t 20 21 US k ɑː n t 22 23 German ɪˈmaːnu eːl ˈkant 24 25 22 April 1724 12 February 1804 was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers 26 27 Born in Konigsberg Kant s comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology metaphysics ethics and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western philosophy 26 28 Immanuel KantPortrait by Johann Gottlieb Becker 1768Born 1724 04 22 22 April 1724Konigsberg Kingdom of Prussia present day Kaliningrad Russia Died12 February 1804 1804 02 12 aged 79 Konigsberg East Prussia Kingdom of PrussiaEducationCollegium FridericianumUniversity of Konigsberg BA MA April 1755 PhD September 1755 PhD 1 August 1770 EraAge of EnlightenmentRegionWestern philosophySchoolEnlightenment philosophy Kantianism Other schools Classical liberalismCorrespondence theory of truth a 3 Empirical realismFoundationalism 4 German idealism 5 Indirect realism 6 Liberal naturalism 7 Metaphysical conceptualism 8 Perceptual non conceptualism 9 10 Transcendental idealismInstitutionsUniversity of KonigsbergThesesPrincipiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio September 1755 De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis August 1770 Academic advisorsMartin Knutzen Johann Gottfried Teske M A advisor Konrad Gottlieb Marquardt 11 Notable studentsJakob Sigismund Beck Johann Gottlieb Fichte Johann Gottfried Herder Karl Leonhard Reinhold epistolary correspondent 19 Main interestsAesthetics cosmogony epistemology ethics metaphysics systematic philosophyNotable ideas Abstract concrete distinction 12 Aesthetic teleological judgmentsAnalytic synthetic distinctionCategorical and hypothetical imperativeCategoriesCosmotheologyCritical philosophyCopernican revolution in philosophyDisinterested delightEmpirical realismKant s antinomiesKant s pitchforkKantian ethicsKingdom of EndsMathematical vs dynamical sublimity 13 Nebular hypothesisNoogony and noologyNoumenon vs thing in itselfOntotheologyPrimacy of practical reason 14 Public reasonRadical evilRechtsstaatSapere audeTranscendental schemaTheoretical vs practical philosophyTranscendental idealismTranscendental subjectTranscendental theologyUnderstanding reason distinctionInfluences WolffEmilie du ChateletBaumgartenGreen 15 16 PlatoAristotleHamannEmpiricusLucretiusHumeSmithDescartesLeibnizLockeRousseauNewtonTetens 17 Crusius 18 Swedenborg disputed Influenced Virtually all subsequent Western philosophySignatureIn his doctrine of transcendental idealism Kant argued that space and time are mere forms of intuition which structure all experience and therefore while things in themselves exist and contribute to experience they are nonetheless distinct from the objects of experience From this it follows that the objects of experience are mere appearances and that the nature of things as they are in themselves is unknowable to us 29 30 In an attempt to counter the skepticism he found in the writings of philosopher David Hume 31 he wrote the Critique of Pure Reason 1781 1787 32 his most well known work In it he developed his theory of experience to answer the question of whether synthetic a priori knowledge is possible which would in turn make it possible to determine the limits of metaphysical inquiry Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal to think of the objects of the senses as conforming to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition so that we have a priori cognition of those objects b Kant believed that reason is also the source of morality and that aesthetics arise from a faculty of disinterested judgment Kant s views continue to have a major influence on contemporary philosophy especially the fields of epistemology ethics political theory and post modern aesthetics 28 He attempted to explain the relationship between reason and human experience and to move beyond what he believed to be the failures of traditional philosophy and metaphysics He wanted to put an end to what he saw as an era of futile and speculative theories of human experience while resisting the skepticism of thinkers such as Hume He regarded himself as showing the way past the impasse between rationalists and empiricists 34 and is widely held to have synthesized both traditions in his thought 35 Kant was an exponent of the idea that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation and that perhaps this could be the culminating stage of world history 36 The nature of Kant s religious views continues to be the subject of scholarly dispute with viewpoints ranging from the impression that he shifted from an early defense of an ontological argument for the existence of God to a principled agnosticism to more critical treatments epitomized by Schopenhauer who criticized the imperative form of Kantian ethics as theological morals and the Mosaic Decalogue in disguise 37 and Friedrich Nietzsche who claimed that Kant had theologian blood 38 and was merely a sophisticated apologist for traditional Christian faith c Beyond his religious views Kant has also been criticized for the racism presented in some of his lesser known papers such as On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy and On the Different Races of Man 40 41 42 43 Although he was a proponent of scientific racism for much of his career Kant s views on race changed significantly in the last decade of his life and he ultimately rejected racial hierarchies and European colonialism in Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 1795 44 Kant published other important works on ethics religion law aesthetics astronomy and history during his lifetime These include the Universal Natural History 1755 the Critique of Practical Reason 1788 the Critique of Judgment 1790 Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 1793 and the Metaphysics of Morals 1797 27 Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Young scholar 1 2 Early work 1 3 Publication of The Critique of Pure Reason 1 4 Later work 1 5 Death and burial 2 Philosophy 2 1 Epistemology 2 1 1 Theory of perception 2 2 Time and space 2 2 1 Categories of the Faculty of Understanding 2 2 2 Transcendental schema doctrine 2 3 Ethics 2 3 1 First formulation 2 3 2 Second formulation 2 3 3 Third formulation 2 3 4 Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 2 3 5 Idea of freedom 2 3 6 Categories of freedom 2 3 7 Aesthetic philosophy 2 4 Political philosophy 2 5 Anthropology 2 5 1 Racism 2 5 2 Women 3 Influence and legacy 3 1 Historical influence 3 2 Influence on modern thinkers 3 3 Film television 4 Bibliography 4 1 List of major works 4 2 Collected works in German 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 7 1 Works cited 8 Further reading 9 External linksBiography EditKant was born on 22 April 1724 into a Prussian German family of Lutheran Protestant faith in Konigsberg East Prussia since 1946 the Russian city of Kaliningrad His mother Anna Regina Reuter 45 1697 1737 was born in Konigsberg to a father from Nuremberg citation needed Her surname is sometimes erroneously given as Porter Kant s father Johann Georg Kant 1682 1746 was a German harness maker from Memel at the time Prussia s most northeastern city now Klaipeda Lithuania Kant believed that his paternal grandfather Hans Kant was of Scottish origin 46 While scholars of Kant s life long accepted the claim modern scholarship challenges it It is possible that Kants got their name from the village of Kantvainiai German Kantwaggen today part of Priekule and were of Kursenieki origin 47 48 Kant was the fourth of nine children six of whom reached adulthood 49 Baptized Emanuel he later changed the spelling of his name to Immanuel 50 after learning Hebrew He was brought up in a pietist household that stressed religious devotion humility and a literal interpretation of the Bible 51 citation needed His education was strict punitive and disciplinary and focused on Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science 52 In his Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals he reveals a belief in immortality as the necessary condition of humanity s approach to the highest morality possible 53 54 However as Kant was skeptical about some of the arguments used prior to him in defence of theism and maintained that human understanding is limited and can never attain knowledge about God or the soul various commentators have labelled him a philosophical agnostic 55 56 57 58 59 60 even though it has also been suggested that Kant intends other people to think of him as a pure rationalist who is defined by Kant as someone who recognizes revelation but asserts that to know and accept it as real is not a necessary requisite to religion 61 Kant apparently lived a strict and disciplined life it was said that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks He never married 62 but seems to have had a rewarding social life he was a popular teacher as well as a modestly successful author even before starting on his major philosophical works He had a circle of friends with whom he frequently met among them Joseph Green an English merchant in Konigsberg whom reportedly he first spoke to in an argument in 1763 or before According to the story Kant was strolling in the Danhofscher Garten when he saw one of his acquaintances speaking to a group of men he did not know He joined the conversation which soon turned to unusual current events in the world The topic of the disagreement between the British and the Americans came up Kant took the side of the Americans and this upset Green He challenged Kant to a fight Kant reportedly explained that patriotism did not get in the way of his view and that any cosmopolitan citizen could take his position if he held Kant s political principles which Kant explained to Green Green was so stunned by Kant s ability to express his views that Green offered to become friends with Kant and invited him to his apartment that evening 63 Many myths grew about Kant s personal mannerisms these are listed explained and refuted in Goldthwait s introduction to his translation of Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime 64 Between 1750 and 1754 Kant worked as a tutor Hauslehrer in the Lithuanian village of Juciai German Judtschen 65 approximately 20 km east of Konigsberg and in Gross Arnsdorf 66 now Jarnoltowo near Morag German Mohrungen Poland approximately 145 km east of Konigsberg Young scholar Edit Kant showed a great aptitude for study at an early age He first attended the Collegium Fridericianum from which he graduated at the end of the summer of 1740 In 1740 aged 16 he enrolled at the University of Konigsberg where he spent his whole career 67 He studied the philosophy of Gottfried Leibniz and Christian Wolff under Martin Knutzen Associate Professor of Logic and Metaphysics from 1734 until his death in 1751 a rationalist who was also familiar with developments in British philosophy and science and introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of Isaac Newton Knutzen dissuaded Kant from the theory of pre established harmony which he regarded as the pillow for the lazy mind 68 He also dissuaded Kant from idealism the idea that reality is purely mental which most philosophers in the 18th century regarded in a negative light The theory of transcendental idealism that Kant later included in the Critique of Pure Reason was developed partially in opposition to traditional idealism His father s stroke and subsequent death in 1746 interrupted his studies Kant left Konigsberg shortly after August 1748 69 he would return there in August 1754 70 He became a private tutor in the towns surrounding Konigsberg but continued his scholarly research In 1749 he published his first philosophical work Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces written in 1745 47 71 Early work Edit Kant is best known for his work in the philosophy of ethics and metaphysics 26 but he made significant contributions to other disciplines In 1754 while contemplating on a prize question by the Berlin Academy about the problem of Earth s rotation he argued that the Moon s gravity would slow down Earth s spin and he also put forth the argument that gravity would eventually cause the Moon s tidal locking to coincide with the Earth s rotation d 73 The next year he expanded this reasoning to the formation and evolution of the Solar System in his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens 73 In 1755 Kant received a license to lecture in the University of Konigsberg and began lecturing on a variety of topics including mathematics physics logic and metaphysics In his 1756 essay on the theory of winds Kant laid out an original insight into the Coriolis force In 1756 Kant also published three papers on the 1755 Lisbon earthquake 74 Kant s theory which involved shifts in huge caverns filled with hot gases though inaccurate was one of the first systematic attempts to explain earthquakes in natural rather than supernatural terms According to Walter Benjamin Kant s slim early book on the earthquake probably represents the beginnings of scientific geography in Germany And certainly the beginnings of seismology In 1757 Kant began lecturing on geography making him one of the first lecturers to explicitly teach geography as its own subject 75 76 Geography was one of Kant s most popular lecturing topics and in 1802 a compilation by Friedrich Theodor Rink of Kant s lecturing notes Physical Geography was released After Kant became a professor in 1770 he expanded the topics of his lectures to include lectures on natural law ethics and anthropology along with other topics 75 Kant s house in Konigsberg In the Universal Natural History Kant laid out the Nebular hypothesis in which he deduced that the Solar System had formed from a large cloud of gas a nebula Kant also correctly deduced that the Milky Way was a large disk of stars which he theorized formed from a much larger spinning gas cloud He further suggested that other distant nebulae might be other galaxies These postulations opened new horizons for astronomy for the first time extending it beyond the Solar System to galactic and intergalactic realms 77 According to Thomas Huxley 1867 Kant also made contributions to geology in his Universal Natural History 78 79 From then on Kant turned increasingly to philosophical issues although he continued to write on the sciences throughout his life In the early 1760s Kant produced a series of important works in philosophy The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures a work in logic was published in 1762 Two more works appeared the following year Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy and The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God By 1764 Kant had become a notable popular author and wrote Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime 80 he was second to Moses Mendelssohn in a Berlin Academy prize competition with his Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality often referred to as The Prize Essay In 1766 Kant wrote Dreams of a Spirit Seer which dealt with the writings of Emanuel Swedenborg The exact influence of Swedenborg on Kant as well as the extent of Kant s belief in mysticism according to Dreams of a Spirit Seer remain controversial On the face of it Dreams of a Spirit Seer argued against the ideas of Swedenborg Kant poked holes in the logic of Swedenborg s view of the nature of spirits 81 but also communicated his curiosity about Swedenborg s mysticism 82 On 31 March 1770 aged 45 Kant was finally appointed Full Professor of Logic and Metaphysics Professor Ordinarius der Logic und Metaphysic at the University of Konigsberg In defense of this appointment Kant wrote his inaugural dissertation Inaugural Dissertation De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World 1 This work saw the emergence of several central themes of his mature work including the distinction between the faculties of intellectual thought and sensible receptivity To miss this distinction would mean to commit the error of subreption and as he says in the last chapter of the dissertation only in avoiding this error does metaphysics flourish The issue that vexed Kant was central to what 20th century scholars called the philosophy of mind The flowering of the natural sciences had led to an understanding of how data reaches the brain Sunlight falling on an object is reflected from its surface in a way that maps the surface features color texture etc The reflected light reaches the human eye passes through the cornea is focused by the lens onto the retina where it forms an image similar to that formed by light passing through a pinhole into a camera obscura The retinal cells send impulses through the optic nerve and then they form a mapping in the brain of the visual features of the object The interior mapping is not the exterior object and our belief that there is a meaningful relationship between the object and the mapping in the brain depends on a chain of reasoning that is not fully grounded But the uncertainty aroused by these considerations by optical illusions misperceptions delusions etc is not the end of the problem Kant saw that the mind could not function as an empty container that simply receives data from outside Something must be giving order to the incoming data Images of external objects must be kept in the same sequence in which they were received This ordering occurs through the mind s intuition of time The same considerations apply to the mind s function of constituting space for ordering mappings of visual and tactile signals arriving via the already described chains of physical causation It is often claimed that Kant was a late developer that he only became an important philosopher in his mid 50s after rejecting his earlier views While it is true that Kant wrote his greatest works relatively late in life there is a tendency to underestimate the value of his earlier works Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these pre critical writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work 83 Publication of The Critique of Pure Reason Edit Main article Critique of Pure Reason At age 46 Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher and much was expected of him In correspondence with his ex student and friend Markus Herz Kant admitted that in the inaugural dissertation he had failed to account for the relation between our sensible and intellectual faculties 84 He needed to explain how we combine what is known as sensory knowledge with the other type of knowledge i e reasoned knowledge these two being related but having very different processes Portrait of philosopher David Hume Kant also credited David Hume with awakening him from a dogmatic slumber in which he had unquestioningly accepted the tenets of both religion and natural philosophy 85 86 Hume in his 1739 Treatise