fbpx
Wikipedia

Pierre-Simon Laplace

Pierre-Simon, Marquis de Laplace (/ləˈplɑːs/; French: [pjɛʁ simɔ̃ laplas]; 23 March 1749 – 5 March 1827) was a French scholar and polymath whose work was important to the development of engineering, mathematics, statistics, physics, astronomy, and philosophy. He summarized and extended the work of his predecessors in his five-volume Mécanique céleste (Celestial Mechanics) (1799–1825). This work translated the geometric study of classical mechanics to one based on calculus, opening up a broader range of problems. In statistics, the Bayesian interpretation of probability was developed mainly by Laplace.[2]

Pierre-Simon Laplace
Pierre-Simon Laplace as chancellor of the Senate under the First French Empire
Born(1749-03-23)23 March 1749
Died5 March 1827(1827-03-05) (aged 77)
Alma materUniversity of Caen
Known for
Scientific career
FieldsAstronomy and Mathematics
InstitutionsÉcole Militaire (1769–1776)
Academic advisorsJean d'Alembert
Christophe Gadbled
Pierre Le Canu
Notable studentsSiméon Denis Poisson
Napoleon Bonaparte
Minister of the Interior
In office
12 November 1799 – 25 December 1799
Prime MinisterNapoleon Bonaparte (as First Consul)
Preceded byNicolas Marie Quinette
Succeeded byLucien Bonaparte
Signature

Laplace formulated Laplace's equation, and pioneered the Laplace transform which appears in many branches of mathematical physics, a field that he took a leading role in forming. The Laplacian differential operator, widely used in mathematics, is also named after him. He restated and developed the nebular hypothesis of the origin of the Solar System and was one of the first scientists to suggest an idea similar to that of a black hole.

Laplace is regarded as one of the greatest scientists of all time. Sometimes referred to as the French Newton or Newton of France, he has been described as possessing a phenomenal natural mathematical faculty superior to that of almost all of his contemporaries.[3] He was Napoleon's examiner when Napoleon graduated from the École Militaire in Paris in 1785.[4] Laplace became a count of the Empire in 1806 and was named a marquis in 1817, after the Bourbon Restoration.

Early years

 
Portrait of Pierre-Simon Laplace by Johann Ernst Heinsius (1775)

Some details of Laplace's life are not known, as records of it were burned in 1925 with the family château in Saint Julien de Mailloc, near Lisieux, the home of his great-great-grandson the Comte de Colbert-Laplace. Others had been destroyed earlier, when his house at Arcueil near Paris was looted in 1871.[5]

Laplace was born in Beaumont-en-Auge, Normandy on 23 March 1749, a village four miles west of Pont l'Évêque. According to W. W. Rouse Ball,[6] his father, Pierre de Laplace, owned and farmed the small estates of Maarquis. His great-uncle, Maitre Oliver de Laplace, had held the title of Chirurgien Royal. It would seem that from a pupil he became an usher in the school at Beaumont; but, having procured a letter of introduction to d'Alembert, he went to Paris to advance his fortune. However, Karl Pearson[5] is scathing about the inaccuracies in Rouse Ball's account and states:

Indeed Caen was probably in Laplace's day the most intellectually active of all the towns of Normandy. It was here that Laplace was educated and was provisionally a professor. It was here he wrote his first paper published in the Mélanges of the Royal Society of Turin, Tome iv. 1766–1769, at least two years before he went at 22 or 23 to Paris in 1771. Thus before he was 20 he was in touch with Lagrange in Turin. He did not go to Paris a raw self-taught country lad with only a peasant background! In 1765 at the age of sixteen Laplace left the "School of the Duke of Orleans" in Beaumont and went to the University of Caen, where he appears to have studied for five years and was a member of the Sphinx. The École Militaire of Beaumont did not replace the old school until 1776.

His parents, Pierre Laplace and Marie-Anne Sochon, were from comfortable families. The Laplace family was involved in agriculture until at least 1750, but Pierre Laplace senior was also a cider merchant and syndic of the town of Beaumont.

Pierre Simon Laplace attended a school in the village run at a Benedictine priory, his father intending that he be ordained in the Roman Catholic Church. At sixteen, to further his father's intention, he was sent to the University of Caen to read theology.[7]

At the university, he was mentored by two enthusiastic teachers of mathematics, Christophe Gadbled and Pierre Le Canu, who awoke his zeal for the subject. Here Laplace's brilliance as a mathematician was quickly recognised and while still at Caen he wrote a memoir Sur le Calcul integral aux differences infiniment petites et aux differences finies. This provided the first intercourse between Laplace and Lagrange. Lagrange was the senior by thirteen years, and had recently founded in his native city Turin a journal named Miscellanea Taurinensia, in which many of his early works were printed and it was in the fourth volume of this series that Laplace's paper appeared. About this time, recognising that he had no vocation for the priesthood, he resolved to become a professional mathematician. Some sources state that he then broke with the church and became an atheist.[citation needed] Laplace did not graduate in theology but left for Paris with a letter of introduction from Le Canu to Jean le Rond d'Alembert who at that time was supreme in scientific circles.[7][8]

According to his great-great-grandson,[5] d'Alembert received him rather poorly, and to get rid of him gave him a thick mathematics book, saying to come back when he had read it. When Laplace came back a few days later, d'Alembert was even less friendly and did not hide his opinion that it was impossible that Laplace could have read and understood the book. But upon questioning him, he realised that it was true, and from that time he took Laplace under his care.

Another account is that Laplace solved overnight a problem that d'Alembert set him for submission the following week, then solved a harder problem the following night. D'Alembert was impressed and recommended him for a teaching place in the École Militaire.[9]

With a secure income and undemanding teaching, Laplace now threw himself into original research and for the next seventeen years, 1771–1787, he produced much of his original work in astronomy.[10]

 
The Calorimeter of Lavoisier and La Place, Encyclopaedia Londinensis, 1801

From 1780 to 1784, Laplace and French chemist Antoine Lavoisier collaborated on several experimental investigations, designing their own equipment for the task.[11] In 1783 they published their joint paper, Memoir on Heat, in which they discussed the kinetic theory of molecular motion.[12] In their experiments they measured the specific heat of various bodies, and the expansion of metals with increasing temperature. They also measured the boiling points of ethanol and ether under pressure.

Laplace further impressed the Marquis de Condorcet, and already by 1771 Laplace felt entitled to membership in the French Academy of Sciences. However, that year admission went to Alexandre-Théophile Vandermonde and in 1772 to Jacques Antoine Joseph Cousin. Laplace was disgruntled, and early in 1773 d'Alembert wrote to Lagrange in Berlin to ask if a position could be found for Laplace there. However, Condorcet became permanent secretary of the Académie in February and Laplace was elected associate member on 31 March, at age 24.[13] In 1773 Laplace read his paper on the invariability of planetary motion in front of the Academy des Sciences. That March he was elected to the academy, a place where he conducted the majority of his science.[14]

On 15 March 1788,[15][5] at the age of thirty-nine, Laplace married Marie-Charlotte de Courty de Romanges, an eighteen-year-old girl from a "good" family in Besançon.[16] The wedding was celebrated at Saint-Sulpice, Paris. The couple had a son, Charles-Émile (1789–1874), and a daughter, Sophie-Suzanne (1792–1813).[17][18]

Analysis, probability, and astronomical stability

Laplace's early published work in 1771 started with differential equations and finite differences but he was already starting to think about the mathematical and philosophical concepts of probability and statistics.[19] However, before his election to the Académie in 1773, he had already drafted two papers that would establish his reputation. The first, Mémoire sur la probabilité des causes par les événements was ultimately published in 1774 while the second paper, published in 1776, further elaborated his statistical thinking and also began his systematic work on celestial mechanics and the stability of the Solar System. The two disciplines would always be interlinked in his mind. "Laplace took probability as an instrument for repairing defects in knowledge."[20] Laplace's work on probability and statistics is discussed below with his mature work on the analytic theory of probabilities.

Stability of the Solar System

Sir Isaac Newton had published his Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica in 1687 in which he gave a derivation of Kepler's laws, which describe the motion of the planets, from his laws of motion and his law of universal gravitation. However, though Newton had privately developed the methods of calculus, all his published work used cumbersome geometric reasoning, unsuitable to account for the more subtle higher-order effects of interactions between the planets. Newton himself had doubted the possibility of a mathematical solution to the whole, even concluding that periodic divine intervention was necessary to guarantee the stability of the Solar System. Dispensing with the hypothesis of divine intervention would be a major activity of Laplace's scientific life.[21] It is now generally regarded that Laplace's methods on their own, though vital to the development of the theory, are not sufficiently precise to demonstrate the stability of the Solar System,[22] and indeed, the Solar System is understood to be chaotic, although it happens to be fairly stable.

One particular problem from observational astronomy was the apparent instability whereby Jupiter's orbit appeared to be shrinking while that of Saturn was expanding. The problem had been tackled by Leonhard Euler in 1748 and Joseph Louis Lagrange in 1763 but without success.[23] In 1776, Laplace published a memoir in which he first explored the possible influences of a purported luminiferous ether or of a law of gravitation that did not act instantaneously. He ultimately returned to an intellectual investment in Newtonian gravity.[24] Euler and Lagrange had made a practical approximation by ignoring small terms in the equations of motion. Laplace noted that though the terms themselves were small, when integrated over time they could become important. Laplace carried his analysis into the higher-order terms, up to and including the cubic. Using this more exact analysis, Laplace concluded that any two planets and the Sun must be in mutual equilibrium and thereby launched his work on the stability of the Solar System.[25] Gerald James Whitrow described the achievement as "the most important advance in physical astronomy since Newton".[21]

Laplace had a wide knowledge of all sciences and dominated all discussions in the Académie.[26] Laplace seems to have regarded analysis merely as a means of attacking physical problems, though the ability with which he invented the necessary analysis is almost phenomenal. As long as his results were true he took but little trouble to explain the steps by which he arrived at them; he never studied elegance or symmetry in his processes, and it was sufficient for him if he could by any means solve the particular question he was discussing.[10]

Tidal dynamics

Dynamic theory of tides

While Newton explained the tides by describing the tide-generating forces and Bernoulli gave a description of the static reaction of the waters on Earth to the tidal potential, the dynamic theory of tides, developed by Laplace in 1775,[27] describes the ocean's real reaction to tidal forces.[28] Laplace's theory of ocean tides took into account friction, resonance and natural periods of ocean basins. It predicted the large amphidromic systems in the world's ocean basins and explains the oceanic tides that are actually observed.[29][30]

The equilibrium theory, based on the gravitational gradient from the Sun and Moon but ignoring the Earth's rotation, the effects of continents, and other important effects, could not explain the real ocean tides.[31][32][33][29][34][35][36][37][38]

 
Newton's three-body model

Since measurements have confirmed the theory, many things have possible explanations now, like how the tides interact with deep sea ridges and chains of seamounts give rise to deep eddies that transport nutrients from the deep to the surface.[39] The equilibrium tide theory calculates the height of the tide wave of less than half a meter, while the dynamic theory explains why tides are up to 15 meters.[40] Satellite observations confirm the accuracy of the dynamic theory, and the tides worldwide are now measured to within a few centimeters.[41][42] Measurements from the CHAMP satellite closely match the models based on the TOPEX data.[43][44][45] Accurate models of tides worldwide are essential for research since the variations due to tides must be removed from measurements when calculating gravity and changes in sea levels.[46]

Laplace's tidal equations

 
A. Lunar gravitational potential: this depicts the Moon directly over 30° N (or 30° S) viewed from above the Northern Hemisphere.
 
B. This view shows same potential from 180° from view A. Viewed from above the Northern Hemisphere. Red up, blue down.

In 1776, Laplace formulated a single set of linear partial differential equations, for tidal flow described as a barotropic two-dimensional sheet flow. Coriolis effects are introduced as well as lateral forcing by gravity. Laplace obtained these equations by simplifying the fluid dynamic equations. But they can also be derived from energy integrals via Lagrange's equation.

For a fluid sheet of average thickness D, the vertical tidal elevation ζ, as well as the horizontal velocity components u and v (in the latitude φ and longitude λ directions, respectively) satisfy Laplace's tidal equations:[47]

 

where Ω is the angular frequency of the planet's rotation, g is the planet's gravitational acceleration at the mean ocean surface, a is the planetary radius, and U is the external gravitational tidal-forcing potential.

William Thomson (Lord Kelvin) rewrote Laplace's momentum terms using the curl to find an equation for vorticity. Under certain conditions this can be further rewritten as a conservation of vorticity.

On the figure of the Earth

During the years 1784–1787 he published some memoirs of exceptional power. Prominent among these is one read in 1783, reprinted as Part II of Théorie du Mouvement et de la figure elliptique des planètes in 1784, and in the third volume of the Mécanique céleste. In this work, Laplace completely determined the attraction of a spheroid on a particle outside it. This is memorable for the introduction into analysis of spherical harmonics or Laplace's coefficients, and also for the development of the use of what we would now call the gravitational potential in celestial mechanics.

Spherical harmonics

 
Spherical harmonics.

In 1783, in a paper sent to the Académie, Adrien-Marie Legendre had introduced what are now known as associated Legendre functions.[10] If two points in a plane have polar coordinates (r, θ) and (r ', θ'), where r ' ≥ r, then, by elementary manipulation, the reciprocal of the distance between the points, d, can be written as:

 

This expression can be expanded in powers of r/r ' using Newton's generalised binomial theorem to give:

 

The sequence of functions P0k(cos φ) is the set of so-called "associated Legendre functions" and their usefulness arises from the fact that every function of the points on a circle can be expanded as a series of them.[10]

Laplace, with scant regard for credit to Legendre, made the non-trivial extension of the result to three dimensions to yield a more general set of functions, the spherical harmonics or Laplace coefficients. The latter term is not in common use now.[10]: p. 340ff 

Potential theory

This paper is also remarkable for the development of the idea of the scalar potential.[10] The gravitational force acting on a body is, in modern language, a vector, having magnitude and direction. A potential function is a scalar function that defines how the vectors will behave. A scalar function is computationally and conceptually easier to deal with than a vector function.

Alexis Clairaut had first suggested the idea in 1743 while working on a similar problem though he was using Newtonian-type geometric reasoning. Laplace described Clairaut's work as being "in the class of the most beautiful mathematical productions".[48] However, Rouse Ball alleges that the idea "was appropriated from Joseph Louis Lagrange, who had used it in his memoirs of 1773, 1777 and 1780".[10] The term "potential" itself was due to Daniel Bernoulli, who introduced it in his 1738 memoire Hydrodynamica. However, according to Rouse Ball, the term "potential function" was not actually used (to refer to a function V of the coordinates of space in Laplace's sense) until George Green's 1828 An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis to the Theories of Electricity and Magnetism.[49][50]

Laplace applied the language of calculus to the potential function and showed that it always satisfies the differential equation:[10]

 

An analogous result for the velocity potential of a fluid had been obtained some years previously by Leonhard Euler.[51][52]

Laplace's subsequent work on gravitational attraction was based on this result. The quantity ∇2V has been termed the concentration of V and its value at any point indicates the "excess" of the value of V there over its mean value in the neighbourhood of the point.[53] Laplace's equation, a special case of Poisson's equation, appears ubiquitously in mathematical physics. The concept of a potential occurs in fluid dynamics, electromagnetism and other areas. Rouse Ball speculated that it might be seen as "the outward sign" of one of the a priori forms in Kant's theory of perception.[10]

The spherical harmonics turn out to be critical to practical solutions of Laplace's equation. Laplace's equation in spherical coordinates, such as are used for mapping the sky, can be simplified, using the method of separation of variables into a radial part, depending solely on distance from the centre point, and an angular or spherical part. The solution to the spherical part of the equation can be expressed as a series of Laplace's spherical harmonics, simplifying practical computation.

Planetary and lunar inequalities

 
Title page of an 1817 copy of Delambre's "Tables écliptiques des satellites de Jupiter," which references Laplace's contributions in its title.
 
Tables in an 1817 copy of Delambre's "Tables écliptiques des satellites de Jupiter" - these calculations were influenced by Laplace's previous discoveries.

Jupiter–Saturn great inequality

Laplace presented a memoir on planetary inequalities in three sections, in 1784, 1785, and 1786. This dealt mainly with the identification and explanation of the perturbations now known as the "great Jupiter–Saturn inequality". Laplace solved a longstanding problem in the study and prediction of the movements of these planets. He showed by general considerations, first, that the mutual action of two planets could never cause large changes in the eccentricities and inclinations of their orbits; but then, even more importantly, that peculiarities arose in the Jupiter–Saturn system because of the near approach to commensurability of the mean motions of Jupiter and Saturn.[3][54]

In this context commensurability means that the ratio of the two planets' mean motions is very nearly equal to a ratio between a pair of small whole numbers. Two periods of Saturn's orbit around the Sun almost equal five of Jupiter's. The corresponding difference between multiples of the mean motions, (2nJ − 5nS), corresponds to a period of nearly 900 years, and it occurs as a small divisor in the integration of a very small perturbing force with this same period. As a result, the integrated perturbations with this period are disproportionately large, about 0.8° degrees of arc in orbital longitude for Saturn and about 0.3° for Jupiter.

