fbpx
Wikipedia

Heraclitus

Heraclitus (/ˌhɛrəˈkltəs/; Greek: Ἡράκλειτος Herákleitos; fl.c. 500 BC)[1] was an ancient Greek pre-Socratic philosopher from the city of Ephesus, which was then part of the Persian Empire.

Heraclitus
Possible bust of Heraclitus, from the Hall of Philosophers in the Capitoline Museums
Bornc. 6th century BC
Diedc. 5th century BC
EraPre-Socratic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolIonian
Main interests
Cosmology
Process
Paradox
Notable ideas
Fire is the arche
Logos
Flux
Unity of opposites

Little is known of Heraclitus's life. He wrote a single work, only fragments of which have survived. Most of the ancient stories about him are thought to be later fabrications based on interpretations of the preserved fragments. His paradoxical philosophy and appreciation for wordplay and cryptic, oracular epigrams has earned him the epithets "the dark" and "the obscure" since antiquity. He was considered arrogant and depressed, a misanthrope who was subject to melancholia. Consequently, he became known as "the weeping philosopher" in contrast to the ancient philosopher Democritus, who was known as "the laughing philosopher".

The central ideas of Heraclitus' philosophy are the unity of opposites and the concept of change. He also saw harmony and justice in strife. He viewed the world as constantly in flux, always "becoming" but never "being". He expressed this in sayings like "Everything flows" (Greek: πάντα ρει, panta rei) and "No man ever steps in the same river twice". This changing aspect of his philosophy is contrasted with that of the ancient philosopher Parmenides, who believed in "being" and in the static nature of reality.

Like the Milesians before him – Thales with water, Anaximander with apeiron, and Anaximenes with air – Heraclitus chose fire as the arche, the fundamental element that gave rise to the other elements. He also saw the logos as giving structure to the world.

Life edit

 
Theater in Ephesus on the coast of Asia Minor, birthplace of Heraclitus

Heraclitus, the son of Blyson, was from the Ionian city of Ephesus, a port on the Kayster River, on the western coast of Asia Minor (modern-day Turkey). In the 6th century BC, Ephesus, like other cities in Ionia, lived under the effects of both the rise of Lydia under Croesus and his overthrow by Cyrus the Great c. 547 BC.[2] Ephesus appears to have subsequently cultivated a close relationship with the Persian Empire; during the suppression of the Ionian revolt by Darius the Great in 494 BC, Ephesus was spared and emerged as the dominant Greek city in Ionia.[2] Miletus, the home to the previous philosophers, was sacked and captured.[3]

The main source for the life of Heraclitus is the doxographer Diogenes Laërtius.[a] Although most of the information provided by Laertius is unreliable, the anecdote that Heraclitus relinquished the hereditary title of "king" to his younger brother may at least imply that Heraclitus was from an aristocratic family in Ephesus.[2][note 1] Heraclitus appears to have had little sympathy for democracy or the masses.[c][d] However, it is unclear whether he was "an unconditional partisan of the rich," or if, like the sage Solon, he was "withdrawn from competing factions".[2]

Since antiquity, Heraclitus has been labeled an arrogant misanthrope.[5][6][a] The skeptic Timon of Phlius called Heraclitus a "mob-abuser" (ochloloidoros).[a] Heraclitus considered himself self-taught.[e] He did not consider others incapable, but unwilling: "And though reason is common, most people live as though they had an understanding peculiar to themselves."[f] Heraclitus did not seem to like the prevailing religion of the time, criticizing the popular mystery cults.[g][h][i] He also criticized Homer,[j][k] Hesiod,[l] Pythagoras,[m] Xenophanes, and Hecataeus.[a][n] He endorsed the sage Bias of Priene, who is quoted as saying "Most men are bad".[o] He praised a man named Hermodorus as the best among the Ephesians, who he says should all kill themselves for exiling him.[p]

Heraclitus is traditionally considered to have flourished in the 69th Olympiad (504–501 BC),[7][a] but this date may simply be based on a prior account synchronizing his life with the reign of Darius the Great.[2][note 2] However, this date can be considered "roughly accurate" based on a fragment that references Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Hecataeus as older contemporaries, placing him near the end of the sixth century BC.[2][9]

According to Diogenes Laertius, Heraclitus died covered in dung after failing to cure himself from dropsy. This may be to parody his doctrine that for souls it is death to become water, and that a dry soul is best.[10][q]

On Nature edit

 
A modern reconstruction of the Ephesian Temple of Artemis, located in modern Istanbul. According to Diogenes Laertius, Heraclitus deposited his book in the temple.

Heraclitus is said to have produced a single work on papyrus,[a] which has not survived; however, over 100 fragments of this work survive in quotations by other authors.[note 3] The title is unknown,[13] but many later writers refer to this work, and works by other pre-Socratics, as On Nature.[14][a]

According to Diogenes Laërtius, Heraclitus deposited the book in the Artemision – one of the Seven Wonders of the Ancient World – as a dedication.[a] Classicist Charles Kahn states: "Down to the time of Plutarch and Clement, if not later, the little book of Heraclitus was available in its original form to any reader who chose to seek it out."[15] Yet, by the time of Simplicius of Cilicia, a 6th century neoplatonic philosopher, who mentions Heraclitus 32 times but never quotes from him, Heraclitus' work was so rare that it was unavailable even to Simplicius and the other scholars at the Platonic Academy in Athens.[16]

Structure edit

Diogenes Laertius wrote that the book was divided into three parts: the universe, politics, and theology,[a] but, classicists have challenged that division. John Burnet has argued that "it is not to be supposed that this division is due to [Heraclitus] himself; all we can infer is that the work fell naturally into these parts when the Stoic commentators took their editions of it in hand".[17] The Stoics divided their own philosophy into three parts: ethics, logic, and physics.[18] Philologist Karl Deichgräber has argued that the Stoic Cleanthes divided philosophy into dialectics, rhetoric, ethics, politics, physics, and theology, with the last three the same as the alleged division of Heraclitus.[19] The philosopher Paul Schuster has argued that the division came from the Pinakes.[20][21]

Scholar Martin Litchfield West claims that while the existing fragments do not give much of an idea of the overall structure,[22] the beginning of the discourse can probably be determined,[note 4] starting with the opening lines, which are quoted by Sextus Empiricus:[r]

Of the logos being forever do men prove to be uncomprehending, both before they hear and once they have heard it. For although all things happen according to this Word they are like the unexperienced experiencing words and deeds such as I explain when I distinguish each thing according to its nature and declare how it is. Other men are unaware of what they do when they are awake just as they are forgetful of what they do when they are asleep.

Style edit

 
Heraclitus's writing style has been compared to a sibyl, as depicted here by Domenichino.

Heraclitus's style has been compared to a Sibyl,[4][23][24] who "with raving lips uttering things mirthless, unbedizened, and unperfumed, reaches over a thousand years with her voice, thanks to the god in her".[s] Kahn characterized the main features of Heraclitus's writing as "linguistic density", meaning that single words and phrases have multiple meanings, and "resonance", meaning that expressions evoke one another.[25] Heraclitus used literary devices like alliteration and chiasmus.[1] Aristotle quotes part of the opening line in the Rhetoric to outline the difficulty in punctuating Heraclitus without ambiguity; he debated whether "forever" applied to "being" or to "prove".[1][t] Theophrastus says that "some parts of his work [are] half-finished, while other parts [made] a strange medley".[a] Theophrastus thought an inability to finish the work showed Heraclitus was melancholic.[a]

According to Diogenes Laërtius, Timon of Phlius called Heraclitus "the Riddler" (αἰνικτής; ainiktēs) a likely reference to an alleged similarity to Pythagorean riddles.[26] Timon said Heraclitus wrote his book "rather unclearly" (asaphesteron); according to Timon, this was intended to allow only the "capable" to attempt it.[a] By the time of Cicero, this epithet became "The Dark" (ὁ Σκοτεινός; ho Skoteinós) or "The Obscure" as he had spoken nimis obscurē ("too obscurely") concerning nature and had done so deliberately in order to be misunderstood.[27][28]

Philosophy edit

Heraclitus has been the subject of numerous interpretations. According to the entry at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Heraclitus has been seen as a "material monist or a process philosopher; a scientific cosmologist, a metaphysician and a religious thinker; an empiricist, a rationalist, a mystic; a conventional thinker and a revolutionary; a developer of logic – one who denied the law of non-contradiction; the first genuine philosopher and an anti-intellectual obscurantist".[1]

Unity of opposites and Flux edit

The hallmarks of Heraclitus' philosophy are the unity of opposites and change, or flux.[4] Diogenes Laërtius summarizes Heraclitus's philosophy as follows: "All things come into being by conflict of opposites, and the sum of things (τὰ ὅλα ta hola ('the whole')) flows like a stream."[a] According to Aristotle, Heraclitus was a dialetheist, or one who denies the law of noncontradiction.[u] (a law of thought in logic which states that one cannot say of what is and that it is not at the same time)

Several fragments seem to relate to these two concepts.[4] For example, on the unity of opposites: "The straight and the crooked path of the fuller's comb is one and the same";[v] "The way up is the way down";[w] "Beginning and end, on a circle's circumference, are common";[x] and "Thou shouldst unite things whole and things not whole, that which tends to unite and that which tends to separate, the harmonious and the discordant; from all things arises the one, and from the one all things."[y]

Over time, the opposites change into each other:[29][30] "Mortals are immortals and immortals are mortals, the one living the others' death and dying the others' life";[z] "As the same thing in us is living and dead, waking and sleeping, young and old. For these things having changed around are those, and those in turn having changed around are these";[aa] and "Cold things warm up, the hot cools off, wet becomes dry, dry becomes wet."[ab]

It also seems they change into each other depending on one's point of view, a case of relativism or perspectivism.[29] Heraclitus states: "Disease makes health sweet and good; hunger, satiety; toil, rest."[ac] While men drink and wash with water, fish prefer to drink saltwater, pigs prefer to wash in mud, and fowls prefer to wash in dust.[ad][ae][af] "Oxen are happy when they find bitter vetches to eat"[ag] and "asses would rather have refuse than gold."[ah]

Panta rhei edit

Jonathan Barnes states that "Panta rhei, 'everything flows' is probably the most familiar of Heraclitus' sayings, yet few modern scholars think he said it".[31] Barnes observes that although the exact phrase was not ascribed to Heraclitus until the 6th century by Simplicius, a similar saying expressing the same idea,[31] panta chorei, or "everything moves" is ascribed to Heraclitus by Plato in the Cratylus.[ai]

You cannot step into the same river twice edit

 
The Halys River, Turkey's longest.

Since Plato, Heraclitus's theory of flux has been associated with the metaphor of a flowing river, which cannot be stepped into twice.[1][ai] This fragment from Heraclitus's writings has survived in three different forms:[31]

"On those who step into the same rivers, different and different waters flow" — Arius Didymus, quoted in Stobaeus [aj]
"We both step and do not step into the same, we both are and are not" — Heraclitus Homericus, Homeric Allegories [ak]
"It is not possible to step into the same river twice" — Plutarch, On the E at Delphi [al]

Heraclitus illustrated the same point using the Sun: "the Sun is new each day."[32] The river fragments (especially the second "we both are and are not") seem to suggest not only is the river constantly changing, but we do as well, perhaps commenting on existential questions about humanity and personhood.[33]

The classicist Karl Reinhardt identified the first river quote as the genuine one.[1] Scholars such as Reinhardt also interpreted the metaphor as illustrating what is stable, rather than the usual interpretation of illustrating change.[34] Classicist Karl-Martin Dietz [de] has said: "You will not find anything, in which the river remains constant ... Just the fact, that there is a particular river bed, that there is a source and an estuary etc. is something, that stays identical. And this is ... the concept of a river."[35]

Attempting to follow Aristotle, Guthrie interprets flux versus stability as a question of matter versus form. Thus, Heraclitus is a flux theorist because he is a materialist. Since there are no unchanging forms like Plato, but only the material world, then everything changes.[36] According to American philosopher W. V. O. Quine, the river parable illustrates that the river is a process through time. One cannot step twice into the same river-stage.[37]

Professor M. M. McCabe has argued that the three statements on rivers should all be read as fragments from a discourse. McCabe suggests reading them as though they arose in succession. The three fragments "could be retained, and arranged in an argumentative sequence".[11] In McCabe's reading of the fragments, Heraclitus can be read as a philosopher capable of sustained argument, rather than just aphorism.[11]

Strife is justice edit

 
Dike depicted on the Vermont state house. Heraclitus considered strife fundamental to a just world.

Heraclitus said "strife is justice"[am] and "all things take place by strife".[an] He called the opposites in conflict ἔρις (eris), "strife", and theorized that the apparently unitary state, δίκη (dikê), "justice", results in "the most beautiful harmony",[an] in contrast to Anaximander, who described the same as injustice.[24][38][39]

Aristotle said Heraclitus disagreed with Homer because Homer wished that strife would leave the world, which according to Heraclitus would destroy the world; "there would be no harmony without high and low notes, and no animals without male and female, which are opposites".[ao] It may also explain why he disagreed with the Pythagorean emphasis on harmony, but not on strife.[36]

Heraclitus suggests that the world and its various parts are kept together through the tension produced by the unity of opposites, like the string of a bow or a lyre.[40][ap] On one account, this is the earliest use of the concept of force.[41] A quote about the bow shows his appreciation for wordplay: "The bow's name is life, but its work is death."[aq][note 5] Each substance contains its opposite, making for a continual circular exchange of generation, destruction, and motion that results in the stability of the world.[42][43] This can be illustrated by the quote "Even the barley-drink separates if it is not stirred."[ar]

According to Abraham Schoener: "War is the central principle in Heraclitus' thought."[44] Another of Heraclitus' famous sayings highlights the idea that the unity of opposites is also a conflict of opposites: "War is father of all and king of all; and some he manifested as gods, some as men; some he made slaves, some free";[as] war is a creative tension that brings things into existence.[42][45] Heraclitus says further "Gods and men honour those slain in war";[at] "Greater deaths gain greater portions";[au] and "Every beast is tended by blows."[av]

Heraclitus may also have been the first advocate of natural law:[4] "People ought to fight to keep their law as to defend the city walls. For all human laws get nourishment from the one divine law."[aw]

Cosmology edit

 
Heraclitus (named outlined in red) in a fragment of Oxyrhynchus Papyri discusses the Moon.

