fbpx
Wikipedia

Madhyamaka

Mādhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; Chinese: 中觀見; pinyin: Zhōngguān Jìan; Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ ; dbu ma pa), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no svabhāva doctrine"), refers to a tradition of Buddhist philosophy and practice founded by the Indian Buddhist monk and philosopher Nāgārjuna (c. 150 – c. 250 CE).[1][2][3] The foundational text of the Mādhyamaka tradition is Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā ("Root Verses on the Middle Way"). More broadly, Mādhyamaka also refers to the ultimate nature of phenomena as well as the non-conceptual realization of ultimate reality that is experienced in meditation.[4]

Classical Indian Mādhyamika thinkers. Clockwise from upper left: Nāgārjuna (founder), Bhāvavivēka and Candrakīrti (commentators), Śāntarakṣita (synthesized the school with Yogācāra).

Since the 4th century CE onwards, Mādhyamaka philosophy had a major influence on the subsequent development of the Mahāyāna Buddhist tradition,[5] especially following the spread of Buddhism throughout Asia.[5][6] It is the dominant interpretation of Buddhist philosophy in Tibetan Buddhism and has also been influential in East Asian Buddhist thought.[5][7]

According to the classical Indian Mādhyamika thinkers, all phenomena (dharmas) are empty (śūnya) of "nature",[8] of any "substance" or "essence" (svabhāva) which could give them "solid and independent existence", because they are dependently co-arisen.[9] But this "emptiness" itself is also "empty": it does not have an existence on its own, nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality.[10][11][12]

Etymology

Madhya is a Sanskrit word meaning "middle". It is cognate with Latin med-iu-s and English mid. The -ma suffix is a superlative, giving madhyama the meaning of "mid-most" or "medium". The -ka suffix is used to form adjectives, thus madhyamaka means "middling". The -ika suffix is used to form possessives, with a collective sense, thus mādhyamika mean "belonging to the mid-most" (the -ika suffix regularly causes a lengthening of the first vowel and elision of the final -a).

In a Buddhist context, these terms refer to the "middle path" (madhyama pratipada), which refers to right view (samyagdṛṣṭi) which steers clear of the metaphysical extremes of annihilationism (ucchedavāda) and eternalism (śassatavāda). For example, the Sanskrit Kātyāyanaḥsūtra states that though the world "relies on a duality of existence and non-existence", the Buddha teaches a correct view which understands that:[13]

Arising in the world, Kātyayana, seen and correctly understood just as it is, shows there is no non-existence in the world. Cessation in the world, Kātyayana, seen and correctly understood just as it is, shows there is no permanent existence in the world. Thus avoiding both extremes the Tathāgata teaches a dharma by the middle path (madhyamayā pratipadā). That is: this being, that becomes; with the arising of this, that arises. With ignorance as condition there is volition ... [to be expanded with the standard formula of the 12 links of dependent origination]”[14]

Though all Buddhist schools saw themselves as defending a middle path in accord with the Buddhist teachings, the name madhyamaka refers to a school of Mahayana philosophy associated with Nāgārjuna and his commentators. The term mādhyamika refers to adherents of the madhyamaka school.

Note that in both words the stress is on the first syllable.

Philosophical overview

Svabhāva, what madhyamaka denies

Central to madhyamaka philosophy is śūnyatā, "emptiness", and this refers to the central idea that dharmas are empty of svabhāva.[15] This term has been translated variously as essence, intrinsic nature, inherent existence, own being and substance.[16][17][15] Furthermore, according to Richard P. Hayes, svabhava can be interpreted as either "identity" or as "causal independence".[18] Likewise, Westerhoff notes that svabhāva is a complex concept that has ontological and cognitive aspects. The ontological aspects include svabhāva as essence, as a property which makes an object what it is, as well as svabhāva as substance, meaning, as the madhyamaka thinker Candrakirti defines it, something that does "not depend on anything else".[15]

It is substance-svabhāva, the objective and independent existence of any object or concept, which madhyamaka arguments mostly focus on refuting.[19] A common structure which madhyamaka uses to negate svabhāva is the catuṣkoṭi ("four corners" or tetralemma), which roughly consists of four alternatives: a proposition is true; a proposition is false; a proposition is both true and false; a proposition is neither true nor false. Some of the major topics discussed by classical madhyamaka include causality, change, and personal identity.[20]

Madhyamaka's denial of svabhāva does not mean a nihilistic denial of all things, for in a conventional everyday sense, madhyamaka does accept that one can speak of "things", and yet ultimately these things are empty of inherent existence.[21] Furthermore, "emptiness" itself is also "empty": it does not have an existence on its own, nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality.[10][11][12]

Svabhāva's cognitive aspect is merely a superimposition (samāropa) that beings make when they perceive and conceive of things. In this sense then, emptiness does not exist as some kind of primordial reality, but it is simply a corrective to a mistaken conception of how things exist.[17] This idea of svabhāva that madhyamaka denies is then not just a conceptual philosophical theory, but it is a cognitive distortion that beings automatically impose on the world, such as when we regard the five aggregates as constituting a single self. Candrakirti compares it to someone who suffers from vitreous floaters that cause the illusion of hairs appearing in their visual field.[22] This cognitive dimension of svabhāva means that just understanding and assenting to madhyamaka reasoning is not enough to end the suffering caused by our reification of the world, just like understanding how an optical illusion works does not make it stop functioning. What is required is a kind of cognitive shift (termed realization) in the way the world appears and therefore some kind of practice to lead to this shift.[23] As Candrakirti says:

For one on the road of cyclic existence who pursues an inverted view due to ignorance, a mistaken object such as the superimposition (samāropa) on the aggregates appears as real, but it does not appear to one who is close to the view of the real nature of things.[24]

Much of madhyamaka philosophy centers on showing how various essentialist ideas have absurd conclusions through reductio ad absurdum arguments (known as prasanga in Sanskrit). Chapter 15 of Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā centers on the words svabhava [note 1] parabhava[note 2] bhava [note 3] and abhava.[note 4] According to Peter Harvey:

Nagarjuna's critique of the notion of own-nature[note 5] (Mk. ch. 15) argues that anything which arises according to conditions, as all phenomena do, can have no inherent nature, for what is depends on what conditions it. Moreover, if there is nothing with own-nature, there can be nothing with 'other-nature' (para-bhava), i.e. something which is dependent for its existence and nature on something else which has own-nature. Furthermore, if there is neither own-nature nor other-nature, there cannot be anything with a true, substantial existent nature (bhava). If there is no true existent, then there can be no non-existent (abhava).[30]

An important element of madhyamaka refutation is that the classical Buddhist doctrine of dependent arising (the idea that every phenomena is dependent on other phenomena) cannot be reconciled with "a conception of self-nature or substance" and that therefore essence theories are contrary not only to the Buddhist scriptures but to the very ideas of causality and change.[31] Any enduring essential nature would prevent any causal interaction, or any kind of origination. For things would simply always have been, and will always continue to be, without any change.[32][note 6] As Nāgārjuna writes in the MMK:

We state that conditioned origination is emptiness. It is mere designation depending on something, and it is the middle path. (24.18) Since nothing has arisen without depending on something, there is nothing that is not empty. (24.19)[33][better source needed]

The two truths

Beginning with Nāgārjuna, madhyamaka discerns two levels of truth, conventional truth (everyday commonsense reality) and ultimate truth (emptiness).[10][34] Ultimately, madhyamaka argues that all phenomena are empty of svabhava and only exist in dependence on other causes, conditions and concepts. Conventionally, madhyamaka holds that beings do perceive concrete objects which they are aware of empirically.[35] In madhyamaka this phenomenal world is the limited truth - saṃvṛti satya, which means "to cover", "to conceal", or "obscure". (and thus it is a kind of ignorance)[36][37] Saṃvṛti is also said to mean "conventional", as in a customary, norm based, agreed upon truth (like linguistic conventions) and it is also glossed as vyavahāra-satya (transactional truth).[37] Finally, Chandrakirti also has a third explanation of saṃvṛti, which is “mutual dependence” (parasparasaṃbhavana).[37]

This seeming reality does not really exist as the highest truth realized by wisdom which is paramartha satya (parama is literally "supreme or ultimate", and artha means "object, purpose, or actuality"), and yet it has a kind of conventional reality which has its uses for reaching liberation.[38] This limited truth includes everything, including the Buddha himself, the teachings (dharma), liberation and even Nāgārjuna's own arguments.[39][better source needed] This two truth schema which did not deny the importance of convention allowed Nāgārjuna to defend himself against charges of nihilism; understanding both correctly meant seeing the middle way:

"Without relying upon convention, the ultimate fruit is not taught. Without understanding the ultimate, nirvana is not attained."[note 7]

The limited, perceived reality is an experiential reality or a nominal reality which beings impute on the ultimate reality. It is not an ontological reality with substantial or independent existence.[35][34] Hence, the two truths are not two metaphysical realities; instead, according to Karl Brunnholzl, "the two realities refer to just what is experienced by two different types of beings with different types and scopes of perception".[41] As Candrakirti says:

It is through the perfect and the false seeing of all entities

That the entities that are thus found bear two natures.

The object of perfect seeing is true reality,

And false seeing is seeming reality.

This means that the distinction between the two truths is primarily epistemological and dependent on the cognition of the observer, not ontological.[41] As Shantideva writes, there are "two kinds of world", "the one of yogins and the one of common people".[42] The seeming reality is the world of samsara because conceiving of concrete and unchanging objects leads to clinging and suffering. As Buddhapalita states: "unskilled persons whose eye of intelligence is obscured by the darkness of delusion conceive of an essence of things and then generate attachment and hostility with regard to them".[43]

According to Hayes, the two truths may also refer to two different goals in life: the highest goal of nirvana, and the lower goal of "commercial good". The highest goal is the liberation from attachment, both material and intellectual.[44]

The nature of ultimate reality

According to Paul Williams, Nāgārjuna associates emptiness with the ultimate truth but his conception of emptiness is not some kind of Absolute, but rather it is the very absence of true existence with regards to the conventional reality of things and events in the world.[45] Because the ultimate is itself empty, it is also explained as a "transcendence of deception" and hence is a kind of apophatic truth which experiences the lack of substance.[3]

Because the nature of ultimate reality is said to be empty, empty even of "emptiness" itself, both the concept of "emptiness" and the very framework of the two truths are also mere conventional realities, not part of the ultimate. This is often called "the emptiness of emptiness" and refers to the fact that even though madhyamikas speak of emptiness as the ultimate unconditioned nature of things, this emptiness is itself empty of any real existence.[46]

The two truths themselves are therefore just a practical tool used to teach others, but do not exist within the actual meditative equipoise that realizes the ultimate.[47] As Candrakirti says: "the noble ones who have accomplished what is to be accomplished do not see anything that is delusive or not delusive".[48] From within the experience of the enlightened ones there is only one reality which appears non-conceptually, as Nāgārjuna says in the Sixty stanzas on reasoning: "that nirvana is the sole reality, is what the Victors have declared."[49] Bhāvaviveka's Madhyamakahrdayakārikā describes the ultimate truth through a negation of all four possibilities of the catuskoti:[50]

Its character is neither existent, nor nonexistent, / Nor both existent and nonexistent, nor neither. / Centrists should know true reality / That is free from these four possibilities.

Atisha describes the ultimate as "here, there is no seeing and no seer, no beginning and no end, just peace.... It is nonconceptual and nonreferential ... it is inexpressible, unobservable, unchanging, and unconditioned."[51] Because of the non-conceptual nature of the ultimate, according to Brunnholzl, the two truths are ultimately inexpressible as either "one" or "different".[52]

The Middle Way

As noted by Roger Jackson, some non-Buddhist writers, like some Buddhist writers both ancient and modern, have argued that the madhyamaka philosophy is nihilistic. This claim has been challenged by others who argue that it is a Middle Way (madhyamāpratipad) between nihilism and eternalism.[53][54][55] Madhyamaka philosophers themselves explicitly rejected the nihilist interpretation from the outset: Nāgārjuna writes: "through explaining true reality as it is, the seeming samvrti does not become disrupted."[56] Candrakirti also responds to the charge of nihilism in his Lucid Words:

Therefore, emptiness is taught in order to completely pacify all discursiveness without exception. So if the purpose of emptiness is the complete peace of all discursiveness and you just increase the web of discursiveness by thinking that the meaning of emptiness is nonexistence, you do not realize the purpose of emptiness [at all].[57]

This although some scholars (e.g., Murti) interpret emptiness as described by Nāgārjuna as a Buddhist transcendental absolute, other scholars (such as David Kalupahana) consider this claim a mistake, since then emptiness teachings could not be characterized as a middle way.[58][59]

Madhyamaka thinkers also argue that since things have the nature of lacking true existence or own being (niḥsvabhāva), all things are mere conceptual constructs (prajñaptimatra) because they are just impermanent collections of causes and conditions.[60] This also applies to the principle of causality itself, since everything is dependently originated.[61] Therefore, in madhyamaka, phenomena appear to arise and cease, but in an ultimate sense they do not arise or remain as inherently existent phenomena.[62][63][note 8] This tenet is held to show that views of absolute or eternalist existence (such as the Hindu ideas of Brahman or sat-dravya) and nihilism are both equally untenable.[62][64][21] These two views are considered to be the two extremes that madhyamaka steers clear from. The first is essentialism[65] or eternalism (sastavadava)[21] -- a belief that things inherently or substantially exist and are therefore efficacious objects of craving and clinging;[65] Nagarjuna argues that we naively and innately perceive things as substantial, and it is this predisposition which is the root delusion that lies at the basis of all suffering.[65] The second extreme is nihilism[65] or annihilationism (ucchedavada)[21] -- encompassing views that could lead one to believe that there is no need to be responsible for one's actions -- such as the idea that one is annihilated at death or that nothing has causal effects -- but also the view that absolutely nothing exists.

The usefulness of reason

In madhyamaka, reason and debate are understood as a means to an end (liberation), and therefore they must be founded on the wish to help oneself and others end suffering.[66] Reason and logical arguments, however (such as those employed by classical Indian philosophers, i.e., pramana), are also seen as being empty of any true validity or reality. They serve only as conventional remedies for our delusions.[67] Nāgārjuna's Vigrahavyāvartanī famously attacked the notion that one could establish a valid cognition or epistemic proof (pramana):

If your objects are well established through valid cognitions, tell us how you establish these valid cognitions. If you think they are established through other valid cognitions, there is an infinite regress. Then, the first one is not established, nor are the middle ones, nor the last. If these [valid cognitions] are established even without valid cognition, what you say is ruined. In that case, there is an inconsistency, And you ought to provide an argument for this distinction.[68]

Candrakirti comments on this statement by stating that madhyamaka does not completely deny the use of pramanas conventionally, and yet ultimately they do not have a foundation:

Therefore we assert that mundane objects are known through the four kinds of authoritative cognition. They are mutually dependent: when there is authoritative cognition, there are objects of knowledge; when there are objects of knowledge, there is authoritative cognition. But neither authoritative cognition nor objects of knowledge exist inherently.[69]

To the charge that if Nāgārjuna's arguments and words are also empty they therefore lack the power to refute anything, Nāgārjuna responds that:

My words are without nature. Therefore, my thesis is not ruined. Since there is no inconsistency, I do not have to state an argument for a distinction.[70]

Nāgārjuna goes on:

Just as one magical creation may be annihilated by another magical creation, and one illusory person by another person produced by an illusionist, this negation is the same.[71]

Shantideva makes the same point: "thus, when one's son dies in a dream, the conception "he does not exist" removes the thought that he does exist, but it is also delusive".[72] In other words, madhyamaka thinkers accept that their arguments, just like all things, are not ultimately valid in some foundational sense. But one is still able to use the opponent's own reasoning apparatus in the conventional field to refute their theories and help them see their errors. This remedial deconstruction does not replace false theories of existence with other ones, but simply dissolves all views, including the very fictional system of epistemic warrants (pramanas) used to establish them.[73] The point of madhyamaka reasoning is not to establish any abstract validity or universal truth, it is simply a pragmatic project aimed at ending delusion and suffering.[74]

Nāgārjuna also argues that madhyamaka only negates things conventionally, since ultimately, there is nothing there to negate: "I do not negate anything and there is also nothing to be negated."[75] Therefore, it is only from the perspective of those who cling to the existence of things that it seems as if something is being negated. In truth, madhyamaka is not annihilating something, merely elucidating that this so-called existence never existed in the first place.[75]

Thus, madhyamaka uses language to make clear the limits of our concepts. Ultimately, reality cannot be depicted by concepts.[10][76] According to Jay Garfield, this creates a sort of tension in madhyamaka literature, since it has use some concepts to convey its teachings.[76]

Soteriology

For madhyamaka, the realization of emptiness is not just a satisfactory theory about the world, but a key understanding which allows one to reach liberation or nirvana. As Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā ("Root Verses on the Middle Way") puts it:

With the cessation of ignorance, formations will not arise. Moreover, the cessation of ignorance occurs through right understanding. Through the cessation of this and that, this and that will not come about. The entire mass of suffering thereby completely ceases.[77]

The words "this" and "that" allude to the mind's profound addiction to dualism, but also and more specifically to the mind that has not yet grasped the reality of dependent origination. The insight of dependent origination -- that nothing arises or happens independently, that everything is rooted in or "made of" something else, and conditioned by other things, each of which are likewise made of and conditioned by other things in the same way, so that nothing at all "is" independently -- is central to the fundamental Buddhist analysis of the arising of suffering and the liberation from it. Therefore, according to Nāgārjuna, the cognitive shift which sees the nonexistence of svabhāva leads to the cessation of the first link in this chain of suffering, which then leads to the ending of the entire chain of causes and thus, of all suffering.[77] Nāgārjuna adds:

Liberation (moksa) results from the cessation of actions (karman) and defilements (klesa). Actions and defilements result from representations (vikalpa). These [come] from false imagining (prapañca). False imagining stops in emptiness (sunyata). (18.5)[78][better source needed]

Therefore, the ultimate aim of understanding emptiness is not philosophical insight as such, but the actualization of a liberated mind which does not cling to anything. To encourage this awakening, meditation on emptiness may proceed in stages, starting with the emptiness of self, of objects and of mental states,[79] culminating in a "natural state of nonreferential freedom".[80][note 9]

Moreover, the path to understanding ultimate truth is not one that negates or invalidates relative truths (especially truths about the path to awakening). Instead it is only through properly understanding and using relative truth that the ultimate can be attained, as Bhāvaviveka maintains:

In order to guide beginners a method is taught, comparable to the steps of a staircase that leads to perfect Buddhahood. Ultimate reality is only to be entered once we have understood seeming reality.[81]

Does madhyamaka have a position?

Nāgārjuna is famous for arguing that his philosophy was not a view, and that he in fact did not take any position (paksa) or thesis (pratijña) whatsoever since this would just be another form of clinging to some form of existence.[82][69] In his Vigrahavyāvartanī , Nāgārjuna states:

If I had any position, I thereby would be at fault. Since I have no position, I am not at fault at all. If there were anything to be observed through direct perception and the other instances [of valid cognition], it would be something to be established or rejected. However, since no such thing exists, I cannot be criticized.[83]

Likewise in his Sixty Stanzas on Reasoning, Nāgārjuna says: "By taking any standpoint whatsoever, you will be snatched by the cunning snakes of the afflictions. Those whose minds have no standpoint will not be caught."[84]

Randall Collins argues that for Nāgārjuna, ultimate reality is simply the idea that "no concepts are intelligible", while Ferrer emphasizes that Nāgārjuna criticized those whose mind held any "positions and beliefs", including the view of emptiness. As Nāgārjuna says: "The Victorious Ones have announced that emptiness is the relinquishing of all views. Those who are possessed of the view of emptiness are said to be incorrigible."[85][86] Aryadeva echoes this idea in his Four Hundred Verses:

"First, one puts an end to what is not meritorious. In the middle, one puts an end to identity. Later, one puts an end to all views. Those who understand this are skilled."[87]

Other writers, however, do seem to affirm emptiness as a specific madhyamaka thesis or view. Shantideva for example says "one cannot uphold any faultfinding in the thesis of emptiness" and Bhavaviveka's Blaze of Reasoning says: "as for our thesis, it is the emptiness of nature, because this is the nature of phenomena".[88] Jay Garfield notes that Nāgārjuna and Candrakirti both make positive arguments, and cites both the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā ("Root Verses on the Middle Way") --"There does not exist anything that is not dependently arisen. Therefore there does not exist anything that is not empty" -- and Candrakirti's commentary on it: "We assert the statement, 'Emptiness itself is a designation.'"[69]

These positions are not really in contradiction, however, since madhyamaka can be said to have the "thesis of emptiness" only conventionally, in the context of debating or explaining it. According to Karl Brunnholzl, even though madhyamaka thinkers may express a thesis pedagogically, what they deny is that "they have any thesis that involves real existence or reference points, or any thesis that is to be defended from their own point of view".[89]

Brunnholzl underlines that madhyamaka analysis applies to all systems of thought, ideas and concepts, including madhyamaka itself. This is because the nature of madhyamaka is "the deconstruction of any system and conceptualization whatsoever, including itself".[90] In the Root verses on the Middle Way, Nāgārjuna illustrates this point:

By the flaw of having views about emptiness, those of little understanding are ruined, just as when incorrectly seizing a snake or mistakenly practicing an awareness-mantra.[91]

Origins and sources

The madhyamaka school is usually considered to have been founded by Nāgārjuna, though it may have existed earlier.[92] Various scholars have noted that some of themes in the work of Nāgārjuna can also be found in earlier Buddhist sources.

Early Buddhist Texts

It is well known that the only sutra that Nāgārjuna explicitly cites in his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā (Chapter 15.7) is the "Advice to Kātyāyana.". He writes, "according to the Instructions to Kātyāyana, both existence and nonexistence are criticized by the Blessed One who opposed being and non-being."[93] This appears to have been a Sanskrit version of the Kaccānagotta Sutta (Saṃyutta Nikāya ii.16-17 / SN 12.15, with parallel in the Chinese Saṃyuktāgama 301).[93] The Kaccānagotta Sutta itself says:

This world, Kaccāna, for the most part depends on a duality–upon the notion of existence and the notion of nonexistence. But for one who sees the origin of the world as it really is with correct wisdom, there is no notion of nonexistence in regard to the world. And for one who sees the cessation of the world as it really is with correct wisdom, there is no notion of existence in regard to the world.[93]

Joseph Walser also points out that verse six of chapter 15 contains an allusion to the "Mahahatthipadopama sutta", another early sutra of the Nidanavagga, the collection which also contains the Kaccānagotta, and which contains various sutras that focus on the avoidance of extreme views, which are all held to be associated with either the extreme of eternality (sasvata) or the extreme of disruption (uccheda).[93] Another allusion to an early Buddhist text noted by Walser occurs in Nāgārjuna's Ratnavali chapter 1, where he makes reference to a statement in the Kevaddha sutta.[94]

Some scholars, like Tillman Vetter and Luis Gomez, have also seen some passages from the early Aṭṭhakavagga (Pali, "Octet Chapter") and the Pārāyanavagga (Pali, "Way to the Far Shore Chapter"), which focusing on letting go of all views, as teaching a kind of "Proto-Mādhyamika."[note 10][95][96] Other scholars such as Paul Fuller and Alexander Wynne have rejected the arguments of Gomez and Vetter.[97][98][note 11]

Finally, the Dazhidulun, a text attributed to Nāgārjuna in the Chinese tradition (though this attribution has been questioned), cites the Sanskrit Arthavargīya sūtra (which parallels the Aṭṭhakavagga) in its discussion of ultimate truth.[99]

Abhidharma and early Buddhist schools

The madhyamaka school has been perhaps simplistically regarded as a reaction against the development of Buddhist abhidharma, however according to Joseph Walser, this is problematic.[100] In abhidharma, dharmas are characterized by defining traits (lakṣaṇa) or own-existence (svabhāva). The Abhidharmakośabhāṣya states for example: "dharma means 'upholding,' [namely], upholding intrinsic nature (svabhāva)", while the Mahāvibhāṣā states "intrinsic nature is able to uphold its own identity and not lose it".[101] However this does not mean that all abhidharma systems hold that dharmas exist independently in an ontological sense, since all Buddhist schools hold that (most) dharmas are dependently originated, this doctrine being a central core Buddhist view. Therefore, in abhidharma, svabhāva is typically something which arises dependent on other conditions and qualities.[101]

Svabhāva in the early abhidharma systems then, is not a kind of ontological essentialism, but it is a way to categorize dharmas according to their distinctive characteristics. According to Noa Ronkin, the idea of svabhava evolved towards ontological dimension in the Sarvāstivādin Vaibhasika school's interpretation, which began to also use the term dravya which means "real existence".[101] This then, may have been the shift which Nagarjuna sought to attack when he targets certain Sarvastivada tenets.

However, the relationship between madhyamaka and abhidharma is complex, as Joseph Walser notes, "Nagarjuna's position vis-à-vis abhidharma is neither a blanket denial nor a blanket acceptance. Nagarjuna's arguments entertain certain abhidharmic standpoints while refuting others."[100] One example can be seen in Nagarjuna's Ratnavali which supports the study of a list of 57 moral faults which Nagarjuna takes from the Ksudravastuka (an abhidharma texts that is part of the Sarvastivada Dharmaskandha).[102] Abhidharmic analysis figures prominently in madhyamaka treatises, and authoritative commentators like Candrakīrti emphasize that abhidharmic categories function as a viable (and favored) system of conventional truths - they are more refined than ordinary categories, and they are not dependent on either the extreme of eternalism or on the extreme view of the discontinuity of karma, as the non-Buddhist categories of the time did.