on Human Nature had argued that we only know the mind through a subjective essentially illusory series of perceptions 85 Ideas such as causality morality and objects are not evident in experience so their reality may be questioned Kant felt that reason could remove this skepticism and he set himself to solving these problems Although fond of company and conversation with others Kant isolated himself and resisted friends attempts to bring him out of his isolation e When Kant emerged from his silence in 1781 the result was the Critique of Pure Reason Kant countered Hume s empiricism by claiming that some knowledge exists inherently in the mind independent of experience 85 He drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal that worldly objects can be intuited a priori beforehand and that intuition is consequently distinct from objective reality b He acquiesced to Hume somewhat by defining causality as a regular constant sequence of events in time and nothing more 88 Although now uniformly recognized as one of the greatest works in the history of philosophy this Critique disappointed Kant s readers upon its initial publication 89 The book was long over 800 pages in the original German edition and written in a convoluted style It received few reviews and these granted it no significance citation needed Kant s former student Johann Gottfried Herder criticized it for placing reason as an entity worthy of criticism instead of considering the process of reasoning within the context of language and one s entire personality 90 Similar to Christian Garve and Johann Georg Heinrich Feder he rejected Kant s position that space and time possessed a form that could be analyzed Additionally Garve and Feder also faulted Kant s Critique for not explaining differences in perception of sensations 91 Its density made it as Herder said in a letter to Johann Georg Hamann a tough nut to crack obscured by all this heavy gossamer 92 Its reception stood in stark contrast to the praise Kant had received for earlier works such as his Prize Essay and shorter works that preceded the first Critique These well received and readable tracts include one on the earthquake in Lisbon that was so popular that it was sold by the page 93 Prior to the change in course documented in the first Critique his books had sold well 80 Kant was disappointed with the first Critique s reception Recognizing the need to clarify the original treatise Kant wrote the Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics in 1783 as a summary of its main views Shortly thereafter Kant s friend Johann Friedrich Schultz 1739 1805 professor of mathematics published Erlauterungen uber des Herrn Professor Kant Critik der reinen Vernunft Konigsberg 1784 which was a brief but very accurate commentary on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Engraving of Immanuel Kant Kant s reputation gradually rose through the latter portion of the 1780s sparked by a series of important works the 1784 essay Answer to the Question What is Enlightenment 1785 s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals his first work on moral philosophy and from 1786 Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science But Kant s fame ultimately arrived from an unexpected source In 1786 Karl Leonhard Reinhold published a series of public letters on Kantian philosophy 94 In these letters Reinhold framed Kant s philosophy as a response to the central intellectual controversy of the era the pantheism controversy Friedrich Jacobi had accused the recently deceased Gotthold Ephraim Lessing a distinguished dramatist and philosophical essayist of Spinozism Such a charge tantamount to atheism was vigorously denied by Lessing s friend Moses Mendelssohn leading to a bitter public dispute among partisans The controversy gradually escalated into a debate about the values of the Enlightenment and the value of reason Reinhold maintained in his letters that Kant s Critique of Pure Reason could settle this dispute by defending the authority and bounds of reason Reinhold s letters were widely read and made Kant the most famous philosopher of his era Later work Edit Kant published a second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787 heavily revising the first parts of the book Most of his subsequent work focused on other areas of philosophy He continued to develop his moral philosophy notably in 1788 s Critique of Practical Reason known as the second Critique and 1797 s Metaphysics of Morals The 1790 Critique of Judgment the third Critique applied the Kantian system to aesthetics and teleology In 1792 Kant s attempt to publish the Second of the four Pieces of Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 95 in the journal Berlinische Monatsschrift met with opposition from the King s censorship commission which had been established that same year in the context of the French Revolution 96 Kant then arranged to have all four pieces published as a book routing it through the philosophy department at the University of Jena to avoid the need for theological censorship 96 This insubordination earned him a now famous reprimand from the King 96 When he nevertheless published a second edition in 1794 the censor was so irate that he arranged for a royal order that required Kant never to publish or even speak publicly about religion 96 Kant then published his response to the King s reprimand and explained himself in the preface of The Conflict of the Faculties 96 Kant with friends including Christian Jakob Kraus Johann Georg Hamann Theodor Gottlieb von Hippel and Karl Gottfried Hagen He also wrote a number of semi popular essays on history religion politics and other topics These works were well received by Kant s contemporaries and confirmed his preeminent status in 18th century philosophy There were several journals devoted solely to defending and criticizing Kantian philosophy Despite his success philosophical trends were moving in another direction Many of Kant s most important disciples and followers including Reinhold Beck and Fichte transformed the Kantian position into increasingly radical forms of idealism The progressive stages of revision of Kant s teachings marked the emergence of German idealism Kant opposed these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in 1799 97 It was one of his final acts expounding a stance on philosophical questions In 1800 a student of Kant named Gottlob Benjamin Jasche 1762 1842 published a manual of logic for teachers called Logik which he had prepared at Kant s request Jasche prepared the Logik using a copy of a textbook in logic by Georg Friedrich Meier entitled Auszug aus der Vernunftlehre in which Kant had written copious notes and annotations The Logik has been considered of fundamental importance to Kant s philosophy and the understanding of it The great 19th century logician Charles Sanders Peirce remarked in an incomplete review of Thomas Kingsmill Abbott s English translation of the introduction to Logik that Kant s whole philosophy turns upon his logic 98 Also Robert Schirokauer Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz wrote in the translators introduction to their English translation of the Logik Its importance lies not only in its significance for the Critique of Pure Reason the second part of which is a restatement of fundamental tenets of the Logic but in its position within the whole of Kant s work 99 Death and burial Edit Kant s health long poor worsened and he died at Konigsberg on 12 February 1804 uttering Es ist gut It is good before expiring 100 His unfinished final work was published as Opus Postumum Kant always cut a curious figure in his lifetime for his modest rigorously scheduled habits which have been referred to as clocklike However Heinrich Heine noted the magnitude of his destructive world crushing thoughts and considered him a sort of philosophical executioner comparing him to Robespierre with the observation that both men represented in the highest the type of provincial bourgeois Nature had destined them to weigh coffee and sugar but Fate determined that they should weigh other things and placed on the scales of the one a king on the scales of the other a god 101 When his body was transferred to a new burial spot his skull was measured during the exhumation and found to be larger than the average German male s with a high and broad forehead 102 His forehead has been an object of interest ever since it became well known through his portraits In Dobler s portrait and in Kiefer s faithful if expressionistic reproduction of it as well as in many of the other late eighteenth and early nineteenth century portraits of Kant the forehead is remarkably large and decidedly retreating Was Kant s forehead shaped this way in these images because he was a philosopher or to follow the implications of Lavater s system was he a philosopher because of the intellectual acuity manifested by his forehead Kant and Johann Kaspar Lavater were correspondents on theological matters and Lavater refers to Kant in his work Physiognomic Fragments for the Education of Human Knowledge and Love of People Leipzig amp Winterthur 1775 1778 103 Kant s tomb in Kaliningrad Russia Kant s mausoleum adjoins the northeast corner of Konigsberg Cathedral in Kaliningrad Russia The mausoleum was constructed by the architect Friedrich Lahrs and was finished in 1924 in time for the bicentenary of Kant s birth Originally Kant was buried inside the cathedral but in 1880 his remains were moved to a neo Gothic chapel adjoining the northeast corner of the cathedral Over the years the chapel became dilapidated and was demolished to make way for the mausoleum which was built on the same location The tomb and its mausoleum are among the few artifacts of German times preserved by the Soviets after they captured the city 104 Today many newlyweds bring flowers to the mausoleum Artifacts previously owned by Kant known as Kantiana were included in the Konigsberg City Museum However the museum was destroyed during World War II A replica of the statue of Kant that in German times stood in front of the main University of Konigsberg building was donated by a German entity in the early 1990s and placed in the same grounds After the expulsion of Konigsberg s German population at the end of World War II the University of Konigsberg where Kant taught was replaced by the Russian language Kaliningrad State University which appropriated the campus and surviving buildings In 2005 the university was renamed Immanuel Kant State University of Russia The name change was announced at a ceremony attended by President Vladimir Putin of Russia and Chancellor Gerhard Schroder of Germany and the university formed a Kant Society dedicated to the study of Kantianism The university was again renamed in the 2010s to Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University 105 In 2018 his tomb and statue were vandalized with paint by unknown assailants who also scattered leaflets glorifying Rus and denouncing Kant as a traitor The incident was apparently connected with a recent vote to rename Khrabrovo Airport where Kant was in the lead for a while prompting Russian nationalist resentment 106 Philosophy EditMain article Kantianism This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed April 2017 Learn how and when to remove this template message In Kant s essay Answering the Question What is Enlightenment he defined the Enlightenment as an age shaped by the Latin motto Sapere aude Dare to be wise Kant maintained that one ought to think autonomously free of the dictates of external authority His work reconciled many of the differences between the rationalist and empiricist traditions of the 18th century He had a decisive impact on the Romantic and German Idealist philosophies of the 19th century His work has also been a starting point for many 20th century philosophers Kant asserted that because of the limitations of argumentation in the absence of irrefutable evidence no one could really know whether there is a God and an afterlife or not For the sake of morality and as a ground for reason Kant asserted people are justified in believing in God even though they could never know God s presence empirically Thus the entire armament of reason in the undertaking that one can call pure philosophy is in fact directed only at the three problems that have been mentioned God the soul and freedom These themselves however have in turn their more remote aim namely what is to be done if the will is free if there is a God and if there is a future world Now since these concern our conduct in relation to the highest end the ultimate aim of nature which provides for us wisely in the disposition of reason is properly directed only to what is moral 33 674 5 A 800 1 B 828 9 Immanuel Kant by Carle Vernet 1758 1836 The sense of an enlightened approach and the critical method required that If one cannot prove that a thing is he may try to prove that it is not If he fails to do either as often occurs he may still ask whether it is in his interest to accept one or the other of the alternatives hypothetically from the theoretical or the practical point of view Hence the question no longer is as to whether perpetual peace is a real thing or not a real thing or as to whether we may not be deceiving ourselves when we adopt the former alternative but we must act on the supposition of its being real 107 The presupposition of God soul and freedom was then a practical concern for Morality in itself constitutes a system but happiness does not except insofar as it is distributed precisely in accordance with morality This however is possible only in the intelligible world under a wise author and regent Reason sees itself as compelled either to assume such a thing together with life in such a world which we must regard as a future one or else to regard the moral laws as empty figments of the brain 33 680 A 811 B 839 Kant drew a parallel between the Copernican revolution and the epistemology of his new transcendental philosophy involving two interconnected foundations of his critical philosophy the epistemology of transcendental idealism and the moral philosophy of the autonomy of practical reason These teachings placed the active rational human subject at the center of the cognitive and moral worlds Kant argued that the rational order of the world as known by science was not just the accidental accumulation of sense perceptions Conceptual unification and integration is carried out by the mind through concepts or the categories of the understanding operating on the perceptual manifold within space and time The latter are not concepts 108 but are forms of sensibility that are a priori necessary conditions for any possible experience Thus the objective order of nature and the causal necessity that operates within it depend on the mind s processes the product of the rule based activity that Kant called synthesis There is much discussion among Kant scholars about the correct interpretation of this train of thought The two world interpretation regards Kant s position as a statement of epistemological limitation that we are not able to transcend the bounds of our own mind meaning that we cannot access the thing in itself However Kant also speaks of the thing in itself or transcendental object as a product of the human understanding as it attempts to conceive of objects in abstraction from the conditions of sensibility Following this line of thought some interpreters have argued that the thing in itself does not represent a separate ontological domain but simply a way of considering objects by means of the understanding alone this is known as the two aspect view The notion of the thing in itself was much discussed by philosophers after Kant It was argued that because the thing in itself was unknowable its existence must not be assumed Rather than arbitrarily switching to an account that was ungrounded in anything supposed to be the real as did the German Idealists another group arose who asked how our presumably reliable accounts of a coherent and rule abiding universe were actually grounded This new kind of philosophy became known as Phenomenology and its founder was Edmund Husserl With regard to morality Kant argued that the source of the good lies not in anything outside the human subject either in nature or given by God but rather is only the good will itself A good will is one that acts from duty in accordance with the universal moral law that the autonomous human being freely gives itself This law obliges one to treat humanity understood as rational agency and represented through oneself as well as others as an end in itself rather than merely as means to other ends the individual might hold This necessitates practical self reflection in which we universalize our reasons These ideas have largely framed or influenced all subsequent philosophical discussion and analysis The specifics of Kant s account generated immediate and lasting controversy Nevertheless his theses that the mind itself necessarily makes a constitutive contribution to its knowledge that this contribution is transcendental rather than psychological that philosophy involves self critical activity that morality is rooted in human freedom and that to act autonomously is to act according to rational moral principles have all had a lasting effect on subsequent philosophy Epistemology Edit Main article Transcendental idealism Bust of Immanuel Kant Theory of perception Edit Main article Critique of Pure Reason Kant defines his theory of perception in his very influential 1781 work the Critique of Pure Reason which has often been cited as the most significant volume of metaphysics and epistemology in modern philosophy 109 Kant maintains that understanding of the external world had its foundations not merely in experience but in both experience and a priori concepts thus offering a non empiricist critique of rationalist philosophy which is what has been referred to as his Copernican revolution 110 Firstly Kant distinguishes between analytic and synthetic propositions Analytic proposition a proposition whose predicate concept is contained in its subject concept e g All bachelors are unmarried or All bodies take up space Synthetic proposition a proposition whose predicate concept is not contained in its subject concept e g All bachelors are alone or All bodies have weight An analytic proposition is true by nature of the meaning of the words in the sentence we require no further knowledge than a grasp of the language to understand this proposition On the other hand a synthetic statement is one that tells us something about the world The truth or falsehood of synthetic statements derives from something outside their linguistic content In this instance weight is not a necessary