While considered an ancient cosmologist, Heraclitus did not seem as interested in astronomy, meteorology, or mathematics as his predecessors.[14][4] It is surmised Heraclitus believed that the earth was flat and extended infinitely in all directions.[14] He also believed that the Sun is as large as it looks,[14][note 6] and that if it "exceeds the due times of the year" (the seasons), then "Erinyes, the ministers of Justice, will find him out".[ay] On one account, he believed the Sun and Moon were bowls containing fire, with lunar phases explained by the turning of the bowl.[4][az] His study of the moon near the end of the month is contained in one of the Oxyrhynchus Papyri, the best evidence of Heraclitean astronomy.[1][46]

Fire as arche edit

 
An Eternal flame from a Zoroastrian fire temple in Yazd, Iran. The role of fire in Heraclitean philosophy has been compared with fire worship in Zoroastrianism, the state religion of the Achaemenid Empire during Heraclitus' life.

The Milesians before Heraclitus conceived of certain elements as the arche – Thales with water, Anaximander with apeiron, and Anaximenes with air – Many philosophers concluded that Heraclitus construed of fire as the arche, the fundamental element that gave rise to the other elements. However, it is also argued by many that he never identified Fire as the arche rather, he only use fire to explain his notion of flux.[47][ba] Pre-Socratic scholar Eduard Zeller has argued that Heraclitus believed that heat in general and dry exhalation in particular, rather than visible fire, was the arche.[48]

In one fragment, Heraclitus writes:

"This world-order [Kosmos], the same of all, no god nor man did create, but it ever was and is and will be: ever-living fire, kindling in measures and being quenched in measures."[bb]

This is the oldest extant quote using kosmos, or order, to mean the world.[1] Fire is the one thing eternal in the universe.[49] From fire all things originate and all things return again in a process of never-ending cycles. He describes the transformations:

"Fire lives the death of earth, and air lives the death of fire; water lives the death of air, and earth that of water."[bc] and "The turnings of fire: first sea, and of sea half is earth, half fireburst. [Earth] is liquefied as sea and measured into the same proportion as it had before it became earth."[bd]

On one interpretation, rejecting both the flux and stability interpretation, Heraclitus is not a material monist, but a revolutionary process philosopher who chooses fire in an attempt to say there is no arche. Fire is a symbol or metaphor for change, rather than the basic stuff which changes the most.[29] Perspectives of this sort emphasize his statements on change such as "The way up is the way down",[w] as well as the quote "All things are an exchange for Fire, and Fire for all things, even as wares for gold and gold for wares",[be] which has been understood as stating that while all can be transformed into fire, not everything comes from fire, just as not everything comes from gold.[29]

Foreign influence edit

Heraclitus' description of a doctrine of purification of fire has also been investigated for influence from the Zoroastrian concept of Atar.[50] Many of the doctrines of Zoroastrian fire do not match exactly with those of Heraclitus, such as the relation of fire to earth, but he may have taken some inspiration from them.[50] Zoroastrian parallels to Heraclitus are often difficult to identify specifically due to a lack of surviving Zoroastrian literature from the period and mutual influence with Greek philosophy.[note 7]

The interchange of other elements with fire also has parallels in Vedic literature from the same time period, such as the Kaushitaki Upanishad and Taittiriya Upanishad.[51] West stresses that these doctrines of the interchange of elements were common throughout written works on philosophy that have survived from that period, so Heraclitus' doctrine of fire can not be definitively be said to have been influenced by any other particular Iranian or Indian influence, but may have been part of a mutual interchange of influence over time across the Ancient Near East.[52]

 
Zeus hurls a thunderbolt.

Philosopher Gustav Teichmüller sought to prove Heraclitus was influenced by the Egyptians,[14][53] either directly, by reading the Book of the Dead, or indirectly through the Greek mystery cults.[14] "As the sun of Heraclitus was daily generated from water, so Horus, as Ra of the sun, daily proceeded from Lotus the water."[14] Paul Tannery took up Teichmüller's interpretation.[54] They thought Heraclitus's book was an offering rather than deposited, and only for initiates.[20] Edmund Pfleiderer argued that Heraclitus was influenced by the mystery cults. He interprets Heraclitus seeming condemning of the mysteries[g][h] as the condemning of abuses rather than the idea itself.[14][clarification needed]

God and the soul edit

Heraclitus said that the "thunderbolt steers all things",[bf] a rare comment on meteorology and likely a reference to Zeus as the supreme being.[1] "Wisdom is one thing: [to understand the intelligence by which all things are steered through all things]; it is willing and it is unwilling to be called by the name Zeus."[bg] He invokes relativism with the divine too: God sees man the same way man sees children and apes;[bh][bi] and he seems to give a theodicy, "for god all things are fair and good and just, but men suppose that some are unjust and others just".[1][bj]

Heraclitus regarded the soul (psyche) as a mixture of fire and water, and believed that fire was the noble part of the soul and water the ignoble part. He considered mastery of one's worldly desires to be a noble pursuit that purified the soul's fire,[55] while drunkenness damages the soul by causing it to be moist.[bk][q] The Aristotelian tradition is responsible for a great part of the transmission of Heraclitus' conception of the soul from this physical point of view[56].

Heraclitus also compares the soul to a spider and the body to the web.[bl] Heraclitus believed the soul is also what unifies the body and grants linguistic understanding, departing from Homer's conception of it as merely the breath of life.[57][58] Heraclitus ridicules Homer's conception of the soul leaving the body out of the nose to become a shade by saying "Souls smell in Hades"[bm] and "If all things should become smoke, then perception would be by the nostrils".[bn] His own views on the afterlife remain unclear,[4] but he did state: "There await men after they are dead things which they do not expect or imagine."[bo]

Logos edit

 
Greek spelling of logos

A fundamental concept for Heraclitus is logos, an ancient Greek word literally meaning "word, speech, discourse, or meaning", but with a wide variety of other uses, such that Heraclitus might have a different meaning of the word for each usage in his book. Kahn has argued that Heraclitus used the word in multiple senses,[59] whereas Guthrie has argued that there is no evidence Heraclitus used it in a way that was significantly different from that in which it was used by contemporaneous speakers of Greek.[60]

For Heraclitus, the logos provided the link between rational discourse and the world's rational structure.[61] Logos was like a universal law that unites the cosmos, according to one fragment: "Listening not to me but to the logos, it is wise to agree (homologein) that all things are one."[bp] Another fragment reads: "[hoi polloi] ... do not know how to listen [to Logos] or how to speak [the truth]."[62][bq]

Professor Michael Stokes interprets Heraclitus' use of logos as a public fact like a proposition or formula; like Guthrie, he views Heraclitus as a materialist, and he grants Heraclitus would not have considered these as abstract objects or immaterial things.[4][38] Another possibility is the logos referred to the truth or the book itself.[63][64] Classicist Walther Kranz translated it as "sense".[64]

Ethos edit

The phrase Ethos anthropoi daimon ("man's character is [his] fate"), attributed to Heraclitus, has led to numerous interpretations, and might mean one's luck is related to one's character.[1] The translation of daimon in this context to mean "fate" is disputed. Another translation on offer is supported by Charles Kahn and Philip Wheelwright: "a man's character is his guardian divinity."[65][66] Rather than being followed around by a guardian angel, one's character is his fate.[4]

Time edit

Heraclitus said "Time (Aion) is a child playing draughts, the kingly power is a child's."[b] It is disputed whether this means time and life is determined by rules like a game, by conflict like a game, or by arbitrary whims of the gods like a child plays.[67]

Legacy edit

 
Plaque on Path of Visionaries

Heraclitus' writings have exerted a wide influence on Western philosophy, including the works of Plato and Aristotle, who interpreted him in terms of their own doctrines.[68] Heraclitus is also considered a potential source for understanding the Ancient Greek religion since the discovery of the Derveni papyrus.[69] His influence also extends into art, literature, and medicine, as writings in the Hippocratic corpus show signs of Heraclitean themes.[br][bs]

Ancient edit

Presocratics edit

It is unknown whether or not Heraclitus had any students in his lifetime.[68] In his dialogue Cratylus, Plato presented Cratylus as a Heraclitean and as a linguistic naturalist who believed that names must apply naturally to their objects.[70][71] According to Aristotle, Cratylus went a step beyond his master's doctrine and said that one cannot step into the same river once. He took the view that nothing can be said about the ever-changing world and "ended by thinking that one need not say anything, and only moved his finger".[72] To explain both characterisations by Plato and Aristotle, Cratylus may have thought continuous change warrants skepticism because one cannot define a thing that does not have a permanent nature.[73] Diogenes Laertius lists an otherwise historically obscure Antisthenes who wrote a commentary on Heraclitus.[note 8] According to one author, "there were no doubt other Heracliteans whose names are now lost to us".[74]

Eleatics edit
 
Parmenides, a contemporary who espoused a doctrine of unchanging Being, has been contrasted with Heraclitus and his doctrine of constant change.

Parmenides of Elea, a philosopher and near-contemporary, proposed a doctrine of changelessness, in contrast to the doctrine of flux put forth by Heraclitus.[75][76][77] He is generally agreed to either have influenced or been influenced by Heraclitus.[29][68] Different philosophers have argued that either one of them may have substantially influenced each other, some taking Heraclitus to be responding to Parmenides, but more often Parmenides is seen as responding to Heraclitus.[29] Some also argue that any direct chain of influence between the two is impossible to determine.[77] Although Heraclitus refers to older figures such as Pythagoras,[a][n] neither Parmenides or Heraclitus refer to each other by name in any surviving fragments, so any speculation on influence must be based on interpretation.[77]

Pluralists and atomists edit

The surviving fragments of several other pre-Socratic philosophers show Heraclitean themes.[68] Diogenes of Apollonia thought the action of one thing on another meant they were made of one substance.[4] The pluralists may have been influenced by Heraclitus. The philosopher Anaxagoras refuses to separate the opposites in the "one cosmos".[4] Empedocles has forces (arguably the first since Heraclitus's tension)[41] which are in opposition, known as Love and Hate, or more accurately, Harmony and Strife.[4] Democritus and the atomists were also influenced by Heraclitus.[68] The atomists and Heraclitus both believed that everything was in motion.[78][79][ai] On one interpretation: "Essentially what the atomists did was try to find a middle-way between the contradictory philosophical schemes of Heraclitus and Parmenides."[80]

 
Plato's Theory of Forms was a result of reconciling Heraclitus and Parmenides.
Sophists edit

The sophists, inclusing as Protagoras of Abdera and Gorgias of Leontini, may also have been influenced by Heraclitus.[81] One tradition associated their concern with politics and preventing party strife with Heraclitus.[82][83] Gorgias seems to have been influenced by the Heraclitean idea of the logos, when he argued in his work On Non-Being, possibly parodying the Eleatics, that being cannot exist or be communicated. According to one author, Gorgias "in a sense ... completes Heraclitus."[83]

Classical and Hellenistic philosophy edit

Plato knew of the teachings of Heraclitus through the Heraclitean philosopher Cratylus.[72] Plato held that for Heraclitus knowledge is made impossible by the flux of sensible objects, and thus the need for the imperceptible Forms as objects of knowledge.[84][85] Aristotle accused Heraclitus of denying the law of noncontradiction, and that he thereby failed in his reasoning.[u] However, Aristotle's material monist and world conflagration interpretation of Heraclitus also influenced the Stoics.[4][86]

Stoics edit
 
The Stoic Cleanthes wrote a lost, four-volume Interpretation of Heraclitus. (1605 engraving)

The Stoics believed major tenets of their philosophy derived from the thought of Heraclitus; especially the logos, used to support their belief that rational law governs the universe.[87][88] A four-volume work titled Interpretation of Heraclitus was written by the Stoic philosopher Cleanthes, but has not survived.[68][89][a] In surviving stoic writings, this is most evident in the writings of Marcus Aurelius.[90] According to one author, "Heraclitus of Ephesus was the father of Stoic physics."[91] Many of the later Stoics interpreted the logos as the arche, as a creative fire that ran through all things;[92] Marcus Aurelius understood the Logos as "the account which governs everything." Heraclitus also states, "We should not act and speak like children of our parents", which Marcus Aurelius interpreted to mean one should not simply accept what others believe. West observes that Plato, Aristotle, Theophrastus, and Sextus Empiricus all make no mention of this doctrine, and concludes that the language and thought are "obviously Stoic" and not attributable to Heraclitus.[93] Long concludes the earliest Stoic fragments are also "modifications of Heraclitus".[94] Burnet cautions that these Stoic modifications of Heraclitus make it harder to interpret Heraclitus himself, as the Stoics ascribed their own interpretations of terms like logos and ekpyrosis to Heraclitus.[95]

 
Coin from c. 230 CE depicting Heraclitus as a Cynic, with club and raised hand.
Cynics edit

The Cynics were influenced by Heraclitus, such as by his condemnation of the mystery cults.[19][96][h] Heraclitus is sometimes even depicted as a cynic. According to one source, "the Cynic affinity with Heraclitus lies not so much in his philosophy as in his cultural criticism and (idealised) lifestyle."[97] The Cynics attributed several of the later Cynic epistles to his authorship.[98] Heraclitus wrote: "Dogs bark at every one they do not know."[bt] Similarly, Diogenes the Cynic, when asked by Alexander why he considered himself a dog, responded that he "barks at those who give me nothing".[99][100]

Pyrrhonists edit

The Pyrrhonists were also influenced by Heraclitus. He may be the predecessor to Pyrrho's doctrine "No More This than That".[74] Aenesidemus, one of the major ancient Pyrrhonist philosophers, claimed in a now-lost work that Pyrrhonism was a way to Heraclitean philosophy because Pyrrhonist practice helps one to see how opposites appear to be the case about the same thing. Once one sees this, it leads to understanding the Heraclitean view of opposites being the case about the same thing.[101] A later Pyrrhonist philosopher, Sextus Empiricus, disagreed, arguing opposites appearing to be the case about the same thing is not a dogma of the Pyrrhonists but a matter occurring to the Pyrrhonists, to the other philosophers, and to all of humanity.[101]

Early Christianity edit

 
John 1:1 in the page showing the first chapter of John in the King James Bible.

Heraclitus was often read by early Christian philosophers, who[102] following the Stoics, interpreted the logos as meaning the Christian "Word of God", such as in John 1:1: "In the beginning was the Word (logos) and the Word was God." Hippolytus of Rome, one of the early Church Fathers of the Christian Church, identified Heraclitus along with the other Pre-Socratics and Academics as a source of heresy, in Heraclitus's case namely the heresy of Noetus.[102] The Christian apologist Justin Martyr took a more positive view of Heraclitus.[92] In his First Apology, he said both Socrates and Heraclitus were Christians before Christ: "those who lived reasonably are Christians, even though they have been thought atheists; as, among the Greeks, Socrates and Heraclitus, and men like them."[103]

Modern scholars such as John Burnet have viewed the relationship between Heraclitean logos and Johannine logos as fallacious, saying; "the Johannine doctrine of the logos has nothing to do with Herakleitos or with anything at all in Greek philosophy, but comes from the Hebrew Wisdom literature".[13] When Heraclitus speaks of "God" he does not mean a single deity as an omnipotent and omniscient or God as Creator, the universe being eternal; he meant the divine as opposed to human, the immortal as opposed to the mortal, and the cyclical as opposed to the transient. Thus, it is arguably more accurate to speak of "the Divine" and not of "God".[104]

Weeping philosopher edit

 
Donato Bramante painted Heraclitus and Democritus as the weeping and laughing philosopher.

