fbpx
Wikipedia

Classical liberalism

Classical liberalism is a political tradition and a branch of liberalism that advocates free market and laissez-faire economics and civil liberties under the rule of law, with special emphasis on individual autonomy, limited government, economic freedom, political freedom and freedom of speech.[1] Classical liberalism, contrary to liberal branches like social liberalism, looks more negatively on social policies, taxation and the state involvement in the lives of individuals, and it advocates deregulation.[2]

Until the Great Depression and the rise of social liberalism, classical liberalism was called economic liberalism. Later, the term was applied as a retronym, to distinguish earlier 19th-century liberalism from social liberalism.[3] By modern standards, in the United States, simple liberalism often means social liberalism, but in Europe and Australia, simple liberalism often means classical liberalism.[4][5]

Classical liberalism gained full flowering in the early 18th century, building on ideas starting at least as far back as the 16th century, within the Iberian, Anglo-Saxon, and central European contexts, and it was foundational to the American Revolution and "American Project" more broadly.[6][7][8] Notable liberal individuals whose ideas contributed to classical liberalism include John Locke,[9] Jean-Baptiste Say, Thomas Malthus, and David Ricardo. It drew on classical economics, especially the economic ideas as espoused by Adam Smith in Book One of The Wealth of Nations, and on a belief in natural law,[10] social progress,[11] and utilitarianism.[12] In contemporary times, Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, Ludwig von Mises, Thomas Sowell, George Stigler and Larry Arnhart are seen as the most prominent advocates of classical liberalism.[13][14] However, other scholars have made reference to these contemporary thoughts as neoclassical liberalism, distinguishing them from 18th-century classical liberalism.[15][16]

In the context of American politics, "classical liberalism" may be described as "fiscally conservative" and "socially liberal".[17] Despite this, classical liberals tend to reject the right's higher tolerance for economic protectionism and the left's inclination for collective group rights due to classical liberalism's central principle of individualism.[18] Additionally, in the United States, classical liberalism is considered closely tied to, or synonymous with, American libertarianism.[19][20]

Evolution of core beliefs edit

Core beliefs of classical liberals included new ideas – which departed from both the older conservative idea of society as a family and from the later sociological concept of society as a complex set of social networks.

Classical liberals agreed with Thomas Hobbes that individuals created government to protect themselves from each other and to minimize conflict between individuals that would otherwise arise in a state of nature. These beliefs were complemented by a belief that financial incentive could be best motivate labourers. This belief led to the passage of the Poor Law Amendment Act 1834, which limited the provision of social assistance, based on the idea that markets are the mechanism that most efficiently leads to wealth.

Drawing on ideas of Adam Smith, classical liberals believed that it is in the common interest that all individuals be able to secure their own economic self-interest.[21] They were critical of what would come to be the idea of the welfare state as interfering in a free market.[22] Despite Smith's resolute recognition of the importance and value of labour and of labourers, classical liberals criticized labour's group rights being pursued at the expense of individual rights[23] while accepting corporations' rights, which led to inequality of bargaining power.[21][24] Classical liberals argued that individuals should be free to obtain work from the highest-paying employers, while the profit motive would ensure that products that people desired were produced at prices they would pay. In a free market, both labour and capital would receive the greatest possible reward, while production would be organized efficiently to meet consumer demand.[25] Classical liberals argued for what they called a minimal state and government, limited to the following functions:

  • Laws to protect citizens from wrongs committed against them by other citizens, which included protection of individual rights, private property, enforcement of contracts and common law.
  • A common national defence to provide protection against foreign invaders.[26]
  • Public works and services that cannot be provided in a free market such as a stable currency, standard weights and measures and building and upkeep of roads, canals, harbours, railways, communications and postal services.[26]

Classical liberals asserted that rights are of a negative nature and therefore stipulate that other individuals and governments are to refrain from interfering with the free market, opposing social liberals who assert that individuals have positive rights, such as the right to vote, the right to an education, the right to health care,[dubious ] and the right to a minimum wage. For society to guarantee positive rights, it requires taxation over and above the minimum needed to enforce negative rights.[27][28]

Core beliefs of classical liberals did not necessarily include democracy nor government by a majority vote by citizens because "there is nothing in the bare idea of majority rule to show that majorities will always respect the rights of property or maintain rule of law".[29][30] For example, James Madison argued for a constitutional republic with protections for individual liberty over a pure democracy, reasoning that in a pure democracy a "common passion or interest will, in almost every case, be felt by a majority of the whole ... and there is nothing to check the inducements to sacrifice the weaker party".[31]

In the late 19th century, classical liberalism developed into neoclassical liberalism, which argued for government to be as small as possible to allow the exercise of individual freedom. In its most extreme form, neoclassical liberalism advocated social Darwinism.[32] Right-libertarianism is a modern form of neoclassical liberalism.[32] However, Edwin Van de Haar states although classical liberal thought influenced libertarianism, there are significant differences between them.[33] Classical liberalism refuses to give priority to liberty over order and therefore does not exhibit the hostility to the state which is the defining feature of libertarianism.[34] As such, right-libertarians believe classical liberals do not have enough respect for individual property rights and lack sufficient trust in the free market's workings and spontaneous order leading to their support of a much larger state.[35] Right-libertarians also disagree with classical liberals as being too supportive of central banks and monetarist policies.[36]

Typology of beliefs edit

Friedrich Hayek identified two different traditions within classical liberalism, namely the British tradition and the French tradition:

Hayek conceded that the national labels did not exactly correspond to those belonging to each tradition since he saw the Frenchmen Montesquieu, Benjamin Constant, Joseph De Maistre and Alexis de Tocqueville as belonging to the British tradition and the British Thomas Hobbes, Joseph Priestley, Richard Price, Edward Gibbon, Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Jefferson and Thomas Paine as belonging to the French tradition.[37][38] Hayek also rejected the label laissez-faire as originating from the French tradition and alien to the beliefs of Hume and Smith.

Guido De Ruggiero also identified differences between "Montesquieu and Rousseau, the English and the democratic types of liberalism"[39] and argued that there was a "profound contrast between the two Liberal systems".[40] He claimed that the spirit of "authentic English Liberalism" had "built up its work piece by piece without ever destroying what had once been built, but basing upon it every new departure". This liberalism had "insensibly adapted ancient institutions to modern needs" and "instinctively recoiled from all abstract proclamations of principles and rights".[40] Ruggiero claimed that this liberalism was challenged by what he called the "new Liberalism of France" that was characterised by egalitarianism and a "rationalistic consciousness".[41]

In 1848, Francis Lieber distinguished between what he called "Anglican and Gallican Liberty". Lieber asserted that "independence in the highest degree, compatible with safety and broad national guarantees of liberty, is the great aim of Anglican liberty, and self-reliance is the chief source from which it draws its strength".[42] On the other hand, Gallican liberty "is sought in government ... . [T]he French look for the highest degree of political civilisation in organisation, that is, in the highest degree of interference by public power".[43]

History edit

Great Britain edit

French physiocracy heavily influenced British classical liberalism, which traces its roots to the Whigs and Radicals. Whiggery had become a dominant ideology following the Glorious Revolution of 1688 and was associated with supporting the British Parliament, upholding the rule of law, defending landed property and sometimes included freedom of the press and freedom of speech. The origins of rights were seen as being in an ancient constitution existing from time immemorial. Custom rather than as natural rights justified these rights. Whigs believed that executive power had to be constrained. While they supported limited suffrage, they saw voting as a privilege rather than as a right. However, there was no consistency in Whig ideology and diverse writers including John Locke, David Hume, Adam Smith and Edmund Burke were all influential among Whigs, although none of them were universally accepted.[44]

From the 1790s to the 1820s, British radicals concentrated on parliamentary and electoral reform, emphasising natural rights and popular sovereignty. Richard Price and Joseph Priestley adapted the language of Locke to the ideology of radicalism.[44] The radicals saw parliamentary reform as a first step toward dealing with their many grievances, including the treatment of Protestant Dissenters, the slave trade, high prices, and high taxes.[45] There was greater unity among classical liberals than there had been among Whigs. Classical liberals were committed to individualism, liberty, and equal rights, as well as some other important tenants of leftism, since classical liberalism was introduced in the late 18th century as a leftist movement.[17] They believed these goals required a free economy with minimal government interference. Some elements of Whiggery were uncomfortable with the commercial nature of classical liberalism. These elements became associated with conservatism.[46]

 
A meeting of the Anti-Corn Law League in Exeter Hall in 1846

Classical liberalism was the dominant political theory in Britain from the early 19th century until the First World War. Its notable victories were the Roman Catholic Relief Act 1829, the Reform Act of 1832 and the repeal of the Corn Laws in 1846. The Anti-Corn Law League brought together a coalition of liberal and radical groups in support of free trade under the leadership of Richard Cobden and John Bright, who opposed aristocratic privilege, militarism, and public expenditure and believed that the backbone of Great Britain was the yeoman farmer. Their policies of low public expenditure and low taxation were adopted by William Gladstone when he became Chancellor of the Exchequer and later Prime Minister. Classical liberalism was often associated with religious dissent and nonconformism.[47]

Although classical liberals aspired to a minimum of state activity, they accepted the principle of government intervention in the economy from the early 19th century on, with passage of the Factory Acts. From around 1840 to 1860, laissez-faire advocates of the Manchester School and writers in The Economist were confident that their early victories would lead to a period of expanding economic and personal liberty and world peace, but would face reversals as government intervention and activity continued to expand from the 1850s. Jeremy Bentham and James Mill, although advocates of laissez-faire, non-intervention in foreign affairs, and individual liberty, believed that social institutions could be rationally redesigned through the principles of utilitarianism. The Conservative Prime Minister Benjamin Disraeli rejected classical liberalism altogether and advocated Tory democracy. By the 1870s, Herbert Spencer and other classical liberals concluded that historical development was turning against them.[48] By the First World War, the Liberal Party had largely abandoned classical liberal principles.[49]

The changing economic and social conditions of the 19th century led to a division between neo-classical and social (or welfare) liberals, who while agreeing on the importance of individual liberty differed on the role of the state. Neo-classical liberals, who called themselves "true liberals", saw Locke's Second Treatise as the best guide and emphasised "limited government" while social liberals supported government regulation and the welfare state. Herbert Spencer in Britain and William Graham Sumner were the leading neo-classical liberal theorists of the 19th century.[50] The evolution from classical to social/welfare liberalism is for example reflected in Britain in the evolution of the thought of John Maynard Keynes.[51]

Ottoman Empire edit

The Ottoman Empire had liberal free trade policies by the 18th century, with origins in capitulations of the Ottoman Empire, dating back to the first commercial treaties signed with France in 1536 and taken further with capitulations in 1673, in 1740 which lowered duties to only 3% for imports and exports and in 1790. Ottoman free trade policies were praised by British economists advocating free trade such as J. R. McCulloch in his Dictionary of Commerce (1834) but criticized by British politicians opposing free trade such as Prime Minister Benjamin Disraeli, who cited the Ottoman Empire as "an instance of the injury done by unrestrained competition" in the 1846 Corn Laws debate, arguing that it destroyed what had been "some of the finest manufactures of the world" in 1812.[52]

United States edit

In the United States, liberalism took a strong root because it had little opposition to its ideals, whereas in Europe liberalism was opposed by many reactionary or feudal interests such as the nobility; the aristocracy, including army officers; the landed gentry; and the established church.[53] Thomas Jefferson adopted many of the ideals of liberalism, but in the Declaration of Independence changed Locke's "life, liberty and property" to the more socially liberal "Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness".[9] As the United States grew, industry became a larger and larger part of American life; and during the term of its first populist President, Andrew Jackson, economic questions came to the forefront. The economic ideas of the Jacksonian era were almost universally the ideas of classical liberalism.[54] Freedom, according to classical liberals, was maximised when the government took a "hands off" attitude toward the economy.[55] Historian Kathleen G. Donohue argues:

[A]t the center of classical liberal theory [in Europe] was the idea of laissez-faire. To the vast majority of American classical liberals, however, laissez-faire did not mean no government intervention at all. On the contrary, they were more than willing to see government provide tariffs, railroad subsidies, and internal improvements, all of which benefited producers. What they condemned was intervention on behalf of consumers.[56]

The Nation magazine espoused liberalism every week starting in 1865 under the influential editor Edwin Lawrence Godkin (1831–1902).[57] The ideas of classical liberalism remained essentially unchallenged until a series of depressions, thought to be impossible according to the tenets of classical economics, led to economic hardship from which the voters demanded relief. In the words of William Jennings Bryan, "You shall not crucify this nation on a cross of gold". Classical liberalism remained the orthodox belief among American businessmen until the Great Depression.[58] The Great Depression in the United States saw a sea change in liberalism, with priority shifting from the producers to consumers. Franklin D. Roosevelt's New Deal represented the dominance of modern liberalism in politics for decades. In the words of Arthur Schlesinger Jr.:[59]

When the growing complexity of industrial conditions required increasing government intervention in order to assure more equal opportunities, the liberal tradition, faithful to the goal rather than to the dogma, altered its view of the state. ... There emerged the conception of a social welfare state, in which the national government had the express obligation to maintain high levels of employment in the economy, to supervise standards of life and labour, to regulate the methods of business competition, and to establish comprehensive patterns of social security.