Further developments of these theorems on planetary motion were given in his two memoirs of 1788 and 1789, but with the aid of Laplace's discoveries, the tables of the motions of Jupiter and Saturn could at last be made much more accurate. It was on the basis of Laplace's theory that Delambre computed his astronomical tables.[10]

Books

Laplace now set himself the task to write a work which should "offer a complete solution of the great mechanical problem presented by the Solar System, and bring theory to coincide so closely with observation that empirical equations should no longer find a place in astronomical tables."[3] The result is embodied in the Exposition du système du monde and the Mécanique céleste.[10]

The former was published in 1796, and gives a general explanation of the phenomena, but omits all details. It contains a summary of the history of astronomy. This summary procured for its author the honour of admission to the forty of the French Academy and is commonly esteemed one of the masterpieces of French literature, though it is not altogether reliable for the later periods of which it treats.[10]

Laplace developed the nebular hypothesis of the formation of the Solar System, first suggested by Emanuel Swedenborg and expanded by Immanuel Kant, a hypothesis that continues to dominate accounts of the origin of planetary systems. According to Laplace's description of the hypothesis, the Solar System had evolved from a globular mass of incandescent gas rotating around an axis through its centre of mass. As it cooled, this mass contracted, and successive rings broke off from its outer edge. These rings in their turn cooled, and finally condensed into the planets, while the Sun represented the central core which was still left. On this view, Laplace predicted that the more distant planets would be older than those nearer the Sun.[10][55]

As mentioned, the idea of the nebular hypothesis had been outlined by Immanuel Kant in 1755,[55] and he had also suggested "meteoric aggregations" and tidal friction as causes affecting the formation of the Solar System. Laplace was probably aware of this, but, like many writers of his time, he generally did not reference the work of others.[5]

Laplace's analytical discussion of the Solar System is given in his Mécanique céleste published in five volumes. The first two volumes, published in 1799, contain methods for calculating the motions of the planets, determining their figures, and resolving tidal problems.[3] The third and fourth volumes, published in 1802 and 1805, contain applications of these methods, and several astronomical tables. The fifth volume, published in 1825, is mainly historical, but it gives as appendices the results of Laplace's latest researches. Laplace's own investigations embodied in it are so numerous and valuable that it is regrettable to have to add that many results are appropriated from other writers with scanty or no acknowledgement, and the conclusions — which have been described as the organised result of a century of patient toil — are frequently mentioned as if they were due to Laplace.[10]

 
First pages to Exposition du Système du Monde (1799)

Jean-Baptiste Biot, who assisted Laplace in revising it for the press, says that Laplace himself was frequently unable to recover the details in the chain of reasoning, and, if satisfied that the conclusions were correct, he was content to insert the constantly recurring formula, "Il est aisé à voir que ... " ("It is easy to see that ..."). The Mécanique céleste is not only the translation of Newton's Principia into the language of the differential calculus, but it completes parts of which Newton had been unable to fill in the details. The work was carried forward in a more finely tuned form in Félix Tisserand's Traité de mécanique céleste (1889–1896), but Laplace's treatise will always remain a standard authority.[10] In the years 1784–1787, Laplace produced some memoirs of exceptional power. The significant among these was one issued in 1784, and reprinted in the third volume of the Méchanique céleste.[citation needed] In this work he completely determined the attraction of a spheroid on a particle outside it. This is known for the introduction into analysis of the potential, a useful mathematical concept of broad applicability to the physical sciences.

Black holes

Laplace also came close to propounding the concept of the black hole. He suggested that there could be massive stars whose gravity is so great that not even light could escape from their surface (see escape velocity).[56][1][57][58] However, this insight was so far ahead of its time that it played no role in the history of scientific development.[59]

Arcueil

 
Laplace's house at Arcueil to the south of Paris.

In 1806, Laplace bought a house in Arcueil, then a village and not yet absorbed into the Paris conurbation. The chemist Claude Louis Berthollet was a neighbour – their gardens were not separated[60] – and the pair formed the nucleus of an informal scientific circle, latterly known as the Society of Arcueil. Because of their closeness to Napoleon, Laplace and Berthollet effectively controlled advancement in the scientific establishment and admission to the more prestigious offices. The Society built up a complex pyramid of patronage.[61] In 1806, Laplace was also elected a foreign member of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences.

Analytic theory of probabilities

In 1812, Laplace issued his Théorie analytique des probabilités in which he laid down many fundamental results in statistics. The first half of this treatise was concerned with probability methods and problems, the second half with statistical methods and applications. Laplace's proofs are not always rigorous according to the standards of a later day, and his perspective slides back and forth between the Bayesian and non-Bayesian views with an ease that makes some of his investigations difficult to follow, but his conclusions remain basically sound even in those few situations where his analysis goes astray.[62] In 1819, he published a popular account of his work on probability. This book bears the same relation to the Théorie des probabilités that the Système du monde does to the Méchanique céleste.[10] In its emphasis on the analytical importance of probabilistic problems, especially in the context of the "approximation of formula functions of large numbers," Laplace's work goes beyond the contemporary view which almost exclusively considered aspects of practical applicability.[63] Laplace's Théorie analytique remained the most influential book of mathematical probability theory to the end of the 19th century. The general relevance for statistics of Laplacian error theory was appreciated only by the end of the 19th century. However, it influenced the further development of a largely analytically oriented probability theory.

Inductive probability

In his Essai philosophique sur les probabilités (1814), Laplace set out a mathematical system of inductive reasoning based on probability, which we would today recognise as Bayesian. He begins the text with a series of principles of probability, the first six being:

  1. Probability is the ratio of the "favored events" to the total possible events.
  2. The first principle assumes equal probabilities for all events. When this is not true, we must first determine the probabilities of each event. Then, the probability is the sum of the probabilities of all possible favoured events.
  3. For independent events, the probability of the occurrence of all is the probability of each multiplied together.
  4. For events not independent, the probability of event B following event A (or event A causing B) is the probability of A multiplied by the probability that, given A, B will occur.
  5. The probability that A will occur, given that B has occurred, is the probability of A and B occurring divided by the probability of B.
  6. Three corollaries are given for the sixth principle, which amount to Bayesian probability. Where event Ai ∈ {A1, A2, ... An} exhausts the list of possible causes for event B, Pr(B) = Pr(A1, A2, ..., An). Then
 

One well-known formula arising from his system is the rule of succession, given as principle seven. Suppose that some trial has only two possible outcomes, labelled "success" and "failure". Under the assumption that little or nothing is known a priori about the relative plausibilities of the outcomes, Laplace derived a formula for the probability that the next trial will be a success.

 

where s is the number of previously observed successes and n is the total number of observed trials. It is still used as an estimator for the probability of an event if we know the event space, but have only a small number of samples.

The rule of succession has been subject to much criticism, partly due to the example which Laplace chose to illustrate it. He calculated that the probability that the sun will rise tomorrow, given that it has never failed to in the past, was

 

where d is the number of times the sun has risen in the past. This result has been derided as absurd, and some authors have concluded that all applications of the Rule of Succession are absurd by extension. However, Laplace was fully aware of the absurdity of the result; immediately following the example, he wrote, "But this number [i.e., the probability that the sun will rise tomorrow] is far greater for him who, seeing in the totality of phenomena the principle regulating the days and seasons, realizes that nothing at the present moment can arrest the course of it."[64]

Probability-generating function

The method of estimating the ratio of the number of favourable cases to the whole number of possible cases had been previously indicated by Laplace in a paper written in 1779. It consists of treating the successive values of any function as the coefficients in the expansion of another function, with reference to a different variable.[3] The latter is therefore called the probability-generating function of the former.[3] Laplace then shows how, by means of interpolation, these coefficients may be determined from the generating function. Next he attacks the converse problem, and from the coefficients he finds the generating function; this is effected by the solution of a finite difference equation.[10]

Least squares and central limit theorem

The fourth chapter of this treatise includes an exposition of the method of least squares, a remarkable testimony to Laplace's command over the processes of analysis. In 1805 Legendre had published the method of least squares, making no attempt to tie it to the theory of probability. In 1809 Gauss had derived the normal distribution from the principle that the arithmetic mean of observations gives the most probable value for the quantity measured; then, turning this argument back upon itself, he showed that, if the errors of observation are normally distributed, the least squares estimates give the most probable values for the coefficients in regression situations. These two works seem to have spurred Laplace to complete work toward a treatise on probability he had contemplated as early as 1783.[62]

In two important papers in 1810 and 1811, Laplace first developed the characteristic function as a tool for large-sample theory and proved the first general central limit theorem. Then in a supplement to his 1810 paper written after he had seen Gauss's work, he showed that the central limit theorem provided a Bayesian justification for least squares: if one were combining observations, each one of which was itself the mean of a large number of independent observations, then the least squares estimates would not only maximise the likelihood function, considered as a posterior distribution, but also minimise the expected posterior error, all this without any assumption as to the error distribution or a circular appeal to the principle of the arithmetic mean.[62] In 1811 Laplace took a different non-Bayesian tack. Considering a linear regression problem, he restricted his attention to linear unbiased estimators of the linear coefficients. After showing that members of this class were approximately normally distributed if the number of observations was large, he argued that least squares provided the "best" linear estimators. Here it is "best" in the sense that it minimised the asymptotic variance and thus both minimised the expected absolute value of the error, and maximised the probability that the estimate would lie in any symmetric interval about the unknown coefficient, no matter what the error distribution. His derivation included the joint limiting distribution of the least squares estimators of two parameters.[62]

Laplace's demon

In 1814, Laplace published what may have been the first scientific articulation of causal determinism:[65]

We may regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its past and the cause of its future. An intellect which at a certain moment would know all forces that set nature in motion, and all positions of all items of which nature is composed, if this intellect were also vast enough to submit these data to analysis, it would embrace in a single formula the movements of the greatest bodies of the universe and those of the tiniest atom; for such an intellect nothing would be uncertain and the future just like the past would be the present to it.

— Pierre Simon Laplace, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities[66]

This intellect is often referred to as Laplace's demon (in the same vein as Maxwell's demon) and sometimes Laplace's Superman (after Hans Reichenbach). Laplace, himself, did not use the word "demon", which was a later embellishment. As translated into English above, he simply referred to: "Une intelligence ... Rien ne serait incertain pour elle, et l'avenir comme le passé, serait présent à ses yeux."

Even though Laplace is generally credited with having first formulated the concept of causal determinism, in a philosophical context the idea was actually widespread at the time, and can be found as early as 1756 in Maupertuis' 'Sur la Divination'.[67] As well, Jesuit scientist Boscovich first proposed a version of scientific determinism very similar to Laplace's in his 1758 book Theoria philosophiae naturalis.[68]

Laplace transforms

As early as 1744, Euler, followed by Lagrange, had started looking for solutions of differential equations in the form:[69]

 

The Laplace transform has the form:

 

This integral operator transforms a function of time ( ) into a function of a complex variable ( ), usually interpreted as complex frequency.

Other discoveries and accomplishments

Mathematics

Among the other discoveries of Laplace in pure and applied mathematics are:

Surface tension

Laplace built upon the qualitative work of Thomas Young to develop the theory of capillary action and the Young–Laplace equation.

Speed of sound

Laplace in 1816 was the first to point out that the speed of sound in air depends on the heat capacity ratio. Newton's original theory gave too low a value, because it does not take account of the adiabatic compression of the air which results in a local rise in temperature and pressure. Laplace's investigations in practical physics were confined to those carried on by him jointly with Lavoisier in the years 1782 to 1784 on the specific heat of various bodies.[10]

Politics

Minister of the Interior

In his early years, Laplace was careful never to become involved in politics, or indeed in life outside the Académie des sciences. He prudently withdrew from Paris during the most violent part of the Revolution.[70]

In November 1799, immediately after seizing power in the coup of 18 Brumaire, Napoleon appointed Laplace to the post of Minister of the Interior.[3] The appointment, however, lasted only six weeks, after which Lucien Bonaparte, Napoleon's brother, was given the post.[3] Evidently, once Napoleon's grip on power was secure, there was no need for a prestigious but inexperienced scientist in the government.[71] Napoleon later (in his Mémoires de Sainte Hélène) wrote of Laplace's dismissal as follows:[10]

Geometrician of the first rank, Laplace was not long in showing himself a worse than average administrator; from his first actions in office we recognized our mistake. Laplace did not consider any question from the right angle: he sought subtleties everywhere, conceived only problems, and finally carried the spirit of "infinitesimals" into the administration.

Grattan-Guinness, however, describes these remarks as "tendentious", since there seems to be no doubt that Laplace "was only appointed as a short-term figurehead, a place-holder while Napoleon consolidated power".[71]

From Bonaparte to the Bourbons

 
Laplace.

Although Laplace was removed from office, it was desirable to retain his allegiance. He was accordingly raised to the senate, and to the third volume of the Mécanique céleste he prefixed a note that of all the truths therein contained the most precious to the author was the declaration he thus made of his devotion towards the peacemaker of Europe.[3] In copies sold after the Bourbon Restoration this was struck out. (Pearson points out that the censor would not have allowed it anyway.) In 1814 it was evident that the empire was falling; Laplace hastened to tender his services to the Bourbons, and in 1817 during the Restoration he was rewarded with the title of marquis.

According to Rouse Ball, the contempt that his more honest colleagues felt for his conduct in the matter may be read in the pages of Paul Louis Courier. His knowledge was useful on the numerous scientific commissions on which he served, and, says Rouse Ball, probably accounts for the manner in which his political insincerity was overlooked.[10]

Roger Hahn in his 2005 biography disputes this portrayal of Laplace as an opportunist and turncoat, pointing out that, like many in France, he had followed the debacle of Napoleon's Russian campaign with serious misgivings. The Laplaces, whose only daughter Sophie had died in childbirth in September 1813, were in fear for the safety of their son Émile, who was on the eastern front with the emperor. Napoleon had originally come to power promising stability, but it was clear that he had overextended himself, putting the nation at peril. It was at this point that Laplace's loyalty began to weaken. Although he still had easy access to Napoleon, his personal relations with the emperor cooled considerably. As a grieving father, he was particularly cut to the quick by Napoleon's insensitivity in an exchange related by Jean-Antoine Chaptal: "On his return from the rout in Leipzig, he [Napoleon] accosted Mr Laplace: 'Oh! I see that you have grown thin—Sire, I have lost my daughter—Oh! that's not a reason for losing weight. You are a mathematician; put this event in an equation, and you will find that it adds up to zero.'"[72]

Political philosophy

In the second edition (1814) of the Essai philosophique, Laplace added some revealing comments on politics and governance. Since it is, he says, "the practice of the eternal principles of reason, justice and humanity that produce and preserve societies, there is a great advantage to adhere to these principles, and a great inadvisability to deviate from them".[73][74] Noting "the depths of misery into which peoples have been cast" when ambitious leaders disregard these principles, Laplace makes a veiled criticism of Napoleon's conduct: "Every time a great power intoxicated by the love of conquest aspires to universal domination, the sense of liberty among the unjustly threatened nations breeds a coalition to which it always succumbs." Laplace argues that "in the midst of the multiple causes that direct and restrain various states, natural limits" operate, within which it is "important for the stability as well as the prosperity of empires to remain". States that transgress these limits cannot avoid being "reverted" to them, "just as is the case when the waters of the seas whose floor has been lifted by violent tempests sink back to their level by the action of gravity".[75][76]

About the political upheavals he had witnessed, Laplace formulated a set of principles derived from physics to favour evolutionary over revolutionary change:

Let us apply to the political and moral sciences the method founded upon observation and calculation, which has served us so well in the natural sciences. Let us not offer fruitless and often injurious resistance to the inevitable benefits derived from the progress of enlightenment; but let us change our institutions and the usages that we have for a long time adopted only with extreme caution. We know from past experience the drawbacks they can cause, but we are unaware of the extent of ills that change may produce. In the face of this ignorance, the theory of probability instructs us to avoid all change, especially to avoid sudden changes which in the moral as well as the physical world never occur without a considerable loss of vital force.[77]

In these lines, Laplace expressed the views he had arrived at after experiencing the Revolution and the Empire. He believed that the stability of nature, as revealed through scientific findings, provided the model that best helped to preserve the human species. "Such views," Hahn comments, "were also of a piece with his steadfast character."[76]

In the Essai philosophique, Laplace also illustrates the potential of probabilities in political studies by applying the law of large numbers to justify the candidates’ integer-valued ranks used in the Borda method of voting, with which the new members of the Academy of Sciences were elected. Laplace’s verbal argument is so rigorous that it can easily be converted into a formal proof.[78][79]

Death

 
Tomb of Pierre-Simon Laplace

Laplace died in Paris on 5 March 1827, which was the same day Alessandro Volta died. His brain was removed by his physician, François Magendie, and kept for many years, eventually being displayed in a roving anatomical museum in Britain. It was reportedly smaller than the average brain.[5] Laplace was buried at Père Lachaise in Paris but in 1888 his remains were moved to Saint Julien de Mailloc in the canton of Orbec and reinterred on the family estate.[80] The tomb is situated on a hill overlooking the village of St Julien de Mailloc, Normandy, France.