Heraclitus's influence also extends outside of philosophy. A motif found in art and literature is Heraclitus as the "weeping philosopher" and Democritus as the "laughing philosopher", which may have originated with the Cynic philosopher Menippus,[105] generally references their reactions to the folly of mankind.[106][107]

 
Heraclitus painted as the weeping philosopher by Hendrik ter Brugghen (1628)

For example, in Lucian of Samosata's "Philosophies for Sale", Heraclitus is auctioned off as the "weeping philosopher" and Democritus as the "laughing philosopher".[bu] The Roman poet Juvenal wrote: "Heraclitus, weep at life much more than you did while alive, for now life is more pitiable."[108]

Heraclitus also appears in painter Raphael's School of Athens, in which he is represented by Michelangelo, since they shared a "sour temper and bitter scorn for all rivals".[6]

Modern edit

 
Heraclitus painted as the weeping philosopher by Johannes Moreelse c. 1630

Modern interest in early Greek philosophy can be traced back to 1573, when French printer Henri Estienne (also known as Henricus Stephanus) collected a number of pre-Socratic fragments, including those of Heraclitus, and published them in Latin in Poesis philosophica.[109] Renaissance skeptic Michel de Montaigne's essay On Democritus and Heraclitus, in which he sided with the laughing philosopher over the weeping philosopher, was probably written soon after.[110]

The Merchant of Venice by William Shakespeare features the melancholic character of Antonio, who some critics contend is modeled after Heraclitus.[111] Additionally, in one scene of the play Portia assesses her potential suitors, and says of one County Palatine: "I fear he will prove the weeping philosopher when he grows old".[112]

Cartesianism edit

According to one author, Rene Descartes' anti-Aristotelianism was motivated by Protagoras and Heraclitus.[113] According to Bernard Freyberg, "both Parmenides and Heraclitus are direct if distant ancestors of Spinoza", since they both said all is one.[114] According to Heinrich Bluecher, "If you read the whole system of Spinoza, it is nothing but the changed system of Heraclitus."[115]

British empiricism edit

David Hume wrote while discussing personal identity: "Thus as the nature of a river consists in the motion and change of parts; tho' in less than four and twenty hours these be totally alter'd; this hinders not the river from continuing the same during several ages."[116]

German idealism edit

 
Schleiermacher was "the pioneer of Heraclitean studies".

Since Kant, philosophers have sometimes been divided into rationalists and empiricists.[117] Heraclitus has been considered each by different scholars.[14][118] For rationalism,[119] philosophers cite fragments like "Poor witnesses for men are the eyes and ears of those who have barbarian souls."[bv] For empiricism,[21] they cite fragments like "The things that can be seen, heard, and learned are what I prize the most."[bw] Gottlob Mayer has argued that the philosophical pessimism of Arthur Schopenhauer recapitulated the thought of Heraclitus.[120]

The German theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher was one of the first to collect the fragments of Heraclitus specifically and write them out in his native tongue, the "pioneer of Heraclitean studies".[121][122][123] Schleiermacher was also one of the first to posit Persian influence upon Heraclitus, a question taken up by succeeding scholars Friedrich Creuzer and August Gladisch.[102][123]

The influence of Heraclitus on German idealist G. W. F. Hegel was so profound that he remarked in his Lectures on the History of Philosophy: "there is no proposition of Heraclitus which I have not adopted in my Logic."[124] Hegel interpreted Heraclitus as a dialetheist and as a process philosopher, seeing the "becoming" in Heraclitus as a natural result of the ontology of "being" and "non-being" in Parmenides.[1] He also doubted the world-conflagaration interpretation, which had been popular since Aristotle.[1]

 
Hegel said "there is no proposition of Heraclitus which I have not adopted in my Logic."

The Young Hegelian and socialist Ferdinand Lassalle wrote a book on Heraclitus.[119] "Lassalle follows Hegel in styling the doctrine of Heraclitus 'the philosophy of the logical law of the identity of contradictories.'"[102] Lassalle also thought Persian theology influenced Heraclitus.[119][53][125] Marx compared Lasalle's work to that of "a schoolboy"[126] and Lenin accused him of "sheer plagiarism".[125]

Classical philologist Jakob Bernays also wrote a work on Heraclitus.[102] Inspired by Bernays, the English scholar Ingram Bywater collected all fragments of Heraclitus in a critical edition, Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae (1877).[127] An English translation was provided by G. T. W. Patrick in 1889.[14] Hermann Diels wrote "Bywater's book has come to be accounted ... as the only reliable collection of the remains of that philosopher."[127] Diels published the first edition of the authoritative Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (The Fragments of the Pre-Socratics) in 1903, later revised and expanded three times, and finally revised in two subsequent editions by Walther Kranz. Diels–Kranz is used in academia to cite pre-Socratic philosophers. In Diels–Kranz, each ancient personality and each passage is assigned a number to uniquely identify it; Heraclitus is traditionally catalogued as philosopher number 22.[128]

Continental edit

The existentialist and classical philologist Friedrich Nietzsche preferred Heraclitus above all the other pre-Socratics.[24][129] The nationalist philosopher of history Oswald Spengler wrote his (failed) dissertation on Heraclitus.[130] Existentialist and phenomenologist Martin Heidegger was also influenced by Heraclitus, as seen in his Introduction to Metaphysics. Heidegger believed that the thinking of Heraclitus and Parmenides was the origin of philosophy and misunderstood by Plato and Aristotle, leading all of Western philosophy astray.[131][68]

The Irish author Oscar Wilde was influenced by Heraclitus.[132] Wilde is credited with the saying "expect the unexpected", though Heraclitus said "If you do not expect the unexpected, you will not find it; for it is hard to be sought out and difficult."[133][bx]

In the 1950s, a term originating with Heraclitus, "idios kosmos", meaning "private world" as distinguished from the "common world" (koinos kosmos) was adopted by phenomenological and existential psychologists, such as Ludwig Binswanger and Rollo May, to refer to the experience of people with delusions, or other problems, who have trouble seeing beyond the limits of their own minds, or who confuse this private world with shared reality.[134] It was an important part of novelist Philip K. Dick's views on schizophrenia.[135] Those thinkers have relied on Heraclitus statement that "The waking have one common world, but the sleeping turn aside each into a world of his own."[by]

Anglo-American edit

The British philosopher A. N. Whitehead has been called a process philosopher in the tradition of Heraclitus.[136] In Bertrand Russell's essay Mysticism and Logic, he contends Heraclitus proves himself a metaphysician by his blending of mystical and scientific impulses.[137] Ludwig Wittgenstein was known to read Plato and in his return to philosophy in 1929 he made several remarks resembling those of Heraclitus: "The fundamental thing expressed grammatically: What about the sentence: One cannot step into the same river twice?"[138] He then seemed to make a dramatic shift by 1931, saying one can step twice into the same river.[139] The philosopher Peter Geach was inspired by Heraclitus's comments on the river to formulate his idea of relative identity,[140][141] which he also used to solve such issues as the Trinity.[142][143]

Philosophy of Time edit
 
Presentism is seen as a Heraclitean view.

The British idealist J. M. E. McTaggart is best known for his paper "The Unreality of Time" (1908), in which he argues that time is unreal. His "A series", also known as presentism or "temporal becoming", which conceptualizes of time as tensed (i.e., having the properties of being past, present, or future), has been described as Heraclitean. By contrast, his " "B-theory", under which time is tenseless (i.e., earlier than, simultaneous to, or later than), has been associated with Parmenides[144][145][146] Advocates of presentism include Arthur Prior and William Lane Craig.

Contradiction edit
 
Graham Priest is a dialetheist.

Aristotle's arguments for the law of non contradiction have been in doubt ever since their criticism by Polish logician Jan Łukasiewicz.[147] Recent approaches in logic, such as paraconsistent logic, have led to some philosophers advancing logical pluralism and dialetheism, such as Graham Priest and JC Beall. Priest agrees with G. W. F. Hegel's contradictory account of motion, based on Zeno of Elea's Paradox of the Arrow, which is arguably Heraclitus' account of flux.[148] On this account of motion, to move is to be both here and not here.[148] Beall argues for a contradictory account of Jesus Christ as both man and divine.[149]

Notes edit

Explanatory notes edit

  1. ^ It may also be an unwarranted interpretation of the fragment from Heraclitus stating "the kingdom is a child's".[4][b]
  2. ^ Two alleged letters between Heraclitus and Darius, quoted by Diogenes Laërtius, are later forgeries.[8]
  3. ^ Some classicists and professors of ancient philosophy have disputed which of these fragments can truly be attributed to Heraclitus.[11][12]
  4. ^ West suggests that the beginning may be tentatively ordered as follows:[22] B1; B114; B2; B89; B30; B31; B90; B60
  5. ^ Biós with the accent on the O, is the Greek for "bow". Bίοs with the accent on the I, is the Greek for "life."
  6. ^ Literally, the width of a man's foot.[ax]
  7. ^ The 9th century CE Dadestan i Denig preserves information on Zoroastrian cosmology, but also shows direct borrowings from Aristotle.[51]
  8. ^ Not to be confused with the cynic.[a]