Alan Wolfe summarizes the viewpoint that there is a continuous liberal understanding that includes both Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes:

The idea that liberalism comes in two forms assumes that the most fundamental question facing mankind is how much government intervenes into the economy. ... When instead we discuss human purpose and the meaning of life, Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes are on the same side. Both of them possessed an expansive sense of what we are put on this earth to accomplish. ... For Smith, mercantilism was the enemy of human liberty. For Keynes, monopolies were. It makes perfect sense for an eighteenth-century thinker to conclude that humanity would flourish under the market. For a twentieth century thinker committed to the same ideal, government was an essential tool to the same end.[60]

The view that modern liberalism is a continuation of classical liberalism is controversial and disputed by many.[61][62][63][64][65] James Kurth, Robert E. Lerner, John Micklethwait, Adrian Wooldridge and several other political scholars have argued that classical liberalism still exists today, but in the form of American conservatism.[66][67][68][69] According to Deepak Lal, only in the United States does classical liberalism continue to be a significant political force through American conservatism.[70] American libertarians also claim to be the true continuation of the classical liberal tradition.[71]

Intellectual sources edit

John Locke edit

 
John Locke

Central to classical liberal ideology was their interpretation of John Locke's Second Treatise of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration, which had been written as a defence of the Glorious Revolution of 1688. Although these writings were considered too radical at the time for Britain's new rulers, Whigs, radicals and supporters of the American Revolution later came to cite them.[72] However, much of later liberal thought was absent in Locke's writings or scarcely mentioned and his writings have been subject to various interpretations. For example, there is little mention of constitutionalism, the separation of powers and limited government.[73]

James L. Richardson identified five central themes in Locke's writing:

Although Locke did not develop a theory of natural rights, he envisioned individuals in the state of nature as being free and equal. The individual, rather than the community or institutions, was the point of reference. Locke believed that individuals had given consent to government and therefore authority derived from the people rather than from above. This belief would influence later revolutionary movements.[74]

As a trustee, government was expected to serve the interests of the people, not the rulers; and rulers were expected to follow the laws enacted by legislatures. Locke also held that the main purpose of men uniting into commonwealths and governments was for the preservation of their property. Despite the ambiguity of Locke's definition of property, which limited property to "as much land as a man tills, plants, improves, cultivates, and can use the product of", this principle held great appeal to individuals possessed of great wealth.[75]

Locke held that the individual had the right to follow his own religious beliefs and that the state should not impose a religion against Dissenters, but there were limitations. No tolerance should be shown for atheists, who were seen as amoral, or to Catholics, who were seen as owing allegiance to the Pope over their own national government.[76]

Adam Smith edit

 
Adam Smith

Adam Smith's The Wealth of Nations, published in 1776, was to provide most of the ideas of economics, at least until the publication of John Stuart Mill's Principles of Political Economy in 1848.[77] Smith addressed the motivation for economic activity, the causes of prices and the distribution of wealth and the policies the state should follow to maximise wealth.[78]

Smith wrote that as long as supply, demand, prices and competition were left free of government regulation, the pursuit of material self-interest, rather than altruism, would maximise the wealth of a society[24] through profit-driven production of goods and services. An "invisible hand" directed individuals and firms to work toward the public good as an unintended consequence of efforts to maximise their own gain. This provided a moral justification for the accumulation of wealth, which had previously been viewed by some as sinful.[78]

He assumed that workers could be paid wages as low as was necessary for their survival, which was later transformed by David Ricardo and Thomas Robert Malthus into the "iron law of wages".[79] His main emphasis was on the benefit of free internal and international trade, which he thought could increase wealth through specialisation in production.[80] He also opposed restrictive trade preferences, state grants of monopolies and employers' organisations and trade unions.[81] Government should be limited to defence, public works and the administration of justice, financed by taxes based on income.[82]

Smith's economics was carried into practice in the nineteenth century with the lowering of tariffs in the 1820s, the repeal of the Poor Relief Act that had restricted the mobility of labour in 1834 and the end of the rule of the East India Company over India in 1858.[83]

Classical economics edit

In addition to Smith's legacy, Say's law, Thomas Robert Malthus' theories of population and David Ricardo's iron law of wages became central doctrines of classical economics. The pessimistic nature of these theories provided a basis for criticism of capitalism by its opponents and helped perpetuate the tradition of calling economics the "dismal science".[84]

Jean-Baptiste Say was a French economist who introduced Smith's economic theories into France and whose commentaries on Smith were read in both France and Britain.[83] Say challenged Smith's labour theory of value, believing that prices were determined by utility and also emphasised the critical role of the entrepreneur in the economy. However, neither of those observations became accepted by British economists at the time. His most important contribution to economic thinking was Say's law, which was interpreted by classical economists that there could be no overproduction in a market and that there would always be a balance between supply and demand.[85][86] This general belief influenced government policies until the 1930s. Following this law, since the economic cycle was seen as self-correcting, government did not intervene during periods of economic hardship because it was seen as futile.[87]

Malthus wrote two books, An Essay on the Principle of Population (published in 1798) and Principles of Political Economy (published in 1820). The second book which was a rebuttal of Say's law had little influence on contemporary economists.[88] However, his first book became a major influence on classical liberalism.[89][90] In that book, Malthus claimed that population growth would outstrip food production because population grew geometrically while food production grew arithmetically. As people were provided with food, they would reproduce until their growth outstripped the food supply. Nature would then provide a check to growth in the forms of vice and misery. No gains in income could prevent this and any welfare for the poor would be self-defeating. The poor were in fact responsible for their own problems which could have been avoided through self-restraint.[90]

Ricardo, who was an admirer of Smith, covered many of the same topics, but while Smith drew conclusions from broadly empirical observations he used deduction, drawing conclusions by reasoning from basic assumptions [91] While Ricardo accepted Smith's labour theory of value, he acknowledged that utility could influence the price of some rare items. Rents on agricultural land were seen as the production that was surplus to the subsistence required by the tenants. Wages were seen as the amount required for workers' subsistence and to maintain current population levels.[92] According to his iron law of wages, wages could never rise beyond subsistence levels. Ricardo explained profits as a return on capital, which itself was the product of labour, but a conclusion many drew from his theory was that profit was a surplus appropriated by capitalists to which they were not entitled.[93]

Utilitarianism edit

The central concept of utilitarianism, which was developed by Jeremy Bentham, was that public policy should seek to provide "the greatest happiness of the greatest number". While this could be interpreted as a justification for state action to reduce poverty, it was used by classical liberals to justify inaction with the argument that the net benefit to all individuals would be higher.[84]

Utilitarianism provided British governments with the political justification to implement economic liberalism, which was to dominate economic policy from the 1830s. Although utilitarianism prompted legislative and administrative reform and John Stuart Mill's later writings on the subject foreshadowed the welfare state, it was mainly used as a justification for laissez-faire.[94]

Political economy edit

Classical liberals following Mill saw utility as the foundation for public policies. This broke both with conservative "tradition" and Lockean "natural rights", which were seen as irrational. Utility, which emphasises the happiness of individuals, became the central ethical value of all Mill-style liberalism.[95] Although utilitarianism inspired wide-ranging reforms, it became primarily a justification for laissez-faire economics. However, Mill adherents rejected Smith's belief that the "invisible hand" would lead to general benefits and embraced Malthus' view that population expansion would prevent any general benefit and Ricardo's view of the inevitability of class conflict. Laissez-faire was seen as the only possible economic approach and any government intervention was seen as useless and harmful. The Poor Law Amendment Act 1834 was defended on "scientific or economic principles" while the authors of the Poor Relief Act 1601 were seen as not having had the benefit of reading Malthus.[96]

However, commitment to laissez-faire was not uniform and some economists advocated state support of public works and education. Classical liberals were also divided on free trade as Ricardo expressed doubt that the removal of grain tariffs advocated by Richard Cobden and the Anti-Corn Law League would have any general benefits. Most classical liberals also supported legislation to regulate the number of hours that children were allowed to work and usually did not oppose factory reform legislation.[96]

Despite the pragmatism of classical economists, their views were expressed in dogmatic terms by such popular writers as Jane Marcet and Harriet Martineau.[96] The strongest defender of laissez-faire was The Economist founded by James Wilson in 1843. The Economist criticised Ricardo for his lack of support for free trade and expressed hostility to welfare, believing that the lower orders were responsible for their economic circumstances. The Economist took the position that regulation of factory hours was harmful to workers and also strongly opposed state support for education, health, the provision of water and granting of patents and copyrights.[97]

The Economist also campaigned against the Corn Laws that protected landlords in the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland against competition from less expensive foreign imports of cereal products. A rigid belief in laissez-faire guided the government response in 1846–1849 to the Great Famine in Ireland, during which an estimated 1.5 million people died. The minister responsible for economic and financial affairs, Charles Wood, expected that private enterprise and free trade, rather than government intervention, would alleviate the famine.[97] The Corn Laws were finally repealed in 1846 by the removal of tariffs on grain which kept the price of bread artificially high,[98] but it came too late to stop the Irish famine, partly because it was done in stages over three years.[99][100]

Free trade and world peace edit

Several liberals, including Smith and Cobden, argued that the free exchange of goods between nations could lead to world peace. Erik Gartzke states: "Scholars like Montesquieu, Adam Smith, Richard Cobden, Norman Angell, and Richard Rosecrance have long speculated that free markets have the potential to free states from the looming prospect of recurrent warfare".[101] American political scientists John R. Oneal and Bruce M. Russett, well known for their work on the democratic peace theory, state:[102]

The classical liberals advocated policies to increase liberty and prosperity. They sought to empower the commercial class politically and to abolish royal charters, monopolies, and the protectionist policies of mercantilism so as to encourage entrepreneurship and increase productive efficiency. They also expected democracy and laissez-faire economics to diminish the frequency of war.

In The Wealth of Nations, Smith argued that as societies progressed from hunter gatherers to industrial societies the spoils of war would rise, but that the costs of war would rise further and thus making war difficult and costly for industrialised nations:[103]

[T]he honours, the fame, the emoluments of war, belong not to [the middle and industrial classes]; the battle-plain is the harvest field of the aristocracy, watered with the blood of the people. ... Whilst our trade rested upon our foreign dependencies, as was the case in the middle of the last century...force and violence, were necessary to command our customers for our manufacturers...But war, although the greatest of consumers, not only produces nothing in return, but, by abstracting labour from productive employment and interrupting the course of trade, it impedes, in a variety of indirect ways, the creation of wealth; and, should hostilities be continued for a series of years, each successive war-loan will be felt in our commercial and manufacturing districts with an augmented pressure

[B]y virtue of their mutual interest does nature unite people against violence and war, for the concept of cosmopolitan right does not protect them from it. The spirit of trade cannot coexist with war, and sooner or later this spirit dominates every people. For among all those powers (or means) that belong to a nation, financial power may be the most reliable in forcing nations to pursue the noble cause of peace (though not from moral motives); and wherever in the world war threatens to break out, they will try to head it off through mediation, just as if they were permanently leagued for this purpose.

Cobden believed that military expenditures worsened the welfare of the state and benefited a small, but concentrated elite minority, summing up British imperialism, which he believed was the result of the economic restrictions of mercantilist policies. To Cobden and many classical liberals, those who advocated peace must also advocate free markets. The belief that free trade would promote peace was widely shared by English liberals of the 19th and early 20th century, leading the economist John Maynard Keynes (1883–1946), who was a classical liberal in his early life, to say that this was a doctrine on which he was "brought up" and which he held unquestioned only until the 1920s.[106] In his review of a book on Keynes, Michael S. Lawlor argues that it may be in large part due to Keynes' contributions in economics and politics, as in the implementation of the Marshall Plan and the way economies have been managed since his work, "that we have the luxury of not facing his unpalatable choice between free trade and full employment".[107] A related manifestation of this idea was the argument of Norman Angell (1872–1967), most famously before World War I in The Great Illusion (1909), that the interdependence of the economies of the major powers was now so great that war between them was futile and irrational; and therefore unlikely.