Religious opinions

I had no need of that hypothesis

A frequently cited but potentially apocryphal interaction between Laplace and Napoleon purportedly concerns the existence of God. Although the conversation in question did occur, the exact words Laplace used and his intended meaning are not known. A typical version is provided by Rouse Ball:[10]

Laplace went in state to Napoleon to present a copy of his work, and the following account of the interview is well authenticated, and so characteristic of all the parties concerned that I quote it in full. Someone had told Napoleon that the book contained no mention of the name of God; Napoleon, who was fond of putting embarrassing questions, received it with the remark, 'M. Laplace, they tell me you have written this large book on the system of the universe, and have never even mentioned its Creator.' Laplace, who, though the most supple of politicians, was as stiff as a martyr on every point of his philosophy, drew himself up and answered bluntly, Je n'avais pas besoin de cette hypothèse-là. ("I had no need of that hypothesis.") Napoleon, greatly amused, told this reply to Lagrange, who exclaimed, Ah! c'est une belle hypothèse; ça explique beaucoup de choses. ("Ah, it is a fine hypothesis; it explains many things.")

An earlier report, although without the mention of Laplace's name, is found in Antommarchi's The Last Moments of Napoleon (1825):[81]

Je m'entretenais avec L ..... je le félicitais d'un ouvrage qu'il venait de publier et lui demandais comment le nom de Dieu, qui se reproduisait sans cesse sous la plume de Lagrange, ne s'était pas présenté une seule fois sous la sienne. C'est, me répondit-il, que je n'ai pas eu besoin de cette hypothèse. ("While speaking with L ..... I congratulated him on a work which he had just published and asked him how the name of God, which appeared endlessly in the works of Lagrange, didn't occur even once in his. He replied that he had no need of that hypothesis.")

In 1884, however, the astronomer Hervé Faye[82][83] affirmed that this account of Laplace's exchange with Napoleon presented a "strangely transformed" (étrangement transformée) or garbled version of what had actually happened. It was not God that Laplace had treated as a hypothesis, but merely his intervention at a determinate point:

In fact Laplace never said that. Here, I believe, is what truly happened. Newton, believing that the secular perturbations which he had sketched out in his theory would in the long run end up destroying the Solar System, says somewhere that God was obliged to intervene from time to time to remedy the evil and somehow keep the system working properly. This, however, was a pure supposition suggested to Newton by an incomplete view of the conditions of the stability of our little world. Science was not yet advanced enough at that time to bring these conditions into full view. But Laplace, who had discovered them by a deep analysis, would have replied to the First Consul that Newton had wrongly invoked the intervention of God to adjust from time to time the machine of the world (la machine du monde) and that he, Laplace, had no need of such an assumption. It was not God, therefore, that Laplace treated as a hypothesis, but his intervention in a certain place.

Laplace's younger colleague, the astronomer François Arago, who gave his eulogy before the French Academy in 1827,[84] told Faye of an attempt by Laplace to keep the garbled version of his interaction with Napoleon out of circulation. Faye writes:[82][83]

I have it on the authority of M. Arago that Laplace, warned shortly before his death that that anecdote was about to be published in a biographical collection, had requested him [Arago] to demand its deletion by the publisher. It was necessary to either explain or delete it, and the second way was the easiest. But, unfortunately, it was neither deleted nor explained.

The Swiss-American historian of mathematics Florian Cajori appears to have been unaware of Faye's research, but in 1893 he came to a similar conclusion.[85] Stephen Hawking said in 1999,[65] "I don't think that Laplace was claiming that God does not exist. It's just that he doesn't intervene, to break the laws of Science."

The only eyewitness account of Laplace's interaction with Napoleon is from the entry for 8 August 1802 in the diary of the British astronomer Sir William Herschel:[86]

The first Consul then asked a few questions relating to Astronomy and the construction of the heavens to which I made such answers as seemed to give him great satisfaction. He also addressed himself to Mr Laplace on the same subject, and held a considerable argument with him in which he differed from that eminent mathematician. The difference was occasioned by an exclamation of the first Consul, who asked in a tone of exclamation or admiration (when we were speaking of the extent of the sidereal heavens): 'And who is the author of all this!' Mons. De la Place wished to shew that a chain of natural causes would account for the construction and preservation of the wonderful system. This the first Consul rather opposed. Much may be said on the subject; by joining the arguments of both we shall be led to 'Nature and nature's God'.

Since this makes no mention of Laplace's saying, "I had no need of that hypothesis," Daniel Johnson[87] argues that "Laplace never used the words attributed to him." Arago's testimony, however, appears to imply that he did, only not in reference to the existence of God.

Views on God

Raised a Catholic, Laplace appears in adult life to have inclined to deism (presumably his considered position, since it is the only one found in his writings). However, some of his contemporaries thought he was an atheist, while a number of recent scholars have described him as agnostic.

Faye thought that Laplace "did not profess atheism",[82] but Napoleon, on Saint Helena, told General Gaspard Gourgaud, "I often asked Laplace what he thought of God. He owned that he was an atheist."[88] Roger Hahn, in his biography of Laplace, mentions a dinner party at which "the geologist Jean-Étienne Guettard was staggered by Laplace's bold denunciation of the existence of God". It appeared to Guettard that Laplace's atheism "was supported by a thoroughgoing materialism".[89] But the chemist Jean-Baptiste Dumas, who knew Laplace well in the 1820s, wrote that Laplace "provided materialists with their specious arguments, without sharing their convictions".[90][91]

Hahn states: "Nowhere in his writings, either public or private, does Laplace deny God's existence."[92] Expressions occur in his private letters that appear inconsistent with atheism.[3] On 17 June 1809, for instance, he wrote to his son, "Je prie Dieu qu'il veille sur tes jours. Aie-Le toujours présent à ta pensée, ainsi que ton père et ta mère [I pray that God watches over your days. Let Him be always present to your mind, as also your father and your mother]."[83][93] Ian S. Glass, quoting Herschel's account of the celebrated exchange with Napoleon, writes that Laplace was "evidently a deist like Herschel".[94]

In Exposition du système du monde, Laplace quotes Newton's assertion that "the wondrous disposition of the Sun, the planets and the comets, can only be the work of an all-powerful and intelligent Being".[95] This, says Laplace, is a "thought in which he [Newton] would be even more confirmed, if he had known what we have shown, namely that the conditions of the arrangement of the planets and their satellites are precisely those which ensure its stability".[96] By showing that the "remarkable" arrangement of the planets could be entirely explained by the laws of motion, Laplace had eliminated the need for the "supreme intelligence" to intervene, as Newton had "made" it do.[97] Laplace cites with approval Leibniz's criticism of Newton's invocation of divine intervention to restore order to the Solar System: "This is to have very narrow ideas about the wisdom and the power of God."[98] He evidently shared Leibniz's astonishment at Newton's belief "that God has made his machine so badly that unless he affects it by some extraordinary means, the watch will very soon cease to go".[99]

In a group of manuscripts, preserved in relative secrecy in a black envelope in the library of the Académie des sciences and published for the first time by Hahn, Laplace mounted a deist critique of Christianity. It is, he writes, the "first and most infallible of principles ... to reject miraculous facts as untrue".[100] As for the doctrine of transubstantiation, it "offends at the same time reason, experience, the testimony of all our senses, the eternal laws of nature, and the sublime ideas that we ought to form of the Supreme Being". It is the sheerest absurdity to suppose that "the sovereign lawgiver of the universe would suspend the laws that he has established, and which he seems to have maintained invariably".[101]

Laplace also ridiculed the use of probability in theology. Even following Pascal's reasoning presented in Pascal's wager, it is not worth making a bet, for the hope of profit – equal to the product of the value of the testimonies (infinitely small) and the value of the happiness they promise (which is significant but finite) – must necessarily be infinitely small.[102]

In old age, Laplace remained curious about the question of God[103] and frequently discussed Christianity with the Swiss astronomer Jean-Frédéric-Théodore Maurice.[104] He told Maurice that "Christianity is quite a beautiful thing" and praised its civilising influence. Maurice thought that the basis of Laplace's beliefs was, little by little, being modified, but that he held fast to his conviction that the invariability of the laws of nature did not permit of supernatural events.[103] After Laplace's death, Poisson told Maurice, "You know that I do not share your [religious] opinions, but my conscience forces me to recount something that will surely please you." When Poisson had complimented Laplace about his "brilliant discoveries", the dying man had fixed him with a pensive look and replied, "Ah! We chase after phantoms [chimères]."[105] These were his last words, interpreted by Maurice as a realisation of the ultimate "vanity" of earthly pursuits.[106] Laplace received the last rites from the curé of the Missions Étrangères (in whose parish he was to be buried)[91] and the curé of Arcueil.[106]

According to his biographer, Roger Hahn, it is "not credible" that Laplace "had a proper Catholic end", and he "remained a skeptic" to the very end of his life.[107] Laplace in his last years has been described as an agnostic.[108][109][110]

Excommunication of a comet

In 1470 the humanist scholar Bartolomeo Platina wrote[111] that Pope Callixtus III had asked for prayers for deliverance from the Turks during a 1456 appearance of Halley's Comet. Platina's account does not accord with Church records, which do not mention the comet. Laplace is alleged to have embellished the story by claiming the Pope had "excommunicated" Halley's comet.[112] What Laplace actually said, in Exposition du système du monde (1796), was that the Pope had ordered the comet to be "exorcised" (conjuré). It was Arago, in Des Comètes en général (1832), who first spoke of an excommunication.[113][114][115]

Honors

Quotations

  • I had no need of that hypothesis. ("Je n'avais pas besoin de cette hypothèse-là", allegedly as a reply to Napoleon, who had asked why he hadn't mentioned God in his book on astronomy.)[10]
  • It is therefore obvious that ... (Frequently used in the Celestial Mechanics when he had proved something and mislaid the proof, or found it clumsy. Notorious as a signal for something true, but hard to prove.)
  • "We are so far from knowing all the agents of nature and their diverse modes of action that it would not be philosophical to deny phenomena solely because they are inexplicable in the actual state of our knowledge. But we ought to examine them with an attention all the more scrupulous as it appears more difficult to admit them."[119]
    • This is restated in Theodore Flournoy's work From India to the Planet Mars as the Principle of Laplace or, "The weight of the evidence should be proportioned to the strangeness of the facts."[120]
    • Most often repeated as "The weight of evidence for an extraordinary claim must be proportioned to its strangeness." (see also: Sagan standard)
  • This simplicity of ratios will not appear astonishing if we consider that all the effects of nature are only mathematical results of a small number of immutable laws.[121]
  • Infinitely varied in her effects, nature is only simple in her causes.[122]
  • What we know is little, and what we are ignorant of is immense. (Fourier comments: "This was at least the meaning of his last words, which were articulated with difficulty.")[60]
  • One sees in this essay that the theory of probabilities is basically only common sense reduced to a calculus. It makes one estimate accurately what right-minded people feel by a sort of instinct, often without being able to give a reason for it.[123]

List of works

  • Traité de mécanique céleste (in French). Vol. 1. Paris: Charles Crapelet. 1799.
  • Traité de mécanique céleste (in French). Vol. 2. Paris: Charles Crapelet. 1799.
  • Traité de mécanique céleste (in French). Vol. 3. Paris: Charles Crapelet. 1802.
  • Traité de mécanique céleste (in French). Vol. 4. Paris: Charles Crapelet. 1805.
  • Traité de mécanique céleste (in French). Vol. 5. Paris: Charles Louis Étienne Bachelier. 1852.
  • Précis de l'histoire de l'astronomie (in Italian). Milano: Angelo Stanislao Brambilla. 1823.
  • Exposition du système du monde (in French). Paris: Charles Louis Étienne Bachelier. 1824.

Bibliography

  • Œuvres complètes de Laplace, 14 vol. (1878–1912), Paris: Gauthier-Villars (copy from Gallica in French)
  • Théorie du movement et de la figure elliptique des planètes (1784) Paris (not in Œuvres complètes)
  • Précis de l'histoire de l'astronomie
  • Alphonse Rebière, Mathématiques et mathématiciens, 3rd edition Paris, Nony & Cie, 1898.

English translations

  •  
    Volumes 1 and 2 of "System of the World" (1809)
    Bowditch, N. (trans.) (1829–1839) Mécanique céleste, 4 vols, Boston
  • – [1829–1839] (1966–1969) Celestial Mechanics, 5 vols, including the original French
  • Pound, J. (trans.) (1809) The System of the World, 2 vols, London: Richard Phillips
  • _ The System of the World (v.1)
  • _ The System of the World (v.2)
  • – [1809] (2007) The System of the World, vol.1, Kessinger, ISBN 1-4326-5367-9
  • Toplis, J. (trans.) (1814) A treatise upon analytical mechanics Nottingham: H. Barnett
  • Laplace, Pierre Simon Marquis De (2007) [1902]. A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities. Translated by Truscott, F.W. & Emory, F.L. ISBN 978-1-60206-328-0., translated from the French 6th ed. (1840)
  • Dale, Andrew I.; Laplace, Pierre-Simon (1995). Philosophical Essay on Probabilities. Sources in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. Vol. 13. Translated by Andrew I. Dale. Springer. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-4184-3. hdl:2027/coo1.ark:/13960/t3126f008. ISBN 978-1-4612-8689-9., translated from the French 5th ed. (1825)