Fragment numbers edit

Citations edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m Graham 2019.
  2. ^ a b c d e f Kahn 1979, p. 1-3.
  3. ^ Ionian Revolt, Blackwell Encyclopedia of Ancient Battles (2011)
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Michael Stokes "Heraclitus" Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) p. 480
  5. ^ Wheelwright, Heraclitus, p. 11, 84
  6. ^ a b Michelangelo and the Pope's Ceiling By Ross King, p. 234
  7. ^ Burnet 1892, p. 130.
  8. ^ Kirk 1954, p. 1.
  9. ^ Clement, Stromateis, 1.129
  10. ^ Fairweather, Janet. “The Death of Heraclitus.” Greek Roman and Byzantine Studies 14 (1973): 233-239.
  11. ^ a b c McCabe 2015.
  12. ^ Kahn 1979, p. 168.
  13. ^ a b Burnet 1892, p. 133.
  14. ^ a b c d e f g h i j G. T. W. Patrick (June 7, 1889). "The Fragments of the Work of Heraclitus of Ephesus on Nature; Translated from the Greek Text of Bywater, with an Introduction Historical and Critical". N. Murray – via Google Books.
  15. ^ Kahn 1979, p. 5.
  16. ^ Mansfield 1999, p. 39.
  17. ^ Burnet 1892, p. 132.
  18. ^ see Laertius, 7.33
  19. ^ a b The Cynics by. Robert Brach Branham p .51
  20. ^ a b Heraclitus and Thales Conceptual Scheme by Aryeh Finkelberg p. 31
  21. ^ a b Heraclitus of Ephesus: An attempt to restore its fragments to their original order, by Paul Robert Schuster
  22. ^ a b West 1971, p. 113-117.
  23. ^ Technopaegnia in Heraclitus and the Delphica Oracles: Shared Compositional Techniques
  24. ^ a b c Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks by Friedrich Nietzsche, p. 64
  25. ^ Kahn 1979, p. 89.
  26. ^ Heresiography in Context by Jaap Mansfeld p. 193
  27. ^ Cicero, De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, Chapter 2, Section 15.
  28. ^ Wheelwright, Heraclitus, p. 116
  29. ^ a b c d e f Heraclitus' Criticism of the Ionian Philosophy, by Daniel W Graham
  30. ^ Graham 2008, p. 175.
  31. ^ a b c Barnes 1982, p. 49.
  32. ^ Bardon, Adrian; Dyke, Heather (November 2, 2015). A Companion to the Philosophy of Time. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 9781119145691 – via Google Books.
  33. ^ Warren 2014, pp. 72–74.
  34. ^ Parmenides, 206-207
  35. ^ Dietz, Karl-Martin (2004). Heraklit von Ephesus und die Entwicklung der Individualität. Stuttgart: Verlag Freies Geistesleben. p. 60. ISBN 978-3772512735.
  36. ^ a b W. K. C. Guthrie "Pre-Socratic Philosophy" Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) p. 443
  37. ^ Quine, W. V. (1950). Identity, Ostension, and Hypostasis. The Journal of Philosophy, 47(22), 621. doi:10.2307/2021795
  38. ^ a b Guthrie 1962, p. 46.
  39. ^ Michael Gagarin (1974). Dike in Archaic Greek Thought. Classical Philology, 69(3), 186–197. doi:10.2307/268491
  40. ^ Snyder, Jane McIntosh (1984). "The Harmonia of Bow and Lyre in Heraclitus Fr. 51 (DK)". Phronesis. 29 (1): 91–95. doi:10.1163/156852884X00201. JSTOR 4182189. Retrieved June 9, 2023 – via jstor.
  41. ^ a b Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Force, by M. Jammer (1961)
  42. ^ a b Sandywell 1996, p. 263-265.
  43. ^ Graham 2008, p. 175-177.
  44. ^ Heraclitus on War by Abraham Schoener
  45. ^ Curd 2020, Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus.
  46. ^ Oxyrhynchus Papyri LIII 3710 ii. 43–47 and iii. 7–11
  47. ^ West 1971, p. 172-173.
  48. ^ Kahn 1979, p. 147
  49. ^ Graham 2008, pp. 170–172.
  50. ^ a b West 1971, p. 170-171.
  51. ^ a b West 1971, p. 174-175.
  52. ^ West 1971, p. 170-176.
  53. ^ a b Early Greek Philosophy on "Being" by C. H. A. Bjerregaard
  54. ^ Gabor Betegh. "Paul Tannery and the Pour L'Histoire De La Science Hellene, De Thales A Empedocle" (PDF). p. 370.
  55. ^ Hussey 1999, p. 111.
  56. ^ Sánchez Castro, Liliana Carolina. The Aristotelian Reception Of Heraclitus’ Conception of the Soul. Brill. pp. 377–403.
  57. ^ Martha C. Nussbaum (1972). ΨΥΧΗ in Heraclitus, I. Phronesis, 17(1), 1–16.
  58. ^ Nussbaum, Martha C. “ΨΥΧΗ in Heraclitus, II.” Phronesis, vol. 17, no. 2, 1972, pp. 153–70. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/4181882. Accessed 18 June 2023.
  59. ^ Kahn 1979.
  60. ^ Guthrie 1962, p. 419.
  61. ^ The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  62. ^ Warren 2014, p. 63; Sandywell 1996, p. 237.
  63. ^ Olof Gigon, Untersuchungen Zu Heraklit, p.4
  64. ^ a b Kirk (1954), p. 37
  65. ^ Plato's Symposium: A Reader's Guide by. Thomas L Cooksey, p. 69
  66. ^ Geldard, Richard G. (June 7, 2000). Remembering Heraclitus. Richard Geldard. ISBN 9780940262980 – via Google Books.
  67. ^ Masking the Abject: A Genealogy of Play p. 18
  68. ^ a b c d e f g Graham 2019, §7.
  69. ^ Betegh 2004.
  70. ^ Dell'Aversana, Paolo (December 6, 2013). Cognition in Geosciences: The feeding loop between geo-disciplines, cognitive sciences and epistemology. Academic Press. ISBN 9789073834682 – via Google Books.
  71. ^ Attardo, Salvatore (2002). "Translation and Humour: An Approach Based on the General Theory of Verbal Humour (GTVH)". The Translator. 8 (2): 173–194. doi:10.1080/13556509.2002.10799131. ISSN 1355-6509. S2CID 142611273.
  72. ^ a b Aristotle. "Γ". Metaphysics. 1010a.
  73. ^ Logic by Wilfrid Hodges, p. 13
  74. ^ a b Pyrrho, his Antecedents, and His Legacy by Richard Bett p. 132
  75. ^ Graham 2002.
  76. ^ Nehamas 2002.
  77. ^ a b c Graham 2002, p. 27-30.
  78. ^ Aristotle, Physics Book 8
  79. ^ Early Greek Philosophy edited by Joe McCoy p. 44
  80. ^ Thinking About the Earth p. 13
  81. ^ "Structural Logos in Heraclitus and the Sophists".
  82. ^ Liberal Temper in Greek Politics, by Eric Havelock, p. 290
  83. ^ a b Rereading the Sophists by Susan Jarratt p. 44
  84. ^ Robinson, T. M. (1991). Heraclitus and Plato on the Language of the Real. The Monist, 74(4), 481–490. JSTOR 27903258
  85. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics, xii.4.1078b12
  86. ^ Mondolfo, Rodolfo, and D. J. Allan. “Evidence of Plato and Aristotle Relating to the Ekpyrosis in Heraclitus.” Phronesis 3, no. 2 (1958): 75–82. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4181631.
  87. ^ Long 2001, chapter 2.
  88. ^ Warren 2014, p. 63.
  89. ^ Diogenes Laertius 7.174
  90. ^ Long 2001, p. 56.
  91. ^ "Stoicism" by Philip Halle, Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961)
  92. ^ a b Erwin Ramsdell Goodenough. The Theology of Justin Martyr.
  93. ^ West 1971, p. 124-125.
  94. ^ Long 2001, p. 51.
  95. ^ Burnet 1892, pp. 142–143.
  96. ^ Branham, Robert Bracht; Goulet-Cazé, Marie-Odile (June 7, 1996). The Cynics: The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy. University of California Press. ISBN 9780520204492 – via Google Books.
  97. ^ Bosman, P. R. “TRACES OF CYNIC MONOTHEISM IN THE EARLY ROMAN EMPIRE.” Acta Classica, vol. 51, 2008, pp. 1–20. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24592647. Accessed 2 Jan. 2024.
  98. ^ J. F. Kindstrand, “The Cynics and Heraclitus”, Eranos 82 (1984), 149–78
  99. ^ Diogenes Laertius Book 6
  100. ^ The Philosophy of Cynicism, Luis Navia, p. 27
  101. ^ a b Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I, Chapter 29, Sections 210–211
  102. ^ a b c d e History of Philosophy, by Friedrich Ueberweg, p. 39
  103. ^ First Apology, Chapter 46
  104. ^ Wheelwright 1959, p. 69-73.
  105. ^ Lepage, J.L. (2012). Laughing and Weeping Melancholy: Democritus and Heraclitus as Emblems. In: The Revival of Antique Philosophy in the Renaissance. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137316660_3
  106. ^ "Heraclitus, Hendrick ter Brugghen, 1628". Rijksmuseum.
  107. ^ "Modern Cynicism". Blackwood's Magazine: 64. 1868.
  108. ^ Juvenal and the Satiric Emotions p. 125
  109. ^ Giannis Stamatellos, Introduction to Presocratics: A Thematic Approach to Early Greek Philosophy with Key Readings. Wiley-Blackwell, 2012., p.7
  110. ^ Montaigne, Michel de. "On Democritus and Heraclitus - The Essays of Michel de Montaigne". HyperEssays.
  111. ^ George Coffin Taylor (1928). "Is Shakespeare's Antonio the "Weeping Philosopher" Heraclitus?". Modern Philology. 26 (2): 161–167. doi:10.1086/387759. JSTOR 433874. S2CID 170717088.
  112. ^ The Merchant of Venice, 1.2.49
  113. ^ Masquerade of the Dream Walkers, by Peter A. Redpath, p. xii
  114. ^ A Dark History of Modern Philosophy, p. 43
  115. ^ Heraclitus and the Metaphysical Tradition
  116. ^ Treatise of Human Nature, 1. 4. 6. 14
  117. ^ Rationalism vs. Empiricism
  118. ^ MOYAL, Georges J. D. “THE UNEXPRESSED RATIONALISM OF HERACLITUS.” Revue de Philosophie Ancienne, vol. 7, no. 2, 1989, pp. 185–98. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24353855. Accessed 2 Jan. 2024.
  119. ^ a b c F. Lassalle. The philosophy of heraclitus the obscure of ephesus, two volumes, berlin, 1858
  120. ^ Heraklit von Ephesus und Arthur Schopenhauer
  121. ^ Heraclitus by Philip Wheelwright
  122. ^ Herakleitos der dunkle, von Ephesos, dargestellt aus den Trümmern seines Werkes und den Zeugnissen der Altens, 1807
  123. ^ a b Roberts, Lee M. (January 14, 2009). Germany and the Imagined East. Cambridge Scholars Publishing. ISBN 9781443804196 – via Google Books.
  124. ^ "Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philosophy". www.marxists.org.
  125. ^ a b Conspectus of Lassalle’s Book The Philosophy of Heraclitus the Obscure of Ephesus by Lenin
  126. ^ Letter to Friedrich Engels, February 1 1858
  127. ^ a b Jackson, William Walrond (June 7, 1917). "Ingram Bywater: The Memoir of an Oxford Scholar, 1840-1914". Clarendon Press – via Google Books.
  128. ^ Diels, Hermann; Kranz, Walther (1957). Plamböck, Gert (ed.). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (in Ancient Greek and German). Rowohlt. ISBN 5875607416. Retrieved 11 April 2022.
  129. ^ Mügge, Maximilian August (May 26, 1911). "Friedrich Nietzsche: His Life and Work". T. Fisher Unwin – via Google Books.
  130. ^ Oswald Spengler. The Fundamental Metaphysical Thought of the Heraclitean Philosophy.
  131. ^ W. Julian Korab-Karpowicz, The Presocratics in the Thought of Martin Heidegger (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2016), page 58.
  132. ^ Heraclitus and Hedonism in Wilde's writing
  133. ^ Language and Mobility
  134. ^ May, Rollo (1958). "Contributions of existential psychotherapy". In May, Rollo; Angel, Ernest; Ellenberger, Henri F. (eds.). Existence: a new dimension in psychiatry and psychology. New York: Basic Books. pp. 37–91 (81). doi:10.1037/11321-002. ISBN 9780671203146. OCLC 14599810.
  135. ^ "Schizophrenia & 'The Book of Changes'". (1964)
  136. ^ "Whitehead's Process Metaphysics as a New Link between Science and Metaphysics".
  137. ^ Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, by Bertrand Russell
  138. ^ Zettel, Wittgenstein, #459
  139. ^ Stern, David G. (1991). Heraclitus’ and Wittgenstein’s River Images: Stepping Twice into the Same River. The Monist 74 (4):579-604.
  140. ^ Cartwright, Helen Morris. “Heraclitus and the Bath Water.” The Philosophical Review 74, no. 4 (1965): 466–85. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183124.
  141. ^ Instantiation, Identity and Constitution, by E. J. Lowe, Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, Vol. 44, No. 1 (Jul., 1983), pp. 45-59
  142. ^ P. T. Geach, Reference and Generality, pp.150-151
  143. ^ Relative Identity and the Doctrine of the Trinity
  144. ^ Markosian, Ned. "Time". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 28 December 2014.
  145. ^ Craig, William Lane (1999). Temporal Becoming and the Direction of Time. Philosophy and Theology 11 (2):349-366.
  146. ^ see Being and Becoming in Modern Physics
  147. ^ Lukasiewicz, Jan & Wedin, Vernon (1971). On the Principle of Contradiction in Aristotle. Review of Metaphysics 24 (3):485 - 509.
  148. ^ a b Priest, Graham. “Inconsistencies in Motion.” American Philosophical Quarterly 22, no. 4 (1985): 339–46. JSTOR 20014114.
  149. ^ Beall, Jc ; Pawl, Timothy ; McCall, Thomas ; Cotnoir, A. J. & Uckelman, Sara L. (2019). Complete Symposium on Jc Beall's Christ – A Contradiction: A Defense of Contradictory Christology. Journal of Analytic Theology 7 (1):400-577.

References edit

Ancient sources edit

This article uses the Diels–Kranz numbering system for testimony (labeled A), fragments (labeled B), and imitation (labeled C) of Pre-Socratic philosophy.

Testimony edit

Fragments edit

Imitation edit

  • C1. Hippocrates (1931). On Regimen. Hippocrates Collected Works. Vol. IV. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • C2. Hippocrates (1923). On Nutrition. Hippocrates Collected Works. Vol. I. Translated by W. H. S. Jones. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • C4. Cleanthes. Hymn to Zeus. fr. 537.
  • C5. Lucian (1905). Philosophies for Sale. The works of Lucian of Samosata. Vol. 1. Translated by Fowler, H. W.; Fowler, F. G.

Modern scholarship edit

  • Barnes, Jonathan (1982). "The Natural Philosophy of Heraclitus". The Presocratic Philosophers. London & New York: Routledge Taylor & Francis Group. pp. 43–62. ISBN 978-0-415-05079-1.
  • Betegh, Gábor (2004). The Derveni papyrus : cosmology, theology, and interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780511584435.
  • Burnet, John (1892). "Heraclitus". Early Greek Philosophy. A. and C. Black. Retrieved 5 March 2022.
  • Curd, Patricia (2020). "Presocratic philosophy". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Graham, D. W. (2008). "Heraclitus: Flux, Order, and Knowledge". In Curd, P.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 169–188. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Graham, D. W. (2002). "Heraclitus and Parmenides". In Caston, V.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 27–44. ISBN 978-0-7546-0502-7.
  • Graham, Daniel W. (2019). "Heraclitus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962). A History of Greek Philosophy: The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hussey, Edward (1999). "Heraclitus". In Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 88–112. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
  • Kahn, Charles H. (1979). The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. An Edition of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-21883-2.
  • Kirk, G. S. (1954). Heraclitus, the Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Long, A. A. (2001). Stoic Studies. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-22974-7.
  • Mansfield, Jaap (1999). Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 22–45. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
  • McCabe, Mary Margaret (2015). "Platonic Conversations". Oxford University Press. pp. 1–31. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198732884.003.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-873288-4. {{cite book}}: Missing or empty |title= (help)
  • Nehamas, Alexander (2002). "Parminidean Being/Heraclitean Fire". In Caston, V.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 45–64. ISBN 978-0-7546-0502-7.
  • Sandywell, Barry (1996). Presocratic Reflexivity: The Construction of Philosophical Discourse c. 600-450 B.C.: Logological Investigations: Volume Three. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-85347-2.
  • Warren, James (5 December 2014). Presocratics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-49337-2.
  • West, Martin L. (1971). Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Clarendon Press. Retrieved 6 March 2022. Chapters 4-6 deal with Heraclitus
  • Wheelwright, Philip (1959). Heraclitus (PDF). Princeton University Press.

Further reading edit

  • Gregory, Andrew (3 January 2008). Ancient Greek Cosmogony. A&C Black. ISBN 978-1-84966-792-0.
  • Hussey, Edward (1972). The Presocratics. New York: Scribner. ISBN 0684131188.
  • Kirk, G. S.; Raven, J. E. (1957). The Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mcevilley, Thomas C. (7 February 2012). The Shape of Ancient Thought: Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-58115-933-2.
  • McKirahan, R. D. (2011). Philosophy before Socrates, An Introduction With Text and Commentary. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 978-1-60384-183-2.
  • Mikalson, Jon (24 June 2010). Greek Popular Religion in Greek Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-957783-5.
  • Mitchell, John Malcolm (1911). "Heraclitus" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 13 (11th ed.). pp. 309–310.
  • Mourelatos, Alexander, ed. (1993). The Pre-Socratics : a collection of critical essays (Rev. ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02088-4.
  • Naddaf, Gerard (2005). The Greek Concept of Nature. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0791463734.
  • Schofield, Malcolm; Nussbaum, Martha Craven, eds. (1982). Language and logos : studies in ancient Greek philosophy presented to G. E. L. Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge U.P. ISBN 978-0-521-23640-9.
  • Stamatellos, Giannis (2007). Plotinus and the Presocratics: A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences in Plotinus' Enneads. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-8031-1.
  • Wright, M. R. (1985). The Presocratics: The main Fragments in Greek with Introduction, Commentary and Appendix Containing Text and Translation of Aristotle on the Presocratics. Bristol: Bristol Classical Press. ISBN 978-0-86292-079-1.