predicate of the body until we are told the heaviness of the body we do not know that it has weight In this case experience of the body is required before its heaviness becomes clear Before Kant s first Critique empiricists cf Hume and rationalists cf Leibniz assumed that all synthetic statements required experience to be known Kant contests this assumption by claiming that elementary mathematics like arithmetic is synthetic a priori in that its statements provide new knowledge not derived from experience This becomes part of his over all argument for transcendental idealism That is he argues that the possibility of experience depends on certain necessary conditions which he calls a priori forms and that these conditions structure and hold true of the world of experience His main claims in the Transcendental Aesthetic are that mathematic judgments are synthetic a priori and that space and time are not derived from experience but rather are its preconditions Once we have grasped the functions of basic arithmetic we do not need empirical experience to know that 100 100 200 and so it appears that arithmetic is analytic However that it is analytic can be disproved by considering the calculation 5 7 12 there is nothing in the numbers 5 and 7 by which the number 12 can be inferred 111 Thus 5 7 and the cube root of 1 728 or 12 are not analytic because their reference is the same but their sense is not the statement 5 7 12 tells us something new about the world It is self evident and undeniably a priori but at the same time it is synthetic Thus Kant argued that a proposition can be synthetic and a priori This statement is synthetic because it supposes both quantity in general which is a conceit from our understanding and succession which is a mode of time that belongs to our sensibility To produce 12 from 5 one needs to add unity to unity seven time Thus to add is not an operation of pure reason but a process that needs time one and then one and again one etc 112 Kant asserts that experience is based on the perception of external objects and a priori knowledge 113 The external world he writes provides those things that we sense But our mind processes this information and gives it order allowing us to comprehend it Our mind supplies the conditions of space and time to experience objects According to the transcendental unity of apperception the concepts of the mind Understanding and perceptions or intuitions that garner information from phenomena Sensibility are synthesized by comprehension Without concepts perceptions are nondescript without perceptions concepts are meaningless Thus the famous statement Thoughts without content are empty intuitions perceptions without concepts are blind 33 193 194 A 51 B 75 Kant also claims that an external environment is necessary for the establishment of the self Although Kant would want to argue that there is no empirical way of observing the self we can see the logical necessity of the self when we observe that we can have different perceptions of the external environment over time By uniting these general representations into one global representation we can see how a transcendental self emerges I am therefore conscious of the identical self in regard to the manifold of the representations that are given to me in an intuition because I call them all together my representations which constitute one 33 248 B 135 According to Guillaume Pigeard de Gurbert Kant s philosophy has its unity in the conceit of time which different uses speculative practical pragmatical historical or teleogical is crucial 114 Time and space Edit The Kantian revolution breaks with previous conceptions of time either metaphysical Leibniz or empirical ones Hume in its relation to space Against metaphysical time and space Kant explains they are not things in themselves but mere shape of the way we feel things Against empiricism he says that these subjective shapes are a priori are not given by experience since any experience of such or such time and space supposes that we are feeling things in the way of time and space The word transcendental qualifies this space and this time lying within the subject that make possible any sensible experience Kant adds that space itself depends on time because nothing can be in space without being within time Categories of the Faculty of Understanding Edit See also Category Kant Kant statue in the School of Philosophy and Human Sciences FAFICH in the Federal University of Minas Gerais UFMG Belo Horizonte Brazil Kant deemed it obvious that we have some objective knowledge of the world such as say Newtonian physics But this knowledge relies on synthetic a priori laws of nature like causality and substance How is this possible Kant s solution was that the subject must supply laws that make experience of objects possible and that these laws are synthetic a priori laws of nature that apply to all objects before we experience them To deduce all these laws Kant examined experience in general dissecting in it what is supplied by the mind from what is supplied by the given intuitions This is commonly called a transcendental deduction 115 To begin with Kant s distinction between the a posteriori being contingent and particular knowledge and the a priori being universal and necessary knowledge must be kept in mind If we merely connect two intuitions together in a perceiving subject the knowledge is always subjective because it is derived a posteriori when what is desired is for the knowledge to be objective that is for the two intuitions to refer to the object and hold good of it for anyone at any time not just the perceiving subject in its current condition What else is equivalent to objective knowledge besides the a priori universal and necessary knowledge Before knowledge can be objective it must be incorporated under an a priori category of understanding 115 116 For example if one says The sun shines on the stone the stone grows warm all that one perceives is phenomena One s judgment is contingent and holds no necessity But if one says The sunshine causes the stone to warm one subsumes the perception under the category of causality which is not found in the perception and one necessarily synthesizes the concept sunshine with the concept heat producing a necessarily universally true judgment 115 To explain the categories in more detail they are the preconditions of the construction of objects in the mind Indeed to even think of the sun and stone presupposes the category of subsistence that is substance For the categories synthesize the random data of the sensory manifold into intelligible objects This means that the categories are also the most abstract things one can say of any object whatsoever and hence one can have an a priori cognition of the totality of all objects of experience if one can list all of them To do so Kant formulates another transcendental deduction 115 Judgments are for Kant the preconditions of any thought Man thinks via judgments so all possible judgments must be listed and the perceptions connected within them put aside so as to make it possible to examine the moments when the understanding is engaged in constructing judgments For the categories are equivalent to these moments in that they are concepts of intuitions in general so far as they are determined by these moments universally and necessarily Thus by listing all the moments one can deduce from them all of the categories 115 One may now ask How many possible judgments are there Kant believed that all the possible propositions within Aristotle s syllogistic logic are equivalent to all possible judgments and that all the logical operators within the propositions are equivalent to the moments of the understanding within judgments Thus he listed Aristotle s system in four groups of three quantity universal particular singular quality affirmative negative infinite relation categorical hypothetical disjunctive and modality problematic assertoric apodeictic The parallelism with Kant s categories is obvious quantity unity plurality totality quality reality negation limitation relation substance cause community and modality possibility existence necessity 115 The fundamental building blocks of experience i e objective knowledge are now in place First there is the sensibility which supplies the mind with intuitions and then there is the understanding which produces judgments of these intuitions and can subsume them under categories These categories lift the intuitions up out of the subject s current state of consciousness and place them within consciousness in general producing universally necessary knowledge For the categories are innate in any rational being so any intuition thought within a category in one mind is necessarily subsumed and understood identically in any mind In other words we filter what we see and hear 115 Transcendental schema doctrine Edit See also Schema Kant Kant ran into a problem with his theory that the mind plays a part in producing objective knowledge Intuitions and categories are entirely disparate so how can they interact Kant s solution is the transcendental schema a priori principles by which the transcendental imagination connects concepts with intuitions through time All the principles are temporally bound for if a concept is purely a priori as the categories are then they must apply for all times Hence there are principles such as substance is that which endures through time and the cause must always be prior to the effect 115 117 In the context of transcendental schema the concept of transcendental reflection is of a great importance 118 Ethics Edit Immanuel Kant Main article Kantian ethics Kant developed his ethics or moral philosophy in three works Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals 1785 Critique of Practical Reason 1788 and Metaphysics of Morals 1797 In Groundwork Kant tries to convert our everyday obvious rational 119 knowledge of morality into philosophical knowledge The latter two works used practical reason which is based only on things about which reason can tell us and not deriving any principles from experience to reach conclusions which can be applied to the world of experience in the second part of The Metaphysics of Morals Kant is known for his theory that there is a single moral obligation which he called the Categorical Imperative and is derived from the concept of duty Kant defines the demands of moral law as categorical imperatives Categorical imperatives are principles that are intrinsically valid they are good in and of themselves they must be obeyed in all situations and circumstances if our behavior is to observe the moral law The Categorical Imperative provides a test against which moral statements can be assessed Kant also stated that the moral means and ends can be applied to the categorical imperative that rational beings can pursue certain ends using the appropriate means Ends based on physical needs or wants create hypothetical imperatives The categorical imperative can only be based on something that is an end in itself that is an end that is not a means to some other need desire or purpose 120 Kant believed that the moral law is a principle of reason itself and is not based on contingent facts about the world such as what would make us happy but to act on the moral law which has no other motive than worthiness to be happy 33 677 A 806 B 834 Accordingly he believed that moral obligation applies only to rational agents 121 Unlike a hypothetical imperative a categorical imperative is an unconditional obligation it has the force of an obligation regardless of our will or desires 122 In Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals 1785 Kant enumerated three formulations of the categorical imperative that he believed to be roughly equivalent 123 In the same book Kant stated Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law 124 According to Kant one cannot make exceptions for oneself The philosophical maxim on which one acts should always be considered to be a universal law without exception One cannot allow oneself to do a particular action unless one thinks it appropriate that the reason for the action should become a universal law For example one should not steal however dire the circumstances because by permitting oneself to steal one makes stealing a universally acceptable act This is the first formulation of the categorical imperative often known as the universalizability principle Kant believed that if an action is not done with the motive of duty then it is without moral value He thought that every action should have pure intention behind it otherwise it is meaningless The final result is not the most important aspect of an action rather how the person feels while carrying out the action is the time when value is attached to the result In Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant also posited the counter utilitarian idea that there is a difference between preferences and values and that considerations of individual rights temper calculations of aggregate utility a concept that is an axiom in economics 125 Everything has either a price or a dignity Whatever has a price can be replaced by something else as its equivalent on the other hand whatever is above all price and therefore admits of no equivalent has a dignity But that which constitutes the condition under which alone something can be an end in itself does not have mere relative worth i e price but an intrinsic worth i e a dignity p 53 italics in original A phrase quoted by Kant which is used to summarize the counter utilitarian nature of his moral philosophy is Fiat justitia pereat mundus Let justice be done though the world perish which he translates loosely as Let justice reign even if all the rascals in the world should perish from it This appears in his 1795 Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch Zum ewigen Frieden Ein philosophischer Entwurf Appendix 1 126 127 128 First formulation Edit In his Metaphysics Immanuel Kant introduced the categorical imperative Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law The first formulation Formula of Universal Law of the moral imperative requires that the maxims be chosen as though they should hold as universal laws of nature 123 This formulation in principle has as its supreme law the creed Always act according to that maxim whose universality as a law you can at the same time will and is the only condition under which a will can never come into conflict with itself 129 One interpretation of the first formulation is called the universalizability test 130 An agent s maxim according to Kant is his subjective principle of human actions that is what the agent believes is his reason to act 131 The universalisability test has five steps Find the agent s maxim i e an action paired with its motivation Take for example the declaration I will lie for personal benefit Lying is the action the motivation is to fulfill some sort of desire Together they form the maxim Imagine a possible world in which everyone in a similar position to the real world agent followed that maxim Decide if contradictions or irrationalities would arise in the possible world as a result of following the maxim If a contradiction or irrationality would arise acting on that maxim is not allowed in the real world If there is no contradiction then acting on that maxim is permissible and is sometimes required For a modern parallel see John Rawls hypothetical situation the original position Second formulation Edit The second formulation or Formula of the End in Itself holds that the rational being as by its nature an end and thus as an end in itself must serve in every maxim as the condition restricting all merely relative and arbitrary ends 123 The principle dictates that you a ct with reference to every rational being whether yourself or another so that it is an end in itself in your maxim meaning that the rational being is the basis of all maxims of action and must be treated never as a mere means but as the supreme limiting condition in the use of all means i e as an end at the same time 132 Third formulation Edit The third formulation i e Formula of Autonomy is a synthesis of the first two and is the basis for the complete determination of all maxims It states that all maxims which stem from autonomous legislation ought to harmonize with a possible realm of ends as with a realm of nature 123 In principle So act as if your maxims should serve at the same time as the universal law of all rational beings meaning that we should so act that we may think of ourselves as a member in the universal realm of ends legislating universal laws through our maxims that is a universal code of conduct in a possible realm of ends 133 No one may elevate themselves above the universal law therefore it is one s duty to follow the maxim s Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason Edit Main article Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason Commentators starting in the 20th century have tended to see Kant as having a strained relationship with religion though this was not the prevalent view in the 19th century Karl Leonhard Reinhold whose letters first made Kant famous wrote I believe that I may infer without reservation that the interest of religion and of Christianity in particular accords completely with the result of the Critique of Reason 134 Johann Schultz who wrote one of the first Kant commentaries wrote And does not this system itself cohere most splendidly with the Christian religion Do not the divinity and beneficence of the latter become all the more evident 135 This view continued throughout the 19th century as noted by Friedrich Nietzsche who said Kant s success is merely a theologian s success 136 The reason for these views was Kant s moral theology and the widespread belief that his philosophy was the great antithesis to Spinozism which had been convulsing the European academy for much of the 18th century Spinozism was widely seen as the cause of the Pantheism controversy and as a form of sophisticated pantheism or even atheism As Kant s philosophy disregarded the possibility of arguing for God through pure reason alone for the same reasons it also disregarded the possibility of arguing against God through pure reason alone This coupled with his moral philosophy his argument that the existence of morality is a rational reason why God and an afterlife do and must exist was the reason he was seen by many at least through the end of the 19th century as a great defender of religion in general and Christianity in particular citation needed Kant articulates his strongest criticisms of the organization and practices of religious organizations to those that encourage what he sees as a religion of counterfeit service to God 137 Among