Walser also notes that Nagarjuna's theories have much in common with the view of a sub-sect of the Mahasamgikas called the Prajñaptivadins, who held that suffering was prajñapti (designation by provisional naming) "based on conditioned entities that are themselves reciprocally designated" (anyonya prajñapti).[103] David Burton argues that for Nagarjuna, "dependently arisen entities have merely conceptually constructed existence (prajñaptisat)".[103] Commenting on this, Walser writes that "Nagarjuna is arguing for a thesis that the Prajñaptivádins already held, using a concept of prajñapti that they were already using."[57]

Mahāyāna sūtras

According to David Seyfort Ruegg, the main canonical Mahāyāna sutra sources of the Madhyamaka school are the Prajñāpāramitā, Ratnakūṭa and Avataṃsaka literature.[104] Other sutras which were widely cited by Madhamikas include the Vimalakīrtinirdeṣa, the Śuraṃgamasamādhi, the Saddharmapuṇḍarīka, the Daśabhūmika, the Akṣayamatinirdeśa, the Tathāgataguhyaka, and the Kāśyapaparivarta.[104]

Ruegg notes that in Candrakīrti's Prasannapadā and Madhyamakāvatāra, in addition to the Prajñāpāramitā, "we find the Akṣayamatinirdeśa, Anavataptahradāpasaṃkramaṇa, Upāliparipṛcchā, Kāśyapaparivarta, Gaganagañja, Tathāgataguhya, Daśabhūmika, Dṛḍhādhyāśaya, Dhāraṇīśvararāja, Pitāputrasamāgama, Mañjuśrīparipṛcchā, Ratnakūṭa, Ratnacūḍaparipṛcchā, Ratnamegha, Ratnākara, Laṅkāvatāra, Lalitavistara, Vimalakirtinirdesa, Śālistamba, Satyadvayāvatāra, Saddharmapuṇḍarīka, Samādhirāja (Candrapradīpa), and Hastikakṣya."[104]

Prajñāpāramitā

Madhyamaka thought is also closely related to a number of Mahāyāna sources; traditionally, the Prajñāpāramitā sūtras are the literature most closely associated with madhyamaka – understood, at least in part, as an exegetical complement to those Sūtras. Traditional accounts also depict Nāgārjuna as retrieving some of the larger Prajñāpāramitā sūtras from the world of the Nāgas (explaining in part the etymology of his name). Prajñā or 'higher cognition' is a recurrent term in Buddhist texts, explained as a synonym of abhidharma, 'insight' (vipaśyanā) and 'analysis of the dharmas' (dharmapravicaya). Within a specifically Mahāyāna context, Prajñā figures as the most prominent in a list of Six Pāramitās ('perfections' or 'perfect masteries') that a Bodhisattva needs to cultivate in order to eventually achieve Buddhahood.

Madhyamaka offers conceptual tools to analyze all possible elements of existence, allowing the practitioner to elicit through reasoning and contemplation the type of view that the Sūtras express more authoritatively (being considered word of the Buddha) but less explicitly (not offering corroborative arguments). The vast Prajñāpāramitā literature emphasizes the development of higher cognition in the context of the Bodhisattva path; thematically, its focus on the emptiness of all dharmas is closely related to the madhyamaka approach. Allusions to the prajñaparamita sutras can be found in Nagarjuna's work. One example is in the opening stanza of the MMK, which seem to allude to the following statement found in two prajñaparamita texts:

And how does he wisely know conditioned co-production? He wisely knows it as neither production, nor stopping, neither cut off nor eternal, neither single nor manifold, neither coming nor going away, as the appeasement of all futile discoursings, and as bliss.[105]

The first stanza of Nagarjuna's MMK meanwhile, state:

I pay homage to the Fully Enlightened One whose true, venerable words teach dependent-origination to be the blissful pacification of all mental proliferation, neither production, nor stopping, neither cut off nor eternal, neither single nor manifold, neither coming, nor going away.[105]

Pyrrhonism

Because of the high degree of similarity between madhyamaka and Pyrrhonism,[106] Thomas McEvilley[107] and Matthew Neale[108][109] suspect that Nāgārjuna was influenced by Greek Pyrrhonist texts imported into India. Pyrrho of Elis (c. 360-c. 270 BCE), who is credited with founding this school of skeptical philosophy, was himself influenced by Buddhist philosophy[110] during his stay in India with Alexander the Great's army.

Indian madhyamaka

 
Nāgārjuna (right) and Āryadeva (middle).

Nāgārjuna

As Jan Westerhoff notes, while Nāgārjuna is "one of the greatest thinkers in the history of Asian philosophy...contemporary scholars agree on hardly any details concerning him". This includes exactly when he lived (it can be narrowed down some time in the first three centuries CE), where he lived (Joseph Walser suggests Amarāvatī in east Deccan) and exactly what constitutes his written corpus.[111]

Numerous texts are attributed to him, but it is at least agreed by some scholars that what is called the "Yukti" (analytical) corpus is the core of his philosophical work. These texts are the "Root verses on the Middle way" (Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, MMK), the "Sixty Stanzas on Reasoning" (Yuktiṣāṣṭika), the "Dispeller of Objections" (Vigrahavyāvartanī), the "Treatise on Pulverization" (Vaidalyaprakaraṇa) and the "Precious Garland" (Ratnāvalī).[112] However, even the attribution of each one of these has been question by some modern scholars, except for the MMK which is by definition seen as his major work.[112]

Nāgārjuna's main goal is often seen by scholars as refuting the essentialism of certain Buddhist abhidharma schools (mainly Vaibhasika) which posited theories of svabhava (essential nature) and also the Hindu Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika schools which posited a theory of ontological substances (dravyatas).[113] In the MMK he used reductio ad absurdum arguments (prasanga) to show that any theory of substance or essence was unsustainable and therefore, phenomena (dharmas) such as change, causality, and sense perception were empty (sunya) of any essential existence. Nāgārjuna also famously equated the emptiness of dharmas with their dependent origination.[114][115][116][note 12]

Because of his philosophical work, Nāgārjuna is seen by some modern interpreters as restoring the Middle Way of the Buddha, which had become challenged by absolutist metaphysical tendencies in certain philosophical quarters.[117][114]

Classical madhyamaka figures

Rāhulabhadra was an early madhyamika, sometimes said to be either a teacher of Nagarjuna or his contemporary and follower. He is most famous for his verses in praise of the Prajñāpāramitā (Skt. Prajñāpāramitāstotra) and Chinese sources maintain that he also composed a commentary on the MMK which was translated by Paramartha.[118]

Nāgārjuna's pupil Āryadeva (3rd century CE) wrote various works on madhyamaka, the most well known of which is his "400 verses". His works are regarded as a supplement to Nāgārjuna's,[119] on which he commented.[120] Āryadeva also wrote refutations of the theories of non-Buddhist Indian philosophical schools.[120]

There are also two commentaries on the MMK which may be by Āryadeva, the Akutobhaya (which has also been regarded as an auto-commentary by Nagarjuna) as well as a commentary which survives only in Chinese (as part of the Chung-Lun, "Middle treatise", Taisho 1564) attributed to a certain "Ch'ing-mu" (aka Pin-lo-chieh, which some scholars have also identified as possibly being Aryadeva).[121] However, Brian C. Bocking, a translator of the Chung-Lung, also states that it is likely the author of this commentary was a certain Vimalāksa, who was Kumarajiva's old Vinaya-master from Kucha.[122]

An influential commentator on Nāgārjuna was Buddhapālita (470–550) who has been interpreted as developing the prāsaṅgika approach to Nāgārjuna's works in his Madhyamakavṛtti (now only extant in Tibetan) which follows the orthodox Madhyamaka method by critiquing essentialism mainly through reductio ad absurdum arguments.[123] Like Nāgārjuna, Buddhapālita's main philosophical method is to show how all philosophical positions are ultimately untenable and self-contradictory, a style of argumentation called prasanga.[123]

Buddhapālita's method is often contrasted with that of Bhāvaviveka (c. 500 – c. 578), who argued in his Prajñāpadīpa (Lamp of Wisdom) for the use of logical arguments using the pramana based epistemology of Indian logicians like Dignāga. In what would become a source of much future debate, Bhāvaviveka criticized Buddhapālita for not putting madhyamaka arguments into proper "autonomous syllogisms" (svatantra).[124] Bhāvaviveka argued that mādhyamika's should always put forth syllogistic arguments to prove the truth of the madhyamaka thesis. Instead of just criticizing other's arguments, a tactic called vitaṇḍā (attacking) which was seen in bad form in Indian philosophical circles, Bhāvaviveka held that madhyamikas must positively prove their position using sources of knowledge (pramanas) agreeable to all parties.[125] He argued that the position of a madhyamaka was simply that phenomena are devoid of an inherent nature.[123] This approach has been labeled the svātantrika style of madhyamaka by Tibetan philosophers and commentators.

Another influential commentator, Candrakīrti (c. 600–650), sought to defend Buddhapālita and critique Bhāvaviveka's position (and Dignāga) that one must construct independent (svatantra) arguments to positively prove the madhyamaka thesis, on the grounds this contains a subtle essentialist commitment.[123] He argued that madhyamikas do not have to argue by svantantra, but can merely show the untenable consequences (prasaṅga) of all philosophical positions put forth by their adversary.[126] Furthermore, for Candrakīrti, there is a problem with assuming that the madhyamika and the essentialist opponent can begin with the same shared premises that are required for this kind of syllogistic reasoning because the essentialist and the madhyamaka do not share a basic understanding of what it means for things to exist in the first place.[127]

Candrakīrti also criticized the Buddhist yogācāra school, which he saw as positing a form of subjective idealism due to their doctrine of "appearance only" (vijñaptimatra). Candrakīrti faults the yogācāra school for not realizing that the nature of consciousness is also a conditioned phenomenon, and for privileging consciousness over its objects ontologically, instead of seeing that everything is empty.[126] Candrakīrti wrote the Prasannapadā (Clear Words), a highly influential commentary on the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā as well as the Madhyamakāvatāra, an introduction to madhyamaka. His works are central to the understanding of madhyamaka in Tibetan Buddhism.

A later svātantrika figure is Avalokitavrata (seventh century), who composed a tika (sub-commentary) on Bhāvaviveka's Prajñāpadīpa and who mentions important figures of the era such as Dharmakirti and Candrakīrti.[128]

Another commentator on Nagarjuna is Bhikshu Vaśitva (Zizai) who composed a commentary on Nagarjuna's Bodhisaṃbhāra that survives in a translation by Dharmagupta in the Chinese canon.[129]

Śāntideva (end 7th century – first half 8th century) is well known for his philosophical poem discussing the bodhisattva path and the six paramitas, the Bodhicaryāvatāra. He united "a deep religiousness and joy of exposure together with the unquestioned Madhyamaka orthodoxy".[130] Later in the 10th century, there were commentators on the works of prasangika authors such as Prajñakaramati who wrote a commentary on the Bodhicaryāvatāra and Jayananda who commented on Candrakīrti's Madhyamakāvatāra.[131]

A lesser known treatise on the six paramitas associated with the madhyamaka school is Ārya Śūra's Pāramitāsamāsa, unlikely to be the same author as that of the Garland of Jatakas.[132]

Other lesser known madhyamikas include Devasarman (fifth to sixth centuries) and Gunamati (the fifth to sixth centuries) both of whom wrote commentaries on the MMK that exist only in Tibetan fragments.[133]

Yogācāra-madhyamaka

According to Ruegg, possibly the earliest figure to work with the two schools was Vimuktisena (early sixth century), a commentator on the Abhisamayalamkara and also is reported to have been a pupil of Bhāvaviveka as well as Vasubandhu.[134]

The seventh and eighth centuries saw a synthesis of the Buddhist yogācāra tradition with madhyamaka, beginning with the work of Śrigupta, Jñānagarbha (Śrigupta's disciple) and his student Śāntarakṣita (8th-century) who, like Bhāvaviveka, also adopted some of the terminology of the Buddhist pramana tradition, in their time best represented by Dharmakīrti.[123][128]

Like the classical madhyamaka, yogācāra-madhyamaka approaches ultimate truth through the prasaṅga method of showing absurd consequences. However, when speaking of conventional reality they also make positive assertions and autonomous arguments like Bhāvaviveka and Dharmakīrti. Śāntarakṣita also subsumed the yogācāra system into his presentation of the conventional, accepting their idealism on a conventional level as a preparation for the ultimate truth of madhyamaka.[123][135]

In his Madhyamakālaṃkāra (verses 92–93), Śāntarakṣita says:

By relying on the Mind Only (cittamatra), know that external entities do not exist. And by relying on this [madhyamaka] system, know that no self at all exists, even in that [mind]. Therefore, due to holding the reigns of logic as one rides the chariots of the two systems, one attains [the path of] the actual Mahayanist.[136]

Śāntarakṣita and his student Kamalaśīla (known for his text on self development and meditation, the Bhavanakrama) were influential in the initial spread of madhyamaka Buddhism to Tibet.[note 13] Haribhadra, another important figure of this school, wrote an influential commentary on the Abhisamayalamkara.

Vajrayana madhyamaka

The madhyamaka philosophy continued to be of major importance during the period of Indian Buddhism when the tantric Vajrayana Buddhism rose to prominence. One of the central Vajrayana madhyamaka philosophers was Arya Nagarjuna (also known as the "tantric Nagarjuna", 7th-8th centuries) who may be the author of the Bodhicittavivarana as well as a commentator on the Guhyasamāja Tantra.[137] Other figures in his lineage include Nagabodhi, Vajrabodhi, Aryadeva-pada and Candrakirti-pada.

Later figures include Bodhibhadra (c. 1000), a Nalanda university master who wrote on philosophy and yoga and who was a teacher of Atiśa Dīpaṃkara Śrījñāna (982 - 1054 CE) who was an influential figure in the transmission of Buddhism to Tibet and wrote the influential Bodhipathapradīpa (Lamp for the Path to Awakening).[138]

Tibetan Buddhism

Madhyamaka philosophy obtained a central position in all the main Tibetan Buddhist schools, all whom consider themselves to be madhyamikas. Madhyamaka thought has been categorized in various ways in India and Tibet.[note 14]

Early transmission

Influential early figures who are important in the transmission of madhyamaka to Tibet include the yogacara-madhyamika Śāntarakṣita (725–788), and his students Haribhadra and Kamalashila (740-795) as well as the later Kadampa figures of Atisha (982–1054) and his pupil Dromtön (1005–1064) who taught madhyamaka by using the works of Bhāviveka and Candrakīrti.[139][140]

The early transmission of Buddhism to Tibet saw these two main strands of philosophical views in debate with each other. The first was the camp which defended the yogacara-madhyamaka interpretation (and thus, svatantrika) centered on the works of the scholars of the Sangphu monastery founded by Ngog Loden Sherab (1059-1109) and also includes Chapa Chokyi Senge (1109-1169).[141]

The second camp was those who championed the work of Candrakirti over the yogacara-madhyamaka interpretation, and included Sangphu monk Patsab Nyima Drag (b. 1055) and Jayananda (fl 12th century).[141] According to John Dunne, it was the madhyamaka interpretation and the works of Candrakirti which became dominant over time in Tibet.[141]

Another very influential figure from this early period is Mabja Jangchub Tsöndrü (d. 1185), who wrote an important commentary on Nagarjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. Mabja was a student of both the Dharmakirtian Chapa and the Candrakirti scholar Patsab and his work shows an attempt to steer a middle course between their views. Mabja affirms the conventional usefulness of Buddhist pramāṇa, but also accepts Candrakirti's prasangika views.[142] Mabja's Madhyamaka scholarship was very influential on later Tibetan Madhyamikas such as Longchenpa, Tsongkhapa, Gorampa, and Mikyö Dorje.[143]

Prāsaṅgika and Svātantrika interpretations

In Tibetan Buddhist scholarship, a distinction began to be made between the Autonomist (Svātantrika, rang rgyud pa) and Consequentialist (Prāsaṅgika, Thal 'gyur pa) approaches to madhyamaka reasoning. The distinction was one invented by Tibetans, and not one made by classical Indian madhyamikas.[144] Tibetans mainly use the terms to refer to the logical procedures used by Bhavaviveka (who argued for the use of svatantra-anumana or autonomous syllogisms) and Buddhapalita (who held that one should only use prasanga, or reductio ad absurdum).[145] Tibetan Buddhism further divides svātantrika into sautrantika svātantrika madhyamaka (applied to Bhāviveka), and yogācāra svātantrika madhyamaka (śāntarakṣita and kamalaśīla).[146]

The svātantrika states that conventional phenomena are understood to have a conventional essential existence, but without an ultimately existing essence. In this way they believe they are able to make positive or "autonomous" assertions using syllogistic logic because they are able to share a subject that is established as appearing in common - the proponent and opponent use the same kind of valid cognition to establish it. The name comes from this quality of being able to use autonomous arguments in debate.[145]

In contrast, the central technique avowed by the prasaṅgika is to show by prasaṅga (or reductio ad absurdum) that any positive assertion (such as "asti" or "nāsti", "it is", or "it is not") or view regarding phenomena must be regarded as merely conventional (saṃvṛti or lokavyavahāra). The prāsaṅgika holds that it is not necessary for the proponent and opponent to use the same kind of valid cognition (pramana) to establish a common subject; indeed it is possible to change the view of an opponent through a reductio argument.

Although presented as a divide in doctrine, the major difference between svātantrika and prasangika may be between two style of reasoning and arguing, while the division itself is exclusively Tibetan. Tibetan scholars were aware of alternative madhyamaka sub-classifications, but later Tibetan doxography emphasizes the nomenclature of prāsaṅgika versus svātantrika. No conclusive evidence can show the existence of an Indian antecedent, and it is not certain to what degree individual writers in Indian and Tibetan discussion held each of these views and if they held a view generally or only in particular instances. Both Prāsaṅgikas and Svātantrikas cited material in the āgamas in support of their arguments.[147]

Longchen Rabjam noted in the 14th century that Candrakirti favored the prasaṅga approach when specifically discussing the analysis for ultimacy, but otherwise he made positive assertions such as when describing the paths of Buddhist practice in his Madhyamakavatāra. Therefore, even prāsaṅgikas make positive assertions when discussing conventional practice, they simply stick to using reductios specifically when analyzing for ultimate truth.[145]

Jonang and "other empty"

 
Thangkha with Jonang lama Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen (1292–1361)

Further Tibetan philosophical developments began in response to the works of the scholar Dölpopa Shérap Gyeltsen (1292–1361) and led to two distinctly opposed Tibetan madhyamaka views on the nature of ultimate reality.[148][149] An important Tibetan treatise on Emptiness and Buddha Nature is found in Dolpopa's voluminous study, Mountain Doctrine.[150]

Dolpopa, the founder of the Jonang school, viewed the Buddha and Buddha Nature as not intrinsically empty, but as truly real, unconditioned, and replete with eternal, changeless virtues.[151] In the Jonang school, ultimate reality, i.e. Buddha Nature (tathagatagarbha) is only empty of what is impermanent and conditioned (conventional reality), not of its own self which is ultimate Buddhahood and the luminous nature of mind.[152] In Jonang, this ultimate reality is a "ground or substratum" which is "uncreated and indestructible, noncomposite and beyond the chain of dependent origination".[153]

Basing himself on the Indian Tathāgatagarbha sūtras as his main sources, Dolpopa described the Buddha Nature as:

[N]on-material emptiness, emptiness that is far from an annihilatory emptiness, great emptiness that is the ultimate pristine wisdom of superiors ...Buddha earlier than all Buddhas, ... causeless original Buddha.[154]

This "great emptiness" i.e. the tathāgatagarbha is said to be filled with eternal powers and virtues:

[P]ermanent, stable, eternal, everlasting. Not compounded by causes and conditions, the matrix-of-one-gone-thus is intrinsically endowed with ultimate buddha qualities of body, speech, and mind such as the ten powers; it is not something that did not exist before and is newly produced; it is self-arisen.'[155]

The Jonang position came to be known as "emptiness of other" (gzhan stong, shentong), because it held that the ultimate truth was positive reality that was not empty of its own nature, only empty of what it was other than itself.[156] Dolpopa considered his view a form of madhyamaka, and called his system "Great Madhyamaka".[157] Dolpopa opposed what he called rangtong (self-empty), the view that ultimate reality is that which is empty of self nature in a relative and absolute sense, that is to say that it is empty of everything, including itself. It is thus not a transcendental ground or metaphysical absolute which includes all the eternal Buddha qualities. This rangtong - shentong distinction became a central issue of contention among Tibetan Buddhist philosophers.

Alternative interpretations of the shentong view is also taught outside of Jonang. Some Kagyu figures, like Jamgon Kongtrul (1813–1899) as well as the unorthodox Sakya philosopher Sakya Chokden (1428–1507), supported their own forms of shentong.

Tsongkhapa and Gelug prāsaṅgika

 
Tsongkhapa

The Gelug school was founded in the beginning of the 15th century by Je Tsongkhapa (1357–1419).[158] Tsongkhapa's conception of emptiness draws mainly from the works of "prāsaṅgika" Indian thinkers like Buddhapalita, Candrakirti, and Shantideva and he argued that only their interpretation of Nagarjuna was ultimately correct. According to José I. Cabezón, Tsongkhapa also argued that the ultimate truth or emptiness was "an absolute negation (med dgag)—the negation of inherent existence—and that nothing was exempt from being empty, including emptiness itself."[156]

Tsongkhapa also maintained that the ultimate truth could be understood conceptually, an understanding which could later be transformed into a non-conceptual one. This conceptual understanding could only be done through the use of madhyamika reasoning, which he also sought to unify with the logical theories of Dharmakirti.[156] Because of Tsongkhapa's view of emptiness as an absolute negation, he strongly attacked the other empty views of Dolpopa in his works. Tsongkhapa major work on madhyamaka is his commentary on the MMK called "Ocean of Reasoning".[159]

According to Thupten Jinpa, Tsongkhapa's "doctrine of the object of negation" is one of his most innovative but also controversial ideas. Tsongkhapa pointed out that if one wants to steer a middle course between the extremes of "over-negation" (straying into nihilism) and "under-negation" (and thus reification), it is important to have a clear concept of exactly what is being negated in Madhyamaka analysis (termed "the object of negation").[160][161]

According to Jay Garfield and Sonam Thakchoe, for Tsongkhapa, there are two aspects of the object of negation: “erroneous apprehension” ( phyin ci log gi ‘dzin pa) and “the existence of intrinsic nature thereby apprehended” (des bzung ba’i rang bzhin yod pa). The second aspect is an erroneously reified fiction which does not exist even conventionally. This is the fundamental object of negation for Tsongkhapa "since the reified object must first be negated in order to eliminate the erroneous subjective state".[162]

Tsongkhapa's understanding of the object of negation (Tib. dgag bya) is subtle, and he describes one aspect of it as an "innate apprehension of self-existence". Thupten Jinpa glosses this as a belief that we have that leads us to "perceive things and events as possessing some kind of intrinsic existence and identity". Tsongkhapa's madhyamaka therefore, does not deny the conventional existence of things per se, but merely rejects our way of experiencing things as existing in an essentialist way, which are false projections or imputations.[160] This is the root of ignorance, which for Tsongkhapa is an "active defiling agency" (Sk. kleśāvaraṇa) which projects a false sense of reality onto objects.[160]

As Garfield and Thakchoe note, Tsongkhapa's view allows him to "preserve a robust sense of the reality of the conventional world in the context of emptiness and to provide an analysis of the relation between emptiness and conventional reality that makes clear sense of the identity of the two truths".[163] Because conventional existence (or 'mere appearance') as an interdependent phenomenon devoid of inherent existence is not negated (khegs pa) or "rationally undermined" in his analysis, Tsongkhapa's approach was criticized by other Tibetan madhyamikas who preferred an anti-realist interpretation of madhyamaka.[164]

Following Candrakirti, Tsongkhapa also rejected the yogacara view of mind only, and instead defended the conventional existence of external objects even though ultimately they are mere "thought constructions" (Tib. rtog pas btags tsam) of a deluded mind.[161] Tsongkhapa also followed Candrakirti in rejecting svātantra ("autonomous") reasoning, arguing that it was enough to show the unwelcome consequences (prasaṅga) of essentialist positions.[161]

Gelug scholarship has generally maintained and defended Tsongkhapa's positions up until the present day, even if there are lively debates considering issues of interpretation. Jamyang Sheba, Changkya Rölpé Dorjé, Gendun Chopel and the 14th Dalai Lama are some of the most influential modern figures in Gelug madhyamaka.

Sakya madhyamaka

 
Gorampa Sonam Senge, the most important madhyamaka philosopher in Sakya

The Sakya school has generally held a classic prāsaṅgika position following Candrakirti closely, though with significant differences from the Gelug. Sakya scholars of Madhyamika, such as Rendawa Shyönnu Lodrö (1349–1412) and Rongtön Sheja Kunrig (1367–1450) were early critics of the "other empty" view.[165]

Gorampa Sonam Senge (1429-1489) was an important Sakya philosopher which defended the orthodox Sakya madhyamika position, critiquing both Dolpopa and Tsongkhapa's interpretations. He is widely studied, not only in Sakya, but also in Nyingma and Kagyu institutions.[166]

According to Cabezón, Gorampa called his version of madhyamaka "the middle way qua freedom from extremes" (mtha' bral dbu ma) or "middle way qua freedom from proliferations" (spros bral kyi dbu ma) and claimed that the ultimate truth was ineffable, beyond predication or concept.[167] Cabezón states that Gorampa's interpretation of madhyamaka is "committed to a more literal reading of the Indian sources than either Dolpopa's or Tsongkhapa's, which is to say that it tends to take the Indian texts at face value."[168] For Gorampa, emptiness is not just the absence of inherent existence, but it is the absence of the four extremes in all phenomena i.e. existence, nonexistence, both and neither (see: catuskoti), without any further qualification.[169]

In other words, conventional truths are also an object of negation, because as Gorampa states "they are not found at all when subjected to ultimate rational analysis".[170] Hence, Gorampa's madhyamaka negates existence itself or existence without qualifications, while for Tsongkhapa, the object of negation is "inherent existence", "intrinsic existence" or "intrinsic nature".[169]

In his Elimination of Erroneous Views (Lta ba ngan sel), Gorampa argues that madhyamaka ultimately negates "all false appearances", which means anything that appears to our mind (i.e. all conventional phenomena). Since all appearances are conceptually produced illusions, they must cease when conceptual reification is brought to an end by insight. This is the "ultimate freedom from conceptual fabrication" (don dam spros bral). To reach this, madhyamikas must negate "the reality of appearances".[163] In other words, all conventional realities are fabrications and since awakening requires transcending all fabrication (spros bral), conventional reality must be negated.[171] Thus, for Gorampa, all conventional knowledge is dualistic, being based on a false distinction between subject and object.[172] Therefore, for Gorampa, madhyamaka analyzes all supposedly real phenomena and concludes through that analysis "that those things do not exist and so that so-called conventional reality is entirely nonexistent".[170]

Regarding the Ultimate truth, Gorampa saw this as being divided into two parts:[169]

  • The emptiness that is reached by rational analysis (this is actually only an analogue, and not the real thing).
  • The emptiness that yogis fathom by means of their own individual gnosis (prajña). This is the real ultimate truth, which is reached by negating the previous rational understanding of emptiness.