Notable thinkers edit

Classical liberal parties worldwide edit

Although general libertarian,[a] liberal-conservative[b] and some right-wing populist[c] political parties are also included in classical liberal parties in a broad sense, but only general classical liberal parties such as Germany's FDP, Denmark's Liberal Alliance and Thailand Democrat Party should be listed.

Classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions edit

Historical classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions (Since 1900s) edit

Criticism edit

Tadd Wilson, writing for the libertarian Foundation for Economic Education, noted that "Many on the left and right criticize classical liberals for focusing purely on economics and politics to the neglect of a vital issue: culture."[150]

Helena Vieira, writing for the London School of Economics, argued that classical liberalism "may contradict some fundamental democratic principles as they are inconsistent with the principle of unanimity (also known as the Pareto Principle) – the idea that if everyone in society prefers a policy A to a policy B, then the former should be adopted."[151]

See also edit

Notes edit

References edit

  1. ^ "Classical liberalism". www.britannica.com. Encyclopædia Britannica. 6 September 2023. Retrieved 17 October 2023.
  2. ^ M. O. Dickerson et al., An Introduction to Government and Politics: A Conceptual Approach (2009) p. 129
  3. ^ Richardson, p. 52.
  4. ^ Goldfarb, Michael (20 July 2010). "Liberal? Are we talking about the same thing?". BBC News. Retrieved 6 August 2020.
  5. ^ Greenberg, David (12 September 2019). "The danger of confusing liberals and leftists". Washington Post. Retrieved 6 August 2020.
  6. ^ Douma, Michael. (2018). What is Classical Liberal History?. Lexington Books. ISBN 978-1-4985-3610-3.
  7. ^ Dickerson, Flanagan & O'Neill, p. 129.
  8. ^ Renshaw, Catherine (18 March 2014). "What is a 'classical liberal' approach to human rights?". The Conversation. Retrieved 12 August 2022.
  9. ^ a b Steven M. Dworetz (1994). The Unvarnished Doctrine: Locke, Liberalism, and the American Revolution.
  10. ^ Appleby, Joyce (1992). Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination. Harvard University Press. p. 58. ISBN 978-0674530133.
  11. ^ Hunt, p. 54.
  12. ^ Gaus, Gerald F.; Kukathas, Chandran (2004). Handbook of Political Theory. Sage. p. 422. ISBN 978-0761967873.
  13. ^ Dilley, Stephen C. (2 May 2013). Darwinian Evolution and Classical Liberalism: Theories in Tension. Lexington Books. pp. 13–14. ISBN 978-0-7391-8107-2.
  14. ^ Peters, Michael A. (16 April 2022). "Hayek as classical liberal public intellectual: Neoliberalism, the privatization of public discourse and the future of democracy". Educational Philosophy and Theory. 54 (5): 443–449. doi:10.1080/00131857.2019.1696303. ISSN 0013-1857. S2CID 213420239.
  15. ^ Mayne, Alan James (1999). From Politics Past to Politics Future: An Integrated Analysis of Current and Emergent Paradigmss. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Publishing Group. pp. 124–125. ISBN 0275961516.
  16. ^ Ishiyama, John T.; Breuning, Marijke; et al. (Ellen Grigsby) (2011). "Neoclassical liberals". 21st Century Political Science A Reference Handbook. SAGE Publications, Inc. pp. 596–603. ISBN 978-1-4129 6901-7.
  17. ^ a b Wright, Edmund, ed. (2006). The Desk Encyclopedia of World History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 370. ISBN 978-0-7394-7809-7.
  18. ^ Goodman, John C. "Classical Liberalism vs. Modern Liberalism and Modern Conservatism". Goodman Institute. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  19. ^ "Libertarianism vs. Classical Liberalism: Is there a Difference?". Reason.com. 6 April 2023. Retrieved 22 September 2023.
  20. ^ Klein, Daniel B. (3 May 2017). "Libertarianism and Classical Liberalism: A Short Introduction | Daniel B. Klein". fee.org. Retrieved 8 March 2022.
  21. ^ a b Dickerson, Flanagan & O'Neill, p. 132.
  22. ^ Alan Ryan, "Liberalism", in A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, ed. Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1995), p. 293.
  23. ^ Evans, M. ed. (2001): Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism: Evidence and Experience, London: Routledge, 55 (ISBN 1579583393).
  24. ^ a b Smith, A. (1778). "8". An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Vol. I. W. Strahan; and T. Cadell.
  25. ^ Hunt, pp. 46–47.
  26. ^ a b Hunt, pp. 51–53.
  27. ^ Kelly, D. (1998): A Life of One's Own: Individual Rights and the Welfare State, Washington, DC: Cato Institute.
  28. ^ Richardson, pp. 36–38.
  29. ^ Ellerman, David (2015). "Does classical liberalism imply democracy?". Ethics & Global Politics. 8 (1): 29310. doi:10.3402/egp.v8.29310.
  30. ^ Ryan, A. (1995): "Liberalism", In: Goodin, R. E. and Pettit, P., eds.: A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, p. 293.
  31. ^ James Madison, Federalist No. 10 (22 November 1787), in Alexander Hamilton, John Jay and James Madison, The Federalist: A Commentary on the Constitution of the United States, ed. Henry Cabot Lodge (New York, 1888), p. 56.
  32. ^ a b Mayne 1999, p. 124.
  33. ^ Van de Haar 2015, p. 71.
  34. ^ Heywood 2004, p. 337.
  35. ^ Van de Haar 2015, p. 42.
  36. ^ Van de Haar 2015, p. 43.
  37. ^ Hayek, F. A. (1976). The Constitution of Liberty. London: Routledge. pp. 55–56. ISBN 978-1317857808.
  38. ^ F. A. Hayek, "Individualism: True and False", in Individualism and Economic Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), pp. 1–32.
  39. ^ De Ruggiero, p. 71.
  40. ^ a b De Ruggiero, p. 81.
  41. ^ De Ruggiero, pp. 81–82.
  42. ^ Lieber, p. 377.
  43. ^ Lieber, pp. 382–383.
  44. ^ a b Vincent, pp. 28–29.
  45. ^ Turner, Michael J. (1999). British Politics in an Age of Reform. Manchester: Manchester University Press. p. 86. ISBN 978-0719051869.
  46. ^ Vincent, pp. 29–30.
  47. ^ Gray, pp. 26–27.
  48. ^ Gray, p. 28.
  49. ^ Gray, p. 32.
  50. ^ Ishiyama & Breuning, p. 596.
  51. ^ See the studies of Keynes by Roy Harrod, Robert Skidelsky, Donald Moggridge and Donald Markwell.
  52. ^ Paul Bairoch (1995). . University of Chicago Press. pp. 31–32. Archived from the original on 12 October 2017. Retrieved 16 August 2017.
  53. ^ Hartz, Louis (1955). "The Concept of a Liberal Society". The Liberal Tradition in America. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0156512695.
  54. ^ Jeremy M. Brown (1995). Explaining the Reagan Years in Central America: A World System Perspective. University Press of America. p. 25. ISBN 978-0819198136.
  55. ^ Paul Kahan (2014). The Homestead Strike: Labor, Violence, and American Industry. Routledge. p. 28. ISBN 978-1136173974. Called the "Jacksonian Era," this era was characterized by greater voting rights for white men, a hands-off approach to economic issues, and a desire to spread U.S. culture and government west (an outlook called "Manifest Destiny").
  56. ^ Kathleen G. Donohue (2005). Freedom from Want: American Liberalism and the Idea of the Consumer. Johns Hopkins University Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0801883910.
  57. ^ Pollak, Gustav (1915). Fifty Years of American Idealism: 1865–1915. Houghton Mifflin Company.
  58. ^ Eric Voegelin, Mary Algozin, and Keith Algozin, "Liberalism and Its History", Review of Politics 36, no. 4 (1974): 504–520. JSTOR 1406338.
  59. ^ Arthur Schelesinger Jr., "Liberalism in America: A Note for Europeans" 12 February 2018 at the Wayback Machine, in The Politics of Hope (Boston: Riverside Press, 1962).
  60. ^ Wolfe, Alan (12 April 2009). "A False Distinction". The New Republic. from the original on 7 April 2020. Retrieved 31 May 2010.
  61. ^ D. Conway (1998). Classical Liberalism: The Unvanquished Ideal. Palgrave Macmillan UK. p. 26. ISBN 978-0230371194.
  62. ^ Richman, Sheldon (12 August 2012). "Classical Liberalism vs. Modern Liberalism". Reason. Reason Foundation. from the original on 8 October 2018. Retrieved 4 November 2016.
  63. ^ Faria, Miguel A. Jr. (21 March 2012). . haciendapublishing.com. Hacienda Publishing. Archived from the original on 13 April 2019. Retrieved 4 November 2016.
  64. ^ Alan Ryan (2012). The Making of Modern Liberalism. Princeton University Press. pp. 23–26. ISBN 978-1400841950.
  65. ^ Andrew Heywood (2012). Political Ideologies: An Introduction. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 59. ISBN 978-0230369948.[permanent dead link]
  66. ^ Nathan Schlueter; Nikolai Wenzel (2016). Selfish Libertarians and Socialist Conservatives?: The Foundations of the Libertarian–Conservative Debate. Stanford University Press. p. 8. ISBN 978-1503600294. American conservatism is a form of classical liberalism.
  67. ^ John Micklethwait; Adrian Wooldridge (2004). The Right Nation: Conservative Power in America. Penguin. p. 343. ISBN 978-1594200205. Whichever way you look at it, American conservatism has embraced a great chunk of classical liberalism-so much of it that many observers have argued that American conservatism was an oxymoron; that it is basically classical liberalism in disguise.
  68. ^ James R. Kirth (2016). "A History of Inherent Contradictions: The Origins and Ends of American Conservatism". In Sanford V. Levinson (ed.). American Conservatism: NOMOS LVI. Melissa S. Williams, Joel Parker. NYU Press. p. 26. ISBN 978-1479865185. Of course, the original conservatives had not really been conservatives either. They were merely classical liberals. It seems to be the case in American that most so-called conservatives have really been something else. This has confused not only external observers of American conservatism (be they on the European Right or on the American Left), but it has confused American conservatives as well.
  69. ^ Robert Lerner; Althea K. Nagai; Stanley Rothman (1996). American Elites. Yale University Press. p. 41. ISBN 978-0300065343. Moreover, Americans do not use the term liberalism in the same way that Europeans do. In fact, classical European liberalism more closely resembles what we (and what Americans generally) call conservatism.
  70. ^ Deepak Lal (2010). Reviving the Invisible Hand: The Case for Classical Liberalism in the Twenty-first Century. Princeton University Press. p. 51. ISBN 978-1400837441. The major votaries of classical liberalism today are American conservatives. For as Hayek noted: "It is the doctrine on which the American system of government is based. "But, contemporary American conservatism is a novel brew which Micklethwait and Wooldridge rightly note is a mixture of the individualism of classical liberalism and "ubertraditionalism." It represents adherence to the bourgeois organization of society epitomized by that much-maligned word, "Victorian": with its faith in individualism, capitalism, progress, and virtue. Having been silenced by the seemingly endless march of "embedded liberalism" since the New Deal, American conservatism has, since the late 1960s, regrouped, and under Presidents Reagan and George W. Bush created a new powerful political movement. Thus, apart from the brief period of Margaret Thatcher's ascendancy in Britain, it is only in the United States that the classical liberal tradition continues to have political force.
  71. ^ McMaken, Ryan (12 September 2019). "'Libertarian' Is Just Another Word for (Classical) Liberal". Mises Wire. Mises Institute. Retrieved 6 November 2020.
  72. ^ Steven M. Dworetz, The Unvarnished Doctrine: Locke, Liberalism, and the American Revolution (1989).
  73. ^ Richardson, pp. 22–23.
  74. ^ Richardson, p. 23.
  75. ^ Richardson, pp. 23–24.
  76. ^ Richardson, p. 24.
  77. ^ Mills, pp. 63, 68.
  78. ^ a b Mills, p. 64.
  79. ^ Mills, p. 65.
  80. ^ Mills, p. 66.
  81. ^ Mills, p. 67.
  82. ^ Mills, p. 68.
  83. ^ a b Mills, p. 69.
  84. ^ a b Mills, p. 76.
  85. ^ Mills, p. 70.
  86. ^ Blaug, Mark (1997). "Say's Law of Markets: What Did It Mean and Why Should We Care?". Eastern Economic Journal. 23 (2): 231–235. ISSN 0094-5056. JSTOR 40325773.
  87. ^ Mills, p. 71.
  88. ^ Mills, pp. 71–72.
  89. ^ Campi, Ashleigh; Scorgie-Porter, Lindsay (2017). An Analysis of John Stuart Mill's On Liberty. CRC Press. ISBN 978-1351352581 – via Google Books.
  90. ^ a b Mills, p. 72.
  91. ^ Mills, pp. 73–74.
  92. ^ Mills, pp. 74–75.
  93. ^ Mills, p. 75.
  94. ^ Richardson, p. 32.
  95. ^ Richardson, p. 31.
  96. ^ a b c Richardson, p. 33.
  97. ^ a b Richardson, p. 34.
  98. ^ George Miller. On Fairness and Efficiency. The Policy Press, 2000. ISBN 978-1861342218 p. 344.
  99. ^ Christine Kinealy. A Death-Dealing Famine:The Great Hunger in Ireland. Pluto Press, 1997. ISBN 978-0745310749. p. 59.
  100. ^ Stephen J. Lee. Aspects of British Political History, 1815–1914. Routledge, 1994. ISBN 978-0415090063. p. 83.
  101. ^ Erik Gartzke, "Economic Freedom and Peace," in Economic Freedom of the World: 2005 Annual Report (Vancouver: Fraser Institute, 2005).
  102. ^ Oneal, J. R.; Russet, B. M. (1997). "The Classical Liberals Were Right: Democracy, Interdependence, and Conflict, 1950–1985". International Studies Quarterly. 41 (2): 267–294. doi:10.1111/1468-2478.00042.
  103. ^ Michael Doyle, Ways of War and Peace: Realism, Liberalism, and Socialism (New York: Norton, 1997), p. 237. ISBN 0393969479.
  104. ^ Edward P. Stringham, "Commerce, Markets, and Peace: Richard Cobden's Enduring Lessons", Independent Review 9, no. 1 (2004): 105, 110, 115.
  105. ^ Immanuel Kant, The Perpetual Peace.
  106. ^ Donald Markwell, John Maynard Keynes and International Relations: Economic Paths to War and Peace 1 September 2017 at the Wayback Machine, Oxford University Press, 2006, ch. 1.
  107. ^ John Maynard Keynes and International Relations: Economic Paths to War and Peace 5 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine Donald Markwell (2006), reviewed by M S Lawlor (February 2008).
  108. ^ Lucien Jaume, "Hobbes and the Philosophical Sources of Liberalism", The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes' Leviathan, 211
  109. ^ Bertrand Badie; Dirk Berg-Schlosser; Leonardo Morlino, eds. (2011). International Encyclopedia of Political Science. Sage. p. 44. ISBN 978-1483305394. ... thought of classical liberal figures such as John Locke, Adam Smith, Immanuel Kant, Giuseppe Mazzini, and John Stuart Mill. ...
  110. ^ "Liberalism rediscovered". The Economist. 5 February 1998. Retrieved 28 June 2017.
  111. ^ James Mark Shields (2017). Against Harmony: Progressive and Radical Buddhism in Modern Japan. Oxford University Press. p. 169. ISBN 9780190664008.
  112. ^ Robert Leeson (2018). Hayek: A Collaborative Biography: Part XI: Orwellian Rectifiers, Mises' 'Evil Seed' of Christianity and the 'Free' Market Welfare State Archival Insights into the Evolution of Economics. Springer. p. 468. ISBN 9783319774282. Friedrich Naumann was regarded as a classical liberal while also promoting National Socialism
  113. ^ P. G. C. van Schie; Gerrit Voermann (2006). The Dividing Line Between Success and Failure: A Comparison of Liberalism in the Netherlands and Germany in the 19th and 20th Centuries. LIT Verlag Münsters. p. 64. By the turn of the century, the left liberals Friedrich Naumann and Barth sought to redefine classical liberalism for the needs of the rising industrial society.
  114. ^ After the Soviet Empire: Legacies and Pathways. BRILL. 2015. p. 143. ISBN 9789004291454. They had all forgotten that the classical liberal Karl Popper was definitely opposed to the big bang of rapid changes in whole societal systems. He assumed that changes of this type were bound to cause massive human suffering.
  115. ^ Walter B. Weimer (2022). Retrieving Liberalism from Rationalist Constructivism, Volume II: Basics of a Liberal Psychological, Social and Moral Order. Springer Nature. p. 255. ISBN 9783030954772.
  116. ^ a b Christian Delacampagne (2022). A History of Philosophy in the Twentieth Century. JHU Press. p. 255. ISBN 9780801868146. Among these figures one finds two defenders of the classical liberal tradition, Karl Popper and Raymond Aron; ...
  117. ^ John Gray (2018). Liberalisms: Essays in Political Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 9780415563758.
  118. ^ Liou, Kuo-Tsai (1998). Handbook of Economic Development. CRC Press. p. 357. ISBN 978-1461671756.
  119. ^ "In praise of Australia's Liberal Democrats » The Spectator".
  120. ^ "Posicionamentos".
  121. ^ "Maxime Bernier's new party stakes out classical liberal values: Don Pittis". from the original on 23 May 2022. Retrieved 21 July 2022.
  122. ^ "Un manifiesto liberal". 24 September 2018.
  123. ^ Thomas J. DiLorenzo, ed. (2016). The Problem with Socialism. Simon and Schuster. p. 82.
  124. ^ Marco Lisi, ed. (2018). Party System Change, the European Crisis and the State of Democracy. Routledge.
  125. ^ Mark Salmon, Culture Smart!, ed. (2019). Denmark – Culture Smart!: The Essential Guide to Customs & Culture. Kuperard. ISBN 978-1787029187. Liberal Alliance Formerly New Alliance, Liberal Alliance are a center right, classical liberal party formed in 2007 by former members of the Social Liberal Party and the Conservative People's Party.
  126. ^ Arturo Bris, ed. (2021). The Right Place: How National Competitiveness Makes or Breaks Companies. Routledge. ISBN 978-1000327793.
  127. ^ Christopher J. Bickerton, Carlo Invernizzi Accetti, ed. (2021). Technopopulism: The New Logic of Democratic Politics. Oxford University Press. p. 60.
  128. ^ "Macron Scrambling to Salvage Liberal Reputation Worldwide After Targeting Islam". The Daily Beast. 12 November 2020. Retrieved 11 December 2021.
  129. ^ Slavoj Zizek, ed. (2019). Like a Thief in Broad Daylight: Power in the Era of Post-Human Capitalism. Seven Stories Press.
  130. ^ William Smaldone, ed. (2019). European Socialism: A Concise History with Documents. Rowman & Littlefields.
  131. ^ Brian Duignan, ed. (2013). The Science and Philosophy of Politics. Britannica Educational Publishing. p. 121. ISBN 978-1615307487.
  132. ^ . Loksatta Party. Archived from the original on 15 March 2018. Retrieved 11 April 2016.
  133. ^ Natacha Gagné, ed. (2013). Being M?ori in the City: Indigenous Everyday Life in Auckland. University of Toronto Press. p. 3.
  134. ^ (Speech). www.act.org.nz. ACT New Zealand. 23 February 2015. Archived from the original on 11 February 2017. Retrieved 8 February 2017.
  135. ^ Jens Rydström (2011). Odd Couples: A History of Gay Marriage in Scandinavia. aksant. p. 97. ISBN 9789052603810.
  136. ^ Marek Payerhin, ed. (2016). Nordic, Central, and Southeastern Europe 2016–2017. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 339. ISBN 978-1475828979. Another new movement was the Modern of Ryszard Petru, later styled as Modern (Nowoczesna) or simply ".N." This classical liberal party created by an economist, Ryszard Petru, received 7.6% of votes and 28 seats in the Sejm (it later gained an additional deputy who left Kukiz'15)
  137. ^ Alan G. Smith (2016). A Comparative Introduction to Political Science: Contention and Cooperation. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 207. ISBN 9781442252608.
  138. ^ "Cotrim Figueiredo: Iniciativa Liberal "não ganhou estas eleições mas ganhou o futuro"". Observador.pt.
  139. ^ "Political parties and elections in Slovakia". Online-Slovakia. Retrieved 3 April 2018.
  140. ^ (PDF). Europe of Freedom and Direct Democracy. 2018. p. 43. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 March 2019. Freedom and Solidarity (Slovak: Sloboda a Solidarita, SaS): Limited government, EU-sceptic, Euro-critical, classical-Liberal/Libertarian
  141. ^ Yusuf Sayed and Robert Van Niekerk. "Ideology and the good society in South Africa: the education policies of the Democratic Alliance" (PDF). Southern African Review of Education, 23 (1): 52–69. ISSN 1563-4418. (PDF) from the original on 19 August 2019.
  142. ^ "Liberalismens grundvärden" (PDF). Sv.se. (PDF) from the original on 8 August 2020. Retrieved 21 February 2022.
  143. ^ Medeiros, Evan S. (2008), Pacific Currents: The Responses of U.S. Allies and Security Partners in East Asia to China's Rise, RAND, p. 130
  144. ^ "Introduction to The Liberal Party Policies". liberal.org.uk. from the original on 24 May 2022. Retrieved 12 July 2022.
  145. ^ "Nosotros". 23 May 2023.
  146. ^ Mommsen, Hans (1996). The Rise and Fall of Weimar Democracy. University of North Carolina Press. p. 58. ISBN 0807822493.
  147. ^ Das, Gurcharan (2002). The Elephant Paradigm. Penguin. p. 244.
  148. ^ Jan-Erik Lane; Svante O. Ersson (1999). Politics and Society in Western Europe. Sage Publications. p. 101. ISBN 978-0761958628. Retrieved 19 July 2013.
  149. ^ The Times (31 December 1872), p. 5.
  150. ^ Wilson, Tadd (1 December 1998). "The Culture of Classical Liberalism". Foundation for Economic Education. Retrieved 3 July 2023.
  151. ^ Vieira, Helena (1 February 2017). "The contradiction of classical liberalism and libertarianism". LSE Business Review. Retrieved 3 July 2023.