the major targets of his criticism are external ritual superstition and a hierarchical church order He sees these as efforts to make oneself pleasing to God in ways other than conscientious adherence to the principle of moral rightness in choosing and acting upon one s maxims Kant s criticisms on these matters along with his rejection of certain theoretical proofs grounded in pure reason particularly the ontological argument for the existence of God and his philosophical commentary on some Christian doctrines have resulted in interpretations that see Kant as hostile to religion in general and Christianity in particular e g Walsh 1967 Nevertheless other interpreters consider that Kant was trying to mark off defensible from indefensible Christian belief 138 Kant sees in Jesus Christ the affirmation of a pure moral disposition of the heart that can make man well pleasing to God 137 Regarding Kant s conception of religion some critics have argued that he was sympathetic to deism 139 Other critics have argued that Kant s moral conception moves from deism to theism as moral theism for example Allen W Wood 140 and Merold Westphal 141 As for Kant s book Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 95 it was emphasized that Kant reduced religiosity to rationality religion to morality and Christianity to ethics 142 However many interpreters including Allen W Wood 143 and Lawrence Pasternack 144 now agree with Stephen Palmquist s claim that a better way of reading Kant s Religion is to see him as raising morality to the status of religion 145 Idea of freedom Edit In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant distinguishes between the transcendental idea of freedom which as a psychological concept is mainly empirical and refers to whether a faculty of beginning a series of successive things or states from itself is to be assumed 33 486 A 448 B 467 and the practical concept of freedom as the independence of our will from the coercion or necessitation through sensuous impulses Kant finds it a source of difficulty that the practical idea of freedom is founded on the transcendental idea of freedom 33 533 A 533 4 B 561 2 but for the sake of practical interests uses the practical meaning taking no account of its transcendental meaning which he feels was properly disposed of in the Third Antinomy and as an element in the question of the freedom of the will is for philosophy a real stumbling block that has embarrassed speculative reason 33 486 A 448 B 467 Kant calls practical everything that is possible through freedom and the pure practical laws that are never given through sensuous conditions but are held analogously with the universal law of causality are moral laws Reason can give us only the pragmatic laws of free action through the senses but pure practical laws given by reason a priori 33 486 A 448 B 467 dictate what is to be done 33 674 676 A 800 2 B 828 30 The same distinction of transcendental and practical meaning can be applied to the idea of God with the proviso that the practical concept of freedom can be experienced 146 Categories of freedom Edit In the Critique of Practical Reason at the end of the second Main Part of the Analytics 147 Kant introduces the categories of freedom in analogy with the categories of understanding their practical counterparts Kant s categories of freedom apparently function primarily as conditions for the possibility for actions i to be free ii to be understood as free and iii to be morally evaluated For Kant although actions as theoretical objects are constituted by means of the theoretical categories actions as practical objects objects of practical use of reason and which can be good or bad are constituted by means of the categories of freedom Only in this way can actions as phenomena be a consequence of freedom and be understood and evaluated as such 148 Aesthetic philosophy Edit Kant discusses the subjective nature of aesthetic qualities and experiences in Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime 1764 Kant s contribution to aesthetic theory is developed in the Critique of Judgment 1790 where he investigates the possibility and logical status of judgments of taste In the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment the first major division of the Critique of Judgment Kant used the term aesthetic in a manner that according to Kant scholar W H Walsh differs from its modern sense 149 In the Critique of Pure Reason to note essential differences between judgments of taste moral judgments and scientific judgments Kant abandoned the term aesthetic as designating the critique of taste noting that judgments of taste could never be directed by laws a priori 150 After A G Baumgarten who wrote Aesthetica 1750 58 151 Kant was one of the first philosophers to develop and integrate aesthetic theory into a unified and comprehensive philosophical system utilizing ideas that played an integral role throughout his philosophy 152 In the chapter Analytic of the Beautiful in the Critique of Judgment Kant states that beauty is not a property of an artwork or natural phenomenon but is instead consciousness of the pleasure that attends the free play of the imagination and the understanding Even though it appears that we are using reason to decide what is beautiful the judgment is not a cognitive judgment 153 and is consequently not logical but aesthetical 1 A pure judgement of taste is subjective since it refers to the emotional response of the subject and is based upon nothing but esteem for an object itself it is a disinterested pleasure and we feel that pure judgements of taste i e judgements of beauty lay claim to universal validity 20 22 It is important to note that this universal validity is not derived from a determinate concept of beauty but from common sense 40 Kant also believed that a judgement of taste shares characteristics engaged in a moral judgement both are disinterested and we hold them to be universal In the chapter Analytic of the Sublime Kant identifies the sublime as an aesthetic quality that like beauty is subjective but unlike beauty refers to an indeterminate relationship between the faculties of the imagination and of reason and shares the character of moral judgments in the use of reason The feeling of the sublime divided into two distinct modes the mathematical and the dynamical sublime describes two subjective moments that concern the relationship of the faculty of the imagination to reason Some commentators 154 argue that Kant s critical philosophy contains a third kind of the sublime the moral sublime which is the aesthetic response to the moral law or a representation and a development of the noble sublime in Kant s theory of 1764 The mathematical sublime results from the failure of the imagination to comprehend natural objects that appear boundless and formless or appear absolutely great 23 25 This imaginative failure is then recuperated through the pleasure taken in reason s assertion of the concept of infinity In this move the faculty of reason proves itself superior to our fallible sensible self 25 26 In the dynamical sublime there is the sense of annihilation of the sensible self as the imagination tries to comprehend a vast might This power of nature threatens us but through the resistance of reason to such sensible annihilation the subject feels a pleasure and a sense of the human moral vocation This appreciation of moral feeling through exposure to the sublime helps to develop moral character Kant developed a theory of humor 54 that has been interpreted as an incongruity theory He illustrated his theory of humor by telling three narrative jokes in the Critique of Judgment He thought that the physiological impact of humor is akin to that of music 155 His knowledge of music however has been reported to be much weaker than his sense of humor He told many more jokes throughout his lectures and writings 156 Kant developed a distinction between an object of art as a material value subject to the conventions of society and the transcendental condition of the judgment of taste as a refined value in his Idea of A Universal History 1784 In the Fourth and Fifth Theses of that work he identified all art as the fruits of unsociableness due to men s antagonism in society 157 and in the Seventh Thesis asserted that while such material property is indicative of a civilized state only the ideal of morality and the universalization of refined value through the improvement of the mind belongs to culture 158 Political philosophy Edit Main article Political philosophy of Immanuel Kant In Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 159 Kant listed several conditions that he thought necessary for ending wars and creating a lasting peace They included a world of constitutional republics 160 His classical republican theory was extended in the Science of Right the first part of the Metaphysics of Morals 1797 161 Kant believed that universal history leads to the ultimate world of republican states at peace but his theory was not pragmatic The process was described in Perpetual Peace as natural rather than rational The guarantee of perpetual peace is nothing less than that great artist nature In her mechanical course we see that her aim is to produce a harmony among men against their will and indeed through their discord As a necessity working according to laws we do not know we call it destiny But considering its designs in universal history we call it providence inasmuch as we discern in it the profound wisdom of a higher cause which predetermines the course of nature and directs it to the objective final end of the human race 162 Kant s political thought can be summarized as republican government and international organization In more characteristically Kantian terms it is doctrine of the state based upon the law Rechtsstaat and of eternal peace Indeed in each of these formulations both terms express the same idea that of legal constitution or of peace through law Kant s political philosophy being essentially a legal doctrine rejects by definition the opposition between moral education and the play of passions as alternate foundations for social life The state is defined as the union of men under law The state is constituted by laws which are necessary a priori because they flow from the very concept of law A regime can be judged by no other criteria nor be assigned any other functions than those proper to the lawful order as such 163 He opposed democracy which at his time meant direct democracy believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty He stated democracy is properly speaking necessarily a despotism because it establishes an executive power in which all decide for or even against one who does not agree that is all who are not quite all decide and this is a contradiction of the general will with itself and with freedom 164 As with most writers at the time he distinguished three forms of government i e democracy aristocracy and monarchy with mixed government as the most ideal form of it Anthropology Edit 5 DM 1974 D silver coin commemorating the 250th birthday of Immanuel Kant in Konigsberg Kant lectured on anthropology the study of human nature for twenty three and a half years 165 His Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View was published in 1798 This was the subject of Michel Foucault s secondary dissertation for his State doctorate Introduction to Kant s Anthropology Kant s Lectures on Anthropology were published for the first time in 1997 in German 166 Introduction to Kant s Anthropology was translated into English and published by the Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy series in 2006 167 Kant was among the first people of his time to introduce anthropology as an intellectual area of study long before the field gained popularity and his texts are considered to have advanced the field His point of view was to influence the works of later philosophers such as Martin Heidegger and Paul Ricoeur Kant was also the first to suggest using a dimensionality approach to human diversity He analyzed the nature of the Hippocrates Galen four temperaments and plotted them in two dimensions 1 activation or energetic aspect of behaviour and 2 orientation on emotionality 168 Cholerics were described as emotional and energetic Phlegmatics as balanced and weak Sanguines as balanced and energetic and Melancholics as emotional and weak These two dimensions reappeared in all subsequent models of temperament and personality traits Kant viewed anthropology in two broad categories 1 the physiological approach which he referred to as what nature makes of the human being and 2 the pragmatic approach which explored the things that a human can and should make of himself 169 Racism Edit Kant was one of the most notable Enlightenment thinkers to defend racism and some have claimed that he was one of the central figures in the birth of modern scientific racism Where figures such as Carl Linnaeus and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach had supposed only empirical observation for racism Kant produced a fully developed theory of race Using the Four Temperaments of ancient Greece he proposed a hierarchy of four racial categories white Europeans yellow Asians black Africans and red Amerindians 43 41 40 42 170 171 Kant wrote that Whites contain all the impulses of nature in affects and passions all talents all dispositions to culture and civilization and can as readily obey as govern They are the only ones who always advance to perfection He describes South Asians as educated to the highest degree but only in the arts and not in the sciences He goes on that Hindustanis can never reach the level of abstract concepts and that a great hindustani man is one who has gone far in the art of deception and has much money He stated that the Hindus always stay the way they are and can never advance About black Africans Kant wrote that they can be educated but only as servants that is they allow themselves to be trained He quotes David Hume as challenging anyone to cite a single example in which a Negro has shown talents and asserts that among the hundreds of thousands of blacks transported during the Atlantic slave trade even among the freed still not a single one was ever found who presented anything great in art or science or any other praiseworthy quality To Kant the Negro can be disciplined and cultivated but is never genuinely civilized He falls of his own accord into savagery Native Americans Kant opined cannot be educated He calls them unmotivated lacking affect passion and love describing them as too weak for labor unfit for any culture and too phlegmatic for diligence He said the Native Americans are far below the Negro who undoubtedly holds the lowest of all remaining levels by which we designate the different races Kant stated that Americans and Blacks cannot govern themselves They thus serve only for slaves 171 41 40 172 J Sai Deepak states that Kant s views on race were consistent from 1764 when he was 40 years of age until 1795 In Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime 1764 he wrote that the black colour of a negro carpenter proved the stupidity of whatever he said and that the difference in the mental faculties of the Whites and Blacks was as large as the difference in their colors 173 Kant was an opponent of miscegenation believing that whites would be degraded and the fusing of races is undesirable for not every race adopts the morals and customs of the Europeans He stated that instead of assimilation which was intended by the melting together of the various races Nature has here made a law of just the opposite 174 He believed that in the future all races would be extinguished except that of the whites 171 Kant was also an antisemite believing that Jews were incapable of transcending material forces which a moral order required In this way Jews are the opposite of autonomous rational Christians and are therefore incapable of being incorporated into an ethical Christian society In his Anthropology Kant called the Jews a nation of cheaters and portrayed them as a group that has followed not the path of transcendental freedom but that of enslavement to the material world 175 Charles W Mills wrote that Kant has been sanitized for public consumption his racist works conveniently ignored 171 Robert Bernasconi stated that Kant supplied the first scientific definition of race Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze is credited with bringing Kant s contributions to racism to light in the 1990s among Western philosophers who often gloss over this part of his life and works 42 He wrote about Kant s ideas of race Kant s position on the importance of skin color not only as encoding but as proof of this codification of rational superiority or inferiority is evident in a comment he made on the subject of the reasoning capacity of a black person When he evaluated a statement made by an African Kant dismissed the statement with the comment this fellow was quite black from head to foot a clear proof that what he said was stupid It cannot therefore be argued that skin color for Kant was merely a physical characteristic It is rather evidence of an unchanging and unchangeable moral quality Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze The Color of Reason The Idea of Race in Kant s Anthropology Postcolonial African Philosophy A Critical Reader 1997 40 Pauline Kleingeld argues that while Kant was indeed a staunch advocate of scientific racism for much of his career his views on race changed significantly in works published in the last decade of his life 44 In particular she argues that Kant unambiguously rejected past views related to racial hierarchies and the diminished rights or moral status of non whites in Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 1795 This work also saw him providing extended arguments against European colonialism which he claimed was morally unjust and incompatible with the equal rights held by indigenous populations Kleingeld argues that this shift in Kant s views later in life has often been forgotten or ignored in the literature on Kant s racist anthropology and that the shift suggests a belated recognition of the fact that racial hierarchy was incompatible with a universalized moral framework 44 While Kant s perspective on the topic of European colonialism became more balanced he still considered Europeans civilized to the exception of others But to this perfection compare the inhospitable actions of the civilized and especially of the commercial states of our part of the world The injustice which they show to lands and peoples they visit which is equivalent to conquering them is carried by them to terrifying lengths America the lands inhabited by the Negro the