See also

References

Citations

  1. ^ a b S.W. Hawking and George F.R. Ellis, The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time, Cambridge University Press, 1973, p. 364.
  2. ^ Stigler, Stephen M. (1986). The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900. Harvard University Press, Chapter 3.
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Clerke, Agnes Mary (1911). "Laplace, Pierre Simon" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 16 (11th ed.). pp. 200–202.
  4. ^ Hankins, Thomas L. (2006). "Pierre Simon Laplace, 1749-1827: A Determined Scientist (Book review)". Physics Today. 59 (9): 62–64. doi:10.1063/1.2364251.
  5. ^ a b c d e f "Laplace, being Extracts from Lectures delivered by Karl Pearson", Biometrika, vol. 21, December 1929, pp. 202–216.
  6. ^ W.W. Rouse Ball A Short Account of the History of Mathematics, 4th edition, 1908.
  7. ^ a b *O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "Pierre-Simon Laplace", MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, University of St Andrews. Retrieved 25 August 2007
  8. ^ Edmund Whittaker (Vol. 33, No. 303 (Feb. 1949), pp. 1–12), "Laplace", The Mathematical Gazette.
  9. ^ Gillispie (1997), pp. 3–4
  10. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab Rouse Ball (1908).
  11. ^ "The Chemical Revolution of Antoine-Laurent Lavoisier International Historic Chemical Landmark". American Chemical Society. 8 June 1999.
  12. ^ Golinski, Jan V. (June 1983). "Antoine Laurent Lavoisier , Pierre Simon , Marquis de Laplace , Henry Guerlac". Isis. 74 (2): 288–289. doi:10.1086/353288.
  13. ^ Gillispie (1997), p. 5
  14. ^ "Effects of the Scientific Community on Laplace" Retrieved on 10 January 2018
  15. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 99. However, Gillispie (1997), p. 67, gives the month of the marriage as May.
  16. ^ Hahn (2005), pp. 99–100
  17. ^ Gillispie (1997), p. 67
  18. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 101
  19. ^ Gillispie (1989), pp. 7–12
  20. ^ Gillispie (1989). pp. 14–15
  21. ^ a b Whitrow (2001)
  22. ^ Celletti, A. & Perozzi, E. (2007). Celestial Mechanics: The Waltz of the Planets. Celestial Mechanics – the Waltz of the Planets. Berlin: Springer. pp. 91–93. Bibcode:2006cmwp.book.....C. ISBN 978-0-387-30777-0.
  23. ^ Whittaker (1949b)
  24. ^ Gillispie (1989). pp. 29–35
  25. ^ Gillispie (1989), pp. 35–36
  26. ^ School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland.
  27. ^ "Short notes on the Dynamical theory of Laplace". 20 November 2011.
  28. ^ Hautala, Susan; Kelly, Kathryn; Thompson, LuAnne (2005). "Tide Dynamics" (PDF).
  29. ^ a b "Higher Education" (PDF).
  30. ^ Ahn, Kyungjin (September 2009). "An Astronomer's View on the Current College-Level Textbook Descriptions of Tides" (PDF). Korean Earth Science Society.
  31. ^ Tidal theory 22 August 2017 at the Wayback Machine website South African Navy Hydrographic Office
  32. ^ "Dynamic theory for tides". Oberlin.edu. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  33. ^ "Dynamic Theory of Tides".
  34. ^ . Web.vims.edu. Archived from the original on 13 January 2013. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  35. ^ . Coa.edu. Archived from the original on 19 December 2013. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  36. ^ "Welcome to nginx!". beacon.salemstate.edu. Archived from the original on 14 December 2012. Retrieved 3 February 2022.
  37. ^ "Tides – building, river, sea, depth, oceans, effects, important, largest, system, wave, effect, marine, Pacific". Waterencyclopedia.com. 27 June 2010.
  38. ^ . Ocean.tamu.edu. Archived from the original on 16 June 2013. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  39. ^ Floor Anthoni. "Tides". Seafriends.org.nz. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  40. ^ "The Cause & Nature of Tides".
  41. ^ "Scientific Visualization Studio TOPEX/Poseidon images". Svs.gsfc.nasa.gov. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  42. ^ "TOPEX/Poseidon Western Hemisphere: Tide Height Model : NASA/Goddard Space Flight Center Scientific Visualization Studio : Free Download & Streaming : Internet Archive". 15 June 2000.
  43. ^ TOPEX data used to model actual tides for 15 days from the year 2000 TOPEX/Poseidon Flat Earth Tide Height Model
  44. ^ http://www.geomag.us/info/Ocean/m2_CHAMP+longwave_SSH.swf[bare URL]
  45. ^ "OSU Tidal Data Inversion". Volkov.oce.orst.edu. Archived from the original on 22 October 2012. Retrieved 2 June 2012.
  46. ^ . Archived from the original on 2 April 2015.
  47. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 11 April 2019. Retrieved 28 October 2017.
  48. ^ Grattan-Guinness, I. (2003). Companion Encyclopedia of the History and Philosophy of the Mathematical Sciences. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 1097–1098. ISBN 978-0-8018-7396-6.
  49. ^ W.W. Rouse Ball A Short Account of the History of Mathematics (4th edition, 1908)
  50. ^ Green, G. (1828). An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis to the Theories of Electricity and Magnetism. Nottingham. arXiv:0807.0088. Bibcode:2008arXiv0807.0088G.
  51. ^ Kline, Morris (1972). Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times. Vol. 2. Oxford University Press. pp. 524–525. ISBN 978-0-19-506136-9.
  52. ^ Euler, Leonhard (1757). "General principles of the motion of fluids". Novi. Comm. Acad. Sci. Petrop.: 271–311.
  53. ^ Maxwell, James (1881). A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism (PDF). p. 29.
  54. ^ Arago, François (1874). Laplace: Eulogy. Translated by Powell, Baden. Smithsonian Institution. p. 5. Retrieved 21 March 2018.
  55. ^ a b Owen, T. C. (2001) "Solar system: origin of the solar system", Encyclopædia Britannica, Deluxe CDROM edition
  56. ^ Laplace, P.-S. (1799). Allgemeine geographische Ephemeriden herausgegeben von F. von Zach. IV. Band, I. Stück, I. Abhandlung, Weimar; translation in English: Hawking, Stephen W.; Ellis, George F.R. (1973). The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time. Cambridge University Press. pp. 365ff. ISBN 978-0-521-09906-6.
  57. ^ Colin Montgomery, Wayne Orchiston and Ian Whittingham, "Michell, Laplace and the origin of the Black Hole Concept" 2 May 2014 at the Wayback Machine, Journal of Astronomical History and Heritage, 12(2), 90–96 (2009).
  58. ^ See Israel (1987), sec. 7.2.
  59. ^ Gribbin, 299
  60. ^ a b Fourier (1829).
  61. ^ Crosland (1967), p. 1
  62. ^ a b c d Stigler, 1975
  63. ^ "Laplace, Pierre-Simon Marquis de – Encyclopedia of Mathematics". encyclopediaofmath.org. Retrieved 18 June 2021.
  64. ^ Laplace, Pierre Simon, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities, translated from the 6th French edition by Frederick Wilson Truscott and Frederick Lincoln Emory. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1902, p. 19. Dover Publications edition (New York, 1951) has same pagination.
  65. ^ a b Hawking, Stephen (1999). . Public Lecture. Archived from the original on 8 July 2000.
  66. ^ Laplace, A Philosophical Essay, New York, 1902, p. 4.
  67. ^ van Strien, Marij (2014). "On the origins and foundations of Laplacian determinism". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 45: 24–31. Bibcode:2014SHPSA..45...24V. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2013.12.003. PMID 24984446. Retrieved 5 February 2021.
  68. ^ Cercignani, Carlo (1998). "Chapter 2: Physics before Boltzmann". Ludwig Boltzmann, The Man Who Trusted Atoms. Oxford University Press. p. 55. ISBN 978-0-19-850154-1.
  69. ^ Grattan-Guinness, in Gillispie (1997), p. 260
  70. ^ Crosland (2006), p. 30
  71. ^ a b Grattan-Guinness (2005), p. 333
  72. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 191
  73. ^ Laplace, A Philosophical Essay, New York, 1902, p. 62. (Translation in this paragraph of article is from Hahn.)
  74. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 184
  75. ^ Laplace, A Philosophical Essay, New York, 1902, p. 63. (Translation in this paragraph of article is from Hahn.)
  76. ^ a b Hahn (2005), p. 185
  77. ^ Laplace, A Philosophical Essay, New York, 1902, pp. 107–108. (Translation in this paragraph of article is from Hahn.)
  78. ^ Black, Duncan (1987) [1958]. The Theory of Committees and Elections. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-0-89838-189-4.
  79. ^ Tangian, Andranik (2020). Analytical Theory of Democracy. Vols. 1 and 2. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 132ff. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-39691-6. ISBN 978-3-030-39690-9. S2CID 216190330.
  80. ^ Gillispie (1997), p. 278
  81. ^ p. 282, Mémoires du docteur F. Antommarchi, ou les derniers momens de Napoléon, vol. 1, 1825, Paris: Barrois L'Ainé
  82. ^ a b c Faye, Hervé (1884), Sur l'origine du monde: théories cosmogoniques des anciens et des modernes. Paris: Gauthier-Villars, pp. 109–111
  83. ^ a b c Pasquier, Ernest (1898). "Les hypothèses cosmogoniques (suite)". Revue néo-scholastique, 5o année, No 18, pp. 124–125, footnote 1.
  84. ^ Arago, François (1827), Laplace: Eulogy before the French Academy, translated by Prof. Baden Powell, Smithsonian Report, 1874
  85. ^ Cajori, Florian (1893), A History of Mathematics. Fifth edition (1991), reprinted by the American Mathematical Society, 1999, p. 262. ISBN 0-8218-2102-4
  86. ^ William Herschel's diary of his trip to Paris, as quoted on p. 310 of The Herschel Chronicle, Constance A. Lubbock, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013, ISBN 1-107-65001-1.
  87. ^ Johnson, Daniel (18 June 2007), "The Hypothetical Atheist", Commentary.
  88. ^ Talks of Napoleon at St. Helena with General Baron Gourgaud, translated by Elizabeth Wormely Latimer. Chicago: A.C. McClurg & Co., 1903, p. 276.
  89. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 67.
  90. ^ Dumas, Jean-Baptiste (1885). Discours et éloges académiques, Vol. II. Paris: Gauthier-Villars, p. 255.
  91. ^ a b Kneller, Karl Alois. Christianity and the Leaders of Modern Science: A Contribution to the History of Culture in the Nineteenth Century, translated from the second German edition by T.M. Kettle. London: B. Herder, 1911, pp. 73–74.
  92. ^ Hahn (1981), p. 95.
  93. ^ Œuvres de Laplace. Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1878, Vol. I, pp. v–vi.
  94. ^ Glass, Ian S. (2006). Revolutionaries of the Cosmos: The Astrophysicists. Cambridge University Press, p. 108. ISBN 0-19-857099-6.
  95. ^ General Scholium, from the end of Book III of the Principia; first appeared in the second edition, 1713.
  96. ^ Laplace, Exposition du système du monde, 6th edition. Brussels, 1827, pp. 522–523.
  97. ^ Laplace, Exposition, 1827, p. 523.
  98. ^ Leibniz to Conti, Nov. or Dec. 1715, in H.G. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz–Clarke Correspondence (Manchester University Press, 1956), Appendix B. 1: "Leibniz and Newton to Conti", p. 185 ISBN 0-7190-0669-4; cited in Laplace, Exposition, 1827, p. 524.
  99. ^ Leibniz to Conti, 1715, in Alexander, ed., 1956, p. 185.
  100. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 220.
  101. ^ Hahn (2005), p. 223.
  102. ^ Jacques Attali (2004), Pascal, Warszawa, p. 368
  103. ^ a b Hahn (2005), p. 202.
  104. ^ Hahn (2005), pp. 202, 233.
  105. ^ De Morgan, Augustus (1872). A budget of paradoxes, Longmans, Green, and co, London, p. 3. Compare Edmund Burke's famous remark, occasioned by a parliamentary candidate's sudden death, about "what shadows we are, and what shadows we pursue".
  106. ^ a b Hahn (2005), p. 204.
  107. ^ Roger Hahn (2005). Pierre Simon Laplace, 1749–1827: A Determined Scientist. Harvard University Press. p. 204. ISBN 978-0-674-01892-1. The Catholic newspaper La Quotidienne [The Daily] announced that Laplace had died in the arms of two curés (priests), implying that he had a proper Catholic end, but this is not credible. To the end, he remained a skeptic, wedded to his deterministic creed and to an uncompromised ethos derived from his vast scientific experience.
  108. ^ Roger Hahn (2005). Pierre Simon Laplace, 1749–1827: A Determined Scientist. Harvard University Press. p. 202. ISBN 978-0-674-01892-1. Publicly, Laplace maintained his agnostic beliefs, and even in his old age continued to be skeptical about any function God might play in a deterministic universe.
  109. ^ Morris Kline (1986). Mathematics and the Search for Knowledge. Oxford University Press. p. 214. ISBN 978-0-19-504230-6. Lagrange and Laplace, though of Catholic parentage, were agnostics.
  110. ^ Edward Kasner; James Newman; James Roy Newman (2001). Mathematics and the Imagination. Courier Dover Publications. p. 253. ISBN 978-0-486-41703-5. Modern physics, indeed all of modern science, is as humble as Lagrange, and as agnostic as Laplace.
  111. ^ E. Emerson (1910). Comet Lore. Schilling Press, New York. p. 83.
  112. ^ C.M. Botley (1971). "The Legend of 1P/Halley 1456". The Observatory. 91: 125–126. Bibcode:1971Obs....91..125B.
  113. ^ Hagen, John G. (1910). "Pierre-Simon Laplace" . In Herbermann, Charles (ed.). Catholic Encyclopedia. Vol. 8. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
  114. ^ Stein, John (1911). "Bartolomeo Platina" . In Herbermann, Charles (ed.). Catholic Encyclopedia. Vol. 12. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
  115. ^ Rigge, William F. (04/1910), "An Historical Examination of the Connection of Calixtus III with Halley's Comet", Popular Astronomy, Vol. 18, pp. 214–219
  116. ^ "P.S. de Laplace (1749–1827)". Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 19 July 2015.
  117. ^ "Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter L" (PDF). American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 28 July 2014.
  118. ^ Schmadel, L.D. (2003). Dictionary of Minor Planet Names (5th rev. ed.). Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-540-00238-3.
  119. ^ Laplace, Pierre Simon (1814). "Essai philosophique sur les probabilités". Nature. 110 (2748): 50. Bibcode:1922Natur.110....6B. doi:10.1038/110006b0. S2CID 4099834.
  120. ^ Flournoy, Théodore (1899). Des Indes à la planète Mars: étude sur un cas de somnambulisme avec glossolalie. Slatkine. pp. 344–345. ISBN 978-2-05-100499-2.*Flournoy, Théodore (2007). From India to the Planet Mars: A Study of a Case of Somnambulism. Daniel D. Vermilye, trans. Cosimo, Inc. pp. 369–370. ISBN 978-1-60206-357-0.
  121. ^ Laplace, A Philosophical Essay, New York, 1902, p. 177.
  122. ^ Laplace, The System of the World, Dublin, 1830, p. 91.
  123. ^ Miller, Joshua B; Gelman, Andrew. "Laplace's theories of cognitive illusions, heuristics, and biases∗" (PDF). Columbia University. unpublished. Retrieved 17 January 2021.

General sources

  • Andoyer, H. (1922). "L'œuvre scientifique de Laplace". Paris (in French). Paris Payot. Bibcode:1922osdl.book.....A.
  • Bigourdan, G. (1931). "La jeunesse de P.-S. Laplace". La Science Moderne (in French). 9: 377–384.
  • Crosland, M. (1967). The Society of Arcueil: A View of French Science at the Time of Napoleon I. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-435-54201-6.
  • – (2006) "A Science Empire in Napoleonic France", History of Science, vol. 44, pp. 29–48
  • Dale, A. I. (1982). "Bayes or Laplace? An examination of the origin and early applications of Bayes' theorem". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 27: 23–47. doi:10.1007/BF00348352. S2CID 116147039.
  • David, F. N. (1965) "Some notes on Laplace", in Neyman, J. & LeCam, L. M. (eds) Bernoulli, Bayes and Laplace, Berlin, pp. 30–44.
  • Deakin, M. A. B. (1981). "The development of the Laplace transform". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 25 (4): 343–390. doi:10.1007/BF01395660. S2CID 117913073.
  • Deakin, Michael A. B. (1982). "The development of the Laplace Transform, 1737-1937 II. Poincaré to Doetsch, 1880-1937". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. Springer Science and Business Media LLC. 26 (4): 351–381. doi:10.1007/bf00418754. ISSN 0003-9519. S2CID 123071842.</ref>
  • Dhombres, J. (1989). "La théorie de la capillarité selon Laplace: mathématisation superficielle ou étendue". Revue d'Histoire des Sciences et de Leurs Applications (in French). 62: 43–70. doi:10.3406/rhs.1989.4134.
  • Duveen, D. & Hahn, R. (1957). "Laplace's succession to Bézout's post of Examinateur des élèves de l'artillerie". Isis. 48 (4): 416–427. doi:10.1086/348608. S2CID 143451316.
  • Finn, B. S. (1964). "Laplace and the speed of sound". Isis. 55: 7–19. doi:10.1086/349791. S2CID 20127770.
  • Fourier, J. B. J. (1829). (PDF). Mémoires de l'Académie Royale des Sciences (in French). 10: lxxxi–cii. Archived from the original (PDF) on 24 July 2013., delivered 15 June 1829, published in 1831.
  • Gillispie, C. C. (1972). "Probability and politics: Laplace, Condorcet, and Turgot". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 116 (1): 1–20.
  • Gillispie, Charles (1997). Pierre-Simon Laplace, 1749–1827 : a life in exact science. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-01185-0. OCLC 36656386.
  • Grattan-Guinness, I., 2005, "'Exposition du système du monde' and 'Traité de méchanique céleste'" in his Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics. Elsevier: 242–57.
  • Gribbin, John. The Scientists: A History of Science Told Through the Lives of Its Greatest Inventors. New York, Random House, 2002. p. 299.
  • Hahn, R. (1955). "Laplace's religious views". Archives Internationales d'Histoire des Sciences. 8: 38–40.
  • – (1981) "Laplace and the Vanishing Role of God in the Physical Universe", in Woolf, Henry, ed., The Analytic Spirit: Essays in the History of Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. ISBN 0-8014-1350-8.
  • Hahn, Roger (1982). Calendar of the correspondence of Pierre Simon Laplace. Berkeley: Office for History of Science and Technology, University of California, Berkeley. ISBN 978-0-918102-07-2. OCLC 8877709.
  • Hahn, Roger (1994). The new calendar of the correspondence of Pierre Simon Laplace. Berkeley, CA: Office for History of Science and Technology, University of California at Berkeley. ISBN 978-0-918102-20-1. OCLC 31967034.
  • Hahn, Roger (2005). Pierre Simon Laplace, 1749-1827 : a determined scientist (in Italian). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-01892-1. OCLC 58457459.
  • Israel, Werner (1987). "Dark stars: the evolution of an idea". In Hawking, Stephen W.; Israel, Werner (eds.). 300 Years of Gravitation. Cambridge University Press. pp. 199–276.
  • O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "Pierre-Simon Laplace", MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, University of St Andrews (1999)
  • Nikulin, M. (1992). "A remark on the converse of Laplace's theorem". Journal of Soviet Mathematics. 59 (4): 976–979. doi:10.1007/bf01099128. S2CID 121149198.
  • Rouse Ball, W.W. [1908] (2003) "Pierre Simon Laplace (1749–1827)", in A Short Account of the History of Mathematics, 4th ed., Dover, ISBN 0-486-20630-0 Also available at Project Gutenberg.
  • Stigler, Stephen M. (1975). "Studies in the History of Probability and Statistics. XXXIV Napoleonic Statistics: The Work of Laplace". Biometrika. JSTOR. 62 (2): 503–517. doi:10.2307/2335393. ISSN 0006-3444. JSTOR 2335393.
  • Stigler, Stephen M. (1978). "Laplace's Early Work: Chronology and Citations". Isis. University of Chicago Press. 69 (2): 234–254. Bibcode:1978Isis...69..234S. doi:10.1086/352006. ISSN 0021-1753. S2CID 143831269.
  • Whitrow, G. J. (2001) "Laplace, Pierre-Simon, marquis de", Encyclopædia Britannica, Deluxe CDROM edition
  • Whittaker, E. T. (1949a). "Laplace". Mathematical Gazette. 33 (303): 1–12. doi:10.2307/3608408. JSTOR 3608408. S2CID 250442315.
  • Whittaker, Edmund (1949b). "Laplace". American Mathematical Monthly. 56 (6): 369–372. doi:10.2307/2306273. JSTOR 2306273.
  • Wilson, C. (1985). "The Great Inequality of Jupiter and Saturn: from Kepler to Laplace". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 33 (1–3): 15–290. Bibcode:1985AHES...33...15W. doi:10.1007/BF00328048. S2CID 121751666.
  • Young, T. (1821). Elementary Illustrations of the Celestial Mechanics of Laplace: Part the First, Comprehending the First Book. London, England: John Murray – via Internet Archive. laplace.