External links edit

  •   Works related to Fragments of Heraclitus at Wikisource
  •   Quotations related to Heraclitus at Wikiquote
  •   Media related to Heraclitus at Wikimedia Commons
  • Stamatellos, Giannis. "Heraclitus of Ephesus: Life and Work". Retrieved 2007-10-12.

heraclitus, other, people, named, disambiguation, confused, with, heraclius, heracles, greek, Ἡράκλειτος, herákleitos, ancient, greek, socratic, philosopher, from, city, ephesus, which, then, part, persian, empire, possible, bust, from, hall, philosophers, cap. For other people named Heraclitus see Heraclitus disambiguation Not to be confused with Heraclius or Heracles Heraclitus ˌ h ɛr e ˈ k l aɪ t e s Greek Ἡrakleitos Herakleitos fl c 500 BC 1 was an ancient Greek pre Socratic philosopher from the city of Ephesus which was then part of the Persian Empire HeraclitusPossible bust of Heraclitus from the Hall of Philosophers in the Capitoline MuseumsBornc 6th century BC Ephesus Ionia Persian Empire now Selcuk Izmir Turkey Diedc 5th century BC Ephesus Ionia Delian LeagueEraPre Socratic philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolIonianMain interestsCosmologyProcessParadoxNotable ideasFire is the archeLogosFluxUnity of oppositesLittle is known of Heraclitus s life He wrote a single work only fragments of which have survived Most of the ancient stories about him are thought to be later fabrications based on interpretations of the preserved fragments His paradoxical philosophy and appreciation for wordplay and cryptic oracular epigrams has earned him the epithets the dark and the obscure since antiquity He was considered arrogant and depressed a misanthrope who was subject to melancholia Consequently he became known as the weeping philosopher in contrast to the ancient philosopher Democritus who was known as the laughing philosopher The central ideas of Heraclitus philosophy are the unity of opposites and the concept of change He also saw harmony and justice in strife He viewed the world as constantly in flux always becoming but never being He expressed this in sayings like Everything flows Greek panta rei panta rei and No man ever steps in the same river twice This changing aspect of his philosophy is contrasted with that of the ancient philosopher Parmenides who believed in being and in the static nature of reality Like the Milesians before him Thales with water Anaximander with apeiron and Anaximenes with air Heraclitus chose fire as the arche the fundamental element that gave rise to the other elements He also saw the logos as giving structure to the world Contents 1 Life 2 On Nature 2 1 Structure 2 2 Style 3 Philosophy 3 1 Unity of opposites and Flux 3 2 Panta rhei 3 3 You cannot step into the same river twice 3 4 Strife is justice 3 5 Cosmology 3 5 1 Fire as arche 3 5 2 Foreign influence 3 5 3 God and the soul 3 6 Logos 3 7 Ethos 3 8 Time 4 Legacy 4 1 Ancient 4 1 1 Presocratics 4 1 1 1 Eleatics 4 1 1 2 Pluralists and atomists 4 1 1 3 Sophists 4 1 2 Classical and Hellenistic philosophy 4 1 2 1 Stoics 4 1 2 2 Cynics 4 1 2 3 Pyrrhonists 4 1 3 Early Christianity 4 1 4 Weeping philosopher 4 2 Modern 4 2 1 Cartesianism 4 2 2 British empiricism 4 2 3 German idealism 4 2 4 Continental 4 2 5 Anglo American 4 2 5 1 Philosophy of Time 4 2 5 2 Contradiction 5 Notes 5 1 Explanatory notes 5 2 Fragment numbers 5 3 Citations 6 References 6 1 Ancient sources 6 1 1 Testimony 6 1 2 Fragments 6 1 3 Imitation 6 2 Modern scholarship 7 Further reading 8 External linksLife edit nbsp Theater in Ephesus on the coast of Asia Minor birthplace of HeraclitusHeraclitus the son of Blyson was from the Ionian city of Ephesus a port on the Kayster River on the western coast of Asia Minor modern day Turkey In the 6th century BC Ephesus like other cities in Ionia lived under the effects of both the rise of Lydia under Croesus and his overthrow by Cyrus the Great c 547 BC 2 Ephesus appears to have subsequently cultivated a close relationship with the Persian Empire during the suppression of the Ionian revolt by Darius the Great in 494 BC Ephesus was spared and emerged as the dominant Greek city in Ionia 2 Miletus the home to the previous philosophers was sacked and captured 3 The main source for the life of Heraclitus is the doxographer Diogenes Laertius a Although most of the information provided by Laertius is unreliable the anecdote that Heraclitus relinquished the hereditary title of king to his younger brother may at least imply that Heraclitus was from an aristocratic family in Ephesus 2 note 1 Heraclitus appears to have had little sympathy for democracy or the masses c d However it is unclear whether he was an unconditional partisan of the rich or if like the sage Solon he was withdrawn from competing factions 2 Since antiquity Heraclitus has been labeled an arrogant misanthrope 5 6 a The skeptic Timon of Phlius called Heraclitus a mob abuser ochloloidoros a Heraclitus considered himself self taught e He did not consider others incapable but unwilling And though reason is common most people live as though they had an understanding peculiar to themselves f Heraclitus did not seem to like the prevailing religion of the time criticizing the popular mystery cults g h i He also criticized Homer j k Hesiod l Pythagoras m Xenophanes and Hecataeus a n He endorsed the sage Bias of Priene who is quoted as saying Most men are bad o He praised a man named Hermodorus as the best among the Ephesians who he says should all kill themselves for exiling him p Heraclitus is traditionally considered to have flourished in the 69th Olympiad 504 501 BC 7 a but this date may simply be based on a prior account synchronizing his life with the reign of Darius the Great 2 note 2 However this date can be considered roughly accurate based on a fragment that references Pythagoras Xenophanes and Hecataeus as older contemporaries placing him near the end of the sixth century BC 2 9 According to Diogenes Laertius Heraclitus died covered in dung after failing to cure himself from dropsy This may be to parody his doctrine that for souls it is death to become water and that a dry soul is best 10 q On Nature edit nbsp A modern reconstruction of the Ephesian Temple of Artemis located in modern Istanbul According to Diogenes Laertius Heraclitus deposited his book in the temple Heraclitus is said to have produced a single work on papyrus a which has not survived however over 100 fragments of this work survive in quotations by other authors note 3 The title is unknown 13 but many later writers refer to this work and works by other pre Socratics as On Nature 14 a According to Diogenes Laertius Heraclitus deposited the book in the Artemision one of the Seven Wonders of the Ancient World as a dedication a Classicist Charles Kahn states Down to the time of Plutarch and Clement if not later the little book of Heraclitus was available in its original form to any reader who chose to seek it out 15 Yet by the time of Simplicius of Cilicia a 6th century neoplatonic philosopher who mentions Heraclitus 32 times but never quotes from him Heraclitus work was so rare that it was unavailable even to Simplicius and the other scholars at the Platonic Academy in Athens 16 Structure edit Diogenes Laertius wrote that the book was divided into three parts the universe politics and theology a but classicists have challenged that division John Burnet has argued that it is not to be supposed that this division is due to Heraclitus himself all we can infer is that the work fell naturally into these parts when the Stoic commentators took their editions of it in hand 17 The Stoics divided their own philosophy into three parts ethics logic and physics 18 Philologist Karl Deichgraber has argued that the Stoic Cleanthes divided philosophy into dialectics rhetoric ethics politics physics and theology with the last three the same as the alleged division of Heraclitus 19 The philosopher Paul Schuster has argued that the division came from the Pinakes 20 21 Scholar Martin Litchfield West claims that while the existing fragments do not give much of an idea of the overall structure 22 the beginning of the discourse can probably be determined note 4 starting with the opening lines which are quoted by Sextus Empiricus r Of the logos being forever do men prove to be uncomprehending both before they hear and once they have heard it For although all things happen according to this Word they are like the unexperienced experiencing words and deeds such as I explain when I distinguish each thing according to its nature and declare how it is Other men are unaware of what they do when they are awake just as they are forgetful of what they do when they are asleep Style edit nbsp Heraclitus s writing style has been compared to a sibyl as depicted here by Domenichino Heraclitus s style has been compared to a Sibyl 4 23 24 who with raving lips uttering things mirthless unbedizened and unperfumed reaches over a thousand years with her voice thanks to the god in her s Kahn characterized the main features of Heraclitus s writing as linguistic density meaning that single words and phrases have multiple meanings and resonance meaning that expressions evoke one another 25 Heraclitus used literary devices like alliteration and chiasmus 1 Aristotle quotes part of the opening line in the Rhetoric to outline the difficulty in punctuating Heraclitus without ambiguity he debated whether forever applied to being or to prove 1 t Theophrastus says that some parts of his work are half finished while other parts made a strange medley a Theophrastus thought an inability to finish the work showed Heraclitus was melancholic a According to Diogenes Laertius Timon of Phlius called Heraclitus the Riddler aἰnikths ainiktes a likely reference to an alleged similarity to Pythagorean riddles 26 Timon said Heraclitus wrote his book rather unclearly asaphesteron according to Timon this was intended to allow only the capable to attempt it a By the time of Cicero this epithet became The Dark ὁ Skoteinos ho Skoteinos or The Obscure as he had spoken nimis obscure too obscurely concerning nature and had done so deliberately in order to be misunderstood 27 28 Philosophy editHeraclitus has been the subject of numerous interpretations According to the entry at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Heraclitus has been seen as a material monist or a process philosopher a scientific cosmologist a metaphysician and a religious thinker an empiricist a rationalist a mystic a conventional thinker and a revolutionary a developer of logic one who denied the law of non contradiction the first genuine philosopher and an anti intellectual obscurantist 1 Unity of opposites and Flux edit The hallmarks of Heraclitus philosophy are the unity of opposites and change or flux 4 Diogenes Laertius summarizes Heraclitus s philosophy as follows All things come into being by conflict of opposites and the sum of things tὰ ὅla ta hola the whole flows like a stream a According to Aristotle Heraclitus was a dialetheist or one who denies the law of noncontradiction u a law of thought in logic which states that one cannot say of what is and that it is not at the same time Several fragments seem to relate to these two concepts 4 For example on the unity of opposites The straight and the crooked path of the fuller s comb is one and the same v The way up is the way down w Beginning and end on a circle s circumference are common x and Thou shouldst unite things whole and things not whole that which tends to unite and that which tends to separate the harmonious and the discordant from all things arises the one and from the one all things y Over time the opposites change into each other 29 30 Mortals are immortals and immortals are mortals the one living the others death and dying the others life z As the same thing in us is living and dead waking and sleeping young and old For these things having changed around are those and those in turn having changed around are these aa and Cold things warm up the hot cools off wet becomes dry dry becomes wet ab It also seems they change into each other depending on one s point of view a case of relativism or perspectivism 29 Heraclitus states Disease makes health sweet and good hunger satiety toil rest ac While men drink and wash with water fish prefer to drink saltwater pigs prefer to wash in mud and fowls prefer to wash in dust ad ae af Oxen are happy when they find bitter vetches to eat ag and asses would rather have refuse than gold ah Panta rhei edit Jonathan Barnes states that Panta rhei everything flows is probably the most familiar of Heraclitus sayings yet few modern scholars think he said it 31 Barnes observes that although the exact phrase was not ascribed to Heraclitus until the 6th century by Simplicius a similar saying expressing the same idea 31 panta chorei or everything moves is ascribed to Heraclitus by Plato in the Cratylus ai You cannot step into the same river twice edit nbsp The Halys River Turkey s longest Since Plato Heraclitus s theory of flux has been associated with the metaphor of a flowing river which cannot be stepped into twice 1 ai This fragment from Heraclitus s writings has survived in three different forms 31 On those who step into the same rivers different and different waters flow Arius Didymus quoted in Stobaeus aj We both step and do not step into the same we both are and are not Heraclitus Homericus Homeric Allegories ak It is not possible to step into the same river twice Plutarch On the E at Delphi al Heraclitus illustrated the same point using the Sun the Sun is new each day 32 The river fragments especially the second we both are and are not seem to suggest not only is the river constantly changing but we do as well perhaps commenting on existential questions about humanity and personhood 33 The classicist Karl Reinhardt identified the first river quote as the genuine one 1 Scholars such as Reinhardt also interpreted the metaphor as illustrating what is stable rather than the usual interpretation of illustrating change 34 Classicist Karl Martin Dietz de has said You will not find anything in which the river remains constant Just the fact that there is a particular river bed that there is a source and an estuary etc is something that stays identical And this is the concept of a river 35 Attempting to follow Aristotle Guthrie interprets flux versus stability as a question of matter versus form Thus Heraclitus is a flux theorist because he is a materialist Since there are no unchanging forms like Plato but only the material world then everything changes 36 According to American philosopher W V O Quine the river parable illustrates that the river is a process through time One cannot step twice into the same river stage 37 Professor M M McCabe has argued that the three statements on rivers should all be read as fragments from a discourse McCabe suggests reading them as though they arose in succession The three fragments could be retained and arranged in an argumentative sequence 11 In McCabe s reading of the fragments Heraclitus can be read as a philosopher capable of sustained argument rather than just aphorism 11 Strife is justice edit nbsp Dike depicted on the Vermont state house Heraclitus considered strife fundamental to a just world Heraclitus said strife is justice am and all things take place by strife an He called the opposites in conflict ἔris eris strife and theorized that the apparently unitary state dikh dike justice results in the most beautiful harmony an in contrast to Anaximander who described the same as injustice 24 38 39 Aristotle said Heraclitus disagreed with Homer because Homer wished that strife would leave the world which according to Heraclitus would destroy the world there would be no harmony without high and low notes and no animals without male and female which are opposites ao It may also explain why he disagreed with the Pythagorean emphasis on harmony but not on strife 36 Heraclitus suggests that the world and its various parts are kept together through the tension produced by the unity of opposites like the string of a bow or a lyre 40 ap On one account this is the earliest use of the concept of force 41 A quote about the bow shows his appreciation for wordplay The bow s name is life but its work is death aq note 5 Each substance contains its opposite making for a continual