Spice Islands the Cape etc were at the time of their discovery considered by these civilized intruders as lands without owners for they counted the inhabitants as nothing In East India Hindustan under the pretense of establishing economic undertakings they brought in foreign soldiers and used them to oppress the natives excited widespread wars among the various states spread famine rebellion perfidy and the whole litany of evils which afflict mankind Immanuel Kant Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 1795 176 Women Edit Many authors have criticised Kant s negative views on women 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 Influence and legacy EditKant s influence on Western thought has been profound 185 Although the basic tenets of Kant s transcendental idealism i e that space and time are a priori forms of human perception rather than real properties and the claim that formal logic and transcendental logic coincide have been claimed to be falsified by modern science and logic 186 187 188 and no longer set the intellectual agenda of contemporary philosophers Kant is credited with having innovated the way philosophical inquiry has been carried at least up to the early nineteenth century This shift consisted in several closely related innovations that although highly contentious in themselves have become important in postmodern philosophy and in the social sciences broadly construed The human subject seen as the centre of inquiry into human knowledge such that it is impossible to philosophize about things as they exist independently of human perception or of how they are for us 189 The notion that is possible to discover and systematically explore the inherent limits to our ability to know entirely a priori The notion of the categorical imperative an assertion that people are naturally endowed with the ability and obligation toward right reason and acting Perhaps his most famous quote is drawn from the Critique of Practical Reason Two things fill my mind with ever increasing wonder and awe the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me The concept of conditions of possibility as in his notion of the conditions of possible experience that is that things knowledge and forms of consciousness rest on prior conditions that make them possible so that to understand or to know them we must first understand these conditions The theory that objective experience is actively constituted or constructed by the functioning of the human mind His notion of moral autonomy as central to humanity His assertion of the principle that human beings should be treated as ends rather than as means Kant s ideas have been incorporated into a variety of schools of thought These include German idealism Marxism positivism phenomenology existentialism critical theory linguistic philosophy structuralism post structuralism and deconstruction citation needed Historical influence Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed July 2016 Learn how and when to remove this template message During his own life much critical attention was paid to his thought He influenced Reinhold Fichte Schelling Hegel and Novalis during the 1780s and 1790s The school of thinking known as German idealism developed from his writings The German idealists Fichte and Schelling for example tried to bring traditional metaphysically laden notions like the Absolute God and Being into the scope of Kant s critical thought 190 In so doing the German idealists tried to reverse Kant s view that we cannot know what we cannot observe Statue of Immanuel Kant in Kaliningrad Konigsberg Russia Replica by Harald Haacke de of the original by Christian Daniel Rauch lost in 1945 The influential English Romantic poet and aesthetic philosopher Samuel Taylor Coleridge was greatly influenced by Kant and helped to spread awareness of him and of German idealism generally in the UK and the USA In his Biographia Literaria 1817 he credits Kant s ideas in coming to believe that the mind is not a passive but an active agent in the apprehension of reality Hegel was one of Kant s first major critics The main accusations Hegel charged Kant s philosophy with were formalism or abstractism and irrationality In Hegel s view the entire project of setting a transcendental subject i e human consciousness apart from nature history and society was fundamentally flawed 191 although parts of that very project could be put to good use in a new direction that Hegel called the absolute idealism Similar concerns moved Hegel s criticisms to Kant s concept of moral autonomy to which Hegel opposed an ethic focused on the ethical life of the community 192 In a sense Hegel s notion of ethical life is meant to subsume rather than replace Kantian ethics And Hegel can be seen as trying to defend Kant s idea of freedom as going beyond finite desires by means of reason Thus in contrast to later critics like Nietzsche or Russell Hegel shares some of Kant s concerns 193 Kant s thinking on religion was used in Britain to challenge the decline in religious faith in the nineteenth century British Catholic writers notably G K Chesterton and Hilaire Belloc followed this approach Ronald Englefield debated this movement and Kant s use of language f Criticisms of Kant were common in the realist views of the new positivism at that time Arthur Schopenhauer was strongly influenced by Kant s transcendental idealism He like G E Schulze Jacobi and Fichte before him was critical of Kant s theory of the thing in itself Things in themselves they argued are neither the cause of what we observe nor are they completely beyond our access Ever since the first Critique of Pure Reason philosophers have been critical of Kant s theory of the thing in itself Many have argued if such a thing exists beyond experience then one cannot posit that it affects us causally since that would entail stretching the category causality beyond the realm of experience g For Schopenhauer things in themselves do not exist outside the non rational will The world as Schopenhauer would have it is the striving and largely unconscious will Michael Kelly in the preface to his 1910 book Kant s Ethics and Schopenhauer s Criticism stated Of Kant it may be said that what is good and true in his philosophy would have been buried with him were it not for Schopenhauer With the success and wide influence of Hegel s writings Kant s influence began to wane though there was in Germany a movement that hailed a return to Kant in the 1860s beginning with the publication of Kant und die Epigonen in 1865 by Otto Liebmann His motto was Back to Kant and a re examination of his ideas began see Neo Kantianism During the turn of the 20th century there was an important revival of Kant s theoretical philosophy known as the Marburg School represented in the work of Hermann Cohen Paul Natorp Ernst Cassirer 194 and anti Neo Kantian Nicolai Hartmann 195 Kant s notion of Critique has been quite influential The early German Romantics especially Friedrich Schlegel in his Athenaeum Fragments used Kant s self reflexive conception of criticism in their Romantic theory of poetry 196 Also in aesthetics Clement Greenberg in his classic essay Modernist Painting uses Kantian criticism what Greenberg refers to as immanent criticism to justify the aims of abstract painting a movement Greenberg saw as aware of the key limitation flatness that makes up the medium of painting 197 French philosopher Michel Foucault was also greatly influenced by Kant s notion of Critique and wrote several pieces on Kant for a re thinking of the Enlightenment as a form of critical thought He went so far as to classify his own philosophy as a critical history of modernity rooted in Kant 198 Kant believed that mathematical truths were forms of synthetic a priori knowledge which means they are necessary and universal yet known through the apriori intuition of space and time as transcendental preconditions of all phenomenal sense experience 199 Kant s often brief remarks about mathematics influenced the mathematical school known as intuitionism a movement in philosophy of mathematics opposed to Hilbert s formalism and Frege and Bertrand Russell s logicism 200 Influence on modern thinkers Edit West German postage stamp 1974 commemorating the 250th anniversary of Kant s birth With his Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch Kant is considered to have foreshadowed many of the ideas that have come to form the democratic peace theory one of the main controversies in political science 201 Prominent recent Kantians include the British philosophers P F Strawson 202 Onora O Neill 203 and Quassim Cassam 204 and the American philosophers Wilfrid Sellars 205 and Christine Korsgaard 206 Due to the influence of Strawson and Sellars among others there has been a renewed interest in Kant s view of the mind Central to many debates in philosophy of psychology and cognitive science is Kant s conception of the unity of consciousness 207 Jurgen Habermas and John Rawls are two significant political and moral philosophers whose work is strongly influenced by Kant s moral philosophy 208 They argued against relativism 209 supporting the Kantian view that universality is essential to any viable moral philosophy Jean Francois Lyotard however emphasized the indeterminacy in the nature of thought and language and has engaged in debates with Habermas based on the effects this indeterminacy has on philosophical and political debates 210 Mou Zongsan s study of Kant has been cited as a highly crucial part in the development of Mou s personal philosophy namely New Confucianism Widely regarded as the most influential Kant scholar in China Mou s rigorous critique of Kant s philosophy having translated all three of Kant s critiques served as an ardent attempt to reconcile Chinese and Western philosophy whilst increasing pressure to westernize in China 211 212 Kant s influence also has extended to the social behavioral and physical sciences as in the sociology of Max Weber the psychology of Jean Piaget and Carl Gustav Jung 213 214 and the linguistics of Noam Chomsky Kant s work on mathematics and synthetic a priori knowledge is also cited by theoretical physicist Albert Einstein as an early influence on his intellectual development but which he later criticised heavily and rejected 215 He held the view that if one does not want to assert that relativity theory goes against reason one cannot retain the a priori concepts and norms of Kant s system 216 However Kant scholar Stephen Palmquist has argued that Einstein s rejection of Kant s influence was primarily a response to mistaken interpretations of Kant being adopted by contemporary philosophers when in fact Kant s transcendental perspective informed Einstein s early worldview and led to his insights regarding simultaneity and eventually to his proposal of the theory of relativity 217 Because of the thoroughness of the Kantian paradigm shift his influence extends to thinkers who neither specifically refer to his work nor use his terminology In recent years there has been renewed interest in Kant s theory of mind from the point of view of formal logic and computer science 218 Joshua Greene s 2008 article The Secret Joke of Kant s Soul 219 argues that Kantian deontological ethics is best understood as rationalization rather than rationalism an attempt to justify intuitive moral judgments post hoc Several philosophers have written critical responses 220 221 222 223 Film television Edit Kant and his work was heavily referenced in the comedy television show The Good Place as the show deals with the subject of ethics and moral philosophy 224 Bibliography EditList of major works Edit Lectures on Ethics trans Louis Infield London Methuen 1930 1749 Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces Gedanken von der wahren Schatzung der lebendigen Krafte March 1755 Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels April 1755 Brief Outline of Certain Meditations on Fire Meditationum quarundam de igne succinta delineatio master s thesis under Johann Gottfried Teske 225 226 227 228 September 1755 A New Elucidation of the First Principles of Metaphysical Cognition Principiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio doctoral thesis 229 230 1756 The Use in Natural Philosophy of Metaphysics Combined with Geometry Part I Physical Monadology Metaphysicae cum geometrica iunctae usus in philosophia naturali cuius specimen I continet monadologiam physicam abbreviated as Monadologia Physica thesis as a prerequisite of associate professorship 231 1762 The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figuren 1763 The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God Der einzig mogliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes 1763 Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy Versuch den Begriff der negativen Grossen in die Weltweisheit einzufuhren 1764 Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime Beobachtungen uber das Gefuhl des Schonen und Erhabenen 1764 Essay on the Illness of the Head Uber die Krankheit des Kopfes 1764 Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality the Prize Essay Untersuchungen uber die Deutlichkeit der Grundsatze der naturlichen Theologie und der Moral 1766 Dreams of a Spirit Seer Traume eines Geistersehers 232 1768 On the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Regions in Space Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiedes der Gegenden im Raume 233 August 1770 Dissertation on the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis doctoral thesis 234 235 236 1 1775 On the Different Races of Man Uber die verschiedenen Rassen der Menschen 1781 First edition of the Critique of Pure Reason 237 Kritik der reinen Vernunft 238 1783 Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Prolegomena zu einer jeden kunftigen Metaphysik 1784 An Answer to the Question What Is Enlightenment Beantwortung der Frage Was ist Aufklarung 239 1784 Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltburgerlicher Absicht 1785 Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten 1786 Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science Metaphysische Anfangsgrunde der Naturwissenschaft 1786 What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking Was heisst sich im Denken orientieren 1786 Conjectural Beginning of Human History Mutmasslicher Anfang der Menschengeschichte 1787 Second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason 240 Kritik der reinen Vernunft 241 1788 Critique of Practical Reason Kritik der praktischen Vernunft 242 1790 Critique of Judgment Kritik der Urteilskraft 243 1793 Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft 95 244 1793 On the Old Saw That May be Right in Theory But It Won t Work in Practice Uber den Gemeinspruch Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein taugt aber nicht fur die Praxis 1795 Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch 245 Zum ewigen Frieden 246 1797 Metaphysics of Morals Metaphysik der Sitten First part is The Doctrine of Right which has often been published separately as The Science of Right 1798 Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht 1798 The Contest of Faculties 247 Der Streit der Fakultaten 248 1800 Logic Logik 1803 On Pedagogy Uber Padagogik 249 1804 Opus Postumum 1817 Lectures on Philosophical Theology Immanuel Kants Vorlesungen uber die philosophische Religionslehre edited by K H L Politz The English edition of A W Wood amp G M Clark Cornell 1978 is based on Politz second edition 1830 of these lectures 250 Collected works in German Edit Printed versionWilhelm Dilthey inaugurated the Academy edition the Akademie Ausgabe abbreviated as AA or Ak of Kant s writings Gesammelte Schriften Koniglich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin 1902 38 in 1895 251 and served as its first editor The volumes are grouped into four sections I Kant s published writings vols 1 9 II Kant s correspondence vols 10 13 III Kant s literary remains or Nachlass vols 14 23 and IV Student notes from Kant s lectures vols 24 29 Electronic version Elektronische Edition der Gesammelten Werke Immanuel Kants vols 1 23 See also Edit Philosophy portalAenesidemus Arthur Schopenhauer s criticism of Immanuel Kant s schemata Critique of the Kantian Philosophy Kant s influence on Mou Zongsan Kantian fallacy List of liberal theorists On the Basis of Morality On Vision and Colors Political philosophy of Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University Kaliningrad Russia Immanuel Kant WikiquoteNotes Edit However Kant has also been interpreted as a defender of the coherence theory of truth 2 a b Up to now it has been assumed that all our cognition must conform to the objects but all attempts to find out something about them a priori through concepts that would extend our cognition have on this presupposition come to nothing Hence let us once try whether we do not get farther with the problems of metaphysics by assuming that the objects must conform to our cognition which would agree better with the requested possibility of an a priori cognition of them which is to establish something about objects before they are given to us This would be just like the first thoughts of Copernicus who when he did not make good progress in the explanation of the celestial motions if he assumed that the entire celestial host revolves around the observer tried to see if he might not have greater success if he made the observer revolve and left the stars at rest Now in metaphysics we can try in a similar way regarding the intuition of objects If intuition has to conform to the constitution of the objects then I do not see how we can know anything of them a priori but if the object as an object of the senses conforms to the constitution of our faculty of intuition then I can very well represent this possibility to myself 33 110 B xvi vii Nietzsche wrote that Kant wanted to prove in a way that would dumbfound the common man that the common man was right that was the secret joke of this soul 39 Kant himself seems to have found his contribution not significant enough that he published his arguments in a newspaper commentary on the prize question and did not submit them to the Academy Whether the Earth has Undergone an Alteration of its Axial Rotation Kant s Cosmogony Translated by Hastie William Glasgow James Maclehose 1900 1754 pp 1 11 Retrieved 29 March 2022 The prize was instead awarded in 1756 to P Frisi who incorrectly argued against the slowing down of the spin 72 It has been noted that in 1778 in response to one of these offers by a former pupil Kant wrote Any change makes me apprehensive even if it offers the greatest promise of improving my condition and I am persuaded by this natural instinct of mine that I must take heed if I