Sources edit

  • Conway, David (2008). "Liberalism, Classical". In Hamowy, Ronald (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage; Cato Institute. pp. 295–298. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n179. ISBN 978-1412965804. LCCN 2008009151. OCLC 750831024. from the original on 9 January 2023. Retrieved 27 January 2016.
  • De Ruggiero, Guido (1959). The History of European Liberalism. Boston: Beacon Press.
  • Dickerson, M. O.; Flanagan, Thomas; O'Neill, Brenda (2009). An Introduction to Government and Politics: A Conceptual Approach. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0176500429.
  • Gray, John (1995). Liberalism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 0816628009.
  • Heywood, Andrew (2004). Political Theory, Third Edition: An Introduction. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 0333961803.
  • Hunt, E. K. (2003). Property and Prophets: The Evolution of Economic Institutions and Ideologies. New York: M. E. Sharpe, Inc. ISBN 0765606089.
  • Ishiyama, John T.; Breuning, Marijike (2010). 21st Century Political Science: A Reference Handbook. Vol. 1. London: Sage Publications. ISBN 978-1412969017.
  • Lieber, Francis (1881). The Miscellaneous Writings of Francis Lieber, Volume II: Contributions to Political Science. Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott & Co.
  • Mills, John (2002). A Critical History of Economics. Basingstoke, England: Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 0333971302.
  • Richardson, James L. (2001). Contending Liberalisms in World Politics: Ideology and Power. Boulder, Colorado: Lynne Rienner Publishers. ISBN 155587939X.
  • Turner, Rachel S. (2008). Neo-Liberal Ideology: History, Concepts and Policies: History, Concepts and Policies. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0748632350.
  • Van de Haar, Edwin (2015). Degrees of Freedom: Liberal Political Philosophy and Ideology. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. ISBN 978-1412855754.
  • Vincent, Andrew (2009). Modern Political Ideologies (Third ed.). Chichester, England: Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1405154956.

Further reading edit

  • Alan Bullock and Maurice Shock, ed. (1967). The Liberal Tradition: From Fox to Keynes. Oxford. Clarendon Press.[ISBN missing]
  • Epstein, Richard A. (2014). The Classical Liberal Constitution: The Uncertain Quest for Limited Government. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674724891.
  • Katherine Henry (2011). Liberalism and the Culture of Security: The Nineteenth-Century Rhetoric of Reform. University of Alabama Press; draws on literary and other writings to study the debates over liberty and tyranny.[ISBN missing]
  • Donald Markwell (2006). John Maynard Keynes and International Relations: Economic Paths to War and Peace. Oxford, England. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0198292364.
  • Mayne, Alan J. (1999). From politics past to politics future : an integrated analysis of current and emergent paradigms. Westport, Conn.: reenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 0275961516.
  • Gustav Pollak, ed. (1915). Fifty Years of American Idealism: 1865–1915; short history of The Nation plus numerous excerpts, most by Edwin Lawrence Godkin.