External links

  • "Laplace, Pierre (1749–1827)". Eric Weisstein's World of Scientific Biography. Wolfram Research. Retrieved 24 August 2007.
  • "Pierre-Simon Laplace" in the MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
  • "Bowditch's English translation of Laplace's preface". Méchanique Céleste. The MacTutor History of Mathematics archive. Retrieved 4 September 2007.
  • Guide to the Pierre Simon Laplace Papers at The Bancroft Library
  • Pierre-Simon Laplace at the Mathematics Genealogy Project
  • English translation 27 December 2012 at the Wayback Machine of a large part of Laplace's work in probability and statistics, provided by Richard Pulskamp 29 October 2012 at the Wayback Machine
  • (last 7 volumes only) Gallica-Math
  • "Sur le mouvement d'un corps qui tombe d'une grande hauteur" (Laplace 1803), online and analysed on BibNum (English).
Political offices
Preceded by Minister of the Interior
12 November 1799 – 25 December 1799
Succeeded by

pierre, simon, laplace, laplace, redirects, here, other, uses, laplace, disambiguation, pierre, simon, marquis, laplace, ɑː, french, pjɛʁ, simɔ, laplas, march, 1749, march, 1827, french, scholar, polymath, whose, work, important, development, engineering, math. Laplace redirects here For other uses see Laplace disambiguation Pierre Simon Marquis de Laplace l e ˈ p l ɑː s French pjɛʁ simɔ laplas 23 March 1749 5 March 1827 was a French scholar and polymath whose work was important to the development of engineering mathematics statistics physics astronomy and philosophy He summarized and extended the work of his predecessors in his five volume Mecanique celeste Celestial Mechanics 1799 1825 This work translated the geometric study of classical mechanics to one based on calculus opening up a broader range of problems In statistics the Bayesian interpretation of probability was developed mainly by Laplace 2 Pierre Simon LaplacePierre Simon Laplace as chancellor of the Senate under the First French EmpireBorn 1749 03 23 23 March 1749Beaumont en Auge Normandy Kingdom of FranceDied5 March 1827 1827 03 05 aged 77 Paris Kingdom of FranceAlma materUniversity of CaenKnown for Work in celestial mechanicsPredicting the existence of black holes 1 Bayesian inferenceBayesian probabilityLaplace s equationLaplacianLaplace transformInverse Laplace transformLaplace distributionLaplace s demonYoung Laplace equationLaplace numberLaplace limitLaplace invariantLaplace principleLaplace s principle of insufficient reasonLaplace s methodLaplace forceLaplace filterLaplace functionalLaplacian matrixLaplace motionLaplace planeLaplace pressureLaplace resonanceLaplace s spherical harmonicsLaplace smoothingLaplace expansionLaplace expansionLaplace Bayes estimatorLaplace Stieltjes transformLaplace Runge Lenz vectorNebular hypothesisScientific careerFieldsAstronomy and MathematicsInstitutionsEcole Militaire 1769 1776 Academic advisorsJean d AlembertChristophe GadbledPierre Le CanuNotable studentsSimeon Denis PoissonNapoleon BonaparteMinister of the InteriorIn office 12 November 1799 25 December 1799Prime MinisterNapoleon Bonaparte as First Consul Preceded byNicolas Marie QuinetteSucceeded byLucien BonaparteSignatureLaplace formulated Laplace s equation and pioneered the Laplace transform which appears in many branches of mathematical physics a field that he took a leading role in forming The Laplacian differential operator widely used in mathematics is also named after him He restated and developed the nebular hypothesis of the origin of the Solar System and was one of the first scientists to suggest an idea similar to that of a black hole Laplace is regarded as one of the greatest scientists of all time Sometimes referred to as the French Newton or Newton of France he has been described as possessing a phenomenal natural mathematical faculty superior to that of almost all of his contemporaries 3 He was Napoleon s examiner when Napoleon graduated from the Ecole Militaire in Paris in 1785 4 Laplace became a count of the Empire in 1806 and was named a marquis in 1817 after the Bourbon Restoration Contents 1 Early years 2 Analysis probability and astronomical stability 2 1 Stability of the Solar System 3 Tidal dynamics 3 1 Dynamic theory of tides 3 2 Laplace s tidal equations 4 On the figure of the Earth 4 1 Spherical harmonics 4 2 Potential theory 5 Planetary and lunar inequalities 5 1 Jupiter Saturn great inequality 5 2 Books 6 Black holes 7 Arcueil 8 Analytic theory of probabilities 8 1 Inductive probability 8 2 Probability generating function 8 3 Least squares and central limit theorem 9 Laplace s demon 10 Laplace transforms 11 Other discoveries and accomplishments 11 1 Mathematics 11 2 Surface tension 11 3 Speed of sound 12 Politics 12 1 Minister of the Interior 12 2 From Bonaparte to the Bourbons 12 3 Political philosophy 13 Death 14 Religious opinions 14 1 I had no need of that hypothesis 14 2 Views on God 14 3 Excommunication of a comet 15 Honors 16 Quotations 17 List of works 18 Bibliography 18 1 English translations 19 See also 20 References 20 1 Citations 20 2 General sources 21 External linksEarly years Edit Portrait of Pierre Simon Laplace by Johann Ernst Heinsius 1775 Some details of Laplace s life are not known as records of it were burned in 1925 with the family chateau in Saint Julien de Mailloc near Lisieux the home of his great great grandson the Comte de Colbert Laplace Others had been destroyed earlier when his house at Arcueil near Paris was looted in 1871 5 Laplace was born in Beaumont en Auge Normandy on 23 March 1749 a village four miles west of Pont l Eveque According to W W Rouse Ball 6 his father Pierre de Laplace owned and farmed the small estates of Maarquis His great uncle Maitre Oliver de Laplace had held the title of Chirurgien Royal It would seem that from a pupil he became an usher in the school at Beaumont but having procured a letter of introduction to d Alembert he went to Paris to advance his fortune However Karl Pearson 5 is scathing about the inaccuracies in Rouse Ball s account and states Indeed Caen was probably in Laplace s day the most intellectually active of all the towns of Normandy It was here that Laplace was educated and was provisionally a professor It was here he wrote his first paper published in the Melanges of the Royal Society of Turin Tome iv 1766 1769 at least two years before he went at 22 or 23 to Paris in 1771 Thus before he was 20 he was in touch with Lagrange in Turin He did not go to Paris a raw self taught country lad with only a peasant background In 1765 at the age of sixteen Laplace left the School of the Duke of Orleans in Beaumont and went to the University of Caen where he appears to have studied for five years and was a member of the Sphinx The Ecole Militaire of Beaumont did not replace the old school until 1776 His parents Pierre Laplace and Marie Anne Sochon were from comfortable families The Laplace family was involved in agriculture until at least 1750 but Pierre Laplace senior was also a cider merchant and syndic of the town of Beaumont Pierre Simon Laplace attended a school in the village run at a Benedictine priory his father intending that he be ordained in the Roman Catholic Church At sixteen to further his father s intention he was sent to the University of Caen to read theology 7 At the university he was mentored by two enthusiastic teachers of mathematics Christophe Gadbled and Pierre Le Canu who awoke his zeal for the subject Here Laplace s brilliance as a mathematician was quickly recognised and while still at Caen he wrote a memoir Sur le Calcul integral aux differences infiniment petites et aux differences finies This provided the first intercourse between Laplace and Lagrange Lagrange was the senior by thirteen years and had recently founded in his native city Turin a journal named Miscellanea Taurinensia in which many of his early works were printed and it was in the fourth volume of this series that Laplace s paper appeared About this time recognising that he had no vocation for the priesthood he resolved to become a professional mathematician Some sources state that he then broke with the church and became an atheist citation needed Laplace did not graduate in theology but left for Paris with a letter of introduction from Le Canu to Jean le Rond d Alembert who at that time was supreme in scientific circles 7 8 According to his great great grandson 5 d Alembert received him rather poorly and to get rid of him gave him a thick mathematics book saying to come back when he had read it When Laplace came back a few days later d Alembert was even less friendly and did not hide his opinion that it was impossible that Laplace could have read and understood the book But upon questioning him he realised that it was true and from that time he took Laplace under his care Another account is that Laplace solved overnight a problem that d Alembert set him for submission the following week then solved a harder problem the following night D Alembert was impressed and recommended him for a teaching place in the Ecole Militaire 9 With a secure income and undemanding teaching Laplace now threw himself into original research and for the next seventeen years 1771 1787 he produced much of his original work in astronomy 10 The Calorimeter of Lavoisier and La Place Encyclopaedia Londinensis 1801From 1780 to 1784 Laplace and French chemist Antoine Lavoisier collaborated on several experimental investigations designing their own equipment for the task 11 In 1783 they published their joint paper Memoir on Heat in which they discussed the kinetic theory of molecular motion 12 In their experiments they measured the specific heat of various bodies and the expansion of metals with increasing temperature They also measured the boiling points of ethanol and ether under pressure Laplace further impressed the Marquis de Condorcet and already by 1771 Laplace felt entitled to membership in the French Academy of Sciences However that year admission went to Alexandre Theophile Vandermonde and in 1772 to Jacques Antoine Joseph Cousin Laplace was disgruntled and early in 1773 d Alembert wrote to Lagrange in Berlin to ask if a position could be found for Laplace there However Condorcet became permanent secretary of the Academie in February and Laplace was elected associate member on 31 March at age 24 13 In 1773 Laplace read his paper on the invariability of planetary motion in front of the Academy des Sciences That March he was elected to the academy a place where he conducted the majority of his science 14 On 15 March 1788 15 5 at the age of thirty nine Laplace married Marie Charlotte de Courty de Romanges an eighteen year old girl from a good family in Besancon 16 The wedding was celebrated at Saint Sulpice Paris The couple had a son Charles Emile 1789 1874 and a daughter Sophie Suzanne 1792 1813 17 18 Analysis probability and astronomical stability EditLaplace s early published work in 1771 started with differential equations and finite differences but he was already starting to think about the mathematical and philosophical concepts of probability and statistics 19 However before his election to the Academie in 1773 he had already drafted two papers that would establish his reputation The first Memoire sur la probabilite des causes par les evenements was ultimately published in 1774 while the second paper published in 1776 further elaborated his statistical thinking and also began his systematic work on celestial mechanics and the stability of the Solar System The two disciplines would always be interlinked in his mind Laplace took probability as an instrument for repairing defects in knowledge 20 Laplace s work on probability and statistics is discussed below with his mature work on the analytic theory of probabilities Stability of the Solar System Edit Sir Isaac Newton had published his Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica in 1687 in which he gave a derivation of Kepler s laws which describe the motion of the planets from his laws of motion and his law of universal gravitation However though Newton had privately developed the methods of calculus all his published work used cumbersome geometric reasoning unsuitable to account for the more subtle higher order effects of interactions between the planets Newton himself had doubted the possibility of a mathematical solution to the whole even concluding that periodic divine intervention was necessary to guarantee the stability of the Solar System Dispensing with the hypothesis of divine intervention would be a major activity of Laplace s scientific life 21 It is now generally regarded that Laplace s methods on their own though vital to the development of the theory are not sufficiently precise to demonstrate the stability of the Solar System 22 and indeed the Solar System is understood to be chaotic although it happens to be fairly stable One particular problem from observational astronomy was the apparent instability whereby Jupiter s orbit appeared to be shrinking while that of Saturn was expanding The problem had been tackled by Leonhard Euler in 1748 and Joseph Louis Lagrange in 1763 but without success 23 In 1776 Laplace published a memoir in which he first explored the possible influences of a purported luminiferous ether or of a law of gravitation that did not act instantaneously He ultimately returned to an intellectual investment in Newtonian gravity 24 Euler and Lagrange had made a practical approximation by ignoring small terms in the equations of motion Laplace noted that though the terms themselves were small when integrated over time they could become important Laplace carried his analysis into the higher order terms up to and including the cubic Using this more exact analysis Laplace concluded that any two planets and the Sun must be in mutual equilibrium and thereby launched his work on the stability of the Solar System 25 Gerald James Whitrow described the achievement as the most important advance in physical astronomy since Newton 21 Laplace had a wide knowledge of all sciences and dominated all discussions in the Academie 26 Laplace seems to have regarded analysis merely as a means of attacking physical problems though the ability with which he invented the necessary analysis is almost phenomenal As long as his results were true he took but little trouble to explain the steps by which he arrived at them he never studied elegance or symmetry in his processes and it was sufficient for him if he could by any means solve the particular question he was discussing 10 Tidal dynamics EditMain article Theory of tides Dynamic theory of tides Edit While Newton explained the tides by describing the tide generating forces and Bernoulli gave a description of the static reaction of the waters on Earth to the tidal potential the dynamic theory of tides developed by Laplace in 1775 27 describes the ocean s real reaction to tidal forces 28 Laplace s theory of ocean tides took into account friction resonance and natural periods of ocean basins It predicted the large amphidromic systems in the world s ocean basins and explains the oceanic tides that are actually observed 29 30 The equilibrium theory based on the gravitational gradient from the Sun and Moon but ignoring the Earth s rotation the effects of continents and other important effects could not explain the real ocean tides 31 32 33 29 34 35 36 37 38 Newton s three body modelSince measurements have confirmed the theory many things have possible explanations now like how the tides interact with deep sea ridges and chains of seamounts give rise to deep eddies that transport nutrients from the deep to the surface 39 The equilibrium tide theory calculates the height of the tide wave of less than half a meter while the dynamic theory explains why tides are up to 15 meters 40 Satellite observations confirm the accuracy of the dynamic theory and the tides worldwide are now measured to within a few centimeters 41 42 Measurements from the CHAMP satellite closely match the models based on the TOPEX data 43 44 45 Accurate models of tides worldwide are essential for research since the variations due to tides must be removed from measurements when calculating gravity and changes in sea levels 46 Laplace s tidal equations Edit A Lunar gravitational potential this depicts the Moon directly over 30 N or 30 S viewed from above the Northern Hemisphere B This view shows same potential from 180 from view A Viewed from above the Northern Hemisphere Red up blue down In 1776 Laplace formulated a single set of linear partial differential equations for tidal flow described as a barotropic two dimensional sheet flow Coriolis effects are introduced as well as lateral forcing by gravity Laplace obtained these equations by simplifying the fluid dynamic equations But they can also be derived from energy integrals via Lagrange s equation For a fluid sheet of average thickness D the vertical tidal elevation z as well as the horizontal velocity components u and v in the latitude f and longitude l directions respectively satisfy Laplace s tidal equations 47 z t 1 a cos f l u D f v D cos f 0 u t v 2 W sin f 1 a cos f l g z U 0 and v t u 2 W sin f 1 a f g z U 0 displaystyle begin aligned frac partial zeta partial t amp frac 1 a cos varphi left frac partial partial lambda uD frac partial partial varphi left vD cos varphi right right 0 2ex frac partial u partial t amp v left 2 Omega sin varphi right frac 1 a cos varphi frac partial partial lambda left g zeta U right 0 qquad text and 2ex frac partial v partial t amp u left 2 Omega sin varphi right frac 1 a frac partial partial varphi left g zeta U right 0 end aligned where W is the angular frequency of the planet s rotation g is the planet s gravitational acceleration at the mean ocean surface a is the planetary radius and U is the external gravitational tidal forcing potential William Thomson Lord Kelvin rewrote Laplace s momentum terms using the curl to find an equation for vorticity Under certain conditions this can be further rewritten as a conservation of vorticity On the figure of the Earth EditDuring the years 1784 1787 he published some memoirs of exceptional power Prominent among these is one read in 1783 reprinted as Part II of Theorie du Mouvement et de la figure elliptique des planetes in 1784 and in the third volume of the Mecanique celeste In this work Laplace completely determined the attraction of a spheroid on a particle outside it This is memorable for the introduction into analysis of spherical harmonics or Laplace s coefficients and also for the development of the use of what we would now call the gravitational potential in celestial mechanics Spherical harmonics Edit Spherical harmonics In 1783 in a paper sent to the Academie Adrien Marie Legendre had introduced what are now known as associated Legendre functions 10 If two points in a plane have polar coordinates r 8 and r 8 where r r then by elementary manipulation the reciprocal of the distance between the points d can be written as 1 d 1 r 1 2 cos 8 8 r r r r 2 1 2 frac 1 d frac 1 r left 1 2 cos theta theta frac r r left frac r r right 2 right tfrac 1 2 This expression can be expanded in powers of r r using Newton s generalised binomial theorem to give 1 d 1 r k 0 P k 0 cos 8 8 r r k frac 1 d frac 1 r sum k 0 infty P k 0 cos theta theta left frac r r right k The sequence of functions P0k cos f is the set of so called associated Legendre functions and their usefulness arises from the fact that every function of the points on a circle can be expanded as a series of them 10 Laplace with scant regard for credit to Legendre made the non trivial extension of the result to three dimensions to yield a more general set of functions the spherical harmonics or Laplace coefficients The latter term is not in common use now 10 p 340ff Potential theory Edit This paper is also remarkable for the development of the idea of the scalar potential 10 The gravitational force acting on a body is in modern language a vector having magnitude and direction A potential function is a scalar function that defines how the vectors will behave A scalar function is computationally and conceptually easier to deal with than a vector function Alexis Clairaut had first suggested the idea in 1743 while working on a similar problem though he was using Newtonian type geometric reasoning Laplace described Clairaut s work as being in the class of the most