wish that the threads which the Fates spin so thin and weak in my case to be spun to any length My great thanks to my well wishers and friends who think so kindly of me as to undertake my welfare but at the same time a most humble request to protect me in my current condition from any disturbance 87 See Englefield s article Kant as Defender of the Faith in Nineteenth century England Question 12 16 27 London Pemberton reprinted in Critique of Pure Verbiage Essays on Abuses of Language in Literary Religious and Philosophical Writings edited by G A Wells and D R Oppenheimer Open Court 1990 For a review of this problem and the relevant literature see The Thing in Itself and the Problem of Affection in the revised edition of Henry Allison s Kant s Transcendental Idealism References Edit a b c Since he had written his last habilitation thesis 14 years earlier a new habilitation thesis was required see S J McGrath Joseph Carew eds Rethinking German Idealism Palgrave Macmillan 2016 p 24 The Coherence Theory of Truth Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 1 November 2019 Retrieved 29 April 2020 David Marian The Correspondence Theory of Truth In Zalta Edward N ed Archived copy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 14 February 2014 Retrieved 18 October 2019 a href Template Cite encyclopedia html title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a CS1 maint archived copy as title link Rockmore Tom 2004 On Foundationalism A Strategy for Metaphysical Realism Rowman amp Littlefield pp 65 ISBN 978 0 7425 3427 8 Frederick C Beiser German Idealism The Struggle Against Subjectivism 1781 1801 Harvard University Press 2002 part I Santos Robinson dos Schmidt Elke Elisabeth 2017 Realism and Antirealism in Kant s Moral Philosophy New Essays Walter de Gruyter GmbH amp Co KG p 199 ISBN 978 3 11 057451 7 Kant is an indirect realist Hanna Robert Kant Science and Human Nature Clarendon Press 2006 p 16 Oberst Michael 2015 Kant on Universals History of Philosophy Quarterly 32 4 335 352 Hanna Robert January 2008 Kantian non conceptualism Philosophical Studies 137 1 41 64 doi 10 1007 s11098 007 9166 0 S2CID 170296391 The application of the term perceptual non conceptualism to Kant s philosophy of perception is debatable see Hanna Robert The Togetherness Principle Kant s Conceptualism and Kant s Non Conceptualism Supplement to Kant s Theory of Judgment In Zalta Edward N ed Kant s Theory of Judgment gt the Togetherness Principle Kant s Conceptualism and Kant s Non Conceptualism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 11 June 2018 Retrieved 20 August 2018 Biographies Konigsberg Professors Manchester University Archived 26 December 2016 at the Wayback Machine His lectures on logic and metaphysics were quite popular and he still taught theology philosophy and mathematics when Kant studied at the university The only textbook found in Kant s library that stems from his student years was Marquardt s book on astronomy KrV A51 B75 6 See also Edward Willatt Kant Deleuze and Architectonics Continuum 2010 p 17 Kant argues that cognition can only come about as a result of the union of the abstract work of the understanding and the concrete input of sensation Burnham Douglas Immanuel Kant Aesthetics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 20 February 2018 Retrieved 18 October 2019 KpV 101 102 Ak V 121 22 See also Paul Saurette The Kantian Imperative Humiliation Common Sense Politics University of Toronto Press 2005 p 255 n 32 Meet Mr Green The Economist Retrieved 11 December 2022 Wie schwul war Kant How gay was Kant PDF Archived from the original PDF on 24 September 2015 Retrieved 11 December 2022 Kuehn 2001 p 251 I Kant Theoretical Philosophy 1755 1770 Cambridge University Press p 496 Immanuel Kant Philosophical Correspondence 1759 1799 University of Chicago Press 1967 p 18 Kant Archived 27 September 2019 at the Wayback Machine Collins English Dictionary Kant Archived 23 October 2014 at the Wayback Machine Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary Wells John C 2008 Longman Pronunciation Dictionary 3rd ed Longman ISBN 978 1 4058 8118 0 Jones Daniel 2011 Roach Peter Setter Jane Esling John eds Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary 18th ed Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 15255 6 Immanuel Duden in German Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 20 October 2018 Kant Duden in German Archived from the original on 20 October 2018 Retrieved 20 October 2018 a b c McCormick Matt Immanuel Kant Metaphysics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 15 February 2019 Retrieved 20 February 2019 a b Rohlf Michael 2020 Immanuel Kant in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University archived from the original on 3 September 2020 retrieved 27 May 2020 a b Immanuel Kant Biography Philosophy Books amp Facts Encyclopedia Britannica Archived from the original on 16 June 2015 Retrieved 27 May 2020 Durant Will Durant Ariel 1967 The Story of Civilization Rousseau and Revolution MJF Books pp 571 574 ISBN 978 1 56731 021 4 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 22 August 2020 Nigel Warburton 2011 Chapter 19 Rose tinted reality Immanuel Kant A little history of philosophy Yale University Press p 134 ISBN 978 0 300 15208 1 Kitcher Patrica 1996 First edition originally published in 1781 second edition originally published in 1787 Introduction by Patricia Kitcher C The Analytic of Principles Critique of Pure Reason By Kant Immanuel Translated by Pluhar Werner S Unified Edition with all variants from the 1781 and 1787 editions ed Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company Inc p l ISBN 0 87220 257 7 Although Hume s name is not mentioned in either version of this section from the beginning Kant s readers have understood that his purpose was to vindicate the causal concept after Hume s devastating attack Kant s reply to Hume was to argue we could have no cognition of events of objects changing by acquiring or losing a property unless we used a concept of causation that included both the offending and related properties of universality and necessity There are two relatively recent translations Kant Immanuel 1999 Critique of Pure Reason The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant Translated by Guyer Paul Wood Allen W Cambridge Cambridge U P ISBN 978 0 5216 5729 7 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 22 August 2020 Kant Immanuel 1996 Critique of Pure Reason Translated by Pluhar Werner S Indianapolis Hackett ISBN 978 0 87220 257 3 Both translations have their virtues and both are better than earlier translations McLaughlin Peter 1999 Review Erkenntnis 51 2 3 357 doi 10 1023 a 1005483714722 Page references to the Critique of Pure Reason are commonly given to the first 1781 and second 1787 editions as published in the Prussian Academy series as respectively A page number and B page number a b c d e f g h i j k Kant Immanuel 1999 Critique of Pure Reason The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W Wood Cambridge Cambridge U P ISBN 978 0 5216 5729 7 Vanzo Alberto January 2013 Kant on Empiricism and Rationalism History of Philosophy Quarterly 30 1 53 74 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 17 December 2015 Rohlf Michael Immanuel Kant In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 12 January 2012 Retrieved 6 October 2015 Kant Immanuel 1784 Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose Arthur Schopenhauer On the Basis of Morals in The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics trans Chris Janaway 2009 sections 4 5 Friedrich Nietzsche The Anti Christ 1895 para 10 Archived 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine Friedrich Nietzsche trans Walter Arnold Kaufmann The Portable Nietzsche 1976 p 96 a b c d Eze Emmanuel Chukwudi 1997 Postcolonial African Philosophy A Critical Reader Wiley pp 103 131 ISBN 978 0 631 20339 1 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 a b c Eze Emmanuel Chukwudi 1997 Race and the Enlightenment A Reader Wiley pp 39 48 ISBN 978 0 631 20136 6 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 a b c Bouie Jamelle 5 June 2018 How the Enlightenment Created Modern Race Thinking and Why We Should Confront It Slate Magazine Archived from the original on 15 June 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 a b Bernasconi Robert 2010 Defining Race Scientifically A response to Michael Banton Ethnicities 10 1 141 148 doi 10 1177 14687968100100010802 ISSN 1468 7968 JSTOR 23890861 S2CID 143925406 a b c Kleingeld Pauline October 2007 Kant s Second Thoughts on Race PDF The Philosophical Quarterly 57 229 573 592 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9213 2007 498 x hdl 11370 e15b6815 5eab 42d6 a789 24a2f6ecb946 S2CID 55185762 Archived PDF from the original on 16 February 2019 Retrieved 14 December 2020 Cosmopolis Koenigsberg is dead de 23 April 2001 Archived from the original on 22 March 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Mortensen Hans and Gertrud Kants vaterliche Ahnen und ihre Umwelt Rede von 1952 in Jahrbuch der Albertus Universitat zu Konigsberg Pr Holzner Verlag Kitzingen Main 1953 Vol 3 p 26 R K Murray The Origin of Immanuel Kant s Family Name Kantian Review 13 1 March 2008 pp 190 93 Rosa Kohlheim Volker Kohlheim Duden Familiennamen Herkunft und Bedeutung von 20 000 Nachnamen Bibliographisches Institut amp F A Brockhaus AG Mannheim 2005 p 365 Haupt Viktor Rede des Bohnenkonigs Von Petersburg bis Panama Die Genealogie der Familie Kant PDF freunde kants com in German p 7 Archived from the original on 25 September 2015 Kuehn 2001 p 26 Pasternack Lawrence Fugate Courtney 2020 Kant s Philosophy of Religion in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 25 February 2021 Kuehn 2001 p 47 Metaphysics p 131 Immanuel Kant Christian Research Institute 30 September 2010 Archived from the original on 20 June 2017 Retrieved 15 June 2017 While this sounds skeptical Kant is only agnostic about our knowledge of metaphysical objects such as God And as noted above Kant s agnosticism leads to the conclusion that we can neither affirm nor deny claims made by traditional metaphysics Andrew Fiala J M D Meiklejohn Critique of Pure Reason Introduction p xi Edward J Verstraete 2008 The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics In Ed Hindson Ergun Caner eds The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics Surveying the Evidence for the Truth of Christianity Harvest House Publishers p 82 ISBN 978 0 7369 2084 1 It is in this sense that modern atheism rests heavily upon the skepticism of David Hume and the agnosticism of Immanuel Kant Norman L Geisler Frank Turek 2004 Kant s Agnosticism Should We Be Agnostic About It I Don t Have Enough Faith to Be an Atheist Crossway pp 59 60 ISBN 978 1 58134 561 2 Immanuel Kant s impact has been even more devastating to the Christian worldview than David Hume s For if Kant s philosophy is right then there is no way to know anything about the real world even empirically verifiable things Gary D Badcock 1997 Light of Truth and Fire of Love A Theology of the Holy Spirit Wm B Eerdmans Publishing p 113 ISBN 978 0 8028 4288 6 Kant has no interest in prayer or worship and is in fact agnostic when it comes to such classical theological questions as the doctrine of God or of the Holy Spirit Norman L Geisler Paul K Hoffman ed 2006 The Agnosticism of Immanuel Kant Why I Am a Christian Leading Thinkers Explain Why They Believe Baker Books p 45 ISBN 978 0 8010 6712 9 Flinn Frank K 2007 Encyclopedia of Catholicism Infobase Publishing p 10 ISBN 978 0 8160 7565 2 Following Locke the classic agnostic claims not to accept more propositions than are warranted by empirical evidence In this sense an agnostic appeals to Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 who claims in his Critique of Pure Reason that since God freedom immortality and the soul can be both proved and disproved by theoretical reason we ought to suspend judgement about them Hare John E 1996 The Moral Gap Kantian Ethics Human Limits and God s Assistance Oxford Clarendon Press p 42 Hare further suggests that Kant is not in the ordinary sense an agnostic about God In his view Kant thinks that there are good moral grounds for theistic belief A person who already understands the claims of duty will find the teachings of Christianity worthy of love even though they are not objectively necessary p 47 Kuehn M 2001 Kant A biography New York Cambridge University Press p 169 Immanuel Kant Joseph Green Robert Kant Immanuel Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime Trans John T Goldthwait University of California Press 1961 2003 ISBN 978 0 520 24078 0 Vorlander Karl 1924 Bei Pfarrer Andersch in Judtschen Immanuel Kant Der Mann und das Werk in German Archived from the original on 18 October 2019 Retrieved 18 October 2019 Vorlander Karl 1924 Bei Major von Hulsen in Arnsdorf Immanuel Kant Der Mann und das Werk in German Archived from the original on 1 August 2020 Retrieved 18 October 2019 The American International Encyclopedia New York J J Little amp Ives 1954 Vol IX Porter Burton 2010 What the Tortoise Taught Us The Story of Philosophy Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers p 133 Kuehn 2001 p 94 Kuehn 2001 p 98 Eric Watkins ed Immanuel Kant Natural Science Cambridge University Press 2012 Thoughts on the true estimation Archived 7 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine Schonfeld Martin 2000 The Philosophy of the Young Kant The Precritical Project Oxford University Press p 84 ISBN 978 0 19 513218 2 a b Brush Stephen G 2014 A History of Modern Planetary Physics Nebulous Earth p 7 ISBN 978 0 521 44171 1 See Kant I 1756a Von den Ursachen der Erderschutterungen bei Gelegenheit des Unglucks welches die westliche Lander von Europa gegen das Ende des vorigen Jahres betroffen hat On the causes of the earthquakes on the occasion of the disaster which affected the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year In Koniglich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences ed s 1902 Kant s gesammelte Schriften Kant s collected writings in German Berlin Germany G Reimer vol 1 pp 417 427 Kant I 1756b Geschichte und Naturbeschreibung der merkwurdigsten Vorfalle des Erdbebens welches an dem Ende des 1755sten Jahres einen grossen Theil der Erde erschuttert hat History and description of the nature of the most remarkable events of the earthquake which shook a large part of the Earth at the end of the year 1755 ibid pp 429 461 Kant I 1756c Immanuel Kants fortgesetzte Betrachtung der seit einiger Zeit wahrgenommenen Erderschutterungen Immanuel Kant s continued consideration of the earthquakes that were felt some time ago ibid pp 463 472 Amador Filomena 2004 The causes of 1755 Lisbon earthquake on Kant In Escribano Benito J J Espanol Gonzalez L Martinez Garcia M A ed s Actas VIII Congreso de la Sociedad Espanola de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Tecnicas Proceedings of the Eighth Congress of the Spanish Society of the History of the Sciences and Technology in English Logrono Spain Sociedad Espanola de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Tecnicas Universidad de la Rioja vol 2 pp 485 495 a b Richards Paul 1974 Kant s Geography and Mental Maps Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 61 1 16 doi 10 2307 621596 JSTOR 621596 Elden Stuart 2009 Reassessing Kant s geography PDF Journal of Historical Geography 35 1 3 25 doi 10 1016 j jhg 2008 06 001 Archived PDF from the original on 1 August 2020 Retrieved 27 September 2019 Gamow George 1947 One Two Three Infinity New York Viking P pp 300ff Address of the President of the Geological Society 1869 mathcs clarku edu Retrieved 11 May 2022 On the causes of earthquakes on the occasion of the calamity that befell the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year 1756 Kant Natural Science The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant Cambridge University Press 2012 pp 327 336 doi 10 1017 CBO9781139014380 009 ISBN 9780521363945 a b Gulyga Arsenij Immanuel Kant His Life and Thought Trans Marijan Despaltovic Boston Birkhauser 1987 p 62 Dreams of a Spirit Seer en wikisource org Retrieved 10 December 2022 A Commentary on Kant s Dreams of a Spirit Seer philpapers org Retrieved 10 December 2022 Cf for example Susan Shell The Embodiment of Reason Chicago 1996 Kuehn Manfred 2009 Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Background Source Materials Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press p 276 ISBN 978 0 521 78162 6 a b c Smith Homer W 1952 Man and His Gods New York Grosset amp Dunlap p 404 Immanuel Kant Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics p 57 Ak 4 260 Christopher Kul Want and Andrzej Klimowski Introducing Kant Cambridge Icon Books 2005 page needed ISBN 978 1 84046 664 5 Smith Homer W 1952 Man and His Gods New York Grosset amp Dunlap p 416 Dorrien Gary 2012 Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit The Idealistic Logic of Modern Theology Malden MA John Wiley amp Sons p 37 ISBN 978 0 470 67331 7 Copleston Frederick Charles 2003 The Enlightenment Voltaire to Kant p 146 Sassen Brigitte Kant s Early Critics The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy 2000 Ein Jahrhundert deutscher Literaturkritik vol III Der Aufstieg zur Klassik in der Kritik der Zeit Berlin 1959 p 315 as quoted in Gulyga Arsenij Immanuel Kant His Life and Thought Trans Marijan Despaltovic Boston Birkhauser 1987 Gulyga Arsenij Immanuel Kant His Life and Thought Trans Marijan Despaltovic Boston Birkhauser 1987 pp 28 29 Guyer Paul 2006 The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press p 631 ISBN 978 0 521 82303 6 a b c Werner S Pluhar Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason Archived 4 March 2020 at the Wayback Machine 2009 Description Archived 1 February 2020 at the Wayback Machine amp Contents With an Introduction Archived 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine by Stephen Palmquist Indianapolis Hackett Publishing Company a b c d e Derrida Vacant Chair p 44 Open letter by Kant denouncing Fichte s Philosophy Korpora org in German Archived from the original on 19 July 2011 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Peirce C S Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 1 HUP 1960 Kant and his Refutation of Idealism p 15 Kant Immanuel Logic G B Jasche ed R S Hartman W Schwarz translators Indianapolis 1984 p xv Karl Vorlander Immanuel Kant Der Mann und das Werk Hamburg Meiner 1992 p II 332 Heine on Immanuel Kant PDF Archived PDF from the original on 23 November 2015 Retrieved 10 July 2015 Examined Lives From Socrates to Nietzsche James Miller p 284 Immanuel Kant and the Bo a rders of Art History Mark Cheetham in The Subjects of Art History Historical