Unlike most orthodox Sakyas, the philosopher Sakya Chokden, a contemporary of Gorampa, also promoted a form of shentong as being complementary to rangtong. He saw shentong as useful for meditative practice, while rangtong as useful for cutting through views.[173]

Comparison of the views of Tsongkhapa and Gorampa

As Garfield and Thakchoe note, for Tsongkhapa, conventional truth is "a kind of truth", "a way of being real" and "a kind of existence" while for Gorampa, the conventional is "entirely false", "unreal", "a kind of nonexistence" and "truth only from the perspective of fools".[174]

Jay L. Garfield and Sonam Thakchoe outline the different competing models of Gorampa and Tsongkhapa as follows:[175]

[Gorampa's]: The object of negation is the conventional phenomenon itself. Let us see how that plays out in an account of the status of conventional truth. Since ultimate truth—emptiness—is an external negation, and since an external negation eliminates its object while leaving nothing behind, when we say that a person is empty, we eliminate the person, leaving nothing else behind. To be sure, we must, as mādhyamikas, in agreement with ordinary persons, admit that the person exists conventionally despite not existing ultimately. But, if emptiness eliminates the person, that conventional existence is a complete illusion: The ultimate emptiness of the person shows that the person simply does not exist. It is no more actual than Santa Claus, the protestations of ordinary people and small children to the contrary notwithstanding.

[Tsongkhapa's]: The object of negation is not the conventional phenomenon itself but instead the intrinsic nature or intrinsic existence of the conventional phenomenon. The consequences of taking the object of negation this way are very different. On this account, when we say that the person does not exist ultimately, what is eliminated by its ultimate emptiness is its intrinsic existence. No other intrinsic identity is projected in the place of that which was undermined by emptiness, even emptiness or conventional reality. But the person is not thereby eliminated. Its conventional existence is therefore, on this account, simply its existence devoid of intrinsic identity as an interdependent phenomenon. On this view, conventional reality is no illusion; it is the actual mode of existence of actual things.

According to Garfield and Thakchoe each of these "radically distinct views" on the nature of the two truths "has scriptural support, and indeed each view can be supported by citations from different passages of the same text or even slightly different contextual interpretations of the same passage".[176]

Kagyu

In the Kagyu tradition, there is a broad field of opinion on the nature of emptiness, with some holding the "other empty" (shentong) view while others holding different positions. One influential Kagyu thinker was Rangjung Dorje, 3rd Karmapa Lama. His view synthesized madhyamaka and yogacara perspectives. According to Karl Brunnholzl, regarding his position in the rangtong-shentong debate he "can be said to regard these two as not being mutually exclusive and to combine them in a creative synthesis".[177] However, Rangjung Dorje never uses these terms in any of his works and thus any claims to him being a promoter of shentong or otherwise is a later interpretation.[178]

Several Kagyu figures disagree with the view that shentong is a form of madhyamaka. According to Brunnholzl, Mikyö Dorje, 8th Karmapa Lama (1507–1554) and Second Pawo Rinpoche Tsugla Trengwa see the term "shentong madhyamaka" as a misnomer, for them the yogacara of Asanga and Vasubandhu and the system of Nagarjuna are "two clearly distinguished systems". They also refute the idea that there is "a permanent, intrinsically existing Buddha nature".[179]

Mikyö Dorje also argues that the language of other emptiness does not appear in any of the sutras or the treatises of the Indian masters. He attacks the view of Dolpopa as being against the sutras of ultimate meaning which state that all phenomena are emptiness as well as being against the treatises of the Indian masters.[180] Mikyö Dorje rejects both perspectives of rangtong and shentong as true descriptions of ultimate reality, which he sees as being "the utter peace of all discursiveness regarding being empty and not being empty".[181]

One of the most influential Kagyu philosophers in recent times was Jamgön Kongtrul Lodrö Taye (1813–1899) who advocated a system of shentong madhyamaka and held that primordial wisdom was "never empty of its own nature and it is there all the time".[182][183]

The modern Kagyu teacher Khenpo Tsultrim (1934–), in his Progressive Stages of Meditation on Emptiness, presents five stages of meditation, which he relates to five tenet systems.[184][185] He holds the "Shentong Madhyamaka" as the highest view, above prasangika. He sees this as a meditation on Paramarthasatya ("Absolute Reality"),[186][note 15] Buddhajnana,[note 16] which is beyond concepts, and described by terms as "truly existing".[188] This approach helps "to overcome certain residual subtle concepts",[188] and "the habit – fostered on the earlier stages of the path – of negating whatever experience arises in his/her mind."[189] It destroys false concepts, as does prasangika, but it also alerts the practitioner "to the presence of a dynamic, positive Reality that is to be experienced once the conceptual mind is defeated."[189]

Nyingma

 
Jamgön Ju Mipham Gyatso (1846–1912), a key exponent of madhyamaka thought in the Nyingma school, known for harmonizing madhyamaka with the dzogchen view.

In the nyingma school, like in Kagyu, there is a variety of views. Some Nyingma thinkers promoted shentong, like Katok Tsewang Norbu, but the most influential Nyingma thinkers like Longchenpa and Ju Mipham held a more classical prāsaṅgika interpretation while at the same time seeking to harmonize it with the dzogchen view found in the dzgochen tantras which are traditionally seen as the pinnacle of the nyingma view.

According to Sonam Thakchoe, the ultimate truth in the Nyingma tradition, following Longchenpa, is that "reality which transcends any mode of thinking and speech, one that unmistakenly appears to the nonerroneous cognitive processes of the exalted and awakened beings" and this is said to be "inexpressible beyond words and thoughts" as well as the reality that is the "transcendence of all elaborations.[190]

The most influential modern Nyingma scholar is Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso (1846–1912). He developed a unique theory of madhyamaka, with two models of the two truths. While he adopts the traditional madhyamaka model of two truths, in which the ultimate truth is emptiness, he also developed a second model, in which the ultimate truth is "reality as it is" (de bzhin nyid) which is "established as ultimately real" (bden par grub pa).[190]

This ultimate truth is associated with the Dzogchen concept of Rigpa. While it might seem that this system conflicts with the traditional madhyamaka interpretation, for Mipham this is not so. For while the traditional model which sees emptiness and ultimate truth as a negation is referring to the analysis of experience, the second Dzogchen influenced model refers to the experience of unity in meditation.[191] Douglas Duckworth sees Mipham's work as an attempt to bring together the two main Mahayana philosophical systems of yogacara and madhyamaka, as well as shentong and rangtong into a coherent system in which both are seen as being of definitive meaning.[192]

Regarding the svatantrika prasangika debate, Ju Mipham explained that using positive assertions in logical debate may serve a useful purpose, either while debating with non-Buddhist schools or to move a student from a coarser to a more subtle view. Similarly, discussing an approximate ultimate helps students who have difficulty using only prasaṅga methods move closer to the understanding of the true ultimate. Ju Mipham felt that the ultimate non-enumerated truth of the svatantrika was no different from the ultimate truth of the Prāsaṅgika. He felt the only difference between them was with respect to how they discussed conventional truth and their approach to presenting a path.[145]

East Asian madhyamaka

 
A painting of Kumārajīva at White Horse Pagoda, Dunhuang

Sānlùn school

Chinese madhyamaka (known as sānlùn, or the three treatise school) began with the work of Kumārajīva (344–413 CE) who translated the works of Nāgārjuna (including the MMK, also known in China as the Chung lun, "Madhyamakaśāstra"; Taishō 1564) to Chinese. Another influential text in Chinese madhyamaka which was said to have been translated by Kumārajīva was the Ta-chih-tu lun, or *Mahāprajñāpāramitopadeśa Śāstra ("Treatise which is a Teaching on the Great Perfection of Wisdom [Sūtra]"). According to Dan Arnold, this text is only extant in Kumārajīva's translation and has material that differs from the work of Nāgārjuna. In spite of this, the Ta-chih-tu lun became a central text for Chinese interpretations of madhyamaka emptiness.[193]

Sānlùn figures like Kumārajīva's pupil Sengzhao (384–414), and the later Jizang (549–623) were influential in restoring a more orthodox and non-essentialist interpretation of emptiness to Chinese Buddhism. Yin Shun (1906–2005) is one modern figure aligned with Sānlùn.

Sengzhao is often seen as the founder of Sānlùn. He was influenced not just by Indian madhyamaka and Mahayana sutras like the Vimalakirti, but also by Taoist works and he widely quotes the Lao-tzu and the Chuang-tzu and uses terminology of the Neo-Daoist "Mystery Learning" (xuanxue 玄学) tradition while maintaining a uniquely Buddhist philosophical view.[194][195] In his essay "The Emptiness of the Non-Absolute" (buzhenkong, 不眞空), Sengzhao points out that the nature of phenomena cannot be taken as being either existent or inexistent:

Hence, there are indeed reasons why myriad dharmas are inexistent and cannot be taken as existent; there are reasons why [myriad dharmas] are not inexistent and cannot be taken as inexistent. Why? If we would say that they exist, their existent is not real; if we would say that they don't exist, their phenomenal forms have taken shape. Having forms and shapes, they are not inexistent. Being not real, they are not truly existent. Hence the meaning of bu zhen kong [not really empty, 不眞空] is made manifest.[196]

Sengzhao saw the central problem in understanding emptiness as the discriminatory activity of prapañca. According to Sengzhao, delusion arises through a dependent relationship between phenomenal things, naming, thought and reification and correct understanding lies outside of words and concepts. Thus, while emptiness is the lack of intrinsic self in all things, this emptiness is not itself an absolute and cannot be grasped by the conceptual mind, it can be only be realized through non-conceptual wisdom (prajña).[197]

Jizang (549–623) was another central figure in Chinese madhyamaka who wrote numerous commentaries on Nagarjuna and Aryadeva and is considered to be the leading representative of the school.[198] Jizang called his method "deconstructing what is misleading and revealing what is corrective". He insisted that one must never settle on any particular viewpoint or perspective but constantly reexamine one's formulations to avoid reifications of thought and behavior.[198] In his commentary on the MMK, Jizang's method and understanding of emptiness can be seen:

The abhidharma thinkers regard the four holy truths as true. The Satyasiddhi regards merely the truth of cessation of suffering, i.e., the principle of emptiness and equality, as true. The southern Mahāyāna tradition regards the principle that refutes truths as true, and the northern [Mahāyāna tradition] regards thatness [suchness] and prajñā as true... Examining these all together, if there is a single [true] principle, it is an eternal view, which is false. If there is no principle at all, it is an evil view, which is also false. Being both existent and non-existent consists of the eternal and nihilistic views altogether. Being neither existent nor nonexistent is a foolish view. One replete with these four phrases has all [wrong] views. One without these four phrases has a severe nihilistic view. Now that [one] does not know how to name what a mind has nothing to rely upon and is free from conceptual construction, [he] foists "thatness" [suchness] upon it, one attains sainthood of the three vehicles... Being deluded in regard to thatness [suchness], one falls into the six realms of disturbed life and death.[199]

In one of his early treatises called "The Meaning of the two Truths" (Erdiyi), Jizang, expounds the steps to realize the nature of the ultimate truth of emptiness as follows:

In the first step, one recognises reality of the phenomena on the conventional level, but assumes their non-reality on the ultimate level. In the second step, one becomes aware of Being or Non-Being on the conventional level and negates both at the ultimate level. In the third step, one either asserts or negates Being and Non-Being on the conventional level, neither confi rming nor rejecting them on the ultimate level. Hence, there is ultimately no assertion or negation anymore; therefore, on the conventional level, one becomes free to accept or reject anything.[200]

In the modern era, there has been a revival of mādhyamaka in Chinese Buddhism. A major figure in this revival is the scholar monk Yin Shun (1906–2005).[201] Yin Shun emphasized the study of Indian Buddhist sources as primary and his books on mādhyamaka had a profound influence on modern Chinese madhyamika scholarship.[202] He argued that the works of Nagarjuna were "the inheritance of the conceptualisation of dependent arising as proposed in the Agamas" and he thus based his mādhyamaka interpretations on the Agamas rather than on Chinese scriptures and commentaries.[203] He saw the writings of Nagarjuna as the correct Buddhadharma while considering the writings of the Sānlùn school as being corrupted due to their synthesizing of the Tathagata-garbha doctrine into madhyamaka.[204]

Many modern Chinese mādhyamaka scholars such as Li Zhifu, Yang Huinan and Lan Jifu have been students of Yin Shun.[205]

Chán

The Chán/Zen-tradition emulated madhyamaka-thought via the San-lun Buddhists, influencing its supposedly "illogical" way of communicating "absolute truth".[10] The madhyamika of Sengzhao for example, influenced the views of the Chan patriarch Shen Hui (670-762), a critical figure in the development of Chan, as can be seen by his "Illuminating the Essential Doctrine" (Hsie Tsung Chi). This text emphasizes that true emptiness or Suchness cannot be known through thought since it is free from thought (wu-nien):[206]

Thus we come to realize that both selves and things are, in their essence, empty, and existence and non-existence both disappear.

Mind is fundamentally non-action; the way is truly no-thought (wu-nien).

There is no thought, no reflection, no seeking, no attainment, no this, no that, no coming, no going.

Shen Hui also states that true emptiness is not nothing, but it is a "Subtle Existence" (miao-yu), which is just "Great Prajña."[206]

Western Buddhism

Thich Nhat Hanh

Thich Nhat Hanh explains the madhyamaka concept of emptiness through the Chinese Buddhist concept of interdependence. In this analogy, there is no first or ultimate cause for anything that occurs. Instead, all things are dependent on innumerable causes and conditions that are themselves dependent on innumerable causes and conditions. The interdependence of all phenomena, including the self, is a helpful way to undermine mistaken views about inherence, or that one's self is inherently existent. It is also a helpful way to discuss Mahayana teachings on motivation, compassion, and ethics. The comparison to interdependence has produced recent discussion comparing Mahayana ethics to environmental ethics.[207]

Modern madhyamaka

Madhyamaka forms an alternative to the perennialist and essentialist understanding of nondualism and modern spiritual metaphysics (influenced by idealistic monism views like Neo-Advaita).[web 1][web 2][web 3]

In some modern works, classical madhyamaka teachings are sometimes complemented with postmodern philosophy,[web 4] critical sociology,[web 5] and social constructionism.[web 6] These approaches stress that there is no transcendental reality beyond this phenomenal world,[web 7] and in some cases even explicitly distinguish themselves from neo-Advaita approaches.[web 8]

Influences and critiques

Yogacara

The yogacara school was the other major Mahayana philosophical school (darsana) in India and its complex relationship with madhyamaka changed over time. The Saṃdhinirmocana sūtra, perhaps the earliest Yogacara text, proclaims itself as being above the doctrine of emptiness taught in other sutras. According to Paul Williams, the Saṃdhinirmocana claims that other sutras that teach emptiness as well as madhyamika teachings on emptiness are merely skillful means and thus are not definitive (unlike the final teachings in the Saṃdhinirmocana).[208]

As Mark Siderits points out, yogacara authors like Asanga were careful to point out that the doctrine of emptiness required interpretation in lieu of their three natures theory which posits an inexpressible ultimate that is the object of a Buddha's cognition.[209] Asanga also argued that one cannot say that all things are empty unless there are things to be seen as either empty or non-empty in the first place.[210] Asanga attacks the view which states "the truth is that all is just conceptual fictions" by stating:

As for their view, due to the absence of the thing itself which serves as basis of the concept, conceptual fictions must all likewise absolutely not exist. How then will it be true that all is just conceptual fictions? Through this conception on their part, reality, conceptual fiction, and the two together are all denied. Because they deny both conceptual fiction and reality, they should be considered the nihilist-in-chief.[211]

Asanga also critiqued madhyamaka because he held that it could lead to a laxity in the following of ethical precepts as well as for being "imaginatively constructed views that are arrived at only through reasoning".[212] He further states:

How, again, is emptiness wrongly conceptualized? Some ascetics and Brahmins do not acknowledge that [viz. intrinsic nature] of which something is empty. Nor do they acknowledge that which is empty [viz. things and dharmas]. It is in this way that emptiness is said to be wrongly conceived. For what reason? Because that of which it is empty is non-existent, but that which is empty is existent— it is thus that emptiness is possible. What will be empty of what, where, when everything is unreal? This thing's being devoid of that is not [then] possible. Thus emptiness is wrongly conceptualized in this case.

Asanga also wrote that:

"if nothing is real, there cannot be any ideas (prajñapti). Someone who holds this view is a nihilist, with whom one should not speak or share living quarters. This person falls into a bad rebirth and takes others with him."[213]

Vasubandhu also states that emptiness does not mean that things have no intrinsic nature, but that this nature is "inexpressible and only to be apprehended by a kind of cognition that transcends the subject-object duality".[209]

Thus early yogacarins were engaged in a project to reinterpret the radical madhyamaka view of emptiness. Later yogacarins like Sthiramati and Dharmapala debated with their madhyamika contemporaries.[214] However, yogacara authors also commented on madhyamaka texts. As noted by Garfield, "Asaṅga, Sthiramati, and Guṇamati composed commentaries on the foundational text of madhyamaka, Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā."[215]

According to Xuanzang, Bhavaviveka, who critiques yogacara views in his Madhyamakahṛdayakārikāḥ, was disturbed by the views of yogacarins and their critiques of madhyamaka as nihilism, and himself traveled to Nalanda to debate Dharmapala face to face, but Dharmapala refused.[216] Bhavaviveka quotes the attacks from the yogacarins in his texts as claiming that while the yogacara approach to prajñaparamita is the "means to attain omniscience", the madhyamaka approach which "concentrates on the negation of arising and cessation" is not.[217] Bhavaviveka responds to various yogacara attacks and views in his Tarkajvālā (Blaze of reason) including the view that there are no external objects (idealism), the view that there is no use for logical argumentation (tarka), and the view that the dependent nature (paratantra-svabhāva) exists in an absolute sense.[218]

Advaita Vedanta

Several modern scholars have argued that the early Advaita Vedanta thinker Gaudapada (c. 6th century CE), was influenced by madhyamaka thought. They note that he borrowed the concept of "ajāta" (un-born) from madhyamaka philosophy,[219][220] which also uses the term "anutpāda" (non-arising, un-originated, non-production).[221][web 9] The Buddhist tradition usually uses the term "anutpāda" for the absence of an origin[219][221] or shunyata.[222][note 17] "Ajātivāda" is the fundamental philosophical doctrine of Gaudapada.[226] According to Gaudapada, the Absolute (Brahman) is not subject to birth, change and death. Echoing Nagarjuna's use of the catuskoti, Gaudapada writes that "nothing whatsoever is originated either from itself or from something else; nothing whatsoever existent, non-existent, or both existent and non-existent is originated".[227]

However, it has been noted that Gaudapada's ultimate philosophical perspective is quite different from Nagarjuna's since Gaudapada posits a metaphysical Absolute (which is aja, the unborn, and eternal) based on the Mandukya Upanishad and thus he remains primarily a Vedantin.[228][226] The empirical world of appearances is considered unreal, and not absolutely existent.[226] In this sense, Gaudapada also shares a doctrine of two truths or two levels of reality with madhyamaka. According to Gaudapada, this absolute, Brahman, cannot undergo alteration, so the phenomenal world cannot arise from Brahman. If the world cannot arise, yet is an empirical fact, then the world has to be an unreal[note 18] appearance of Brahman. From the level of ultimate truth (paramārthatā) the phenomenal world is Maya (illusion).[228]

Richard King notes that the fourth prakarana of the Gaudapadiyakarika promotes several Mahayana Buddhist ideas, such as a middle way free from extremes, not being attached to dharmas and it even references beings called "Buddhas". King notes that this could be an attempt to either reach a rapprochement with Buddhists or to woo Buddhists over to Vedanta.[229] However, King adds that "from a Madhyamaka perspective, the Gaudapadiyakarika's acceptance of an unchanging Absolute supporting the world of appearances is a mistaken form of eternalism, despite Gaudapadian protestations to the contrary."[229]

Shankara (early 8th century), a later Advaitin, directly dismissed madhyamaka as irrational and nihilistic, stating that it was a kind of nihilism that held that "absolutely nothing exists" and that this view:[227][230][231]

is contradicted by all means of right knowledge and requires no special refutation. For this apparent world, whose existence is guaranteed by all means of knowledge, cannot be denied, unless some one should find out some new truth (based on which he could impugn its existence) - for a general principle is proved by the absence of contrary instances.

This critique was upheld by most post Shankara Advaitins. However this did not prevent later Vedanta thinkers like Bhaskara of accusing Shankara of being a crypto-buddhist for his view that everyday reality is Maya (illusion) and that Brahman has no qualities and is undifferentiated. Another Vedantin philosopher, Ramanuja (1017–1137), directly compared Shankara's "mayavada" views to madhyamaka, arguing that if Maya/Avidya is unreal, "that would involve the acceptance of the Madhyamika doctrine, viz. of a general void".[231] This critique by comparison is also echoed by the later philosophers like Madhva as well as Vijñanabhiksu (15th or 16th century), who goes as far as to call Shankara a nastika (unorthodox). Later Advaitins also acknowledged the similarity of their doctrine with madhyamaka. Vimuktatma states that if by asat (nonbeing), the Madhyamaka means Maya and not mere negation, then he is close to Vedanta. Sadananda also states that if by Sunya, what is meant is the reality beyond the intellect, then the madhyamaka accepts Vedanta. Sri Harsha notes that the two schools are similar, but they differ in that Advaita holds consciousness to be pure, real and eternal, while madhyamaka denies this.[231]

Jain philosophy

Modern scholars such as Jeffery Long have also noted that the influential Jain philosopher Kundakunda (2nd CE century CE or later) also adopted a theory of two truths, possibly under the influence of Nagarjuna.[232] According to W. J. Johnson he also adopts other Buddhist terms like prajña under the influence of Nagarjuna, though he applies the term to knowledge of the Self (jiva), which is also the ultimate perspective (niścayanaya), which is distinguished from the worldly perspective (vyavahāranaya).[233]

The Jain philosopher Haribhadra also mentions madhyamaka. In both the Yogabindu and the Yogadrstisamuccaya, Haribhadra singles out Nagarjuna's claim that samsara and nirvana are not different for criticism, labeling the view a "fantasy".[234]

Taoism

It is well known that medieval Chinese Taoism was influenced by Mahayana Buddhism. One particular school, the Chongxuan (重玄, "Twofold Mystery") founded by Cheng Xuanying (fl.632-650), was particularly involved in borrowing and adapting madhyamaka concepts like emptiness, the two truths and the catuskoti into their Taoist philosophical system.[195]

Modern scholarship

As noted by Ruegg, Western scholarship has given a broad variety of interpretations of madhyamaka, including: "nihilism, monism, irrationalism, misology, agnosticism, scepticism, criticism, dialectic, mysticism, acosmism, absolutism, relativism, nominalism, and linguistic analysis with therapeutic value".[235] Jay L. Garfield likewise notes:

"Modern interpreters differ among themselves about the correct way to read it as least as much as canonical interpreters. Nagarjuna has been read as an idealist (Murti 1960), a nihilist (Wood 1994), a skeptic (Garfield 1995), a pragmatist (Kalupahana 1986), and as a mystic (Streng 1967). He has been regarded as a critic of logic (Inada 1970), as a defender of classical logic (Hayes 1994), and as a pioneer of paraconsistent logic (Garfield and Priest 2003)".[236]

These interpretations "reflect almost as much about the viewpoints of the scholars involved as do they reflect the content of Nāgārjuna's concepts".[237]

According to Andrew Tuck, the Western study of Nagarjuna's madhyamaka can be divided into three phases:[238]

  1. The Kantian phase, exemplified by Theodore Stcherbatsky's "The Conception of Buddhist Nirvāna" (1927) who argued that Nagarjuna divides the world into appearance (samsara) and an absolute noumenal reality (nirvana). This is also seen in T. R. V. Murti's 1955 "The Central Philosophy of Buddhism".
  2. The analytic phase, exemplified by Richard Robinson's 1957 article "Some Logical Aspects of Nāgārjuna's System", sought to explain madhyamaka using analytic philosophy's logical apparatus.
  3. The post-Wittgensteinian phase, exemplified by Frederick Streng's "Emptiness" and Chris Gudmunsen's "Wittgenstein and Buddhism", "set out to stress similarities between Nāgārjuna and in particular the later Wittgenstein and his criticism of analytic philosophy."