beautiful mathematical productions 48 However Rouse Ball alleges that the idea was appropriated from Joseph Louis Lagrange who had used it in his memoirs of 1773 1777 and 1780 10 The term potential itself was due to Daniel Bernoulli who introduced it in his 1738 memoire Hydrodynamica However according to Rouse Ball the term potential function was not actually used to refer to a function V of the coordinates of space in Laplace s sense until George Green s 1828 An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis to the Theories of Electricity and Magnetism 49 50 Laplace applied the language of calculus to the potential function and showed that it always satisfies the differential equation 10 2 V 2 V x 2 2 V y 2 2 V z 2 0 nabla 2 V partial 2 V over partial x 2 partial 2 V over partial y 2 partial 2 V over partial z 2 0 An analogous result for the velocity potential of a fluid had been obtained some years previously by Leonhard Euler 51 52 Laplace s subsequent work on gravitational attraction was based on this result The quantity 2V has been termed the concentration of V and its value at any point indicates the excess of the value of V there over its mean value in the neighbourhood of the point 53 Laplace s equation a special case of Poisson s equation appears ubiquitously in mathematical physics The concept of a potential occurs in fluid dynamics electromagnetism and other areas Rouse Ball speculated that it might be seen as the outward sign of one of the a priori forms in Kant s theory of perception 10 The spherical harmonics turn out to be critical to practical solutions of Laplace s equation Laplace s equation in spherical coordinates such as are used for mapping the sky can be simplified using the method of separation of variables into a radial part depending solely on distance from the centre point and an angular or spherical part The solution to the spherical part of the equation can be expressed as a series of Laplace s spherical harmonics simplifying practical computation Planetary and lunar inequalities Edit Title page of an 1817 copy of Delambre s Tables ecliptiques des satellites de Jupiter which references Laplace s contributions in its title Tables in an 1817 copy of Delambre s Tables ecliptiques des satellites de Jupiter these calculations were influenced by Laplace s previous discoveries Jupiter Saturn great inequality Edit Laplace presented a memoir on planetary inequalities in three sections in 1784 1785 and 1786 This dealt mainly with the identification and explanation of the perturbations now known as the great Jupiter Saturn inequality Laplace solved a longstanding problem in the study and prediction of the movements of these planets He showed by general considerations first that the mutual action of two planets could never cause large changes in the eccentricities and inclinations of their orbits but then even more importantly that peculiarities arose in the Jupiter Saturn system because of the near approach to commensurability of the mean motions of Jupiter and Saturn 3 54 In this context commensurability means that the ratio of the two planets mean motions is very nearly equal to a ratio between a pair of small whole numbers Two periods of Saturn s orbit around the Sun almost equal five of Jupiter s The corresponding difference between multiples of the mean motions 2nJ 5nS corresponds to a period of nearly 900 years and it occurs as a small divisor in the integration of a very small perturbing force with this same period As a result the integrated perturbations with this period are disproportionately large about 0 8 degrees of arc in orbital longitude for Saturn and about 0 3 for Jupiter Further developments of these theorems on planetary motion were given in his two memoirs of 1788 and 1789 but with the aid of Laplace s discoveries the tables of the motions of Jupiter and Saturn could at last be made much more accurate It was on the basis of Laplace s theory that Delambre computed his astronomical tables 10 Books Edit Laplace now set himself the task to write a work which should offer a complete solution of the great mechanical problem presented by the Solar System and bring theory to coincide so closely with observation that empirical equations should no longer find a place in astronomical tables 3 The result is embodied in the Exposition du systeme du monde and the Mecanique celeste 10 The former was published in 1796 and gives a general explanation of the phenomena but omits all details It contains a summary of the history of astronomy This summary procured for its author the honour of admission to the forty of the French Academy and is commonly esteemed one of the masterpieces of French literature though it is not altogether reliable for the later periods of which it treats 10 Laplace developed the nebular hypothesis of the formation of the Solar System first suggested by Emanuel Swedenborg and expanded by Immanuel Kant a hypothesis that continues to dominate accounts of the origin of planetary systems According to Laplace s description of the hypothesis the Solar System had evolved from a globular mass of incandescent gas rotating around an axis through its centre of mass As it cooled this mass contracted and successive rings broke off from its outer edge These rings in their turn cooled and finally condensed into the planets while the Sun represented the central core which was still left On this view Laplace predicted that the more distant planets would be older than those nearer the Sun 10 55 As mentioned the idea of the nebular hypothesis had been outlined by Immanuel Kant in 1755 55 and he had also suggested meteoric aggregations and tidal friction as causes affecting the formation of the Solar System Laplace was probably aware of this but like many writers of his time he generally did not reference the work of others 5 Laplace s analytical discussion of the Solar System is given in his Mecanique celeste published in five volumes The first two volumes published in 1799 contain methods for calculating the motions of the planets determining their figures and resolving tidal problems 3 The third and fourth volumes published in 1802 and 1805 contain applications of these methods and several astronomical tables The fifth volume published in 1825 is mainly historical but it gives as appendices the results of Laplace s latest researches Laplace s own investigations embodied in it are so numerous and valuable that it is regrettable to have to add that many results are appropriated from other writers with scanty or no acknowledgement and the conclusions which have been described as the organised result of a century of patient toil are frequently mentioned as if they were due to Laplace 10 First pages to Exposition du Systeme du Monde 1799 Jean Baptiste Biot who assisted Laplace in revising it for the press says that Laplace himself was frequently unable to recover the details in the chain of reasoning and if satisfied that the conclusions were correct he was content to insert the constantly recurring formula Il est aise a voir que It is easy to see that The Mecanique celeste is not only the translation of Newton s Principia into the language of the differential calculus but it completes parts of which Newton had been unable to fill in the details The work was carried forward in a more finely tuned form in Felix Tisserand s Traite de mecanique celeste 1889 1896 but Laplace s treatise will always remain a standard authority 10 In the years 1784 1787 Laplace produced some memoirs of exceptional power The significant among these was one issued in 1784 and reprinted in the third volume of the Mechanique celeste citation needed In this work he completely determined the attraction of a spheroid on a particle outside it This is known for the introduction into analysis of the potential a useful mathematical concept of broad applicability to the physical sciences Black holes EditLaplace also came close to propounding the concept of the black hole He suggested that there could be massive stars whose gravity is so great that not even light could escape from their surface see escape velocity 56 1 57 58 However this insight was so far ahead of its time that it played no role in the history of scientific development 59 Arcueil Edit Laplace s house at Arcueil to the south of Paris Main article Society of Arcueil In 1806 Laplace bought a house in Arcueil then a village and not yet absorbed into the Paris conurbation The chemist Claude Louis Berthollet was a neighbour their gardens were not separated 60 and the pair formed the nucleus of an informal scientific circle latterly known as the Society of Arcueil Because of their closeness to Napoleon Laplace and Berthollet effectively controlled advancement in the scientific establishment and admission to the more prestigious offices The Society built up a complex pyramid of patronage 61 In 1806 Laplace was also elected a foreign member of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences Analytic theory of probabilities EditIn 1812 Laplace issued his Theorie analytique des probabilites in which he laid down many fundamental results in statistics The first half of this treatise was concerned with probability methods and problems the second half with statistical methods and applications Laplace s proofs are not always rigorous according to the standards of a later day and his perspective slides back and forth between the Bayesian and non Bayesian views with an ease that makes some of his investigations difficult to follow but his conclusions remain basically sound even in those few situations where his analysis goes astray 62 In 1819 he published a popular account of his work on probability This book bears the same relation to the Theorie des probabilites that the Systeme du monde does to the Mechanique celeste 10 In its emphasis on the analytical importance of probabilistic problems especially in the context of the approximation of formula functions of large numbers Laplace s work goes beyond the contemporary view which almost exclusively considered aspects of practical applicability 63 Laplace s Theorie analytique remained the most influential book of mathematical probability theory to the end of the 19th century The general relevance for statistics of Laplacian error theory was appreciated only by the end of the 19th century However it influenced the further development of a largely analytically oriented probability theory Inductive probability Edit In his Essai philosophique sur les probabilites 1814 Laplace set out a mathematical system of inductive reasoning based on probability which we would today recognise as Bayesian He begins the text with a series of principles of probability the first six being Probability is the ratio of the favored events to the total possible events The first principle assumes equal probabilities for all events When this is not true we must first determine the probabilities of each event Then the probability is the sum of the probabilities of all possible favoured events For independent events the probability of the occurrence of all is the probability of each multiplied together For events not independent the probability of event B following event A or event A causing B is the probability of A multiplied by the probability that given A B will occur The probability that A will occur given that B has occurred is the probability of A and B occurring divided by the probability of B Three corollaries are given for the sixth principle which amount to Bayesian probability Where event Ai A1 A2 An exhausts the list of possible causes for event B Pr B Pr A1 A2 An ThenPr A i B Pr A i Pr B A i j Pr A j Pr B A j displaystyle Pr A i mid B Pr A i frac Pr B mid A i sum j Pr A j Pr B mid A j dd dd One well known formula arising from his system is the rule of succession given as principle seven Suppose that some trial has only two possible outcomes labelled success and failure Under the assumption that little or nothing is known a priori about the relative plausibilities of the outcomes Laplace derived a formula for the probability that the next trial will be a success Pr next outcome is success s 1 n 2 Pr text next outcome is success frac s 1 n 2 where s is the number of previously observed successes and n is the total number of observed trials It is still used as an estimator for the probability of an event if we know the event space but have only a small number of samples The rule of succession has been subject to much criticism partly due to the example which Laplace chose to illustrate it He calculated that the probability that the sun will rise tomorrow given that it has never failed to in the past was Pr sun will rise tomorrow d 1 d 2 Pr text sun will rise tomorrow frac d 1 d 2 where d is the number of times the sun has risen in the past This result has been derided as absurd and some authors have concluded that all applications of the Rule of Succession are absurd by extension However Laplace was fully aware of the absurdity of the result immediately following the example he wrote But this number i e the probability that the sun will rise tomorrow is far greater for him who seeing in the totality of phenomena the principle regulating the days and seasons realizes that nothing at the present moment can arrest the course of it 64 Probability generating function Edit The method of estimating the ratio of the number of favourable cases to the whole number of possible cases had been previously indicated by Laplace in a paper written in 1779 It consists of treating the successive values of any function as the coefficients in the expansion of another function with reference to a different variable 3 The latter is therefore called the probability generating function of the former 3 Laplace then shows how by means of interpolation these coefficients may be determined from the generating function Next he attacks the converse problem and from the coefficients he finds the generating function this is effected by the solution of a finite difference equation 10 Least squares and central limit theorem Edit The fourth chapter of this treatise includes an exposition of the method of least squares a remarkable testimony to Laplace s command over the processes of analysis In 1805 Legendre had published the method of least squares making no attempt to tie it to the theory of probability In 1809 Gauss had derived the normal distribution from the principle that the arithmetic mean of observations gives the most probable value for the quantity measured then turning this argument back upon itself he showed that if the errors of observation are normally distributed the least squares estimates give the most probable values for the coefficients in regression situations These two works seem to have spurred Laplace to complete work toward a treatise on probability he had contemplated as early as 1783 62 In two important papers in 1810 and 1811 Laplace first developed the characteristic function as a tool for large sample theory and proved the first general central limit theorem Then in a supplement to his 1810 paper written after he had seen Gauss s work he showed that the central limit theorem provided a Bayesian justification for least squares if one were combining observations each one of which was itself the mean of a large number of independent observations then the least squares estimates would not only maximise the likelihood function considered as a posterior distribution but also minimise the expected posterior error all this without any assumption as to the error distribution or a circular appeal to the principle of the arithmetic mean 62 In 1811 Laplace took a different non Bayesian tack Considering a linear regression problem he restricted his attention to linear unbiased estimators of the linear coefficients After showing that members of this class were approximately normally distributed if the number of observations was large he argued that least squares provided the best linear estimators Here it is best in the sense that it minimised the asymptotic variance and thus both minimised the expected absolute value of the error and maximised the probability that the estimate would lie in any symmetric interval about the unknown coefficient no matter what the error distribution His derivation included the joint limiting distribution of the least squares estimators of two parameters 62 Laplace s demon EditMain article Laplace s demon In 1814 Laplace published what may have been the first scientific articulation of causal determinism 65 We may regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its past and the cause of its future An intellect which at a certain moment would know all forces that set nature in motion and all positions of all items of which nature is composed if this intellect were also vast enough to submit these data to analysis it would embrace in a single formula the movements of the greatest bodies of the universe and those of the tiniest atom for such an intellect nothing would be uncertain and the future just like the past would be the present to it Pierre Simon Laplace A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities 66 This intellect is often referred to as Laplace s demon in the same vein as Maxwell s demon and sometimes Laplace s Superman after Hans Reichenbach Laplace himself did not use the word demon which was a later embellishment As translated into English above he simply referred to Une intelligence Rien ne serait incertain pour elle et l avenir comme le passe serait present a ses yeux Even though Laplace is generally credited with having first formulated the concept of causal determinism in a philosophical context the idea was actually widespread at the time and can be found as early as 1756 in Maupertuis Sur la Divination 67 As well Jesuit scientist Boscovich first proposed a version of scientific determinism very similar to Laplace s in his 1758 book Theoria philosophiae naturalis 68 Laplace transforms EditMain article Laplace transform History As early as 1744 Euler followed by Lagrange had started looking for solutions of differential equations in the form 69 z X x e a x d x and z X x x a d x z int X x e ax dx text and z int X x x a dx The Laplace transform has the form F s f t e s t d t displaystyle F s int f t e st dt This integral operator transforms a function of time t t into a function of a complex variable s s usually interpreted as complex frequency Other discoveries and accomplishments EditMathematics Edit Among the other discoveries of Laplace in pure and applied mathematics are Discussion contemporaneously with Alexandre Theophile Vandermonde of the general theory of determinants 1772 10 Proof that every equation of an odd degree must have at least one real quadratic factor clarification needed 10 Laplace s method for approximating integrals Solution of the linear partial differential equation of the second order 10 He was the first to consider the difficult problems involved in equations of mixed differences and to prove that the solution of an equation in finite differences of the first degree and the second order might always be obtained in the form of a continued fraction 3 10 In his theory of probabilities de Moivre Laplace theorem that approximates binomial distribution with a normal distribution Evaluation of several common definite integrals 10 General proof of the Lagrange reversion theorem 10 Surface tension Edit Main article Young Laplace equation History Laplace built upon the qualitative work of Thomas Young to develop the theory of capillary action and the Young Laplace equation Speed of sound Edit Laplace in 1816 was the first to point out that the speed of sound in air depends on the heat capacity ratio Newton s original theory gave too low a value because it does not take account of the adiabatic compression of the air which results in a local rise in temperature and pressure Laplace s investigations in practical physics were confined to those carried on by him jointly with Lavoisier in the years 1782 to 1784 on the specific heat of various bodies 10 Politics EditMinister of the Interior Edit In his early years Laplace was careful never to become involved in politics or indeed in life outside the Academie des sciences He prudently withdrew from Paris during the most violent part of the Revolution 70 In November 1799 immediately after seizing power in the coup