circular exchange of generation destruction and motion that results in the stability of the world 42 43 This can be illustrated by the quote Even the barley drink separates if it is not stirred ar According to Abraham Schoener War is the central principle in Heraclitus thought 44 Another of Heraclitus famous sayings highlights the idea that the unity of opposites is also a conflict of opposites War is father of all and king of all and some he manifested as gods some as men some he made slaves some free as war is a creative tension that brings things into existence 42 45 Heraclitus says further Gods and men honour those slain in war at Greater deaths gain greater portions au and Every beast is tended by blows av Heraclitus may also have been the first advocate of natural law 4 People ought to fight to keep their law as to defend the city walls For all human laws get nourishment from the one divine law aw Cosmology edit nbsp Heraclitus named outlined in red in a fragment of Oxyrhynchus Papyri discusses the Moon While considered an ancient cosmologist Heraclitus did not seem as interested in astronomy meteorology or mathematics as his predecessors 14 4 It is surmised Heraclitus believed that the earth was flat and extended infinitely in all directions 14 He also believed that the Sun is as large as it looks 14 note 6 and that if it exceeds the due times of the year the seasons then Erinyes the ministers of Justice will find him out ay On one account he believed the Sun and Moon were bowls containing fire with lunar phases explained by the turning of the bowl 4 az His study of the moon near the end of the month is contained in one of the Oxyrhynchus Papyri the best evidence of Heraclitean astronomy 1 46 Fire as arche edit See also Classical element Hellenistic philosophy nbsp An Eternal flame from a Zoroastrian fire temple in Yazd Iran The role of fire in Heraclitean philosophy has been compared with fire worship in Zoroastrianism the state religion of the Achaemenid Empire during Heraclitus life The Milesians before Heraclitus conceived of certain elements as the arche Thales with water Anaximander with apeiron and Anaximenes with air Many philosophers concluded that Heraclitus construed of fire as the arche the fundamental element that gave rise to the other elements However it is also argued by many that he never identified Fire as the arche rather he only use fire to explain his notion of flux 47 ba Pre Socratic scholar Eduard Zeller has argued that Heraclitus believed that heat in general and dry exhalation in particular rather than visible fire was the arche 48 In one fragment Heraclitus writes This world order Kosmos the same of all no god nor man did create but it ever was and is and will be ever living fire kindling in measures and being quenched in measures bb This is the oldest extant quote using kosmos or order to mean the world 1 Fire is the one thing eternal in the universe 49 From fire all things originate and all things return again in a process of never ending cycles He describes the transformations Fire lives the death of earth and air lives the death of fire water lives the death of air and earth that of water bc and The turnings of fire first sea and of sea half is earth half fireburst Earth is liquefied as sea and measured into the same proportion as it had before it became earth bd On one interpretation rejecting both the flux and stability interpretation Heraclitus is not a material monist but a revolutionary process philosopher who chooses fire in an attempt to say there is no arche Fire is a symbol or metaphor for change rather than the basic stuff which changes the most 29 Perspectives of this sort emphasize his statements on change such as The way up is the way down w as well as the quote All things are an exchange for Fire and Fire for all things even as wares for gold and gold for wares be which has been understood as stating that while all can be transformed into fire not everything comes from fire just as not everything comes from gold 29 Foreign influence edit Heraclitus description of a doctrine of purification of fire has also been investigated for influence from the Zoroastrian concept of Atar 50 Many of the doctrines of Zoroastrian fire do not match exactly with those of Heraclitus such as the relation of fire to earth but he may have taken some inspiration from them 50 Zoroastrian parallels to Heraclitus are often difficult to identify specifically due to a lack of surviving Zoroastrian literature from the period and mutual influence with Greek philosophy note 7 The interchange of other elements with fire also has parallels in Vedic literature from the same time period such as the Kaushitaki Upanishad and Taittiriya Upanishad 51 West stresses that these doctrines of the interchange of elements were common throughout written works on philosophy that have survived from that period so Heraclitus doctrine of fire can not be definitively be said to have been influenced by any other particular Iranian or Indian influence but may have been part of a mutual interchange of influence over time across the Ancient Near East 52 nbsp Zeus hurls a thunderbolt Philosopher Gustav Teichmuller sought to prove Heraclitus was influenced by the Egyptians 14 53 either directly by reading the Book of the Dead or indirectly through the Greek mystery cults 14 As the sun of Heraclitus was daily generated from water so Horus as Ra of the sun daily proceeded from Lotus the water 14 Paul Tannery took up Teichmuller s interpretation 54 They thought Heraclitus s book was an offering rather than deposited and only for initiates 20 Edmund Pfleiderer argued that Heraclitus was influenced by the mystery cults He interprets Heraclitus seeming condemning of the mysteries g h as the condemning of abuses rather than the idea itself 14 clarification needed God and the soul edit Heraclitus said that the thunderbolt steers all things bf a rare comment on meteorology and likely a reference to Zeus as the supreme being 1 Wisdom is one thing to understand the intelligence by which all things are steered through all things it is willing and it is unwilling to be called by the name Zeus bg He invokes relativism with the divine too God sees man the same way man sees children and apes bh bi and he seems to give a theodicy for god all things are fair and good and just but men suppose that some are unjust and others just 1 bj Heraclitus regarded the soul psyche as a mixture of fire and water and believed that fire was the noble part of the soul and water the ignoble part He considered mastery of one s worldly desires to be a noble pursuit that purified the soul s fire 55 while drunkenness damages the soul by causing it to be moist bk q The Aristotelian tradition is responsible for a great part of the transmission of Heraclitus conception of the soul from this physical point of view 56 Heraclitus also compares the soul to a spider and the body to the web bl Heraclitus believed the soul is also what unifies the body and grants linguistic understanding departing from Homer s conception of it as merely the breath of life 57 58 Heraclitus ridicules Homer s conception of the soul leaving the body out of the nose to become a shade by saying Souls smell in Hades bm and If all things should become smoke then perception would be by the nostrils bn His own views on the afterlife remain unclear 4 but he did state There await men after they are dead things which they do not expect or imagine bo Logos edit nbsp Greek spelling of logosA fundamental concept for Heraclitus is logos an ancient Greek word literally meaning word speech discourse or meaning but with a wide variety of other uses such that Heraclitus might have a different meaning of the word for each usage in his book Kahn has argued that Heraclitus used the word in multiple senses 59 whereas Guthrie has argued that there is no evidence Heraclitus used it in a way that was significantly different from that in which it was used by contemporaneous speakers of Greek 60 For Heraclitus the logos provided the link between rational discourse and the world s rational structure 61 Logos was like a universal law that unites the cosmos according to one fragment Listening not to me but to the logos it is wise to agree homologein that all things are one bp Another fragment reads hoi polloi do not know how to listen to Logos or how to speak the truth 62 bq Professor Michael Stokes interprets Heraclitus use of logos as a public fact like a proposition or formula like Guthrie he views Heraclitus as a materialist and he grants Heraclitus would not have considered these as abstract objects or immaterial things 4 38 Another possibility is the logos referred to the truth or the book itself 63 64 Classicist Walther Kranz translated it as sense 64 Ethos edit The phrase Ethos anthropoi daimon man s character is his fate attributed to Heraclitus has led to numerous interpretations and might mean one s luck is related to one s character 1 The translation of daimon in this context to mean fate is disputed Another translation on offer is supported by Charles Kahn and Philip Wheelwright a man s character is his guardian divinity 65 66 Rather than being followed around by a guardian angel one s character is his fate 4 Time edit Heraclitus said Time Aion is a child playing draughts the kingly power is a child s b It is disputed whether this means time and life is determined by rules like a game by conflict like a game or by arbitrary whims of the gods like a child plays 67 Legacy edit nbsp Plaque on Path of VisionariesHeraclitus writings have exerted a wide influence on Western philosophy including the works of Plato and Aristotle who interpreted him in terms of their own doctrines 68 Heraclitus is also considered a potential source for understanding the Ancient Greek religion since the discovery of the Derveni papyrus 69 His influence also extends into art literature and medicine as writings in the Hippocratic corpus show signs of Heraclitean themes br bs Ancient edit Presocratics edit It is unknown whether or not Heraclitus had any students in his lifetime 68 In his dialogue Cratylus Plato presented Cratylus as a Heraclitean and as a linguistic naturalist who believed that names must apply naturally to their objects 70 71 According to Aristotle Cratylus went a step beyond his master s doctrine and said that one cannot step into the same river once He took the view that nothing can be said about the ever changing world and ended by thinking that one need not say anything and only moved his finger 72 To explain both characterisations by Plato and Aristotle Cratylus may have thought continuous change warrants skepticism because one cannot define a thing that does not have a permanent nature 73 Diogenes Laertius lists an otherwise historically obscure Antisthenes who wrote a commentary on Heraclitus note 8 According to one author there were no doubt other Heracliteans whose names are now lost to us 74 Eleatics edit nbsp Parmenides a contemporary who espoused a doctrine of unchanging Being has been contrasted with Heraclitus and his doctrine of constant change Parmenides of Elea a philosopher and near contemporary proposed a doctrine of changelessness in contrast to the doctrine of flux put forth by Heraclitus 75 76 77 He is generally agreed to either have influenced or been influenced by Heraclitus 29 68 Different philosophers have argued that either one of them may have substantially influenced each other some taking Heraclitus to be responding to Parmenides but more often Parmenides is seen as responding to Heraclitus 29 Some also argue that any direct chain of influence between the two is impossible to determine 77 Although Heraclitus refers to older figures such as Pythagoras a n neither Parmenides or Heraclitus refer to each other by name in any surviving fragments so any speculation on influence must be based on interpretation 77 Pluralists and atomists edit The surviving fragments of several other pre Socratic philosophers show Heraclitean themes 68 Diogenes of Apollonia thought the action of one thing on another meant they were made of one substance 4 The pluralists may have been influenced by Heraclitus The philosopher Anaxagoras refuses to separate the opposites in the one cosmos 4 Empedocles has forces arguably the first since Heraclitus s tension 41 which are in opposition known as Love and Hate or more accurately Harmony and Strife 4 Democritus and the atomists were also influenced by Heraclitus 68 The atomists and Heraclitus both believed that everything was in motion 78 79 ai On one interpretation Essentially what the atomists did was try to find a middle way between the contradictory philosophical schemes of Heraclitus and Parmenides 80 nbsp Plato s Theory of Forms was a result of reconciling Heraclitus and Parmenides Sophists edit The sophists inclusing as Protagoras of Abdera and Gorgias of Leontini may also have been influenced by Heraclitus 81 One tradition associated their concern with politics and preventing party strife with Heraclitus 82 83 Gorgias seems to have been influenced by the Heraclitean idea of the logos when he argued in his work On Non Being possibly parodying the Eleatics that being cannot exist or be communicated According to one author Gorgias in a sense completes Heraclitus 83 Classical and Hellenistic philosophy edit Plato knew of the teachings of Heraclitus through the Heraclitean philosopher Cratylus 72 Plato held that for Heraclitus knowledge is made impossible by the flux of sensible objects and thus the need for the imperceptible Forms as objects of knowledge 84 85 Aristotle accused Heraclitus of denying the law of noncontradiction and that he thereby failed in his reasoning u However Aristotle s material monist and world conflagration interpretation of Heraclitus also influenced the Stoics 4 86 Stoics edit nbsp The Stoic Cleanthes wrote a lost four volume Interpretation of Heraclitus 1605 engraving The Stoics believed major tenets of their philosophy derived from the thought of Heraclitus especially the logos used to support their belief that rational law governs the universe 87 88 A four volume work titled Interpretation of Heraclitus was written by the Stoic philosopher Cleanthes but has not survived 68 89 a In surviving stoic writings this is most evident in the writings of Marcus Aurelius 90 According to one author Heraclitus of Ephesus was the father of Stoic physics 91 Many of the later Stoics interpreted the logos as the arche as a creative fire that ran through all things 92 Marcus Aurelius understood the Logos as the account which governs everything Heraclitus also states We should not act and speak like children of our parents which Marcus Aurelius interpreted to mean one should not simply accept what others believe West observes that Plato Aristotle Theophrastus and Sextus Empiricus all make no mention of this doctrine and concludes that the language and thought are obviously Stoic and not attributable to Heraclitus 93 Long concludes the earliest Stoic fragments are also modifications of Heraclitus 94 Burnet cautions that these Stoic modifications of Heraclitus make it harder to interpret Heraclitus himself as the Stoics ascribed their own interpretations of terms like logos and ekpyrosis to Heraclitus 95 nbsp Coin from c 230 CE depicting Heraclitus as a Cynic with club and raised hand Cynics edit The Cynics were influenced by Heraclitus such as by his condemnation of the mystery cults 19 96 h Heraclitus is sometimes even depicted as a cynic According to one source the Cynic affinity with Heraclitus lies not so much in his philosophy as in his cultural criticism and idealised lifestyle 97 The Cynics attributed several of the later Cynic epistles to his authorship 98 Heraclitus wrote Dogs bark at every one they do not know bt Similarly Diogenes the Cynic when asked by Alexander why he considered himself a dog responded that he barks at those who give me nothing 99 100 Pyrrhonists edit The Pyrrhonists were also influenced by Heraclitus He may be the predecessor to Pyrrho s doctrine No More This than That 74 Aenesidemus one of the major ancient Pyrrhonist philosophers claimed in a now lost work that Pyrrhonism was a way to Heraclitean philosophy because Pyrrhonist practice helps one to see how opposites appear to be the case about the same