The Sri Lankan philosopher David Kalupahana meanwhile saw madhyamaka as a response to certain essentialist philosophical tendencies which had arisen after the time of the Buddha and sees it as a restoration of the early Buddhist middle way pragmatist position.[239][117] Among the critical voices, Richard P. Hayes (influenced by Richard Robinson's view that Nagarjuna's logic fails modern tests for validity) interprets the works of Nagarjuna as "primitive" and guilty "errors in reasoning" such as that of equivocation. Hayes states that Nagarjuna was relying on the different meanings of the word svabhava to make statements which were not logical and that his work relies on various "fallacies and tricks".[240][241] William Magee strongly disagrees with Hayes, referring to Tsonghkhapa's interpretation of Nagarjuna to argue that Hayes misidentifies Nagarjuna's understanding of the different meanings of the term svabhava.[242]

Many recent western scholars (such as Garfield,[243] Napper,[244] Hopkins,[245]) have tended to adopt a Gelug Prāsaṅgika influenced interpretation of madhyamaka. However, American philosopher Mark Siderits is one exception, who has attempted to defend the Svātantrika position as a coherent and rational interpretation of madhyamaka.[246]

C.W. Huntington meanwhile has been particularly critical of the modern Western attempt to read Nagarjuna "through the lens of modern symbolic logic" and to see him as compatible with analytical philosophy's logical system.[241] He argues that in reading Nagarjuna, a thinker who he sees as "profoundly distrustful of logic", in an overly logical manner, we "prejudice our understanding of Nagarjuna's insistence that he has no proposition (pratijña)."[241] He puts forth a more literary interpretation that focuses on the effect Nagarjuna was attempting to "conjure" on his readers (i.e. an experience of having no views) instead of asking how it works (or doesn't) in a logical manner.[241] In response to this, Jay Garfield defends the logical reading of Nagarjuna through the use of Anglo-American analytical philosophy as well as arguing that "Nagarjuna and Candrakirti deploy arguments, take themselves to do so, and even if they did not, we would be wise to do so in commenting on their texts".[69]

Another recent interpreter, Jan Westerhoff, argues that madhyamaka is a kind of anti-foundationalism, "which does not just deny the objective, intrinsic, and mind-independent existence of some class of objects, but rejects such existence for any kinds of objects that we could regard as the most fundamental building-blocks of the world".[247]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ 'Own-beings',[25] unique nature or substance,[26] an identifying characteristic; an identity; an essence,[27]
  2. ^ A differentiating characteristic,[27] the fact of being dependent,[27]
  3. ^ 'Being',[21] 'self-nature or substance'[28]
  4. ^ Not being present; absence:[29]
  5. ^ svabhava
  6. ^ Nāgārjuna equates svabhāva (essence) with bhāva (existence) in Chapter 15 of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā
  7. ^ Susan Kahn further explains: "The emptiness of emptiness refutes ultimate truth as yet another argument for essentialism under the guise of being beyond the conventional or as the foundation of it. To realize emptiness is not to find a transcendent place or truth to land in but to see the conventional as merely conventional. Here lies the key to liberation. For to see the deception is to be free of deception, like a magician who knows the magic trick. When one is no longer fooled by false appearances, phenomena are neither reified nor denied. They are understood interdependently, as ultimately empty and thus, as only conventionally real. This is the Middle Way."[40]
  8. ^ Chapter 21 of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā goes into the reasoning behind this.[62]
  9. ^ See also Atthakavagga and Parayanavagga, for early, Madhyamaka-like texts from the Buddhist canon on freedom from views.
  10. ^ In the Pali canon, these chapters are the fourth and fifth chapters of the Khuddaka Nikaya's Sutta Nipata, respectively.
  11. ^ Wynne devotes a chapter to the Parayanavagga.
  12. ^ Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 24:18
  13. ^ Alex Trisoglio: "In the 8th century, Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the monastery at Samyé. He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka, but the disciple of one of his disciples. He combined the madhyamika-svatantrika and cittamatra schools, and created a new school of madhyamika called svatantrika-yogachara-madhyamika. His disciple Kamalashila, who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika (uma'i sgom rim), developed his ideas further, and together they were very influential in Tibet."Khyentse Rinpoche, Dzongsar Jamyang (2003). "Introduction". In Alex Trisoglio (ed.). Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti's Madhyamakavatara with Commentary (PDF) (1st ed.). Dordogne, France: Khyentse Foundation. p. 8. Retrieved 7 January 2013.
  14. ^ In his Tattvaratnāvalī, the Indian scholar Advayavajra classified madhyamaka into "those who uphold non-duality from the simile of illusion" (māyopamādvayavādin) and "those who uphold non-placement into any dharma" (sarvadharmāpratiṣṭhānavādin); furthermore, in the Madhyamakaṣaṭka he envisaged a specifically Vajrayāna type of Madhyamaka.[citation needed]
  15. ^ According to Hookham, non-dual experience is Ultimate Reality.[187]
  16. ^ According to Hookham, "The Chinese Tathagarba schools describe Buddhajnana as the totality of all that is, which pervades every part of all that is in its totality."[187] According to Hookham, for Shentong Buddhajnana is "the non-dual nature of Mind completely unobscured and endowed with its countless Buddha Qualities (Buddhagunas).[187]
  17. ^ The term is also used in the Lankavatara Sutra.[223] According to D.T Suzuki, "anutpada" is not the opposite of "utpada", but transcends opposites. It is the seeing into the true nature of existence,[224] the seeing that "all objects are without self-substance".[225]
  18. ^ C.q. "transitory"

References

Published references

  1. ^ Williams 2000, p. 140.
  2. ^ Thakchoe, Sonam (Summer 2022). "The Theory of Two Truths in Tibet". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. OCLC 643092515. from the original on 28 May 2022. Retrieved 5 July 2022.
  3. ^ a b Wynne, Alexander (2015) Early Buddhist Teaching as Proto-śūnyavāda. Journal of the Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies, 6. pp. 213-241.
  4. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 29-30.
  5. ^ a b c Donnelly, Paul B. (25 January 2017). "Madhyamaka". Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acrefore/9780199340378.013.191. ISBN 9780199340378.
  6. ^ Acri, Andrea (20 December 2018). "Maritime Buddhism". Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acrefore/9780199340378.013.638. ISBN 9780199340378. from the original on 19 February 2019. Retrieved 30 May 2021.
  7. ^ Hugon, Pascale (Spring 2020). "Tibetan Epistemology and Philosophy of Language". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. OCLC 643092515. from the original on 20 June 2022. Retrieved 5 July 2022.
  8. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 70.
  9. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 590.
  10. ^ a b c d e Cheng 1981.
  11. ^ a b Garfield 1994.
  12. ^ a b Garfield 2012.
  13. ^ Discourse to Katyāyana - Kātyāyanaḥ SF 168. Tripathi 1962: 167–170 (19). Translated by Jayarava. suttacentral.net
  14. ^ Sanskrit: lokasamudayaṁ kātyāyana yathābhūtaṁ samyakprajñayā paśyato yā loke nāstitā sā na bhavati | lokanirodhaṁ yathābhūtaṁ samyakprajñayā paśyato yā loke ’stitā sā na bhavati | ity etāv ubhāv antāv anupagamya madhyamayā pratipadā tathāgato dharmaṁ deśayati | yad utāsmin satīdaṁ bhavaty asyotpādād idam utpadyate | yad utāvidyāpratyayāḥ saṁskārā iti pūrvavad yāvat samudayo nirodhaś ca bhavati |
  15. ^ a b c Westerhoff 2009, p. 12, 25.
  16. ^ Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, p. 180.
  17. ^ a b Westerhoff, Jan Christoph (10 February 2010). "Nāgārjuna". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  18. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 4.
  19. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 30.
  20. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 200.
  21. ^ a b c d e Warder 2000, p. 361.
  22. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 45.
  23. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 13.
  24. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 48.
  25. ^ Warder 2000, p. 360.
  26. ^ Kalupahana 1994, p. 162.
  27. ^ a b c Hayes 1994, p. 317.
  28. ^ Kalupahana 1994, p. 165.
  29. ^ Hayes 1994, p. 316.
  30. ^ Harvey 1995, p. 97.
  31. ^ Kalupahana 1994, p. 165, 162.
  32. ^ Tsondru 2011, p. 40–41, 322–333.
  33. ^ Bronkhorst 2009, p. 146.
  34. ^ a b Rje Tsong Khapa; Garfield, Jay; Geshe Ngawang Samten (translators), Ocean of Reasoning: A Great Commentary on Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. xx.
  35. ^ a b Brunnholzl 2004, p. 73.
  36. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 80, 83.
  37. ^ a b c Cowherds 2010, p. 11-13.
  38. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 81.
  39. ^ Bronkhorst 2009, p. 149.
  40. ^ Kahn, Susan (11 September 2014). "The Two Truths of Buddhism and The Emptiness of Emptiness". Emptiness Teachings. Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  41. ^ a b Brunnholzl, 2004, p. 74.
  42. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 79.
  43. ^ Tsongkhapa, Garfield, The Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path to Enlightenment (Volume 3), 2002, p. 210.
  44. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 8-9.
  45. ^ Williams 2002, p. 147.
  46. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 111.
  47. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 75.
  48. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 76.
  49. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 76-77.
  50. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 84.
  51. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 83-84.
  52. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 89.
  53. ^ Junjirō Takakusu (1998). The Essentials of Buddhist Philosophy. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 4, 105–107. ISBN 978-81-208-1592-6.
  54. ^ Hajime Nakamura (1991). Ways of Thinking of Eastern Peoples: India, China, Tibet, Japan. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 590–591 footnote 20. ISBN 978-81-208-0764-8., Quote: "Already in India, 'sunyata' was liable to be misunderstood as nothingness or nihil'. (...) The Sarvastivadins of Hinayana Buddhism viewed the madhyamika school as 'one that argues that everything is nothing. (...) It is only natural that most of the Western scholars call the prajnaparamita sutra or the doctrine of the madhyamika school nihilism since criticisms were already expressed in India. Against such criticisms, however, Nagarjuna, founder of the madhyamika school says, 'you are ignorant of the function of sunyata, the meaning of the sunyata and sunyata itself'."
  55. ^ G. C. Nayak (2001). Mādhyamika Śūnyatā, a Reappraisal: A Reappraisal of Mādhyamika Philosophical Enterprise with Special Reference to Nāgārjuna and Chandrakīrti. Indian Council of Philosophical Research. pp. 9–12. ISBN 978-81-85636-47-4.
  56. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 212.
  57. ^ a b Walser 2005, p. 239.
  58. ^ Jorge Noguera Ferrer, Revisioning Transpersonal Theory: A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality. SUNY Press, 2002, page 102-103.
  59. ^ David J. Kalupahana, Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way. SUNY Press, 1986, pages 48-50.
  60. ^ Williams 2002, p. 141.
  61. ^ Williams 2000, p. 142.
  62. ^ a b c Tsondru 2011, p. 56–58, 405–417.
  63. ^ Williams 2002, p. 151–152.
  64. ^ unclear
  65. ^ a b c d Garfield 1995, p. 88 footnote.
  66. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 174-175.
  67. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 199.
  68. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 200.
  69. ^ a b c d Garfield, Jay L. Turning a Madhyamaka Trick: Reply to Huntington, J Indian Philos (2008) 36:507–527 DOI 10.1007/s10781-008-9045-9
  70. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 202.
  71. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 203.
  72. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 203-204.
  73. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 202-203.
  74. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 217.
  75. ^ a b Brunnholzl 2004, p. 206.
  76. ^ a b Garfield 1995, p. 102.
  77. ^ a b Westerhoff 2009, p. 47.
  78. ^ Bronkhorst 2009, p. 148.
  79. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 295-310.
  80. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 310.
  81. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 108.
  82. ^ Williams 2002, p. 146.
  83. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 218.
  84. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 34.
  85. ^ Jorge Noguera Ferrer, Revisioning Transpersonal Theory: A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality. SUNY Press, 2002, pages 102. The quote is from the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā.
  86. ^ Randall Collins, The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change. Harvard University Press, 2000, pages 221-222.
  87. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 172.
  88. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 219.
  89. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 221.
  90. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 160.
  91. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 209.
  92. ^ Warder 2000, p. 358.
  93. ^ a b c d Walser 2005, p. 185.
  94. ^ Walser 2005, p. 186–187.
  95. ^ Gomez 1976.
  96. ^ Vetter 1988.
  97. ^ Fuller 2005.
  98. ^ Wynne 2007, p. 75.
  99. ^ Gelongma Karma Migme Chodron (trans from French); Lamotte, Etienne (trans). The Treatise on the Great Virtue of Wisdom, Volume V (Traite de la Grande Vertu de Sagesse de Nagarjuna (Mahaprajnaparamitasastra), Tome V), pp. 52-54.
  100. ^ a b Walser 2005, p. 225.
  101. ^ a b c Ronkin, Noa (16 August 2010). "Abhidharma". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  102. ^ Walser 2005, p. 227.
  103. ^ a b Walser 2005, p. 234.
  104. ^ a b c Ruegg, David Seyfort, ''The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India,'' Otto Harrassowitz Verlag, 1981, p. 7.
  105. ^ a b Walser 2005, p. 170.
  106. ^ Adrian Kuzminski, Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism 2008
  107. ^ Thomas McEvilley, The Shape of Ancient Thought 2002 pp499-505
  108. ^ https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:347ed882-f7ac-4098-908f-5bb391462a6c/download_file?file_format=pdf&safe_filename=THESIS01&type_of_work=Thesis[bare URL PDF]
  109. ^ Archived at Ghostarchive and the : "Sextus Empiricus and Madhyamaka at Oxford's Oriental Institute". YouTube.
  110. ^ Beckwith, Christopher I. (2015). Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia (PDF). Princeton University Press. ISBN 9781400866328.
  111. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 4.
  112. ^ a b Westerhoff 2009, p. 5–6.
  113. ^ Wasler, Joseph. Nagarjuna in Context. New York: Columibia University Press. 2005, pgs. 225-263.
  114. ^ a b Kalupahana 1992, p. 120.
  115. ^ Tsondru 2011, p. 66–71, 447–477.
  116. ^ Williams 2002, p. 142.
  117. ^ a b Kalupahana 1994.
  118. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 49, 54.
  119. ^ Warder 2000, p. 368.
  120. ^ a b Rizzi 1988, p. 2.
  121. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 47–48.
  122. ^ Bocking B; (1995) Nagarjuna in China: A Translation of the Middle Treatise. Lewiston & Lampeter. University of Bristol Centre for Buddhist Studies Series: The Edwin Mellen Press.
  123. ^ a b c d e f Hayes, Richard (6 November 2010). "Madhyamaka". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  124. ^ Newland 2009, p. 78.
  125. ^ Newland 2009, p. 79.
  126. ^ a b Garfield, Jay; Edelglass, William; The Oxford Handbook of World philosophy
  127. ^ Newland 2009, p. 80.
  128. ^ a b Ruegg 1981, p. 67.
  129. ^ Bhikshu Dharmamitra (trans.). The Bodhisambhara Treatise Commentary. An Early Indian Commentary on Nagarjuna's Bodhisambhara Shastra By the Early Indian monk, Bhikshu Vasitva (ca 300-500 ce), Kalavinka press.
  130. ^ Rizzi 1988, p. 5.
  131. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 85.
  132. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 119.
  133. ^ Watanabe, Chikafumi (1998). "A Translation of the Madhyamakahrdayakarika with the Tarkajvala III. 137-146". Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies. 21 (1).
  134. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 88.
  135. ^ Shantarakshita 2005, p. 117-122.
  136. ^ Blumenthal, James, The Ornament of the Middle Way A Study of the Madhyamaka Thought of Santaraksita, Snow Lion, 2004, p. 245.
  137. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 104.
  138. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 109.
  139. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 51.
  140. ^ Apple, James B. (2019). Jewels of the Middle Way: The Madhyamaka Legacy of Atisa and His Early Tibetan Followers, Introduction, pp 1-62. Simon and Schuster.
  141. ^ a b c Dunne, John D. (2011). "Madhyamaka in India and Tibet." In Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy." Edited by J. Garfield and W. Edelglass. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 206-221.
  142. ^ Reason and Experience in Tibetan Buddhism: Mabja Jangchub Tsöndrü and the Traditions of the Middle Way Reviewed by Adam C. Krug. Journal of Buddhist Ethics ISSN 1076-9005 http://blogs.dickinson.edu/buddhistethics Volume 22, 2015
  143. ^ Reason and Experience in Tibetan Buddhism: Mabja Jangchub Tsöndrü and the Traditions of the Middle Way Reviewed by Adam C. Krug. Journal of Buddhist Ethics ISSN 1076-9005 http://blogs.dickinson.edu/buddhistethics Volume 22, 2015
  144. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 333.
  145. ^ a b c d Shantarakshita 2005, p. 131-141.
  146. ^ Cornu 2001, p. 138.
  147. ^ Gombrich 1996, p. 27-28.
  148. ^ Cornu 2001, p. 145, 150.
  149. ^ Stearns, Cyrus (2010). The Buddha from Dölpo: A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dölpopa Sherab Gyaltsen(Rev. and enl. ed.). Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion Publications. ISBN 9781559393430. Retrieved 2 May 2015.
  150. ^ Hopkins, 2006.
  151. ^ Hopkins, 2006, pp 8-15
  152. ^ Brunnholzl 2009, p. 108.
  153. ^ Stearns, Cyrus (1999), The Buddha from Dolpo: A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen, State University of New York Press, p. 82.
  154. ^ Hopkins 2006, p. 14.
  155. ^ Hopkins 2006, p. 8.
  156. ^ a b c Cabezón & Dargyay 2013, p. 29.
  157. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 502.
  158. ^ Snelling 1987, p. 207.
  159. ^ rJe Tsong Kha Pa 2006.
  160. ^ a b c Learman, Oliver (editor), Encyclopedia of Asian Philosophy, Routledge, 2001, p. 374.
  161. ^ a b c Sparham, Gareth (18 July 2011). "Tsongkhapa". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition). Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  162. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 76.
  163. ^ a b Cowherds 2010, p. 82.
  164. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 77.
  165. ^ Cabezón & Dargyay 2013, p. 30.
  166. ^ Kassor, Constance (2 May 2011). "Gorampa [go rams pa]". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition). Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  167. ^ Cabezón & Dargyay 2013, p. 46–48.
  168. ^ Cabezón & Dargyay 2013, p. 49.
  169. ^ a b c Cabezón & Dargyay 2013, p. 50.
  170. ^ a b Cowherds 2010, p. 84.
  171. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 86.
  172. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 83.
  173. ^ Brunnholzl 2009, p. 107.
  174. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 74, 75, 87.
  175. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 75-76.
  176. ^ Cowherds 2010, p. 87.
  177. ^ Brunnholzl 2009, p. 99.
  178. ^ Brunnholzl 2009, p. 114.
  179. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 446.
  180. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 447.
  181. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 448.
  182. ^ Brunnholzl 2004, p. 501.
  183. ^ Ringu Tulku, The Ri-me Philosophy of Jamgon Kongtrul the Great: A Study of the Buddhist Lineages of Tibet 2007, p 219.
  184. ^ Hookham 1991, p. 19-26.
  185. ^ Khenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso 1994.
  186. ^ Hookham 1991, p. 21.
  187. ^ a b c Hookham 1991, p. 37.
  188. ^ a b Hookham 1991, p. 22.
  189. ^ a b Hookham 1991, p. 23.
  190. ^ a b Thakchoe, Sonam (17 February 2011). "The Theory of Two Truths in Tibet". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition). Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  191. ^ Duckworth; Jamgon Mipam, His life and teachings, Pg 81.
  192. ^ Duckworth, Jamgon Mipam, His life and teachings, 82.
  193. ^ Arnold, Dan, Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy, Internet Encyclopedia of philosophy.
  194. ^ Liebenthal, Walter, Chao-Lun The Treatises of Seng Chao, 1968, p. 8.
  195. ^ a b Ozkan 2013.
  196. ^ Ozkan 2013, p. 24.
  197. ^ Dippmann, Jeffrey, Sengzhao (Seng-Chao c. 378—413 C.E.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  198. ^ a b Fox, Alan, Self-reflection in the Sanlun Tradition: Madhyamika as the "Deconstructive Conscience" of Buddhism, Journal of Chinese Philosophy V. 19 (1992) pp. 1-24.
  199. ^ Ozkan 2013, p. 25.
  200. ^ Scherer, Burkhard, Review of The Two Truths in Chinese Buddhism, Chang-Qing Shih (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2004) (Buddhist Tradition Series. 55). Buddhist studies review
  201. ^ Travagnin 2009.
  202. ^ Travagnin 2009, p. 155.
  203. ^ Travagnin 2009, p. 28, 65, 85.
  204. ^ Travagnin 2009, p. 174.
  205. ^ Travagnin 2009, p. 159.
  206. ^ a b Zeuschner, Robert B., The Hsie Tsung Chi (An Early Ch'an (Zen) Buddhist Text) Journal of Chinese Philosophy V. 3 (1976) pp. 253-268.
  207. ^ Thich Nhat Hanh 1988.
  208. ^ Williams 2009, p. 86.
  209. ^ a b Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 115.
  210. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 116.
  211. ^ Dr. Vemuri Ramesam, A Critique Of John Wheeler's "You Were Never Born"
  212. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 117.
  213. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 129.
  214. ^ Williams 2009, p. 88.
  215. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 6.
  216. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 127.
  217. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 131.
  218. ^ Garfield & Westerhoff 2015, p. 135.
  219. ^ a b Renard 2010, p. 157.
  220. ^ Comans 2000, p. 35-36.
  221. ^ a b Bhattacharya 1943, p. 49.
  222. ^ Renard 2010, p. 160.
  223. ^ Suzuki 1999.
  224. ^ Suzuki 1999, p. 123-124.
  225. ^ Suzuki 1999, p. 168.
  226. ^ a b c Sarma 1996, p. 127.
  227. ^ a b Ben-Ami Scharfstein, A Comparative History of World Philosophy: From the Upanishads to Kant, p 380.
  228. ^ a b Comans 2000, p. 36.
  229. ^ a b King, Richard, Early Advaita and madhyamaka Buddhism: The case of the Gaudapadiyakarika.
  230. ^ Gregory Joseph Darling, An Evaluation of the Vedāntic Critique of Buddhism p 358.
  231. ^ a b c Reynolds, Eric T. On the relationship of Advaita Vedanta and Madhyamika Buddhism, 1969.
  232. ^ Long, Jeffery; Jainism: An Introduction, page 66, 216.
  233. ^ W. J. Johnson, Harmless Souls: Karmic Bondage and Religious Change in Early Jainism with Special Reference to Umāsvāti and Kundakunda, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., 1995, p 285.
  234. ^ Chapple, Christopher Key, John Thomas Casey (Translator), Reconciling Yogas: Haribhadra's Collection of Views on Yoga With a New Translation of Haribhadra's Yogadrstisamuccaya, p. 60.
  235. ^ Ruegg 1981, p. 2.
  236. ^ Garfield and Samten 2006, p. xx.
  237. ^ Daye 1971, p. 77.
  238. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 9–10.
  239. ^ Kalupahana 1992.
  240. ^ Hayes 2003, p. 3-5.
  241. ^ a b c d Huntington, C. W. Jr. (2007). "The nature of the Madhyamika trick". Journal of Indian Philosophy. 35 (2): 103–131. doi:10.1007/s10781-007-9018-4. S2CID 6043097.
  242. ^ Magee, 1999, p. 126, "Hayes is misidentifying Nagarjuna's intended meaning of svabhava. In contradistinction to Hayes' belief that Nagarjuna speaks equivocably of an identity nature and a causally independent, non-existent nature, Dzong-ka-ba feels that in chapter XV.1-2 Nagarjuna uses the term svabhava to refer to an existent emptiness nature."
  243. ^ Garfield 1995.
  244. ^ Napper 1989.
  245. ^ Hopkins 1996.
  246. ^ Siderits, Mark, Studies in Buddhist philosophy, p 38.
  247. ^ Westerhoff 2009, p. 208.

Web references

  1. ^ Emptiness. Buddhist and Beyond
  2. ^ . Archived from the original on 2018-12-01. Retrieved 2015-05-11.
  3. ^ Emptiness teachings
  4. ^
  5. ^ Patrick jennings (2014), Tsongkhapa: In Praise of Relativity; The Essence of Eloquence 2015-05-18 at the Wayback Machine
  6. ^
  7. ^ Susan Kahn, The Two Truths of Buddhism and The Emptiness of Emptiness.
  8. ^ emptiness.co, Coming from the Advaitic/Awareness Teachings? Special Pointers
  9. ^ . Archived from the original on 2013-05-30. Retrieved 2019-01-03.

Sources

  • Arena, Leonardo Vittorio (2012), Nonsense as the Meaning, ebook
  • Arnold, Dan (2010). Nāgārjuna's 'Middle Way': A Non-Eliminative Understanding of Selflessness. In:Revue Internationale de Philosophie vol. 64, no.253: 367-395
  • Bhattacharya, Vidhushekhara (1943), Gauḍapādakārikā, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Brunnholzl, Karl (2004), Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition, Snow Lion Publications
  • Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature. Shambhala Publications. ISBN 9781559399142.
  • Cabezón, José Ignacio; Dargyay, Lobsang (2013). Freedom from Extremes: Gorampa's "Distinguishing the Views" and the Polemics of Emptiness. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 9780861718573.
  • Cheng, Hsueh-Li (1981), "The Roots of Zen Buddhism", Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 8 (4): 451–478, doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.1981.tb00267.x
  • Comans, Michael (2000), The Method of Early Advaita Vedānta: A Study of Gauḍapāda, Śaṅkara, Sureśvara, and Padmapāda, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Cornu, Philippe (2001), "Nawoord", Schijn en werkelijkheid. De twee waarheden in de vier boeddhistische leerstelsels, KunchabPublicaties
  • Cowherds (2010). Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199826506.
  • Daye, Douglas D. (1971), Major Schools of the Mahayana: Madhyamaka. In:Charles S. Prebisch, Buddhism, A Modern Perspective. Pages 76-96., ISBN 978-0-271-01195-0
  • Fuller, Paul (2005), (PDF), Routledge, archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-12-02
  • Garfield, Jay L. (1994), "Dependent Arising and the Emptiness of Emptiness: Why Did Nāgārjuna Start with Causation?", Philosophy East & West, 44 (2): 219–250, doi:10.2307/1399593, JSTOR 1399593, S2CID 51932733
  • Garfield, Jay L. (1995), The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way, Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Garfield, Jay L. (2012), Madhyamaka is Not Nihilism (PDF), Smith College, University of Melbourne
  • Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals?. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780190231293.
  • Gomez, Luis O. (1976), , Philosophy East and West, 26 (2): 137–165, doi:10.2307/1398186, JSTOR 1398186, archived from the original on 2016-03-03, retrieved 2015-12-06
  • Harvey, Peter (1995), An introduction to Buddhism. Teachings, history and practices, Cambridge University Press
  • Hayes, Richard P. (1994), Nagarjuna's appeal. In: Journal of Indian Philosophy 22: 299-378
  • Hayes, Richard P. (2003), Nagarjuna: Master of Paradox, Mystic or Perpetrator of Fallacies? (PDF)
  • Hookham, S.K. (1991), The Buddha within : Tathagatagarbha doctrine according to the Shentong interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, ISBN 978-0791403587
  • Hopkins, Jeffrey; Napper, Elizabeth (1996), Meditation on Emptiness
  • Kalupahana, David J. (1992), The Principles of Buddhist Psychology, Delhi: ri Satguru Publications
  • Kalupahana, David J. (1994), A History of Buddhist philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited
  • Loy, David (2006), Second Buddha : Nagarjuna - Buddhism's Greatest Philosopher. In: Winter 2006 edition of Tricycle : The Buddhist Review
  • Magee, William (1999), The Nature of Things. Emptiness and Essence in the Geluk World, Ithaca, New York: Snow Lion
  • Napper, Elizabeth (1989), Dependent-Arising and Emptiness, ISBN 0-86171-057-6
  • Newland, Guy (2009). Introduction to Emptiness: As Taught in Tsong-kha-pa's Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path. Snow Lion. ISBN 9781559393324.
  • Ng, Yu-kwan (1990), , Hamilton, Ontario: dissertation, McMaster University, p. 1, archived from the original on February 3, 2014
  • Ozkan, Cuma (2013). A comparative analysis: Buddhist Madhyamaka and Daoist Chongxuan (twofold mystery) in the early Tang (618-720) (MA). University of Iowa. doi:10.17077/etd.o9rxrm2t.
  • Renard, Philip (2010), Non-Dualisme. De directe bevrijdingsweg, Cothen: Uitgeverij Juwelenschip
  • Rizzi, Cesare (1988), Candrakirti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited
  • Ruegg, D. Seyfort (1981), The literature of the Madhyamaka school of philosophy in India (A History of Indian literature), Harrassowitz, ISBN 978-3-447-02204-0
  • Sarma, Chandradhar (1996), The Advaita Tradition in Indian Philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Shantarakshita; Ju Mipham (2005), The Adornment of the Middle Way, Padmakara Translation, ISBN 1-59030-241-9
  • Suzuki, Daisetz Teitarō (1999), Studies in the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Thich Nhat Hanh (1988), The Heart of Understanding: Commentaries on the Prajnaparamita Heart Sutra
  • Travagnin, Stefania (2009). The Madhyamika Dimension of Yin Shun. A restatement of the school of Nagarjuna in 20th century Chinese Buddhism (PDF) (PhD). University of London.
  • Tsondru, Mabja (2011). Ornament of Reason: The Great Commentary To Nagarjuna's Root Of The Middle Way. Shambhala Publications. ISBN 9781559397421.
  • Tsongkhapa, Lobsang Dragpa; Sparham, Gareth, trans.; in collaboration with Shotaro Iida (1993). Kapstein, Matthew (ed.). Ocean of Eloquence: Tsong kha pa's Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind (in Tibetan and English) (1་ ed.). Albany, NY: State University of New York. ISBN 0791414795. Retrieved 18 December 2012.
  • Tsong Khapa (2002), The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment: Volume 3, Snow Lion Publications, ISBN 1-55939-166-9
  • rJe Tsong Kha Pa; Garfield (tr.), Jay L.; Samten (tr.), Ngawang (2006), Ocean of Reasoning, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-514733-9
  • Vetter, Tilmann (1988), The Ideas and Meditative Practices of Early Buddhism (PDF), BRILL, ISBN 90-04-08959-4
  • Walser, Joseph (2005). Nagarjuna in Context: Mahayana Buddhism and Early Indian Culture. Columbia University Press. ISBN 9780231506236.
  • Warder, A. K. (2000), Indian Buddhism, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers
  • Westerhoff, Jan (2009). Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199705115.
  • Williams, Paul (2000). Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition. Routledge. ISBN 9780415207003.
  • Williams, Paul (2002). Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition. Routledge. ISBN 9781134623259.
  • Williams, Paul (2009). Mahāyāna Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. ISBN 9780415356534.
  • Wynne, Alexander (2007), The Origin of Buddhist Meditation, Routledge

Further reading

  • Della Santina, Peter (1986), Madhyamaka Schools in India, New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Harris, Ian Charles (1991), The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism, New York: E. J.Brill
  • His Holiness the Fourteenth Dalai Lama (Tenzin Gyatso) (2009), The Middle Way: Faith Grounded in Reason, Boston: Wisdom Publications
  • Huntington, C. W., Jr. (1989). The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Madhyamika. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press
  • Jones, Richard H. (2014), Nagarjuna: Buddhism's Most Important Philosopher, New York: Jackson Square Books
  • Jones, Richard H. (2012), Indian Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy After Nagarjuna, 2 vols., New York: Jackson Square Books
  • Narain, Harsh. The Mādhyamika mind. Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 1997.