Objects in Contemporary Perspectives p 16 Beyer Susanne 25 July 2014 Resurrecting Konigsberg Russian City Looks to German Roots Spiegel Online Archived from the original on 4 February 2018 Retrieved 3 February 2018 Executive order on establishing Immanuel Kant University Kishkovsky Sophia 28 November 2018 Kant monument splashed with pink paint in Kaliningrad The Art Newspaper Archived from the original on 4 December 2018 Retrieved 3 December 2018 The Science of Right Conclusion In the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason Kant refers to space as no discursive or general conception of the relation of things but a pure intuition and maintained that We can only represent to ourselves one space The general notion of spaces depends solely upon limitations Meikeljohn trans A25 In the second edition of the CPR Kant adds The original representation of space is an a priori intuition not a concept Kemp Smith trans B40 In regard to time Kant states that Time is not a discursive or what is called a general concept but a pure form of sensible intuition Different times are but parts of one and the same time and the representation which can be given only through a single object is intuition A31 B47 For the differences in the discursive use of reason according to concepts and its intuitive use through the construction of concepts see Critique of Pure Reason A719 B747 ff and A837 B865 On One and the same thing in space and time and the mathematical construction of concepts see A724 B752 Immanuel Kant Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 14 November 2019 Retrieved 29 May 2019 Kant Immanuel definition of Kant Immanuel in the Free Online Encyclopedia Encyclopedia2 thefreedictionary com Archived from the original on 2 March 2014 Retrieved 26 February 2014 Kant Immanuel Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics 2 Archived from the original on 1 August 2020 Retrieved 22 March 2020 Pigeard de Gurbert Guillaume 2015 Kant et le temps in French Paris Kime p 57 ISBN 978 2 84174 708 5 The German word Anschauung which Kant used literally means looking at and generally means what in philosophy in English is called perception However it sometimes is rendered as intuition not however with the vernacular meaning of an indescribable or mystical experience or sixth sense but rather with the meaning of the direct perception or grasping of sensory phenomena In this article both terms perception and intuition are used to stand for Kant s Anschauung Pigeard de Gurbert Guillaume 2015 Kant et le temps in French Paris Kime ISBN 978 2 84174 708 5 a b c d e f g h Immanuel Kant Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics pp 35 43 Deleuze on Kant Archived 14 November 2007 at the Wayback Machine from where the definitions of a priori and a posteriori were obtained Immanuel Kant Critique of Judgment the Introduction to the Hackett edition Balanovskiy Valentin 2018 What is Kant s Transcendental Reflection Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 75 17 27 doi 10 5840 wcp232018751730 ISBN 978 1 63435 038 9 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 29 May 2020 The distinction between rational and philosophical knowledge is given in the Preface to the Groundwork 1785 Kant Foundations p 421 Kant Foundations p 408 Kant Foundations pp 420 421 a b c d Kant Foundations p 436 Kant Immanuel 1993 1785 Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals Translated by Ellington James W 3rd ed Hackett p 30 ISBN 978 0 87220 166 8 It is standard to also reference the Akademie Ausgabe of Kant s works The Groundwork occurs in the fourth volume The above citation is taken from 4 421 Millennium Ecosystem Assessment 2003 Ecosystems and Well being A Framework for Assessment Washington DC Island Press p 142 Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch Appendix 1 Constitution org Archived from the original on 2 May 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Kant Immanuel 1796 Project for a Perpetual Peace p 61 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Kant Immanuel 1838 Hartenstein G ed Immanuel Kant s Werke revidirte Gesammtausg in German p 456 Retrieved 24 July 2009 pereat mundus Kant Kant Foundations p 437 Kant and the German Enlightenment in History of Ethics Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3 pp 95 96 MacMillan 1973 Kant Foundations pp 400 429 Kant Foundations pp 437 38 Kant Foundations pp 438 439 See also Kingdom of Ends Karl Leonhard Reinhold Letters on the Kantian Philosophy 1786 3rd Letter Johann Schultz Exposition of Kant s Critique of Pure Reason 1784 141 The Protestant pastor is the grandfather of German philosophy German philosophy is at bottom a cunning theology Why the rejoicing heard through the German academic world three quarters composed of the sons of pastors and teachers at the appearance of Kant Why the Germans conviction which still find echo even today that with Kant things were taking a turn of the better Kant s success is merely a theologian s success Nietzsche The Antichrist 10 a b Immanuel Kant Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone 1793 Book IV Part 1 Section 1 The Christian religion as a natural religion Pasternack Lawrence Rossi Philip Kant s Philosophy of Religion In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2014 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 9 July 2010 Retrieved 18 October 2019 For example Peter Byrne who wrote about Kant s relationship with deism Byrne Peter 2007 Kant on God London Ashgate p 159 Wood Allen W 1970 Kant s moral religion London and Ithaca Cornell University Press p 16 Westphal Merold 2010 The Emerge of Modern Philosophy of Religion in Taliaferro Charles Draper Paul and Quinn Philip editors A Companion to Philosophy of Religion Oxford Blackwell p 135 Iţu Mircia 2004 Dumnezeu si religia in concepţia lui Immanuel Kant din Religia in limitele raţiunii in Boboc Alexandru and Maris N I editors Studii de istoria filosofiei universale volume 12 Bucharest Romanian Academy Wood Allen W 2020 Kant and Religion Cambridge University Press p 2 See e g Lawrence Pasternack Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason New York Routledge 2014 pp 239 240 Palmquist Stephen 1992 Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality Kant Studien 83 2 pp 129 148 The concept of freedom is also handled in the third section of the Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals in the Critique of Practical Reason see VII and VIII 5 65 67 Susanne Bobzien Die Kategorien der Freiheit bei Kant in Kant Analysen Probleme Kritik Vol 1 1988 193 220 Critique of Judgment in Kant Immanuel Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 4 Macmillan 1973 Kant Critique of Pure Reason A22 B36 Beardsley Monroe History of Aesthetics Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 1 section on Toward a unified aesthetics p 25 Macmillan 1973 Baumgarten coined the term aesthetics and expanded clarified and unified Wolffian aesthetic theory but had left the Aesthetica unfinished See also Tonelli Giorgio Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 1 Macmillan 1973 In Bernard s translation of the Critique of Judgment he indicates in the notes that Kant s reference in 15 in regard to the identification of perfection and beauty is probably a reference to Baumgarten German Idealism in History of Aesthetics Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 1 Macmillan 1973 Kant s general discussions of the distinction between cognition and conscious of are also given in the Critique of Pure Reason notably A320 B376 and section V and the conclusion of section VIII of his Introduction in Logic Clewis Robert 2009 The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom Cambridge Cambridge University Press Archived from the original on 20 October 2012 Retrieved 8 December 2011 Jakobidze Gitman Alexander 2020 Kant s Situated Approach to Musicking and Joking Journal of Interdisciplinary Music Studies 10 17 33 doi 10 25364 24 10 2020 2 Clewis Robert 2020 Kant s Humorous Writings An Illustrated Guide London Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 350 11279 7 Kant Immanuel Idea for a Universal History Trans Lewis White Beck 20 22 Kant Immanuel Idea for a Universal History Trans Lewis White Beck 26 Kant Immanuel Perpetual Peace A Philosophical Sketch Archived 6 April 2019 at the Wayback Machine 1795 Kant Immanuel Perpetual Peace Trans Lewis White Beck 377 Manfred Riedel Between Tradition and Revolution The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy Cambridge 1984 On History ed L W Beck New York Bobbs Merill 1963 p 106 History of Political Philosophy edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey The University of Chicago Press 1987 pp 581 582 603 Kant Immanuel Perpetual Peace Trans Lewis White Beck 352 Wilson Holly 2006 Kant s Pragmatic Anthropology Albany State University of New York Press p 7 ISBN 978 0 7914 6849 4 Thomas Sturm Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen Paderborn Mentis Verlag 2009 Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View ed Robert B Louden introduction by Manfred Kuehn Cambridge University Press 2006 Kant I 1798 Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view trans Mary Gregor The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 1974 VII Gregor Brian Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View By Immanuel Kant Translated and edited by Robert B Louden Heythrop a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Kant Immanuel Kant on the Different Races of Man PDF UMass Amherst Archived PDF from the original on 1 August 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 a b c d Mills Charles W 2017 Black Rights White Wrongs The Critique of Racial Liberalism Oxford University Press pp 169 193 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780190245412 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 024545 0 Archived from the original on 16 June 2020 Retrieved 15 June 2020 Kant on the different human races 1777 Black Central Europe 4 February 2016 Archived from the original on 16 June 2020 Retrieved 16 June 2020 Deepak J Sai 2021 India that is Bharat Coloniality Civilisation Constitution 1st ed USA Bloomsbury p 107 ISBN 9789354352508 Kant Immanuel 1798 Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View p 236 Shrage Laurie 18 March 2019 Should we continue to teach thinkers like Kant Voltaire and Hume without mention of the harmful prejudices they helped legitimize The New York Times Retrieved 10 November 2022 Immanuel Kant Perpetual Peace www mtholyoke edu Retrieved 3 March 2021 Hay Carol 9 December 2013 A Feminist Kant Opinionator Huseyinzadegan Dilek Pascoe Jordan 7 April 2021 Dismantling Kantian Frames Notes toward a Feminist Politics of Location and Accountability Gould Timothy 1990 Intensity and Its Audiences Notes towards a Feminist Perspective on the Kantian Sublime The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48 4 305 315 doi 10 2307 431568 JSTOR 431568 via JSTOR https core ac uk download pdf 232845343 pdf https philpapers org archive MIKKOM pdf Hay Carol 27 January 2013 Hay Carol ed Kantianism Liberalism and Feminism Resisting Oppression Palgrave Macmillan UK pp 50 88 doi 10 1057 9781137003904 2 via Springer Link https philarchive org archive VARKAW 10 A Feminist Defence of Kant Prof Oliver A Johnson claims that With the possible exception of Plato s Republic Critique of Pure Reason is the most important philosophical book ever written Article on Kant within the collection Great thinkers of the Western World Ian P McGreal Ed HarperCollins 1992 Strawson Peter Bounds of Sense Essay on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason ASIN 0415040302 Einstein on Kant www pitt edu Archived from the original on 9 August 2020 Retrieved 2 September 2020 Perrick Michael 1985 Kant and Kripke on Necessary Empirical Truths Mind 94 376 596 598 doi 10 1093 mind XCIV 376 596 ISSN 0026 4423 JSTOR 2254731 See Stephen Palmquist The Architectonic Form of Kant s Copernican Logic Metaphilosophy 17 4 October 1986 pp 266 288 revised and reprinted as Chapter III of Kant s System of Perspectives Archived 14 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy Lanham University Press of America 1993 There is much debate in the recent scholarship about the extent to which Fichte and Schelling actually overstep the boundaries of Kant s critical philosophy thus entering the realm of dogmatic or pre Critical philosophy Beiser s German Idealism discusses some of these issues Beiser Frederick C German Idealism The Struggle against Subjectivism 1781 1801 Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 2002 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1827 Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline Heidelberg pp 14 15 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Natural Law The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law Its Place in Moral Philosophy and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences trans T M Knox Philadelphia PA University of Pennsylvania Press 1975 Hegel s mature view and his concept of ethical life is elaborated in his Philosophy of Right Hegel Philosophy of Right trans T M Knox Oxford University Press 1967 Robert Pippin s Hegel s Idealism Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1989 emphasizes the continuity of Hegel s concerns with Kant s Robert Wallace Hegel s Philosophy of Reality Freedom and God Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2005 explains how Hegel s Science of Logic defends Kant s idea of freedom as going beyond finite inclinations contra skeptics such as David Hume Beck Lewis White Neo Kantianism In Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 5 6 Macmillan 1973 Article on Neo Kantianism by a translator and scholar of Kant Cerf Walter Nicolai Hartmann In Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3 4 Macmillan 1973 Nicolai was a realist who later rejected the idealism of Neo Kantianism his anti Neo Kantian views emerging with the publication of the second volume of Hegel 1929 Schlegel Friedrich Athenaeum Fragments in Philosophical Fragments Trans Peter Firchow Minneapolis MN University of Minnesota Press 1991 See especially fragments Nos 1 43 44 Greenberg Clement Modernist Painting in The Philosophy of Art ed Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley McGraw Hill 1995 See Essential Works of Foucault 1954 1984 vol 2 Aesthetics Method and Epistemology Ed by James Faubion Trans Robert Hurley et al New York City The New Press 1998 2010 reprint See Foucault Michel 1926 entry by Maurice Florence For a discussion and qualified defense of this position see Stephen Palmquist A Priori Knowledge in Perspective I Mathematics Method and Pure Intuition The Review of Metaphysics 41 1 September 1987 pp 3 22 Korner Stephan The Philosophy of Mathematics Dover 1986 For an analysis of Kant s writings on mathematics see Friedman Michael Kant and the Exact Sciences Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1992 Ray James Lee 1998 Does Democracy Cause Peace Annual Review of Political Science 1 27 46 doi 10 1146 annurev polisci 1 1 27 Archived from the original on 17 February 2008 Strawson P F The Bounds of Sense An Essay on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Routledge 2004 When first published in 1966 this book forced many Anglo American philosophers to reconsider Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Aridi Sara 14 March 2017 Onora O Neill Wins Holberg Prize for Academic Research The New York Times Archived from the original on 9 January 2019 Retrieved 9 January 2019 Cassam Q The Possibility of Knowledge Oxford 2009 Sellars Wilfrid Science and Metaphysics Variations on Kantian Themes Ridgeview Publishing Company 1967 Korsgaard Christine Creating the Kingdom of Ends Cambridge New York Cambridge University Press 1996 ISBN 978 0 521 49644 5 Not a commentary but a defense of a broadly Kantian approach to ethics Brook Andrew Kant and the Mind Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1994 See also Meerbote R Kant s Functionalism In J C Smith ed Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science Dordrecht Holland Reidel 1991 Brook has an article on Kant s View of the Mind in the Stanford Encyclopedia Archived 9 July 2010 at the Wayback Machine See Habermas J Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action Trans Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen Cambridge Massachusetts MIT Press 1996 For Rawls see Rawls John Theory of Justice Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1971 Rawls has a well known essay on Kant s concept of good See Rawls Themes in Kant s Moral Philosophy in Kant s Transcendental Deductions Ed Eckart Forster Stanford CA Stanford University Press 1989 Habermas J 1994 The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of Its Voices In Habermas J Eds Postmetaphysical Thinking Political Essays Cambridge Massachusetts 115 148 Rorty R 2984 Habermas and Lyotard on postmodernity Praxis International 32 44 Palmquist Stephen 19 November 2010 Cultivating Personhood Kant and Asian Philosophy 1st ed Hong Kong De Gruyter Inc pp 25 ISBN 978 3 11 022624 9 Wing Cheuk Chan 21 February 2006 Mou Zongsan s Transformation of Kant s Philosophy Journal of Chinese Philosophy 33 1 1 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6253 2006 00340 x Balanovskiy Valentin 2016 Whether jung was a kantian Con Textos Kantianos 4 118 126 doi 10 5281 zenodo 2550828 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 29 May 2020 Balanovskiy Valentin 2017 Kant and Jung on the prospects of Scientific Psychology Estudos Kantianos 5 1 357 390 doi 10 36311 2318 0501 2017 v5n1 26 p375 Archived from the original on 20 December 2020 Retrieved 29 May 2020 Issacson Walter Einstein His Life and Universe p 20 Einstein on Kant www pitt edu Retrieved 13 March 2021 Palmquist S 2010 The Kantian grounding of Einstein s worldview I The early influence of Kant s system of perspectives Polish Journal of Philosophy 4 1 45 64 Theodora Achourioti amp Michiel van Lambalgen A Formalization of Kant s Transcendental Logic The Review of Symbolic Logic 4 2011 254 289 Moral psychology Walter Sinnott Armstrong Cambridge Mass MIT Press 2008 2014 ISBN 978 0 262 33728 1 OCLC 605120795 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint others link Lott Micah October 2016 Moral Implications from Cognitive Neuro Science No Clear Route Ethics 127 1 241 256 doi 10 1086 687337 S2CID 151940241 Konigs Peter 3 April 2018 Two types of debunking arguments Philosophical Psychology 31 3 383 402 doi 10 1080 09515089 2018 1426100 S2CID 148678250 Meyers C D 19 May 2015 Brains trolleys and intuitions Defending deontology from the Greene Singer argument Philosophical Psychology 28 4 466 486 doi 10 1080 