External links edit

  •   Quotations related to Classical liberalism at Wikiquote
  •   The dictionary definition of classical liberalism at Wiktionary
  •   Media related to Classical liberalism at Wikimedia Commons

classical, liberalism, this, article, about, branch, liberalism, that, advocates, civil, liberties, with, emphasis, economic, freedom, liberal, economic, system, organized, individual, lines, economic, liberalism, branch, liberalism, that, endorses, regulated,. This article is about the branch of liberalism that advocates civil liberties with an emphasis on economic freedom For the liberal economic system organized on individual lines see Economic liberalism For the branch of liberalism that endorses a regulated market economy and the expansion of civil and political rights see Social liberalism Classical liberalism is a political tradition and a branch of liberalism that advocates free market and laissez faire economics and civil liberties under the rule of law with special emphasis on individual autonomy limited government economic freedom political freedom and freedom of speech 1 Classical liberalism contrary to liberal branches like social liberalism looks more negatively on social policies taxation and the state involvement in the lives of individuals and it advocates deregulation 2 Until the Great Depression and the rise of social liberalism classical liberalism was called economic liberalism Later the term was applied as a retronym to distinguish earlier 19th century liberalism from social liberalism 3 By modern standards in the United States simple liberalism often means social liberalism but in Europe and Australia simple liberalism often means classical liberalism 4 5 Classical liberalism gained full flowering in the early 18th century building on ideas starting at least as far back as the 16th century within the Iberian Anglo Saxon and central European contexts and it was foundational to the American Revolution and American Project more broadly 6 7 8 Notable liberal individuals whose ideas contributed to classical liberalism include John Locke 9 Jean Baptiste Say Thomas Malthus and David Ricardo It drew on classical economics especially the economic ideas as espoused by Adam Smith in Book One of The Wealth of Nations and on a belief in natural law 10 social progress 11 and utilitarianism 12 In contemporary times Friedrich Hayek Milton Friedman Ludwig von Mises Thomas Sowell George Stigler and Larry Arnhart are seen as the most prominent advocates of classical liberalism 13 14 However other scholars have made reference to these contemporary thoughts as neoclassical liberalism distinguishing them from 18th century classical liberalism 15 16 In the context of American politics classical liberalism may be described as fiscally conservative and socially liberal 17 Despite this classical liberals tend to reject the right s higher tolerance for economic protectionism and the left s inclination for collective group rights due to classical liberalism s central principle of individualism 18 Additionally in the United States classical liberalism is considered closely tied to or synonymous with American libertarianism 19 20 Contents 1 Evolution of core beliefs 1 1 Typology of beliefs 2 History 2 1 Great Britain 2 2 Ottoman Empire 2 3 United States 3 Intellectual sources 3 1 John Locke 3 2 Adam Smith 3 3 Classical economics 3 4 Utilitarianism 4 Political economy 4 1 Free trade and world peace 5 Notable thinkers 6 Classical liberal parties worldwide 6 1 Classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions 6 2 Historical classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions Since 1900s 7 Criticism 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Sources 12 Further reading 13 External linksEvolution of core beliefs editCore beliefs of classical liberals included new ideas which departed from both the older conservative idea of society as a family and from the later sociological concept of society as a complex set of social networks Classical liberals agreed with Thomas Hobbes that individuals created government to protect themselves from each other and to minimize conflict between individuals that would otherwise arise in a state of nature These beliefs were complemented by a belief that financial incentive could be best motivate labourers This belief led to the passage of the Poor Law Amendment Act 1834 which limited the provision of social assistance based on the idea that markets are the mechanism that most efficiently leads to wealth Drawing on ideas of Adam Smith classical liberals believed that it is in the common interest that all individuals be able to secure their own economic self interest 21 They were critical of what would come to be the idea of the welfare state as interfering in a free market 22 Despite Smith s resolute recognition of the importance and value of labour and of labourers classical liberals criticized labour s group rights being pursued at the expense of individual rights 23 while accepting corporations rights which led to inequality of bargaining power 21 24 Classical liberals argued that individuals should be free to obtain work from the highest paying employers while the profit motive would ensure that products that people desired were produced at prices they would pay In a free market both labour and capital would receive the greatest possible reward while production would be organized efficiently to meet consumer demand 25 Classical liberals argued for what they called a minimal state and government limited to the following functions Laws to protect citizens from wrongs committed against them by other citizens which included protection of individual rights private property enforcement of contracts and common law A common national defence to provide protection against foreign invaders 26 Public works and services that cannot be provided in a free market such as a stable currency standard weights and measures and building and upkeep of roads canals harbours railways communications and postal services 26 Classical liberals asserted that rights are of a negative nature and therefore stipulate that other individuals and governments are to refrain from interfering with the free market opposing social liberals who assert that individuals have positive rights such as the right to vote the right to an education the right to health care dubious discuss and the right to a minimum wage For society to guarantee positive rights it requires taxation over and above the minimum needed to enforce negative rights 27 28 Core beliefs of classical liberals did not necessarily include democracy nor government by a majority vote by citizens because there is nothing in the bare idea of majority rule to show that majorities will always respect the rights of property or maintain rule of law 29 30 For example James Madison argued for a constitutional republic with protections for individual liberty over a pure democracy reasoning that in a pure democracy a common passion or interest will in almost every case be felt by a majority of the whole and there is nothing to check the inducements to sacrifice the weaker party 31 In the late 19th century classical liberalism developed into neoclassical liberalism which argued for government to be as small as possible to allow the exercise of individual freedom In its most extreme form neoclassical liberalism advocated social Darwinism 32 Right libertarianism is a modern form of neoclassical liberalism 32 However Edwin Van de Haar states although classical liberal thought influenced libertarianism there are significant differences between them 33 Classical liberalism refuses to give priority to liberty over order and therefore does not exhibit the hostility to the state which is the defining feature of libertarianism 34 As such right libertarians believe classical liberals do not have enough respect for individual property rights and lack sufficient trust in the free market s workings and spontaneous order leading to their support of a much larger state 35 Right libertarians also disagree with classical liberals as being too supportive of central banks and monetarist policies 36 Typology of beliefs edit Friedrich Hayek identified two different traditions within classical liberalism namely the British tradition and the French tradition The British philosophers Bernard Mandeville David Hume Edmund Burke Adam Smith Adam Ferguson Josiah Tucker and William Paley held beliefs in empiricism the common law and in traditions and institutions which had spontaneously evolved but were imperfectly understood The French philosophers Voltaire Jean Jacques Rousseau Denis Diderot Maximilien Robespierre Marquis de Condorcet the Encyclopedists and the Physiocrats believed in rationalism and sometimes showed hostility to tradition and religion Hayek conceded that the national labels did not exactly correspond to those belonging to each tradition since he saw the Frenchmen Montesquieu Benjamin Constant Joseph De Maistre and Alexis de Tocqueville as belonging to the British tradition and the British Thomas Hobbes Joseph Priestley Richard Price Edward Gibbon Benjamin Franklin Thomas Jefferson and Thomas Paine as belonging to the French tradition 37 38 Hayek also rejected the label laissez faire as originating from the French tradition and alien to the beliefs of Hume and Smith Guido De Ruggiero also identified differences between Montesquieu and Rousseau the English and the democratic types of liberalism 39 and argued that there was a profound contrast between the two Liberal systems 40 He claimed that the spirit of authentic English Liberalism had built up its work piece by piece without ever destroying what had once been built but basing upon it every new departure This liberalism had insensibly adapted ancient institutions to modern needs and instinctively recoiled from all abstract proclamations of principles and rights 40 Ruggiero claimed that this liberalism was challenged by what he called the new Liberalism of France that was characterised by egalitarianism and a rationalistic consciousness 41 In 1848 Francis Lieber distinguished between what he called Anglican and Gallican Liberty Lieber asserted that independence in the highest degree compatible with safety and broad national guarantees of liberty is the great aim of Anglican liberty and self reliance is the chief source from which it draws its strength 42 On the other hand Gallican liberty is sought in government T he French look for the highest degree of political civilisation in organisation that is in the highest degree of interference by public power 43 History editGreat Britain edit French physiocracy heavily influenced British classical liberalism which traces its roots to the Whigs and Radicals Whiggery had become a dominant ideology following the Glorious Revolution of 1688 and was associated with supporting the British Parliament upholding the rule of law defending landed property and sometimes included freedom of the press and freedom of speech The origins of rights were seen as being in an ancient constitution existing from time immemorial Custom rather than as natural rights justified these rights Whigs believed that executive power had to be constrained While they supported limited suffrage they saw voting as a privilege rather than as a right However there was no consistency in Whig ideology and diverse writers including John Locke David Hume Adam Smith and Edmund Burke were all influential among Whigs although none of them were universally accepted 44 From the 1790s to the 1820s British radicals concentrated on parliamentary and electoral reform emphasising natural rights and popular sovereignty Richard Price and Joseph Priestley adapted the language of Locke to the ideology of radicalism 44 The radicals saw parliamentary reform as a first step toward dealing with their many grievances including the treatment of Protestant Dissenters the slave trade high prices and high taxes 45 There was greater unity among classical liberals than there had been among Whigs Classical liberals were committed to individualism liberty and equal rights as well as some other important tenants of leftism since classical liberalism was introduced in the late 18th century as a leftist movement 17 They believed these goals required a free economy with minimal government interference Some elements of Whiggery were uncomfortable with the commercial nature of classical liberalism These elements became associated with conservatism 46 nbsp A meeting of the Anti Corn Law League in Exeter Hall in 1846Classical liberalism was the dominant political theory in Britain from the early 19th century until the First World War Its notable victories were the Roman Catholic Relief Act 1829 the Reform Act of 1832 and the repeal of the Corn Laws in 1846 The Anti Corn Law League brought together a coalition of liberal and radical groups in support of free trade under the leadership of Richard Cobden and John Bright who opposed aristocratic privilege militarism and public expenditure and believed that the backbone of Great Britain was the yeoman farmer Their policies of low public expenditure and low taxation were adopted by William Gladstone when he became Chancellor of the Exchequer and later Prime Minister Classical liberalism was often associated with religious dissent and nonconformism 47 Although classical liberals aspired to a minimum of state activity they accepted the principle of government intervention in the economy from the early 19th century on with passage of the Factory Acts From around 1840 to 1860 laissez faire advocates of the Manchester School and writers in The Economist were confident that their early victories would lead to a period of expanding economic and personal liberty and world peace but would face reversals as government intervention and activity continued to expand from the 1850s Jeremy Bentham and James Mill although advocates of laissez faire non intervention in foreign affairs and individual liberty believed that social institutions could be rationally redesigned through the principles of utilitarianism The Conservative Prime Minister Benjamin Disraeli rejected classical liberalism altogether and advocated Tory democracy By the 1870s Herbert Spencer and other classical liberals concluded that historical development was turning against them 48 By the First World War the Liberal Party had largely abandoned classical liberal principles 49 The changing economic and social conditions of the 19th century led to a division between neo classical and social or welfare liberals who while agreeing on the importance of individual liberty differed on the role of the state Neo classical liberals who called themselves true liberals saw Locke s Second Treatise as the best guide and emphasised limited government while social liberals supported government regulation and the welfare state Herbert Spencer in Britain and William Graham Sumner were the leading neo classical liberal theorists of the 19th century 50 The evolution