External links

  • The Mādhyamika or the Śūnyavāda school, Surendranath Dasgupta, 1940
  • "Madhyamaka Buddhism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • "Nagarjuna". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Thinking in Buddhism: Nagarjuna's Middle Way
  • thezensite: articles on Nagarjuna
  • Introduction to the Middle Way A contemporary commentary based on the teachings of Dzongsar Khyentse Rinpoche
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Madhyamaka
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Nagarjuna

madhyamaka, ancient, city, madhyamika, nagari, rajasthan, mādhyamaka, middle, centrism, chinese, 中觀見, pinyin, zhōngguān, jìan, tibetan, དབ, otherwise, known, Śūnyavāda, emptiness, doctrine, niḥsvabhāvavāda, svabhāva, doctrine, refers, tradition, buddhist, phil. For the ancient city of Madhyamika see Nagari Rajasthan Madhyamaka middle way or centrism Chinese 中觀見 pinyin Zhōngguan Jian Tibetan དབ མ པ dbu ma pa otherwise known as Sunyavada the emptiness doctrine and Niḥsvabhavavada the no svabhava doctrine refers to a tradition of Buddhist philosophy and practice founded by the Indian Buddhist monk and philosopher Nagarjuna c 150 c 250 CE 1 2 3 The foundational text of the Madhyamaka tradition is Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika Root Verses on the Middle Way More broadly Madhyamaka also refers to the ultimate nature of phenomena as well as the non conceptual realization of ultimate reality that is experienced in meditation 4 Classical Indian Madhyamika thinkers Clockwise from upper left Nagarjuna founder Bhavaviveka and Candrakirti commentators Santarakṣita synthesized the school with Yogacara Since the 4th century CE onwards Madhyamaka philosophy had a major influence on the subsequent development of the Mahayana Buddhist tradition 5 especially following the spread of Buddhism throughout Asia 5 6 It is the dominant interpretation of Buddhist philosophy in Tibetan Buddhism and has also been influential in East Asian Buddhist thought 5 7 According to the classical Indian Madhyamika thinkers all phenomena dharmas are empty sunya of nature 8 of any substance or essence svabhava which could give them solid and independent existence because they are dependently co arisen 9 But this emptiness itself is also empty it does not have an existence on its own nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality 10 11 12 Contents 1 Etymology 2 Philosophical overview 2 1 Svabhava what madhyamaka denies 2 2 The two truths 2 3 The nature of ultimate reality 2 4 The Middle Way 2 5 The usefulness of reason 2 6 Soteriology 2 7 Does madhyamaka have a position 3 Origins and sources 3 1 Early Buddhist Texts 3 2 Abhidharma and early Buddhist schools 3 3 Mahayana sutras 3 4 Prajnaparamita 3 5 Pyrrhonism 4 Indian madhyamaka 4 1 Nagarjuna 4 2 Classical madhyamaka figures 4 3 Yogacara madhyamaka 4 4 Vajrayana madhyamaka 5 Tibetan Buddhism 5 1 Early transmission 5 1 1 Prasaṅgika and Svatantrika interpretations 5 2 Jonang and other empty 5 3 Tsongkhapa and Gelug prasaṅgika 5 4 Sakya madhyamaka 5 5 Comparison of the views of Tsongkhapa and Gorampa 5 6 Kagyu 5 7 Nyingma 6 East Asian madhyamaka 6 1 Sanlun school 6 2 Chan 7 Western Buddhism 7 1 Thich Nhat Hanh 7 2 Modern madhyamaka 8 Influences and critiques 8 1 Yogacara 8 2 Advaita Vedanta 8 3 Jain philosophy 8 4 Taoism 9 Modern scholarship 10 See also 11 Notes 12 References 12 1 Published references 12 2 Web references 13 Sources 14 Further reading 15 External linksEtymology EditMadhya is a Sanskrit word meaning middle It is cognate with Latin med iu s and English mid The ma suffix is a superlative giving madhyama the meaning of mid most or medium The ka suffix is used to form adjectives thus madhyamaka means middling The ika suffix is used to form possessives with a collective sense thus madhyamika mean belonging to the mid most the ika suffix regularly causes a lengthening of the first vowel and elision of the final a In a Buddhist context these terms refer to the middle path madhyama pratipada which refers to right view samyagdṛṣṭi which steers clear of the metaphysical extremes of annihilationism ucchedavada and eternalism sassatavada For example the Sanskrit Katyayanaḥsutra states that though the world relies on a duality of existence and non existence the Buddha teaches a correct view which understands that 13 Arising in the world Katyayana seen and correctly understood just as it is shows there is no non existence in the world Cessation in the world Katyayana seen and correctly understood just as it is shows there is no permanent existence in the world Thus avoiding both extremes the Tathagata teaches a dharma by the middle path madhyamaya pratipada That is this being that becomes with the arising of this that arises With ignorance as condition there is volition to be expanded with the standard formula of the 12 links of dependent origination 14 Though all Buddhist schools saw themselves as defending a middle path in accord with the Buddhist teachings the name madhyamaka refers to a school of Mahayana philosophy associated with Nagarjuna and his commentators The term madhyamika refers to adherents of the madhyamaka school Note that in both words the stress is on the first syllable Philosophical overview EditSvabhava what madhyamaka denies Edit Main article Svabhava Central to madhyamaka philosophy is sunyata emptiness and this refers to the central idea that dharmas are empty of svabhava 15 This term has been translated variously as essence intrinsic nature inherent existence own being and substance 16 17 15 Furthermore according to Richard P Hayes svabhava can be interpreted as either identity or as causal independence 18 Likewise Westerhoff notes that svabhava is a complex concept that has ontological and cognitive aspects The ontological aspects include svabhava as essence as a property which makes an object what it is as well as svabhava as substance meaning as the madhyamaka thinker Candrakirti defines it something that does not depend on anything else 15 It is substance svabhava the objective and independent existence of any object or concept which madhyamaka arguments mostly focus on refuting 19 A common structure which madhyamaka uses to negate svabhava is the catuṣkoṭi four corners or tetralemma which roughly consists of four alternatives a proposition is true a proposition is false a proposition is both true and false a proposition is neither true nor false Some of the major topics discussed by classical madhyamaka include causality change and personal identity 20 Madhyamaka s denial of svabhava does not mean a nihilistic denial of all things for in a conventional everyday sense madhyamaka does accept that one can speak of things and yet ultimately these things are empty of inherent existence 21 Furthermore emptiness itself is also empty it does not have an existence on its own nor does it refer to a transcendental reality beyond or above phenomenal reality 10 11 12 Svabhava s cognitive aspect is merely a superimposition samaropa that beings make when they perceive and conceive of things In this sense then emptiness does not exist as some kind of primordial reality but it is simply a corrective to a mistaken conception of how things exist 17 This idea of svabhava that madhyamaka denies is then not just a conceptual philosophical theory but it is a cognitive distortion that beings automatically impose on the world such as when we regard the five aggregates as constituting a single self Candrakirti compares it to someone who suffers from vitreous floaters that cause the illusion of hairs appearing in their visual field 22 This cognitive dimension of svabhava means that just understanding and assenting to madhyamaka reasoning is not enough to end the suffering caused by our reification of the world just like understanding how an optical illusion works does not make it stop functioning What is required is a kind of cognitive shift termed realization in the way the world appears and therefore some kind of practice to lead to this shift 23 As Candrakirti says For one on the road of cyclic existence who pursues an inverted view due to ignorance a mistaken object such as the superimposition samaropa on the aggregates appears as real but it does not appear to one who is close to the view of the real nature of things 24 Much of madhyamaka philosophy centers on showing how various essentialist ideas have absurd conclusions through reductio ad absurdum arguments known as prasanga in Sanskrit Chapter 15 of Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika centers on the words svabhava note 1 parabhava note 2 bhava note 3 and abhava note 4 According to Peter Harvey Nagarjuna s critique of the notion of own nature note 5 Mk ch 15 argues that anything which arises according to conditions as all phenomena do can have no inherent nature for what is depends on what conditions it Moreover if there is nothing with own nature there can be nothing with other nature para bhava i e something which is dependent for its existence and nature on something else which has own nature Furthermore if there is neither own nature nor other nature there cannot be anything with a true substantial existent nature bhava If there is no true existent then there can be no non existent abhava 30 An important element of madhyamaka refutation is that the classical Buddhist doctrine of dependent arising the idea that every phenomena is dependent on other phenomena cannot be reconciled with a conception of self nature or substance and that therefore essence theories are contrary not only to the Buddhist scriptures but to the very ideas of causality and change 31 Any enduring essential nature would prevent any causal interaction or any kind of origination For things would simply always have been and will always continue to be without any change 32 note 6 As Nagarjuna writes in the MMK We state that conditioned origination is emptiness It is mere designation depending on something and it is the middle path 24 18 Since nothing has arisen without depending on something there is nothing that is not empty 24 19 33 better source needed The two truths Edit Main article Two truths doctrineBeginning with Nagarjuna madhyamaka discerns two levels of truth conventional truth everyday commonsense reality and ultimate truth emptiness 10 34 Ultimately madhyamaka argues that all phenomena are empty of svabhava and only exist in dependence on other causes conditions and concepts Conventionally madhyamaka holds that beings do perceive concrete objects which they are aware of empirically 35 In madhyamaka this phenomenal world is the limited truth saṃvṛti satya which means to cover to conceal or obscure and thus it is a kind of ignorance 36 37 Saṃvṛti is also said to mean conventional as in a customary norm based agreed upon truth like linguistic conventions and it is also glossed as vyavahara satya transactional truth 37 Finally Chandrakirti also has a third explanation of saṃvṛti which is mutual dependence parasparasaṃbhavana 37 This seeming reality does not really exist as the highest truth realized by wisdom which is paramartha satya parama is literally supreme or ultimate and artha means object purpose or actuality and yet it has a kind of conventional reality which has its uses for reaching liberation 38 This limited truth includes everything including the Buddha himself the teachings dharma liberation and even Nagarjuna s own arguments 39 better source needed This two truth schema which did not deny the importance of convention allowed Nagarjuna to defend himself against charges of nihilism understanding both correctly meant seeing the middle way Without relying upon convention the ultimate fruit is not taught Without understanding the ultimate nirvana is not attained note 7 The limited perceived reality is an experiential reality or a nominal reality which beings impute on the ultimate reality It is not an ontological reality with substantial or independent existence 35 34 Hence the two truths are not two metaphysical realities instead according to Karl Brunnholzl the two realities refer to just what is experienced by two different types of beings with different types and scopes of perception 41 As Candrakirti says It is through the perfect and the false seeing of all entitiesThat the entities that are thus found bear two natures The object of perfect seeing is true reality And false seeing is seeming reality This means that the distinction between the two truths is primarily epistemological and dependent on the cognition of the observer not ontological 41 As Shantideva writes there are two kinds of world the one of yogins and the one of common people 42 The seeming reality is the world of samsara because conceiving of concrete and unchanging objects leads to clinging and suffering As Buddhapalita states unskilled persons whose eye of intelligence is obscured by the darkness of delusion conceive of an essence of things and then generate attachment and hostility with regard to them 43 According to Hayes the two truths may also refer to two different goals in life the highest goal of nirvana and the lower goal of commercial good The highest goal is the liberation from attachment both material and intellectual 44 The nature of ultimate reality Edit Main article SunyataAccording to Paul Williams Nagarjuna associates emptiness with the ultimate truth but his conception of emptiness is not some kind of Absolute but rather it is the very absence of true existence with regards to the conventional reality of things and events in the world 45 Because the ultimate is itself empty it is also explained as a transcendence of deception and hence is a kind of apophatic truth which experiences the lack of substance 3 Because the nature of ultimate reality is said to be empty empty even of emptiness itself both the concept of emptiness and the very framework of the two truths are also mere conventional realities not part of the ultimate This is often called the emptiness of emptiness and refers to the fact that even though madhyamikas speak of emptiness as the ultimate unconditioned nature of things this emptiness is itself empty of any real existence 46 The two truths themselves are therefore just a practical tool used to teach others but do not exist within the actual meditative equipoise that realizes the ultimate 47 As Candrakirti says the noble ones who have accomplished what is to be accomplished do not see anything that is delusive or not delusive 48 From within the experience of the enlightened ones there is only one reality which appears non conceptually as Nagarjuna says in the Sixty stanzas on reasoning that nirvana is the sole reality is what the Victors have declared 49 Bhavaviveka s Madhyamakahrdayakarika describes the ultimate truth through a negation of all four possibilities of the catuskoti 50 Its character is neither existent nor nonexistent Nor both existent and nonexistent nor neither Centrists should know true reality That is free from these four possibilities Atisha describes the ultimate as here there is no seeing and no seer no beginning and no end just peace It is nonconceptual and nonreferential it is inexpressible unobservable unchanging and unconditioned 51 Because of the non conceptual nature of the ultimate according to Brunnholzl the two truths are ultimately inexpressible as either one or different 52 The Middle Way Edit Main article Middle WayAs noted by Roger Jackson some non Buddhist writers like some Buddhist writers both ancient and modern have argued that the madhyamaka philosophy is nihilistic This claim has been challenged by others who argue that it is a Middle Way madhyamapratipad between nihilism and eternalism 53 54 55 Madhyamaka philosophers themselves explicitly rejected the nihilist interpretation from the outset Nagarjuna writes through explaining true reality as it is the seeming samvrti does not become disrupted 56 Candrakirti also responds to the charge of nihilism in his Lucid Words Therefore emptiness is taught in order to completely pacify all discursiveness without exception So if the purpose of emptiness is the complete peace of all discursiveness and you just increase the web of discursiveness by thinking that the meaning of emptiness is nonexistence you do not realize the purpose of emptiness at all 57 This although some scholars e g Murti interpret emptiness as described by Nagarjuna as a Buddhist transcendental absolute other scholars such as David Kalupahana consider this claim a mistake since then emptiness teachings could not be characterized as a middle way 58 59 Madhyamaka thinkers also argue that since things have the nature of lacking true existence or own being niḥsvabhava all things are mere conceptual constructs prajnaptimatra because they are just impermanent collections of causes and conditions 60 This also applies to the principle of causality itself since everything is dependently originated 61 Therefore in madhyamaka phenomena appear to arise and cease but in an ultimate sense they do not arise or remain as inherently existent phenomena 62 63 note 8 This tenet is held to show that views of absolute or eternalist existence such as the Hindu ideas of Brahman or sat dravya and nihilism are both equally untenable 62 64 21 These two views are considered to be the two extremes that madhyamaka steers clear from The first is essentialism 65 or eternalism sastavadava 21 a belief that things inherently or substantially exist and are therefore efficacious objects of craving and clinging 65 Nagarjuna argues that we naively and innately perceive things as substantial and it is this predisposition which is the root delusion that lies at the basis of all suffering 65 The second extreme is nihilism 65 or annihilationism ucchedavada 21 encompassing views that could lead one to believe that there is no need to be responsible for one s actions such as the idea that one is annihilated at death or that nothing has causal effects but also the view that absolutely nothing exists The usefulness of reason Edit In madhyamaka reason and debate are understood as a means to an end liberation and therefore they must be founded on the wish to help oneself and others end suffering 66 Reason and logical arguments however such as those employed by classical Indian philosophers i e pramana are also seen as being empty of any true validity or reality They serve only as conventional remedies for our delusions 67 Nagarjuna s Vigrahavyavartani famously attacked the notion that one could establish a valid cognition or epistemic proof pramana If your objects are well established through valid cognitions tell us how you establish these valid cognitions If you think they are established through other valid cognitions there is an infinite regress Then the first one is not established nor are the middle ones nor the last If these valid cognitions are established even without valid cognition what you say is ruined In that case there is an inconsistency And you ought to provide an argument for this distinction 68 Candrakirti comments on this statement by stating that madhyamaka does not completely deny the use of pramanas conventionally and yet ultimately they do not have a foundation Therefore we assert that mundane objects are known through the four kinds of authoritative cognition They are mutually dependent when there is authoritative cognition there are objects of knowledge when there are objects of knowledge there is authoritative cognition But neither authoritative cognition nor objects of knowledge exist inherently 69 To the charge that if Nagarjuna s arguments and words are also empty they therefore lack the power to refute anything Nagarjuna responds that My words are without nature Therefore my thesis is not ruined Since there is no inconsistency I do not have to state an argument for a distinction 70 Nagarjuna goes on Just as one magical creation may be annihilated by another magical creation and one illusory person by another person produced by an illusionist this negation is the same 71 Shantideva makes the same point thus when one s son dies in a dream the conception he does not exist removes the thought that he does exist but it is also delusive 72 In other words madhyamaka thinkers accept that their arguments just like all things are not ultimately valid in some foundational sense But one is still able to use the opponent s own reasoning apparatus in the conventional field to refute their theories and help them see their errors This remedial deconstruction does not replace false theories of existence with other ones but simply dissolves all views including the very fictional system of epistemic warrants pramanas used to establish them 73 The point of madhyamaka reasoning is not to establish any abstract validity or universal truth it is simply a pragmatic project aimed at ending delusion and suffering 74 Nagarjuna also argues that madhyamaka only negates things conventionally since ultimately there is nothing there to negate I do not negate anything and there is also nothing to be negated 75 Therefore it is only from the perspective of those who cling to the existence of things that it seems as if something is being negated In truth madhyamaka is not annihilating something merely elucidating that this so called existence never existed in the first place 75 Thus madhyamaka uses language to make clear the limits of our concepts Ultimately reality cannot be depicted by concepts 10 76 According to Jay Garfield this creates a sort of tension in madhyamaka literature since it has use some concepts to convey its teachings 76 Soteriology Edit For madhyamaka the realization of emptiness is not just a satisfactory theory about the world but a key understanding which allows one to reach liberation or nirvana As Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika Root Verses on the Middle Way puts it With the cessation of ignorance formations will not arise Moreover the cessation of ignorance occurs through right understanding Through the cessation of this and that this and that will not come about The entire mass of suffering thereby completely ceases 77 The words this and that allude to the mind s profound addiction to dualism but also and more specifically to the mind that has not yet grasped the reality of dependent origination The insight of dependent origination that nothing arises or happens independently that everything is rooted in or made of something else and conditioned by other things each of which are likewise made of and conditioned by other things in the same way so that nothing at all is independently is central to the fundamental Buddhist analysis of the arising of suffering and the liberation from it Therefore according to Nagarjuna the cognitive shift which sees the nonexistence of svabhava leads to the cessation of the first link in this chain of suffering which then leads to the ending of the entire chain of causes and thus of all suffering 77 Nagarjuna adds Liberation moksa results from the cessation of actions karman and defilements klesa Actions and defilements result from representations vikalpa These come from false imagining prapanca False imagining stops in emptiness sunyata 18 5 78 better source needed Therefore the ultimate aim of understanding emptiness is not philosophical insight as such but the actualization of a liberated mind which does not cling to anything To encourage this awakening meditation on emptiness may proceed in stages starting with the emptiness of self of objects and of mental states 79 culminating in a natural state of nonreferential freedom 80 note 9 Moreover the path to understanding ultimate truth is not one that negates or invalidates relative truths especially truths about the path to awakening Instead it is only through properly understanding and using relative truth that the ultimate can be attained as Bhavaviveka maintains In order to guide beginners a method is taught comparable to the steps of a staircase that leads to perfect Buddhahood Ultimate reality is only to be entered once we have understood seeming reality 81 Does madhyamaka have a position Edit Nagarjuna is famous for arguing that his philosophy was not a view and that he in fact did not take any position paksa or thesis pratijna whatsoever since this would just be another form of clinging to some form of existence 82 69 In his Vigrahavyavartani Nagarjuna states If I had any position I thereby would be at fault Since I have no position I am not at fault at all If there were anything to be observed through direct perception and the other instances of valid cognition it would be something to be established or rejected However since no such thing exists I cannot be criticized 83 Likewise in his Sixty Stanzas on Reasoning Nagarjuna says By taking any standpoint whatsoever you will be snatched by the cunning snakes of the afflictions Those whose minds have no standpoint will not be caught 84 Randall Collins argues that for Nagarjuna ultimate reality is simply the idea that no concepts are intelligible while Ferrer emphasizes that Nagarjuna criticized those whose mind held any positions and beliefs including the view of emptiness As Nagarjuna says The Victorious Ones have announced that emptiness is the relinquishing of all views Those who are possessed of the view of emptiness are said to be incorrigible 85 86 Aryadeva echoes this idea in his Four Hundred Verses First one puts an end to what is not meritorious In the middle one puts an end to identity Later one puts an end to all views Those who understand this are skilled 87 Other writers however do seem to affirm emptiness as a specific madhyamaka thesis or view Shantideva for example says one cannot uphold any faultfinding in the thesis of emptiness and Bhavaviveka s Blaze of Reasoning says as for our thesis it is the emptiness of nature because this is the nature of phenomena 88 Jay Garfield notes that Nagarjuna and Candrakirti both make positive arguments and cites both the Mulamadhyamakakarika Root Verses on the Middle Way There does not exist anything that is not dependently arisen Therefore there does not exist anything that is not empty and Candrakirti s commentary on it We assert the statement Emptiness itself is a designation 69 These positions are not really in contradiction however since madhyamaka can be said to have the thesis of emptiness only conventionally in the context of debating or explaining it According to Karl Brunnholzl even though madhyamaka thinkers may express a thesis pedagogically what they deny is that they have any thesis that involves real existence or reference points or any thesis that is to be defended from their own point of view 89 Brunnholzl underlines that madhyamaka analysis applies to all systems of thought ideas and concepts including madhyamaka itself This is because the nature of madhyamaka is the deconstruction of any system and conceptualization whatsoever including itself 90 In the Root verses on the Middle Way Nagarjuna illustrates this point By the flaw of having views about emptiness those of little understanding are ruined just as when incorrectly seizing a snake or mistakenly practicing an awareness mantra 91 Origins and sources EditThe madhyamaka school is usually considered to have been founded by Nagarjuna though it may have existed earlier 92 Various scholars have noted that some of themes in the work of Nagarjuna can also be found in earlier Buddhist sources Early Buddhist Texts Edit It is well known that the only sutra that Nagarjuna explicitly cites in his Mulamadhyamakakarika Chapter 15 7 is the Advice to Katyayana He writes according to the Instructions to Katyayana both existence and nonexistence are criticized by the Blessed One who opposed being and non being 93 This appears to have been a Sanskrit version of the Kaccanagotta Sutta Saṃyutta Nikaya ii 16 17 SN 12 15 with parallel in the Chinese Saṃyuktagama 301 93 The Kaccanagotta Sutta itself says This world Kaccana for the most part depends on a duality upon the notion of existence and the notion of nonexistence But for one who sees the origin of the world as it really is with correct wisdom there is no notion of nonexistence in regard to the world And for one who sees the cessation of the world as it really is with correct wisdom there is no notion of existence in regard to the world 93 Joseph Walser also points out that verse six of chapter 15 contains an allusion to the Mahahatthipadopama sutta another early sutra of the Nidanavagga the collection which also contains the Kaccanagotta and which contains various sutras that focus on the avoidance of extreme views which are all held to be associated with either the extreme of eternality sasvata or the extreme of disruption uccheda 93 Another allusion to an early Buddhist text noted by Walser occurs in Nagarjuna s Ratnavali chapter 1 where he makes reference to a statement in the Kevaddha sutta 94 Some scholars like Tillman Vetter and Luis Gomez have also seen some passages from the early Aṭṭhakavagga Pali Octet Chapter and the Parayanavagga Pali Way to the Far Shore Chapter which focusing on letting go of all views as teaching a kind of Proto Madhyamika note 10 