of 18 Brumaire Napoleon appointed Laplace to the post of Minister of the Interior 3 The appointment however lasted only six weeks after which Lucien Bonaparte Napoleon s brother was given the post 3 Evidently once Napoleon s grip on power was secure there was no need for a prestigious but inexperienced scientist in the government 71 Napoleon later in his Memoires de Sainte Helene wrote of Laplace s dismissal as follows 10 Geometrician of the first rank Laplace was not long in showing himself a worse than average administrator from his first actions in office we recognized our mistake Laplace did not consider any question from the right angle he sought subtleties everywhere conceived only problems and finally carried the spirit of infinitesimals into the administration Grattan Guinness however describes these remarks as tendentious since there seems to be no doubt that Laplace was only appointed as a short term figurehead a place holder while Napoleon consolidated power 71 From Bonaparte to the Bourbons Edit Laplace Although Laplace was removed from office it was desirable to retain his allegiance He was accordingly raised to the senate and to the third volume of the Mecanique celeste he prefixed a note that of all the truths therein contained the most precious to the author was the declaration he thus made of his devotion towards the peacemaker of Europe 3 In copies sold after the Bourbon Restoration this was struck out Pearson points out that the censor would not have allowed it anyway In 1814 it was evident that the empire was falling Laplace hastened to tender his services to the Bourbons and in 1817 during the Restoration he was rewarded with the title of marquis According to Rouse Ball the contempt that his more honest colleagues felt for his conduct in the matter may be read in the pages of Paul Louis Courier His knowledge was useful on the numerous scientific commissions on which he served and says Rouse Ball probably accounts for the manner in which his political insincerity was overlooked 10 Roger Hahn in his 2005 biography disputes this portrayal of Laplace as an opportunist and turncoat pointing out that like many in France he had followed the debacle of Napoleon s Russian campaign with serious misgivings The Laplaces whose only daughter Sophie had died in childbirth in September 1813 were in fear for the safety of their son Emile who was on the eastern front with the emperor Napoleon had originally come to power promising stability but it was clear that he had overextended himself putting the nation at peril It was at this point that Laplace s loyalty began to weaken Although he still had easy access to Napoleon his personal relations with the emperor cooled considerably As a grieving father he was particularly cut to the quick by Napoleon s insensitivity in an exchange related by Jean Antoine Chaptal On his return from the rout in Leipzig he Napoleon accosted Mr Laplace Oh I see that you have grown thin Sire I have lost my daughter Oh that s not a reason for losing weight You are a mathematician put this event in an equation and you will find that it adds up to zero 72 Political philosophy Edit In the second edition 1814 of the Essai philosophique Laplace added some revealing comments on politics and governance Since it is he says the practice of the eternal principles of reason justice and humanity that produce and preserve societies there is a great advantage to adhere to these principles and a great inadvisability to deviate from them 73 74 Noting the depths of misery into which peoples have been cast when ambitious leaders disregard these principles Laplace makes a veiled criticism of Napoleon s conduct Every time a great power intoxicated by the love of conquest aspires to universal domination the sense of liberty among the unjustly threatened nations breeds a coalition to which it always succumbs Laplace argues that in the midst of the multiple causes that direct and restrain various states natural limits operate within which it is important for the stability as well as the prosperity of empires to remain States that transgress these limits cannot avoid being reverted to them just as is the case when the waters of the seas whose floor has been lifted by violent tempests sink back to their level by the action of gravity 75 76 About the political upheavals he had witnessed Laplace formulated a set of principles derived from physics to favour evolutionary over revolutionary change Let us apply to the political and moral sciences the method founded upon observation and calculation which has served us so well in the natural sciences Let us not offer fruitless and often injurious resistance to the inevitable benefits derived from the progress of enlightenment but let us change our institutions and the usages that we have for a long time adopted only with extreme caution We know from past experience the drawbacks they can cause but we are unaware of the extent of ills that change may produce In the face of this ignorance the theory of probability instructs us to avoid all change especially to avoid sudden changes which in the moral as well as the physical world never occur without a considerable loss of vital force 77 In these lines Laplace expressed the views he had arrived at after experiencing the Revolution and the Empire He believed that the stability of nature as revealed through scientific findings provided the model that best helped to preserve the human species Such views Hahn comments were also of a piece with his steadfast character 76 In the Essai philosophique Laplace also illustrates the potential of probabilities in political studies by applying the law of large numbers to justify the candidates integer valued ranks used in the Borda method of voting with which the new members of the Academy of Sciences were elected Laplace s verbal argument is so rigorous that it can easily be converted into a formal proof 78 79 Death Edit Tomb of Pierre Simon LaplaceLaplace died in Paris on 5 March 1827 which was the same day Alessandro Volta died His brain was removed by his physician Francois Magendie and kept for many years eventually being displayed in a roving anatomical museum in Britain It was reportedly smaller than the average brain 5 Laplace was buried at Pere Lachaise in Paris but in 1888 his remains were moved to Saint Julien de Mailloc in the canton of Orbec and reinterred on the family estate 80 The tomb is situated on a hill overlooking the village of St Julien de Mailloc Normandy France Religious opinions EditI had no need of that hypothesis Edit See also God of the gaps A frequently cited but potentially apocryphal interaction between Laplace and Napoleon purportedly concerns the existence of God Although the conversation in question did occur the exact words Laplace used and his intended meaning are not known A typical version is provided by Rouse Ball 10 Laplace went in state to Napoleon to present a copy of his work and the following account of the interview is well authenticated and so characteristic of all the parties concerned that I quote it in full Someone had told Napoleon that the book contained no mention of the name of God Napoleon who was fond of putting embarrassing questions received it with the remark M Laplace they tell me you have written this large book on the system of the universe and have never even mentioned its Creator Laplace who though the most supple of politicians was as stiff as a martyr on every point of his philosophy drew himself up and answered bluntly Je n avais pas besoin de cette hypothese la I had no need of that hypothesis Napoleon greatly amused told this reply to Lagrange who exclaimed Ah c est une belle hypothese ca explique beaucoup de choses Ah it is a fine hypothesis it explains many things An earlier report although without the mention of Laplace s name is found in Antommarchi s The Last Moments of Napoleon 1825 81 Je m entretenais avec L je le felicitais d un ouvrage qu il venait de publier et lui demandais comment le nom de Dieu qui se reproduisait sans cesse sous la plume de Lagrange ne s etait pas presente une seule fois sous la sienne C est me repondit il que je n ai pas eu besoin de cette hypothese While speaking with L I congratulated him on a work which he had just published and asked him how the name of God which appeared endlessly in the works of Lagrange didn t occur even once in his He replied that he had no need of that hypothesis In 1884 however the astronomer Herve Faye 82 83 affirmed that this account of Laplace s exchange with Napoleon presented a strangely transformed etrangement transformee or garbled version of what had actually happened It was not God that Laplace had treated as a hypothesis but merely his intervention at a determinate point In fact Laplace never said that Here I believe is what truly happened Newton believing that the secular perturbations which he had sketched out in his theory would in the long run end up destroying the Solar System says somewhere that God was obliged to intervene from time to time to remedy the evil and somehow keep the system working properly This however was a pure supposition suggested to Newton by an incomplete view of the conditions of the stability of our little world Science was not yet advanced enough at that time to bring these conditions into full view But Laplace who had discovered them by a deep analysis would have replied to the First Consul that Newton had wrongly invoked the intervention of God to adjust from time to time the machine of the world la machine du monde and that he Laplace had no need of such an assumption It was not God therefore that Laplace treated as a hypothesis but his intervention in a certain place Laplace s younger colleague the astronomer Francois Arago who gave his eulogy before the French Academy in 1827 84 told Faye of an attempt by Laplace to keep the garbled version of his interaction with Napoleon out of circulation Faye writes 82 83 I have it on the authority of M Arago that Laplace warned shortly before his death that that anecdote was about to be published in a biographical collection had requested him Arago to demand its deletion by the publisher It was necessary to either explain or delete it and the second way was the easiest But unfortunately it was neither deleted nor explained The Swiss American historian of mathematics Florian Cajori appears to have been unaware of Faye s research but in 1893 he came to a similar conclusion 85 Stephen Hawking said in 1999 65 I don t think that Laplace was claiming that God does not exist It s just that he doesn t intervene to break the laws of Science The only eyewitness account of Laplace s interaction with Napoleon is from the entry for 8 August 1802 in the diary of the British astronomer Sir William Herschel 86 The first Consul then asked a few questions relating to Astronomy and the construction of the heavens to which I made such answers as seemed to give him great satisfaction He also addressed himself to Mr Laplace on the same subject and held a considerable argument with him in which he differed from that eminent mathematician The difference was occasioned by an exclamation of the first Consul who asked in a tone of exclamation or admiration when we were speaking of the extent of the sidereal heavens And who is the author of all this Mons De la Place wished to shew that a chain of natural causes would account for the construction and preservation of the wonderful system This the first Consul rather opposed Much may be said on the subject by joining the arguments of both we shall be led to Nature and nature s God Since this makes no mention of Laplace s saying I had no need of that hypothesis Daniel Johnson 87 argues that Laplace never used the words attributed to him Arago s testimony however appears to imply that he did only not in reference to the existence of God Views on God Edit Raised a Catholic Laplace appears in adult life to have inclined to deism presumably his considered position since it is the only one found in his writings However some of his contemporaries thought he was an atheist while a number of recent scholars have described him as agnostic Faye thought that Laplace did not profess atheism 82 but Napoleon on Saint Helena told General Gaspard Gourgaud I often asked Laplace what he thought of God He owned that he was an atheist 88 Roger Hahn in his biography of Laplace mentions a dinner party at which the geologist Jean Etienne Guettard was staggered by Laplace s bold denunciation of the existence of God It appeared to Guettard that Laplace s atheism was supported by a thoroughgoing materialism 89 But the chemist Jean Baptiste Dumas who knew Laplace well in the 1820s wrote that Laplace provided materialists with their specious arguments without sharing their convictions 90 91 Hahn states Nowhere in his writings either public or private does Laplace deny God s existence 92 Expressions occur in his private letters that appear inconsistent with atheism 3 On 17 June 1809 for instance he wrote to his son Je prie Dieu qu il veille sur tes jours Aie Le toujours present a ta pensee ainsi que ton pere et ta mere I pray that God watches over your days Let Him be always present to your mind as also your father and your mother 83 93 Ian S Glass quoting Herschel s account of the celebrated exchange with Napoleon writes that Laplace was evidently a deist like Herschel 94 In Exposition du systeme du monde Laplace quotes Newton s assertion that the wondrous disposition of the Sun the planets and the comets can only be the work of an all powerful and intelligent Being 95 This says Laplace is a thought in which he Newton would be even more confirmed if he had known what we have shown namely that the conditions of the arrangement of the planets and their satellites are precisely those which ensure its stability 96 By showing that the remarkable arrangement of the planets could be entirely explained by the laws of motion Laplace had eliminated the need for the supreme intelligence to intervene as Newton had made it do 97 Laplace cites with approval Leibniz s criticism of Newton s invocation of divine intervention to restore order to the Solar System This is to have very narrow ideas about the wisdom and the power of God 98 He evidently shared Leibniz s astonishment at Newton s belief that God has made his machine so badly that unless he affects it by some extraordinary means the watch will very soon cease to go 99 In a group of manuscripts preserved in relative secrecy in a black envelope in the library of the Academie des sciences and published for the first time by Hahn Laplace mounted a deist critique of Christianity It is he writes the first and most infallible of principles to reject miraculous facts as untrue 100 As for the doctrine of transubstantiation it offends at the same time reason experience the testimony of all our senses the eternal laws of nature and the sublime ideas that we ought to form of the Supreme Being It is the sheerest absurdity to suppose that the sovereign lawgiver of the universe would suspend the laws that he has established and which he seems to have maintained invariably 101 Laplace also ridiculed the use of probability in theology Even following Pascal s reasoning presented in Pascal s wager it is not worth making a bet for the hope of profit equal to the product of the value of the testimonies infinitely small and the value of the happiness they promise which is significant but finite must necessarily be infinitely small 102 In old age Laplace remained curious about the question of God 103 and frequently discussed Christianity with the Swiss astronomer Jean Frederic Theodore Maurice 104 He told Maurice that Christianity is quite a beautiful thing and praised its civilising influence Maurice thought that the basis of Laplace s beliefs was little by little being modified but that he held fast to his conviction that the invariability of the laws of nature did not permit of supernatural events 103 After Laplace s death Poisson told Maurice You know that I do not share your religious opinions but my conscience forces me to recount something that will surely please you When Poisson had complimented Laplace about his brilliant discoveries the dying man had fixed him with a pensive look and replied Ah We chase after phantoms chimeres 105 These were his last words interpreted by Maurice as a realisation of the ultimate vanity of earthly pursuits 106 Laplace received the last rites from the cure of the Missions Etrangeres in whose parish he was to be buried 91 and the cure of Arcueil 106 According to his biographer Roger Hahn it is not credible that Laplace had a proper Catholic end and he remained a skeptic to the very end of his life 107 Laplace in his last years has been described as an agnostic 108 109 110 Excommunication of a comet Edit In 1470 the humanist scholar Bartolomeo Platina wrote 111 that Pope Callixtus III had asked for prayers for deliverance from the Turks during a 1456 appearance of Halley s Comet Platina s account does not accord with Church records which do not mention the comet Laplace is alleged to have embellished the story by claiming the Pope had excommunicated Halley s comet 112 What Laplace actually said in Exposition du systeme du monde 1796 was that the Pope had ordered the comet to be exorcised conjure It was Arago in Des Cometes en general 1832 who first spoke of an excommunication 113 114 115 Honors EditCorrespondent of the Royal Institute of the Netherlands in 1809 116 Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1822 117 The asteroid 4628 Laplace is named for Laplace 118 A spur of the Montes Jura on the Moon is known as Promontorium Laplace His name is one of the 72 names inscribed on the Eiffel Tower The tentative working name of the European Space Agency Europa Jupiter System Mission is the Laplace space probe A train station in the RER B in Arcueil bears his name A street in Verkhnetemernitsky near Rostov on Don Russia Quotations EditI had no need of that hypothesis Je n avais pas besoin de cette hypothese la allegedly as a reply to Napoleon who had asked why he hadn t mentioned God in his book on astronomy 10 It is therefore obvious that Frequently used in the Celestial Mechanics when he had proved something and mislaid the proof or found it clumsy Notorious as a signal for something true but hard to prove We are so far from knowing all the agents of nature and their diverse modes of action that it would not be philosophical to deny phenomena solely because they are inexplicable in the actual state of our knowledge But we ought to examine them with an attention all the more scrupulous as it appears more difficult to admit them 119 This is restated in Theodore Flournoy s work From India to the Planet Mars as the Principle of Laplace or The weight of the evidence should be proportioned to the strangeness of the facts 120 Most often repeated as The weight of evidence for an extraordinary claim must be proportioned to its strangeness see also Sagan standard This simplicity of ratios will not appear astonishing if we consider that all the effects of nature are only mathematical results of a small number of immutable laws 121 Infinitely varied in her effects nature is only simple in her causes 122 What we know is little and what we are ignorant of is immense Fourier comments This was at least the meaning of his last words which were articulated with difficulty 60 One sees in this essay that the theory of probabilities is basically only common sense reduced to a calculus It makes one estimate accurately what right minded people feel by a sort of instinct often without being able to give a reason for it 123 List of works EditTraite de mecanique celeste in French Vol 1 Paris Charles Crapelet 1799 Traite de mecanique celeste in French Vol 2 Paris Charles Crapelet 1799 Traite de mecanique celeste in French Vol 3 Paris Charles Crapelet 1802 Traite de mecanique celeste in French Vol 4 Paris Charles Crapelet 1805 Traite de mecanique celeste in French Vol 5 Paris Charles Louis Etienne Bachelier 1852 Precis de l histoire de l astronomie in Italian Milano Angelo Stanislao Brambilla 1823 Exposition du systeme du monde in French Paris Charles Louis Etienne Bachelier 1824 Volumes 1 5 of Pierre Simon Laplace s Traite de mecanique celeste 1799 Title page to Volume I of Traite de mecanique celeste 1799 Table of contents to Volume