from classical to social welfare liberalism is for example reflected in Britain in the evolution of the thought of John Maynard Keynes 51 Ottoman Empire edit The Ottoman Empire had liberal free trade policies by the 18th century with origins in capitulations of the Ottoman Empire dating back to the first commercial treaties signed with France in 1536 and taken further with capitulations in 1673 in 1740 which lowered duties to only 3 for imports and exports and in 1790 Ottoman free trade policies were praised by British economists advocating free trade such as J R McCulloch in his Dictionary of Commerce 1834 but criticized by British politicians opposing free trade such as Prime Minister Benjamin Disraeli who cited the Ottoman Empire as an instance of the injury done by unrestrained competition in the 1846 Corn Laws debate arguing that it destroyed what had been some of the finest manufactures of the world in 1812 52 United States edit In the United States liberalism took a strong root because it had little opposition to its ideals whereas in Europe liberalism was opposed by many reactionary or feudal interests such as the nobility the aristocracy including army officers the landed gentry and the established church 53 Thomas Jefferson adopted many of the ideals of liberalism but in the Declaration of Independence changed Locke s life liberty and property to the more socially liberal Life Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness 9 As the United States grew industry became a larger and larger part of American life and during the term of its first populist President Andrew Jackson economic questions came to the forefront The economic ideas of the Jacksonian era were almost universally the ideas of classical liberalism 54 Freedom according to classical liberals was maximised when the government took a hands off attitude toward the economy 55 Historian Kathleen G Donohue argues A t the center of classical liberal theory in Europe was the idea of laissez faire To the vast majority of American classical liberals however laissez faire did not mean no government intervention at all On the contrary they were more than willing to see government provide tariffs railroad subsidies and internal improvements all of which benefited producers What they condemned was intervention on behalf of consumers 56 The Nation magazine espoused liberalism every week starting in 1865 under the influential editor Edwin Lawrence Godkin 1831 1902 57 The ideas of classical liberalism remained essentially unchallenged until a series of depressions thought to be impossible according to the tenets of classical economics led to economic hardship from which the voters demanded relief In the words of William Jennings Bryan You shall not crucify this nation on a cross of gold Classical liberalism remained the orthodox belief among American businessmen until the Great Depression 58 The Great Depression in the United States saw a sea change in liberalism with priority shifting from the producers to consumers Franklin D Roosevelt s New Deal represented the dominance of modern liberalism in politics for decades In the words of Arthur Schlesinger Jr 59 When the growing complexity of industrial conditions required increasing government intervention in order to assure more equal opportunities the liberal tradition faithful to the goal rather than to the dogma altered its view of the state There emerged the conception of a social welfare state in which the national government had the express obligation to maintain high levels of employment in the economy to supervise standards of life and labour to regulate the methods of business competition and to establish comprehensive patterns of social security Alan Wolfe summarizes the viewpoint that there is a continuous liberal understanding that includes both Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes The idea that liberalism comes in two forms assumes that the most fundamental question facing mankind is how much government intervenes into the economy When instead we discuss human purpose and the meaning of life Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes are on the same side Both of them possessed an expansive sense of what we are put on this earth to accomplish For Smith mercantilism was the enemy of human liberty For Keynes monopolies were It makes perfect sense for an eighteenth century thinker to conclude that humanity would flourish under the market For a twentieth century thinker committed to the same ideal government was an essential tool to the same end 60 The view that modern liberalism is a continuation of classical liberalism is controversial and disputed by many 61 62 63 64 65 James Kurth Robert E Lerner John Micklethwait Adrian Wooldridge and several other political scholars have argued that classical liberalism still exists today but in the form of American conservatism 66 67 68 69 According to Deepak Lal only in the United States does classical liberalism continue to be a significant political force through American conservatism 70 American libertarians also claim to be the true continuation of the classical liberal tradition 71 Intellectual sources editJohn Locke edit nbsp John LockeCentral to classical liberal ideology was their interpretation of John Locke s Second Treatise of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration which had been written as a defence of the Glorious Revolution of 1688 Although these writings were considered too radical at the time for Britain s new rulers Whigs radicals and supporters of the American Revolution later came to cite them 72 However much of later liberal thought was absent in Locke s writings or scarcely mentioned and his writings have been subject to various interpretations For example there is little mention of constitutionalism the separation of powers and limited government 73 James L Richardson identified five central themes in Locke s writing Individualism Consent Rule of law and government as trustee Significance of property Religious tolerationAlthough Locke did not develop a theory of natural rights he envisioned individuals in the state of nature as being free and equal The individual rather than the community or institutions was the point of reference Locke believed that individuals had given consent to government and therefore authority derived from the people rather than from above This belief would influence later revolutionary movements 74 As a trustee government was expected to serve the interests of the people not the rulers and rulers were expected to follow the laws enacted by legislatures Locke also held that the main purpose of men uniting into commonwealths and governments was for the preservation of their property Despite the ambiguity of Locke s definition of property which limited property to as much land as a man tills plants improves cultivates and can use the product of this principle held great appeal to individuals possessed of great wealth 75 Locke held that the individual had the right to follow his own religious beliefs and that the state should not impose a religion against Dissenters but there were limitations No tolerance should be shown for atheists who were seen as amoral or to Catholics who were seen as owing allegiance to the Pope over their own national government 76 Adam Smith edit nbsp Adam SmithAdam Smith s The Wealth of Nations published in 1776 was to provide most of the ideas of economics at least until the publication of John Stuart Mill s Principles of Political Economy in 1848 77 Smith addressed the motivation for economic activity the causes of prices and the distribution of wealth and the policies the state should follow to maximise wealth 78 Smith wrote that as long as supply demand prices and competition were left free of government regulation the pursuit of material self interest rather than altruism would maximise the wealth of a society 24 through profit driven production of goods and services An invisible hand directed individuals and firms to work toward the public good as an unintended consequence of efforts to maximise their own gain This provided a moral justification for the accumulation of wealth which had previously been viewed by some as sinful 78 He assumed that workers could be paid wages as low as was necessary for their survival which was later transformed by David Ricardo and Thomas Robert Malthus into the iron law of wages 79 His main emphasis was on the benefit of free internal and international trade which he thought could increase wealth through specialisation in production 80 He also opposed restrictive trade preferences state grants of monopolies and employers organisations and trade unions 81 Government should be limited to defence public works and the administration of justice financed by taxes based on income 82 Smith s economics was carried into practice in the nineteenth century with the lowering of tariffs in the 1820s the repeal of the Poor Relief Act that had restricted the mobility of labour in 1834 and the end of the rule of the East India Company over India in 1858 83 Classical economics edit In addition to Smith s legacy Say s law Thomas Robert Malthus theories of population and David Ricardo s iron law of wages became central doctrines of classical economics The pessimistic nature of these theories provided a basis for criticism of capitalism by its opponents and helped perpetuate the tradition of calling economics the dismal science 84 Jean Baptiste Say was a French economist who introduced Smith s economic theories into France and whose commentaries on Smith were read in both France and Britain 83 Say challenged Smith s labour theory of value believing that prices were determined by utility and also emphasised the critical role of the entrepreneur in the economy However neither of those observations became accepted by British economists at the time His most important contribution to economic thinking was Say s law which was interpreted by classical economists that there could be no overproduction in a market and that there would always be a balance between supply and demand 85 86 This general belief influenced government policies until the 1930s Following this law since the economic cycle was seen as self correcting government did not intervene during periods of economic hardship because it was seen as futile 87 Malthus wrote two books An Essay on the Principle of Population published in 1798 and Principles of Political Economy published in 1820 The second book which was a rebuttal of Say s law had little influence on contemporary economists 88 However his first book became a major influence on classical liberalism 89 90 In that book Malthus claimed that population growth would outstrip food production because population grew geometrically while food production grew arithmetically As people were provided with food they would reproduce until their growth outstripped the food supply Nature would then provide a check to growth in the forms of vice and misery No gains in income could prevent this and any welfare for the poor would be self defeating The poor were in fact responsible for their own problems which could have been avoided through self restraint 90 Ricardo who was an admirer of Smith covered many of the same topics but while Smith drew conclusions from broadly empirical observations he used deduction drawing conclusions by reasoning from basic assumptions 91 While Ricardo accepted Smith s labour theory of value he acknowledged that utility could influence the price of some rare items Rents on agricultural land were seen as the production that was surplus to the subsistence required by the tenants Wages were seen as the amount required for workers subsistence and to maintain current population levels 92 According to his iron law of wages wages could never rise beyond subsistence levels Ricardo explained profits as a return on capital which itself was the product of labour but a conclusion many drew from his theory was that profit was a surplus appropriated by capitalists to which they were not entitled 93 Utilitarianism edit The central concept of utilitarianism which was developed by Jeremy Bentham was that public policy should seek to provide the greatest happiness of the greatest number While this could be interpreted as a justification for state action to reduce poverty it was used by classical liberals to justify inaction with the argument that the net benefit to all individuals would be higher 84 Utilitarianism provided British governments with the political justification to implement economic liberalism which was to dominate economic policy from the 1830s Although utilitarianism prompted legislative and administrative reform and John Stuart Mill s later writings on the subject foreshadowed the welfare state it was mainly used as a justification for laissez faire 94 Political economy editClassical liberals following Mill saw utility as the foundation for public policies This broke both with conservative tradition and Lockean natural rights which were seen as irrational Utility which emphasises the happiness of individuals became the central ethical value of all Mill style liberalism 95 Although utilitarianism inspired wide ranging reforms it became primarily a justification for laissez faire economics However Mill adherents rejected Smith s belief that the invisible hand would lead to general benefits and embraced Malthus view that population expansion would prevent any general benefit and Ricardo s view of the inevitability of class conflict Laissez faire was seen as the only possible economic approach and any government intervention was seen as useless and harmful The Poor Law Amendment Act 1834 was defended on scientific or economic principles while the authors of the Poor Relief Act 1601 were seen as not having had the benefit of reading Malthus 96 However commitment to laissez faire was not uniform and some economists advocated state support of public works and education Classical liberals were also divided on free trade as Ricardo expressed doubt that the removal of grain tariffs advocated by Richard Cobden and the Anti Corn Law League would have any general benefits Most classical liberals also supported legislation to regulate the number of hours that children were allowed to work and usually did not oppose factory reform legislation 96 Despite the pragmatism of classical economists their views were expressed in dogmatic terms by such popular writers as Jane Marcet and Harriet Martineau 96 The strongest defender of laissez faire was The Economist founded by James Wilson in 1843 The Economist criticised Ricardo for his lack of support for free trade and expressed hostility to welfare believing that the lower orders were responsible for their economic circumstances The Economist took the position that regulation of factory hours was harmful to workers and also strongly opposed state support for education health the provision of water and granting of patents and copyrights 97 The Economist also campaigned against