thing Once one sees this it leads to understanding the Heraclitean view of opposites being the case about the same thing 101 A later Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus disagreed arguing opposites appearing to be the case about the same thing is not a dogma of the Pyrrhonists but a matter occurring to the Pyrrhonists to the other philosophers and to all of humanity 101 Early Christianity edit nbsp John 1 1 in the page showing the first chapter of John in the King James Bible Heraclitus was often read by early Christian philosophers who 102 following the Stoics interpreted the logos as meaning the Christian Word of God such as in John 1 1 In the beginning was the Word logos and the Word was God Hippolytus of Rome one of the early Church Fathers of the Christian Church identified Heraclitus along with the other Pre Socratics and Academics as a source of heresy in Heraclitus s case namely the heresy of Noetus 102 The Christian apologist Justin Martyr took a more positive view of Heraclitus 92 In his First Apology he said both Socrates and Heraclitus were Christians before Christ those who lived reasonably are Christians even though they have been thought atheists as among the Greeks Socrates and Heraclitus and men like them 103 Modern scholars such as John Burnet have viewed the relationship between Heraclitean logos and Johannine logos as fallacious saying the Johannine doctrine of the logos has nothing to do with Herakleitos or with anything at all in Greek philosophy but comes from the Hebrew Wisdom literature 13 When Heraclitus speaks of God he does not mean a single deity as an omnipotent and omniscient or God as Creator the universe being eternal he meant the divine as opposed to human the immortal as opposed to the mortal and the cyclical as opposed to the transient Thus it is arguably more accurate to speak of the Divine and not of God 104 Weeping philosopher edit nbsp Donato Bramante painted Heraclitus and Democritus as the weeping and laughing philosopher Heraclitus s influence also extends outside of philosophy A motif found in art and literature is Heraclitus as the weeping philosopher and Democritus as the laughing philosopher which may have originated with the Cynic philosopher Menippus 105 generally references their reactions to the folly of mankind 106 107 nbsp Heraclitus painted as the weeping philosopher by Hendrik ter Brugghen 1628 For example in Lucian of Samosata s Philosophies for Sale Heraclitus is auctioned off as the weeping philosopher and Democritus as the laughing philosopher bu The Roman poet Juvenal wrote Heraclitus weep at life much more than you did while alive for now life is more pitiable 108 Heraclitus also appears in painter Raphael s School of Athens in which he is represented by Michelangelo since they shared a sour temper and bitter scorn for all rivals 6 Modern edit nbsp Heraclitus painted as the weeping philosopher by Johannes Moreelse c 1630Modern interest in early Greek philosophy can be traced back to 1573 when French printer Henri Estienne also known as Henricus Stephanus collected a number of pre Socratic fragments including those of Heraclitus and published them in Latin in Poesis philosophica 109 Renaissance skeptic Michel de Montaigne s essay On Democritus and Heraclitus in which he sided with the laughing philosopher over the weeping philosopher was probably written soon after 110 The Merchant of Venice by William Shakespeare features the melancholic character of Antonio who some critics contend is modeled after Heraclitus 111 Additionally in one scene of the play Portia assesses her potential suitors and says of one County Palatine I fear he will prove the weeping philosopher when he grows old 112 Cartesianism edit According to one author Rene Descartes anti Aristotelianism was motivated by Protagoras and Heraclitus 113 According to Bernard Freyberg both Parmenides and Heraclitus are direct if distant ancestors of Spinoza since they both said all is one 114 According to Heinrich Bluecher If you read the whole system of Spinoza it is nothing but the changed system of Heraclitus 115 British empiricism edit David Hume wrote while discussing personal identity Thus as the nature of a river consists in the motion and change of parts tho in less than four and twenty hours these be totally alter d this hinders not the river from continuing the same during several ages 116 German idealism edit nbsp Schleiermacher was the pioneer of Heraclitean studies Since Kant philosophers have sometimes been divided into rationalists and empiricists 117 Heraclitus has been considered each by different scholars 14 118 For rationalism 119 philosophers cite fragments like Poor witnesses for men are the eyes and ears of those who have barbarian souls bv For empiricism 21 they cite fragments like The things that can be seen heard and learned are what I prize the most bw Gottlob Mayer has argued that the philosophical pessimism of Arthur Schopenhauer recapitulated the thought of Heraclitus 120 The German theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher was one of the first to collect the fragments of Heraclitus specifically and write them out in his native tongue the pioneer of Heraclitean studies 121 122 123 Schleiermacher was also one of the first to posit Persian influence upon Heraclitus a question taken up by succeeding scholars Friedrich Creuzer and August Gladisch 102 123 The influence of Heraclitus on German idealist G W F Hegel was so profound that he remarked in his Lectures on the History of Philosophy there is no proposition of Heraclitus which I have not adopted in my Logic 124 Hegel interpreted Heraclitus as a dialetheist and as a process philosopher seeing the becoming in Heraclitus as a natural result of the ontology of being and non being in Parmenides 1 He also doubted the world conflagaration interpretation which had been popular since Aristotle 1 nbsp Hegel said there is no proposition of Heraclitus which I have not adopted in my Logic The Young Hegelian and socialist Ferdinand Lassalle wrote a book on Heraclitus 119 Lassalle follows Hegel in styling the doctrine of Heraclitus the philosophy of the logical law of the identity of contradictories 102 Lassalle also thought Persian theology influenced Heraclitus 119 53 125 Marx compared Lasalle s work to that of a schoolboy 126 and Lenin accused him of sheer plagiarism 125 Classical philologist Jakob Bernays also wrote a work on Heraclitus 102 Inspired by Bernays the English scholar Ingram Bywater collected all fragments of Heraclitus in a critical edition Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae 1877 127 An English translation was provided by G T W Patrick in 1889 14 Hermann Diels wrote Bywater s book has come to be accounted as the only reliable collection of the remains of that philosopher 127 Diels published the first edition of the authoritative Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker The Fragments of the Pre Socratics in 1903 later revised and expanded three times and finally revised in two subsequent editions by Walther Kranz Diels Kranz is used in academia to cite pre Socratic philosophers In Diels Kranz each ancient personality and each passage is assigned a number to uniquely identify it Heraclitus is traditionally catalogued as philosopher number 22 128 Continental edit The existentialist and classical philologist Friedrich Nietzsche preferred Heraclitus above all the other pre Socratics 24 129 The nationalist philosopher of history Oswald Spengler wrote his failed dissertation on Heraclitus 130 Existentialist and phenomenologist Martin Heidegger was also influenced by Heraclitus as seen in his Introduction to Metaphysics Heidegger believed that the thinking of Heraclitus and Parmenides was the origin of philosophy and misunderstood by Plato and Aristotle leading all of Western philosophy astray 131 68 The Irish author Oscar Wilde was influenced by Heraclitus 132 Wilde is credited with the saying expect the unexpected though Heraclitus said If you do not expect the unexpected you will not find it for it is hard to be sought out and difficult 133 bx In the 1950s a term originating with Heraclitus idios kosmos meaning private world as distinguished from the common world koinos kosmos was adopted by phenomenological and existential psychologists such as Ludwig Binswanger and Rollo May to refer to the experience of people with delusions or other problems who have trouble seeing beyond the limits of their own minds or who confuse this private world with shared reality 134 It was an important part of novelist Philip K Dick s views on schizophrenia 135 Those thinkers have relied on Heraclitus statement that The waking have one common world but the sleeping turn aside each into a world of his own by Anglo American edit The British philosopher A N Whitehead has been called a process philosopher in the tradition of Heraclitus 136 In Bertrand Russell s essay Mysticism and Logic he contends Heraclitus proves himself a metaphysician by his blending of mystical and scientific impulses 137 Ludwig Wittgenstein was known to read Plato and in his return to philosophy in 1929 he made several remarks resembling those of Heraclitus The fundamental thing expressed grammatically What about the sentence One cannot step into the same river twice 138 He then seemed to make a dramatic shift by 1931 saying one can step twice into the same river 139 The philosopher Peter Geach was inspired by Heraclitus s comments on the river to formulate his idea of relative identity 140 141 which he also used to solve such issues as the Trinity 142 143 Philosophy of Time edit nbsp Presentism is seen as a Heraclitean view The British idealist J M E McTaggart is best known for his paper The Unreality of Time 1908 in which he argues that time is unreal His A series also known as presentism or temporal becoming which conceptualizes of time as tensed i e having the properties of being past present or future has been described as Heraclitean By contrast his B theory under which time is tenseless i e earlier than simultaneous to or later than has been associated with Parmenides 144 145 146 Advocates of presentism include Arthur Prior and William Lane Craig Contradiction edit nbsp Graham Priest is a dialetheist Aristotle s arguments for the law of non contradiction have been in doubt ever since their criticism by Polish logician Jan Lukasiewicz 147 Recent approaches in logic such as paraconsistent logic have led to some philosophers advancing logical pluralism and dialetheism such as Graham Priest and JC Beall Priest agrees with G W F Hegel s contradictory account of motion based on Zeno of Elea s Paradox of the Arrow which is arguably Heraclitus account of flux 148 On this account of motion to move is to be both here and not here 148 Beall argues for a contradictory account of Jesus Christ as both man and divine 149 Notes editExplanatory notes edit It may also be an unwarranted interpretation of the fragment from Heraclitus stating the kingdom is a child s 4 b Two alleged letters between Heraclitus and Darius quoted by Diogenes Laertius are later forgeries 8 Some classicists and professors of ancient philosophy have disputed which of these fragments can truly be attributed to Heraclitus 11 12 West suggests that the beginning may be tentatively ordered as follows 22 B1 B114 B2 B89 B30 B31 B90 B60 Bios with the accent on the O is the Greek for bow Bios with the accent on the I is the Greek for life Literally the width of a man s foot ax The 9th century CE Dadestan i Denig preserves information on Zoroastrian cosmology but also shows direct borrowings from Aristotle 51 Not to be confused with the cynic a Fragment numbers edit a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p A1 a b Hippolytus B52 Clement Stromateis B29 B49 B101 Sextus Empiricus Against the Mathematicians B2 a b B5 a b c Clement Protrepticus B14 Clement Protrepticus B15 Diogenes Laertius B42 Diogenes Laertius B56 Diogenes Laertius B57 B81 a b Diogenes Laertius B40 B39 B121 a b Stobaeus B118 Sextus Empiricus Against the Mathematicians B1 Plutarch On the Pythian Oracle B92 A4 a b A7 Hippolytus B59 a b Hippolytus B60 B103 Pseudo Aristotle De Mundo B10 Hippolytus B62 B88 B126 Stobaeus B111 B13 B37 Hippolytus B61 B4 Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics B9 a b c A6 B12 B49a Plutarch On the E at Delphi B91 Origen B80 a b Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics B8 A22 Hippolytus B51 B48 B125 Hippolytus B53 Clement Stromateis B24 Clement Stromateis B25 Pseudo Aristotle De Mundo B11 Stobaeus B114 B3 B94 Aetius A12 A5 Clement Stromateis B30 Aurelius B76 Clement Stromateis B31 Plutarch On the E at Delphi B90 Hippolytus B64 Clement Stromateis B32 B83 Origen B79 B102 Stobaeus B117 B67a B98 B7 Clement Stromateis B27 Hippolytus B50 Clement Stromateis B19 C1 C2 B97 C5 B107 Hippolytus B55 Clement Stromateis B18 B89 Citations edit a b c d e f g h i j k l m Graham 2019 a b c d e f Kahn 1979 p 1 3 Ionian Revolt Blackwell Encyclopedia of Ancient Battles 2011 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Michael Stokes Heraclitus Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1961 p 480 Wheelwright Heraclitus p 11 84 a b Michelangelo and the Pope s Ceiling By Ross King p 234 Burnet 1892 p 130 Kirk 1954 p 1 Clement Stromateis 1 129 Fairweather Janet The Death of Heraclitus Greek Roman and Byzantine Studies 14 1973 233 239 a b c McCabe 2015 Kahn 1979 p 168 a b Burnet 1892 p 133 a b c d e f g h i j G T W Patrick June 7 1889 The Fragments of the Work of Heraclitus of Ephesus on Nature Translated from the Greek Text of Bywater with an Introduction Historical and Critical N Murray via Google Books Kahn 1979 p 5 Mansfield 1999 p 39 Burnet 1892 p 132 see Laertius 7 33 a b The Cynics by Robert Brach Branham p 51 a b Heraclitus and Thales Conceptual Scheme by Aryeh Finkelberg p 31 a b Heraclitus of Ephesus An attempt to restore its fragments to their original order by Paul Robert Schuster a b West 1971 p 113 117 Technopaegnia in Heraclitus and the Delphica Oracles Shared Compositional Techniques a b c Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks by Friedrich Nietzsche p 64 Kahn 1979 p 89 Heresiography in Context by Jaap Mansfeld p 193 Cicero De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum Chapter 2 Section 15 Wheelwright Heraclitus p 116 a b c d e f Heraclitus Criticism of the Ionian Philosophy by Daniel W Graham Graham 2008 p 175 a b c Barnes 1982 p 49 Bardon Adrian Dyke Heather November 2 2015 A Companion to the Philosophy of Time John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 9781119145691 via Google Books Warren 2014 pp 72 74 Parmenides 206 207 Dietz Karl Martin 2004 Heraklit von Ephesus und die Entwicklung der Individualitat Stuttgart Verlag Freies Geistesleben p 60 ISBN 978 3772512735 a b W K C Guthrie Pre Socratic Philosophy Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1961 p 443 Quine W V 1950 Identity Ostension and Hypostasis The Journal of Philosophy 47 22 621 doi 10 2307 2021795 a b Guthrie 1962 p 46 Michael Gagarin 1974 Dike in Archaic Greek Thought Classical Philology 69 3 186 197 doi 10 2307 268491 Snyder Jane McIntosh 1984 The Harmonia of Bow and Lyre in Heraclitus Fr 51 DK Phronesis 29 1 91 95 doi 10 1163 156852884X00201 JSTOR 4182189 Retrieved June 9 2023 via jstor a b Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Force by M Jammer 1961 a b Sandywell 1996 p 263 265 Graham 2008 p 175 177 Heraclitus on War by Abraham Schoener Curd 2020 Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus Oxyrhynchus Papyri LIII 3710 ii 43 47 and iii 7 11 West 1971 p 172 173 Kahn 1979 p 147 Graham 2008 pp 170 172 a b West 1971 p 170 171 a b West 1971 p 174 175 West 1971 p 170 176 a b Early Greek Philosophy on Being by C H A Bjerregaard Gabor Betegh Paul Tannery and the Pour L Histoire De La Science Hellene De Thales A Empedocle PDF p 370 Hussey 1999 p 111 Sanchez Castro Liliana Carolina The Aristotelian Reception Of Heraclitus Conception of the Soul Brill pp 377 403 Martha C Nussbaum 1972 PSYXH in Heraclitus I Phronesis 17 1 1 16 Nussbaum Martha C PSYXH in Heraclitus II Phronesis vol 17 no 2 1972 pp 153 70 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 4181882 Accessed 18 June 2023 Kahn 1979 Guthrie 1962 p 419 The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Warren 