09515089 2013 849381 S2CID 146547149 Kahane Guy 2012 On the Wrong Track Process and Content in Moral Psychology Mind amp Language 27 5 519 545 doi 10 1111 mila 12001 PMC 3546390 PMID 23335831 Wansbrough Aleks Kantian comedy the philosophy of The Good Place The Conversation Retrieved 20 February 2022 The thesis was submitted on 17 April 1755 The public examination was held four weeks later on 13 May and the degree was formally awarded on 12 June Eric Watkins Kant Natural Science Cambridge University Press 2012 p 309 Eric Watkins ed Kant and the Sciences Oxford University Press 2001 p 27 Martin Schonfeld The Philosophy of the Young Kant The Precritical Project Oxford University Press 2000 p 74 Available online at Bonner Kant Korpus Archived 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine The thesis was publicly disputed on 27 September 1755 Kuehn 2001 p 100 Available online at Bonner Kant Korpus Archived 6 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine Kant s application for the position was unsuccessful He defended it on 10 April 1756 Kuehn 2001 p 102 Available online at Archive org Immanuel Kant Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space Archived 16 July 2018 at the Wayback Machine The thesis was publicly disputed on 21 August 1770 Kuehn 2001 p 189 Available online at Google Books Archived 3 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine English translation available online at Wikisource Immanuel Kant The Critique of Pure Reason Etext library adelaide edu au Archived from the original on 2 December 2008 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Kritik der reinen Vernunft 1 Auflage Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE Archived from the original on 9 June 2007 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Frank Christian Lilienweihs 10 June 1999 Immanuel Kant Beantwortung der Frage Was ist Aufklaerung Prometheusonline de Archived from the original on 1 August 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Critique of Pure Reason Hkbu edu hk 31 October 2003 Archived from the original on 27 April 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Kritik der reinen Vernunft 2 Auflage Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE 20 July 2009 Archived from the original on 26 December 2005 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Kritik der praktischen Vernunft Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE Archived from the original on 9 June 2007 Retrieved 24 July 2009 s The Critique of Judgment Immanuel Kant Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone by Immanuel Kant 1793 Marxists org Archived from the original on 1 June 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Perpetual Peace Mtholyoke edu Archived from the original on 6 April 2019 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Zum ewigen Frieden 12 02 2004 Friedensratschlag Uni kassel de Archived from the original on 23 September 2009 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Kant The Contest of Faculties Chnm gmu edu 1798 Archived from the original on 4 August 2011 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Der Streit der Facultaten Kapitel 1 in German Projekt Gutenberg DE Archived from the original on 9 June 2007 Retrieved 24 July 2009 Available online at DeutschesTextArchiv de Archived 10 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine As noted by Allen W Wood in his Introduction p 12 Wood further speculates that the lectures themselves were delivered in the Winter of 1783 84 Immanuel Kant Notes and Fragments Cambridge University Press 2005 p xvi Works cited Edit Kant Immanuel Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals Trans Lewis White Beck Indianapolis Bobbs Merrill 1969 Page numbers citing this work are Beck s marginal numbers that refer to the page numbers of the standard edition of Koniglich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin 1902 38 Kuehn Manfred Kant a Biography Cambridge University Press 2001 ISBN 978 0 521 49704 6 Further reading EditIn Germany one important contemporary interpreter of Kant and the movement of German Idealism he began is Dieter Henrich who has work available in English P F Strawson s The Bounds of Sense 1966 played a significant role in determining the contemporary reception of Kant in England and America More recent interpreters in the English speaking world include Lewis White Beck Jonathan Bennett Henry Allison Paul Guyer Christine Korsgaard Stephen Palmquist Robert B Pippin Roger Scruton Rudolf Makkreel and Beatrice Longuenesse General introductions to his thought Adamson Robert 1911 Kant Immanuel Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 15 11th ed pp 662 672 Broad C D Kant An Introduction Cambridge University Press 1978 ISBN 978 0 521 21755 2 0 521 29265 4 Gardner Sebastian Kant and the Critique of Pure Reason Routledge 1999 ISBN 978 0 415 11909 2 Martin Gottfried Kant s Metaphysics and Theory of Science Greenwood Press 1955 ISBN 978 0 8371 7154 8 elucidates Kant s most fundamental concepts in their historical context Seung T K 2007 Kant a Guide for the Perplexed London Continuum ISBN 978 0 8264 8580 9 Satyananda Giri Kant Durham CT Strategic Publishing Group 2010 ISBN 978 1 60911 686 6 Scruton Roger Kant a Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press 2001 ISBN 978 0 19 280199 9 provides a brief account of his life and a lucid introduction to the three major critiques Uleman Jennifer An Introduction to Kant s Moral Philosophy Cambridge University Press 2010 ISBN 978 0 521 13644 0 Luchte James Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Bloomsbury Publishing 2007 ISBN 978 0 8264 9322 4 Deleuze Gilles Kant s Critical Philosophy The Doctrine of the Faculties The Athlone Press 1983 ISBN 978 0 485 11249 8Biography and historical context Bader Ralph 2008 Kant Immanuel 1724 1804 In Hamowy Ronald ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA Sage Cato Institute pp 269 271 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 n161 ISBN 978 1 4129 6580 4 LCCN 2008009151 OCLC 750831024 Beck Lewis White Early German Philosophy Kant and his Predecessors Harvard University Press 1969 a survey of Kant s intellectual background Beiser Frederick C The Fate of Reason German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte Harvard University Press 1987 Chamberlain Houston Stewart Immanuel Kant a study and a comparison with Goethe Leonardo da Vinci Bruno Plato and Descartes the authorised translation from the German by Lord Redesdale with his Introduction The Bodley Head London 1914 2 volumes Johnson G R ed Kant on Swedenborg Dreams of a Spirit Seer and Other Writings Swedenborg Foundation 2002 new translation and analysis many supplementary texts Lehner Ulrich L Kants Vorsehungskonzept auf dem Hintergrund der deutschen Schulphilosophie und theologie Archived 23 September 2006 at the Wayback Machine Leiden 2007 Kant s concept of Providence and its background in German school philosophy and theology Pinkard Terry German Philosophy 1760 1860 the Legacy of Idealism Cambridge 2002 Schabert Joseph A Kant s Influence on his Successors The American Catholic Quarterly Review Vol XLVII January 1922 Collections of essays Firestone Chris L and Palmquist Stephen eds Kant and the New Philosophy of Religion Notre Dame Indiana University Press 2006 ISBN 978 0 253 21800 1 Forster Eckart ed Kant s Transcendental Deductions The Three Critiques and the Opus Postumum Stanford Stanford University Press 1989 Includes an essay by Dieter Henrich Mohanty J N and Shahan Robert W eds Essays on Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Norman University of Oklahoma Press 1982 ISBN 978 0 8061 1782 9 Phillips Dewi et al eds Kant and Kierkegaard on Religion New York Palgrave Macmillan 2000 ISBN 978 0 312 23234 4 Collection of essays about Kantian religion and its influence on Kierkegaardian and contemporary philosophy of religion Proceedings of the International Kant Congresses Several Congresses numbered edited by various publishers Theoretical philosophy Ameriks Karl Kant s Theory of Mind An Analysis of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason Oxford Clarendon Press 1982 one of the first detailed studies of the Dialectic in English Banham Gary Kant s Transcendental Imagination London and New York Palgrave Macmillan 2006 Gram Moltke S The Transcendental Turn The Foundation of Kant s Idealism Gainesville University Presses of Florida 1984 ISBN 978 0 8130 0787 8 Greenberg Robert Kant s Theory of A Priori Knowledge Penn State Press 2001 ISBN 978 0 271 02083 9 Guyer Paul Kant and the Claims of Knowledge Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1987 modern defense of the view that Kant s theoretical philosophy is a patchwork of ill fitting arguments Heidegger Martin Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics Trans Richard Taft Bloomington Indiana University Press 1997 ISBN 978 0 253 21067 8 Henrich Dieter The Unity of Reason Essays on Kant s Philosophy Ed with introduction by Richard L Velkley trans Jeffrey Edwards et al Harvard University Press 1994 ISBN 978 0 674 92905 0 Kemp Smith Norman A Commentary to Kant s Critique of Pure Reason London Macmillan 1930 influential commentary on the first Critique recently reprinted Kitcher Patricia Kant s Transcendental Psychology New York Oxford University Press 1990 Longuenesse Beatrice Kant and the Capacity to Judge Princeton University Press 1998 ISBN 978 0 691 04348 7 argues that the notion of judgment provides the key to understanding the overall argument of the first Critique Melnick Arthur Kant s Analogies of Experience Chicago University of Chicago Press 1973 important study of Kant s Analogies including his defense of the principle of causality Paton H J Kant s Metaphysic of Experience a Commentary on the First Half of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft Two volumes London Macmillan 1936 extensive study of Kant s theoretical philosophy Pippin Robert B Kant s Theory of Form An Essay on the Critique of Pure Reason New Haven Yale University Press 1982 influential examination of the formal character of Kant s work Schopenhauer Arthur Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung Erster Band Anhang Kritik der Kantischen Philosophie F A Brockhaus Leipzig 1859 In English Arthur Schopenhauer New York Dover Press Volume I Appendix Critique of the Kantian Philosophy ISBN 978 0 486 21761 1 Schott Robin May 1997 Feminist interpretations of Immanuel Kant University Park Pennsylvania Pennsylvania State University Press ISBN 978 0 271 01676 4 Seung T K Kant s Transcendental Logic New Haven Yale University Press 1969 Tonelli Giorgio Kant s Critique of Pure Reason within the Tradition of Modern Logic A Commentary on its History Hildesheim Olms 1994 Werkmeister W H Kant The Architectonic and Development of His Philosophy Open Court Publishing Co La Salle Ill 1980 ISBN 978 0 87548 345 0 it treats as a whole the architectonic and development of Kant s philosophy from 1755 through the Opus postumum Wolff Robert Paul Kant s Theory of Mental Activity A Commentary on the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1963 detailed and influential commentary on the first part of the Critique of Pure Reason Yovel Yirmiyahu Kant and the Philosophy of History Princeton Princeton University Press 1980 review Archived 4 January 2017 at the Wayback Machine Practical philosophy Allison Henry Kant s Theory of Freedom Cambridge University Press 1990 Banham Gary Kant s Practical Philosophy From Critique to Doctrine Palgrave Macmillan 2003 Dorschel Andreas Die idealistische Kritik des Willens Versuch uber die Theorie der praktischen Subjektivitat bei Kant und Hegel Hamburg Felix Meiner 1992 Schriften zur Transzendentalphilosophie 10 ISBN 978 3 7873 1046 3 Friedman Michael June 1998 Kantian themes in contemporary philosophy Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes 72 1 111 130 doi 10 1111 1467 8349 00038 JSTOR 4107015 Korsgaard Christine M The Sources of Normativity Cambridge University Press 1996 Michalson Gordon E Fallen Freedom Kant on Radical Evil and Moral Regeneration Cambridge University Press 1990 Michalson Gordon E Kant and the Problem of God Blackwell Publishers 1999 Paton H J The Categorical Imperative A Study in Kant s Moral Philosophy University of Pennsylvania Press 1971 Seung T K Kant s Platonic Revolution in Moral and Political Philosophy Johns Hopkins 1994 Wolff Robert Paul The Autonomy of Reason A Commentary on Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals New York HarperCollins 1974 ISBN 978 0 06 131792 7 Aesthetics Allison Henry Kant s Theory of Taste A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press 2001 Banham Gary Kant and the Ends of Aesthetics London and New York Macmillan Press 2000 Crawford Donald Kant s Aesthetic Theory Wisconsin 1974 Doran Robert The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press 2015 Guyer Paul Kant and the Claims of Taste Cambridge Massachusetts and London 1979 Hammermeister Kai The German Aesthetic Tradition Cambridge University Press 2002 Immanuel Kant entry in Kelly Michael Editor in Chief 1998 Encyclopedia of Aesthetics New York Oxford Oxford University Press Kaplama Erman Cosmological Aesthetics through the Kantian Sublime and Nietzschean Dionysian Lanham UPA Rowman amp Littlefield 2014 McCloskey Mary Kant s Aesthetic SUNY 1987 Schaper Eva Studies in Kant s Aesthetics Edinburgh 1979 Zammito John H The Genesis of Kant s Critique of Judgment Chicago and London Chicago University Press 1992 Zupancic Alenka Ethics of the Real Kant and Lacan Verso 2000 Philosophy of religion Palmquist Stephen Kant s Critical Religion Archived 14 April 2012 at the Wayback Machine Volume Two of Kant s System of Perspectives Ashgate 2000 ISBN 978 0 7546 1333 6 Perez Daniel Omar Religion Politica y Medicina en Kant El Conflicto de las Proposiciones Cinta de Moebio Revista de Epistemologia de Ciencias Sociales v 28 p 91 103 2007 Uchile cl Archived 20 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine Spanish Perpetual peace and international relations Sir Harry Hinsley Power and the Pursuit of Peace Cambridge University Press 1962 Martin Wight Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory Machiavelli Grotius Kant and Mazzini Archived 29 November 2014 at the Wayback Machine ed Gabriele Wight amp Brian Porter Oxford Oxford University Press 2005 Bennington Geoffrey December 2011 Kant s open secret PDF Theory Culture amp Society 28 7 8 26 40 doi 10 1177 0263276411423036 S2CID 143513241 Archived PDF from the original on 8 February 2020 Retrieved 31 May 2020 Other works Botul Jean Baptiste La vie sexuelle d Emmanuel Kant Paris Ed Mille et une Nuits 2008 ISBN 978 2 84205 424 3 Caygill Howard A Kant Dictionary Oxford Cambridge Mass Blackwell Reference 1995 ISBN 978 0 631 17534 6 Derrida Jacques Mochlos or The Conflict of the Faculties Columbia University 1980 Mosser Kurt Necessity and Possibility The Logical Strategy of Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Catholic University of America Press 2008 ISBN 978 0 8132 1532 7 White Mark D Kantian Ethics and Economics Autonomy Dignity and Character Archived 16 November 2011 at the Wayback Machine Stanford University Press 2011 ISBN 978 0 8047 6894 8 Contemporary philosophy with a Kantian influence Assiter Alison July 2013 Kant and Kierkegaard on freedom and evil Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 72 275 296 Bibcode 1995kppp book O doi 10 1017 S1358246113000155 S2CID 170661991 Bird Graham June 1998 Kantian themes in contemporary philosophy Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes 72 1 131 152 doi 10 1111 1467 8349 00039 JSTOR 4107015 Guyer Paul Knowledge Reason and Taste Kant s Response to Hume Princeton University Press 2008 Hanna Robert Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy Clarendon Press 2004 Herman Barbara The Practice of Moral Judgement Harvard University Press 1993 Hill Judith M June 1987 Pornography and degradation Hypatia A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 2 2 39 54 doi 10 1111 j 1527 2001 1987 tb01064 x JSTOR 3810015 S2CID 145504474 A Kantian approach to the issue of pornography and degradation McDowell John Mind and World Harvard University Press 1994 ISBN 978 0 674 57609 4 offers a Kantian solution to a dilemma in contemporary epistemology regarding the relation between mind and world O Neill Onora June 1998 Kant on duties regarding nonrational nature Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes 72 1 211 228 doi 10 1111 1467 8349 00043 JSTOR 4107017 Parfit Derek On What Matters 2 vols New York Oxford University Press 2011 ISBN 978 0 19 926592 3 Pinker Steven The Stuff of Thought Viking Press 2007 ISBN 978 0 670 06327 7 Chapter 4 Cleaving the Air discusses Kant s anticipation of modern cognitive science Wood Allen W Kant s Ethical Thought Cambridge New York Cambridge University Press 1999 ISBN 978 0 521 64836 3 comprehensive in depth study of Kant s ethics with emphasis on formula of humanity as most accurate formulation of the categorical imperative Wood Allen W June 1998 Kant on duties regarding nonrational nature Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes 72 1 189 210 doi 10 1111 1467 8349 00042 JSTOR 4107017 External links EditImmanuel Kant at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Media from Commons Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Data from Wikidata Works by Immanuel Kant at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Immanuel Kant at Internet Archive Works by Immanuel Kant at LibriVox public domain audiobooks KantPapers authors and papers database powered by PhilPapers focused on Kant and located at Cornell University Immanuel Kant at the Encyclopaedia Britannica Immanuel Kant in the Christian Cyclopedia Works by Immanuel Kant at Duisburg Essen University Stephen Palmquist s Glossary of Kantian Terminology Kant s Ethical Theory Kantian ethics explained applied and evaluated Notes on Utilitarianism A conveniently brief survey of Kant s Utilitarianism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant An Overview Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Aesthetics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Logic Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Metaphysics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Philosophy of Mind Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Philosophy of Religion Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Radical Evil Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Transcendental Idealism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Immanuel Kant Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Immanuel Kant amp oldid 1138624348, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.