the Corn Laws that protected landlords in the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland against competition from less expensive foreign imports of cereal products A rigid belief in laissez faire guided the government response in 1846 1849 to the Great Famine in Ireland during which an estimated 1 5 million people died The minister responsible for economic and financial affairs Charles Wood expected that private enterprise and free trade rather than government intervention would alleviate the famine 97 The Corn Laws were finally repealed in 1846 by the removal of tariffs on grain which kept the price of bread artificially high 98 but it came too late to stop the Irish famine partly because it was done in stages over three years 99 100 Free trade and world peace editSeveral liberals including Smith and Cobden argued that the free exchange of goods between nations could lead to world peace Erik Gartzke states Scholars like Montesquieu Adam Smith Richard Cobden Norman Angell and Richard Rosecrance have long speculated that free markets have the potential to free states from the looming prospect of recurrent warfare 101 American political scientists John R Oneal and Bruce M Russett well known for their work on the democratic peace theory state 102 The classical liberals advocated policies to increase liberty and prosperity They sought to empower the commercial class politically and to abolish royal charters monopolies and the protectionist policies of mercantilism so as to encourage entrepreneurship and increase productive efficiency They also expected democracy and laissez faire economics to diminish the frequency of war In The Wealth of Nations Smith argued that as societies progressed from hunter gatherers to industrial societies the spoils of war would rise but that the costs of war would rise further and thus making war difficult and costly for industrialised nations 103 T he honours the fame the emoluments of war belong not to the middle and industrial classes the battle plain is the harvest field of the aristocracy watered with the blood of the people Whilst our trade rested upon our foreign dependencies as was the case in the middle of the last century force and violence were necessary to command our customers for our manufacturers But war although the greatest of consumers not only produces nothing in return but by abstracting labour from productive employment and interrupting the course of trade it impedes in a variety of indirect ways the creation of wealth and should hostilities be continued for a series of years each successive war loan will be felt in our commercial and manufacturing districts with an augmented pressure Richard Cobden 104 B y virtue of their mutual interest does nature unite people against violence and war for the concept of cosmopolitan right does not protect them from it The spirit of trade cannot coexist with war and sooner or later this spirit dominates every people For among all those powers or means that belong to a nation financial power may be the most reliable in forcing nations to pursue the noble cause of peace though not from moral motives and wherever in the world war threatens to break out they will try to head it off through mediation just as if they were permanently leagued for this purpose Immanuel Kant 105 Cobden believed that military expenditures worsened the welfare of the state and benefited a small but concentrated elite minority summing up British imperialism which he believed was the result of the economic restrictions of mercantilist policies To Cobden and many classical liberals those who advocated peace must also advocate free markets The belief that free trade would promote peace was widely shared by English liberals of the 19th and early 20th century leading the economist John Maynard Keynes 1883 1946 who was a classical liberal in his early life to say that this was a doctrine on which he was brought up and which he held unquestioned only until the 1920s 106 In his review of a book on Keynes Michael S Lawlor argues that it may be in large part due to Keynes contributions in economics and politics as in the implementation of the Marshall Plan and the way economies have been managed since his work that we have the luxury of not facing his unpalatable choice between free trade and full employment 107 A related manifestation of this idea was the argument of Norman Angell 1872 1967 most famously before World War I in The Great Illusion 1909 that the interdependence of the economies of the major powers was now so great that war between them was futile and irrational and therefore unlikely Notable thinkers editThis article possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed September 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Thomas Hobbes 108 1588 1679 James Harrington 1611 1677 John Locke 1632 1704 Montesquieu 1689 1755 David Hume 1711 1776 Voltaire 1694 1778 Jean Jacques Rousseau 1712 1778 Benjamin Franklin 1706 1790 Adam Smith 1723 1790 Edward Gibbon 1737 1794 Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 Anders Chydenius 1729 1803 Thomas Paine 1737 1809 Cesare Beccaria 1738 1794 Marquis de Condorcet 1743 1794 Thomas Jefferson 1743 1826 Jeremy Bentham 1748 1832 Gaetano Filangieri 1753 1788 Benjamin Constant 1767 1830 David Ricardo 1772 1823 Alexis de Tocqueville 1805 1859 Giuseppe Mazzini 1805 1872 109 John Stuart Mill 1806 1872 William Ewart Gladstone 110 1809 1898 Horace Greeley 1811 1873 Fukuzawa Yukichi 111 1835 1901 Henry George 1839 1897 Friedrich Naumann 112 113 1860 1919 Ludwig Von Mises 1881 1973 Friedrich Hayek 1899 1992 Karl Popper 114 115 116 1902 1994 Raymond Aron 116 1905 1983 Milton Friedman 1912 2006 Robert Nozick 117 1938 2002 Classical liberal parties worldwide editAlthough general libertarian a liberal conservative b and some right wing populist c political parties are also included in classical liberal parties in a broad sense but only general classical liberal parties such as Germany s FDP Denmark s Liberal Alliance and Thailand Democrat Party should be listed Classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions edit Argentina Liberty Advances citation needed Australia Liberal Party of Australia 118 Liberal Democratic Party 119 Austria NEOS The New Austria and Liberal Forum Freedom Party of Austria factions Belgium Open Flemish Liberals and Democrats Reformist Movement Brazil New Party 120 Canada People s Party 121 Chile Evopoli 122 Denmark Venstre 123 Liberal Alliance 124 125 Estonia Estonian Reform Party 126 France Renaissance 127 128 129 130 Germany Free Democratic Party 131 Iceland Reform Party India Lok Satta Party 132 Latvia For Latvia s Development Movement For Lithuania Liberals Movement Luxembourg Democratic Party Netherlands People s Party for Freedom and Democracy Belang van Nederland New Zealand New Zealand National Party 133 ACT New Zealand 134 Norway Venstre 135 Progress Party Poland Modern 136 Civic Platform 137 Portugal Liberal Initiative 138 Romania National Liberal Party Russia PARNAS Serbia Liberal Democratic Party of Serbia Slovakia Freedom and Solidarity 139 140 South Africa Democratic Alliance 141 Sweden Liberals 142 Classical Liberal Party Switzerland FDP The Liberals Thailand Democrat Party 143 Turkey Liberal Democratic Party United Kingdom Liberal Party 144 Venezuela Come Venezuela 145 Historical classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions Since 1900s edit Belgium Liberal Party Party for Freedom and Progress Liberal Reformist Party Chile Liberal Party Amplitude Germany German Democratic Party 146 India Swatantra Party 147 Ireland Progressive Democrats Japan Liberal Party 1998 Liberal League Netherlands Freedom Party New Zealand New Zealand Liberal Party United Party New Zealand Party South Korea New Democratic Party Switzerland Free Democratic Party of Switzerland 148 Liberal Party of Switzerland United Kingdom Liberal Party 149 Criticism editTadd Wilson writing for the libertarian Foundation for Economic Education noted that Many on the left and right criticize classical liberals for focusing purely on economics and politics to the neglect of a vital issue culture 150 Helena Vieira writing for the London School of Economics argued that classical liberalism may contradict some fundamental democratic principles as they are inconsistent with the principle of unanimity also known as the Pareto Principle the idea that if everyone in society prefers a policy A to a policy B then the former should be adopted 151 See also edit nbsp Liberalism portal nbsp Politics portalAge of Enlightenment Austrian School Bourbon Democrat National Democratic Party Classical economics Cultural liberalism Classical radicalism Modern liberalism Classical republicanism Constitutionalism Constitutional liberalism Conservative liberalism Economic liberalism Fiscal conservatism Friedrich Naumann Foundation Georgism Gladstonian liberalism Jeffersonian democracy Liberal conservatism Liberal democracy Liberalism in Europe Libertarianism Left libertarianism Right libertarianism List of liberal theorists Neoclassical liberalism Neoliberalism Night watchman state Opportunist Republicans Orleanist Physiocracy Political individualism Rule of law Separation of powers Whig historyNotes edit Example the U S Libertarian Party KORWiN etc Example the Christian Democratic Union of Germany Les Republicains etc Example Progress Party Norway People s Party of Canada enc References edit Classical liberalism www britannica com Encyclopaedia Britannica 6 September 2023 Retrieved 17 October 2023 M O Dickerson et al An Introduction to Government and Politics A Conceptual Approach 2009 p 129 Richardson p 52 Goldfarb Michael 20 July 2010 Liberal Are we talking about the same thing BBC News Retrieved 6 August 2020 Greenberg David 12 September 2019 The danger of confusing liberals and leftists Washington Post Retrieved 6 August 2020 Douma Michael 2018 What is Classical Liberal History Lexington Books ISBN 978 1 4985 3610 3 Dickerson Flanagan amp O Neill p 129 Renshaw Catherine 18 March 2014 What is a classical liberal approach to human rights The Conversation Retrieved 12 August 2022 a b Steven M Dworetz 1994 The Unvarnished Doctrine Locke Liberalism and the American Revolution Appleby Joyce 1992 Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination Harvard University Press p 58 ISBN 978 0674530133 Hunt p 54 Gaus Gerald F Kukathas Chandran 2004 Handbook of Political Theory Sage p 422 ISBN 978 0761967873 Dilley Stephen C 2 May 2013 Darwinian Evolution and Classical Liberalism Theories in Tension Lexington Books pp 13 14 ISBN 978 0 7391 8107 2 Peters Michael A 16 April 2022 Hayek as classical liberal public intellectual Neoliberalism the privatization of public discourse and the future of democracy Educational Philosophy and Theory 54 5 443 449 doi 10 1080 00131857 2019 1696303 ISSN 0013 1857 S2CID 213420239 Mayne Alan James 1999 From Politics Past to Politics Future An Integrated Analysis of Current and Emergent Paradigmss Westport Connecticut Greenwood Publishing Group pp 124 125 ISBN 0275961516 Ishiyama John T Breuning Marijke et al Ellen Grigsby 2011 Neoclassical liberals 21st Century Political Science A Reference Handbook SAGE Publications Inc pp 596 603 ISBN 978 1 4129 6901 7 a b Wright Edmund ed 2006 The Desk Encyclopedia of World History New York Oxford University Press p 370 ISBN 978 0 7394 7809 7 Goodman John C Classical Liberalism vs Modern Liberalism and Modern Conservatism Goodman Institute Retrieved 2 January 2022 Libertarianism vs Classical Liberalism Is there a Difference Reason com 6 April 2023 Retrieved 22 September 2023 Klein Daniel B 3 May 2017 Libertarianism and Classical Liberalism A Short Introduction Daniel B Klein fee org Retrieved 8 March 2022 a b Dickerson Flanagan amp O Neill p 132 Alan Ryan Liberalism in A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy ed Robert E Goodin and Philip Pettit Oxford Blackwell Publishing 1995 p 293 Evans M ed 2001 Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism Evidence and Experience London Routledge 55 ISBN 1579583393 a b Smith A 1778 8 An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations Vol I W Strahan and T Cadell Hunt pp 46 47 a b Hunt pp 51 53 Kelly D 1998 A Life of One s Own Individual Rights and the Welfare State Washington DC Cato Institute Richardson pp 36 38 Ellerman David 2015 Does classical liberalism imply democracy Ethics amp Global Politics 8 1 29310 doi 10 3402 egp v8 29310 Ryan A 1995 Liberalism In Goodin R E and Pettit P eds A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy Oxford Blackwell Publishing p 293 James Madison Federalist No 10 22 November 1787 in Alexander Hamilton John Jay and James Madison The Federalist A Commentary on the Constitution of the United States ed Henry Cabot Lodge New York 1888 p 56 a b Mayne 1999 p 124 Van de Haar 2015 p 71 Heywood 2004 p 337 Van de Haar 2015 p 42 Van de Haar 2015 p 43 Hayek F A 1976 The Constitution of Liberty London Routledge pp 55 56 ISBN 978 1317857808 F A Hayek Individualism True and False in Individualism and Economic Order Chicago University of Chicago Press 1980 pp 1 32 De Ruggiero p 71 a b De Ruggiero p 81 De Ruggiero pp 81 82 Lieber p 377 Lieber pp 382 383 a b Vincent pp 28 29 Turner Michael J 1999 British Politics in an Age of Reform Manchester Manchester University Press p 86 ISBN 978 0719051869 Vincent pp 29 30 Gray pp 26 27 Gray p 28 Gray p 32 Ishiyama amp Breuning p 596 See the studies of Keynes by Roy Harrod Robert Skidelsky Donald Moggridge and Donald Markwell Paul Bairoch 1995 Economics and World History Myths and Paradoxes University of Chicago Press pp 31 32 Archived from the original on 12 October 2017 Retrieved 16 August 2017 Hartz Louis 1955 The Concept of a Liberal Society The Liberal Tradition in America Houghton Mifflin Harcourt ISBN 978 0156512695 Jeremy M Brown 1995 Explaining the Reagan Years in Central America A World System Perspective University Press of America p 25 ISBN 978 0819198136 Paul Kahan 2014 The Homestead Strike Labor Violence and American Industry Routledge p 28 ISBN 978 1136173974 Called the Jacksonian Era this era was characterized by greater voting rights for white men a hands off approach to economic issues and a desire to spread U S culture and government west an outlook called Manifest Destiny Kathleen G Donohue 2005 Freedom from Want American Liberalism and the Idea of the Consumer Johns Hopkins University Press p 2 ISBN 978 0801883910 Pollak Gustav 1915 Fifty Years of American Idealism 1865 1915 Houghton Mifflin Company Eric Voegelin Mary Algozin and Keith Algozin Liberalism and Its History Review of Politics 36 no 4 1974 504 520 JSTOR 1406338 Arthur Schelesinger Jr Liberalism in America A Note for Europeans Archived 12 February 2018 at the Wayback Machine in The Politics of Hope Boston Riverside Press 1962 Wolfe Alan 12 April 2009 A False Distinction The New Republic Archived from the original on 7 April 2020 Retrieved 31 May 2010 D Conway 1998 Classical Liberalism The Unvanquished Ideal Palgrave Macmillan