95 96 Other scholars such as Paul Fuller and Alexander Wynne have rejected the arguments of Gomez and Vetter 97 98 note 11 Finally the Dazhidulun a text attributed to Nagarjuna in the Chinese tradition though this attribution has been questioned cites the Sanskrit Arthavargiya sutra which parallels the Aṭṭhakavagga in its discussion of ultimate truth 99 Abhidharma and early Buddhist schools Edit The madhyamaka school has been perhaps simplistically regarded as a reaction against the development of Buddhist abhidharma however according to Joseph Walser this is problematic 100 In abhidharma dharmas are characterized by defining traits lakṣaṇa or own existence svabhava The Abhidharmakosabhaṣya states for example dharma means upholding namely upholding intrinsic nature svabhava while the Mahavibhaṣa states intrinsic nature is able to uphold its own identity and not lose it 101 However this does not mean that all abhidharma systems hold that dharmas exist independently in an ontological sense since all Buddhist schools hold that most dharmas are dependently originated this doctrine being a central core Buddhist view Therefore in abhidharma svabhava is typically something which arises dependent on other conditions and qualities 101 Svabhava in the early abhidharma systems then is not a kind of ontological essentialism but it is a way to categorize dharmas according to their distinctive characteristics According to Noa Ronkin the idea of svabhava evolved towards ontological dimension in the Sarvastivadin Vaibhasika school s interpretation which began to also use the term dravya which means real existence 101 This then may have been the shift which Nagarjuna sought to attack when he targets certain Sarvastivada tenets However the relationship between madhyamaka and abhidharma is complex as Joseph Walser notes Nagarjuna s position vis a vis abhidharma is neither a blanket denial nor a blanket acceptance Nagarjuna s arguments entertain certain abhidharmic standpoints while refuting others 100 One example can be seen in Nagarjuna s Ratnavali which supports the study of a list of 57 moral faults which Nagarjuna takes from the Ksudravastuka an abhidharma texts that is part of the Sarvastivada Dharmaskandha 102 Abhidharmic analysis figures prominently in madhyamaka treatises and authoritative commentators like Candrakirti emphasize that abhidharmic categories function as a viable and favored system of conventional truths they are more refined than ordinary categories and they are not dependent on either the extreme of eternalism or on the extreme view of the discontinuity of karma as the non Buddhist categories of the time did Walser also notes that Nagarjuna s theories have much in common with the view of a sub sect of the Mahasamgikas called the Prajnaptivadins who held that suffering was prajnapti designation by provisional naming based on conditioned entities that are themselves reciprocally designated anyonya prajnapti 103 David Burton argues that for Nagarjuna dependently arisen entities have merely conceptually constructed existence prajnaptisat 103 Commenting on this Walser writes that Nagarjuna is arguing for a thesis that the Prajnaptivadins already held using a concept of prajnapti that they were already using 57 Mahayana sutras Edit According to David Seyfort Ruegg the main canonical Mahayana sutra sources of the Madhyamaka school are the Prajnaparamita Ratnakuṭa and Avataṃsaka literature 104 Other sutras which were widely cited by Madhamikas include the Vimalakirtinirdeṣa the Suraṃgamasamadhi the Saddharmapuṇḍarika the Dasabhumika the Akṣayamatinirdesa the Tathagataguhyaka and the Kasyapaparivarta 104 Ruegg notes that in Candrakirti s Prasannapada and Madhyamakavatara in addition to the Prajnaparamita we find the Akṣayamatinirdesa Anavataptahradapasaṃkramaṇa Upaliparipṛccha Kasyapaparivarta Gaganaganja Tathagataguhya Dasabhumika Dṛḍhadhyasaya Dharaṇisvararaja Pitaputrasamagama Manjusriparipṛccha Ratnakuṭa Ratnacuḍaparipṛccha Ratnamegha Ratnakara Laṅkavatara Lalitavistara Vimalakirtinirdesa Salistamba Satyadvayavatara Saddharmapuṇḍarika Samadhiraja Candrapradipa and Hastikakṣya 104 Prajnaparamita Edit Madhyamaka thought is also closely related to a number of Mahayana sources traditionally the Prajnaparamita sutras are the literature most closely associated with madhyamaka understood at least in part as an exegetical complement to those Sutras Traditional accounts also depict Nagarjuna as retrieving some of the larger Prajnaparamita sutras from the world of the Nagas explaining in part the etymology of his name Prajna or higher cognition is a recurrent term in Buddhist texts explained as a synonym of abhidharma insight vipasyana and analysis of the dharmas dharmapravicaya Within a specifically Mahayana context Prajna figures as the most prominent in a list of Six Paramitas perfections or perfect masteries that a Bodhisattva needs to cultivate in order to eventually achieve Buddhahood Madhyamaka offers conceptual tools to analyze all possible elements of existence allowing the practitioner to elicit through reasoning and contemplation the type of view that the Sutras express more authoritatively being considered word of the Buddha but less explicitly not offering corroborative arguments The vast Prajnaparamita literature emphasizes the development of higher cognition in the context of the Bodhisattva path thematically its focus on the emptiness of all dharmas is closely related to the madhyamaka approach Allusions to the prajnaparamita sutras can be found in Nagarjuna s work One example is in the opening stanza of the MMK which seem to allude to the following statement found in two prajnaparamita texts And how does he wisely know conditioned co production He wisely knows it as neither production nor stopping neither cut off nor eternal neither single nor manifold neither coming nor going away as the appeasement of all futile discoursings and as bliss 105 The first stanza of Nagarjuna s MMK meanwhile state I pay homage to the Fully Enlightened One whose true venerable words teach dependent origination to be the blissful pacification of all mental proliferation neither production nor stopping neither cut off nor eternal neither single nor manifold neither coming nor going away 105 Pyrrhonism Edit Main article Similarities between Pyrrhonism and Buddhism Because of the high degree of similarity between madhyamaka and Pyrrhonism 106 Thomas McEvilley 107 and Matthew Neale 108 109 suspect that Nagarjuna was influenced by Greek Pyrrhonist texts imported into India Pyrrho of Elis c 360 c 270 BCE who is credited with founding this school of skeptical philosophy was himself influenced by Buddhist philosophy 110 during his stay in India with Alexander the Great s army Indian madhyamaka Edit Nagarjuna right and Aryadeva middle Nagarjuna Edit As Jan Westerhoff notes while Nagarjuna is one of the greatest thinkers in the history of Asian philosophy contemporary scholars agree on hardly any details concerning him This includes exactly when he lived it can be narrowed down some time in the first three centuries CE where he lived Joseph Walser suggests Amaravati in east Deccan and exactly what constitutes his written corpus 111 Numerous texts are attributed to him but it is at least agreed by some scholars that what is called the Yukti analytical corpus is the core of his philosophical work These texts are the Root verses on the Middle way Mulamadhyamakakarika MMK the Sixty Stanzas on Reasoning Yuktiṣaṣṭika the Dispeller of Objections Vigrahavyavartani the Treatise on Pulverization Vaidalyaprakaraṇa and the Precious Garland Ratnavali 112 However even the attribution of each one of these has been question by some modern scholars except for the MMK which is by definition seen as his major work 112 Nagarjuna s main goal is often seen by scholars as refuting the essentialism of certain Buddhist abhidharma schools mainly Vaibhasika which posited theories of svabhava essential nature and also the Hindu Nyaya and Vaiseṣika schools which posited a theory of ontological substances dravyatas 113 In the MMK he used reductio ad absurdum arguments prasanga to show that any theory of substance or essence was unsustainable and therefore phenomena dharmas such as change causality and sense perception were empty sunya of any essential existence Nagarjuna also famously equated the emptiness of dharmas with their dependent origination 114 115 116 note 12 Because of his philosophical work Nagarjuna is seen by some modern interpreters as restoring the Middle Way of the Buddha which had become challenged by absolutist metaphysical tendencies in certain philosophical quarters 117 114 Classical madhyamaka figures Edit Rahulabhadra was an early madhyamika sometimes said to be either a teacher of Nagarjuna or his contemporary and follower He is most famous for his verses in praise of the Prajnaparamita Skt Prajnaparamitastotra and Chinese sources maintain that he also composed a commentary on the MMK which was translated by Paramartha 118 Nagarjuna s pupil Aryadeva 3rd century CE wrote various works on madhyamaka the most well known of which is his 400 verses His works are regarded as a supplement to Nagarjuna s 119 on which he commented 120 Aryadeva also wrote refutations of the theories of non Buddhist Indian philosophical schools 120 There are also two commentaries on the MMK which may be by Aryadeva the Akutobhaya which has also been regarded as an auto commentary by Nagarjuna as well as a commentary which survives only in Chinese as part of the Chung Lun Middle treatise Taisho 1564 attributed to a certain Ch ing mu aka Pin lo chieh which some scholars have also identified as possibly being Aryadeva 121 However Brian C Bocking a translator of the Chung Lung also states that it is likely the author of this commentary was a certain Vimalaksa who was Kumarajiva s old Vinaya master from Kucha 122 An influential commentator on Nagarjuna was Buddhapalita 470 550 who has been interpreted as developing the prasaṅgika approach to Nagarjuna s works in his Madhyamakavṛtti now only extant in Tibetan which follows the orthodox Madhyamaka method by critiquing essentialism mainly through reductio ad absurdum arguments 123 Like Nagarjuna Buddhapalita s main philosophical method is to show how all philosophical positions are ultimately untenable and self contradictory a style of argumentation called prasanga 123 Buddhapalita s method is often contrasted with that of Bhavaviveka c 500 c 578 who argued in his Prajnapadipa Lamp of Wisdom for the use of logical arguments using the pramana based epistemology of Indian logicians like Dignaga In what would become a source of much future debate Bhavaviveka criticized Buddhapalita for not putting madhyamaka arguments into proper autonomous syllogisms svatantra 124 Bhavaviveka argued that madhyamika s should always put forth syllogistic arguments to prove the truth of the madhyamaka thesis Instead of just criticizing other s arguments a tactic called vitaṇḍa attacking which was seen in bad form in Indian philosophical circles Bhavaviveka held that madhyamikas must positively prove their position using sources of knowledge pramanas agreeable to all parties 125 He argued that the position of a madhyamaka was simply that phenomena are devoid of an inherent nature 123 This approach has been labeled the svatantrika style of madhyamaka by Tibetan philosophers and commentators Another influential commentator Candrakirti c 600 650 sought to defend Buddhapalita and critique Bhavaviveka s position and Dignaga that one must construct independent svatantra arguments to positively prove the madhyamaka thesis on the grounds this contains a subtle essentialist commitment 123 He argued that madhyamikas do not have to argue by svantantra but can merely show the untenable consequences prasaṅga of all philosophical positions put forth by their adversary 126 Furthermore for Candrakirti there is a problem with assuming that the madhyamika and the essentialist opponent can begin with the same shared premises that are required for this kind of syllogistic reasoning because the essentialist and the madhyamaka do not share a basic understanding of what it means for things to exist in the first place 127 Candrakirti also criticized the Buddhist yogacara school which he saw as positing a form of subjective idealism due to their doctrine of appearance only vijnaptimatra Candrakirti faults the yogacara school for not realizing that the nature of consciousness is also a conditioned phenomenon and for privileging consciousness over its objects ontologically instead of seeing that everything is empty 126 Candrakirti wrote the Prasannapada Clear Words a highly influential commentary on the Mulamadhyamakakarika as well as the Madhyamakavatara an introduction to madhyamaka His works are central to the understanding of madhyamaka in Tibetan Buddhism A later svatantrika figure is Avalokitavrata seventh century who composed a tika sub commentary on Bhavaviveka s Prajnapadipa and who mentions important figures of the era such as Dharmakirti and Candrakirti 128 Another commentator on Nagarjuna is Bhikshu Vasitva Zizai who composed a commentary on Nagarjuna s Bodhisaṃbhara that survives in a translation by Dharmagupta in the Chinese canon 129 Santideva end 7th century first half 8th century is well known for his philosophical poem discussing the bodhisattva path and the six paramitas the Bodhicaryavatara He united a deep religiousness and joy of exposure together with the unquestioned Madhyamaka orthodoxy 130 Later in the 10th century there were commentators on the works of prasangika authors such as Prajnakaramati who wrote a commentary on the Bodhicaryavatara and Jayananda who commented on Candrakirti s Madhyamakavatara 131 A lesser known treatise on the six paramitas associated with the madhyamaka school is Arya Sura s Paramitasamasa unlikely to be the same author as that of the Garland of Jatakas 132 Other lesser known madhyamikas include Devasarman fifth to sixth centuries and Gunamati the fifth to sixth centuries both of whom wrote commentaries on the MMK that exist only in Tibetan fragments 133 Yogacara madhyamaka Edit Kamalashila According to Ruegg possibly the earliest figure to work with the two schools was Vimuktisena early sixth century a commentator on the Abhisamayalamkara and also is reported to have been a pupil of Bhavaviveka as well as Vasubandhu 134 The seventh and eighth centuries saw a synthesis of the Buddhist yogacara tradition with madhyamaka beginning with the work of Srigupta Jnanagarbha Srigupta s disciple and his student Santarakṣita 8th century who like Bhavaviveka also adopted some of the terminology of the Buddhist pramana tradition in their time best represented by Dharmakirti 123 128 Like the classical madhyamaka yogacara madhyamaka approaches ultimate truth through the prasaṅga method of showing absurd consequences However when speaking of conventional reality they also make positive assertions and autonomous arguments like Bhavaviveka and Dharmakirti Santarakṣita also subsumed the yogacara system into his presentation of the conventional accepting their idealism on a conventional level as a preparation for the ultimate truth of madhyamaka 123 135 In his Madhyamakalaṃkara verses 92 93 Santarakṣita says By relying on the Mind Only cittamatra know that external entities do not exist And by relying on this madhyamaka system know that no self at all exists even in that mind Therefore due to holding the reigns of logic as one rides the chariots of the two systems one attains the path of the actual Mahayanist 136 Santarakṣita and his student Kamalasila known for his text on self development and meditation the Bhavanakrama were influential in the initial spread of madhyamaka Buddhism to Tibet note 13 Haribhadra another important figure of this school wrote an influential commentary on the Abhisamayalamkara Vajrayana madhyamaka Edit The madhyamaka philosophy continued to be of major importance during the period of Indian Buddhism when the tantric Vajrayana Buddhism rose to prominence One of the central Vajrayana madhyamaka philosophers was Arya Nagarjuna also known as the tantric Nagarjuna 7th 8th centuries who may be the author of the Bodhicittavivarana as well as a commentator on the Guhyasamaja Tantra 137 Other figures in his lineage include Nagabodhi Vajrabodhi Aryadeva pada and Candrakirti pada Later figures include Bodhibhadra c 1000 a Nalanda university master who wrote on philosophy and yoga and who was a teacher of Atisa Dipaṃkara Srijnana 982 1054 CE who was an influential figure in the transmission of Buddhism to Tibet and wrote the influential Bodhipathapradipa Lamp for the Path to Awakening 138 Tibetan Buddhism EditMadhyamaka philosophy obtained a central position in all the main Tibetan Buddhist schools all whom consider themselves to be madhyamikas Madhyamaka thought has been categorized in various ways in India and Tibet note 14 Early transmission Edit Influential early figures who are important in the transmission of madhyamaka to Tibet include the yogacara madhyamika Santarakṣita 725 788 and his students Haribhadra and Kamalashila 740 795 as well as the later Kadampa figures of Atisha 982 1054 and his pupil Dromton 1005 1064 who taught madhyamaka by using the works of Bhaviveka and Candrakirti 139 140 The early transmission of Buddhism to Tibet saw these two main strands of philosophical views in debate with each other The first was the camp which defended the yogacara madhyamaka interpretation and thus svatantrika centered on the works of the scholars of the Sangphu monastery founded by Ngog Loden Sherab 1059 1109 and also includes Chapa Chokyi Senge 1109 1169 141 The second camp was those who championed the work of Candrakirti over the yogacara madhyamaka interpretation and included Sangphu monk Patsab Nyima Drag b 1055 and Jayananda fl 12th century 141 According to John Dunne it was the madhyamaka interpretation and the works of Candrakirti which became dominant over time in Tibet 141 Another very influential figure from this early period is Mabja Jangchub Tsondru d 1185 who wrote an important commentary on Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika Mabja was a student of both the Dharmakirtian Chapa and the Candrakirti scholar Patsab and his work shows an attempt to steer a middle course between their views Mabja affirms the conventional usefulness of Buddhist pramaṇa but also accepts Candrakirti s prasangika views 142 Mabja s Madhyamaka scholarship was very influential on later Tibetan Madhyamikas such as Longchenpa Tsongkhapa Gorampa and Mikyo Dorje 143 Prasaṅgika and Svatantrika interpretations Edit Main article Svatantrika Prasaṅgika distinction In Tibetan Buddhist scholarship a distinction began to be made between the Autonomist Svatantrika rang rgyud pa and Consequentialist Prasaṅgika Thal gyur pa approaches to madhyamaka reasoning The distinction was one invented by Tibetans and not one made by classical Indian madhyamikas 144 Tibetans mainly use the terms to refer to the logical procedures used by Bhavaviveka who argued for the use of svatantra anumana or autonomous syllogisms and Buddhapalita who held that one should only use prasanga or reductio ad absurdum 145 Tibetan Buddhism further divides svatantrika into sautrantika svatantrika madhyamaka applied to Bhaviveka and yogacara svatantrika madhyamaka santarakṣita and kamalasila 146 The svatantrika states that conventional phenomena are understood to have a conventional essential existence but without an ultimately existing essence In this way they believe they are able to make positive or autonomous assertions using syllogistic logic because they are able to share a subject that is established as appearing in common the proponent and opponent use the same kind of valid cognition to establish it The name comes from this quality of being able to use autonomous arguments in debate 145 In contrast the central technique avowed by the prasaṅgika is to show by prasaṅga or reductio ad absurdum that any positive assertion such as asti or nasti it is or it is not or view regarding phenomena must be regarded as merely conventional saṃvṛti or lokavyavahara The prasaṅgika holds that it is not necessary for the proponent and opponent to use the same kind of valid cognition pramana to establish a common subject indeed it is possible to change the view of an opponent through a reductio argument Although presented as a divide in doctrine the major difference between svatantrika and prasangika may be between two style of reasoning and arguing while the division itself is exclusively Tibetan Tibetan scholars were aware of alternative madhyamaka sub classifications but later Tibetan doxography emphasizes the nomenclature of prasaṅgika versus svatantrika No conclusive evidence can show the existence of an Indian antecedent and it is not certain to what degree individual writers in Indian and Tibetan discussion held each of these views and if they held a view generally or only in particular instances Both Prasaṅgikas and Svatantrikas cited material in the agamas in support of their arguments 147 Longchen Rabjam noted in the 14th century that Candrakirti favored the prasaṅga approach when specifically discussing the analysis for ultimacy but otherwise he made positive assertions such as when describing the paths of Buddhist practice in his Madhyamakavatara Therefore even prasaṅgikas make positive assertions when discussing conventional practice they simply stick to using reductios specifically when analyzing for ultimate truth 145 Jonang and other empty Edit Thangkha with Jonang lama Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen 1292 1361 Further Tibetan philosophical developments began in response to the works of the scholar Dolpopa Sherap Gyeltsen 1292 1361 and led to two distinctly opposed Tibetan madhyamaka views on the nature of ultimate reality 148 149 An important Tibetan treatise on Emptiness and Buddha Nature is found in Dolpopa s voluminous study Mountain Doctrine 150 Dolpopa the founder of the Jonang school viewed the Buddha and Buddha Nature as not intrinsically empty but as truly real unconditioned and replete with eternal changeless virtues 151 In the Jonang school ultimate reality i e Buddha Nature tathagatagarbha is only empty of what is impermanent and conditioned conventional reality not of its own self which is ultimate Buddhahood and the luminous nature of mind 152 In Jonang this ultimate reality is a ground or substratum which is uncreated and indestructible noncomposite and beyond the chain of dependent origination 153 Basing himself on the Indian Tathagatagarbha sutras as his main sources Dolpopa described the Buddha Nature as N on material emptiness emptiness that is far from an annihilatory emptiness great emptiness that is the ultimate pristine wisdom of superiors Buddha earlier than all Buddhas causeless original Buddha 154 This great emptiness i e the tathagatagarbha is said to be filled with eternal powers and virtues P ermanent stable eternal everlasting Not compounded by causes and conditions the matrix of one gone thus is intrinsically endowed with ultimate buddha qualities of body speech and mind such as the ten powers it is not something that did not exist before and is newly produced it is self arisen 155 The Jonang position came to be known as emptiness of other gzhan stong shentong because it held that the ultimate truth was positive reality that was not empty of its own nature only empty of what it was other than itself 156 Dolpopa considered his view a form of madhyamaka and called his system Great Madhyamaka 157 Dolpopa opposed what he called rangtong self empty the view that ultimate reality is that which is empty of self nature in a relative and absolute sense that is to say that it is empty of everything including itself It is thus not a transcendental ground or metaphysical absolute which includes all the eternal Buddha qualities This rangtong shentong distinction became a central issue of contention among Tibetan Buddhist philosophers Alternative interpretations of the shentong view is also taught outside of Jonang Some Kagyu figures like Jamgon Kongtrul 1813 1899 as well as the unorthodox Sakya philosopher Sakya Chokden 1428 1507 supported their own forms of shentong Tsongkhapa and Gelug prasaṅgika Edit Tsongkhapa See also Prasaṅgika according to TsongkhapaThe Gelug school was founded in the beginning of the 15th century by Je Tsongkhapa 1357 1419 158 Tsongkhapa s conception of emptiness draws mainly from the works of prasaṅgika Indian thinkers like Buddhapalita Candrakirti and Shantideva and he argued that only their interpretation of Nagarjuna was ultimately correct According to Jose I Cabezon Tsongkhapa also argued that the ultimate truth or emptiness was an absolute negation med dgag the negation of inherent existence and that nothing was exempt from being empty including emptiness itself 156 Tsongkhapa also maintained that the ultimate truth could be understood conceptually an understanding which could later be transformed into a non conceptual one This conceptual understanding could only be done through the use of madhyamika reasoning which he also sought to unify with the logical theories of Dharmakirti 156 Because of Tsongkhapa s view of emptiness as an absolute negation he strongly attacked the other empty views of Dolpopa in his works Tsongkhapa major work on madhyamaka is his commentary on the MMK called Ocean of Reasoning 159 According to Thupten Jinpa Tsongkhapa s doctrine of the object of negation is one of his most innovative but also controversial ideas Tsongkhapa pointed out that if one wants to steer a middle course between the extremes of over negation straying into nihilism and under negation and thus reification it is important to have a clear concept of exactly what is being negated in Madhyamaka analysis termed the object of negation 160 161 According to Jay Garfield and Sonam Thakchoe for Tsongkhapa there are two aspects of the object of negation erroneous apprehension phyin ci log gi dzin pa and the existence of intrinsic nature thereby apprehended des bzung ba i rang bzhin yod pa The second aspect is an erroneously reified fiction which does not exist even conventionally This is the fundamental object of negation for Tsongkhapa since the reified object must first be negated in order to eliminate the erroneous subjective state 162 Tsongkhapa s understanding of the object of negation Tib dgag bya is subtle and he describes one aspect of it as an innate apprehension of self existence Thupten Jinpa glosses this as a belief that we have that leads us to perceive things and events as possessing some kind of intrinsic existence and identity Tsongkhapa s madhyamaka therefore does not deny the conventional existence of things per se but merely rejects our way of experiencing things as existing in an essentialist way which are false projections or imputations 160 This is the root of ignorance which for Tsongkhapa is an active defiling agency Sk klesavaraṇa which projects a false sense of reality onto objects 160 As Garfield and Thakchoe note Tsongkhapa s view allows him to preserve a robust sense of the reality of the conventional world in the context of emptiness and to provide an analysis of the relation between emptiness and conventional reality that makes clear sense of the identity of the two truths 163 Because conventional existence or mere appearance as an interdependent phenomenon devoid of inherent existence is not negated khegs pa or rationally undermined in his analysis Tsongkhapa s approach was criticized by other Tibetan madhyamikas who preferred an anti realist interpretation of madhyamaka 164 Following Candrakirti Tsongkhapa also rejected the yogacara view of mind only and instead defended the conventional existence of external objects even though ultimately they are mere thought constructions Tib rtog pas btags tsam of a deluded mind 161 Tsongkhapa also followed Candrakirti in rejecting svatantra autonomous reasoning arguing that it was enough to show the unwelcome consequences prasaṅga of essentialist positions 161 Gelug scholarship has generally maintained and defended Tsongkhapa s positions up until the present day even if there are lively debates considering issues of interpretation Jamyang Sheba Changkya Rolpe Dorje Gendun Chopel and the 14th Dalai Lama are some of the most influential modern figures in Gelug madhyamaka Sakya madhyamaka Edit Gorampa Sonam Senge the most important madhyamaka philosopher in Sakya The Sakya school has generally held a classic prasaṅgika position following Candrakirti closely though with significant differences from the Gelug Sakya scholars of Madhyamika such as Rendawa Shyonnu Lodro 1349 1412 and Rongton Sheja Kunrig 1367 1450 were early critics of the other empty view 165 Gorampa Sonam Senge 1429 1489 was an important Sakya philosopher which defended the orthodox Sakya madhyamika position critiquing both Dolpopa and Tsongkhapa s interpretations He is widely studied not only in Sakya but also in Nyingma and Kagyu institutions 166 According to Cabezon Gorampa called his version of madhyamaka the middle way