2014 p 63 Sandywell 1996 p 237 Olof Gigon Untersuchungen Zu Heraklit p 4 a b Kirk 1954 p 37 Plato s Symposium A Reader s Guide by Thomas L Cooksey p 69 Geldard Richard G June 7 2000 Remembering Heraclitus Richard Geldard ISBN 9780940262980 via Google Books Masking the Abject A Genealogy of Play p 18 a b c d e f g Graham 2019 7 Betegh 2004 Dell Aversana Paolo December 6 2013 Cognition in Geosciences The feeding loop between geo disciplines cognitive sciences and epistemology Academic Press ISBN 9789073834682 via Google Books Attardo Salvatore 2002 Translation and Humour An Approach Based on the General Theory of Verbal Humour GTVH The Translator 8 2 173 194 doi 10 1080 13556509 2002 10799131 ISSN 1355 6509 S2CID 142611273 a b Aristotle G Metaphysics 1010a Logic by Wilfrid Hodges p 13 a b Pyrrho his Antecedents and His Legacy by Richard Bett p 132 Graham 2002 Nehamas 2002 a b c Graham 2002 p 27 30 Aristotle Physics Book 8 Early Greek Philosophy edited by Joe McCoy p 44 Thinking About the Earth p 13 Structural Logos in Heraclitus and the Sophists Liberal Temper in Greek Politics by Eric Havelock p 290 a b Rereading the Sophists by Susan Jarratt p 44 Robinson T M 1991 Heraclitus and Plato on the Language of the Real The Monist 74 4 481 490 JSTOR 27903258 Aristotle Metaphysics xii 4 1078b12 Mondolfo Rodolfo and D J Allan Evidence of Plato and Aristotle Relating to the Ekpyrosis in Heraclitus Phronesis 3 no 2 1958 75 82 http www jstor org stable 4181631 Long 2001 chapter 2 Warren 2014 p 63 Diogenes Laertius 7 174 Long 2001 p 56 Stoicism by Philip Halle Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1961 a b Erwin Ramsdell Goodenough The Theology of Justin Martyr West 1971 p 124 125 Long 2001 p 51 Burnet 1892 pp 142 143 Branham Robert Bracht Goulet Caze Marie Odile June 7 1996 The Cynics The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy University of California Press ISBN 9780520204492 via Google Books Bosman P R TRACES OF CYNIC MONOTHEISM IN THE EARLY ROMAN EMPIRE Acta Classica vol 51 2008 pp 1 20 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 24592647 Accessed 2 Jan 2024 J F Kindstrand The Cynics and Heraclitus Eranos 82 1984 149 78 Diogenes Laertius Book 6 The Philosophy of Cynicism Luis Navia p 27 a b Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I Chapter 29 Sections 210 211 a b c d e History of Philosophy by Friedrich Ueberweg p 39 First Apology Chapter 46 Wheelwright 1959 p 69 73 Lepage J L 2012 Laughing and Weeping Melancholy Democritus and Heraclitus as Emblems In The Revival of Antique Philosophy in the Renaissance Palgrave Macmillan New York https doi org 10 1057 9781137316660 3 Heraclitus Hendrick ter Brugghen 1628 Rijksmuseum Modern Cynicism Blackwood s Magazine 64 1868 Juvenal and the Satiric Emotions p 125 Giannis Stamatellos Introduction to Presocratics A Thematic Approach to Early Greek Philosophy with Key Readings Wiley Blackwell 2012 p 7 Montaigne Michel de On Democritus and Heraclitus The Essays of Michel de Montaigne HyperEssays George Coffin Taylor 1928 Is Shakespeare s Antonio the Weeping Philosopher Heraclitus Modern Philology 26 2 161 167 doi 10 1086 387759 JSTOR 433874 S2CID 170717088 The Merchant of Venice 1 2 49 Masquerade of the Dream Walkers by Peter A Redpath p xii A Dark History of Modern Philosophy p 43 Heraclitus and the Metaphysical Tradition Treatise of Human Nature 1 4 6 14 Rationalism vs Empiricism MOYAL Georges J D THE UNEXPRESSED RATIONALISM OF HERACLITUS Revue de Philosophie Ancienne vol 7 no 2 1989 pp 185 98 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 24353855 Accessed 2 Jan 2024 a b c F Lassalle The philosophy of heraclitus the obscure of ephesus two volumes berlin 1858 Heraklit von Ephesus und Arthur Schopenhauer Heraclitus by Philip Wheelwright Herakleitos der dunkle von Ephesos dargestellt aus den Trummern seines Werkes und den Zeugnissen der Altens 1807 a b Roberts Lee M January 14 2009 Germany and the Imagined East Cambridge Scholars Publishing ISBN 9781443804196 via Google Books Hegel s Lectures on the History of Philosophy www marxists org a b Conspectus of Lassalle s Book The Philosophy of Heraclitus the Obscure of Ephesus by Lenin Letter to Friedrich Engels February 1 1858 a b Jackson William Walrond June 7 1917 Ingram Bywater The Memoir of an Oxford Scholar 1840 1914 Clarendon Press via Google Books Diels Hermann Kranz Walther 1957 Plambock Gert ed Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker in Ancient Greek and German Rowohlt ISBN 5875607416 Retrieved 11 April 2022 Mugge Maximilian August May 26 1911 Friedrich Nietzsche His Life and Work T Fisher Unwin via Google Books Oswald Spengler The Fundamental Metaphysical Thought of the Heraclitean Philosophy W Julian Korab Karpowicz The Presocratics in the Thought of Martin Heidegger Frankfurt am Main Peter Lang 2016 page 58 Heraclitus and Hedonism in Wilde s writing Language and Mobility May Rollo 1958 Contributions of existential psychotherapy In May Rollo Angel Ernest Ellenberger Henri F eds Existence a new dimension in psychiatry and psychology New York Basic Books pp 37 91 81 doi 10 1037 11321 002 ISBN 9780671203146 OCLC 14599810 Schizophrenia amp The Book of Changes 1964 Whitehead s Process Metaphysics as a New Link between Science and Metaphysics Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays by Bertrand Russell Zettel Wittgenstein 459 Stern David G 1991 Heraclitus and Wittgenstein s River Images Stepping Twice into the Same River The Monist 74 4 579 604 Cartwright Helen Morris Heraclitus and the Bath Water The Philosophical Review 74 no 4 1965 466 85 https doi org 10 2307 2183124 Instantiation Identity and Constitution by E J Lowe Philosophical Studies An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition Vol 44 No 1 Jul 1983 pp 45 59 P T Geach Reference and Generality pp 150 151 Relative Identity and the Doctrine of the Trinity Markosian Ned Time Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 28 December 2014 Craig William Lane 1999 Temporal Becoming and the Direction of Time Philosophy and Theology 11 2 349 366 see Being and Becoming in Modern Physics Lukasiewicz Jan amp Wedin Vernon 1971 On the Principle of Contradiction in Aristotle Review of Metaphysics 24 3 485 509 a b Priest Graham Inconsistencies in Motion American Philosophical Quarterly 22 no 4 1985 339 46 JSTOR 20014114 Beall Jc Pawl Timothy McCall Thomas Cotnoir A J amp Uckelman Sara L 2019 Complete Symposium on Jc Beall s Christ A Contradiction A Defense of Contradictory Christology Journal of Analytic Theology 7 1 400 577 References editAncient sources edit This article uses the Diels Kranz numbering system for testimony labeled A fragments labeled B and imitation labeled C of Pre Socratic philosophy Testimony edit A1 nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925 Others Heraclitus Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 2 9 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library A2 Strabo 1929 Book XIV Geographica in Ancient Greek and English Translated by Jones Horace Leonard Sterrett J R Sitlington London Heinemann pp 632 633 A3 Clement of Alexandria 1885 Book I Chapter XIV Stromateis Ante Nicene Fathers Translated by William Wilson via Wikisource A4 Aristotle Rhetoric Book III section 5 1407b via Wikisource A5 Aristotle A Metaphysics 984a A6 Plato Cratylus 402a A7 Aristotle G Metaphysics 1005b23 A8 Aetius 7 In Stobaeus ed Placita Anthologium Vol I line 77 A9 Aristotle Book V On the Parts of Animals 645a17 A10 Plato Sophist 242d A11 14 Aetius 13 In Stobaeus ed Placita Anthologium Vol II line 8 A15 Aristotle Book II On the Soul 405a25 A16 Sextus Empiricus Book VII Against the Mathematicians 126 A17 Aetius 7 In Stobaeus ed Placita Anthologium Vol IV line 2 A18 Aetius Book V Vetusta Placita line 23 A19 Plutarch In Defence of Oracles 415e A20 Chalcide Scholia 251 A21 Clement of Alexandria Book II Stromateis 130 A22 Aristotle Eudemian Ethics 1235a25 A23 Polybius Book IV Histories 20 Fragments edit B1 2 Sextus Empiricus Book XVII Against the Mathematicians 132 B3 Aetius Book II Placita 21 4 B4 Albertus Magnus Book VI De veget 401 B5 Aristocritus Theosophia 68 B6 Aristotle Book II Meteorology 355a B7 Aristotle Book 5 On Sense Perception 443a B8 9 Aristotle Book II Nicomachean Ethics B10 11 Pseudo Aristotle De Mundo 396b B12 Eusebius 1903 Epitomae of Arius Didymus Praeparatio evangelica Translated by E H Gifford Clarendon Press Book XV Chapter XVIII XX via Tertullian Project B13 Athanaeus Book V Deipnosophistae 178F B14 15 Clement of Alexandria Protrepticus B16 Clement of Alexandria Paedagogus B17 36 Clement of Alexandria Stromateis Translated by William Wilson via Wikisource B37 Columella De re rustica B38 nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925 The Seven Sages Thales Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 1 1 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library 23 B39 nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925 The Seven Sages Bias Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 1 1 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library 88 B40 46 nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925 Others Heraclitus Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 2 9 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library B47 nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925 Others Pyrrho Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 2 9 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library 77 B48 Etymologicum Magnum B49 Galen On the knowledge of the pulse VIII 773 B49a Heraclitus commentator Homeric Allegories B50 67 Hippolytus of Rome Refutation of All Heresies Book IX Chapter 4 5 via Wikisource B67a Hisdosus Scholasticus 2016 Andrew Hicks ed De Anima Mundi Platonica Commentary on Chalcides translation of the Timaeus dialogue Mediaeval Studies 78 ISBN 978 0 88844 680 0 B68 69 Iamblichus On the Mysteries B70 Iamblichus On the Soul B71 76 Marcus Aurelius Meditations B77 Porphyry The Cave of the Nymphs B78 80 Origen of Alexandria Contra Celsum B81 Philodemus On Rhetoric B82 83 Plato Hippias major B84a 84b Plotinus Enneads B85 86 Plutarch Life of Coriolanus B87 Plutarch On Hearing B88 Plutarch Consolation to Apollonius B89 Plutarch On Superstition B90 91 Plutarch On the E at Delphi B92 93 Plutarch On the Pythian Oracle B94 Plutarch On Exile B95 96 Plutarch Symposiacs B97 Plutarch An seni respublica gerenda sit B98 Plutarch On the face in the moon B99 Plutarch On Fire and Water B100 Plutarch Platonic Questions B101 Plutarch Against Colotes B101a Polybius Book 12 Histories line 27 B102 Porphyry Ad Iliadem 4 4 B103 Porphyry Notes on Homer B104 Proclus Commentary on Plato s Alcibiades B105 Scholia to Homer 289B B106 Plutarch Life of Camillus B107 Sextus Empiricus Book XVII Against the Mathematicians 126 B108 119 Stobaeus Florilegium B120 121 Strabo Geography B122 Suda B123 Themistius Speeches V B124 125 Theophrastus On Vertigo B125a John Tzetzes Commentary on Aristophanes Wealth B126 John Tzetzes Book XVII Commentary on the Iliad 126 Imitation edit C1 Hippocrates 1931 On Regimen Hippocrates Collected Works Vol IV Cambridge Harvard University Press C2 Hippocrates 1923 On Nutrition Hippocrates Collected Works Vol I Translated by W H S Jones Cambridge Harvard University Press C4 Cleanthes Hymn to Zeus fr 537 C5 Lucian 1905 Philosophies for Sale The works of Lucian of Samosata Vol 1 Translated by Fowler H W Fowler F G Modern scholarship edit Barnes Jonathan 1982 The Natural Philosophy of Heraclitus The Presocratic Philosophers London amp New York Routledge Taylor amp Francis Group pp 43 62 ISBN 978 0 415 05079 1 Betegh Gabor 2004 The Derveni papyrus cosmology theology and interpretation Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780511584435 Burnet John 1892 Heraclitus Early Greek Philosophy A and C Black Retrieved 5 March 2022 Curd Patricia 2020 Presocratic philosophy In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Graham D W 2008 Heraclitus Flux Order and Knowledge In Curd P Graham D W eds The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy New York Oxford University Press pp 169 188 ISBN 978 0 19 514687 5 Graham D W 2002 Heraclitus and Parmenides In Caston V Graham D W eds Presocratic Philosophy Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos Aldershot Ashgate pp 27 44 ISBN 978 0 7546 0502 7 Graham Daniel W 2019 Heraclitus In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Guthrie W K C 1962 A History of Greek Philosophy The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans Vol 1 Cambridge Cambridge University Press Hussey Edward 1999 Heraclitus In Long A A ed The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy Cambridge University Press pp 88 112 ISBN 978 0 521 44667 9 Kahn Charles H 1979 The Art and Thought of Heraclitus An Edition of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 21883 2 Kirk G S 1954 Heraclitus the Cosmic Fragments Cambridge Cambridge University Press Long A A 2001 Stoic Studies University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 22974 7 Mansfield Jaap 1999 Long A A ed The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy Cambridge University Press pp 22 45 ISBN 978 0 521 44667 9 McCabe Mary Margaret 2015 Platonic Conversations Oxford University Press pp 1 31 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780198732884 003 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 873288 4 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a Missing or empty title help Nehamas Alexander 2002 Parminidean Being Heraclitean Fire In Caston V Graham D W eds Presocratic Philosophy Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos Aldershot Ashgate pp 45 64 ISBN 978 0 7546 0502 7 Sandywell Barry 1996 Presocratic Reflexivity The Construction of Philosophical Discourse c 600 450 B C Logological Investigations Volume Three Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 85347 2 Warren James 5 December 2014 Presocratics Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 49337 2 West Martin L 1971 Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient Clarendon Press Retrieved 6 March 2022 Chapters 4 6 deal with Heraclitus Wheelwright Philip 1959 Heraclitus PDF Princeton University Press Further reading editGregory Andrew 3 January 2008 Ancient Greek Cosmogony A amp C Black ISBN 978 1 84966 792 0 Hussey Edward 1972 The Presocratics New York Scribner ISBN 0684131188 Kirk G S Raven J E 1957 The Pre Socratic Philosophers A Critical History with a Selection of Texts 2nd ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press Mcevilley Thomas C 7 February 2012 The Shape of Ancient Thought Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 1 58115 933 2 McKirahan R D 2011 Philosophy before Socrates An Introduction With Text and Commentary Indianapolis Hackett ISBN 978 1 60384 183 2 Mikalson Jon 24 June 2010 Greek Popular Religion in Greek Philosophy OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 957783 5 Mitchell John Malcolm 1911 Heraclitus Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 13 11th ed pp 309 310 Mourelatos Alexander ed 1993 The Pre Socratics a collection of critical essays Rev ed Princeton NJ Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 02088 4 Naddaf Gerard 2005 The Greek Concept of Nature SUNY Press ISBN 978 0791463734 Schofield Malcolm Nussbaum Martha Craven eds 1982 Language and logos studies in ancient Greek philosophy presented to G E L Owen Cambridge Cambridge U P ISBN 978 0 521 23640 9 Stamatellos Giannis 2007 Plotinus and the Presocratics A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences in Plotinus Enneads State University of New York Press ISBN 978 0 7914 8031 1 Wright M R 1985 The Presocratics The main Fragments in Greek with Introduction Commentary and Appendix Containing Text and Translation of Aristotle on the Presocratics Bristol Bristol Classical Press ISBN 978 0 86292 079 1 External links edit nbsp Works related to Fragments of Heraclitus at Wikisource nbsp Quotations related to Heraclitus at Wikiquote nbsp Media related to Heraclitus at Wikimedia Commons Stamatellos Giannis Heraclitus of Ephesus Life and Work Retrieved 2007 10 12 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Heraclitus amp oldid 1194844377, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.