UK p 26 ISBN 978 0230371194 Richman Sheldon 12 August 2012 Classical Liberalism vs Modern Liberalism Reason Reason Foundation Archived from the original on 8 October 2018 Retrieved 4 November 2016 Faria Miguel A Jr 21 March 2012 Classical Liberalism vs Modern Liberalism Socialism A Primer haciendapublishing com Hacienda Publishing Archived from the original on 13 April 2019 Retrieved 4 November 2016 Alan Ryan 2012 The Making of Modern Liberalism Princeton University Press pp 23 26 ISBN 978 1400841950 Andrew Heywood 2012 Political Ideologies An Introduction Palgrave Macmillan p 59 ISBN 978 0230369948 permanent dead link Nathan Schlueter Nikolai Wenzel 2016 Selfish Libertarians and Socialist Conservatives The Foundations of the Libertarian Conservative Debate Stanford University Press p 8 ISBN 978 1503600294 American conservatism is a form of classical liberalism John Micklethwait Adrian Wooldridge 2004 The Right Nation Conservative Power in America Penguin p 343 ISBN 978 1594200205 Whichever way you look at it American conservatism has embraced a great chunk of classical liberalism so much of it that many observers have argued that American conservatism was an oxymoron that it is basically classical liberalism in disguise James R Kirth 2016 A History of Inherent Contradictions The Origins and Ends of American Conservatism In Sanford V Levinson ed American Conservatism NOMOS LVI Melissa S Williams Joel Parker NYU Press p 26 ISBN 978 1479865185 Of course the original conservatives had not really been conservatives either They were merely classical liberals It seems to be the case in American that most so called conservatives have really been something else This has confused not only external observers of American conservatism be they on the European Right or on the American Left but it has confused American conservatives as well Robert Lerner Althea K Nagai Stanley Rothman 1996 American Elites Yale University Press p 41 ISBN 978 0300065343 Moreover Americans do not use the term liberalism in the same way that Europeans do In fact classical European liberalism more closely resembles what we and what Americans generally call conservatism Deepak Lal 2010 Reviving the Invisible Hand The Case for Classical Liberalism in the Twenty first Century Princeton University Press p 51 ISBN 978 1400837441 The major votaries of classical liberalism today are American conservatives For as Hayek noted It is the doctrine on which the American system of government is based But contemporary American conservatism is a novel brew which Micklethwait and Wooldridge rightly note is a mixture of the individualism of classical liberalism and ubertraditionalism It represents adherence to the bourgeois organization of society epitomized by that much maligned word Victorian with its faith in individualism capitalism progress and virtue Having been silenced by the seemingly endless march of embedded liberalism since the New Deal American conservatism has since the late 1960s regrouped and under Presidents Reagan and George W Bush created a new powerful political movement Thus apart from the brief period of Margaret Thatcher s ascendancy in Britain it is only in the United States that the classical liberal tradition continues to have political force McMaken Ryan 12 September 2019 Libertarian Is Just Another Word for Classical Liberal Mises Wire Mises Institute Retrieved 6 November 2020 Steven M Dworetz The Unvarnished Doctrine Locke Liberalism and the American Revolution 1989 Richardson pp 22 23 Richardson p 23 Richardson pp 23 24 Richardson p 24 Mills pp 63 68 a b Mills p 64 Mills p 65 Mills p 66 Mills p 67 Mills p 68 a b Mills p 69 a b Mills p 76 Mills p 70 Blaug Mark 1997 Say s Law of Markets What Did It Mean and Why Should We Care Eastern Economic Journal 23 2 231 235 ISSN 0094 5056 JSTOR 40325773 Mills p 71 Mills pp 71 72 Campi Ashleigh Scorgie Porter Lindsay 2017 An Analysis of John Stuart Mill s On Liberty CRC Press ISBN 978 1351352581 via Google Books a b Mills p 72 Mills pp 73 74 Mills pp 74 75 Mills p 75 Richardson p 32 Richardson p 31 a b c Richardson p 33 a b Richardson p 34 George Miller On Fairness and Efficiency The Policy Press 2000 ISBN 978 1861342218 p 344 Christine Kinealy A Death Dealing Famine The Great Hunger in Ireland Pluto Press 1997 ISBN 978 0745310749 p 59 Stephen J Lee Aspects of British Political History 1815 1914 Routledge 1994 ISBN 978 0415090063 p 83 Erik Gartzke Economic Freedom and Peace in Economic Freedom of the World 2005 Annual Report Vancouver Fraser Institute 2005 Oneal J R Russet B M 1997 The Classical Liberals Were Right Democracy Interdependence and Conflict 1950 1985 International Studies Quarterly 41 2 267 294 doi 10 1111 1468 2478 00042 Michael Doyle Ways of War and Peace Realism Liberalism and Socialism New York Norton 1997 p 237 ISBN 0393969479 Edward P Stringham Commerce Markets and Peace Richard Cobden s Enduring Lessons Independent Review 9 no 1 2004 105 110 115 Immanuel Kant The Perpetual Peace Donald Markwell John Maynard Keynes and International Relations Economic Paths to War and Peace Archived 1 September 2017 at the Wayback Machine Oxford University Press 2006 ch 1 John Maynard Keynes and International Relations Economic Paths to War and Peace Archived 5 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine Donald Markwell 2006 reviewed by M S Lawlor February 2008 Lucien Jaume Hobbes and the Philosophical Sources of Liberalism The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes Leviathan 211 Bertrand Badie Dirk Berg Schlosser Leonardo Morlino eds 2011 International Encyclopedia of Political Science Sage p 44 ISBN 978 1483305394 thought of classical liberal figures such as John Locke Adam Smith Immanuel Kant Giuseppe Mazzini and John Stuart Mill Liberalism rediscovered The Economist 5 February 1998 Retrieved 28 June 2017 James Mark Shields 2017 Against Harmony Progressive and Radical Buddhism in Modern Japan Oxford University Press p 169 ISBN 9780190664008 Robert Leeson 2018 Hayek A Collaborative Biography Part XI Orwellian Rectifiers Mises Evil Seed of Christianity and the Free Market Welfare StateArchival Insights into the Evolution of Economics Springer p 468 ISBN 9783319774282 Friedrich Naumann was regarded as a classical liberal while also promoting National Socialism P G C van Schie Gerrit Voermann 2006 The Dividing Line Between Success and Failure A Comparison of Liberalism in the Netherlands and Germany in the 19th and 20th Centuries LIT Verlag Munsters p 64 By the turn of the century the left liberals Friedrich Naumann and Barth sought to redefine classical liberalism for the needs of the rising industrial society After the Soviet Empire Legacies and Pathways BRILL 2015 p 143 ISBN 9789004291454 They had all forgotten that the classical liberal Karl Popper was definitely opposed to the big bang of rapid changes in whole societal systems He assumed that changes of this type were bound to cause massive human suffering Walter B Weimer 2022 Retrieving Liberalism from Rationalist Constructivism Volume II Basics of a Liberal Psychological Social and Moral Order Springer Nature p 255 ISBN 9783030954772 a b Christian Delacampagne 2022 A History of Philosophy in the Twentieth Century JHU Press p 255 ISBN 9780801868146 Among these figures one finds two defenders of the classical liberal tradition Karl Popper and Raymond Aron John Gray 2018 Liberalisms Essays in Political Philosophy Routledge ISBN 9780415563758 Liou Kuo Tsai 1998 Handbook of Economic Development CRC Press p 357 ISBN 978 1461671756 In praise of Australia s Liberal Democrats The Spectator Posicionamentos Maxime Bernier s new party stakes out classical liberal values Don Pittis Archived from the original on 23 May 2022 Retrieved 21 July 2022 Un manifiesto liberal 24 September 2018 Thomas J DiLorenzo ed 2016 The Problem with Socialism Simon and Schuster p 82 Marco Lisi ed 2018 Party System Change the European Crisis and the State of Democracy Routledge Mark Salmon Culture Smart ed 2019 Denmark Culture Smart The Essential Guide to Customs amp Culture Kuperard ISBN 978 1787029187 Liberal Alliance Formerly New Alliance Liberal Alliance are a center right classical liberal party formed in 2007 by former members of the Social Liberal Party and the Conservative People s Party Arturo Bris ed 2021 The Right Place How National Competitiveness Makes or Breaks Companies Routledge ISBN 978 1000327793 Christopher J Bickerton Carlo Invernizzi Accetti ed 2021 Technopopulism The New Logic of Democratic Politics Oxford University Press p 60 Macron Scrambling to Salvage Liberal Reputation Worldwide After Targeting Islam The Daily Beast 12 November 2020 Retrieved 11 December 2021 Slavoj Zizek ed 2019 Like a Thief in Broad Daylight Power in the Era of Post Human Capitalism Seven Stories Press William Smaldone ed 2019 European Socialism A Concise History with Documents Rowman amp Littlefields Brian Duignan ed 2013 The Science and Philosophy of Politics Britannica Educational Publishing p 121 ISBN 978 1615307487 Loksatta Government by the people Loksatta Party Archived from the original on 15 March 2018 Retrieved 11 April 2016 Natacha Gagne ed 2013 Being M ori in the City Indigenous Everyday Life in Auckland University of Toronto Press p 3 Our classical liberal tribe Speech www act org nz ACT New Zealand 23 February 2015 Archived from the original on 11 February 2017 Retrieved 8 February 2017 Jens Rydstrom 2011 Odd Couples A History of Gay Marriage in Scandinavia aksant p 97 ISBN 9789052603810 Marek Payerhin ed 2016 Nordic Central and Southeastern Europe 2016 2017 Rowman amp Littlefield p 339 ISBN 978 1475828979 Another new movement was the Modern of Ryszard Petru later styled as Modern Nowoczesna or simply N This classical liberal party created by an economist Ryszard Petru received 7 6 of votes and 28 seats in the Sejm it later gained an additional deputy who left Kukiz 15 Alan G Smith 2016 A Comparative Introduction to Political Science Contention and Cooperation Rowman amp Littlefield p 207 ISBN 9781442252608 Cotrim Figueiredo Iniciativa Liberal nao ganhou estas eleicoes mas ganhou o futuro Observador pt Political parties and elections in Slovakia Online Slovakia Retrieved 3 April 2018 Who is Who On the EU Critical Right of Centre PDF Europe of Freedom and Direct Democracy 2018 p 43 Archived from the original PDF on 28 March 2019 Freedom and Solidarity Slovak Sloboda a Solidarita SaS Limited government EU sceptic Euro critical classical Liberal Libertarian Yusuf Sayed and Robert Van Niekerk Ideology and the good society in South Africa the education policies of the Democratic Alliance PDF Southern African Review of Education 23 1 52 69 ISSN 1563 4418 Archived PDF from the original on 19 August 2019 Liberalismens grundvarden PDF Sv se Archived PDF from the original on 8 August 2020 Retrieved 21 February 2022 Medeiros Evan S 2008 Pacific Currents The Responses of U S Allies and Security Partners in East Asia to China s Rise RAND p 130 Introduction to The Liberal Party Policies liberal org uk Archived from the original on 24 May 2022 Retrieved 12 July 2022 Nosotros 23 May 2023 Mommsen Hans 1996 The Rise and Fall of Weimar Democracy University of North Carolina Press p 58 ISBN 0807822493 Das Gurcharan 2002 The Elephant Paradigm Penguin p 244 Jan Erik Lane Svante O Ersson 1999 Politics and Society in Western Europe Sage Publications p 101 ISBN 978 0761958628 Retrieved 19 July 2013 The Times 31 December 1872 p 5 Wilson Tadd 1 December 1998 The Culture of Classical Liberalism Foundation for Economic Education Retrieved 3 July 2023 Vieira Helena 1 February 2017 The contradiction of classical liberalism and libertarianism LSE Business Review Retrieved 3 July 2023 Sources editConway David 2008 Liberalism Classical In Hamowy Ronald ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA Sage Cato Institute pp 295 298 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 n179 ISBN 978 1412965804 LCCN 2008009151 OCLC 750831024 Archived from the original on 9 January 2023 Retrieved 27 January 2016 De Ruggiero Guido 1959 The History of European Liberalism Boston Beacon Press Dickerson M O Flanagan Thomas O Neill Brenda 2009 An Introduction to Government and Politics A Conceptual Approach Cengage Learning ISBN 978 0176500429 Gray John 1995 Liberalism Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press ISBN 0816628009 Heywood Andrew 2004 Political Theory Third Edition An Introduction Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 0333961803 Hunt E K 2003 Property and Prophets The Evolution of Economic Institutions and Ideologies New York M E Sharpe Inc ISBN 0765606089 Ishiyama John T Breuning Marijike 2010 21st Century Political Science A Reference Handbook Vol 1 London Sage Publications ISBN 978 1412969017 Lieber Francis 1881 The Miscellaneous Writings of Francis Lieber Volume II Contributions to Political Science Philadelphia J B Lippincott amp Co Mills John 2002 A Critical History of Economics Basingstoke England Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 0333971302 Richardson James L 2001 Contending Liberalisms in World Politics Ideology and Power Boulder Colorado Lynne Rienner Publishers ISBN 155587939X Turner Rachel S 2008 Neo Liberal Ideology History Concepts and Policies History Concepts and Policies Edinburgh Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 0748632350 Van de Haar Edwin 2015 Degrees of Freedom Liberal Political Philosophy and Ideology New Brunswick NJ Transaction Publishers ISBN 978 1412855754 Vincent Andrew 2009 Modern Political Ideologies Third ed Chichester England Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 1405154956 Further reading editAlan Bullock and Maurice Shock ed 1967 The Liberal Tradition From Fox to Keynes Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN missing Epstein Richard A 2014 The Classical Liberal Constitution The Uncertain Quest for Limited Government Cambridge Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674724891 Katherine Henry 2011 Liberalism and the Culture of Security The Nineteenth Century Rhetoric of Reform University of Alabama Press draws on literary and other writings to study the debates over liberty and tyranny ISBN missing Donald Markwell 2006 John Maynard Keynes and International Relations Economic Paths to War and Peace Oxford England Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0198292364 Mayne Alan J 1999 From politics past to politics future an integrated analysis of current and emergent paradigms Westport Conn reenwood Publishing Group ISBN 0275961516 Gustav Pollak ed 1915 Fifty Years of American Idealism 1865 1915 short history of The Nation plus numerous excerpts most by Edwin Lawrence Godkin External links edit nbsp Quotations related to Classical liberalism at Wikiquote nbsp The dictionary definition of classical liberalism at Wiktionary nbsp Media related to Classical liberalism at Wikimedia Commons Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Classical liberalism amp oldid 1195408987, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.