qua freedom from extremes mtha bral dbu ma or middle way qua freedom from proliferations spros bral kyi dbu ma and claimed that the ultimate truth was ineffable beyond predication or concept 167 Cabezon states that Gorampa s interpretation of madhyamaka is committed to a more literal reading of the Indian sources than either Dolpopa s or Tsongkhapa s which is to say that it tends to take the Indian texts at face value 168 For Gorampa emptiness is not just the absence of inherent existence but it is the absence of the four extremes in all phenomena i e existence nonexistence both and neither see catuskoti without any further qualification 169 In other words conventional truths are also an object of negation because as Gorampa states they are not found at all when subjected to ultimate rational analysis 170 Hence Gorampa s madhyamaka negates existence itself or existence without qualifications while for Tsongkhapa the object of negation is inherent existence intrinsic existence or intrinsic nature 169 In his Elimination of Erroneous Views Lta ba ngan sel Gorampa argues that madhyamaka ultimately negates all false appearances which means anything that appears to our mind i e all conventional phenomena Since all appearances are conceptually produced illusions they must cease when conceptual reification is brought to an end by insight This is the ultimate freedom from conceptual fabrication don dam spros bral To reach this madhyamikas must negate the reality of appearances 163 In other words all conventional realities are fabrications and since awakening requires transcending all fabrication spros bral conventional reality must be negated 171 Thus for Gorampa all conventional knowledge is dualistic being based on a false distinction between subject and object 172 Therefore for Gorampa madhyamaka analyzes all supposedly real phenomena and concludes through that analysis that those things do not exist and so that so called conventional reality is entirely nonexistent 170 Regarding the Ultimate truth Gorampa saw this as being divided into two parts 169 The emptiness that is reached by rational analysis this is actually only an analogue and not the real thing The emptiness that yogis fathom by means of their own individual gnosis prajna This is the real ultimate truth which is reached by negating the previous rational understanding of emptiness Unlike most orthodox Sakyas the philosopher Sakya Chokden a contemporary of Gorampa also promoted a form of shentong as being complementary to rangtong He saw shentong as useful for meditative practice while rangtong as useful for cutting through views 173 Comparison of the views of Tsongkhapa and Gorampa Edit As Garfield and Thakchoe note for Tsongkhapa conventional truth is a kind of truth a way of being real and a kind of existence while for Gorampa the conventional is entirely false unreal a kind of nonexistence and truth only from the perspective of fools 174 Jay L Garfield and Sonam Thakchoe outline the different competing models of Gorampa and Tsongkhapa as follows 175 Gorampa s The object of negation is the conventional phenomenon itself Let us see how that plays out in an account of the status of conventional truth Since ultimate truth emptiness is an external negation and since an external negation eliminates its object while leaving nothing behind when we say that a person is empty we eliminate the person leaving nothing else behind To be sure we must as madhyamikas in agreement with ordinary persons admit that the person exists conventionally despite not existing ultimately But if emptiness eliminates the person that conventional existence is a complete illusion The ultimate emptiness of the person shows that the person simply does not exist It is no more actual than Santa Claus the protestations of ordinary people and small children to the contrary notwithstanding Tsongkhapa s The object of negation is not the conventional phenomenon itself but instead the intrinsic nature or intrinsic existence of the conventional phenomenon The consequences of taking the object of negation this way are very different On this account when we say that the person does not exist ultimately what is eliminated by its ultimate emptiness is its intrinsic existence No other intrinsic identity is projected in the place of that which was undermined by emptiness even emptiness or conventional reality But the person is not thereby eliminated Its conventional existence is therefore on this account simply its existence devoid of intrinsic identity as an interdependent phenomenon On this view conventional reality is no illusion it is the actual mode of existence of actual things According to Garfield and Thakchoe each of these radically distinct views on the nature of the two truths has scriptural support and indeed each view can be supported by citations from different passages of the same text or even slightly different contextual interpretations of the same passage 176 Kagyu Edit Mikyo Dorje 8th Karmapa Lama In the Kagyu tradition there is a broad field of opinion on the nature of emptiness with some holding the other empty shentong view while others holding different positions One influential Kagyu thinker was Rangjung Dorje 3rd Karmapa Lama His view synthesized madhyamaka and yogacara perspectives According to Karl Brunnholzl regarding his position in the rangtong shentong debate he can be said to regard these two as not being mutually exclusive and to combine them in a creative synthesis 177 However Rangjung Dorje never uses these terms in any of his works and thus any claims to him being a promoter of shentong or otherwise is a later interpretation 178 Several Kagyu figures disagree with the view that shentong is a form of madhyamaka According to Brunnholzl Mikyo Dorje 8th Karmapa Lama 1507 1554 and Second Pawo Rinpoche Tsugla Trengwa see the term shentong madhyamaka as a misnomer for them the yogacara of Asanga and Vasubandhu and the system of Nagarjuna are two clearly distinguished systems They also refute the idea that there is a permanent intrinsically existing Buddha nature 179 Mikyo Dorje also argues that the language of other emptiness does not appear in any of the sutras or the treatises of the Indian masters He attacks the view of Dolpopa as being against the sutras of ultimate meaning which state that all phenomena are emptiness as well as being against the treatises of the Indian masters 180 Mikyo Dorje rejects both perspectives of rangtong and shentong as true descriptions of ultimate reality which he sees as being the utter peace of all discursiveness regarding being empty and not being empty 181 One of the most influential Kagyu philosophers in recent times was Jamgon Kongtrul Lodro Taye 1813 1899 who advocated a system of shentong madhyamaka and held that primordial wisdom was never empty of its own nature and it is there all the time 182 183 The modern Kagyu teacher Khenpo Tsultrim 1934 in his Progressive Stages of Meditation on Emptiness presents five stages of meditation which he relates to five tenet systems 184 185 He holds the Shentong Madhyamaka as the highest view above prasangika He sees this as a meditation on Paramarthasatya Absolute Reality 186 note 15 Buddhajnana note 16 which is beyond concepts and described by terms as truly existing 188 This approach helps to overcome certain residual subtle concepts 188 and the habit fostered on the earlier stages of the path of negating whatever experience arises in his her mind 189 It destroys false concepts as does prasangika but it also alerts the practitioner to the presence of a dynamic positive Reality that is to be experienced once the conceptual mind is defeated 189 Nyingma Edit Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso 1846 1912 a key exponent of madhyamaka thought in the Nyingma school known for harmonizing madhyamaka with the dzogchen view In the nyingma school like in Kagyu there is a variety of views Some Nyingma thinkers promoted shentong like Katok Tsewang Norbu but the most influential Nyingma thinkers like Longchenpa and Ju Mipham held a more classical prasaṅgika interpretation while at the same time seeking to harmonize it with the dzogchen view found in the dzgochen tantras which are traditionally seen as the pinnacle of the nyingma view According to Sonam Thakchoe the ultimate truth in the Nyingma tradition following Longchenpa is that reality which transcends any mode of thinking and speech one that unmistakenly appears to the nonerroneous cognitive processes of the exalted and awakened beings and this is said to be inexpressible beyond words and thoughts as well as the reality that is the transcendence of all elaborations 190 The most influential modern Nyingma scholar is Jamgon Ju Mipham Gyatso 1846 1912 He developed a unique theory of madhyamaka with two models of the two truths While he adopts the traditional madhyamaka model of two truths in which the ultimate truth is emptiness he also developed a second model in which the ultimate truth is reality as it is de bzhin nyid which is established as ultimately real bden par grub pa 190 This ultimate truth is associated with the Dzogchen concept of Rigpa While it might seem that this system conflicts with the traditional madhyamaka interpretation for Mipham this is not so For while the traditional model which sees emptiness and ultimate truth as a negation is referring to the analysis of experience the second Dzogchen influenced model refers to the experience of unity in meditation 191 Douglas Duckworth sees Mipham s work as an attempt to bring together the two main Mahayana philosophical systems of yogacara and madhyamaka as well as shentong and rangtong into a coherent system in which both are seen as being of definitive meaning 192 Regarding the svatantrika prasangika debate Ju Mipham explained that using positive assertions in logical debate may serve a useful purpose either while debating with non Buddhist schools or to move a student from a coarser to a more subtle view Similarly discussing an approximate ultimate helps students who have difficulty using only prasaṅga methods move closer to the understanding of the true ultimate Ju Mipham felt that the ultimate non enumerated truth of the svatantrika was no different from the ultimate truth of the Prasaṅgika He felt the only difference between them was with respect to how they discussed conventional truth and their approach to presenting a path 145 East Asian madhyamaka Edit A painting of Kumarajiva at White Horse Pagoda Dunhuang Sanlun school Edit Chinese madhyamaka known as sanlun or the three treatise school began with the work of Kumarajiva 344 413 CE who translated the works of Nagarjuna including the MMK also known in China as the Chung lun Madhyamakasastra Taishō 1564 to Chinese Another influential text in Chinese madhyamaka which was said to have been translated by Kumarajiva was the Ta chih tu lun or Mahaprajnaparamitopadesa Sastra Treatise which is a Teaching on the Great Perfection of Wisdom Sutra According to Dan Arnold this text is only extant in Kumarajiva s translation and has material that differs from the work of Nagarjuna In spite of this the Ta chih tu lun became a central text for Chinese interpretations of madhyamaka emptiness 193 Sanlun figures like Kumarajiva s pupil Sengzhao 384 414 and the later Jizang 549 623 were influential in restoring a more orthodox and non essentialist interpretation of emptiness to Chinese Buddhism Yin Shun 1906 2005 is one modern figure aligned with Sanlun Sengzhao is often seen as the founder of Sanlun He was influenced not just by Indian madhyamaka and Mahayana sutras like the Vimalakirti but also by Taoist works and he widely quotes the Lao tzu and the Chuang tzu and uses terminology of the Neo Daoist Mystery Learning xuanxue 玄学 tradition while maintaining a uniquely Buddhist philosophical view 194 195 In his essay The Emptiness of the Non Absolute buzhenkong 不眞空 Sengzhao points out that the nature of phenomena cannot be taken as being either existent or inexistent Hence there are indeed reasons why myriad dharmas are inexistent and cannot be taken as existent there are reasons why myriad dharmas are not inexistent and cannot be taken as inexistent Why If we would say that they exist their existent is not real if we would say that they don t exist their phenomenal forms have taken shape Having forms and shapes they are not inexistent Being not real they are not truly existent Hence the meaning of bu zhen kong not really empty 不眞空 is made manifest 196 Sengzhao saw the central problem in understanding emptiness as the discriminatory activity of prapanca According to Sengzhao delusion arises through a dependent relationship between phenomenal things naming thought and reification and correct understanding lies outside of words and concepts Thus while emptiness is the lack of intrinsic self in all things this emptiness is not itself an absolute and cannot be grasped by the conceptual mind it can be only be realized through non conceptual wisdom prajna 197 Jizang 549 623 was another central figure in Chinese madhyamaka who wrote numerous commentaries on Nagarjuna and Aryadeva and is considered to be the leading representative of the school 198 Jizang called his method deconstructing what is misleading and revealing what is corrective He insisted that one must never settle on any particular viewpoint or perspective but constantly reexamine one s formulations to avoid reifications of thought and behavior 198 In his commentary on the MMK Jizang s method and understanding of emptiness can be seen The abhidharma thinkers regard the four holy truths as true The Satyasiddhi regards merely the truth of cessation of suffering i e the principle of emptiness and equality as true The southern Mahayana tradition regards the principle that refutes truths as true and the northern Mahayana tradition regards thatness suchness and prajna as true Examining these all together if there is a single true principle it is an eternal view which is false If there is no principle at all it is an evil view which is also false Being both existent and non existent consists of the eternal and nihilistic views altogether Being neither existent nor nonexistent is a foolish view One replete with these four phrases has all wrong views One without these four phrases has a severe nihilistic view Now that one does not know how to name what a mind has nothing to rely upon and is free from conceptual construction he foists thatness suchness upon it one attains sainthood of the three vehicles Being deluded in regard to thatness suchness one falls into the six realms of disturbed life and death 199 In one of his early treatises called The Meaning of the two Truths Erdiyi Jizang expounds the steps to realize the nature of the ultimate truth of emptiness as follows In the first step one recognises reality of the phenomena on the conventional level but assumes their non reality on the ultimate level In the second step one becomes aware of Being or Non Being on the conventional level and negates both at the ultimate level In the third step one either asserts or negates Being and Non Being on the conventional level neither confi rming nor rejecting them on the ultimate level Hence there is ultimately no assertion or negation anymore therefore on the conventional level one becomes free to accept or reject anything 200 In the modern era there has been a revival of madhyamaka in Chinese Buddhism A major figure in this revival is the scholar monk Yin Shun 1906 2005 201 Yin Shun emphasized the study of Indian Buddhist sources as primary and his books on madhyamaka had a profound influence on modern Chinese madhyamika scholarship 202 He argued that the works of Nagarjuna were the inheritance of the conceptualisation of dependent arising as proposed in the Agamas and he thus based his madhyamaka interpretations on the Agamas rather than on Chinese scriptures and commentaries 203 He saw the writings of Nagarjuna as the correct Buddhadharma while considering the writings of the Sanlun school as being corrupted due to their synthesizing of the Tathagata garbha doctrine into madhyamaka 204 Many modern Chinese madhyamaka scholars such as Li Zhifu Yang Huinan and Lan Jifu have been students of Yin Shun 205 Chan Edit The Chan Zen tradition emulated madhyamaka thought via the San lun Buddhists influencing its supposedly illogical way of communicating absolute truth 10 The madhyamika of Sengzhao for example influenced the views of the Chan patriarch Shen Hui 670 762 a critical figure in the development of Chan as can be seen by his Illuminating the Essential Doctrine Hsie Tsung Chi This text emphasizes that true emptiness or Suchness cannot be known through thought since it is free from thought wu nien 206 Thus we come to realize that both selves and things are in their essence empty and existence and non existence both disappear Mind is fundamentally non action the way is truly no thought wu nien There is no thought no reflection no seeking no attainment no this no that no coming no going Shen Hui also states that true emptiness is not nothing but it is a Subtle Existence miao yu which is just Great Prajna 206 Western Buddhism EditThich Nhat Hanh Edit Thich Nhat Hanh explains the madhyamaka concept of emptiness through the Chinese Buddhist concept of interdependence In this analogy there is no first or ultimate cause for anything that occurs Instead all things are dependent on innumerable causes and conditions that are themselves dependent on innumerable causes and conditions The interdependence of all phenomena including the self is a helpful way to undermine mistaken views about inherence or that one s self is inherently existent It is also a helpful way to discuss Mahayana teachings on motivation compassion and ethics The comparison to interdependence has produced recent discussion comparing Mahayana ethics to environmental ethics 207 Modern madhyamaka Edit Madhyamaka forms an alternative to the perennialist and essentialist understanding of nondualism and modern spiritual metaphysics influenced by idealistic monism views like Neo Advaita web 1 web 2 web 3 In some modern works classical madhyamaka teachings are sometimes complemented with postmodern philosophy web 4 critical sociology web 5 and social constructionism web 6 These approaches stress that there is no transcendental reality beyond this phenomenal world web 7 and in some cases even explicitly distinguish themselves from neo Advaita approaches web 8 Influences and critiques EditYogacara Edit The yogacara school was the other major Mahayana philosophical school darsana in India and its complex relationship with madhyamaka changed over time The Saṃdhinirmocana sutra perhaps the earliest Yogacara text proclaims itself as being above the doctrine of emptiness taught in other sutras According to Paul Williams the Saṃdhinirmocana claims that other sutras that teach emptiness as well as madhyamika teachings on emptiness are merely skillful means and thus are not definitive unlike the final teachings in the Saṃdhinirmocana 208 As Mark Siderits points out yogacara authors like Asanga were careful to point out that the doctrine of emptiness required interpretation in lieu of their three natures theory which posits an inexpressible ultimate that is the object of a Buddha s cognition 209 Asanga also argued that one cannot say that all things are empty unless there are things to be seen as either empty or non empty in the first place 210 Asanga attacks the view which states the truth is that all is just conceptual fictions by stating As for their view due to the absence of the thing itself which serves as basis of the concept conceptual fictions must all likewise absolutely not exist How then will it be true that all is just conceptual fictions Through this conception on their part reality conceptual fiction and the two together are all denied Because they deny both conceptual fiction and reality they should be considered the nihilist in chief 211 Asanga also critiqued madhyamaka because he held that it could lead to a laxity in the following of ethical precepts as well as for being imaginatively constructed views that are arrived at only through reasoning 212 He further states How again is emptiness wrongly conceptualized Some ascetics and Brahmins do not acknowledge that viz intrinsic nature of which something is empty Nor do they acknowledge that which is empty viz things and dharmas It is in this way that emptiness is said to be wrongly conceived For what reason Because that of which it is empty is non existent but that which is empty is existent it is thus that emptiness is possible What will be empty of what where when everything is unreal This thing s being devoid of that is not then possible Thus emptiness is wrongly conceptualized in this case Asanga also wrote that if nothing is real there cannot be any ideas prajnapti Someone who holds this view is a nihilist with whom one should not speak or share living quarters This person falls into a bad rebirth and takes others with him 213 Vasubandhu also states that emptiness does not mean that things have no intrinsic nature but that this nature is inexpressible and only to be apprehended by a kind of cognition that transcends the subject object duality 209 Thus early yogacarins were engaged in a project to reinterpret the radical madhyamaka view of emptiness Later yogacarins like Sthiramati and Dharmapala debated with their madhyamika contemporaries 214 However yogacara authors also commented on madhyamaka texts As noted by Garfield Asaṅga Sthiramati and Guṇamati composed commentaries on the foundational text of madhyamaka Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika 215 According to Xuanzang Bhavaviveka who critiques yogacara views in his Madhyamakahṛdayakarikaḥ was disturbed by the views of yogacarins and their critiques of madhyamaka as nihilism and himself traveled to Nalanda to debate Dharmapala face to face but Dharmapala refused 216 Bhavaviveka quotes the attacks from the yogacarins in his texts as claiming that while the yogacara approach to prajnaparamita is the means to attain omniscience the madhyamaka approach which concentrates on the negation of arising and cessation is not 217 Bhavaviveka responds to various yogacara attacks and views in his Tarkajvala Blaze of reason including the view that there are no external objects idealism the view that there is no use for logical argumentation tarka and the view that the dependent nature paratantra svabhava exists in an absolute sense 218 Advaita Vedanta Edit Several modern scholars have argued that the early Advaita Vedanta thinker Gaudapada c 6th century CE was influenced by madhyamaka thought They note that he borrowed the concept of ajata un born from madhyamaka philosophy 219 220 which also uses the term anutpada non arising un originated non production 221 web 9 The Buddhist tradition usually uses the term anutpada for the absence of an origin 219 221 or shunyata 222 note 17 Ajativada is the fundamental philosophical doctrine of Gaudapada 226 According to Gaudapada the Absolute Brahman is not subject to birth change and death Echoing Nagarjuna s use of the catuskoti Gaudapada writes that nothing whatsoever is originated either from itself or from something else nothing whatsoever existent non existent or both existent and non existent is originated 227 However it has been noted that Gaudapada s ultimate philosophical perspective is quite different from Nagarjuna s since Gaudapada posits a metaphysical Absolute which is aja the unborn and eternal based on the Mandukya Upanishad and thus he remains primarily a Vedantin 228 226 The empirical world of appearances is considered unreal and not absolutely existent 226 In this sense Gaudapada also shares a doctrine of two truths or two levels of reality with madhyamaka According to Gaudapada this absolute Brahman cannot undergo alteration so the phenomenal world cannot arise from Brahman If the world cannot arise yet is an empirical fact then the world has to be an unreal note 18 appearance of Brahman From the level of ultimate truth paramarthata the phenomenal world is Maya illusion 228 Richard King notes that the fourth prakarana of the Gaudapadiyakarika promotes several Mahayana Buddhist ideas such as a middle way free from extremes not being attached to dharmas and it even references beings called Buddhas King notes that this could be an attempt to either reach a rapprochement with Buddhists or to woo Buddhists over to Vedanta 229 However King adds that from a Madhyamaka perspective the Gaudapadiyakarika s acceptance of an unchanging Absolute supporting the world of appearances is a mistaken form of eternalism despite Gaudapadian protestations to the contrary 229 Shankara early 8th century a later Advaitin directly dismissed madhyamaka as irrational and nihilistic stating that it was a kind of nihilism that held that absolutely nothing exists and that this view 227 230 231 is contradicted by all means of right knowledge and requires no special refutation For this apparent world whose existence is guaranteed by all means of knowledge cannot be denied unless some one should find out some new truth based on which he could impugn its existence for a general principle is proved by the absence of contrary instances This critique was upheld by most post Shankara Advaitins However this did not prevent later Vedanta thinkers like Bhaskara of accusing Shankara of being a crypto buddhist for his view that everyday reality is Maya illusion and that Brahman has no qualities and is undifferentiated Another Vedantin philosopher Ramanuja 1017 1137 directly compared Shankara s mayavada views to madhyamaka arguing that if Maya Avidya is unreal that would involve the acceptance of the Madhyamika doctrine viz of a general void 231 This critique by comparison is also echoed by the later philosophers like Madhva as well as Vijnanabhiksu 15th or 16th century who goes as far as to call Shankara a nastika unorthodox Later Advaitins also acknowledged the similarity of their doctrine with madhyamaka Vimuktatma states that if by asat nonbeing the Madhyamaka means Maya and not mere negation then he is close to Vedanta Sadananda also states that if by Sunya what is meant is the reality beyond the intellect then the madhyamaka accepts Vedanta Sri Harsha notes that the two schools are similar but they differ in that Advaita holds consciousness to be pure real and eternal while madhyamaka denies this 231 Jain philosophy Edit Modern scholars such as Jeffery Long have also noted that the influential Jain philosopher Kundakunda 2nd CE century CE or later also adopted a theory of two truths possibly under the influence of Nagarjuna 232 According to W J Johnson he also adopts other Buddhist terms like prajna under the influence of Nagarjuna though he applies the term to knowledge of the Self jiva which is also the ultimate perspective niscayanaya which is distinguished from the worldly perspective vyavaharanaya 233 The Jain philosopher Haribhadra also mentions madhyamaka In both the Yogabindu and the Yogadrstisamuccaya Haribhadra singles out Nagarjuna s claim that samsara and nirvana are not different for criticism labeling the view a fantasy 234 Taoism Edit It is well known that medieval Chinese Taoism was influenced by Mahayana Buddhism One particular school the Chongxuan 重玄 Twofold Mystery founded by Cheng Xuanying fl 632 650 was particularly involved in borrowing and adapting madhyamaka concepts like emptiness the two truths and the catuskoti into their Taoist philosophical system 195 Modern scholarship EditAs noted by Ruegg Western scholarship has given a broad variety of interpretations of madhyamaka including nihilism monism irrationalism misology agnosticism scepticism criticism dialectic mysticism acosmism absolutism relativism nominalism and linguistic analysis with therapeutic value 235 Jay L Garfield likewise notes Modern interpreters differ among themselves about the correct way to read it as least as much as canonical interpreters Nagarjuna has been read as an idealist Murti 1960 a nihilist Wood 1994 a skeptic Garfield 1995 a pragmatist Kalupahana 1986 and as a mystic Streng 1967 He has been regarded as a critic of logic Inada 1970 as a defender of classical logic Hayes 1994 and as a pioneer of paraconsistent logic Garfield and Priest 2003 236 These interpretations reflect almost as much about the viewpoints of the scholars involved as do they reflect the content of Nagarjuna s concepts 237 According to Andrew Tuck the Western study of Nagarjuna s madhyamaka can be divided into three phases 238 The Kantian phase exemplified by Theodore Stcherbatsky s The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana 1927 who argued that Nagarjuna divides the world into appearance samsara and an absolute noumenal reality nirvana This is also seen in T R V Murti s 1955 The Central Philosophy of Buddhism The analytic phase exemplified by Richard Robinson s 1957 article Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna s System sought to explain madhyamaka using analytic philosophy s logical apparatus The post Wittgensteinian phase exemplified by Frederick Streng