I of Traite de mecanique celeste 1799 First page of Volume I of Traite de mecanique celeste 1799 Bibliography EditŒuvres completes de Laplace 14 vol 1878 1912 Paris Gauthier Villars copy from Gallica in French Theorie du movement et de la figure elliptique des planetes 1784 Paris not in Œuvres completes Precis de l histoire de l astronomie Alphonse Rebiere Mathematiques et mathematiciens 3rd edition Paris Nony amp Cie 1898 English translations Edit Volumes 1 and 2 of System of the World 1809 Bowditch N trans 1829 1839 Mecanique celeste 4 vols Boston New edition by Reprint Services ISBN 0 7812 2022 X 1829 1839 1966 1969 Celestial Mechanics 5 vols including the original French Pound J trans 1809 The System of the World 2 vols London Richard Phillips The System of the World v 1 The System of the World v 2 1809 2007 The System of the World vol 1 Kessinger ISBN 1 4326 5367 9 Toplis J trans 1814 A treatise upon analytical mechanics Nottingham H Barnett Laplace Pierre Simon Marquis De 2007 1902 A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities Translated by Truscott F W amp Emory F L ISBN 978 1 60206 328 0 translated from the French 6th ed 1840 A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities 1902 at the Internet Archive Dale Andrew I Laplace Pierre Simon 1995 Philosophical Essay on Probabilities Sources in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Vol 13 Translated by Andrew I Dale Springer doi 10 1007 978 1 4612 4184 3 hdl 2027 coo1 ark 13960 t3126f008 ISBN 978 1 4612 8689 9 translated from the French 5th ed 1825 See also EditHistory of the metre Laplace Bayes estimator Ratio estimator Seconds pendulum List of things named after Pierre Simon Laplace Pascal s wagerReferences EditCitations Edit a b S W Hawking and George F R Ellis The Large Scale Structure of Space Time Cambridge University Press 1973 p 364 Stigler Stephen M 1986 The History of Statistics The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900 Harvard University Press Chapter 3 a b c d e f g h i j k Clerke Agnes Mary 1911 Laplace Pierre Simon Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 16 11th ed pp 200 202 Hankins Thomas L 2006 Pierre Simon Laplace 1749 1827 A Determined Scientist Book review Physics Today 59 9 62 64 doi 10 1063 1 2364251 a b c d e f Laplace being Extracts from Lectures delivered by Karl Pearson Biometrika vol 21 December 1929 pp 202 216 W W Rouse Ball A Short Account of the History of Mathematics 4th edition 1908 a b O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F Pierre Simon Laplace MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews Retrieved 25 August 2007 Edmund Whittaker Vol 33 No 303 Feb 1949 pp 1 12 Laplace The Mathematical Gazette Gillispie 1997 pp 3 4 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab Rouse Ball 1908 The Chemical Revolution of Antoine Laurent Lavoisier International Historic Chemical Landmark American Chemical Society 8 June 1999 Golinski Jan V June 1983 Antoine Laurent Lavoisier Pierre Simon Marquis de Laplace Henry Guerlac Isis 74 2 288 289 doi 10 1086 353288 Gillispie 1997 p 5 Effects of the Scientific Community on Laplace Retrieved on 10 January 2018 Hahn 2005 p 99 However Gillispie 1997 p 67 gives the month of the marriage as May Hahn 2005 pp 99 100 Gillispie 1997 p 67 Hahn 2005 p 101 Gillispie 1989 pp 7 12 Gillispie 1989 pp 14 15 a b Whitrow 2001 Celletti A amp Perozzi E 2007 Celestial Mechanics The Waltz of the Planets Celestial Mechanics the Waltz of the Planets Berlin Springer pp 91 93 Bibcode 2006cmwp book C ISBN 978 0 387 30777 0 Whittaker 1949b Gillispie 1989 pp 29 35 Gillispie 1989 pp 35 36 School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Short notes on the Dynamical theory of Laplace 20 November 2011 Hautala Susan Kelly Kathryn Thompson LuAnne 2005 Tide Dynamics PDF a b Higher Education PDF Ahn Kyungjin September 2009 An Astronomer s View on the Current College Level Textbook Descriptions of Tides PDF Korean Earth Science Society Tidal theory Archived 22 August 2017 at the Wayback Machine website South African Navy Hydrographic Office Dynamic theory for tides Oberlin edu Retrieved 2 June 2012 Dynamic Theory of Tides Dynamic Tides In contrast to static theory the dynamic theory of tides recognizes that water covers only three quarters o Web vims edu Archived from the original on 13 January 2013 Retrieved 2 June 2012 The Dynamic Theory of Tides Coa edu Archived from the original on 19 December 2013 Retrieved 2 June 2012 Welcome to nginx beacon salemstate edu Archived from the original on 14 December 2012 Retrieved 3 February 2022 Tides building river sea depth oceans effects important largest system wave effect marine Pacific Waterencyclopedia com 27 June 2010 TIDES Ocean tamu edu Archived from the original on 16 June 2013 Retrieved 2 June 2012 Floor Anthoni Tides Seafriends org nz Retrieved 2 June 2012 The Cause amp Nature of Tides Scientific Visualization Studio TOPEX Poseidon images Svs gsfc nasa gov Retrieved 2 June 2012 TOPEX Poseidon Western Hemisphere Tide Height Model NASA Goddard Space Flight Center Scientific Visualization Studio Free Download amp Streaming Internet Archive 15 June 2000 TOPEX data used to model actual tides for 15 days from the year 2000 TOPEX Poseidon Flat Earth Tide Height Model http www geomag us info Ocean m2 CHAMP longwave SSH swf bare URL OSU Tidal Data Inversion Volkov oce orst edu Archived from the original on 22 October 2012 Retrieved 2 June 2012 Dynamic and residual ocean tide analysis for improved GRACE de aliasing DAROTA Archived from the original on 2 April 2015 The Laplace Tidal Equations and Atmospheric Tides PDF Archived from the original PDF on 11 April 2019 Retrieved 28 October 2017 Grattan Guinness I 2003 Companion Encyclopedia of the History and Philosophy of the Mathematical Sciences Baltimore Johns Hopkins University Press pp 1097 1098 ISBN 978 0 8018 7396 6 W W Rouse Ball A Short Account of the History of Mathematics 4th edition 1908 Green G 1828 An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis to the Theories of Electricity and Magnetism Nottingham arXiv 0807 0088 Bibcode 2008arXiv0807 0088G Kline Morris 1972 Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times Vol 2 Oxford University Press pp 524 525 ISBN 978 0 19 506136 9 Euler Leonhard 1757 General principles of the motion of fluids Novi Comm Acad Sci Petrop 271 311 Maxwell James 1881 A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism PDF p 29 Arago Francois 1874 Laplace Eulogy Translated by Powell Baden Smithsonian Institution p 5 Retrieved 21 March 2018 a b Owen T C 2001 Solar system origin of the solar system Encyclopaedia Britannica Deluxe CDROM edition Laplace P S 1799 Allgemeine geographische Ephemeriden herausgegeben von F von Zach IV Band I Stuck I Abhandlung Weimar translation in English Hawking Stephen W Ellis George F R 1973 The Large Scale Structure of Space Time Cambridge University Press pp 365ff ISBN 978 0 521 09906 6 Colin Montgomery Wayne Orchiston and Ian Whittingham Michell Laplace and the origin of the Black Hole Concept Archived 2 May 2014 at the Wayback Machine Journal of Astronomical History and Heritage 12 2 90 96 2009 See Israel 1987 sec 7 2 Gribbin 299 a b Fourier 1829 Crosland 1967 p 1 a b c d Stigler 1975 Laplace Pierre Simon Marquis de Encyclopedia of Mathematics encyclopediaofmath org Retrieved 18 June 2021 Laplace Pierre Simon A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities translated from the 6th French edition by Frederick Wilson Truscott and Frederick Lincoln Emory New York John Wiley amp Sons 1902 p 19 Dover Publications edition New York 1951 has same pagination a b Hawking Stephen 1999 Does God Play Dice Public Lecture Archived from the original on 8 July 2000 Laplace A Philosophical Essay New York 1902 p 4 van Strien Marij 2014 On the origins and foundations of Laplacian determinism Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 45 24 31 Bibcode 2014SHPSA 45 24V doi 10 1016 j shpsa 2013 12 003 PMID 24984446 Retrieved 5 February 2021 Cercignani Carlo 1998 Chapter 2 Physics before Boltzmann Ludwig Boltzmann The Man Who Trusted Atoms Oxford University Press p 55 ISBN 978 0 19 850154 1 Grattan Guinness in Gillispie 1997 p 260 Crosland 2006 p 30 a b Grattan Guinness 2005 p 333 Hahn 2005 p 191 Laplace A Philosophical Essay New York 1902 p 62 Translation in this paragraph of article is from Hahn Hahn 2005 p 184 Laplace A Philosophical Essay New York 1902 p 63 Translation in this paragraph of article is from Hahn a b Hahn 2005 p 185 Laplace A Philosophical Essay New York 1902 pp 107 108 Translation in this paragraph of article is from Hahn Black Duncan 1987 1958 The Theory of Committees and Elections Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 0 89838 189 4 Tangian Andranik 2020 Analytical Theory of Democracy Vols 1 and 2 Studies in Choice and Welfare Cham Switzerland Springer pp 132ff doi 10 1007 978 3 030 39691 6 ISBN 978 3 030 39690 9 S2CID 216190330 Gillispie 1997 p 278 p 282 Memoires du docteur F Antommarchi ou les derniers momens de Napoleon vol 1 1825 Paris Barrois L Aine a b c Faye Herve 1884 Sur l origine du monde theories cosmogoniques des anciens et des modernes Paris Gauthier Villars pp 109 111 a b c Pasquier Ernest 1898 Les hypotheses cosmogoniques suite Revue neo scholastique 5o annee No 18 pp 124 125 footnote 1 Arago Francois 1827 Laplace Eulogy before the French Academy translated by Prof Baden Powell Smithsonian Report 1874 Cajori Florian 1893 A History of Mathematics Fifth edition 1991 reprinted by the American Mathematical Society 1999 p 262 ISBN 0 8218 2102 4 William Herschel s diary of his trip to Paris as quoted on p 310 of The Herschel Chronicle Constance A Lubbock Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2013 ISBN 1 107 65001 1 Johnson Daniel 18 June 2007 The Hypothetical Atheist Commentary Talks of Napoleon at St Helena with General Baron Gourgaud translated by Elizabeth Wormely Latimer Chicago A C McClurg amp Co 1903 p 276 Hahn 2005 p 67 Dumas Jean Baptiste 1885 Discours et eloges academiques Vol II Paris Gauthier Villars p 255 a b Kneller Karl Alois Christianity and the Leaders of Modern Science A Contribution to the History of Culture in the Nineteenth Century translated from the second German edition by T M Kettle London B Herder 1911 pp 73 74 Hahn 1981 p 95 Œuvres de Laplace Paris Gauthier Villars 1878 Vol I pp v vi Glass Ian S 2006 Revolutionaries of the Cosmos The Astrophysicists Cambridge University Press p 108 ISBN 0 19 857099 6 General Scholium from the end of Book III of the Principia first appeared in the second edition 1713 Laplace Exposition du systeme du monde 6th edition Brussels 1827 pp 522 523 Laplace Exposition 1827 p 523 Leibniz to Conti Nov or Dec 1715 in H G Alexander ed The Leibniz Clarke Correspondence Manchester University Press 1956 Appendix B 1 Leibniz and Newton to Conti p 185 ISBN 0 7190 0669 4 cited in Laplace Exposition 1827 p 524 Leibniz to Conti 1715 in Alexander ed 1956 p 185 Hahn 2005 p 220 Hahn 2005 p 223 Jacques Attali 2004 Pascal Warszawa p 368 a b Hahn 2005 p 202 Hahn 2005 pp 202 233 De Morgan Augustus 1872 A budget of paradoxes Longmans Green and co London p 3 Compare Edmund Burke s famous remark occasioned by a parliamentary candidate s sudden death about what shadows we are and what shadows we pursue a b Hahn 2005 p 204 Roger Hahn 2005 Pierre Simon Laplace 1749 1827 A Determined Scientist Harvard University Press p 204 ISBN 978 0 674 01892 1 The Catholic newspaper La Quotidienne The Daily announced that Laplace had died in the arms of two cures priests implying that he had a proper Catholic end but this is not credible To the end he remained a skeptic wedded to his deterministic creed and to an uncompromised ethos derived from his vast scientific experience Roger Hahn 2005 Pierre Simon Laplace 1749 1827 A Determined Scientist Harvard University Press p 202 ISBN 978 0 674 01892 1 Publicly Laplace maintained his agnostic beliefs and even in his old age continued to be skeptical about any function God might play in a deterministic universe Morris Kline 1986 Mathematics and the Search for Knowledge Oxford University Press p 214 ISBN 978 0 19 504230 6 Lagrange and Laplace though of Catholic parentage were agnostics Edward Kasner James Newman James Roy Newman 2001 Mathematics and the Imagination Courier Dover Publications p 253 ISBN 978 0 486 41703 5 Modern physics indeed all of modern science is as humble as Lagrange and as agnostic as Laplace E Emerson 1910 Comet Lore Schilling Press New York p 83 C M Botley 1971 The Legend of 1P Halley 1456 The Observatory 91 125 126 Bibcode 1971Obs 91 125B Hagen John G 1910 Pierre Simon Laplace In Herbermann Charles ed Catholic Encyclopedia Vol 8 New York Robert Appleton Company Stein John 1911 Bartolomeo Platina In Herbermann Charles ed Catholic Encyclopedia Vol 12 New York Robert Appleton Company Rigge William F 04 1910 An Historical Examination of the Connection of Calixtus III with Halley s Comet Popular Astronomy Vol 18 pp 214 219 P S de Laplace 1749 1827 Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences Retrieved 19 July 2015 Book of Members 1780 2010 Chapter L PDF American Academy of Arts and Sciences Retrieved 28 July 2014 Schmadel L D 2003 Dictionary of Minor Planet Names 5th rev ed Berlin Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 540 00238 3 Laplace Pierre Simon 1814 Essai philosophique sur les probabilites Nature 110 2748 50 Bibcode 1922Natur 110 6B doi 10 1038 110006b0 S2CID 4099834 Flournoy Theodore 1899 Des Indes a la planete Mars etude sur un cas de somnambulisme avec glossolalie Slatkine pp 344 345 ISBN 978 2 05 100499 2 Flournoy Theodore 2007 From India to the Planet Mars A Study of a Case of Somnambulism Daniel D Vermilye trans Cosimo Inc pp 369 370 ISBN 978 1 60206 357 0 Laplace A Philosophical Essay New York 1902 p 177 Laplace The System of the World Dublin 1830 p 91 Miller Joshua B Gelman Andrew Laplace s theories of cognitive illusions heuristics and biases PDF Columbia University unpublished Retrieved 17 January 2021 General sources Edit Andoyer H 1922 L œuvre scientifique de Laplace Paris in French Paris Payot Bibcode 1922osdl book A Bigourdan G 1931 La jeunesse de P S Laplace La Science Moderne in French 9 377 384 Crosland M 1967 The Society of Arcueil A View of French Science at the Time of Napoleon I Cambridge MA Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 435 54201 6 2006 A Science Empire in Napoleonic France History of Science vol 44 pp 29 48 Dale A I 1982 Bayes or Laplace An examination of the origin and early applications of Bayes theorem Archive for History of Exact Sciences 27 23 47 doi 10 1007 BF00348352 S2CID 116147039 David F N 1965 Some notes on Laplace in Neyman J amp LeCam L M eds Bernoulli Bayes and Laplace Berlin pp 30 44 Deakin M A B 1981 The development of the Laplace transform Archive for History of Exact Sciences 25 4 343 390 doi 10 1007 BF01395660 S2CID 117913073 Deakin Michael A B 1982 The development of the Laplace Transform 1737 1937 II Poincare to Doetsch 1880 1937 Archive for History of Exact Sciences Springer Science and Business Media LLC 26 4 351 381 doi 10 1007 bf00418754 ISSN 0003 9519 S2CID 123071842 lt ref gt Dhombres J 1989 La theorie de la capillarite selon Laplace mathematisation superficielle ou etendue Revue d Histoire des Sciences et de Leurs Applications in French 62 43 70 doi 10 3406 rhs 1989 4134 Duveen D amp Hahn R 1957 Laplace s succession to Bezout s post of Examinateur des eleves de l artillerie Isis 48 4 416 427 doi 10 1086 348608 S2CID 143451316 Finn B S 1964 Laplace and the speed of sound Isis 55 7 19 doi 10 1086 349791 S2CID 20127770 Fourier J B J 1829 Eloge historique de M le Marquis de Laplace PDF Memoires de l Academie Royale des Sciences in French 10 lxxxi cii Archived from the original PDF on 24 July 2013 delivered 15 June 1829 published in 1831 Gillispie C C 1972 Probability and politics Laplace Condorcet and Turgot Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 116 1 1 20 Gillispie Charles 1997 Pierre Simon Laplace 1749 1827 a life in exact science Princeton N J Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 01185 0 OCLC 36656386 Grattan Guinness I 2005 Exposition du systeme du monde and Traite de mechanique celeste in his Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics Elsevier 242 57 Gribbin John The Scientists A History of Science Told Through the Lives of Its Greatest Inventors New York Random House 2002 p 299 Hahn R 1955 Laplace s religious views Archives Internationales d Histoire des Sciences 8 38 40 1981 Laplace and the Vanishing Role of God in the Physical Universe in Woolf Henry ed The Analytic Spirit Essays in the History of Science Ithaca NY Cornell University Press ISBN 0 8014 1350 8 Hahn Roger 1982 Calendar of the correspondence of Pierre Simon Laplace Berkeley Office for History of Science and Technology University of California Berkeley ISBN 978 0 918102 07 2 OCLC 8877709 Hahn Roger 1994 The new calendar of the correspondence of Pierre Simon Laplace Berkeley CA Office for History of Science and Technology University of California at Berkeley ISBN 978 0 918102 20 1 OCLC 31967034 Hahn Roger 2005 Pierre Simon Laplace 1749 1827 a determined scientist in Italian Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 01892 1 OCLC 58457459 Israel Werner 1987 Dark stars the evolution of an idea In Hawking Stephen W Israel Werner eds 300 Years of Gravitation Cambridge University Press pp 199 276 O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F Pierre Simon Laplace MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews 1999 Nikulin M 1992 A remark on the converse of Laplace s theorem Journal of Soviet Mathematics 59 4 976 979 doi 10 1007 bf01099128 S2CID 121149198 Rouse Ball W W 1908 2003 Pierre Simon Laplace 1749 1827 in A Short Account of the History of Mathematics 4th ed Dover ISBN 0 486 20630 0 Also available at Project Gutenberg Stigler Stephen M 1975 Studies in the History of Probability and Statistics XXXIV Napoleonic Statistics The Work of Laplace Biometrika JSTOR 62 2 503 517 doi 10 2307 2335393 ISSN 0006 3444 JSTOR 2335393 Stigler Stephen M 1978 Laplace s Early Work Chronology and Citations Isis University of Chicago Press 69 2 234 254 Bibcode 1978Isis 69 234S doi 10 1086 352006 ISSN 0021 1753 S2CID 143831269 Whitrow G J 2001 Laplace Pierre Simon marquis de Encyclopaedia Britannica Deluxe CDROM edition Whittaker E T 1949a Laplace Mathematical Gazette 33 303 1 12 doi 10 2307 3608408 JSTOR 3608408 S2CID 250442315 Whittaker Edmund 1949b Laplace American Mathematical Monthly 56 6 369 372 doi 10 2307 2306273 JSTOR 2306273 Wilson C 1985 The Great Inequality of Jupiter and Saturn from Kepler to Laplace Archive for History of Exact Sciences 33 1 3 15 290 Bibcode 1985AHES 33 15W doi 10 1007 BF00328048 S2CID 121751666 Young T 1821 Elementary Illustrations of the Celestial Mechanics of Laplace Part the First Comprehending the First Book London England John Murray via Internet Archive laplace External links Edit Wikimedia Commons has media related to Pierre Simon Laplace Wikiquote has quotations related to Pierre Simon Laplace Wikisource has original works by or about Pierre Simon Laplace Laplace Pierre 1749 1827 Eric Weisstein s World of Scientific Biography Wolfram Research Retrieved 24 August 2007 Pierre Simon Laplace in the MacTutor History of Mathematics archive Bowditch s English translation of Laplace s preface Mechanique Celeste The MacTutor History of Mathematics archive Retrieved 4 September 2007 Guide to the Pierre Simon Laplace Papers at The Bancroft Library Pierre Simon Laplace at the Mathematics Genealogy Project English translation Archived 27 December 2012 at the Wayback Machine of a large part of Laplace s work in probability and statistics provided by Richard Pulskamp Archived 29 October 2012 at the Wayback Machine Pierre Simon Laplace Œuvres completes last 7 volumes only Gallica Math Sur le mouvement d un corps qui tombe d une grande hauteur Laplace 1803 online and analysed on BibNum English Political officesPreceded byNicolas Marie Quinette Minister of the Interior12 November 1799 25 December 1799 Succeeded byLucien Bonaparte Portals Biography France Engineering Mathematics Physics Astronomy Stars Outer space Science Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Pierre Simon Laplace amp oldid 1165647937, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.