s Emptiness and Chris Gudmunsen s Wittgenstein and Buddhism set out to stress similarities between Nagarjuna and in particular the later Wittgenstein and his criticism of analytic philosophy The Sri Lankan philosopher David Kalupahana meanwhile saw madhyamaka as a response to certain essentialist philosophical tendencies which had arisen after the time of the Buddha and sees it as a restoration of the early Buddhist middle way pragmatist position 239 117 Among the critical voices Richard P Hayes influenced by Richard Robinson s view that Nagarjuna s logic fails modern tests for validity interprets the works of Nagarjuna as primitive and guilty errors in reasoning such as that of equivocation Hayes states that Nagarjuna was relying on the different meanings of the word svabhava to make statements which were not logical and that his work relies on various fallacies and tricks 240 241 William Magee strongly disagrees with Hayes referring to Tsonghkhapa s interpretation of Nagarjuna to argue that Hayes misidentifies Nagarjuna s understanding of the different meanings of the term svabhava 242 Many recent western scholars such as Garfield 243 Napper 244 Hopkins 245 have tended to adopt a Gelug Prasaṅgika influenced interpretation of madhyamaka However American philosopher Mark Siderits is one exception who has attempted to defend the Svatantrika position as a coherent and rational interpretation of madhyamaka 246 C W Huntington meanwhile has been particularly critical of the modern Western attempt to read Nagarjuna through the lens of modern symbolic logic and to see him as compatible with analytical philosophy s logical system 241 He argues that in reading Nagarjuna a thinker who he sees as profoundly distrustful of logic in an overly logical manner we prejudice our understanding of Nagarjuna s insistence that he has no proposition pratijna 241 He puts forth a more literary interpretation that focuses on the effect Nagarjuna was attempting to conjure on his readers i e an experience of having no views instead of asking how it works or doesn t in a logical manner 241 In response to this Jay Garfield defends the logical reading of Nagarjuna through the use of Anglo American analytical philosophy as well as arguing that Nagarjuna and Candrakirti deploy arguments take themselves to do so and even if they did not we would be wise to do so in commenting on their texts 69 Another recent interpreter Jan Westerhoff argues that madhyamaka is a kind of anti foundationalism which does not just deny the objective intrinsic and mind independent existence of some class of objects but rejects such existence for any kinds of objects that we could regard as the most fundamental building blocks of the world 247 See also EditBuddha nature Candrakirti Materialism Mentalism Nagarjuna Mulamadhyamakakarika Schools of Buddhism Prasangika Svatantrika Yogachara East Asian Madhyamaka Sunyata Tathagata Two Truths DoctrineNotes Edit Own beings 25 unique nature or substance 26 an identifying characteristic an identity an essence 27 A differentiating characteristic 27 the fact of being dependent 27 Being 21 self nature or substance 28 Not being present absence 29 svabhava Nagarjuna equates svabhava essence with bhava existence in Chapter 15 of the Mulamadhyamakakarika Susan Kahn further explains The emptiness of emptiness refutes ultimate truth as yet another argument for essentialism under the guise of being beyond the conventional or as the foundation of it To realize emptiness is not to find a transcendent place or truth to land in but to see the conventional as merely conventional Here lies the key to liberation For to see the deception is to be free of deception like a magician who knows the magic trick When one is no longer fooled by false appearances phenomena are neither reified nor denied They are understood interdependently as ultimately empty and thus as only conventionally real This is the Middle Way 40 Chapter 21 of the Mulamadhyamakakarika goes into the reasoning behind this 62 See also Atthakavagga and Parayanavagga for early Madhyamaka like texts from the Buddhist canon on freedom from views In the Pali canon these chapters are the fourth and fifth chapters of the Khuddaka Nikaya s Sutta Nipata respectively Wynne devotes a chapter to the Parayanavagga Mulamadhyamakakarika 24 18 Alex Trisoglio In the 8th century Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the monastery at Samye He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka but the disciple of one of his disciples He combined the madhyamika svatantrika and cittamatra schools and created a new school of madhyamika called svatantrika yogachara madhyamika His disciple Kamalashila who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika uma i sgom rim developed his ideas further and together they were very influential in Tibet Khyentse Rinpoche Dzongsar Jamyang 2003 Introduction In Alex Trisoglio ed Introduction to the Middle Way Chandrakirti s Madhyamakavatara with Commentary PDF 1st ed Dordogne France Khyentse Foundation p 8 Retrieved 7 January 2013 In his Tattvaratnavali the Indian scholar Advayavajra classified madhyamaka into those who uphold non duality from the simile of illusion mayopamadvayavadin and those who uphold non placement into any dharma sarvadharmapratiṣṭhanavadin furthermore in the Madhyamakaṣaṭka he envisaged a specifically Vajrayana type of Madhyamaka citation needed According to Hookham non dual experience is Ultimate Reality 187 According to Hookham The Chinese Tathagarba schools describe Buddhajnana as the totality of all that is which pervades every part of all that is in its totality 187 According to Hookham for Shentong Buddhajnana is the non dual nature of Mind completely unobscured and endowed with its countless Buddha Qualities Buddhagunas 187 The term is also used in the Lankavatara Sutra 223 According to D T Suzuki anutpada is not the opposite of utpada but transcends opposites It is the seeing into the true nature of existence 224 the seeing that all objects are without self substance 225 C q transitory References EditPublished references Edit Williams 2000 p 140 Thakchoe Sonam Summer 2022 The Theory of Two Truths in Tibet In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University ISSN 1095 5054 OCLC 643092515 Archived from the original on 28 May 2022 Retrieved 5 July 2022 a b Wynne Alexander 2015 Early Buddhist Teaching as Proto sunyavada Journal of the Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies 6 pp 213 241 Brunnholzl 2004 p 29 30 a b c Donnelly Paul B 25 January 2017 Madhyamaka Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Religion Oxford Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acrefore 9780199340378 013 191 ISBN 9780199340378 Acri Andrea 20 December 2018 Maritime Buddhism Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Religion Oxford Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acrefore 9780199340378 013 638 ISBN 9780199340378 Archived from the original on 19 February 2019 Retrieved 30 May 2021 Hugon Pascale Spring 2020 Tibetan Epistemology and Philosophy of Language In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University ISSN 1095 5054 OCLC 643092515 Archived from the original on 20 June 2022 Retrieved 5 July 2022 Brunnholzl 2004 p 70 Brunnholzl 2004 p 590 a b c d e Cheng 1981 a b Garfield 1994 a b Garfield 2012 Discourse to Katyayana Katyayanaḥ SF 168 Tripathi 1962 167 170 19 Translated by Jayarava suttacentral net Sanskrit lokasamudayaṁ katyayana yathabhutaṁ samyakprajnaya pasyato ya loke nastita sa na bhavati lokanirodhaṁ yathabhutaṁ samyakprajnaya pasyato ya loke stita sa na bhavati ity etav ubhav antav anupagamya madhyamaya pratipada tathagato dharmaṁ desayati yad utasmin satidaṁ bhavaty asyotpadad idam utpadyate yad utavidyapratyayaḥ saṁskara iti purvavad yavat samudayo nirodhas ca bhavati a b c Westerhoff 2009 p 12 25 Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy p 180 a b Westerhoff Jan Christoph 10 February 2010 Nagarjuna In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Retrieved 2021 04 02 Hayes 2003 p 4 Westerhoff 2009 p 30 Westerhoff 2009 p 200 a b c d e Warder 2000 p 361 Westerhoff 2009 p 45 Westerhoff 2009 p 13 Westerhoff 2009 p 48 Warder 2000 p 360 Kalupahana 1994 p 162 a b c Hayes 1994 p 317 Kalupahana 1994 p 165 Hayes 1994 p 316 Harvey 1995 p 97 Kalupahana 1994 p 165 162 Tsondru 2011 p 40 41 322 333 Bronkhorst 2009 p 146 sfn error no target CITEREFBronkhorst2009 help a b Rje Tsong Khapa Garfield Jay Geshe Ngawang Samten translators Ocean of Reasoning A Great Commentary on Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika Oxford University Press 2006 p xx a b Brunnholzl 2004 p 73 Brunnholzl 2004 p 80 83 a b c Cowherds 2010 p 11 13 Brunnholzl 2004 p 81 Bronkhorst 2009 p 149 sfn error no target CITEREFBronkhorst2009 help Kahn Susan 11 September 2014 The Two Truths of Buddhism and The Emptiness of Emptiness Emptiness Teachings Retrieved 2021 04 02 a b Brunnholzl 2004 p 74 Brunnholzl 2004 p 79 Tsongkhapa Garfield The Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path to Enlightenment Volume 3 2002 p 210 Hayes 2003 p 8 9 Williams 2002 p 147 Brunnholzl 2004 p 111 Brunnholzl 2004 p 75 Brunnholzl 2004 p 76 Brunnholzl 2004 p 76 77 Brunnholzl 2004 p 84 Brunnholzl 2004 p 83 84 Brunnholzl 2004 p 89 Junjirō Takakusu 1998 The Essentials of Buddhist Philosophy Motilal Banarsidass pp 4 105 107 ISBN 978 81 208 1592 6 Hajime Nakamura 1991 Ways of Thinking of Eastern Peoples India China Tibet Japan Motilal Banarsidass pp 590 591 footnote 20 ISBN 978 81 208 0764 8 Quote Already in India sunyata was liable to be misunderstood as nothingness or nihil The Sarvastivadins of Hinayana Buddhism viewed the madhyamika school as one that argues that everything is nothing It is only natural that most of the Western scholars call the prajnaparamita sutra or the doctrine of the madhyamika school nihilism since criticisms were already expressed in India Against such criticisms however Nagarjuna founder of the madhyamika school says you are ignorant of the function of sunyata the meaning of the sunyata and sunyata itself G C Nayak 2001 Madhyamika Sunyata a Reappraisal A Reappraisal of Madhyamika Philosophical Enterprise with Special Reference to Nagarjuna and Chandrakirti Indian Council of Philosophical Research pp 9 12 ISBN 978 81 85636 47 4 Brunnholzl 2004 p 212 a b Walser 2005 p 239 Jorge Noguera Ferrer Revisioning Transpersonal Theory A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality SUNY Press 2002 page 102 103 David J Kalupahana Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna The Philosophy of the Middle Way SUNY Press 1986 pages 48 50 Williams 2002 p 141 Williams 2000 p 142 a b c Tsondru 2011 p 56 58 405 417 Williams 2002 p 151 152 unclear a b c d Garfield 1995 p 88 footnote Brunnholzl 2004 p 174 175 Brunnholzl 2004 p 199 Brunnholzl 2004 p 200 a b c d Garfield Jay L Turning a Madhyamaka Trick Reply to Huntington J Indian Philos 2008 36 507 527 DOI 10 1007 s10781 008 9045 9 Brunnholzl 2004 p 202 Brunnholzl 2004 p 203 Brunnholzl 2004 p 203 204 Brunnholzl 2004 p 202 203 Brunnholzl 2004 p 217 a b Brunnholzl 2004 p 206 a b Garfield 1995 p 102 a b Westerhoff 2009 p 47 Bronkhorst 2009 p 148 sfn error no target CITEREFBronkhorst2009 help Brunnholzl 2004 p 295 310 Brunnholzl 2004 p 310 Brunnholzl 2004 p 108 Williams 2002 p 146 Brunnholzl 2004 p 218 Brunnholzl 2004 p 34 Jorge Noguera Ferrer Revisioning Transpersonal Theory A Participatory Vision of Human Spirituality SUNY Press 2002 pages 102 The quote is from the Mulamadhyamakakarika Randall Collins The Sociology of Philosophies A Global Theory of Intellectual Change Harvard University Press 2000 pages 221 222 Brunnholzl 2004 p 172 Brunnholzl 2004 p 219 Brunnholzl 2004 p 221 Brunnholzl 2004 p 160 Brunnholzl 2004 p 209 Warder 2000 p 358 a b c d Walser 2005 p 185 Walser 2005 p 186 187 Gomez 1976 Vetter 1988 Fuller 2005 Wynne 2007 p 75 Gelongma Karma Migme Chodron trans from French Lamotte Etienne trans The Treatise on the Great Virtue of Wisdom Volume V Traite de la Grande Vertu de Sagesse de Nagarjuna Mahaprajnaparamitasastra Tome V pp 52 54 a b Walser 2005 p 225 a b c Ronkin Noa 16 August 2010 Abhidharma In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Retrieved 2021 04 02 Walser 2005 p 227 a b Walser 2005 p 234 a b c Ruegg David Seyfort The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India Otto Harrassowitz Verlag 1981 p 7 a b Walser 2005 p 170 Adrian Kuzminski Pyrrhonism How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism 2008 Thomas McEvilley The Shape of Ancient Thought 2002 pp499 505 https ora ox ac uk objects uuid 347ed882 f7ac 4098 908f 5bb391462a6c download file file format pdf amp safe filename THESIS01 amp type of work Thesis bare URL PDF Archived at Ghostarchive and the Wayback Machine Sextus Empiricus and Madhyamaka at Oxford s Oriental Institute YouTube Beckwith Christopher I 2015 Greek Buddha Pyrrho s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia PDF Princeton University Press ISBN 9781400866328 Westerhoff 2009 p 4 a b Westerhoff 2009 p 5 6 Wasler Joseph Nagarjuna in Context New York Columibia University Press 2005 pgs 225 263 a b Kalupahana 1992 p 120 Tsondru 2011 p 66 71 447 477 Williams 2002 p 142 a b Kalupahana 1994 Ruegg 1981 p 49 54 Warder 2000 p 368 a b Rizzi 1988 p 2 Ruegg 1981 p 47 48 Bocking B 1995 Nagarjuna in China A Translation of the Middle Treatise Lewiston amp Lampeter University of Bristol Centre for Buddhist Studies Series The Edwin Mellen Press a b c d e f Hayes Richard 6 November 2010 Madhyamaka In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2017 Edition Retrieved 2021 04 02 Newland 2009 p 78 Newland 2009 p 79 a b Garfield Jay Edelglass William The Oxford Handbook of World philosophy Newland 2009 p 80 a b Ruegg 1981 p 67 Bhikshu Dharmamitra trans The Bodhisambhara Treatise Commentary An Early Indian Commentary on Nagarjuna s Bodhisambhara Shastra By the Early Indian monk Bhikshu Vasitva ca 300 500 ce Kalavinka press Rizzi 1988 p 5 Ruegg 1981 p 85 Ruegg 1981 p 119 Watanabe Chikafumi 1998 A Translation of the Madhyamakahrdayakarika with the Tarkajvala III 137 146 Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 21 1 Ruegg 1981 p 88 Shantarakshita 2005 p 117 122 sfn error no target CITEREFShantarakshita2005 help Blumenthal James The Ornament of the Middle Way A Study of the Madhyamaka Thought of Santaraksita Snow Lion 2004 p 245 Ruegg 1981 p 104 Ruegg 1981 p 109 Brunnholzl 2004 p 51 Apple James B 2019 Jewels of the Middle Way The Madhyamaka Legacy of Atisa and His Early Tibetan Followers Introduction pp 1 62 Simon and Schuster a b c Dunne John D 2011 Madhyamaka in India and Tibet In Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy Edited by J Garfield and W Edelglass Oxford Oxford University Press 206 221 Reason and Experience in Tibetan Buddhism Mabja Jangchub Tsondru and the Traditions of the Middle Way Reviewed by Adam C Krug Journal of Buddhist Ethics ISSN 1076 9005 http blogs dickinson edu buddhistethics Volume 22 2015 Reason and Experience in Tibetan Buddhism Mabja Jangchub Tsondru and the Traditions of the Middle Way Reviewed by Adam C Krug Journal of Buddhist Ethics ISSN 1076 9005 http blogs dickinson edu buddhistethics Volume 22 2015 Brunnholzl 2004 p 333 a b c d Shantarakshita 2005 p 131 141 sfn error no target CITEREFShantarakshita2005 help Cornu 2001 p 138 Gombrich 1996 p 27 28 sfn error no target CITEREFGombrich1996 help Cornu 2001 p 145 150 Stearns Cyrus 2010 The Buddha from Dolpo A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen Rev and enl ed Ithaca NY Snow Lion Publications ISBN 9781559393430 Retrieved 2 May 2015 Hopkins 2006 Hopkins 2006 pp 8 15 Brunnholzl 2009 p 108 Stearns Cyrus 1999 The Buddha from Dolpo A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen State University of New York Press p 82 Hopkins 2006 p 14 sfn error no target CITEREFHopkins2006 help Hopkins 2006 p 8 sfn error no target CITEREFHopkins2006 help a b c Cabezon amp Dargyay 2013 p 29 Brunnholzl 2004 p 502 Snelling 1987 p 207 sfn error no target CITEREFSnelling1987 help rJe Tsong Kha Pa 2006 sfn error no target CITEREFrJe Tsong Kha Pa2006 help a b c Learman Oliver editor Encyclopedia of Asian Philosophy Routledge 2001 p 374 a b c Sparham Gareth 18 July 2011 Tsongkhapa In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2017 Edition Retrieved 2021 04 02 Cowherds 2010 p 76 a b Cowherds 2010 p 82 Cowherds 2010 p 77 Cabezon amp Dargyay 2013 p 30 Kassor Constance 2 May 2011 Gorampa go rams pa In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2017 Edition Retrieved 2021 04 02 Cabezon amp Dargyay 2013 p 46 48 Cabezon amp Dargyay 2013 p 49 a b c Cabezon amp Dargyay 2013 p 50 a b Cowherds 2010 p 84 Cowherds 2010 p 86 Cowherds 2010 p 83 Brunnholzl 2009 p 107 Cowherds 2010 p 74 75 87 Cowherds 2010 p 75 76 Cowherds 2010 p 87 Brunnholzl 2009 p 99 Brunnholzl 2009 p 114 Brunnholzl 2004 p 446 Brunnholzl 2004 p 447 Brunnholzl 2004 p 448 Brunnholzl 2004 p 501 Ringu Tulku The Ri me Philosophy of Jamgon Kongtrul the Great A Study of the Buddhist Lineages of Tibet 2007 p 219 Hookham 1991 p 19 26 Khenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso 1994 sfn error no target CITEREFKhenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso1994 help Hookham 1991 p 21 a b c Hookham 1991 p 37 a b Hookham 1991 p 22 a b Hookham 1991 p 23 a b Thakchoe Sonam 17 February 2011 The Theory of Two Truths in Tibet In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2017 Edition Retrieved 2021 04 02 Duckworth Jamgon Mipam His life and teachings Pg 81 Duckworth Jamgon Mipam His life and teachings 82 Arnold Dan Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of philosophy Liebenthal Walter Chao Lun The Treatises of Seng Chao 1968 p 8 a b Ozkan 2013 Ozkan 2013 p 24 Dippmann Jeffrey Sengzhao Seng Chao c 378 413 C E Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Fox Alan Self reflection in the Sanlun Tradition Madhyamika as the Deconstructive Conscience of Buddhism Journal of Chinese Philosophy V 19 1992 pp 1 24 Ozkan 2013 p 25 Scherer Burkhard Review of The Two Truths in Chinese Buddhism Chang Qing Shih Delhi Motilal Banarsidass 2004 Buddhist Tradition Series 55 Buddhist studies review Travagnin 2009 Travagnin 2009 p 155 Travagnin 2009 p 28 65 85 Travagnin 2009 p 174 Travagnin 2009 p 159 a b Zeuschner Robert B The Hsie Tsung Chi An Early Ch an Zen Buddhist Text Journal of Chinese Philosophy V 3 1976 pp 253 268 Thich Nhat Hanh 1988 Williams 2009 p 86 a b Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 115 Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 116 Dr Vemuri Ramesam A Critique Of John Wheeler s You Were Never Born Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 117 Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 129 Williams 2009 p 88 Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 6 Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 127 Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 131 Garfield amp Westerhoff 2015 p 135 a b Renard 2010 p 157 Comans 2000 p 35 36 a b Bhattacharya 1943 p 49 Renard 2010 p 160 Suzuki 1999 Suzuki 1999 p 123 124 Suzuki 1999 p 168 a b c Sarma 1996 p 127 a b Ben Ami Scharfstein A Comparative History of World Philosophy From the Upanishads to Kant p 380 a b Comans 2000 p 36 a b King Richard Early Advaita and madhyamaka Buddhism The case of the Gaudapadiyakarika Gregory Joseph Darling An Evaluation of the Vedantic Critique of Buddhism p 358 a b c Reynolds Eric T On the relationship of Advaita Vedanta and Madhyamika Buddhism 1969 Long Jeffery Jainism An Introduction page 66 216 W J Johnson Harmless Souls Karmic Bondage and Religious Change in Early Jainism with Special Reference to Umasvati and Kundakunda Motilal Banarsidass Publ 1995 p 285 Chapple Christopher Key John Thomas Casey Translator Reconciling Yogas Haribhadra s Collection of Views on Yoga With a New Translation of Haribhadra s Yogadrstisamuccaya p 60 Ruegg 1981 p 2 Garfield and Samten 2006 p xx sfn error no target CITEREFGarfield and Samten2006 help Daye 1971 p 77 Westerhoff 2009 p 9 10 Kalupahana 1992 Hayes 2003 p 3 5 a b c d Huntington C W Jr 2007 The nature of the Madhyamika trick Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 2 103 131 doi 10 1007 s10781 007 9018 4 S2CID 6043097 Magee 1999 p 126 Hayes is misidentifying Nagarjuna s intended meaning of svabhava In contradistinction to Hayes belief that Nagarjuna speaks equivocably of an identity nature and a causally independent non existent nature Dzong ka ba feels that in chapter XV 1 2 Nagarjuna uses the term svabhava to refer to an existent emptiness nature Garfield 1995 Napper 1989 Hopkins 1996 sfn error no target CITEREFHopkins1996 help Siderits Mark Studies in Buddhist philosophy p 38 Westerhoff 2009 p 208 Web references Edit Emptiness Buddhist and Beyond The Non Buddhist Archived from the original on 2018 12 01 Retrieved 2015 05 11 Emptiness teachings Review of Richard Rorty s Philosophy and Social Hope Patrick jennings 2014 Tsongkhapa In Praise of Relativity The Essence of Eloquence Archived 2015 05 18 at the Wayback Machine emptiness co Review of Kenneth J Gergen s An Invitation to Social Construction Susan Kahn The Two Truths of Buddhism and The Emptiness of Emptiness emptiness co Coming from the Advaitic Awareness Teachings Special Pointers Sanskrit Dictionary for Spoken Sanskrit Anutpada Archived from the original on 2013 05 30 Retrieved 2019 01 03 Sources EditArena Leonardo Vittorio 2012 Nonsense as the Meaning ebook Arnold Dan 2010 Nagarjuna s Middle Way A Non Eliminative Understanding of Selflessness In Revue Internationale de Philosophie vol 64 no 253 367 395 Bhattacharya Vidhushekhara 1943 Gauḍapadakarika Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Brunnholzl Karl 2004 Center of the Sunlit Sky Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition Snow Lion Publications Brunnholzl Karl 2009 Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature Shambhala Publications ISBN 9781559399142 Cabezon Jose Ignacio Dargyay Lobsang 2013 Freedom from Extremes Gorampa s Distinguishing the Views and the Polemics of Emptiness Simon and Schuster ISBN 9780861718573 Cheng Hsueh Li 1981 The Roots of Zen Buddhism Journal of Chinese Philosophy 8 4 451 478 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6253 1981 tb00267 x Comans Michael 2000 The Method of Early Advaita Vedanta A Study of Gauḍapada Saṅkara Suresvara and Padmapada Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Cornu Philippe 2001 Nawoord Schijn en werkelijkheid De twee waarheden in de vier boeddhistische leerstelsels KunchabPublicaties Cowherds 2010 Moonshadows Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199826506 Daye Douglas D 1971 Major Schools of the Mahayana Madhyamaka In Charles S Prebisch Buddhism A Modern Perspective Pages 76 96 ISBN 978 0 271 01195 0 Fuller Paul 2005 The Notion of Diṭṭhi in Theravada Buddhism The Point of View PDF Routledge archived from the original PDF on 2014 12 02 Garfield Jay L 1994 Dependent Arising and the Emptiness of Emptiness Why Did Nagarjuna Start with Causation Philosophy East amp West 44 2 219 250 doi 10 2307 1399593 JSTOR 1399593 S2CID 51932733 Garfield Jay L 1995 The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way Oxford Oxford University Press Garfield Jay L 2012 Madhyamaka is Not Nihilism PDF Smith College University of Melbourne Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals Oxford University Press ISBN 9780190231293 Gomez Luis O 1976 Proto Madhyamika in the Pali canon Philosophy East and West 26 2 137 165 doi 10 2307 1398186 JSTOR 1398186 archived from the original on 2016 03 03 retrieved 2015 12 06 Harvey Peter 1995 An introduction to Buddhism Teachings history and practices Cambridge University Press Hayes Richard P 1994 Nagarjuna s appeal In Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 299 378 Hayes Richard P 2003 Nagarjuna Master of Paradox Mystic or Perpetrator of Fallacies PDF Hookham S K 1991 The Buddha within Tathagatagarbha doctrine according to the Shentong interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga Albany NY State University of New York Press ISBN 978 0791403587 Hopkins Jeffrey Napper Elizabeth 1996 Meditation on Emptiness Kalupahana David J 1992 The Principles of Buddhist Psychology Delhi ri Satguru Publications Kalupahana David J 1994 A History of Buddhist philosophy Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited Loy David 2006 Second Buddha Nagarjuna Buddhism s Greatest Philosopher In Winter 2006 edition of Tricycle The Buddhist Review Magee William 1999 The Nature of Things Emptiness and Essence in the Geluk World Ithaca New York Snow Lion Napper Elizabeth 1989 Dependent Arising and Emptiness ISBN 0 86171 057 6 Newland Guy 2009 Introduction to Emptiness As Taught in Tsong kha pa s Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path Snow Lion ISBN 9781559393324 Ng Yu kwan 1990 Chih i and Madhyamika Hamilton Ontario dissertation McMaster University p 1 archived from the original on February 3 2014 Ozkan Cuma 2013 A comparative analysis Buddhist Madhyamaka and Daoist Chongxuan twofold mystery in the early Tang 618 720 MA University of Iowa doi 10 17077 etd o9rxrm2t Renard Philip 2010 Non Dualisme De directe bevrijdingsweg Cothen Uitgeverij Juwelenschip Rizzi Cesare 1988 Candrakirti Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Private Limited Ruegg D Seyfort 1981 The literature of the Madhyamaka school of philosophy in India A History of Indian literature Harrassowitz ISBN 978 3 447 02204 0 Sarma Chandradhar 1996 The Advaita Tradition in Indian Philosophy Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Shantarakshita Ju Mipham 2005 The Adornment of the Middle Way Padmakara Translation ISBN 1 59030 241 9 Suzuki Daisetz Teitarō 1999 Studies in the Laṅkavatara Sutra Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Thich Nhat Hanh 1988 The Heart of Understanding Commentaries on the Prajnaparamita Heart Sutra Travagnin Stefania 2009 The Madhyamika Dimension of Yin Shun A restatement of the school of Nagarjuna in 20th century Chinese Buddhism PDF PhD University of London Tsondru Mabja 2011 Ornament of Reason The Great Commentary To Nagarjuna s Root Of The Middle Way Shambhala Publications ISBN 9781559397421 Tsongkhapa Lobsang Dragpa Sparham Gareth trans in collaboration with Shotaro Iida 1993 Kapstein Matthew ed Ocean of Eloquence Tsong kha pa s Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind in Tibetan and English 1 ed Albany NY State University of New York ISBN 0791414795 Retrieved 18 December 2012 Tsong Khapa 2002 The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment Volume 3 Snow Lion Publications ISBN 1 55939 166 9 rJe Tsong Kha Pa Garfield tr Jay L Samten tr Ngawang 2006 Ocean of Reasoning Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 514733 9 Vetter Tilmann 1988 The Ideas and Meditative Practices of Early Buddhism PDF BRILL ISBN 90 04 08959 4 Walser Joseph 2005 Nagarjuna in Context Mahayana Buddhism and Early Indian Culture Columbia University Press ISBN 9780231506236 Warder A K 2000 Indian Buddhism Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Publishers Westerhoff Jan 2009 Nagarjuna s Madhyamaka A Philosophical Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199705115 Williams Paul 2000 Buddhist Thought A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition Routledge ISBN 9780415207003 Williams Paul 2002 Buddhist Thought A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition Routledge ISBN 9781134623259 Williams Paul 2009 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge ISBN 9780415356534 Wynne Alexander 2007 The Origin of Buddhist Meditation RoutledgeFurther reading EditDella Santina Peter 1986 Madhyamaka Schools in India New Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Harris Ian Charles 1991 The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism New York E J Brill His Holiness the Fourteenth Dalai Lama Tenzin Gyatso 2009 The Middle Way Faith Grounded in Reason Boston Wisdom Publications Huntington C W Jr 1989 The Emptiness of Emptiness An Introduction to Early Madhyamika Honolulu University of Hawaii Press Jones Richard H 2014 Nagarjuna Buddhism s Most Important Philosopher New York Jackson Square Books Jones Richard H 2012 Indian Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy After Nagarjuna 2 vols New York Jackson Square Books Narain Harsh The Madhyamika mind Motilal Banarsidass Publishers 1997 External links Edit Wikimedia Commons has media related to Madhyamaka The Madhyamika or the Sunyavada school Surendranath Dasgupta 1940 Madhyamaka Buddhism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Nagarjuna Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Thinking in Buddhism Nagarjuna s Middle Way thezensite articles on Nagarjuna Introduction to the Middle Way A contemporary commentary based on the teachings of Dzongsar Khyentse Rinpoche Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Madhyamaka Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Nagarjuna Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Madhyamaka amp oldid 1145025632, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.